Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 24

Review of Probability, Expected Utility

Economics 302 - Microeconomic Theory II: Strategic Behavior

Instructor: Songzi Du
compiled by Shih En Lu
Simon Fraser University

January 13, 2015

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

1 / 11

Review of Probability

Probability is a number between 0 and 1 and is a (either subjective or


objective) measure of how likely an outcome happens.
Outcomes, mutually exclusive. For example, set of outcomes
= {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6} for the roll of a dice. p(i) = 1/6 for i = 1, 2, . . . , 6.

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

2 / 11

Review of Probability

Probability is a number between 0 and 1 and is a (either subjective or


objective) measure of how likely an outcome happens.
Outcomes, mutually exclusive. For example, set of outcomes
= {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6} for the roll of a dice. p(i) = 1/6 for i = 1, 2, . . . , 6.
Event is a subset of outcomes. For example, that the roll is even is an
event ({2, 4, 6}).
Probability of an event is the sum of probabilities of outcomes in that
event.

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

2 / 11

Review of Probability

Probability is a number between 0 and 1 and is a (either subjective or


objective) measure of how likely an outcome happens.
Outcomes, mutually exclusive. For example, set of outcomes
= {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6} for the roll of a dice. p(i) = 1/6 for i = 1, 2, . . . , 6.
Event is a subset of outcomes. For example, that the roll is even is an
event ({2, 4, 6}).
Probability of an event is the sum of probabilities of outcomes in that
event.
Probabilities over all outcomes add up to 1.

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

2 / 11

Expected value
Suppose that the outcomes = {1, 2, . . . , n}. Probability of outcome i
is p(i).
Suppose that we have a function that depend on the outcome: X (i).
This is called a random variable.

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

3 / 11

Expected value
Suppose that the outcomes = {1, 2, . . . , n}. Probability of outcome i
is p(i).
Suppose that we have a function that depend on the outcome: X (i).
This is called a random variable.
The expected value of X is
E [X ] =

n
X

X (i)p(i) = X (1)p(1) + X (2)p(2) + + X (n)p(n).

i=1

Expected value is a notion of average.

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

3 / 11

Examples

What is the expected value of a roll of dice?

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

4 / 11

Examples

What is the expected value of a roll of dice?


n
X

i=1

1
1
1
1
1
= 1 + 2 + + 6 = 21 = 3.5.
6
6
6
6
6

If Alice gets a grade of 90 with probability 3/10, 80 with probability


2/10, 70 with probability 4/10, and 0 with probability 1/10. What is
her expected grade?

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

4 / 11

Examples

What is the expected value of a roll of dice?


n
X

i=1

1
1
1
1
1
= 1 + 2 + + 6 = 21 = 3.5.
6
6
6
6
6

If Alice gets a grade of 90 with probability 3/10, 80 with probability


2/10, 70 with probability 4/10, and 0 with probability 1/10. What is
her expected grade?

90

3
2
4
1
+ 80
+ 70
+0
= 27 + 16 + 28 = 71.
10
10
10
10

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

4 / 11

Independence

We may have two unrelated events. They are called independent


events. For example, the rolls of two dice; the weather in Vancouver
and the weather in Miami; the birth dates of two strangers, etc.
If two events are independent, knowing one event has no bearing on
the probability of the other event.

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

5 / 11

Independence

We may have two unrelated events. They are called independent


events. For example, the rolls of two dice; the weather in Vancouver
and the weather in Miami; the birth dates of two strangers, etc.
If two events are independent, knowing one event has no bearing on
the probability of the other event.
Probability of two independent events = probability of first
event probability of second event.

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

5 / 11

Independence

Alice goes to class with probability 1/2 (and skip class with
probability 1/2). Bob goes to class with probability 1/3 (and skip
class with probability 2/3). Assume Alice and Bob act independently.
What is the probability that both show up in class?

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

6 / 11

Independence

Alice goes to class with probability 1/2 (and skip class with
probability 1/2). Bob goes to class with probability 1/3 (and skip
class with probability 2/3). Assume Alice and Bob act independently.
What is the probability that both show up in class?
What is the probability that at least one of them skips class?

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

6 / 11

Independence

Alice goes to class with probability 1/2 (and skip class with
probability 1/2). Bob goes to class with probability 1/3 (and skip
class with probability 2/3). Assume Alice and Bob act independently.
What is the probability that both show up in class?
What is the probability that at least one of them skips class?
What is the probability that exactly one of them shows up in class?

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

6 / 11

Independence

Alice goes to class with probability 1/2 (and skip class with
probability 1/2). Bob goes to class with probability 1/3 (and skip
class with probability 2/3). Assume Alice and Bob act independently.
What is the probability that both show up in class?
What is the probability that at least one of them skips class?
What is the probability that exactly one of them shows up in class?
What is the probability of 4 Heads from 4 tosses of a coin?

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

6 / 11

Choice Under Uncertainty


You probably have learned about preferences and utility functions
over certain outcomes.
When preferences are complete and transitive, they can be
represented by a utility function.
(I.e. There exists a utility function u such that A % B if and only if
u(A) u(B).)

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

7 / 11

Choice Under Uncertainty


You probably have learned about preferences and utility functions
over certain outcomes.
When preferences are complete and transitive, they can be
represented by a utility function.
(I.e. There exists a utility function u such that A % B if and only if
u(A) u(B).)
But life is full of uncertainty! You dont know for sure how good (or
how bad) the economy will be in two years. You dont know for sure
what other people will do.
You have to make decision under uncertainty.
Goal: represent preferences over uncertain outcomes.

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

7 / 11

Notation and Terminology

Suppose a situation has n possible outcomes, labeled 1, 2, ..., n.


A lottery [p(1), p(2), ..., p(n)] is a list of probabilities, where p(i) is
the probability that outcome i occurs. (We must have
p(1) + p(2) + ... + p(n) = 1).

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

8 / 11

Notation and Terminology

Suppose a situation has n possible outcomes, labeled 1, 2, ..., n.


A lottery [p(1), p(2), ..., p(n)] is a list of probabilities, where p(i) is
the probability that outcome i occurs. (We must have
p(1) + p(2) + ... + p(n) = 1).
Example: you get a grade of A with probability 30%, B with
probability 40%, F with probability 30%.
Define outcome 1 as A, outcome 2 as B, and outcome 3 as F.
The lottery is then [0.3, 0.4, 0.3].

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

8 / 11

Expected Utility

Suppose outcome 1 gives you utility u(1), outcome 2 u(2), and so on.
What is the utility of lottery L = [p(1), p(2), ..., p(n)]?
Natural answer:

E[u] =

n
X

u(i)p(i) = p(1)u(1) + p(2)u(2) + + p(n)u(n),

i=1

which is the Ls expected utility.


Expected utility gives a preference over lotteries.

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

9 / 11

Expected Utility

Example: You prefer A over B over F. Assigning utility of 2 to A, 1 to


B, and 0 to F would represent your preferences over these certain
outcomes.

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

10 / 11

Expected Utility

Example: You prefer A over B over F. Assigning utility of 2 to A, 1 to


B, and 0 to F would represent your preferences over these certain
outcomes.
But suppose you prefer {B for sure} over {a 90% chance of A and a
10% chance of F}. With the above utilities, does expected utility
represent your preferences over lotteries?

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

10 / 11

Expected Utility

Example: You prefer A over B over F. Assigning utility of 2 to A, 1 to


B, and 0 to F would represent your preferences over these certain
outcomes.
But suppose you prefer {B for sure} over {a 90% chance of A and a
10% chance of F}. With the above utilities, does expected utility
represent your preferences over lotteries?
So its important to assign the right intensity of utility to each
outcome not just the order (ordinal utility), but the size matters
(cardinal utility).

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

10 / 11

Axioms for Expected Utility


Given preferences over lotteries, it turns out that its not always
possible to find a set of utilities over outcomes such that expected
utility represents the said preferences over lotteries.
Just as you needed assumptions on preferences over outcomes to
build a utility function representing them, you need assumptions on
preferences over lotteries to build an expected utility function
representing them.
There are four required assumptions (i.e., axioms): completeness,
transitivity, continuity, and independence.
They are fairly reasonable and intuitive.

Axioms for expected utility are due to John von Neumann and Oskar
Morgenstern, the founding fathers of game theory.
Expected utility makes preference over lotteries easy to work with.

ECON 302 (SFU)

Lecture 2

January 13, 2015

11 / 11

You might also like