Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 38

1

I.

Introduction

II.

Preface

III.

Postulates of Existics

IV.

Axiomatization of the Postulates of Existics

V.

Interaction: Basis for Existence


a. Relative Frames of Reference
b. Reference Frame Schemata
c. Invariance through Identity

VI.

Existics Equations (Basic)

VII. Intermediary Frames of Reference

Copyright 2012, Gavin Wince


Friday, the 13th of January, 2012

Existics is neither the name of a book nor the name of any specific dogma,
doctrine or ontology. Existics is intended and designed to be independent of bias
or opinion; an open subject employed to change through the refinement of its
terms. Therefore, in its own right, Existics is the study of the laws that govern
existence.- Gavin Wince

I.

Introduction

If one studies everything that one possibly can, and then goes on even
further to search for common patterns in areas most unexpected, one will find
that there is an invisible, inexpressible fundamental truth that, from which, all
other things extend. This truth is so universal and so fine in nature, that it evades
most worldviews, even though it is always directly in contact with us. It is within
us and all about us. It is us, yet it is not us either. It is independent of having any
extension having no manifest form or instantiated representation. However, its
paradoxical behavior, which is eternally present and persistently evading
rhetorical and sensual encapsulation, is the very means of measure through which
the axioms of Existics are founded upon. This is an attempt to formalize that
which has been considered unable to be formalized: the relationship between the
self and the other-than-self. Existics is a formalization designed around
observation, logic and mathematics dealing with the ultimate questions about
existence; a study of the basic laws of existence.

II.

Preface

That, from whence all things come from and therefore must again return
to, is neither existent nor nonexistent. For it to exist, it would have to have
extension from some initial source. 'To be' is not initial, rather 'to be' is having
had been initiated. Therefore it does not exist. But what is it then that I am
referring to as that which does not exist? If I Can refer to something, then that
something must have some kind of existence such that it can be referred to.
Therefore, it does not exist, nor does it not exist either. How can this be? It
is! Then what is it? Simple: it is the source that from which all things extend.
Even though this thing that I am referring to is inexplicable, we will assume that it
is that from which existence arises.
However, one must not fall into the immediate trap of assuming that this
thing is distinctly separate from existence. In fact, it is existence, but we are
cursed with a flawed language, indirect contact through sensory input; a skewed
view through emotions, superstition, and lack of desire for whole understanding.
We have a veil of ignorance glazed over our every faculty preventing us from
being able to encounter it or refer to it directly independent of a dualistic
construct or a variety of expressions through a multiplicity of forms.
So from the get go we are absolutely wrong in our every description of
existence. We are trapped and stumble upon that very thing; having to proceed
forward in counter intuitive and paradoxical terms. We are at the least
pompously arrogant to assert that we could successfully finish such a task; as to
claim such knowledge is the greatest decree of stupidity. Consequently, in order
to describe something that cannot be described we must describe it anyway
knowing that it is not the object of our description and that we must proceed with
the utmost caution and humility.

III. Postulates of Existics


1). Existence is.
A). Something exists.
i). Something is not nothing.
ii). Something is not everything.
iii). Something is one or more things.
B). For something to exist, it must be in an interaction with some other
thing that exists.
i). There are at least two things.
ii). No two things are exactly the same.
iii). No two things are totally different.
iv). No two things are perfectly complementary.
2). Existence is both physical and nonphysical.
A). Something is both physical and nonphysical.
i). No thing is completely physical.
ii). No thing is completely nonphysical.
iii). No two things have the exact same proportion of
physicality to nonphysicality.
iv). No two things have the exact inverse proportions of
physicality to nonphysicality.
5

B). Both the physical and the nonphysical, infinitely, are gradient blends
of the physical and the nonphysical, where one is becoming more of the
other.
i). The physical and nonphysical can never completely blend into
one.
ii). The physical and the nonphysical can never completely
separate or be completely distinguishable.
iii). The nonphysical forms (manifests); the physical is formed
(manifested).
iv). The nonphysical animates; the physical is animated.
3). Existence is experienced through objective and subjective frames of reference.
A). The objective frame of reference is of the physical.
i). No thing physical is experienced subjectively.
ii). Existence is the objective link to the subjective.
B). The subjective frame of reference is of the nonphysical.
i). No thing nonphysical is experienced objectively.
ii). Experience is the subjective link to the objective.
4). Experience is the relationship between observation and existence.
A). Animate (observer) objects:
i). Experience physical existence through objective frames of
reference.

ii). Experience nonphysical existence through subjective frames of


reference.
B). Inanimate (observed) objects:
i). Physically exist as observed objects.
ii). Nonphysically exist as observed forms.
C). All things that exist have and exist within both subjective and objective
frames of reference.
i). If something has subjective experience, it must have objective
(physical) existence.
ii). If something is objectively experienced, it must have subjective
(nonphysical) existence.
5). Observation is the relationship between the observer and that, which is being
observed.
A). Something is subjectively observant of something else being objectively
observed.
i). Something is not observant of nothing.
ii). Something is not observant of everything.
B). Observation is experienced through subjective and objective frames of
reference and exists through physical/nonphysical interactions.
i). For something to be in observation, it must have both subjective
and objective frames of reference.
ii). For subjective and objective frames of reference to exist, there
must be an observer and something to be observed.
7

IV. Axiomatization of the Postulates of Existics

Let 1)
If 1), then 1)A)
Let 1)A) = 1)A) {i, ii, iii}
Let 1)B)
If 1)B), then 1)B) {i}
Let 1)B) {i} = 1)B) {ii, iii, iv}

Let 2)
If 1)A) and 2), then 2)A)
If 1)A) {ii}, then 2)A) {i}
If 1)A) {i}, then 2)A) {ii}
If 2)A) {i, ii}, and if 1)B) {iii, iv}, then 2)A) {iii, iv}

Let 3)
If 3)A) {i, ii}, then 3)B) {i, ii}
If 3)B) {i, ii}, then 3)A) {i, ii}

Let 4)
If 4)A) {i}, then 4)A) {ii}
Let 4)B) {i, ii}
If ([ 3)A) {i, ii} and 3)B) {i, ii} ] and

[if 4)A) {i}, then 4)A) {ii} ]), then 4)C) {i, ii}

Let 5)
If [all of 1), all of 2), all of 3), all of 4) ], then 5)A) and 5)B).
Let 5)A) = 5)A) {i, ii}
Let 5)B) = 5)B) {i, ii}

Discussion: This basic axiomitization of these proposed postulates of Existics is to


illustrate how these postulates follow fundamental rules of logic, such as TruthFunction Rules, Modal Rules, or Quantificational Rules, using very specific
assumptions. A more thorough treatment of these postulates, using conventional
forms of Logic, is the subject of a Logic essay and not necessary for the basic
understanding of Existics. These axioms are here, to be established as rules, for
the benefit of reference when deriving the Existics equations from the proposed
postulates. Notwithstanding, Existics has five assumptions from which the
treatment of Relative Frames of Reference, the Reference Frame Schemata, and
the concept of Invariance through Identity are derived; all of which becomes
expressible through arithmetic.

V.

Interaction: Basis for Existence

a. Relative Frames of Reference


Let us examine how the rules of Existics apply to an interaction between two
different subjects. Let them be two people: person A and person B.

Each person exists in two categories of reference frames: physical and


nonphysical, or objective and subjective. You can imagine the objective or
physical frame of reference as being something with extension and/or volume in
space/time that contains all of the objects of our sensory experience. You can
imagine the subjective or nonphysical frame of reference as an inwardly open
expanse where things of mental and/or instinctual effect take place.

10

11

The objective frame of reference extends outwardly away from the senses of the
individual, and the subjective frame of reference extends inwardly away from the
senses of the individual. The individual is composed of both physical and
nonphysical attributes which arise in their respective frames of reference.

The individual exists physically in their respective objective frame of reference,


and the individual exists nonphysically in their respective subjective frame of
reference. Something observed in the objective frame of reference is not the
same thing as that experienced in the subjective frame of reference relative to
that thing observed objectively, as seeing a flame is not equivalent to feeling its
heat.
The objective frame of reference, relative to one thing, is not the same objective
frame of reference relative to some other thing, such as two different
perspectives yielding two different observations. Also, some observers objective
reference of some object is not equivalent to that object in any other frame of
reference. In other word, the objective frame of reference of person A is
different from the objective frame of reference of person B. It would follow that
the subjective frame of reference of person A is different from the subjective
frame of reference of person B.
When two individuals observe some third party, let us say some person C, there is
a person C relative to A, a person C relative to B, and a person C relative to
12

itself. This holds true for any given number of things, unless they are in fact the
same thing.

A and B in observation of one another:


A

The entanglement of A and B in an event:

Since person A and person B exist in different frames of reference relative to one
other, person A and person B exist in relative frame of reference. So, there is a
person A relative to person A, a person A relative to a person B, a person B
relative to person B, and a person B relative to person A.

13

There is a subjective and objective frame of reference for person A relative to


person A, there is a subjective and objective frame of reference for person A
relative to person B, there is a subjective and objective frame of reference for
person B relative to person B, there is a subjective and objective frame of
reference for person B relative to person A.

We will use a simplified notation to represent the following: person A relative to


person A is (A)A or "A relative to A", person A relative to person B is (A)B or "A
relative to B", person B relative to person B is (B)B or "B relative to B", and person
B relative to person A is (B)A or "B relative to A".
14

b. Reference Frame Schemata


We can therefore define person A and person B in terms of relative frames of
reference pertaining to person A and person B.
A can be defined as (A)A, and (A)B. (A)A and (A)B can be broken down further
into subjective and objective frames of reference such as
.

In order to completely define A, we must define B.


B can be defined as (B)B and (B)A. (A)A and (A)B can be broken down further in
subjective and objective frames of reference such as
.

15

The objective and subjective frames of reference between A and B can be seen
collectively as a greater subjective and objective frame of reference making a
larger collective object between A and B, namely A. Since it is the case that for
one object to exist, it must be in an interaction with some other object, there
must be some other greater object B in relation to A. It would also follow that
the initial A and B are composed of sub-units of subjective and objective frames
of reference that belong to some lesser object a and some lesser object b.

Therefore, the relative frames of reference extend into greater and greater and
lesser and lesser relative frames of reference. Not only are there relative frames
of reference, but there are relative-relative frames of reference, relative frames
of reference existing as subset frames of reference; all existing within greater and
greater sets, ad infinitum.

16

Since there are relative frames of reference between A and B, there are infinite
sequences of reference frames relative to A and B. These are series of relative
frame of reference such as (((A)B)A)B..., or ((((A)B)A)B)A..., or (((((B)A)B)A)B)A...,
etc. The series of relative frames of reference that concern us are of the type
where each relative frame of reference alternates between observants such as
the example just given.

c. Invariance through Identity


The interaction between A and B can be broken down, described, and formalized
as being sequences of interactions between physical and nonphysical attributes
17

of A and B in a one to one correspondence through an infinite series of subjective


and objective relative frames of reference. Referring back to the Postulates of
Existics, specifically 1)B)- for something to exist it must be in an interaction with
some other thing that exists, it follows that i) there are at least two things, and ii)
no two things are exactly the same, et seq.

Assume we have two people engaged in some kind of interaction. Since they are
not the same individual, there must be some type of quantifiable differences
between the two individuals that can be used to measure relative frames of
reference. From our perspective, we are all composed of the same stuff, do
about the same thing, and all travel at about the same relativistic speeds all
within about the same given area. So, there really is no observable variance in
relative frames of reference between two observers outside phenomena
concerning Special and General Relativity; or is there?
Let us take this into consideration: suppose we assume that observers can
experience different rates of the passage of time, relative to one another, outside
phenomena concerning Special and General Relativity. For instance, people report
that as they get older the experienced rate of the passage of time increases
exponentially. Therefore, this could be used as an analogy to figure out how to
calculate the alleged variance in the experience of the passage time between two
observers experiencing the same non-relativistic event. Indeed, many people will
argue that yes, it would seem, time goes by faster as we age. We can recall when
we were children, days, weeks, months seemed to last forever; memories left as
little road markers at times in our life where we can distinctly see how the
experience of the rate of the passage of time appears to increase with age.
Therefore, using this analogy to establish a formal mathematics, let us also
assume that, at an initial point of an observers existence, the experienced rate of
the passage of time is at a stand-still, and, at a hypothetical point of infinite age,
the experienced rate of the passage of time is instantaneous. As the limit
18

approaches infinity from zero, as the observers age starts at zero and ends with
infinity, the experienced rate of the passage of time increases exponentially.

We will assume that for older people, the experienced rate of the passage of time
is noticeably faster than the experienced rate of the passage of time as perceived
by younger people. Assuming this to be the case, we must take notice of a funny
little predicament: when and older and younger person are engaged in an
interaction of some kind, the older person is experiencing that event at a faster
rate (passage of time) that the younger person; which creates a conundrum--What is occurring with time between the two people? It would be easy to scoff
this off and say that when two people come together, regardless of the
experienced rate of the passage of time, time passes at the same rate regardless
and that it is just a subjective perception that time goes by faster with age. This
seemingly pragmatic point-of-view has an assumption buried within it: what we
as individuals experience objectively, is the same for all other individuals
objectively, and that we all exist within and share a common objective reality. At
first glance, this assumption seems tame and common sense. However, I will
point out its fatal flaw: all empirical data we receive comes to us via the senses.
Therefore, fundamentally, even though it may seem funny to assume we each live
in different fields of existence relative to time in relation one another, the fact of
the matter is we do! This is an inescapable reality that prevents us from any
certainty outside the belief that there is a common objective reality. Since we
are limited to the use of senses, our entire experience of physical reality could be
an illusion for all we know. Therefore, we are justified in continuing along the
path of reasoning we have gone thus so far.
It can be deduced that since the older person experiences time at a faster rate,
that person is further ahead in time relative to their own experience of the event
relative to the younger person, and the younger person is further behind in time
relative to the experience of the event relative to the older person. This means
that the older person is in the relative future, and the younger person is in the
relative past; relative to each other. Assuming this to be the case, it means that
19

there is at least one extra dimension of time. This all fits perfectly within the
framework we have already laid out.
Indeed, when the older person, say person A, experiences a particular moment,
the younger person, say person B, will come to experience it at a latter time. The
ratio of A/B tell us how many units of time relative to A equal one unit of time
relative to B. The ratio B/A tells us how many units of time relative to B equal
one unit of time relative to A. If A and B are equivalent, then the ratio between A
and B equal one. Thus, we will amend postulate 1)B) {ii} to state that No two
things are exactly the same, but if they are, then they are in fact the same thing.
We will let the expression A/B = I, where I is the Identity Constant. When the
Identity Constant equal one, the expression A/B = 1, where A and B are
equivalent. If the Identity Constant relative to A is greater than one, A/B > 1, and
the Identity Constant relative to B is less than one, B/A < 1, then A is greater than
B and B is less than A.

VI. Existics Equations (Basic)

Where N is the number of units of time A experiences relative to one unit of time
for B, and U is the number of units of time B experiences relative to one unit of
time for A. If A and B are the same age, and therefore experience the passage of
time at the same rate, the N and U would both equal 1.

20

However, within our framework, there are an infinite number of relative frames
of reference, so we shall account for this in the following way: relative to A, there
is a B, relative to that B there is another A, and relative to that A there is another
B; ad infinitum. The same can be said for B.
We can interpret this as a slight shift more into the future for A, and a slight shift
more into the past for B. Using the ratios A/B and B/A to find the invariance
between the infinite relative frames of reference between A and B, we will
expand the ratios A/B and B/A into the following continued fractions:

(A)B)A)B)A)B) arithmetically represented as A over B, relative to A, over B,


relative to A, over B, etc.

(B)A)B)A)B)A) arithmetically represented as B over A, relative to B, over A,


relative to B, over A, etc.

N' is the extension given to A, and U' is the retraction take from B. Taking infinite
relative frames of reference into account, we will let the continued fraction
relative to A equal some number N*, and we will let the continued fraction
relative to B equal some number U*. As the continued fraction is expanded
infinitely, we will let N' approach N* and U' approach U*.

21

At the limit, or when the fraction has been carried out infinitely;
N' = N*, and U' = U*.

(where B >1)

We now have N* and U* which accounts for infinite relative frames of reference
between two individuals engaged in some kind of interaction. Since N* and U* do
not multiply to equal 1, we will let their sum equal some number I, the Identity
Constant, which almost equals 1. If A and B experienced the same rate of the
passage of time, the N* would equal N which would equal 1, and U* would equal
U which would equal 1. In this case, the Identity Constant is one: I = 1. When A
and B have the same identity, or experience the same rate of the passage of time,
they are one and the same individual. Therefore I, the identity constant,
quantifies the variance in rate between two different individuals separate
experiences of the passage of time from that of two individuals experiencing the
passage of time at the same rate.

22

In order to construct an equation that allows us to calculate where in time A and


B exist in relative to one another, we must take notice of the following: whenever
we divide a larger number by a smaller number, and the numbers are relatively
close in value, we get some number close in value to 1; like 1.347, 1.216, etc. We
know that two people close to the same age, i.e. experiencing nearly the same
rate of the passage of time, would have ratios like 100/99 = N and 99/100 = U.
The closer the experience in the passage of time, the closer N and U go towards
being some fraction away from one.
For these reasons, we must subtract away from N a number close to 1 in order to
add some number to A to get the value A* representing where in the future A is
relative to B. Likewise, we must subtract U away from a number close to 1 in
order to subtract some number from B to get the value B* representing where B
is in the past relative to A.
However, we are working with infinite relative frames of reference between A
and B, so we must use N*, U*, and I rather than N, U, and 1.

When A comes to experience some particular moment during some given event,
B is in the past (B*) relative to A. When B come to experience that particular
moment during the same given event, A is in the future (A*) relative to B.
Example:
Suppose we have two people: person A, who is 100 years old; and person B, who
is 20 years old.
A = 100
B =20
23

From this we obtain:

At the event relative to A, (A)A is 100 units of age, (B)A is 20 units of age, and (B)B
is 19.1559 units of age. As (B)B progresses towards being 20 units of age, and
(A)B is 100 units of age, (A)A progresses towards being 104.2211 units of age.
Once (B)B is 20 units of age and progresses towards 20.1980 units of age, (A)A
progresses towards 105.2632 units of age.

24

Therefore, we can deduce from the preceding equations the following


information:
Approximately 1 unit of time relative to person B equals 5.2632 units of time
relative to person A. Approximately 1 unit of time relative to person A equals
0.1980 units of time relative to person B. At the instantaneous superposition of
both events (relative to A and relative to B) (A)A is 4.2211 units of time ahead,
and (B)B is 0.8441 units of time behind.

If we graph this information, designating A as the y-coordinate and B as the xcoordinate, we find that there are two curves and a line. The single line with a
slope A/B represents linear time. Time relative to A is represented by the
hyperbolic curve extending down from (0, ), reaching a minimum, and then
extending asymptotically back up towards the linear time line in a positive
25

direction. Time relative to B is represented by the curve extending off of the yaxis at some finite point, making a slightly tilted bell-curve, and then progressing
asymptotically towards the linear time line in a positive direction. All three time
lines (curves) converge at infinity.
Note: When B is approximately at the midpoint along the bell-curve, and A is
approximately at the minimum point, A/B approximately equals 2, and B/A
approximately equals 1/2. When A is roughly twice the age of B, and B is roughly
half the age of A, A* passes through a point with the least relativistic age with the
most distance away from linear time, and B* reaches it maximum point away
from linear time.

In other words, A and B begin to converge towards having the same age, and
experiencing the same rate of the passage of time. The interesting bulge in the
curve of B has to do with the transformation for A*. There is a center of time
frame of reference, namely when A and B interact in linear time. A and B extend
26

away from linear time along their respective curves towards the minimum
number of intermediary states, and towards the maximum amount of time
variance (see intermediary frames of reference).

Examine the equation:

Notice that B must be greater than 1. Surely these equations must be able to
account for variance in relative time using figures like 0.75, or 0.001 . How is this
issue to be dealt with?
Multiply A and B by some common number, that is the minimum value great
enough so that (B -1)>0.

Then when equations have been solved for A* and B*, you can then factor and
return the values to the original units.

This solution could also be used for ratios that are so large, the difference
between A and B is too great to calculate A* and B* without some alteration to
the equations.
However, it can be imagined very quickly that there could exist ratios so large or
small that the common factor trick no longer works as a good tool for
approximation. At this point a new concept must be introduced.

27

VII. Intermediary Frames of Reference

We can imagine A and B having extremely variant experiences of the rate of the
passage of time and between A and B there exist others, such as C, D, E, ... etc.,
such that the experience of the rate of the passage of time relative to the others
sequences between A's and B's variant rates. For instance, in terms of rate:
A>G>F>E>D>C>B. The ratio between A:G, G:F, F:E, E:D, D:C, C:B are such that
each of them is to its neighbor close enough to avoid anomalies in the equations.
Before we answer the obvious question (what number of intermediaries?), let us
first better define what is meant by intermediary frames of reference.

We are going to introduce a new notation to distinguish between using


intermediaries and no intermediaries. Instead of using A and B for our two
different subjects, we shall adopt the notation: , , , , , ..., .
will
represent the one experiencing the 'fastest rate' as the initial, and
will
represent the one experiencing the 'slowest rate' as the final in a series or
sequence of subjects, from initial (fastest) to final (slowest) where n-1 represent
the number of intermediaries between
and
. In other words, , , , ...,
are intermediary subjects between
and . Therefore,
reference of ,
relative to reference of , relative to reference of , relative to
reference of , etc., can be used to intermediate the variance in time between
and
relative to . Also,
reference of
, relative to
reference of
, relative to
reference of
, relative to
reference of
, etc. can be used
to intermediate the variance in time between
and
relative to .
Example:
Let

= 100,000, and let

We will use

= 2.1
as intermediaries.

28

Let:

= 10,000

We must first find

= 1000

relative to

= 100

= 10

, via the intermediaries

Find the following:

First:

29

Next:

Next:

30

Next:

Finally:

31

We have solved for


we must solve for

relative to , via the intermediaries , , , . Now


relative to , via the intermediaries , , , .

Find the following:

First:

32

Next:

Next:

33

Next:

Finally:

34

Therefore:

We can summaries these equations as the following:

We can define intermediary frames of reference as the following:

35

Now it is the time to answer the question yet not asked: How many
intermediaries are necessary in order to make the equations exact, rather than
approximations? We need to find a maximum and minimum number of
intermediaries, and then we can use this information to make the equations
precise. The maximum number of intermediaries will be the limit as n approaches
all possible values between
and . The minimum number of intermediaries
will be determined by the limit that B is greater than 1.

If we look at the problem at hand very closely, namely finding the maximum
number of intermediaries between
and , we realize that this is actual a
continuum problem. In other words, to even solve the question at hand, we must
refer to the Calculus to know what the ultimate limit is that n approaches.
Referring to the limit as defined in C3, where zero is the power set of the infinites,
zero is its own reciprocal, zero lies at both ends of the continuum, and zero is the
ultimate limit of intermediaries between two subjects.
When we solve for
, the initial value and the initial intermediary are so
close, that in fact they are the same value. Since they are the same value, N*=1,
and U*=1. Likewise, when we solve for
, the final value and the final
intermediary are so close, that in fact they are the same value. Since they are the
same value, N*=1, and U*=1. With the maximum number of intermediaries, there
is no variance in relative time; rather, the maximum number if intermediaries
represents linear time without variance.

Therefore:

36

Since the identity constant is 1, there are no relative frames of reference.


Therefore, in the case of the maximum number of intermediaries, both subjects
exist in the same frame of reference; linear time.
Consequently, linear time is the expression equivalent to the limit of all possible
rational experiences between at least two subjects in a one to one
correspondence, as the limit approaches the maximum number of intermediaries.

We can define maximum and minimum intermediary frames of reference as:

Now it is possible to construct a proper equation that integrates the values from
maximum to minimum and gives us the curves for two or more subjects.

37

The curve relative to A and the curve relative to B both exist in two dimensions of
time: future-past (x-coordinate) and positive-negative rate of change ( ycoordinate). What must be stressed is that in both of these curves of time A and
B do not intersect; only in linear time that we find A and B intersecting.
Therefore, it must be concluded that there is a third dimension of time. If we
examine this idea of linear time, we see that it intersects the present time in
sequences of different present moments, or it intersects periods of the same
present. If the rate of the passage of time is designated as the y-coordinate, if the
sequential periods of linear time are designated as the x-coordinate, then the
third dimension of time is designated as the z-coordinate: a dimension of the
present; a perpetual present tense. Re-thinking this idea, it becomes intuitive, yet
striking to acknowledge that time has three dimensions just as space. This new
addition to the symmetry between space and time gives space/time a sixdimensional basis.

38

You might also like