The Spontaneous Order: A Contribution To Hayek's Liberalism?

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 38

POL3046: Dissertation in Politics

Name: Craig Johnson


Title: The Spontaneous Order: A Contribution to Hayeks Liberalism?
Student number: 092729535
Advisor: Professor Peter Jones
Submitted: April 2012

SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF BACHELOR OF


ARTS IN POLITICS

SCHOOL OF GEOGRAPHY, POLITICS AND SOCIOLOGY

CRAIG JOHNSON1
THE SPONTANEOUS ORDER: A CONTRIBUTION TO HAYEKS LIBERALISM

ABSTRACT
This paper considers Hayeks concept of the spontaneous order, and questions its contribution to his
liberalism. Many offer that the spontaneous order cements his place as a liberal or as a libertarian, whilst
others put forward that his scepticism of human reason and rational thought mark him as a conservative.
In this article, I put forward that Hayeks definition of the economy as a spontaneous order sits
comfortably as a doctrine of classical liberalism. However, his methods of analysing such spontaneity, and
his support for tradition and the limits of human understanding leave him with a conservative nature
similar in places to that of Michael Oakeshott. Following a detailed overview of the concept of the
spontaneous order, I assess Hayeks view of knowledge, rationalism and tradition, and place his thought
within the context of both liberalism and conservatism. The underlying message of this article is that
Hayeks social theory, like many before him, sits amongst the competing philosophies of liberalism and
conservatism.

CONTENTS

INTRODUCTION

THE SPONTANEOUS ORDER: A THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

RATIONALISM

14

HAYEKS CONSERVATIVE LIBERALISM

23

School of Geography, Politics and Sociology, University of Newcastle. This paper builds upon research
conducted in a module on liberal political thought, led by Dr David Walker. I am indebted to him for fuelling my
interest in Friedrich Hayek. I have also benefited greatly from the advice and supervision of Professor Peter
Jones, and thank him for his detailed and considered comments on sections of this paper.

INTRODUCTION

When Friedrich Hayek died in 1992, effusive tributes labelled him one of the great thinkers of the 20th
Century. The award of the Nobel Prize in Economics in 1974 represented a watershed for the
previously disillusioned thinker, whose economic and political thought had occupied a small share of
support compared to the rise of socialism and revisionism. Influenced by the thought of Immanuel Kant
(see Sullivan 1989) and Karl Popper (1945 and 1957)2, Hayek had continuously argued, previously to
little or no avail, that governments did not have the ability to manage economies, and that the results
for society would be disastrous if attempts to do so were realised. Hayek argues that the economic
market, and the formation of society that we know, has been formed spontaneously. This formation
should not be altered by a government intent on designing a different product. In this sense Hayek seeks
to defend the economic frameworks that have evolved over time. His writings represent a library of
work determined to rescue liberalism.

Throughout his career, Hayek contributed to many different academic disciplines, from economics and
psychology, through to political science and philosophy, never fully resting himself in one. In an era of
intellectual specialisation, he stood apart. He was a prolific writer unbounded by any longstanding
commitments to public policy or governance, and his collection of work stands as one of the most
substantial contributions to modern liberalism since John Stuart Mill. As the spontaneous order, for
Hayek, is liberalisms central concept (Hayek 1967: 162), it is important to analyse the influence this
notion had on his liberal philosophy.

This paper will assess the extent to which the concept of the spontaneous order, guided by his view of
human nature, contributes to his liberalism. It will show that whilst there are undoubtedly strong
elements of his economic thought which are unquestionably liberal, his view of human reason and

The debate goes on about the true influences on Hayek. Popper and Kant were undoubtedly important in
Hayeks early work, but Forsyth (1988: 238-241) suggests that Hayeks thought is un-Kantian in its nature, and
equates his thought more to the philosopher Ernst Mach, particularly for his work on the capability of the human
mind.

tradition leaves him susceptible to the criticism that he is a conservative, despite his strenuous efforts to
deny it3. Following an introduction to the context of this discussion, this paper will offer a detailed
analysis of Hayeks theory of the spontaneous order. It will demonstrate the relationship between his
concept of spontaneity, and his theories of knowledge, rationalism, and tradition. It will then question
the contribution of his spontaneous order to his liberalism. Hayek has long been regarded as a liberal,
seeking to offer a theory of philosophy more resonant with the values offered by the classical liberal
generation, before the rise of socialism and revisionism. However, many of the positions he defends can
often be identified with a conservative view of society rather than a liberal one. This paper concludes by
arguing that Hayeks spontaneous order, whilst contributing to his liberalism, offers an amalgamation of
conservative and liberal political thought.

Despite the rising nature of his profile, Hayek has received relatively little critical analysis. It is still
suggested that Hayek is more of an ideologue than a social theorist (see Downing and Thigpen 1984).
Consequently, he is often labelled as nothing more than a classical liberal who is unable to construct a
coherent political theory applicable to modern society. In assessing Hayeks contribution to liberalism,
this paper will dispel many of the myths that have arisen about Hayek. The rise of economic liberalism
in the 1980s in Britain and America, led by the New Right movement, suggested that the very ideas for
which he had been criticised were now being realised and supported, and subsequently improved his
standing as a philosopher and social theorist. However, since his name was used to provide intellectual
credibility and inspiration to the governing creeds of Thatcherism and other New Right movements, it
is perhaps inevitable that many of the ideas associated with the New Right wrongly became affiliated
with him. Whilst this improved his public standing, it also committed his philosophy to association with
an ideological stereotype far distant from the ideas that he was advocating. A brief assessment of the
Thatcher government represents a commitment to intervention. Whilst radically different from the

See Hayek (1960: 519-535) for a detailed postscript chapter entitled Why I am not a conservative. The use of
criticism to imply conservatism in his thought is to echo his personal feelings towards the notion.

interventions of socialist and revisionist governments before, it still embodied a government of radical
intervention4.

Hayek developed the concept of the spontaneous order as a means of explaining how society could
operate peacefully. Whilst not his own creation, it is ubiquitous throughout his social theory (Hunt and
McNamara 2007), and is the concept which underpins his theory of social justice, and from which he
seeks to promote and defend liberalism (Hayek 1982: 37) from the design arguments of socialism. He
uses the examples of law and legislation as a means of distinguishing between spontaneity and design.
Law, on the one hand, has evolved spontaneously, consisting of a system of rules regulate society in an
abstract and general fashion. Whilst the law applies equally to all, it reflects the conventions that have
emerged instinctively over time through the assorted efforts of actors (Bellamy 1994: 421-422).
Legislation on the other hand belongs to a constructed order, with rules submitted to society for the
direct achievement of specific ends (Hayek 1973: ch. 2).

Hayek admits that it was once possible to have a society operated through a more consciously ordered
programme. In this context, he refers to the former small scale agricultural societies, where this may
have been conceivable. However, now society has evolved to become a Great Society5, and to attempt
to plan these through legislation will inevitably fail, and descend a society into one of great inefficiency
and coercion. It is Hayeks view that the rise of socialism, followed by the evolution of social liberal
theory, led many thinkers to hold a harmful view of the power of human reason. They placed too much
faith in their ability to understand social knowledge and to order the way in which society should be
structured, instead of understanding the limits of human reason. It is from this premise that he offers his
concept of the spontaneous order, which will be fully explored in the following chapter.
4

This is not to suggest that Hayek himself was against radical intervention. However, Thatcher often intervened
in ways that made the state larger. Hayek would never support such action. This debate often features the terms
enterprise association and civic association, labels used predominantly by the conservative thinker Michael
Oakeshott. Hayek disagreed with Oakeshott and said that the state was an enterprise association, but one which
must be kept strictly limited to perform its purpose, which was provide only a framework for the market
mechanism to take place. The similarities of Hayeks later writings with Oakeshott warrants much greater
inspection, but will be discussed briefly in the latter stages of this paper.
5
Hayek compares his conception of the Great Society to Poppers Open Society. For a more detailed analysis
of this relationship, see Rowland (1988) and Vernon (1976).

THE SPONTANEOUS ORDER: A THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

Order represents the way in which things exist. For Hayek, order is:

a state of affairs in which a multiplicity of elements of various kinds are so related


to each other that we may learn from our acquaintance with some spatial or temporal
part of the whole to form correct explanations concerning the rest, or at least
expectations which have a good chance of proving correct (Hayek 1973: 36).

Orders can be designed. Businesses exist by being ordered by method of design. People create them
from the outset, and employ other people to perform certain tasks specifically to contribute to that
business order. Alternatively, orders can be formed without design, caused instead by the collaboration
of elements. Whilst the conditions can be created to benefit the generation of such orders, an intended
method of design cannot be applied. They are created spontaneously, an ideal which can be applied
extensively across our society. Frameworks of morality that we follow, or concepts of law that we
accept, have evolved through generations of change and adaptation. Whilst they appear to us as
structured edifices, man has never been solely capable of the conception of such a framework applicable
to, and accepted by society. Such structures were not designed in any process of unvarying continuity,
but have undergone a permanent process of change, as adaptation to such structures takes place.

Hayek puts forward that the order of society is the product of forces not of the control of man, but at
the mercy of spontaneity. It is an order of events that are not the product of specific human intention,
but with the order of events that are the product of human action (Barry 1982: 7-8). The spontaneous
order arises out of the multifarious practices of a wide group of actors, each unaware of the direct
intention of the other. Knowledge arises in a process of experimental interaction of widely dispersed,
different and even conflicting beliefs of millions of communicating individuals (Hayek 1988: 80).
Hayek argues that knowledge is intrinsically hostile to organised assembly, and a mechanism is required
to ensure that knowledge can be most usefully capitalised upon (Connin 1990: 309-310). This
mechanism is the spontaneous order.

In its most humble form, the spontaneous order represents the notion that individuals are restrained by
rules of conduct not designed by individual human mind. The rules of conduct are generated naturally
over time through the evolution of institutions and through a process of selection based on their success.
The selection process is not specific, but more a general acceptance by society. Human wisdom cannot
decide this, but more the ultimate decision about what is good or bad will be made by the decline of
groups that have adhered to the wrong beliefs (Hayek 1960: 36).

The concept of the spontaneous order was not coined by Hayek. He traces the concept back to the
writings of Bernard Mandeville in the early 18th Century, and was committed to the cause of developing
this theory. He even offered new terms which he felt more accurately described the nature of the order
he was describing. For Hayek, the typical language used previously in economic and social theory
exhibited a socialist bias, engrained in the available vocabulary. Hayeks analysis instead offers a battery
of concepts, often twinned with others. For instance, economy implies that each of the actors within
an entire order share a specific goal, something Hayek strenuously denies. Instead, he offers the term
catallaxy, which is more the result of individual economies adjusting to a spontaneous order (Hayek
1976: 108).

Original terms are also used for Hayeks concepts of order: taxis and kosmos (Hayek 1973: 36-38).
A taxis represents an object of human design, with a single source of authority, which is rarely
compromised (Gamble 1996: 37)6. A kosmos on the other hand represents spontaneity; an order not
consciously designed or created. Some have misinterpreted Hayeks differentiations (see Barry 1984) to
mean that Hayek is against taxis as a rule. This isnt true. He is not against single authority, designed
institutions, but opposes the attempt of evolving this element of design into a construction of a social
order. This is an important distinction and one which Hayek develops in his critique of socialism.

Hayek fails to acknowledge here, and throughout his writings, that authority can be exercised in manners other
than hierarchical. In doing so, he ignores the possibility of more democratic methods of authority.

Hayek is in fact enthusiastic for the organised factory system. He supports the infliction of authority
upon the work-force. His view of the Great Society contains many taxis, organised from the top down
and enacting a planned and coordinated model of practice. However, they are only able to do this freely
because the society within which they operate does not have a taxis at its centre. The development of
society to this point was dependent upon no single authority or will, but instead the experimentation of
individuals. Often, the experimentation will not have been successful, and will have failed, but it is the
experimentation that is successful that makes the Great Society. Without a kosmos, but a taxis, society
would never be able to allow such experimentation.

Hayeks most prevalent example of a kosmos is the spontaneous market order, or catallaxy. It isnt
perfect. It is Hayeks objective that this can and will never be the case. It is the correct order for society
precisely because it is imperfect, and fragmented to account for each individual. It cannot be attributed
to Hayeks earlier writings on general equilibrium7, but more to the aim of uncertainty.

The market order in particular will regularly secure only a certain probability that
the expected relations will prevail, but it is, nevertheless, the only way in which so
many activities depending on dispersed knowledge can be effectively integrated into
a single order (Hayek 1973: 42).
The aim of the market order is to cope with the inevitable ignorance of
everybody of most of the particular facts which determine this order. By a process
which men did not understand, their activities have produced an order much more
extensive and comprehensive than anything they could have comprehended, but on
the functioning of which we have become utterly dependent (Hayek 1983: 19).

What becomes important for Hayek is the observation of rules of conduct. These rules need not be
commanded, but present to allow the will of individuals participating in society to come to fruition
(Gamble 1996: 38)8.
7

In a speech in 1936, Hayek defines equilibrium as "the different plans which the individuals composing [a
society] have made for action in time are mutually compatible" (Hayek 1937 (reprinted in Hayek 1952): 41).
Hayek was not seeking to achieve equilibrium, but more to ascertain if the market process created a tendency
towards equilibrium.
8
Hayeks assertion of the qualities of the spontaneous order can be challenged here. Is the spontaneous order
really the best method of utilising dispersed knowledge? If a health emergency within society (such as a flu
epidemic or something similar) was to occur, the spontaneous forces of society would surely struggle to cope and

MARKETS

Hayeks theory of the spontaneous order arises from his study of economics. His account of the organic
nature of human development and decline represents a submission of faith to the market. Rowland
(1988: 224-225) goes further to label it blind submission. Hayek (1944: 17-19) argues that mans
submission to the market, and its impersonal nature, has allowed individuals to adjust to changes which
they cannot understand, and themselves within society have evolved as a consequence. Hayek (1933)
sought to address how human action could be coordinated without a central controlling authority,
building upon the work of Menger (1883) and Mises (1936). He developed a fascination with
spontaneity and order in response to the more interventionist ideas forward by Keynes and Lange.

Oskar Lange, like the Austrian economists, also sought to address what Mises considered the key
weakness of socialism: how an absence of a market for capital goods and for production would reflect
what enterprises in the consumer sector required (Gamble 1996: 64-66). Lange proposed that a central
board would be able to set prices for capital goods, which would trigger a response from enterprises,
and prices would be adjusted through trial and error, depending upon the performance of the economy.
In essence, socialism for Lange was maintaining the principles of economic calculation that had arisen
under market conditions, but replacing the mechanism for carrying out its function9. Implicit in Langes
work was that, since market economies were renowned for being inefficient, socialism may actually

respond to the situation effectively? Governments on the other hand are able to fund research into a cure, issue
information quickly to the public via national media outlets and broadcasters, and provide helpful information. As
Kley (1994: 121-122) points out, it is unlikely that the will of each individual within the catallaxy for large parts
of society to be killed.
9
Langes work represents part of a growing trend at the time of responding to Mises claim that socialism simply
was not possible. Langes work was aided by the work of non-socialist economists who were simply keen to
explore whether Mises claim could be upheld; in particular, Vilfredo Pareto and Enrico Barone (see Schumpeter
1950), who displayed signs more of intrigue than of support for socialism. Both demonstrated a socialist economy
was theoretically possible, so long as the cost of production was as low as possible, and that prices were equated
to the cost of production. Lange began from this premise to counter Mises theory.

achieve something close to general equilibrium between supply and demand, and a flexible set of prices
as a result (Gamble 1996: 66)10.

Hayeks contribution to the debate of economic calculation aimed to demonstrate that the arguments of
Lange and Schumpeter were wrong, and that working from the assumptions of neoclassical economics
was the wrong method by which to approach this discussion. In doing so, he developed a theory of
social knowledge which perhaps stands as his most important contribution to social science11, and builds
upon the work of the Scottish school, encompassing philosophers such as David Hume, Bernard De
Mandeville and Edmund Burke, and the Austrian school. Key insights of the Austrian school become
evident in Hayeks thought: first, that knowledge is always imperfect in human societies, and second,
that the cost of any economic activity is subjective (Gamble 1996: 67). Hayeks own work refines these
insights, warning that society must cope with ignorance, and recognise that the only things which can
help us are the evolved institutions of the market, the rule of law and limited government (Connin
1990: 300). The only way in which the entire knowledge of society can be collected is through the
market, bringing it together into some coordinated form.

Hayeks thought represents a commitment to the epistemological foundations of political thought. In


defending the principles of ignorance from a liberal perspective, he is using a theory of social knowledge
as an explanation for the social and political landscape we encounter. In doing so, his theory of
knowledge demonstrates Kantian ideals (Gray 1986: 4-8):

What I contend, in short, is that the mind must be capable of performing abstract
operations in order to perceive particulars, and that this capacity appears long before
we can speak of conscious awareness of particulars. When we want to explain what
makes us tick, we must start with the abstract relations governing the order which, as
a whole, gives particulars their distinct place (Hayek 1978: 36-37).

10

The demonstration of arguments by Lange and Barone led commentators such as Charles Lindblom (1965) and
Joseph Schumpeter (1950) to conclude that socialism had won this particular debate. Whatever its merits,
socialism was possible.
11
There can be no doubt that the spontaneous order provides the largest contribution to Hayeks writings, but
the more original nature of Hayeks theory of knowledge suggests a greater importance.

10

Evolving from his work in The Sensory Order (Hayek 1952), Hayek agrees with Kant in recognising the
ability of the mind to perceive external stimuli. However, he suggests that our classificatory is further
defined by our impulses and experiences, which are received by our sensory order. It is this which
determines us from other individuals: the uniqueness of our individual experiences, and their
subsequent classification. The theory of the mind acts as a genesis for the further theoretical approaches
that Hayek develops elsewhere (Connin 1990: 302).

In society, knowledge is ultimately fragmented. It is the combined knowledge of each person in society
that makes society work. A modern economy can only work if it can cope with the fragmentation of
knowledge (Hayek 1973: 14).

The economic problem of society is thus not merely a problem of how to allocate
given resources if given is taken to mean given to a single mind which
deliberately solves the problem set by these data. It is rather a problem of how to
secure the best use of resources known to any of the members of society, for ends
whose relative importance only these individuals know. Or, to put it briefly, it is a
problem of the utilisation of knowledge, which is not given to anyone in its totality
(Hayek 1948: 77-78).

Nobody can know, in any entirety, what members preferences and choices are. Nor can they know
which kinds of things or services are wanted, and how urgently they are wanted (Hayek 1978: 182).
To respond to Langes (and others) comments, Hayek maintains that even if a central organisation knew
all that was required to detail the preferences of individuals, it would not be able to organise an
economy efficiently (Kley 1994: 50-51). Lack of knowledge of each local economy, and each individual
economy, would make any kind of knowledge gathering futile. Along with this ultimate dilemma,
Hayeks theory of knowledge has a temporal dimension. Even if we were to accept that sufficient
knowledge could be gathered to warrant a painstaking collection process, the fugacity of such data
would lag behind reality to such an extent it would be rendered worthless. A solution to this problem
for Hayek is not possible due to the embryonic nature of relevant knowledge. Once it has been
discovered, it will already have served its purpose. Once collected, the purpose has passed.

11

Hayeks critique of perfect knowledge is at the heart of his critique of socialism. The market is not
something to be praised for because of its greater efficiency or user satisfaction; the market is to be
praised because it is the only means by which the correct conditions can be set for society to be ordered.
The market is imperfect, in the same way that human knowledge is imperfect. The market is simply less
imperfect than anything else (certainly socialism).

The market itself was something which had developed, according to Hayek, spontaneously. It was a
natural phenomenon that had evolved without planning (Gamble 1996: 68). The role of government, or
whatever the title of the central authority, was not to fashion how the market should operate, or
propose grand claims as to what goals it should achieve, but simply to ensure that the basic conditions
are in places so it can function effectively. Basic conditions include the protection of property and the
maintenance of contracts. It can certainly be said at this juncture that Hayeks analysis of the emergence
of the market is misleading at best; false at worst. States have often being prolific in their ability to
maintain and strengthen the market economy. Whilst some of the market has undoubtedly arisen
spontaneously, it is not a universally natural evolution.

Economic history reveals that the emergence of national markets was in no way the
result of the gradual and spontaneous emancipation of the economic sphere from
governmental control. On the contrary, the market has been the outcome of a
conscious and often violent intervention on the part of government (Polanyi 1944:
258).

Whilst the strength of Polanyis argument can be discussed elsewhere, the potency of his underlying
point is undeniable. As the market order has evolved throughout history, particularly during Hayek's
conception of the Great Society, it has been assisted and strengthened by the actions of various and
successive governments. When Hayek and the Scottish school devote their time to analysis of the free
market and the promotion of its ideals, they often do so in the hope of ensuring its longevity (Hodgson
1984).

12

In spite of this analysis, Hayek argued against attempts to simulate the character of the market, as its key
character was spontaneity. For Hayek, the market is a process of discovery, and the only means of
achieving this process is through competition. This position was shared by fellow supporters of
capitalism such as Mises, but also by Marx. Marx viewed competition as necessary for creating and
maintaining insecurity. This was necessary to force companies and individuals to constantly drive down
expenditure and cut labour. This allowed actors to then provide stimulus for new products and new
industries (Gamble 1996: 71). Competition was the force that made capitalism productive12.
Competition was therefore the result of spontaneity, and necessary for maintaining the market order as
it stood. Competition led to coordination of the market and of the complex economy that existed13.
This chapter has demonstrated Hayeks theory of the spontaneous order within the context of
knowledge and the economy. However, as the concept of spontaneity is ubiquitous within Hayeks
thought, there are other notions and ideas which need to be explored to fully understand Hayeks
political philosophy. The following chapter will explore Hayeks theories of rationalism and tradition.

12

Much of the Marxist analysis of competition was shared by Mises. The obvious difference was that Marx
thought that capitalism was the transitory process to socialism. Mises, and Hayek subsequently, maintained that
this was as good as it got.
13
Hayeks unfailing support for competition conflicts with the wider experiences of society, and it is a conflict
which he never truly resolves. Hayeks assertion that the market economy would continue to allow individuals to
make full use of the knowledge known only to them, and subsequently encourage further competition, was and
has not being realised in practice. Instead, there has been an increasing emergence of monopolies, each centrally
organised and limiting competition and individual participation in the economy (Gamble 1996: 72-73). Many
liberals urged political action to limit this rise of monopoly companies. Hayek (1960: 264-267) was not one of
them, insisting that there was no coercion by these organisations, and that they were in fact the embodiment of
competition.

13

Rationalism

Hayek commonly puts forward arguments in terms of dichotomies. Many of the concepts within his
thought can be set out as polarities:

kosmos
catalaxxy
spontaneity
freedom
abstract
justice

taxis;
economy
organisation
coercion
concrete
social justice

These concepts represent a key argument of Hayek: that society has been formed spontaneously,
through a process of unplanned development. The tenets on the left hand side of the polarity represent
liberalism for Hayek; the right represents rationalism. His own stance is to staunchly argue against
rationalism. Whilst influential on events, human reason can never be in control of their environment,
or attempt to design a better one (Gamble 1996: 31-32). They can make small improvements, but
anything more is doomed to fail. Rationalism for Hayek comes in two forms, and could be placed on the
list of dichotomies above: constructivist rationalism and evolutionary rationalism.

Constructivist rationalism comprises three underlying features. It presupposes firstly that all social
institutions are, and ought to be, the product of deliberate design (Hayek 1973: 5). It assumes secondly
that reason is a sufficient tool by which to know how to shape the institutions of the social order
according to the preferences of the humans who comprise its membership (Hayek 1973: 29-33). Its
final aspect contests that existing institutions are not capable of achieving the ends that are possible.
Constructivism, Hayek argues, insists that institutions not visibly serving approved ends should be
discarded (Hayek 1978: 13)14

14

This third tenet of constructivism will be explored in more detail in the section entitled Tradition.

14

Constructivist rationalists would not be inhibited by caution, but would believe in the power of human
reason to propose untried and untested practices and institutions for the perceived good of society. This
brand of social thought was developed primarily by philosophers from the French tradition, namely
Descartes, Rousseau and Comte. It is also present in the utilitarianism offered by Jeremy Bentham. For
Hayek, it is not difficult to find the similarity between these traditions and the ideas offered by the
socialists and New Liberals of a more contemporary time.

Hayeks theory of knowledge (or lack thereof) clashes with these ideas. Hayek contends that it is not
possible to achieve the aims and objectives that those of constructivism seek to realise. The acquisition
of such knowledge is not conceivable. Hayeks Nobel laureate address stressed this very principle,
claiming that the thinkers of the French tradition had begun from the belief that we possess the
knowledge and the power which enables us to shape the processes of society to our liking, knowledge
which in fact we do not possess (Hayek 1978: 33). The knowledge, for Hayek, that is required to be
able to control the conclusions of events we wish to order is simply not able to be obtained. Social
knowledge is unlike the knowledge of the natural sciences; it is fragmented, dispersed and ultimately
subjective; belonging to and making sense only to each particular agent (Connin 1990: 299).

Evolutionary rationalism allows change, but in a manner which promotes caution. It promotes change
only in incremental form. The concern for the evolutionary rationalist is how society has developed.
Those in favour of evolutionary rationalism were able to maintain a healthy dose of scepticism in a time
when the power of reason was becoming ever more appealing. Their insights stand parallel to Hayeks
concept of the spontaneous order. They identified that society was the product not of human design,
but of human action. The best practices were of spontaneous evolution. They were not from the
designing mind of a creator, who could not be aware of the intricate details of each individuals
circumstances. Only spontaneous evolution could facilitate each specific circumstance into an order able
to be maintained. For Hayek, we are guided (or even operated) by rules of which we are not aware,
and conscious reason can therefore always only take account only of some of the circumstances which
determine our actions (Hayek 1967: 87).

15

The philosophers of the Scottish school were the first to recognise the value of spontaneity. Orders that
arose by a process of evolution were such that they enabled actors to experiment and try new methods
of creativity. Some would be unsuccessful, clearly, but those that worked would be accepted by general
society, and would be developed to improve the way in which the common order operated. The
Scottish philosophers, housing theorists such as Adam Smith and David Hume, argued that the best
outcomes in economics and in society had evolved in the absence of central planning. Hayek (1967: 87)
pays particular tribute to David Hume, sharing the view that whilst reason has role, it is a limited role.
It serves our values but does not determine them, and coincides with Humes view that the rules of
morality are not the conclusions of our reason (Hume 1739 (1978): 454). Hayek also dedicates a great
deal of time and attention to Bernard De Mandeville15. Mandeville observed a disjunction between
individual behaviour and social outcomes. Instead of arguing for a control of private lives to ensure the
public good, Mandeville observed that the public good would only be realised if individuals were able to
pursue their own private vices16.

Whilst Hayek claims to be an anti-rationalist, this does not mean that he is irrational. He is against
constructivist rationalism. He discusses the theft of the term rationalism from the true liberal thinkers
by those who placed greater faith in the capacity of human reason than him. Those who did not agree
with their views on the proper use of reason should have been labelled anti-rationalists (Hayek 1967:
84). Rationalists see human reason in all human behaviour, and argue for a remodelling of society
according to rational criteria (Gamble 1996: 32). Hayek says that this is a fallacy, and that constructivism
represents the error that society has been designed by some rational mind. In arguing this point, Hayek
commits himself more to the ideas of Mandeville, Hume and Burke, than to the propositions of
constructivism. For the latter, order is imposed upon the world by the exercise of reason. For Hayek,
this is a dangerous premise, and false. The mind is as much a force of spontaneity as society is, and our

15

See Hayek (1978: ch. 15).


As Gamble (1996: 33-34) notes, Mandevilles insight can be seen as constructivist thinking. Hayek prefers to
draw upon his work as a reinforcement of his own view about the lack of available knowledge of what is good for
society.
16

16

ideas are merely the visible exfoliation of spontaneous forces (Gray 1986 (1998): 30). Constructivism
mistakenly neglects the primacy of spontaneity over reason within the mind, and in doing so wrongly
combines tacit and explicit knowledge. Reason is not capable of performing the role of design in this
context. Constructivism wrongly claims that it is17.

Hayek continues to stress that he is not against reason as a concept. He refers back to the damage that
those philosophers have caused by not recognising the limits of individual reason18. He argues that reason
has lost its meaning, and was changed during that period, from one which understood a capacity to
recognise the capacity of truth, evolving to one which sought to deduce reasons from explicit premises
(Hayek 1967: 84-85). It is from this point that Hayek defines their concept of reason as rationalist
constructivism, and couples it with his use of scientism which he first used in 1952.

17

This view of rationalism places Hayek in a rather difficult and tangled position. Often this debate becomes
simplified to the notions of planning and free markets. Hayek does not accept this view. For Hayek, the
supporters of the free market still support planning, but planning of individual lives as much as is possible.
Hayeks position of the worthiness of design relates to the comprehensiveness of the objectives that are being
proposed. The market economy was still a product of planning, but planning at an individual and autonomous
level. The following quote from Hayek (1978: 234) summarises this view:
Planning is popular because it means that we should use as much foresight as we can command. In this sense
everybody who is not a complete fatalist is a planner but what our planners demand is a central direction of all
economic activity according to a single plan, laying down how the resources of society should be consciously
directed to serve particular ends in a definite way. The dispute between the modern planners and their
opponents is, therefore, not a dispute on whether we ought to choose inteliigently between the various possible
organisations of society; it is a dispute about what is the best way of employing foresight and systematic
thinking in planning our common affairs. The question is whether for this purpose it is better that the holder of
coercive power should confine himself in general to creating conditions under which the knowledge and initiative
of individuals are given the best scope so that they can plan most successfully or whether a rational utilization of
our resources requires central direction and organization of all our activities according to some consciously
constructed blueprint.
Rowland (1988: 227-228) defines this as individual constructivism. Hayek (1948: 19-22) himself likens this
section of his thought to the liberal individualist aspect: the theory of individualism contributes to techniques of
constructing a suitable legal framework and of improving the institutions which have grown up spontaneously it
allows almost unlimited scope to human ingenuity in the designing of the most effective set of rules. It is at the
least dubious to claim that this form of constructivism is so radically separate from the very people he criticises.
18
He singles out Rene Descartes at this particular moment (Hayek 1967: 84).

17

Rationalism in this sense is the doctrine which assumes that all institutions which
benefit humanity have in the past and ought in the future to be invented in clear
awareness of the desirable effects that they produce; that they are approved and
respected only to the extent that we can show that the particular effects they will
produce in any given situation are preferable to the effects another arrangement
would produce; that we have it in our power so to shape our institutions that of all
possible sets of results that which we prefer to all others will be realised; and that our
reason should never resort to automatic or mechanical devices when conscious
considerations of all factors would make preferable an outcome different from that of
the spontaneous process. It is from this kind of social rationalism or constructivism
that all modern socialism, planning and totalitarianism derives (Hayek 1967: 85).

The theoretical attempts of Lange and others to centralise knowledge is an example of constructivist
thinking. Working from a neoclassical approach to economics, Hayek was unable to firmly decompose
the arguments of those against Mises. Hayek admitted that conventional economic approaches could
support socialism, but it was the conventional approaches that Hayek was aiming to critique; they had
abandoned the concept of the market order.

TRADITION

In order to ensure that political philosophy can offer more than wishful thinking and irrelevant
rationalism, Hayek believes that we need a correct understanding of how the social order operates and
the limitations of human beings to alter it. Hayeks lifelong research leads him to the conclusion that the
spontaneous order is the only concept capable of accounting for both the restrictions and possibilities of
society. Hayeks justification of the spontaneous order is both a promotion of its qualities and a defence
of its existence. Kley (1994: 185) labels the first the proceduralist argument and the second the
traditionalist argument19. The proceduralist argument was explored in this paper through Hayeks
account of the market mechanism. Only a market can co-ordinate each individual economy and secure

19

Hayek himself does not distinguish between these two arguments. Kleys distinction is not perfect; Hayeks
concepts each overlap and can be viewed as an overall coherent theory. However, the distinction between the
proceduralist and traditionalist arguments is a useful one, as they provide a premise for the inconsistencies in
Hayeks political philosophy, which will be explored later in this paper.

18

prosperity (in a general sense) and a peaceful outcome. The traditionalist argument is explored in this
segment.

The traditionalist argument that Hayek advances builds upon the evolutionary rationalism that was the
explored in the previous section. Hayek rejects what I outlined as the third tenet of constructivism: that
the worth of an institution should be judged upon it existing as a rational means to a defined end20.
Hayek rejects this requirement of an institution, as he feels it would leave him powerless to present a
valid defence of the liberal order (Hayek 1988: 60-62 and 71). His rejection is based on two claims:
firstly that market institutions represent tacit embodiments of the accumulated experience of
consecutive generations, and secondly that the ignorance of each individual as to how a collective
catallaxy works means that we cannot defend explicitly what an institution has or can achieve (Kley
1994: 188): man has certainly more often learnt to do the right thing without comprehending why it
was the right thing, and he still is often served better by custom than understanding (Hayek 1973: 157).

This argument reiterates Rowlands view, referred to earlier, that Hayeks commitment to the market
represents a blind submission. For Hayek, the market is the only tool available to secure the wellbeing of the individual within the wider social order, repudiating why this needs to be so in the process.
His scepticism rules out any justification of the legality and morality of institutions.

that traditional morals, etc. are not rationally justifiable, this is also true of any
possible moral code, including any that socialists might ever be able to come up with.
Hence no matter what rules we follow, we will not be able to justify them as
demanded; so no argument about morals- or law- can legitimately turn on the
issue of justification (Hayek 1988: 68).

20

This is not to say that Hayek believes that institutions have no worth in terms of achieving ends, but more that
their achievements are more than can be explicitly explained.

19

The belief that justification is necessary is, for Hayek, one of the fundamental mistakes of constructivism
(Hayek 1988: 67). He rejects even that he is justifying it on the grounds that it enables us to survive.
This is not a justification, but merely a statement21.

Hayeks statement of the spontaneous order represents an attempt to describe the features of the
economic market mechanism. Attempts to alter the mechanism are what Hayek labels the fatal conceit
(1988). To suggest a course of sweeping reform is to put at risk the traditional rules which have evolved
over time and now possess a wisdom that the individual human mind cannot match. This then begs the
question as to how the market came into existence. Hayek attributes this to cultural evolution; an
invisible hand account of the social order. The market represents the product of a slow process of
evolution in the course of which much more experience and knowledge has been precipitated in them
than any one person can fully know (Hayek 1967: 92). The competitive nature arose from the process
in which practices which had first been adopted for other reasons, or even purely accidentally, were
preserved because they enabled the group in which they had arisen to prevail over others (Hayek 1973:
9). It is important to note the apparent random nature of this evolution. It was not due to rational choice
by public bodies, but more it was those groups who happened to fall (upon these practices that)
prospered and multiplied (Hayek 1983: 46). Far from selecting the rules and constraints of the market,
these constraints selected us: they enabled us to survive (Hayek 1988: 14).

As noted, Hayek does not ascribe an author to these rules. Whilst the market economy represents
genuine knowledge, it is not explicit, and is not based on some theory of cause and effect (Hayek
1978: 10). The rules of the market do not provide a historic account of the evolving interdependency of
man and society, but they prescribe general constraints that have proved most conducive to successful
individual agency (Kley 1994: 159). They are thus an adaptation to a factual regularity on which we
depend but which we know only partially and on which we can count only if we observe those norms
(Hayek 1967: 80). Hayeks silence on how we can observe rules successfully is, according to him, self-

21

Hayek does at least concede that since the market does enable us to survive, there is something perhaps
to be said for that (Hayek 1988: 70).

20

explanatory. These rules did not arise out of some process of logic of perception (Hayek 1973: 30) nor
did they arise as a result of genetic evolution, as such an argument fails to explain the rapidity at which
social and economic institutions have changed (Hayek 1979: 154). These rules exist because the groups
who practised them were more successful and displaced others (Hayek 1973: 18)22 23.

Hayeks ambiguity about the scope of this evolution hampers critical discussion of his argument. He is
never fully clear as to how the selection process works in practice. This ambiguity is striking as he
attributes almost every cultural aspect of the social order to an evolutionary argument: Our habits and
skills, our emotional attitudes, our tools, and our institutions all are in this sense adaptations to past
experience which have grown up by selective elimination of less suitable conduct (Hayek 1960: 26).
When grouped with the conventions, customs, rules, practices, traditions, morals, languages, law,
money and values that he also attributes to cultural evolution (see Hayek 1979: 153-178), the
significance becomes apparent.

It is Hayeks argument of cultural evolution that reveals the largest tension within his thought. If the
market mechanism, and the wider social order, has evolved over a long period of time, it is logical that
the only direction that society can go next will be decided by the process of further cultural evolution.
However, his endorsement of controlled legal rules and limits defines the further development that the
social order can take, going against the evolution which has made the order he praises. It is an

22

Hayek (1967: 67-79 and 163-168, and 1973: 9-19) outlines the process by which these rules emerged. He asks
us to imagine an initial equilibrium situation. Various groups, each with their own rules of social theory and coordination, exist within the social order. A chance mutation occurs in one of the groups, and there is a
transformation of the way their members synchronise their activities. Hayek offers that three outcomes are
possible. Firstly, nothing changes. The mutation has no significant effect on the groups operation. Secondly, the
group shows signs of deterioration. If the group does not return to its former method of procedure, then the
group must disband and members will join other groups. The final outcome is that the group becomes more
efficient, and begins to benefit from the new methods it follows. If the other groups do not adjust to the new
rules, then they instead will fall behind and eventually disband themselves. It is such situations that Hayek
believes have led to the evolution of the market mechanism from the hunter gathers into the Great Society. Elster
(1979: 28-35) offers a helpful account of this explanation.
23
There is both a collectivist and individualist tendency to this explanation. The group success theory both relates
to the success of the group as an entity and also the success of the aggregate of each individual.

21

inconsistent position that Hayek fails to resolve, and one which he is incapable of resolving with the
position he takes.

Hayeks theory of tradition and cultural evolution can be equated to a Burkean theme of the social order.
Hayeks discussion of Burke is positive, respectful and appreciative24. Hayek does not view Burke as the
original author of the ideas he aspires to develop, but is the philosopher who reiterated them during a
period of revolutionary doctrine (Rowland 1988: 230). His view on the connection between tradition
and the free society is also admired25. In his seminal chapter Why I am not a conservative, Hayek pays
direct tribute to Burke and fellow conservatives, whose loving and reverential study of the value of
grown institutions we owe some profound insights which are the real contributions to our
understanding of a free society (Hayek 1960: 399). Hayeks awe at the human ability to create things
greater than they know (Hayek 1952: 9) echo Burkes own reverence of the fact. They share the
assertion that society develops as the individual develops.

It is consequential from this that Hayeks account of rationalism and tradition reflects an embedded
conservatism. Whilst liberals may use the concept of the spontaneous order as a means of establishing
and defending the free market, conservatives use it to promote the customary practices built up through
existing institutions. In the concluding chapter, I will assess the extent to which Hayeks conception of
spontaneity commits him to the philosophies of liberalism and conservatism.

24

To the point where in a book published after his death in 1994 (25), he claimed to be becoming a Burkean
Whig.
25
Hayeks view is certainly inspired by the vision articulated by Burke. Men are qualified for civil liberty in exact
proportion to their disposition to put moral chains upon their own appetites; in proportion as their love of justice
is above their rapacity; in proportion as their own soundness and sobriety of understanding is above their vanity
and presumption (Hayek 1952: 23-24).

22

Hayeks Conservative Liberalism

Hayek stands as one of the most influential critics of socialism. Although Murray Rothbard may attempt
to liken Hayek to the socialists he criticises, there arent many that would mistake him for such ideas.
However, to argue for the spontaneous market order in place of socialism does not necessarily equate
Hayek as a liberal. Is Hayek best described as a liberal, as a conservative, an amalgamation of the two, or
as something else? Is he a neo-liberal? A libertarian? A Burkean Whig? In this chapter, I outline Hayeks
relationship with each different strand of political philosophy.

The debate over the convergence of conservatism and liberalism was not limited to Friedrich Hayek.
The New Right movements that emerged in the late 1960s in Britain and America represented
combined elements of each ideology. Some suggested that the hijacking of liberalism with socialism
meant a more permanent interlinking was taking place: a realignment of both the political forces and the
political ideas of conservatism and liberalism (Gamble 1996: 101). Yet, the connection was not
supported universally. Defining this new group of thinkers was difficult, and the term libertarian
became increasingly popular in the United States. However, this term provided some undesirable
connotations. To conservatives, it implied support for the rampant individualism to which they had been
opposed for generations previous. To Hayek, it implied the same degree of constructivism that he spent
his career criticising so fiercely.

It is significant then that Hayek stands as an intellectual figurehead for the New Right. Margaret
Thatcher often recommended his books to colleagues in the House of Commons, and once told an
adviser, of a more One Nation tendency, that The Constitution of Liberty is what we believe (Ranelagh
1991). It is significant therefore that the man who refused to be labelled as a conservative or as a
libertarian stands as a beacon for both the intellectual and political movements of the New Right. To
determine the philosophical grounding of Hayek and his concept of the spontaneous order, I will analyse
their relation to three key components of the New Right movement, each linked with him:
conservatism, libertarianism, and finally liberalism.

23

CONSERVATISM

It is important to note that I will not reduce conservatism to a form of pragmatism. Instead, I offer that
conservatism, as with any strand of political philosophy, is made up of underlying principles which allow
ideas and concepts to reside under its name. Conservatism stresses the importance of the individual, but
within the context of their responsibility to society, built upon the values of tradition, consensus and the
rule of law. This is best upheld through order and authority based upon a framework of morality
(Scruton 1982).

Hayeks postscript to The Constitution of Liberty, Why I am not a Conservative aimed to dismiss the idea
that conservatism could be unified with liberalism. Whilst conservatism had certain admirable qualities,
it offered no intellectual defence to the collectivist arguments put forward by socialism. He labelled it
inevitable that many of the positions which he espoused were identified as conservative. The true
conservatives and liberals had been forced to come together in common opposition to developments
which threaten their different ideals equally (Hayek 1960: 397). It far from warms Hayek to the
association that exists, however. His objection is decisive:

It is that by its very nature it cannot offer an alternative to the direction in which we
are moving. It may succeed by its opposition to current tendencies in slowing down
undesirable developments but, since it does not indicate another direction, it cannot
prevent their continuance. It has, for this reason, invariably been the fate of
conservatism to be dragged along the path not of its own choosing. The tug of war
between conservatives and progressives can only affect the speed, not the direction,
of contemporary development. But, though there is need for a brake on the vehicle
of progress, I personally cannot be content with simply helping to apply the brake.
What the liberal must ask, first of all, is not how fast or how far we should move, but
where we should move (Hayek 1960: 398).

Implicit in Hayeks comments about conservatism is a support for rationalism, despite his strenuous
efforts to reject it. The character of the conservative opposition to Hayeks rationalist tendency is
captured best in Michael Oakeshotts repudiation of Hayek in Rationalism in Politics: this is, perhaps,
the main significance of Hayeks Road to Serfdom-not the cogency of his doctrine, but the fact that it is a

24

doctrine. A plan to resist all planning may be better than its opposite, but it belongs to the same style of
politics (Oakeshott 1962: 21). Oakeshott, as a conservative, rejects progress as a theory, and accuses
Hayek of converting the resource of resistance into a principle of resistance. In essence, Hayek does not
reject this, in turn criticising conservatism for being nothing more than a useful practical maxim, that
cannot be a political philosophy, since it does not give us any guiding principles which can influence
long-range developments (Hayek 1960: 411).

Hayeks criticism of rationalism is not rationalism itself, but a rationalism that does not recognise the
limits of the social order. In this regard, he is separate from the notions we associate with conservatism.

Order appears to the conservative as the result of the continuous attention of


authority, which, for this purpose, must be allowed to do what is required by the
particular circumstances and not be tied to rigid rule. A commitment to principles
presupposes an understanding of the general forces by which the efforts of society are
co-ordinated, but it is such a theory of society and especially of the economic
mechanism that conservatism conspicuously lacks (Hayek 1960: 401).

Unlike conservatives, Hayek wishes to understand how to utilise the spontaneous ordering process.
Whilst the conservative concerns him or herself with a fear of change, the liberal places confidence in
the spontaneity of the market to change, despite the lack of awareness of the adaptations that the market
will make (Hayek 1960: 398-402).

Hayek does not reject conservatism completely, but faults them for their aversion to change when it is
the right step to take. They are right to appreciate the spontaneously grown institutions such as language
and law, but their failure to convert their insights into a positive recognition of new developments sets
them apart from the true liberals (Gamble 1996: 103), conservatives are inclined to use the powers
of government to prevent changes or to limit its rate to whatever appeals to the more timid mind
(Hayek 1960: 400).

Hayek saw a direct relationship between conservatives lack of understanding of economic forces and
their uncontrolled trust in authority. Whilst Hayek, and liberals more widely, are concerned with the

25

limitation of government power, conservatives are more concerned with who wields that power. The
conservative is therefore like the socialist, (as) he regards himself as entitled to force the value he holds
on other people (Hayek 1960: 401). Hayeks priority is that a society exists which does not exert force
upon other people. In doing so, it promotes peace. A consequence of this is that people are allowed to
pursue ends which are different to the ideal of those in power. To Hayek, this is irrelevant, so long as
those ends can be pursued freely and not at the expense of others freedom. Whilst Hayek agrees with
many of the values of the conservative (Hayek 1960: 402), he condemns the approach that allows the
promotion of these values via coercion, to live and work successfully with others requires more than
faithfulness to ones concrete aims. It requires an intellectual commitment to a type of order in which
even on issues which to one are fundamental, others are allowed to pursue different ends (Hayek 1960:
402).

In essence, the obscurantism apparent in conservatism is Hayeks main objection. He states that many of
the ideals that conservatives promote were first offered by liberals anyway26. Yet they still insist on
rejecting new knowledge out of an inherent distrust of the consequences that might arise from it. It is
this insistence that Hayek believes establishes a bridge not between conservatism and liberalism, but
conservatism and collectivism.

The growth of ideas is an international process, and only those who fully take part in
the discussion will be able to exercise a significant influence to think in terms of
our industry or resource is only a short step away from demanding that these
national assets can be directed in the national interest the more a person dislikes
the strange and thinks his own ways superior, the more he tends to regard it as his
mission to civilise others (Hayek 1960: 405-406, footnote omitted).

Hayeks conclusion in his postscript is that conservatives are useful allies in the short term fight against
collectivism, but are unable to unite with liberals in the long term fight for peace and the right social
order due to their fragmented understanding of the economic mechanism. However, this postscript,
26

So unproductive has conservatism in producing a general conception of how a social order is maintained that
its modern votaries, in trying to construct a theoretical foundation, invariably find themselves appealing almost
exclusively to authors who regarded themselves as liberal (Hayek 1960: 401). As always, Hayeks definition of
liberal is very specific to his own ends. He includes Burke as a liberal in this regard instead of a conservative.

26

written in 1960, represents only a section of Hayeks ideological thought. Despite his best efforts, there
is a vast proportion of his thought, particularly in relation to the spontaneous order, that represents a
conservative tendency. To deconstruct this, it is important to recognise the change in Hayeks political
thought over time. In essence, a pre-1960 Hayek, and a post-1960 Hayek.

Taking the most abstract view of political philosophy, Hayek never truly offers a coherent theory of the
complicated relationship between freedom and reason that arises from his writings27. The pre-1960
Hayek maintains that no morality is justifiable and that we should be free to do as we wish, safe from the
impediments of the rationally imposed ideas of others. Freedom and reason can be characterised in a
consistent manner if there are rules and conduct that constrain our moral actions but do not prescribe
them (Hayek 1944: 13). However, the post-1960 Hayek puts forward that all we can do is hope for the
best (Hayek 1973: 169). His pessimism for the possibilities of society to maintain the market
mechanism increasingly commits him to a concrete support for traditional institutions which made
civilisation possible (Hayek 1979: 168).

Hayeks combination of pessimism and blind faith in the market mechanism rejects the state as artificial,
and promotes capitalism as spontaneous. As the evolutionary process of the spontaneous order cannot of
itself be a guarantee of the preservation of the market order, Hayeks task is to revive the case for
limited government, there to free the process of spontaneous growth from the obstacles and
encumbrances that human folly has erected (Hayek 1960: 410). Hayeks consequential desire to
promote the individualist aspect of society requires a significant changing of the order, informed by
classical liberal principles. This does not equate with a definition of conservatism. Whilst there are
undoubtedly aspects of Hayeks thought which mirror the conservative tradition (he admits this himself),
he cannot universally be described as a conservative.

27

The reconciliation of these two positions is often the task of moral political philosophy (see Kukathas 1989:
189-190, and Hare 1963).

27

LIBERTARIANISM

Whilst Hayek disagreed with many in the New Right movement, he shared with many of them the
desire to reconnect liberalism with the individualist aspects of thought that were associated with the
liberals of the nineteenth century. Certain thinkers began to use the term libertarianism as a label of
their philosophy. Defining the term, as with any philosophy, is difficult. W. H. Greenleaf (1983: 15-20)
puts forward four elements which he considers to be crucial: the importance of the individual; the
inalienable title of the individual to a free real of self-regarding action; opposition to central
concentration of power; support for the rule of law. The definition is helpful, but incredibly vague.
Whilst it would not exclude Hayek, it would also not exclude many of the liberals that Hayek would
characterise as false individualists, such as Locke and Mill. It would also arguably allow the social
liberals of the 20th Century, such as Hobhouse, Gore and Green to be characterised in this manner.

Roger Scruton seeks to offer a more precise definition. For Scruton, libertarianism is the form of
liberalism which believes in freeing the people not merely from the constraints of traditional political
institutions, but also from the inner constraints imposed by their mistaken attribution of power to
ineffectual things (it is) a radical form of the theory of laissez-faire, which believes that economic
activity must be actively liberated from the bondage of needless political constraints in order to achieve
true prosperity (Scruton 1982: 271, emphasis omitted). This definition rather clouds issue in the
context of Hayek. Hayeks concept of the spontaneous order is undoubtedly libertarian if we follow
Scrutons terms. Hayek strongly believed in advancing a programme of economic liberalism that called
for the removal of the political constraints which had hindered the free market for so long. However, his
support for this concept as an evolutionary process meant that he was unable to support little or no
restraint on individual behaviour, if this went against the traditional wisdom that had prevailed
previously.

Scrutons definition highlights the disjointed relationship that exists between Hayek and libertarianism.
This can be appreciated if we consider Hayeks political philosophy in comparison to two leading

28

libertarian thinkers: Murray Rothbard and Robert Nozick. Murray Rothbard put forward the most
radical form of economic liberalism, often referred to as anarcho-capitalism. Rothbards premise is
that since all government actions must be funded by taxes, they are funded by coercion. Whether
government comprises of a heavily taxed economy or a liberal economy promoted by Hayek, it is an
economy of coercion. Rothbard insists that there need be no exceptions of his proposals, and that every
government service can be privatised. It is possible to conceive of a truly free market, in which no
invasion of property takes place either because everyone voluntary refrains from such aggression or
because whatever method of forcible defence exists on the free market is sufficient to prevent any such
aggression (Rothbard 1977: 1-2).

Rothbard is against the idea that state action can be justified in any sphere. There are no public goods in
Rothbards vision of society. His position draws attention to Hayeks view that the state must exist to
ensure that the rules of the economic order are followed. Rothbard holds no such view.

how can the rightist trumpet his devotion to private property and free enterprise
while at the same time favouring war, conscription, and the outlawing of noninvasive activities and practices that he deems immoral? And how can the rightist
favour a free market while seeing nothing amiss in the vast subsidies, distortions, and
unproductive inefficiencies involved in the military-industrial complex? (Rothbard
1978: 24)

Such is the absolutist nature of Rothbards position, all existing state controls would wither away as
private agencies took over their application. In this context, Hayek cannot be a libertarian. However,
there is a libertarian recognition of the role of the state, and that is made in the strongest terms by
Robert Nozick.

Robert Nozick (1974) sought to provide a rights-based argument for a state which was minimal but in
existence. Whilst he accepts many of the arguments that Rothbard puts forward, he offers that certain
parts of society would not function properly without a state monopoly; the classically liberal functions of
defence and justice are Nozicks exceptions to a market led economy. Nozicks argument is the result of
a simple cost/benefit analysis. The cost to the individual citizen of taking part in each of the competing

29

protection agencies would outweigh the cost of giving the state the monopoly power. The benefits
would be the same in this field. The similarities between Nozick and Hayek are much more apparent
than with Rothbard. Hayek remained avid in his critique of the state, but kept the view that in certain
cases it was a necessary evil. If the wishes of both thinkers were realised, the differences may well be
small. However, it is worth noting the objectives of each thinker. Whilst Hayek seeks a small state that
preserves the framework of the market mechanism, Nozick prioritised a politics based on abstract rights
of the individual.

Nozick and Rothbard disagreed on the means of achieving a libertarian style of politics, but agreed on
the end objectives. They offered concrete principles from which politics and policy could be tested and
judged. Hayeks ambiguity partially separates him from this strand of philosophy. Whilst he articulated
the role of the state, it was in a manner more prudential than philosophical. Hayek sought to achieve the
conditions that would allow the Great Society to develop. For libertarians, this is not a sufficient test of
the state; where will the line be drawn in order to ensure the development and evolution of the
spontaneous order? For libertarians, there can be no guarantee in Hayeks model of a minimal state.
Whilst Hayek can be associated with certain aspects of libertarian thought, he cannot be regarded as a
libertarian in the style advocated by Nozick or Rothbard.

LIBERALISM

Hayeks philosophy cannot be described as universally conservative or libertarian. The question remains
as to whether this can be done for any philosopher, but Hayek demonstrates the difficulty more than
most. In this final and concluding section, I will articulate why Hayeks concept of the spontaneous
order contributes to his liberalism, but in a manner that fails to establish his philosophy in any absolute
form. Throughout, I have sought to compare Hayeks spontaneous order to broader principles of
liberalism. This section will aim to be more specific in the comparison. There are clearly many
definitions of liberalism, aimed at covering the many branches of the philosophy that have arisen over
time. Even if we restrict the definition to classical liberalism, the form usually associated with Hayek,

30

the definition is far from easy to provide. However, this does not make it impossible, or irrelevant, to
define the principles which are at the core of the classical liberal movement.

Harold Laski claimed that liberalism arose to launch a concerted attack upon:
the claims of the nobility, the legal system, the habits of government, [and] the
economic basis of society [all of which needed to be] examined afresh... on the
dangerous assumption that most of the traditions they represented were evil. It was
the age of reason; and the philosophers used the weapon of rational criticism to
declare that freedom is good and restraint on its nature bad. They sought quite
consciously to evade whatever limited the right of individual personality to make its
own terms with life (Laski 1971: 107).

In this regard, classical liberals sought prosperity via freedom for the individual. The liberal doctrine,
according to Laski, put forward that the old traditions and customs of how people should live were not
great pearls of wisdom, but were merely dictating terms to the general population, and shaping their
human development as a consequence28. By investigating the true nature of society, we could begin to
rationally reconstruct the way the social order to one that served prosperity and liberty. Such a theory
subscribes to the view that instead of accepting tradition, one should believe in human reason to shape
and direct the social order29.

By this definition, Hayek does not qualify as a liberal. Hayeks support for tradition is as strong as his
critique of rationalism However, Hayek claims to be rescuing liberalism from this hubris. Hayek claims
that in believing a superiority of reason over others, liberals have fallen into an equally frightening trap;
one which recreates the same problems of past eras. The only way in which institutions and social orders
can improve is through trial and error. The only thing guaranteed from rationally designing the social
order, for Hayek, is error. It is the most distinctive feature of Hayeks conception of liberalism that man
is incapable of self-determinism. To be a liberal, is to submit to the lowly position that one occupies
28

Liberalism, Hayek argues, 'derives from the discovery of a self-generating or spontaneous order in social
affairs..., an order which made it possible to utilize the knowledge and skill of all members of society to a much
greater extent than would be possible in any order created by central direction...' (Hayek 1967: 162). Whilst this
definition may have value, it demonstrates more than anything the tendency of defining terms in such a manner
that suits your own argument.
29
This echoes Voltaires statement, "If you want good laws, burn those you have and make new ones."

31

within the social order, and to submit to the natural processes that arise from it. It is against liberalism to
think conversely, that man is capable of anything more. Hayek views freedom as something which is
often impeded by reason, or more accurately, rationalism. Rationalism for Hayek is held by all of the
liberals that strive to know the details of the universe, and to design the social order from that point. It
is from this point that Hayek runs into difficulty, and leads Forsyth (1989) to refer to Hayeks bizarre
liberalism. In his analysis of the social order and of spontaneity, Hayeks prescription stands in direct
contrast to his diagnosis.

His diagnosis of the problems of the social order leads him to divide liberalism into the true liberals and
the false liberals, the evolutionaries and the constructvists, and consequently suggest that the problems
of Western civilisation are of intellectual making. If this is the case, then evolution should surely have
abandoned constructivism by now? Rationalist liberalism has been a central part of the Western tradition
for the last four hundred years, yet Hayek implies that it has no place in society.

The ideological cast of is thought means that on several questions he fails to purse
some of his most important arguments and insights. These closures include his failure
to apply his concept of evolution to the explanding role of the state and democracy,
to apply his concept of coercion to the subordiante position of workers in factories,
and to apply his concept of dependency to the organisation of industry (Gamble
1996: 189-190, footnote omitted).

His diagnosis is to reject the authenticity of so much of the tradition that he claims to value 30. His
prescription is no less contradictory, and arises directly from his diagnosis. In order to achieve his
desired outcome, Hayek is forced to abandon the evolutionary argument, and employ a method of
design himself. In attempting to ensure the correct rules and laws of the market mechanism are in
place, Hayek is forced to construct an order. This order is no longer one of spontaneity but one of
constructed design. The implications of his philosophy would be to undertake a radical transformation of
the social order as great as the socialist ideal he avidly criticised.

30

Forsyth (1989: 250): Far from being a classical liberalism purged of its errors, it is a classical liberalism purged
of its truths.

32

Hayeks attempt to delegitimise the socialist facet of Western political tradition prevents him from
accepting any other framework of society, even if that framework is inherently liberal. Hayeks
expectation that socialism as a creed would retreat may have partially been realised, but his failure to
recognise some of its political success renders him incapable of moving from his rigid position. As
socialism failed, social democracy, and eventually neo-liberal capitalism, flourished. Each of them has a
very active state, offering wide ranging welfare programmes, state education and health care and many
other public services. Hayeks problem, and the problem for the wider Austrian critique of the
economic order, is that his arguments worked very well against a centrally planned economy, but not
against the liberal welfare state. Hayeks philosophy never reaches a coherent political doctrine because
he fails to recognise that the spontaneous order cannot provide a universally accepted theory. It is this
ideological closure that sets him apart from a lucid theory of liberalism.

CONCLUSION

I described earlier the temporal change in Hayeks thought. Pre-1960, the spontaneous order occupied
the majority of his analysis. Post-1960, the argument shifted towards one of evolutionary rationalism,
and an advocation of a more cautious attitude to change and reform31. Even so, his attitude still reflected
one of rationalist constructivism as opposed to the evolutionary behaviour he was supposedly promoting
(Gamble 1996: 187-188). It is Hayeks constructivism that marks him as a liberal, and explains the
strong criticisms that conservatives continue to put forward. As noted earlier, comparing Hayek to the
conservative thinker Michael Oakeshott helps to explain his philosophy.

Just as there is a debate over the validity of Hayeks liberalism, there is a debate over the validity of
Oakeshotts conservatism. Oakeshotts philosophy is liberal in that he promotes the liberal tenets of
moral individualism, the free market, and limited government. However, his justification for each is

31

This does not equate him to a conservative disposition. In his final publications, he still advocated huge changes
in trade union legislation and monetary policy.

33

grounded more in support for tradition and authority than in support for classical liberalism. In the same
manner, Hayeks thought can be characterised as conservative in his distrust of experimentation and an
increasingly significant support of tradition and authority. Like Oakeshott, Hayek was a critic of
democracy, though not to the same extent. Hayek did not go as far to support unlimited authority for
the state as an association. The state is a burden; a necessary burden, but a burden all the same. Hayeks
preference remained never for authority as an end, but for any proposal which resulted in the reduction
in power of government. It is Hayeks aversion to the state and his support for the spontaneity of the
market mechanism that represents his contribution to liberalism. His concept of the spontaneous order
is one in which the insights of each actor are independent, and as each action comes together with every
other action, the sum total will prove its worth over time.

It is therefore apparent that Hayeks theory does not represent a coherent philisophical defence of
liberalism. His spontaneous order is not one which seeks to defend liberalism on the grounds of
theology, as John Locke attempted to do. It does not seek to defend liberalism on the basis of a
utilitarian appeal to reason, as Jeremy Bentham or John Stuart Mill attempted to do. Nor does it seek to
defend liberalism on the basis of sociological truisms, as Herbert Spencer put forward. Hayeks defence
is more a proposition of what practicing liberalism should be. His theory of knowledge, the markets,
rationalism, and tradition, together represent the spontaneous order, and together represent a blind
submission to a form of conservative liberalism offered by no other. As I hope will have become
apparent throughout this paper, it is the unequivocal conclusion of this paper that Hayeks concept of the
spontaneous order is an inherentently flawed one. It also remains the conclusion of this paper that it is
without doubt a contribution to his liberalism.

34

Bibliography

Bay, Christian (1971). Hayeks Liberalism: The Constitution of Perpetual Privilege The Political Science
Reviewer 1: 93-124;
Barry, Norman (1979). Hayeks Social and Economic Philosophy. London: Macmillan;
Barry, Norman (1982). The Tradition of Spontaneous Order Literature of Liberty 5 (2): 7-58;
Barry, Norman (1984). Hayek on Liberty 263-288, in Zbigniew Pelcznyski and John Gray (eds.),
Conceptions of Liberty. London: Athlone Press;
Bellamy, Richard (1994). Dethroning Politics: Liberalism, Constitutionalism and Democracy in the
Thought of F. A. Hayek British Journal of Political Science 24 (4): 419-441;
Connin, Lawrence J. (1990). Hayek, Liberalism and Social Knowledge Canadian Journal of Political
Science 23 (2): 297-315;
Downing, L. and R. Thigpen (1984). Ideology and Truth-Seeking in Liberal Theory: The Case of
Ackermans Social Justice in the Liberal State Review of Politics 46: 45-64;
Elster, Jon (1979). Ulysses and the Sirens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press;
Finer, Herman (1963). The Road to Reaction. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press;
Forsyth, Murray (1988). Hayeks Bizarre Liberalism: A Critique Political Studies 36: 235-250;
Galeotti, Anna E. (1987). Individualism, Social Rules and Tradition: The Case of Friedrich A. Hayek
Political Theory 15 (2): 163-181;
Gamble, Andrew (1996). Hayek: The Iron Cage of Liberty. Oxford: Blackwell;
Gissurarson, Hannes H. (1987). Hayeks Conservative Liberalism. New York: Garland;
Gray, John (1980). F. A. Hayek on Liberty and Tradition The Journal of Libertarian Studies 4 (2): 119137;
Gray, John (1986 (1998)). Hayek on Liberty. Oxford: Blackwell;
Gray, John (1993). Post-liberalism: Studies in Political Thought. New York: Routledge;
Green, David G. (1987). The New Conservatism: The Counter Revolution in Political, Economic and Social
Thought. New York: St Martins Press;
Greenleaf, W. H. (1983). The British Political Tradition vol. 1: The Rise of Collectivism. London: Meuthen;

35

Hare, Richard M. (1963). Freedom and Reason. Oxford: Clarendom Press;


Hayek, Friedrich A. (1933). Monetary Theory and the Trade Cycle. London: Cape;
Hayek, Friedrich A. ed. (1935). Collectivist Economic Planning: Critical Studies on the Possibilities of Socialism.
London: Routledge;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1944). The Road to Serfdom. London: Routledge;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1948). Individualism and Economic Order. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1952). The Sensory Order: An Inquiry into the Foundations of Theoretical Psychology.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1960). The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1967). Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics. Chicago: Chicago University
Press;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1973). Law, Legislation and Liberty, i: Rules and Order. London: Routledge;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1976). Law, Legislation and Liberty, ii: The Mirage of Social Justice. London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1978). New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas. London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1979). Law, Legislation and Liberty, iii: The Political Order of a Free People. London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1983). Knowledge, Evolution and Society. London: Adam Smith Institute;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1988). The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism. London: Routledge;
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1994) ed. S. Kresge and L. Wenar. Hayek on Hayek. London: Routledge;
Hodgson, G. (1984). The Democratic Economy: a new look at planning, markets and power. Harmondsworth:
Penguin;
Hoy, Calvin (1984). A Philosophy of Individual Freedom: The Political Thought of F. A. Hayek. London:
Greenwood Press;
Hume, David (1739) (ed. 1978 by Selby-Bigge L. A.). A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford: Oxford
University Press;
Hunt, Louis and McNamara, Peter (2007). Liberalism, Conservatism, and Hayeks Idea of Spontaneous Order.
New York: Palgrave;

36

Kley, Roland (1994). Hayeks Social and Political Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press;
Kukathas, Chandran (1989). Hayek and Modern Liberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press;
Kresge, S. and Wenar L. ed. (1994). Hayek on Hayek. London: Routledge;
Laski, Harold J. (1971). The Rise of European Liberalism. London: Unwin Books;
Lindblom, Charles E. (1965). The Intelligence of Democracy: Decision Making Through Mutual Adjustment.
New York: Free Press;
Menger, Carl (1883 (1985)): Investigations into the method of the social sciences with special reference to
economics. Translated by Francis J. Nock. New York: New York University Press;
Mises, Ludvig von (1936). Socialism: An Economic and Sociological Analysis. London: Cape;
Oakeshott, Michael (1962). Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays. New York: Basic Books Publishers;
Oakeshott, Michael (1975). On Human Conduct. Oxford: Clarendon Press;
ODriscoll, Gerald (1977). Economics as a Coordination of Problem: The Contributions of Friedrich A. Hayek.
Kansas City: Sheed Andrews and McMeel;
Nozick, Robert (1974). Anarchy, State and Utopia. Oxford: Blackwell;
Polanyi, Karl (2001 [1944]). The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of Our Time.
Boston: Beacon Press;
Popper, Karl (1945). The Open Society and Its Enemies. London: Routledge;
Popper, Karl (1957). The Poverty of Historicism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul;
Ranelagh, John (1991). Thatchers People. London: Fontana;
Rothbard, Murray (1977). Power and Market. Kansas: Sheed, Andrew and McMeel;
Rothbard, Murray (1978). For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto. New York: Collier-Macmillan;
Rowland, Barbara M. (1988). Beyond Hayeks Pessimism: Reason, Tradition and Bounded
Constructivist Rationalism British Journal of Political Science 18: 221-241;
Schumpeter, Joseph (1950). Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy. London: Allen and Unwin;
Scruton, Roger (1982). A Dictionary of Political Thought. London: Macmillan;
Sullivan, Roger J. (1989). Immanuel Kants Moral Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press;

37

Vanberg, Viktor (1986). Spontaneous Market Order and Social Rules: A Critical Examination of F. A.
Hayeks Theory of Cultural Evolution Economics and Philosophy 2: 75-100;
Vernon, Richard (1976). The Great Society and the Open Society: Liberalism in Hayek and
Popper. Canadian Journal of Political Science 9 (2): 261-276;
Why F A Hayek is a conservative Adam Smith Institute,
(http://adamsmith.org/files/HayekConservative.pdf - 11 March 2011);

38

You might also like