Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9

The quantum mechanics of time travel through post-selected teleportation

Seth Lloyd1 , Lorenzo Maccone1 , Raul Garcia-Patron1, Vittorio Giovannetti2 , Yutaka Shikano1,3
1
xQIT,Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 77 Mass Ave, Cambridge MA.
2
NEST-CNR-INFM & Scuola Normale Superiore, Piazza dei Cavalieri 7, I-56126, Pisa, Italy.
3
Dep. Physics, Tokyo Institute of Technology, 2-12-1 Oh-Okayama, Meguro, Tokyo, 152-8551, Japan.

This paper discusses the quantum mechanics of closed timelike curves (CTCs) and of other po-
tential methods for time travel. We analyze a specific proposal for such quantum time travel, the
quantum description of CTCs based on post-selected teleportation (P-CTCs). We compare the
theory of P-CTCs to previously proposed quantum theories of time travel: the theory is physically
inequivalent to Deutsch’s theory of CTCs, but it is consistent with path-integral approaches (which
are the best suited for analyzing quantum field theory in curved spacetime). We derive the dy-
namical equations that a chronology-respecting system interacting with a CTC will experience. We
arXiv:1007.2615v2 [quant-ph] 19 Jul 2010

discuss the possibility of time travel in the absence of general relativistic closed timelike curves, and
investigate the implications of P-CTCs for enhancing the power of computation.

PACS numbers: 03.67.-a,03.65.Ud,04.00.00,04.62.+v,04.60.-m

Einstein’s theory of general relativity allows the exis- discovers on the beach a crumbling monument, centuries
tence of closed timelike curves, paths through spacetime old, memorializing him. The Gaelic hero Finn McCool
that, if followed, allow a time traveler – whether human suffers a similar fate. These stories also dwell on the dan-
being or elementary particle – to interact with her for- gers of time travel. Urashima Taro is given a magic box
mer self. The possibility of such closed timelike curves and told not to open it. Finn receives the gift of a magic
(CTCs) was pointed out by Kurt Gödel [1], and a vari- horse and told not to dismount. When, inevitably, Taro
ety of spacetimes containing closed timelike curves have opens the box, and Finn’s toe touches the ground, they
been proposed [2, 3]. Reconciling closed timelike curves instantaneously age and crumble into dust.
with quantum mechanics is a difficult problem that has These tales involve time travel to the future. Perhaps
been addressed repeatedly, for example, using path in- because of the various paradoxes to which it gives rise,
tegral techniques [4–9]. This paper explores a particu- the concept of travel to the past is a more recent in-
lar version of closed timelike curves based on combining vention. Starting in the late eighteenth century, a few
quantum teleportation with post-selection. The result- narratives take a stab at time travel to the past, the best
ing post-selected closed timelike curves (P-CTCs) pro- known being Charles Dickens’s A Christmas Carol, and
vide a self-consistent picture of the quantum mechanics Mark Twain’s A Connecticut Yankee in King Arthur’s
of time-travel. P-CTCs offer a theory of closed timelike Court. The contemporary notion of time travel, together
curves that is physically inequivalent to other Hilbert- with all its attendant paradoxes, did not come into being
space based theories, e.g., that of Deutsch [10]. As in until H.G. Wells’ masterpiece, The Time Machine, which
all versions of time travel, closed timelike curves embody is also the first book to propose an actual device that can
apparent paradoxes, such as the grandfather paradox, in be used to travel back and forth in time.
which the time traveller inadvertently or on purpose per- As frequently happens, scientific theories of time travel
forms an action that causes her future self not to exist. lagged behind the fictional versions. Although Einstein’s
Einstein (a good friend of Gödel) was himself seriously theory of general relativity implicitly allows travel to the
disturbed by the discovery of CTCs [11]. Because the past, it took several decades before Gödel proposed an
theory of P-CTCs rely on post-selection, they provide explicit space-time geometry containing closed timelike
self-consistent resolutions to such paradoxes: anything curves (CTCs). The Gödel universe consists of a cloud of
that happens in a P-CTC can also happen in conventional swirling dust, of sufficient gravitational power to support
quantum mechanics with some probability. Similarly, the closed timelike curves. Later, it was realized that closed
post-selected nature of P-CTCs allows the predictions timelike curves are a generic feature of highly curved, ro-
and retrodictions of the theory to be tested experimen- tating spacetimes: the Kerr solution for a rotating black
tally, even in the absence of an actual general-relativistic hole contains closed timelike curves within the black hole
closed timelike curve. horizon; and massive rapidly rotating cylinders typically
Time travel is a subject that has fascinated human are associated with closed timelike curves [2, 8, 12]. The
beings for thousands of years. In the Hindu epic, the topic of closed timelike curves in general relativity con-
Mahabarata, for example, King Revaita accepts an invi- tinues to inspire debate: Hawking’s chronology protec-
tation to visit Brahma’s palace. Although he stays for tion postulate, for example, suggests that the conditions
only a few days, when he returns to earth he finds that needed to create closed timelike curves cannot arise in
many eons have passed. The Japanese fisherman in the any physically realizable spacetime [13]. For example,
folk tale Urashima Taro, having saved a sea turtle, is in- while Gott showed that cosmic string geometries can con-
vited to the palace of the sea-king; upon returning home tain closed timelike curves [3], Deser et al. showed that
2

physical cosmic strings cannot create CTCs from scratch described by a quantum communication channel to the
[14, 15]. past. A well-known quantum communication channel is
At bottom, the behavior of matter is governed by the given by quantum teleportation, in which shared entan-
laws of quantum mechanics. Considerable effort has gone glement combined with quantum measurement and clas-
into constructing quantum mechanical theories for closed sical communication allows quantum states to be trans-
timelike curves. The initial efforts to construct such the- ported between sender and receiver. We show that if
ories involved path integral formulations of quantum me- quantum teleportation is combined with post-selection,
chanics. Hartle and Politzer pointed out that in the pres- then the result is a quantum channel to the past. The en-
ence of closed timelike curves, the ordinary correspon- tanglement occurs between the forward- and backward-
dence between the path-integral formulation of quantum going parts of the curve, and post-selection replaces the
mechanics and the formulation in terms of unitary evolu- quantum measurement and obviates the need for classi-
tion of states in Hilbert space breaks down [5, 7]. Morris cal communication, allowing time travel to take place.
et al. explored the quantum prescriptions needed to con- The resulting theory allows a description both of the
struct closed timelike curves in the presence of worm- quantum mechanics of general relativistic closed time-
holes, bits of spacetime geometry that, like the han- like curves, and of Wheeler-like quantum time travel in
dle of a coffee cup, ‘break off’ from the main body of ordinary spacetime.
the universe and rejoin it in the the past [4]. Mean- As described in previous work [17], the notion that
while, Deutsch formulated a theory of closed timelike entanglement and projection can give rise to closed time-
curves in the context of Hilbert space, by postulating like curves to has arisen independently in a variety of
self-consistency conditions for the states that enter and contexts. This combination lies at the heart of the
exit the closed timelike curve [10]. Horowitz-Maldacena model for information escape from
General relativistic closed timelike curves provide one black holes [18–21], and Gottesmann and Preskill note
potential mechanism for time travel, but they need not in passing that this mechanism might be used for time
provide the only one. Quantum mechanics supports a va- travel [20]. Pegg explored the use of a related mecha-
riety of counter-intuitive phenomena which might allow nism for ‘probabilistic time machines’ [22]. Bennett and
time travel even in the absence of a closed timelike curve Schumacher have explored similar notions in unpublished
in the geometry of spacetime. One of the best-known ver- work [23]. Ralph suggests using teleportation for time
sions of non-general relativistic quantum versions of time traveling, although in a different setting, namely, dis-
travel comes from Wheeler, as described by Feynman in placing the entangled resource in time [24]. Svetlichny
his Nobel Prize lecture [16]: describes experimental techniques for investigating quan-
‘I received a telephone call one day at the graduate college tum travel based on entanglement and projection [25].
at Princeton from Professor Wheeler, in which he said, Chiribella eet al. cosider this mechanism while analyz-
“Feynman, I know why all electrons have the same charge ing extensions to the quantum computational model [26].
and the same mass.” Brukner et al. have analyzed probabilistic teleportation
“Why?” (where only the cases in which the Bell measurement
“Because, they are all the same electron!” yields the desired result are retained) as a computational
And, then he explained on the telephone, resource in [27].
“Suppose that the world lines which we were ordinarily The outline of the paper follows. In Sec. I we describe
considering before in time and space - instead of only P-CTCs and Deutsch’s mechanism in detail, emphasiz-
going up in time were a tremendous knot, and then, when ing the differences between the two approaches. Then,
we cut through the knot, by the plane corresponding to a in Sec. II we relate P-CTCs to the path-integral for-
fixed time, we would see many, many world lines and that mulation of quantum mechanics. This formulation is
would represent many electrons, except for one thing. If particularly suited for the description of quantum field
in one section this is an ordinary electron world line, in theory in curved spacetime [28], and has been used be-
the section in which it reversed itself and is coming back fore to provide quantum descriptions of closed timelike
from the future we have the wrong sign to the proper time curves [5–7, 9, 29–32]. Our proposal is consistent with
- to the proper four velocities - and that’s equivalent to these path-integral approaches. In particular, the path-
changing the sign of the charge, and, therefore, that part integral description of fermions using Grassmann fields
of a path would act like a positron.” ’ given by Politzer [5] yields a dynamical description which
coincides with ours for systems of quantum bits. Other
As we will see, post-selected closed timelike curves make descriptions, such as Hartle’s [7], are more difficult to
up a precise physical theory which instantiates Wheeler’s compare as they do not provide an explicit prescription
whimsical idea. to calculate the details of the dynamics of the interaction
The purpose of the current paper is to provide a unify- with systems inside closed timelike curves. In any case,
ing description of closed timelike curves in quantum me- their general framework is consistent with our deriva-
chanics. We start from the prescription that time travel tions. By contrast, Deutsch’s CTCs are not compatible
effectively represents a communication channel from the with the Politzer path-integral approach, and are ana-
future to the past. Quantum time travel, then, should be lyzed by him on a different footing [5]. Indeed, suppose
3

that the path integral is performed over classical paths P-CTCs appear to be less pathological [17]. They are
which agree both at the entrance to– and at the exit based on a different self-consistent condition that states
from– the CTC, so that x-in, p-in are the same as x- that self-contradictory events do not happen (Novikov
out, p-out. Similarly, in the Grassmann case, suppose principle [29]). Pegg points out that this can arise be-
that spin-up along the z axis at the entrance emerges as cause of destructive interference of self-contradictory his-
spin-up along the z axis at the exit. Then, the quan- tories [22]. Here we further compare Deutsch’s and post-
tum version of the CTC must exhibit the same perfect selected closed timelike curves, and give an in-depth anal-
correlation between input and output. But, as the grand- ysis of the latter, showing how they can be naturally ob-
father paradox experiment [17] shows, Deutsch’s CTCs tained in the path-integral formulation of quantum the-
need not exhibit such correlations: spin-up in is mapped ory and deriving the equations of motions that describe
to spin-down out (although the overall quantum state the interactions with CTCs. As noted, in addition to
remains the same). By contrast, P-CTCs exhibit per- general-relativistic CTCs, our proposed theory can also
fect correlation between in- and out- versions of all vari- be seen as a theoretical elaboration of Wheeler’s asser-
ables. Note that a quantum-field theoretical justification tion to Feynman that ‘an electron is a positron mov-
of Deutsch’s solution is proposed in [33, 34] and is based ing backward in time’ [16]. In particular, any quantum
on introducing additional Hilbert subspaces for particles theory which allows the nonlinear process of postselec-
and fields along the geodesic: observables at different tion supports time travel even in the absence of general-
points along the geodesic commute because they act on relativistic closed timelike curves.
different Hilbert spaces. The mechanism of P-CTCs [17] can be summarized by
The path-integral formulation also shows that using P- saying that they behave exactly as if the initial state of
CTCs it is impossible to assign a well defined state to the the system in the P-CTC were in a maximal entangled
system in the CTC. This is a natural requirement (or, at state (entangled with an external purification space) and
least, a desirable property), given the cyclicity of time the final state were post-selected to be in the same entan-
there. In contrast, Deutsch’s consistency condition (1) gled state. When the probability amplitude for the tran-
is explicitly built to provide a prescription for a definite sition between these two states is null, we postulate that
quantum state ρCT C of the system in the CTC. the related event does not happen (so that the Novikov
In Sec. III we go beyond the path-integral formula- principle [29] is enforced). By contrast, Deutsch’s CTCs
tion and provide the dynamical evolution formulas in the are based on imposing the consistency condition
context of generic quantum mechanics (the Hilbert-space
formulation). Namely, we treat the CTC as a generic ρCT C = TrA [U (ρCT C ⊗ ρA )U † ], (1)
quantum transformation, where the transformed system
where ρCT C is the state of the system inside the closed
emerges at a previous time “after” eventually interacting
timelike curve, ρA is the state of the system outside
with some chronology-respecting systems. In this frame-
(i.e. of the chronology-respecting part of spacetime), U is
work we obtain the explicit prescription of how to cal-
the unitary transformation that is responsible for even-
culate the nonlinear evolution of the state of the system
tual interactions among the two systems, and where the
in the chronology-respecting part of the spacetime. This
trace is performed over the chronology-respecting system.
nonlinearity is exactly of the form that previous investi-
The existence of a state ρ that satisfies (1) is ensured by
gations (e.g. Hartle’s [7]) have predicted.
the fact that any completely-positive map of the form
In Sec. IV we consider time travel situations that are L[ρ] = TrA [U (ρ ⊗ ρA )U † ] always has at least one fixed
independent from general-relativistic CTCs. We then point ρ (or, equivalently, one eigenvector ρ with eigen-
conclude in Sec. V with considerations on the compu- value one). If more than one state ρCT C satisfies the
tational power of the different models of CTCs. consistency condition (1), Deutsch separately postulates
a “maximum entropy rule”, requesting that the maxi-
mum entropy one must be chosen. Note that Deutsch’s
I. P-CTCS AND DEUTSCH’S CTCS formulation assumes that the state exiting the CTC in
the past is completely uncorrelated with the chronology-
Any quantum theory of gravity will have to propose preserving variables at that time: the time-traveler’s
a prescription to deal with the unavoidable [7] nonlin- ‘memories’ of events in the future are no longer valid.
earities that plague CTCs. This requires some sort of The primary conceptual difference between Deutsch’s
modification of the dynamical equations of motions of CTCs and P-CTCs lies in the self-consistency condition
quantum mechanics that are always linear. Deutsch in imposed. Consider a measurement that can be made ei-
his seminal paper [10] proposed one such prescription, ther on the state of the system as it enters the CTC,
based on a self-consistency condition referred to the state or on the state as it emerges from the CTC. Deutsch
of the systems inside the CTC. Deutsch’s theory has re- demands that these two measurements yield the same
cently been critiqued by several authors as exhibiting statistics for the CTC state alone: that is, the density
self-contradictory features [33–36]. By contrast, although matrix of the system as it enters the CTC is the same as
any quantum theory of time travel quantum mechanics the density matrix of the system as it exits the CTC. By
is likely to yield strange and counter-intuitive results, contrast, we demand that these two measurements yield
4

|ψ> where |Ψ(±) i ∝ |01i ± |10i and |Φ(±) i ∝ |00i ± |11i are
a) b)
the four states in a Bell basis for qubit systems and σα s
Alice V t
are the three Pauli matrices. Eq. (2) is equivalent to
M Bob |ψ> Eq. (5) of Ref. [37], where the extension to higher di-
|ψ> |ψ> mensional systems is presented (the extension to infinite
dimensional systems is presented in [38]). It is immediate
to see that, if the system 1 entering the CTC together
with the purification system 3 are post-selected to be in
the same Bell state |Ψ(−) i13 as the initial one, then only
FIG. 1: Description of closed timelike curves through telepor- the first term of Eq. (2) survives. Apart from an in-
tation. a) Conventional teleportation: Alice and Bob start
consequential minus sign, this implies that the system 2
from a maximally
S entangled state shared among them rep-
resented by “ ”. Alice performs a Bell measurement M on emerging from the CTC is in the state |ψi2 , which is
her half of the shared state and on the unknown state |ψi she exactly the same state of the system that has entered
wants to transmit. This measurement tells her which entan- (rather, will enter) the CTC.
gled state the two systems are in. She then communicates It seems that, based on what is currently known on
(dotted line) the measurement result to Bob who performs a these two approaches, we cannot conclusively choose P-
unitary V on his half of the entangled state, obtaining the
CTCs over Deutsch’s, or vice versa. Both arise from
initial unknown state |ψi. b) Post-selected teleportation:
S the
system in state |ψi and half of the Bell state “ ” are pro- reasonable physical assumptions and both are consistent
T with different approaches to reconciling quantum me-
jected onto the same Bell state “ ”. This means that the
other half of the Bell state is projected into the initial state chanics with closed timelike curves in general relativity.
of the system |ψi even before this state is available. A final decision on which of the two is “actually the case”
may have to be postponed to when a full quantum the-
ory of gravity is derived (which would allow to calculate
the same statistics for the CTC state together with its from first principles what happens in a CTC) or when
correlations with any chronology preserving variables. It a CTC is discovered that can be tested experimentally.
is this demand that closed timelike curves respect both However, because of the huge recent interest on CTCs
statistics for the time-traveling state together with its in physics and in computer science (e.g. see [35, 36, 39–
correlations with other variables that distinguishes P- 43]), it is important to point out that there are reason-
CTCs from Deutsch’s CTCs. The fact that P-CTCs re- able alternatives to the leading theory in the field. We
spect correlations effectively enforces the Novikov prin- also point out that our post-selection based description of
ciple [29], and, as will be seen below, makes P-CTCs CTCs seems to be less pathological than Deutsch’s: for
consistent with path-integral approaches to CTCs. example P-CTCs have less computational power and do
The connection between P-CTCs and teleporta- not require to separately postulate a “maximum entropy
tion [37] is illustrated (see Fig. 1) with the following sim- rule” [17]. Therefore, they are in some sense preferable,
ple example that employs qubits (extensions to higher at least from an Occam’s razor perspective. Independent
dimensional systems are straightforward). Suppose that of such questions of aesthetic preference, as we will now
the initial Bell state is |Ψ(−) i ∝ |01i − |10i (but any show, P-CTCs are consistent with previous path integral
maximally entangled Bell state will equivalently work), formulations of closed timelike curves, whereas Deutsch’s
and suppose that the initial state of the system enter- CTCs are not.
ing the CTC is |ψi. Then the joint state of the three
systems (system 1 entering the CTC, system 2 emerging
from the CTC, and system 3, its purification) is given
by |ψi1 |Ψ(−) i23 . These three systems are denoted by the
three vertical lines of Fig. 1b. It is immediate to see that II. P-CTCS AND PATH INTEGRALS
this state can be also written as
Path integrals [44, 45] allow one to calculate the tran-
(−|Ψ(−) i13 |ψi2 − |Ψ(+) i13 σz |ψi2 + sition amplitude for going from an initial state |Ii to a
|Φ(−) i13 σx |ψi2 + i|Φ(+) i13 σy |ψi2 )/2 , (2) final state |F i as an integral over paths of the action, i.e.

Z +∞ Z y Z τ
hF | exp(− ~i Hτ )|Ii = dx dy I(x) F ∗ (y) Dx(t) exp[ ~i S], where S = dtL(x, ẋ) , (3)
−∞ x 0

and where L = T − V is the Lagrangian


R and S is the action, I(x) and F (x) are the position representations of |Ii
and |F i respectively (i.e. |Ii = dx I(x)|xi), and the paths in the integration over paths all start in x and end in y.
Of course in this form it is suited only to describing the dynamics of a particle in space (or a collection of particles).
5

It will be extended to other systems in the next section.


In order to add a CTC, we first divide the spacetime into two parts,
Z +∞ Z y,y ′
hF |C hF ′ | exp(− ~i Hτ )|Ii|I ′ iC = dx dx′ dy dy ′ I(x) I ′ (x′ ) F ∗ (y) F ′∗ (y ′ ) Dx(t) exp[ ~i S] , (4)
−∞ x,x′

The “conventional” strategy to deal with CTCs using path integrals is to send the system C to a prior time unchanged
(i.e. with the same values of x, ẋ), while the other system (the chronology-respecting one) evolves normally. This is
enforced by imposing periodic boundary conditions on the CTC boundaries. Namely, the probability amplitude for
the chronology-respecting system is
Z +∞ Z y,y ′
hF | exp(− ~i Hτ )|Ii = dx dx′ dy dy ′ I(x) F ∗ (y) δ(x′ − y ′ ) Dx(t) exp[ ~i S] , (5)
−∞ x,x′

where the δ-function ensures that the initial and final boundary conditions in the CTC system are the same. Note
that we have removed I ′ (x′ ) and F ′ (y ′ ), but we are coherently adding all possible initial and final conditions (through
the x′ and y ′ integrals). This implies that it is not possible to assign a definite state to the system inside a CTC: all
possible states of the system (except possibly forbidden ones) are compatible with such boundary conditions. Note
also that the boundary conditions of Eq. (5) have previously appeared in the literature (e.g. see [9] and, in the classical
context, in the seminal paper [46]).

To show that Eq. (5) is the same formula thatR one obtains using post-selected teleportation, we have to calculate
hF |C hΨ| exp(− ~i Hτ ) ⊗ 11|Ii|ΨiC , where |Ψi ∝ dx|xxi is a maximally entangled EPR state [47] and where the
Hamiltonian acts only on the system and on the first of the two Hilbert spaces of |Ψi. Use Eq. (4) for the system and
for the first Hilbert space of |Ψi to obtain
Z +∞
hF |C hΨ| exp(− ~i Hτ ) ⊗ 11|Ii|ΨiC = dx dx′ dy dy ′ dz dz ′ I(x) F ∗ (y) δ(x′ − z) δ(y ′ − z ′ )hz|11|z ′ i
−∞
y,y ′ ∞ y,y ′  
i
Z Z Z
′ ′ ∗ ′ ′
× Dx(t) exp[ ~i S] = dxdx dydy I(x)F (y) δ(x − y ) Dx(t) exp S , (6)
x,x′ −∞ x,x′ ~

where
R we have used the position representation |Ψi = in a P-CTC, it is impossible to assign a definite state
dy dz δ(y − z)|yi|zi. Eq. (6) is clearly equal to Eq. (5) to the CTC system at any time, given the cyclicity of
since hz|z ′ i = δ(z − z ′ ). Note that this result is inde- time there. This is evident, for example, from Eq. (5):
pendent of the particular form of the EPR state |Ψi as in the CTC system no state is assigned, only periodic
long as it is maximally entangled in position (and hence boundary conditions. Another aspect that the two-state
in momentum). formalism and P-CTCs share is the nonlinear renormal-
All the above discussion holds for initial and final pure ization of the states and probabilities. In both cases this
states. However, the extension to mixed states in the arises because of the post-selection. In addition to the
path-integral formulation is straightforward: one only two-state formalism, our approach can also be related to
needs to employ appropriate purification spaces [49, 50]. weak values [48, 52], since we might be performing mea-
The formulas then reduce to the previous ones. surements between when the system emerges from the
CTC and when it re-enters it. Considerations analogous
Here we briefly comment on the two-state vector for- to the ones presented above apply. It would be a mistake,
malism of quantum mechanics [48, 51]. It is based on however, to think that the theory of post-selected closed
post-selection of the final state and on renormalizing the timelike curves in some sense requires or even singles out
resulting transition amplitudes: it is a time-symmetrical the weak value theory. Although the two are compati-
formulation of quantum mechanics in which not only the ble with each other, the theory of P-CTCs is essentially
initial state, but also the final state is specified. As such, a ‘free-standing’ theory that does not give preference to
it shares many properties with our post-selection based one interpretation of quantum mechanics over another.
treatment of CTCs. In particular, in both theories it
is impossible to assign a definite quantum state at each
time: in the two-state formalism the unitary evolution
forward in time from the initial state might give a dif-
ferent mid-time state with respect to the unitary evolu-
tion backward in time from the final state. Analogously,
6

III. GENERAL SYSTEMS in the general qudit case, our post-selected teleportation
approach gives the same result one would obtain from
The formula (5) was derived in the path-integral for- a specific path-integral formulation. In addition, it has
mulation of quantum mechanics, but it can be easily ex- been pointed out many times before (e.g. see [30, 53])
tended to generic quantum evolution. that when quantum fields inside a CTC interact with
We start by recalling the usual Kraus decomposition external fields, linearity and unitarity is lost. It is also
of a generic quantum evolution (that can describe the worth to notice that there have been various proposals to
evolution of both isolated and open systems). It is given restore unitarity by modifying the structure of quantum
by mechanics itself or by postulating an inaccessible purifi-
X cation space that is added to uphold unitarity [54, 55].
L[ρ] = TrE [U (ρ ⊗ |eihe|)U † ] = hi|U |ei ρ he|U † |ii The evolution (9) coming from our approach is to be
i compared with Deutsch’s evolution,
X
= Bi ρBi† , (7) D[ρ] = TrCT C [U (ρCT C ⊗ ρ)U † ], where
i
ρCT C = TrA [U (ρCT C ⊗ ρ)U † ] (10)
where |ei is the initial state of the environment (or, equiv- satisfies the consistency condition. The direct compari-
alently, of a putative abstract purification space), U is son of Eqs. (9) and (10) highlights the differences in the
the unitary operator governing the interaction between general prescription for the dynamics of CTCs of these
system initially in the state ρ and environment, and two approaches.
Bi ≡ hi|U |ei is the Kraus operator. In contrast, the non- Even though the results presented in this section
linear evolution of our post-selected teleportation scheme are directly applicable only to general finite-dimensional
is given by systems, the extension to systems living in infinite-
h dimensional separable Hilbert spaces seems conceptually
N [ρ] = TrEE ′ (U ⊗ 11E ′ ) (ρ ⊗ |ΨihΨ|) U † ⊗ 11E ′

straightforward, although mathematically involved.
i X In his path-integral formulation of CTCs, Hartle notes
× (11 ⊗ |ΨihΨ|) = hl|U |li ρ hj|U † |ji = CρC † ,(8) that CTCs might necessitate abandoning not only uni-
l,j
tarity and linearity, but even the familiar Hilbert space
where C ≡TrCT C [U ] and |Ψi ∝
P formulation of quantum mechanics [7]. Indeed, the fact
i |iiE |iiE ′ (or any
other maximally entangled state, which would give the that the state of a system at a given time can be writ-
same result). Obviously, the evolution in (8) is nonlinear ten as the tensor product states of subsystems relies cru-
(because of the post-selection), so one has to renormalize cially on the fact that operators corresponding to space-
the final state: N [ρ] → N [ρ]/TrN [ρ]. In other words, ac- like separated regions of spacetime commute with each
cording to our approach, a chronology-respecting system other. When CTCs are introduced, the notion of ‘space-
in a state ρ that interacts with a CTC using a unitary U like’ separation becomes muddied. The formulation of
will undergo the transformation closed timelike curves in terms of P-CTCs shows, how-
ever, that the Hilbert space structure of quantum me-
C ρ C† chanics can be retained.
N [ρ] = , (9)
Tr[C ρ C † ]
where we suppose that the evolution does not happen IV. TIME TRAVEL IN THE ABSENCE OF
if C ≡TrCT C [U ] = 0. The comparison with (7) is in- GENERAL-RELATIVISTIC CTCS
structive: there the non-unitarity comes from the inac-
cessibility of the environment. Analogously, in (9) the Although the theory of P-CTCs was developed to ad-
non-unitarity comes from the fact that, after the CTC is dress the question of quantum mechanics in general-
closed, for the chronology-respecting system it will be for- relativistic closed timelike curves, it also allows us to
ever inaccessible. The nonlinearity of (9) is more difficult address the possibility of time travel in other contexts.
to interpret, but is connected with the periodic bound- Essentially, any quantum theory that allows the nonlin-
ary conditions in the CTC. Note that this general evolu- ear process of projection onto some particular state, such
tion equation (9) is consistent with previous derivations as the entangled states of P-CTCs, allows time travel
based on path integrals. For example, it is equivalent to even when no spacetime closed timelike curve exists. In-
Eq. (4.6) of Ref. [7] by Hartle. However, in contrast to deed, the mechanism for such time travel closely follows
here, the actual form of the evolution operators C is not Wheeler’s famous telephone call above. Non-general-
provided there. As a further example, consider Ref. [5], relativistic P-CTCs can be implemented by the creation
where Politzer derives a path integral approach of CTCs of and projection onto entangled particle-antiparticle
for qubits, using Grassmann fields. His Eq. (5) is compat- pairs. Such a mechanism is just what is used in our
ible with Eq. (8). He also derives a nonunitary evolution experimental tests of P-CTCs [17]: although projection
that is consistent with Eq. (9) in the case in which the is a non-linear process that cannot be implemented de-
initial state is pure. In particular, this implies that, also terministically in ordinary quantum mechanics, it can
7

easily be implemented in a probabilistic fashion. Con-


sequently, the effect of P-CTCs can be tested simply by
performing quantum teleportation experiments, and by t
post-selecting only the results that correspond to the de-
sired entangled-state output.
If it turns out that the linearity of quantum mechanics
FIG. 2: Closed timelike loops can collapse the time-depth
is only approximate, and that projection onto particular
of any circuit to one, allowing to compute any problem not
states does in fact occur – for example, at the singu- merely efficiently, but instantaneously.
larities of black holes [18–21] – then it might be possi-
ble to implement time travel even in the absence of a
general-relativistic closed timelike curve. The formalism overall mixed state exiting the curve is the same as the
of P-CTCs shows that such quantum time travel can be one that enters. Consequently, Bennett et al. argue, the
thought of as a kind of quantum tunneling backwards programmer who is using a Deutschian closed timelike
in time, which can take place even in the absence of a curve as part of her quantum computer typically finds
classical path from future to past. the output of the curve is completely decorrelated from
the problem she would like to solve: the curve emits ran-
dom states.
V. COMPUTATIONAL POWER OF CTCS In contrast, because P-CTCs are formulated explicitly
to retain correlations with chronology preserving curves,
It has been long known that nonlinear quantum me- quantum computation using P-CTCs do not suffer from
chanics potentially allows the rapid solution of hard prob- state-preparation ambiguity. That is not so say that P-
lems such as NP-complete problems [56]. The nonlin- CTCs are computationally innocuous: their nonlinear
earities in the quantum mechanics of closed timelike nature typically renormalizes the probability of states in
curves is no exception [41–43]. Aaronson and Watrous an input superposition, yielding to strange and counter-
have shown quantum computation with Deutsch’s closed intuitive effects. For example, any CTC can be used
timelike curves allows the solution of any problem in to compress any computation to depth one, as shown
PSPACE, the set of problems that can be solved using in Fig. 2. Indeed, it is exactly the ability of nonlin-
polynomial space resources [41]. Similarly, Aaronson has ear quantum mechanics to renormalize probabilities from
shown that quantum computation combined with post- their conventional values that gives rise to the amplifi-
selection allows the solution of any problem in the com- cation of small components of quantum superpositions
putational class PP, probabilistic polynomial time(where that allows the solution of hard problems. Not least
a probabilistic polynomial Turing machine accepts with of the counter-intuitive effects of P-CTCs is that they
probability 21 if and only if the answer is “yes.”). Quan- could still solve hard computational problems with ease!
tum computation with post-selection explicitly allows P- The ‘excessive’ computational power of P-CTCs is ef-
CTCs, and P-CTCs in turn allow the performance of fectively an argument for why the types of nonlineari-
any desired post-selected quantum computation. Ac- ties that give rise to P-CTCs, if they exist, should only
cordingly, quantum computation with P-CTCs can solve be found under highly exceptional circumstances such as
any problem in PP, including NP-complete problems. general-relativistic closed timelike curves or black-hole
Since the class PP is thought to be strictly contained in singularities.
PSPACE, quantum computation with P-CTCs is appar-
ently strictly less powerful than quantum computation
with Deutsch’s CTCs. VI. CONCLUSIONS
In the case of quantum computating with Deutschian
CTCs, Bennett et al. [35] have questioned whether the This paper reviewed quantum mechanical theories for
notion of programming a quantum computer even makes time travel, focusing on the theory of P-CTCs [17]. Our
sense. Ref. [35] notes that in Deutsch’s closed timelike purpose in presenting this work is to make precise the
curves, the nonlinearity introduces ambiguities in the def- similarities and differences between varying quantum the-
inition of state preparation: as is well-known in nonlin- ories of time travel. We summarize our findings here.
ear quantum theories, the result of sending either the We have extensively argued that P-CTCs are phys-
state |ψi through a closed-timelike curve or the state ically inequivalent to Deutsch’s CTCs. In Sec. II we
|φi is no longer equivalent to sending the mixed state showed that P-CTCs are compatible with the path-
(1/2)(|ψihψ| + |φihφ|) through the curve. The prob- integral formulation of quantum mechanics. This for-
lem with computation arises because, as is clear from mulation is at the basis of most of the previous analysis
our grandfather-paradox circuit [17], Deutsch’s closed of quantum descriptions of closed time-like curves, since
timelike curves typically break the correlation between it is particularly suited to calculations of quantum me-
chronology preserving variables and the components of a chanics in curved space time. P-CTCs are reminiscent of,
mixed state that enters the curve: the component that and consistent with, the two-state-vector and weak-value
enters the CTC as |0i can exit the curve as |1i, even if the formulation of quantum mechanics. It is important to
8

note, however, that P-CTCs do not in any sense require ture somehow provides the nonlinear dynamics afforded
such a formulation. Then, in Sec. III we extended our by final-state projection, then it is possible for particles
analysis to general systems where the path-integral for- (and, in principle, people) to tunnel from the future to
mulation may not always be possible and derived a sim- the past.
ple prescription for the calculation of the CTC dynamics,
Finally, in Sec. V we have seen that P-CTCs are com-
namely Eq. (9). In this way we have performed a com-
putationally very powerful, though less powerful than the
plete characterization of P-CTC in the most commonly
Aaronson-Watrous theory of Deutsch’s CTCs.
employed frameworks for quantum mechanics, with the
exception of algebraic methods (e.g. see [57]). Our hope in elaborating the theory of P-CTCs is that
In Sec. IV we have argued that, as Wheeler’s picture this theory may prove useful in formulating a quantum
of positrons as electrons moving backwards in time sug- theory of gravity, by providing new insight on one of the
gests, P-CTCs might also allow time travel in spacetimes most perplexing consequences of general relativity, i.e.,
without general-relativistic closed timelike curves. If na- the possibility of time-travel.

[1] K. Gödel, Rev. Mod. Phys. 21, 447 (1949). [26] G. Chiribella, G. M. D’Ariano, P. Perinotti, B. Valiron,
[2] W.B. Bonnor, J. Phys. A 13, 2121 (1980). arXiv:0912.0195 (2009).
[3] J.R. Gott, Phys. Rev. Lett. 66, 1126 (1991). [27] Č. Brukner, J.-W. Pan, C. Simon, G. Weihs, A. Zeilinger,
[4] M.S. Morris, K.S. Thorne, U. Yurtsever, Phys. Rev. Lett. Phys. Rev. A 67, 034304 (2003).
61, 1446 (1988). [28] N.D. Birrell, P.C.W. Davies, Quantum Fields in Curved
[5] H.D. Politzer, Phys. Rev. D 49, 3981 (1994). Space (Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, 1982).
[6] D.G. Boulware, Phys. Rev. D 46, 4421 (1992). [29] J. Friedman, M.S. Morris, I.D. Novikov, F. Echeverria,
[7] J.B. Hartle, Phys. Rev. D 49, 6543 (1994). G. Klinkhammer, K.S. Thorne, and U. Yurtsever, Phys.
[8] W.J. van Stockum, Proc. Roy. Soc. A 57, 135 (1937). Rev. D 42, 1915 (1990).
[9] H.D. Politzer, Phys. Rev. D 46, 4470 (1992). [30] J.L. Friedman, N.J. Papastamatiou, J.Z. Simon, Phys.
[10] D. Deutsch, Phys. Rev. D 44, 3197 (1991). Rev. D 46, 4456 (1992).
[11] A. Einstein in Albert Einstein, Philosopher-Scientist: [31] J.L. Friedman, M.S. Morris, Phys. Rev. Lett. 66, 401
The Library of Living Philosophers Volume VII, P.A. (1991).
Schilpp (ed.) (Open Court, 3rd edition , 1998). [32] P.F. González-Dı́az, Phys. Rev. D 58, 124011 (1998).
[12] C. Lanczos, Z. Phys. 21, 73 (1924). [33] T.C. Ralph, Phys. Rev. A 76, 012336 (2007).
[13] S. Hawking, Phys. Rev. D 46, 603 (1992). [34] T.C. Ralph, G.J. Milburn, and T. Downes, Phys. Rev. A
[14] S. Deser, R. Jackiw, G.’t Hooft, Phys. Rev. Lett. 68, 267 79, 022121 (2009).
(1992). [35] Bennett C.H., Leung D., Smith G., Smolin J.A., Phys.
[15] S.M. Carroll, E. Farhi, A.H. Guth, K.D. Olum, Phys. Rev. Lett. 103, 170502 (2009).
Rev. D 50, 6190 (1994). [36] T.C. Ralph, C.R. Myers, arXiv:1003.1987 (2010).
[16] R. Feynman, in Nobel Lectures, Physics 1963-1970, Else- [37] C.H. Bennett, G. Brassard, C. Crépeau, R. Jozsa, A.
vier Publishing Company, Amsterdam, 1972. Peres, W.K. Wootters Phys. Rev. Lett. 70, 1895 (1993).
[17] S. Lloyd, L. Maccone, R. Garcia-Patron, V. Giovan- [38] S.L. Braunstein, H.J. Kimble, Phys. Rev. Lett. 80, 869
netti, Y. Shikano, S. Pirandola, L.A. Rozema, A. (1998).
Darabi, Y. Soudagar, L.K. Shalm, and A.M. Steinberg, [39] D. Bacon, Phys. Rev. A 70, 032309 (2004).
arXiv:1005.2219 (2010). [40] T.A. Brun, J. Harrington, M.M. Wilde Phys. Rev. Lett.
[18] G. T. Horowitz and J. Maldacena, JHEP 0402, 8 (2004). 102, 210402 (2009).
[19] U. Yurtsever and G. Hockney, Class. Quant. Grav. 22 [41] S. Aaronson, J. Watrous, Proc. Roy. Soc. A 465, 631
295-312 (2005); arXiv:gr-qc/0409112. (2009); arXiv:0808.2669.
[20] D. Gottesman and J. Preskill, JHEP 0403, 26 (2004). [42] S. Aaronson, Proc. Roy. Soc. A 461, 3473 (2005);
[21] S. Lloyd, Phys. Rev. Lett. 96, 061302 (2006). arXiv:quant-ph/0412187.
[22] D.T. Pegg, in “Time’s Arrows, Quantum Measurement [43] T.A. Brun, Found. Phys. Lett. 16, 245 (2003).
and Superluminal Behaviour”, edited by D.Mugnai et al [44] R.P. Feynman, and A.R. Hibbs, Quantum Mechanics and
(Consiglio Nazionale delle Richerche, Roma, 2001) p.113, Path Integrals, (McGraw-Hill, New York, 1965).
arXiv:quant-ph/0506141 (2005). [45] R. P. Feynman, Rev. Mod. Phys. 20, 367 (1948).
[23] C.H. Bennett and B. Schumacher, lecture at [46] F. Echeverria, G. Klinkhammer, K.S. Thorne, Phys. Rev.
QUPON conference Vienna, Austria May 2005 D 44, 1077 (1991).
http://www.research.ibm.com/people/b/bennetc/QU- [47] A. Einstein, B. Podolsky, N. Rosen, Phys. Rev. 47, 777
PONBshort.pdf ; C.H. Bennett and B. Schumacher, (1935).
lecture at Tata Institute for Fundamental Research, [48] Y. Aharonov, L. Vaidman, in Time in Quantum Mechan-
Mumbai, India, February 2002; archived Aug 2003 at ics, edited by Muga J.G., Sala Mayato R., EgusquizaI. L.
http://web.archive.org/web/*/http://qpip-server.tcs.ti- eds. (Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer) p 399; arXiv:quant-
fr.res.in/ qpip/HTML/Courses/Bennett/TIFR5.pdf ph/0105101 (2001).
[24] T.C. Ralph, arXiv:quant-ph/0510038v1 (2005). [49] Y. Shikano and A. Hosoya, J. Phys. A: Math. Theor. 43,
[25] G. Svetlichny, arXiv:0902.4898 (2009). 025304 (2010).
9

[50] G. Chiribella, G.M. D’Ariano, P. Perinotti, Phys. Rev. [54] A. Anderson, Phys. Rev. D 51, 5707 (1995).
A 80, 022339 (2009). [55] C.J. Fewster, C. G. Wells, Phys. Rev. D 52, 5773 (1995).
[51] Y. Aharonov, P. G. Bergmann, and J. L. Lebowitz, Phys. [56] Abrams, D., and S. Lloyd Phys. Rev. Lett., 81, 3992
Rev. 134, B1410 (1964). (1998).
[52] Aharonov Y., Albert D.Z. and Vaidman L., Phys. Rev. [57] U. Yurtsever, Class. Quantum Grav. 11, 999 (1994).
Lett. 60 1351 (1988).
[53] M.J. Cassidy, Phys. Rev. D 52, 5676 (1995).

You might also like