Social Network As A Subjective Construct Artricle 1969 Social Networki

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 14

Social Network as a Subjective

Construct: A New Application for


an Old Idea*

R O B E R T A. S T E B B I N S / MemorialUniversityofNewfoundland
Bott a dCfini le rCseau social comme Ctant un ensemble de relations sociales qui ne
posshdent pas de frontikres communes. Par ailleurs personne ne sest prCoccup6
&explorer les rCpercussions quengendrent cette connexion entre ces deux concepts. En se basant sur la dC6nition WebCrienne dune relation sociale ou interpersonnelle (IR), il devient 6vident quessentiellement cest une orientation mutuelle
entre deux individus; cest une perception subjective ou une prhdisposition. Les
conskquences logiques de cette observation par rapport au rCseau social sont
examinks. On arrive i la conclusion que les rCseaux sont aussi des modeles subjectifs et, par voie de consCquence, ils possiident le pouvoir de guider la conduite
dans une situation sociale.
Bott has defined social network as a set of social relationships for which there is
no common boundary. Yet, no one has ever bothered to explore the implications
of this connection between these two concepts. By examining Webers definition
of social or interpersonal relationship (IR) , it becomes evident that it is basically
a mutual orientation between two persons; it is a subjective construct or predisposition. The logical consequences of this observation for the social network
are considered, and it is concluded that networks are also subjective constructs
and therefore have the potential to guide behaviour in the social situation.
The ever-growing body of literature incorporating the notion of social network into its analysis is strong evidence for the fertility of an idea formally
introduced into social science by J. A. Barnes (1954). The numerous studies
which have appeared since that time have related social network to an extensive array of subjects. A majority of these have employed this idea as an
explanatory factor, explaining or helping to explain such diverse phenomena
as social change, efficiency of communities as melting pots, links between
the various groups in a society, social class, maintenance of rural ties, and
nature of contacts outside the family (Epstein, 1961; Gutkind, 1965; P.
Mayer, 1962; Mitchell, 1966; Srinivas and Beteille, 1964; Bott, 1957;
Nelson, 1966; Young and Wilmott, 1957; Barnes, 1954). A somewhat
smaller proportion of studies or summaries has treated social networks as
objects of explanation while investigating influences of rural to urban migration on networks, formation of interpersonal relationships as they atrect
networks, types of networks, gossip and networks, and how networks
originate (Frankenberg, 1965; Katz, 1966; Adams, 1967; Bott, 1957;
Barnes, 1954; Hannerz, 1968).

1 would like to express my gratitude to D. Ralph Matthews and Robert Paine for
their valuable comments on a draft of this paper.
Rev. canad. k.
& Anth./Canad. Rev. Soc. & Anth. 6(1)1969

For the purposes of this introductory discussion we can accept Botts


definition of social network as a set of social relationships for which there is
no common boundary (Bott, 1957:59). In the strict sense of the word a network is not a structure, since it has no shared boundaries (boundaries recognized by everyone in the social network) and no commonly recognized
hierarchy or central co-ordinating agency. Nevertheless, there are interconnections between others in the network in that some of its members are
directly in touch with each other while others are not. Thus, it is also a characteristic of networks that their mesh may be closely-knit (many members
having direct contact) or loosely-knit (few members having direct contact)
(Barnes, 1954; Bott, 1957:59). Many of the studies mentioned above provide evidence for Botts definition of social networks as comprised of social
relationships.
A certain amount of confusion has sprung up among those who have
endeavoured to consider the idea of network on a theoretical plane. This
confusion is almost entirely centred in the question of whether a network
should be approached from the point of view of a particular person (egocentred perspective) or from a more totalistic stance in which the component
relationships are seen as a sum total of every persons network (holistic perspective). The ego-centred perspective is like the standpoint used in kinship
analysis, whereas the holistic perspective focuses less on any particular point
in the network than on the total structure of relationships.
What has happened, as Adrian Mayer (1966) recently observed, is that
Bott used network in an ego-centred sense, a usage which Barnes originally
reserved for the term set which he never developed to any definitive degree.
Most subsequent writers have continued to follow Bott, and we shall do the
same here. This definition has become established in the parlance of anthropologists and sociologists.
Outside of these few attempts at conceptual clarification, there has been
a regrettable paucity of theoretical discussion about the concept of social
network. In order to strengthen the explanatory power of this idea, we shall
examine its logical connection with the concept of interpersonal or social
relationship (IR) and the implications which this link has for the network as
an explanation. The set of statements below will serve as a sort of itinerary for
the theoretical excursion which follows:
1. Interpersonal relationships as mutual orientations between persons are
basically psychological predispositions to respond which guide behaviour in
the social situation.
2. Interpersonal relationships are the component parts of social networks.
3. If one or more of a persons IRs influence his actions as they are being
carried out with reference to still another IR, then we can say that part or all
of that persons social network directly guides his situated behaviour.
4. Therefore, we can say that a social network is also a psychological predisposition to respond.
2

1 For a critique of the term social network and the closely related notion of field
(also used by Barnes), which is somewhat contradictory to Mayer, see Jay (1964).

5 . The observation that the network is a predisposition which can directly


explain behaviour, although perhaps not wholly new, has received little or no
systematic empirical or theoretical attention in the past.
INTERPERSONAL RELATIONSHIPS

Max Weber I: 1947: 118) can be given credit for setting the basic theoretical
foundation of the contemporary approach to social or interpersonal relationships: The term social relationship will be used to denote the behaviour of
a plurality of actors in so far as, in its meaningful content, the action of each
takes account of that of the others and is oriented in these terms. The social
relationship thus consists entirely and exclusively in the existence of a probability that there will be, in some meaningfully understandable sense, a course
of social a c t i ~ n . It~is clear from this quote and Webers subsequent discussion that mutual orientation is the essence of IR. In order to have a more
concise definition at hand, which emphasizes this subjective quality, we shall
redefine the interpersonal relationship as egos sustained orientation toward a
particular alter which is perceived by ego to be reciprocated by that alter.3
Certain basic characteristics of IRS must first be discussed as a prerequisite
to our later consideration of IRS as predispositions. Accordingly, we shall
briefly review the intimate nature of IRS, their changeability, some of the reasons for their continuation, the relationship of sentiments to IRS, and the private culture of IRS.
Interpersonal relationships are born in the prolonged interaction of two
people, and it is not unusual to find that more than one has sprung up between them (Znaniecki, 1965:89).4Related to this observation is the fact
that there is i l strain toward totality whereby as time goes on, the flow of
external events calls forth more and more of the total set of identities of the
individuals involved (McCall and Simmons, 1966: 186).
Each of the parties in an IR recognizes the other as a distinct individual
about whom he has some degree of prior knowledge (McCall and Simmons,
1966:169). This knowledge is not only historical knowledge about ones
partner but intimate knowledge as well, a facet of IRS which probably characterizes all but themarginal cases (Simmel, 1950: 12&127).j
It is probably acknowledged by most participants in IRS that they are by no
2 Cooley (1922: 114-120) also approached IRS from a subjective point of view by treating them as clusters of sentiments attached to a symbol or image of another person.
3 Because IRS develop through sustained contact, it is probably safe to say that, in fact,
they are reciprocated. There appears to be little likelihood that a normal person
would see an IR between himself and another individual while the latter did not see
one between them. Of course, the intensity of the sentiments involved may vary, as
we shall see shortly. Evidence that IRS, in fact, are reciprocated can be found in Newcomb (1961 ). Schutz (1964: 111 ) presents what is basically an operational definition
of an interpersonal relationship: each of them [the partners in the IR] has the chance
to reestablish the we-relation, if interrupted, and to continue it as if no intermittance
had occurred.
4 A common example of two IRS between the same parties is that of the father-son and
employer-employee relationships.
5 Schutz (1964: 1 1 3 ) has also defined intimacy in an operational manner: the degree
of reliable knowledge we have of another person.

means totally static conditions even though some exhibit a greater constancy
than others. Strauss notes that involvements are evolvements - in the course
of which parties and their relationships become transformed (Strauss,
1959:37). Thus, there are unevenly spaced high points in the career of any
IR after which one is a difEerent person to the other and the other is difEerent
to oneself. Such experiences along with less dramatic ones may actually effect
the development of additional IRS, as when the boss invites his subordinate
to accompany him on a fishing trip thereby initiating a sequence of interaction
which may lead to a friendship relationship.
It is also important for our purposes to recognize that while IRS quite frequently terminate, there are forces which may prevent this from happening.
Reward dependability is a characteristic feature of many IRS and a major
reason for their existence and continuation.6 Ascription, both desired and
undesired, is a second compelling reason for maintaining a certain relationship, as well as for initiating it. Men may also be more or less forced to remain in an IR for reasons other than ascription. Commitment, as this process is sometimes referred to, is manifested by means of a variety of arrangements, such as the existence of pension funds and seniority rights which make
it costly for a person to quit his job simply because he does not get along with
his boss (Becker, 1960). Of course, the person may also become positively
attached or involved in an IR. Furthermore, ones investment in terms of
time and other resources may operate to sustain a relationship. The effectiveness of these forces apparently depends somewhat upon the IR under consideration; for instance, kin relationships, at least for some segments of the
population, are harder to break than others (Bott, 1957:93; McCall and
Simmons, 1966: 179).

Sentiments and Interpersonal Relationships


Essential to any discussion of IRS is the idea of sentiment, or the basic unit of
organization of affect (Pear, 1964 :634-635 ) .8 A sentiment is the generalized
feeling which one person has for the other in an IR, and it is to be identified
through a pattern of response, rather than through any particular act (Shibutani, 1961:333). Thus, a man in love with a woman expresses different
emotions according to the situation in which he finds himself; he expressesjoy
in her presence, sorrow in her prolonged absence, fear when her life is in
danger, and so forth. Sentiment organizes the appropriate emotions in the
ongoing situation and it must be stressed that neither this underlying sentiment nor its emotional manifestations need always be positive in a relationship. One can have a negative IR with a neighbour or work superior, for instance, based upon the sentiment of hate, and it seems that this is especially
likely to happen where he is committed to that IR. Although there is considerable empirical and theoretical work on specific negative relationships,

6 Most of these forces are presented by McCall and Simmons (1966: 179).
7 For a further discussion of the distinction between attachment and commitment, see
Stebbins (1969).
8 Some of the basic works on sentiment are those of Shand (1920), McDougall(1908),
and Shibutani (1961).

general discussions of the nature of IRS tend to overlook this characteristic by


by limiting their focus to relationships built on positive bonds 0nly.O
Of course, the intensity of the sentiment in an IR varies from situation to
situation for each person, as well as varying over the career of the relationship. Variation in the intensity of sentiments alerts us to the fact that sentiment is only part, albeit a very important part, of the meaning which an
enduring IR may have for a person. An IR may also have rational, evaluative,
and traditional meanings for those involved in them, and these forms of meaning may also vary from situation to situation and over the career of the relationship. If there were not several kinds of meaning contained in an IR, many
relationships would probably disintegrate or come dangerously close to disintegration with each dip of the intensity of the supporting sentiment. We are
assuming, of course, that no one will maintain an IR which does not hold some
meaning for him.

The Private Culture


Because IRS are basically subjectiveconstructs, it should be apparent that they
develop from virtual social identities or the categories to which the parties
of the relationship judge the other to belong (GofFman, 1963:2).1 These
are to be distinguished from actual social identities or those categories to
which one can be proved, by objective analysis, to belong and those attributes
which one can be proved to possess.
In the broad sense of the term, identities have roles attached to them; roles
shall be defined here as sets of expectations of behaviour. This set of expectations can always be subdivided into a publicly-recognized component and a
private component, the latter having been generated exclusively in the interaction of the two participants. The public expectations are generally acknowledged by members of the community to apply to those persons claiming to
have or imputed to possess certain attributes and to those claiming to be or
said to be members of certain categories. While there are always some community-wide or public expectations associated with them, for certain kinds
of IRS (e.g., enemy, friend, and lover) the private aspect, nevertheless, is said
tobeby farthelargest (Nadel, 1957:42).
This private aspect of role is part of the larger private culture associated
with the IR, which may include a rudimentary common language, common
goals, memories of common experiences, and so forth. The recognition of a
private culture associated with an IR contributes to the perception of the relationship as being unique among other relationships.
Znterpersonul Relationships as Predispositions
By treating interpersonal relationships as predispositions, we give them a
more explicit psychological foundation, a foundation implied in the words
reciprocal or mutual orientation found within the definitions presented
9 See, for example, S i m e l ( l 9 5 0 : 118-142) and McCall and Simmons (1966, chap. 7).
10 Identity is preferred over closely related ideas like status, position, and rank
because of its apparently broader scope. For example, one can have the identity of
neighbour, but we would not ordinarily call this a position or a status.

earlier. Furthermore, as we shall see later, the proposition that IRS are predispositional is an essential part of the causal nexus linking this concept and that
of social network to situated behaviour. Social relationships have traditionally
been seen in this latter role of guiding behaviour, a view which can be traced
back to Webers statement on this subject. However, their conceptualization
as predispositions and, hence, as subjective constructs has never been clearly
formulated.
The usage of the term predisposition follows that of Campbell
( 1963:97-112). He limits his statement to acquired states, stressing the importance of the fact that predispositions (or as he calls them, acquired
behavioural dispositions) are enduring and that they remain dormant until
activated by situational stimuli. When activated, these products of past
experience impinge upon our awareness, equip us with a specific view of the
world, and guide behaviour in the immediate present. Values, attitudes, bits
of knowledge, memory, habits, and meanings all have predispositionalqualiities about them.
The use of the term orientation in definitions of the IR is itself a clue to
the latters status as a predisposition. Websters Third International Dictionary defines an orientation in one sense of the word as the choice or adjustment of associations, connections, or dispositions. It is of interest that
Campbell includes adju~tment,~
orientation, and disposition in his
extensive list of acquired behavioural dispositions. In harmony with the definition of orientation as an adjustment of predispositions, there are several
subsidiary presdispositions to be found in any IR. Knowledge about the other
person, whether intimate or simply historical, may be considered as one such
predisposition. The same is also true of the knowledge ego holds about alters
expectations of him and other aspects of the private culture. Commitment or
attachment to a particular IR is a predisposition and so are the sentiments and
other meanings which are part of any relationship.
Interpersonal relationships are also special views of the world; views which
develop from their component subsidiary predispositions. It is perhaps this
facet of IRS which explains best Nadels observation (1957:9) that there is
a consistency about the many diverse acts which take place within them.
Within wide limits we may still say of persons in a given relationship that
they act towards each other always in the same manner.
To the people in them IRS when activated have a very poignant reality which
is manifested in at least three ways. First of all, the continuous interaction between the two parties works to emphasize the existence of the relationship.
Secondly, the high points in the career of the IR also make the participants
conscious of it. Finally, the basic sentiment and its various emotional expressions make the person aware of the relationship.
T H E SOCIAL N E T W O R K

As we have already observed, Botts definitionof social network ( 1957:59)


indicates the importance of interpersonal relationships as the basic elements

of this construction. She viewed a social network as a set of social relationships for which there is no common boundary. However, we have also noted
that the traditional approach to IRS is essentially predispositional which means
that upon activation these mental states help guide behaviour in the immediate
setting. Now., since most people have several relationships at any one period
in their lives, there is a strong possibility that one or more of them will be
activated during interaction with members of the community. Where the
ongoing interchange is with one of egos relationship partners and his behaviour is at least partially guided by his reflection about one or more other
IRS activated because they are relevant to the business at hand, we can say that
all or a portion of his social network is influencing his actions. Because
clusters of IRS, and perhaps not infrequently even the total set of IRS, can influence a persons action in the situation, we are forced to conclude that the
social network also has subjective or predispositional qualities.l
Awareness of the Social Network
Like an IR, a social network as an activated predisposition must also be subjectively real to the individual whose network it is; that is, we are aware of
activated predispositions. There is a considerable amount of theoretical discourse and empirical evidence in various social science fields which support
this assertion. We shall briefly review some of them here.
One of the ways subjective awareness is manifested is through the direct
and indirect effects which IRS in a network have upon each other. Direct contact between others in the various IRS is especially likely where the social network is closely-knit. Under these circumstances what transpires between two
people in one relationship may affect another relationship through transactions in the social network of the second person. In this way a chain reaction can be set up, becoming, for example, a form of social control (Epstein,
1961; Hannerz, 1968). This direct influence is also seen where a third party,
an IR signific:ant in the network of both individuals, intercedes or threatens
to intercede in the affairs of their I R . ~For instance, Kemper (1968) found
that wives arid parents influence egos response to alter in IRS established in
a work organization.
Another possibility of direct influence is seen in Newcombs A-B-x theory
of the symmetry of orientation (1961, chap. 2). Where A is the central actor in
an IR, B is his partner, and x is another person (for our purposes one with
whom both have IRS), the following postulate may be advanced: The
stronger the forces toward AS co-orientation in respect to B and x, ( a ) the
greater AS strain toward symmetry with B in respect to x; and ( 6 ) the greater
the likelihood of increased symmetry as a consequence of one or more
11 Statements by B l u e r (1956), Cicourel (1964: 119), and Fenton (1968) all support

the belief that if structural variables can be said to influence ongoing behaviour, then
they are mediated by the personal interpretation of the actor; and if personal interpretation has not been demonstrated, then any putative causal link between structure
and behaviour may actually be no more than a chance correlation.
12 Nadel (1957:86-87) refers to this situation as the triadization of roles. See also
Blau (l964:3 1-32).

communicative acts.13 The influencing force here is the desire on the part of
the central actor to maintain some sort of cognitive equilibrium with respect to
the elements of his social network through communication about this matter
to his partner, B. The intensity of co-orientation determines which xs will
require symmetry. The possibilities of disequilibrium, and hence awareness
of the network, are considerable when we remember that A may see himself
in a positive or negative relationshipto B as well as to x.
The various IRS also may have indirect effects through the person whose
network it is. Much, if not all, of this can be fitted into one of the various balance theories, which are in many ways like Newcombs A-B-x model but do
not involve communication with the actors partner. In general, a state of
balance exists for the actor when the elements in the social network have noncontradictory relationships for him.The basic proposition in balance theory
is that where there is imbalance a person strives to restore the state of balance.
Udiie the A-B-x model the elements themselves are not, as a rule, in contact.
Thus, when in one mans social network his clergyman demands attitudes of
racial equality whereas close friends in his neighbourhood demand attitudes
of discrimination, a state of imbalance prevails. Balance theory hypothesizes
that the individual in question will strive for balance, which may be achieved
in various ways. Unfortunately, it is beyond the scope of this paper to examine
these at the present time; our objective is simply to point out that the social
network is very much a reality to the individual because of the pressures
which originate within it.
In addition to the pervasive influence of the component IRS on each other,
the problems of trying to intermesh the daily and weekly routines associated
with each relationship create an awareness of the over-all network. One
comes to realize which IRS mean the most to him as he distributes his time to
each. As McCall and Simmons (1966:246) put it, it is a concern of agendaconstruction, and ones agenda is not altogether a personal matter but must
be interactively determined.
Because ofthe problems of agenda-construction connected with maintaining several IRS, the addition or loss of an IR also calls for a certain amount of
planning, an activity which in itself makes one conscious of his network.
Moreover, gaining new IRS or losing old ones may upset network balance or
symmetry. It may be hypothesized that these problems are especially acute in
what Bott (1957:95) has called the transitional network: where one is
changing froma tightly-knit to a loosely-knit network, or vice versa. Finally,
Morenos discussion (1960:W) about death in the social atom (see footnote
15) can be interpreted as illustrating these points: If we happen to survive
the ones we love or hate, we die a bit with them as we feel the shadow of death
marching from one person in our social atom to another.

13 The term a-orientation or simultaneous orientation is equivalent to attitude in


the more inclusive sense of refemng to both cathectic and cognitive tendencies.
Symmetry refers to the similarities of AS and BS orientations to x.
14 For a further discussion and bibliography of some of the various balance models, see

Brown (1965,chap. 11).

size is also an important factor for agenda-construction;only so many IRS


can be properly maintained in any given period of time. Thus, we can say that
size makes the network subjectivelyreal by curtailing the addition of new relationships and by pushing the claims on ones time resources to the limit. After
assessing a variety of IRS, Jennings (1950:309)discovered that the typical
maximum number was twelve. Nelson (1966) has provided some evidence
from his study of families that tightly-knit networks are more demanding of
time than the loosely-knit ones. Another important observation on the factor
of size is supplied by Goodenough ( 1965:7) to the effect that the number of
IRS depends upon how many are available, and this may vary from one culture
to another. Finally, we may note that even if further expansion is possible
from the point of view of the agenda, the psychological necessities of maintaining balance and symmetry set or strongly favour network growth in particular directions, directions which are compatible with the existing IRS. It
would seem, in light of this last statement, that people also become at least
partially committed to networks, as well as to certain IRS.
Social Networks as Predispositions
If social networks are to be accepted as predispositions, then we must be able
to demonstrate this characteristic of them in a way independent of the dispositional nature of their component IRS.Just because each individual IR in the
network is a tendency to respond is not reason enough to assert that the network as a whole or any subpart of it also has this quality when activated.
What features of a social network and its various segments give it the alleged
predispositional character?
We can answer this question by pointing out that, like an IR, a social network is an orientation or an adjustment of subsidiary dispositions. The knowledge which a person has about the direct influence which IRS in his network
have upon each other may be taken as one of these dispositions. Imbalance
stemming from the presence of contradictory elements is definitely a state of
mind which also predisposes a person to respond. Conflict of the daily and
weekly routines associated with each IR not only creates awareness of the
over-all social network but activates an adjustment disposition which is manifested in agenda construction. The same sort of conflict emerges when one
attempts to increase the size of his set of IRS. Adjustment, in this case, may be
simply to refuse to interact with the person in question, thereby preventing
the development of a relationship.
Botts earlier definition of social network while noting the role of IRS does
not adequately convey this subjective characteristic which we have been discussing. It has been pointed out that she generally takes an ego-centred
approach. A social network from our perspective is not ego-centred, in that
the individual is merely the point from which analysis may begin, but personcentred: it is seen from the subjective standpoint of the individual whose network it is. Thus, we can now redefine social network as the orientation which
develops from considering all or a portion of ones interpersonal relationships.

Formulated in this way this notion differs from several related ones which
have appeared in the sociological and social psychological literature.ls
SOCIAL NETWORK I N EXPLANATIONS OF BEHAVIOUR

The principal use to which networks have been put in the past is that of help
ing to account for the pattern of distribution of values, attitudes, or some sort
of information. The kind of content conveyed may be gossip, rural values in
the city, news about kin, or any number of other interests which can be spread
by human contact. Recognizing and treating the social network as a predisposition does not in any way supplant this approach, but rather the predispositional point of view complements the communicationsnetwork stance by
opening up a new avenue of application: the direct explanation of behaviour
in the social situation. Just how new this use of social network actually is
could be a matter of conjecture. Observations like the following from Elizabeth Botts study (1957:94)have, no doubt, appeared from time to time in
the network literature: But although external people may help the elementary family, close-knit networks may also interfere with conjugal solidarity.
A wifes loyalty to her mother may interfere with her relationship with her
husband. Similarly her relationship with her husband may interfere with her
relationship with her mother. A mans loyalty to his friends may interfere
with his obligations to his wife and vice versa.
The point which should be stressed is that there has been no explicit formulation of a predispositional or subjective approach to networks. And, such
an approach has utility as an explanation for certain kinds of human action
as it is played out in social settings.
We can begin by asking when is this predispositional point of view of social
networks and IRS called for in explanations? Or, perhaps, why is it needed at
all? Is not the ordinary objective stance adequate? In answering these questions we may note that first of all, the predispositional point of view is required when the object of explanation is human social action of some kind:
e.g., migration to an urban centre or the channels of gossip, to name two

10

15 The formulation which comes closest to being synonymous with our version of social
network is Morenos social atom (196052-54). However, the following two features of social atoms disqualify them as social networks from our point of view. (1)
Moreno states that actors can be related to others even when those others do not
know it. However, the best evidence to date suggests that IRS, as we have been discussing them in this paper, are reciprocated (Newcomb, 1961). ( 2 ) Moreno includes
wished-for relationships in his social atom, while the idea of social network as developed in this paper is comprised only of ongoing IRS. Other similar formulations
like Mertons status-set and role-set (1 957:368-384) or Znanieckis social circle
(1965:203-209) focus on one role or identity of the individual actor, while a social
network encompasses all of the actors identities and roles as long as there are established IRS involved. Finally Kempers reference-set ( 1966) should be mentioned
since it includes the total aggregation of others from whom one derives central notions about oneself. Certainly any social network would include many of these, but
it would, at the same time, exclude certain reference others with whom there are no
IRS established (e.g., the prominent baseball star for the ten-year-old boy) and it
would include certain non-reference others (e.g., the hated superior or the hostile
neighbour).

recent foci of network studies. More specifically, and this is the second point,
it is needed when structural or cultural explanations or both fail to d o their
job adequately - when there is variation in social action which these frameworks cannot: account for. When this happens we may be sure that personal
interpretation has entered the picture. This personal interpretation has been
referred to as the definition of the situation (see Stebbins, 1967b); the combination of internalized (and therefore previously interpreted) elements of
culture and social structure, of personality, and of the situation which when
reflected upon and defined in the ongoing setting can lead to behaviour that
is to some degree different from what is categorically expected. The significance of the process of interpretation for the social sciences has been clearly
stated by Herbert Blumer in his critique of variable analysis: In my judgment, the crucial limit to the successful application of variable analysis to
human group life is set by the process of interpretation or definition that goes
on in human groups. This process, which I believe to be the core of human
action, gives a character to human group life that seems at variance with the
logical premnses of variable analysis. ... Any scheme designed to analyze
human group life in its general character has to fit this process of interpretation (1956:686).
The definition of the situation is basically an interrelation and interpretation of other predispositions which have been activated by certain situational
factors. It is our contention that among the persons predispositions will be
found specific IRS and all or a portion of his social network, where activated.
Thus, the strength of this predispositional view lies in the fact that it enables
us to study peoples social networks at the situational level where it is hypothesized that on some occasions these networks modify culturally expected
behaviour.
Research utilizing these concepts in this way should not be diflticult. Interpersonal reIationships can be inferred in a variety of ways; such as, by length
of time in which ego has known alter, by amount of contact between the pair,
by ability to predict the others behaviour, as well as by the chances of reestablishing the relationship as suggested by Schutz and cited earlier in this
article. Whether or not any particular IR was influencing behaviour in a given
situation could easily be discovered by in-depth interviewing with regard to
alters salience at that time. Social networks could be determined by getting
the respondent to report all interpersonal relationships of sufficient length,
intimacy, and frequency of contact in various spheres of life: occupational,
familial, recreational, neighbourly, religious, political, educational, commercial, and governmental. The activation of ones social network in any specific
situation coulld be uncovered by a question like were there certain things you
wouldnt do with or say to certain other persons present because you were
afraid it would get back to a mutual acquaintance? Information about the
respondents awareness of the incompatibility of expectations stemming from
various IRS as they affect his behaviour indicates influence of the network as
does awareness of a conflict of routine.

11

SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS

Our main purpose has been to examine the logical connection between the
concept of interpersonal or social relationship (IR) and that of social network, and to determine the implications of this link for network as an explanation. On the basis of the observation that since Webers time IRS have been
regarded as reciprocated orientations between two people, we presented a
definition which more adequately conveyed this subjective or predispositional
nature of the relationship. It followsthat because of their status as predispositions IRS influence actual behaviour in the social situation. Botts definition
of social network as a set of relationships was assessed from this point of
view. If one or more of a persons IRS influence his actions as they are being
camed out with reference to one or more other IRS, then it is possible to conclude that part or all of that persons social network directly guides his situated behaviour. Therefore, we can say that a social network is also a psychological predisposition. This observation that the network is fundamentally a
subjective construct which can be used as a direct explanation of behaviour,
although perhaps not wholly new, has received little or no systematic empirical or theoretical attention in the past. Yet, such an application of network
could be very fruitful in helping to account for why men d&e situations as
they do and hence, why they act as they do. Moreover, as Boissevain
(1968:546-9) has pointed out, non-group phenomena like networks help to
free social anthropology from the grip of functionalism, thus opening new
vistas for research and explanation.
REFERENCES

12

Adams, B. N.
1967 Interaction theory and the social network. Sociometry 30:64-78.
Barnes, J. A.
1954 Class and committees in a Norwegian island parish.
Human Relations 7:39-58.
Becker, H. S.
1960 Notes on the concept of commitment.
American Journal of Sociology 66: 3 2 4 0 .
Blau, P. M.
1964 Power and Exchange in Social Life. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Blumer, H.
1956 Sociological analysis and the variable.
American Sociological Review 21 :683-690.
Boissevain, J.
1968 The place of nongroups in the social sciences. Man 3:542-556.
Bott, E.
1957 Family and Social Network. London: Tavistock Publications.
Brown, R.
1965 Social Psychology. New York: The Free Press.
Campbell, D. T.
1963 Social attitudes and other acquired behavioral dispositions,
pp. 94-172 in Sigmund Koch (ed.), Psychology: AStudy of a Science.
Vol. 6. New York: McGraw-Hill Co.
Cicourel, A. V.
1964 Method and Measurement in Sociology. New York: The Free Press.

Cooley, C. H.
1922 Human Nature and the Social Order. New York: Schocken Books.
Epstein, A. L.
1961 The network and urban social organization.
Rhodes-Livingstone Journal 29: 29-62.
Fenton, C. S.
1968 The myth of subjectivism as a special method of sociology.
The Sociological Review 16:333-349.
Frankenberg, R.
1965 Communities in Britain. Harmondsworth Middlesex: Penguin Books.
Goffman, E.
1963 Stigma. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
Goodenough, W. H.
1965 Rethinking status and role, pp. 1-24 in Association of Social
Anthropologists, The Relevance of Models for Social Anthropology, V O ~ .1.
London: Tavistock Publications.
Gutkind, P. W.
1965 African urbanism, mobility, and the social network.
International Journal of Comparative Sociology 6: 48-60.
Hannen, U.
1968 Gossip, networks, and culture in a black American ghetto.
Ethnos 32:35-60.
Jay, E. J.
1964 The concept of field and network in anthropological research.
M a 64~137-138.
Jennings, H. H.
1950 Leadership and Isolation, 2nd ed. New York: Longmans, Green & Co.
Katz, F. E.
1966 Social participation and social structure. Social Forces 45: 1%210.
Kemper, T. D.
1966 Self-conceptions and the expectations of significant others.
Sociological Quarterly 7: 323-344.
1968 Third party penetration of local social systems. Sociometry 31:1-29.
Mayer, A. C.
1966 The significance of quasi-groups in the study of complex societies,
pp. 97-122 in Association of Social Anthropologists,The Social
Anthropology of Complex Societies,vol. 4. London: Tavistock Publications.
Mayer, P.
1962 Labour migrancy and the social network, pp. 21-34 in J. F. Holleman,
et al. (eds.), Problems of Transition: Proceedings of the
Social Science Research Conference held in University of Natal, Durban.
Pietermaritzburg: Natal University Press.
McCall, G. J., and J. L. Simmons
1966 Identities and Interactions. New York: The Free Press.
McDougall, W.
1908 An Introduction to Social Psychology. London: Methuen & Co.
Merton, R. K.
1957 Social Theory and Social Structure, rev. ed. New York: The Free Press.
Mitchell, C. J.
1966 Theoretical orientations in African urban studies, pp. 37-68 in
Association of Social Anthropologists,The Social Anthropology of
Complex Societies, vol. 4. London: Tavistock Publications.
Moreno, J. L., et al.
1960 The Sot-iometry Reader. New York: The Free Press.
Nadel, S. F.
1957 The Theory of Social Structure. New York: The Free Press.
Nelson, J. I.
1966 Clique contacts and family orientations.
American Sociological Review 3 1 :663-672.

13

Newcomb, T. M.
1961 The Aquaintame Process. New York: Holt, Rinehart &Winston.
Pear, T. H.
1964 Sentiment, pp. 634-635 in Julius Gould and W. L. Kolb (eds.),
A Dictionary of the Social Sciences. New York: The Free Press.
Schutz, A.
1964 Collected Papers 11: Studies in Social Theory.The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
%and, A. F.
1920 The Foundations of Character. London: Macmillan.
Shibutani, T.
1961 Society and Personality. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
Simmel, G.
1950 The Sociology of Georg Simmel, trans. K. Wolff.
New York: The Free Press.
Srinivas, N. M., and A. Beteille
1964 Networks in Indian social structure. Man 64: 165-8.
Stebbins, R. A.
1967 A theory of the definition of the situation.
Canadian Review of Sociology and Anthropology 4: 148-164.
1969 Commitment to Deviance: the Non-professional Criminal in the
Community. New York: Greenwood Publishing Corp.
Strauss, A. L.
1959 Mirrors and Masks. New York: The Free Press.
Young, M., and P. Wilmott
1957 Family and Kinship in East London. New York: The Free Press.
Znaniecki, F.
1965 Social Relations and Social Roles. San Francisco: Chandler Publishing Co.

14

You might also like