Leibniz and Newton Calculus Controversy

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 6

Leibniz and Newton calculus controversy 1

Leibniz and Newton calculus controversy


The calculus controversy was an argument between seventeenth-century mathematicians Isaac Newton and
Gottfried Leibniz (begun or fomented in part by their disciples and associates – see Development of the quarrel
below) over who had first invented calculus. Newton claimed to have begun working on a form of the calculus
(which he called "the method of fluxions and fluents") in 1666, but did not publish it except as a minor annotation in
the back of one of his publications decades later. (A relevant Newton manuscript of October 1666 is now published
among his mathematical papers.[1] .) Gottfried Leibniz began working on his variant of the calculus in 1674, and in
1684 published his first paper employing it. L'Hopital published a text on Leibniz's calculus in 1696 (in which he
expressed recognition about Newton's 'Principia' of 1687, that Newton's work was 'nearly all about this calculus'.[2] )
Meanwhile, Newton, though he explained his (geometrical) form of calculus in Section I of Book I of the 'Principia'
of 1687,[3] did not explain his eventual fluxional notation for the calculus in print until 1693 (in part) and 1704 (in
full). While visiting London in 1676, Leibniz was shown at least one unpublished manuscript by Newton, raising the
question as to whether or not Leibniz's work was actually based upon Newton's idea. It is a question that had been
the cause of a major intellectual controversy over who first discovered calculus, one that began simmering in 1699
and broke out in full force in 1711.

The quarrel
The last years of Leibniz's life, 1709–1716, were embittered by a long controversy with John Keill, Newton, and
others, over whether Leibniz had discovered calculus independently of Newton, or whether he had merely invented
another notation for ideas that were fundamentally Newton's. Newton manipulated the quarrel. The most remarkable
aspect of this barren struggle was that no participant doubted for a moment that Newton had already developed his
method of fluxions when Leibniz began working on the differential calculus. Yet there was seemingly no proof
beyond Newton's word. He had published a calculation of a tangent with the note: "This is only a special case of a
general method whereby I can calculate curves and determine maxima, minima, and centers of gravity." How this
was done he explained to a pupil a full twenty years later, when Leibniz's articles were already well-read. Newton's
manuscripts came to light only after his death.
The infinitesimal calculus can be expressed either in the notation of fluxions or in that of differentials, or, as noted
above, it was also expressed by Newton in geometrical form, as in the 'Principia' of 1687. Newton employed fluxions
as early as 1666, but did not publish an account of his notation until 1693. The earliest use of differentials in
Leibniz's notebooks may be traced to 1675. He employed this notation in a 1677 letter to Newton. The differential
notation also appeared in Leibniz's memoir of 1684.
The claim that Leibniz invented the calculus independently of Newton rests on the fact that Leibniz
1. Published a description of his method some years before Newton printed anything on fluxions;
2. Always alluded to the discovery as being his own invention. Moreover, this statement went unchallenged some
years;
3. Rightly enjoys the strong presumption that he acted in good faith;
4. Demonstrates in his private papers his development of the ideas of calculus in a manner independent of the path
taken by Newton
According to Leibniz's detractors, to rebut this case it is necessary to show that he (I) saw some of Newton's papers
on the subject in or before 1675 or at least 1677, and (II) obtained the fundamental ideas of the calculus from those
papers. They see the fact that Leibniz's claim went unchallenged for some years as immaterial.
No attempt was made to rebut #4, which was not known at the time, but which provides very strong evidence that
Leibniz came to the calculus independently from Newton. For instance Leibniz came first to integration, which he
saw as a generalization of the summation of infinite series, whereas Newton began from derivatives. However, to
Leibniz and Newton calculus controversy 2

view the development of calculus as entirely independent between the work of Newton and Leibniz misses the point
that both had some knowledge of the methods of the other, and in fact worked together on some aspects, in particular
power series, as is shown in a letter to Henry Oldenburg dated October 24, 1676 where he remarks that Leibniz had
developed a number of methods, one of which was new to him. Both Leibniz and Newton could see by this exchange
of letters that the other was far along towards the calculus (Leibniz in particular mentions it) but only Leibniz was
prodded thereby into publication.
That Leibniz saw some of Newton's manuscripts had always been likely. In 1849, C. J. Gerhardt, while going
through Leibniz's manuscripts, found extracts from Newton's De Analysi per Equationes Numero Terminorum
Infinitas (published in 1704 as part of the De Quadratura Curvarum but also previously circulated among
mathematicians starting with Newton giving a copy to Isaac Barrow in 1669 and Barrow sending it to John Collins[4]
) in Leibniz's handwriting, the existence of which had been previously unsuspected, along with notes re-expressing
the content of these extracts in Leibniz's differential notation. Hence when these extracts were made becomes
all-important. It is known that a copy of Newton's manuscript had been sent to Tschirnhaus in May 1675, a time
when he and Leibniz were collaborating; it is not impossible that these extracts were made then. It is also possible
that they may have been made in 1676, when Leibniz discussed analysis by infinite series with Collins and
Oldenburg. It is a priori probable that they would have then shown him the manuscript of Newton on that subject, a
copy of which one or both of them surely possessed. On the other hand it may be supposed that Leibniz made the
extracts from the printed copy in or after 1704. Shortly before his death, Leibniz admitted in a letter to Abbot
Antonio Conti, that in 1676 Collins had shown him some of Newton's papers, but Leibniz also implied that they were
of little or no value. Presumably he was referring to Newton's letters of 13 June and 24 October 1676, and to the
letter of 10 December 1672, on the method of tangents, extracts from which accompanied the letter of 13 June.
Whether Leibniz made use of the manuscript from which he had copied extracts, or whether he had previously
invented the calculus, are questions on which no direct evidence is available at present. It is, however, worth noting
that the unpublished Portsmouth Papers [5] show that when Newton went carefully (but with an obvious bias) into the
whole dispute in 1711, he picked out this manuscript as the one which had probably somehow fallen into Leibniz's
hands. At that time there was no direct evidence that Leibniz had seen this manuscript before it was printed in 1704;
hence Newton's conjecture was not published. But Gerhardt's discovery of a copy made by Leibniz tends to confirm
its accuracy. Those who question Leibniz's good faith allege that to a man of his ability, the manuscript, especially if
supplemented by the letter of 10 December 1672, sufficed to give him a clue as to the methods of the calculus. Since
Newton's work at issue did employ the fluxional notation, anyone building on that work would have to invent a
notation, but some deny this.

Development of the quarrel


The quarrel was a retrospective affair. In 1696, already some years later than the events that became the subject of
the quarrel, the position still looked potentially peaceful: Newton and Leibniz had each made limited
acknowledgements of the other's work, and L'Hopital's 1696 book about the calculus from a Leibnizian point of view
had also acknowledged Newton's published work of the 1680s as 'nearly all about this calculus' ('presque tout de ce
calcul'), while expressing preference for the convenience of Leibniz's notation.[2]
At first, there was no reason to suspect Leibniz's good faith. In 1699 Nicolas Fatio de Duillier had accused Leibniz of
plagiarizing Newton, but Fatio was not a person of consequence. It was not until the 1704 publication of an
anonymous review of Newton's tract on quadrature, a review implying that Newton had borrowed the idea of the
fluxional calculus from Leibniz, that any responsible mathematician doubted that Leibniz had invented the calculus
independently of Newton. With respect to the review of Newton's quadrature work, all admit that there was no
justification or authority for the statements made therein, which were rightly attributed to Leibniz. But the
subsequent discussion led to a critical examination of the whole question, and doubts emerged. Had Leibniz derived
the fundamental idea of the calculus from Newton? The case against Leibniz, as it appeared to Newton's friends, was
Leibniz and Newton calculus controversy 3

[6]
summed up in the Commercium Epistolicum of 1712, which referenced all allegations. That document was
thoroughly machined by Newton.
No such summary (with facts, dates, and references) of the case for Leibniz was issued by his friends; but Johann
Bernoulli attempted to indirectly weaken the evidence by attacking the personal character of Newton in a letter dated
7 June 1713. When pressed for an explanation, Bernoulli most solemnly denied having written the letter. In
accepting the denial, Newton added in a private letter to Bernoulli the following remarks, Newton's claimed reasons
for why he took part in the controversy. "I have never," he said, "grasped at fame among foreign nations, but I am
very desirous to preserve my character for honesty, which the author of that epistle, as if by the authority of a great
judge, had endeavoured to wrest from me. Now that I am old, I have little pleasure in mathematical studies, and I
have never tried to propagate my opinions over the world, but I have rather taken care not to involve myself in
disputes on account of them."
Leibniz explained his silence as follows, in a letter to Conti dated 9 April 1716:
"Pour répondre de point en point à l'ouvrage publié contre moi, il falloit entrer dans un grand détail de
quantité de minutiés passées il y a trente à quarante ans, dont je ne me souvenois guère: il me falloit
chercher mes vieilles lettres, dont plusiers se sont perdus, outre que le plus souvent je n'ai point gardé les
minutes des miennes: et les autres sont ensevelies dans un grand tas de papiers, que je ne pouvois
débrouiller qu'avec du temps et de la patience; mais je n'en avois guère le loisir, étant chargé
présentement d'occupations d'une toute autre nature."
["In order to respond point by point to all the work published against me, I would have to go into much
minutiae that occurred thirty, forty years ago, of which I remember little: I would have to search my old
letters, of which many are lost. Moreover, in most cases I did not keep a copy, and when I did, the copy
is buried in a great heap of papers, which I could sort through only with time and patience. I have
enjoyed little leisure, being so weighted down of late with occupations of a totally different nature."]
While Leibniz's death put a temporary stop to the controversy, the debate persisted for many years.
To Newton's staunch supporters this was a case of Leibniz's word against a number of contrary, suspicious details.
His unacknowledged possession of a copy of part of one of Newton's manuscripts may be explicable; but it appears
that on more than one occasion, Leibniz deliberately altered or added to important documents (e.g., the letter of June
7, 1713, in the Charta Volans, and that of April 8, 1716, in the Acta Eruditorum), before publishing them, and
falsified a date on a manuscript (1675 being altered to 1673). All this casts doubt on his testimony.
Several points should be noted. Considering Leibniz's intellectual prowess, as demonstrated by his other
accomplishments, he had more than the requisite ability to invent the calculus. What he is alleged to have received
was a number of suggestions rather than an account of the calculus; it is possible that since he did not publish his
results of 1677 until 1684 and since the differential notation was his invention, Leibniz may have minimized, 30
years later, any benefit he may have enjoyed from reading Newton's work in manuscript. Moreover, he may have
seen the question of who originated the calculus as immaterial when set against the expressive power of his notation.
In any event, a bias favoring Newton tainted the whole affair from the outset. The Royal Society set up a committee
to pronounce on the priority dispute, in response to a letter it had received from Leibniz. That committee never asked
Leibniz to give his version of the events. The report of the committee, finding in favor of Newton, was written by
Newton himself and published as "Commercium Epistolicum" (mentioned above) early in 1713. But Leibniz did not
see it until the autumn of 1714.
The prevailing opinion in the eighteenth century was against Leibniz (in Britain, not in the German-speaking world).
Today the consensus is that Leibniz and Newton independently invented and described the calculus in Europe in the
17th century.
"It was certainly Isaac Newton who first devised a new infinitesimal calculus and elaborated it into a
widely extensible algorithm, whose potentialities he fully understood; of equal certainty, the differential
Leibniz and Newton calculus controversy 4

and integral calculus, the fount of great developments flowing continuously from 1684 to the present
day, was created independently by Gottfried Leibniz." (Hall 1980: 1)
One author has identified the dispute as being about 'profoundly different' methods:
"Despite... points of resemblance, the methods [of Newton and Leibniz] are profoundly different, so
making the priority row a nonsense." (Grattan-Guinness 1997: 247)
On the other hand, other authors have emphasized the equivalences and mutual translatability of the methods: here N
Guicciardini (2003) appears to confirm L'Hopital (1696) (already cited):
"... the Newtonian and Leibnizian schools shared a common mathematical method. They adopted two
algorithms, the analytical method of fluxions, and the differential and integral calculus, which were
translatable one into the other." (Guicciardini 2003, at page 250)[7]

References in fiction
The Calculus Controversy is a major topic in Neal Stephenson's set of historical novels The Baroque Cycle
(2003–04).
The antagonistic nature of the dispute plays a role in Greg Keyes' steam punk alternate history series The Age of
Unreason.

Sources
• Ivor Grattan-Guinness, 1997. The Norton History of the Mathematical Sciences. W W Norton. A thorough
scholarly discussion.
• Hall, A. R., 1980. Philosophers at War: The Quarrel between Newton and Gottfried Leibniz. Cambridge Uni.
Press.
• W. W. Rouse Ball, 1908. A Short Account of the History of Mathematics [8], 4th ed. Dated.
• Kandaswamy, Anand. The Newton/Leibniz Conflict in Context [9].
• Stephen Hawking, 1988. A Brief History of Time From the Big Bang to Black Holes. Bantam Books

See also
• Isaac Newton
• Gottfried Leibniz
• Possible transmission of Keralese mathematics to Europe
• History of calculus
• List of scientific priority disputes

References
[1] D T Whiteside (ed.), The Mathematical Papers of Isaac Newton (Volume 1), (Cambridge University Press, 1967), part 7 "The October 1666
Tract on Fluxions", at page 400, in 2008 reprint (http:/ / books. google. com/ books?id=1ZcYsNBptfYC& pg=PA400).
[2] Marquis de l'Hôpital's original words about the 'Principia': "lequel est presque tout de ce calcul": see the preface to his Analyse des Infiniment
Petits (Paris, 1696). The Principia has been called "a book dense with the theory and application of the infinitesimal calculus" also in modern
times: see Clifford Truesdell, Essays in the History of Mechanics (Berlin, 1968), at p.99; for a similar view of another modern scholar see also
D T Whiteside (1970), "The mathematical principles underlying Newton's Principia Mathematica", Journal for the History of Astronomy,
vol.1 (1970), 116-138, especially at p.120.
[3] Section I of Book I of the 'Principia', explaining "the method of first and last ratios", a geometrical form of infinitesimal calculus, as
recognized both in Newton's time and in modern times -- see citations above by L'Hospital (1696), Truesdell (1968) and Whiteside (1970) -- is
available online in its English translation of 1729, at page 41 (http:/ / books. google. com/ books?id=Tm0FAAAAQAAJ& pg=PA41).
[4] D Gjertsen (1986), "The Newton handbook", (London (Routledge & Kegan Paul) 1986), at page 149.
[5] http:/ / www. newtonproject. imperial. ac. uk/ prism. php?id=21
[6] http:/ / www. maths. tcd. ie/ pub/ HistMath/ People/ Newton/ CommerciumAccount/
Leibniz and Newton calculus controversy 5

[7] Niccolò Guicciardini, "Reading the Principia: The Debate on Newton's Mathematical Methods for Natural Philosophy from 1687 to 1736",
(Cambridge University Press, 2003), at page 250 (http:/ / books. google. com/ books?id=Og9azRoVmz8C& pg=PA250).
[8] http:/ / www. maths. tcd. ie/ pub/ HistMath/ People/ Leibniz/ RouseBall/ RB_Gottfried_Leibniz. html
[9] http:/ / www. math. rutgers. edu/ courses/ 436/ Honors02/ newton. html
Article Sources and Contributors 6

Article Sources and Contributors


Leibniz and Newton calculus controversy  Source: http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?oldid=374713253  Contributors: 4C, A bit iffy, Afasmit, Anskas, Anterior1, BlackJeebus, Brian0918,
Bucephalus, Charles Matthews, Christian75, Coldacid, Concerned cynic, D.H, Darklilac, Dodiad, Dsp13, Egsan Bacon, Elassint, Falard, Freddicus, G9615111, Gene Ward Smith, Geometry guy,
Gimmetrow, Headbomb, Hermitage17, Heron, Husond, Immunize, Jagz, Kbdank71, Koavf, Kunkerlund, Kushal one, M a s, MagneticFlux, Megastar, Meile, Melchoir, Michael Hardy, Muspilli,
Myasuda, Neethis, Noctibus, Nousernamesleft, Orinthe, Owlgorithm, Padvi, Paul Foxworthy, Pdcook, Petri Krohn, Pfold, Proberton, Rich Farmbrough, Richard Arthur Norton (1958- ),
Robertvan1, Salix alba, Seanahan, SkerHawx, SlickWillyLovesSex, SpecOp Macavity, Terry0051, Thumperward, Thunderboltz, Tpbradbury, Trebor, Vicenarian, Wafulz, WaveEtherSniffer,
Wikicontribute, Xxanthippe, Yamamoto Ichiro, Yeungchunk, Zondor, 127 anonymous edits

License
Creative Commons Attribution-Share Alike 3.0 Unported
http:/ / creativecommons. org/ licenses/ by-sa/ 3. 0/

You might also like