Aristocracy

You might also like

Download as doc, pdf, or txt
Download as doc, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 3

Aristocracy

From LoveToKnow 1911

Ads by Google

Royal Title - Intl Commission Nobility & Royalty Certification of True Honors
www.nobility-royalty.com

Plato - Plato's Harmonia Discovered It is a Music Scale!


www.recoveryoflostknowledge.com

Is Jesus Really God? - Scholars Examine the Facts About Jesus' Claims to be God
www.Y-Jesus.com/JesusGod

ARISTOCRACY (Gr. iipcaros, best; Kparia, government), etymologically, the "rule of


the best," a form of government variously defined and appreciated at different times and
by different authorities. In Greek political philosophy, aristocracy is the government of
those who most nearly attain to the ideal of human perfection. Thus Plato in the Republic
advocates the rule of the "philosopher-king" who, in the social scheme, is analogous to
Reason in the intellectual, and alone is qualified to control the active principles, i.e. the
fighting population and the artisans or workers. Aristocracy is thus the government by
those who are superior both morally and intellectually, and, therefore, govern directly in
the interests of the governed, as a good doctor works for the good of his patient. Aristotle
classified good governments under three heads - monarchy, aristocracy and
commonwealth (iroXcTEia), to which he opposed the three perverted forms - tyranny or
absolutism, oligarchy and democracy or mob-rule. The distinction between aristocracy
and oligarchy, which are both necessarily the rule of the few, is that whereas the few
apcaroc will govern unselfishly, the oligarchs, being the few wealthy ("plutocracy" in
modern terminology), will allow their personal interests to predominate. While Plato's
aristocracy might be the rule of the wise and benevolent despot, Aristotle's is necessarily
the rule of the few.

Historically aristocracy develops from primitive monarchy by the gradual progressive


limitation of the regal authority. This process is effected primarily by the nobles who
have hitherto formed the council of the king (an excellent example will be found in
Athenian politics, see Archon), whose triple prerogative - religious, military and judicial -
is vested, e.g., in a magistracy of three. These are either members of the royal house or
the heads of noble families, and are elected for life or periodically by their peers, i.e. by
the old royal council (cf. the Areopagus at Athens, the Senate at Rome), now the
sovereign power. In practice this council depends primarily on a birth qualification, and
thus has always been more or less inferior to the Aristotelian ideal; it is, by definition, an
"oligarchy" of birth, and is recruited from the noble families, generally by the addition of
emeritus magistrates. From the earliest times, therefore, the word "aristocracy" became
practically synonymous with "oligarchy," and as such it is now generally used in
opposition to democracy (which similarly took the place of Aristotle's 7roXCTELa), in
which the ultimate sovereignty resides in the whole citizen body.

The aristocracy of which we know most in ancient Greece was that of Athens prior to the
reforms of Cleisthenes, but all the Greek city-states passed through a period of
aristocratic or oligarchic government. Rome, between the regal and the imperial periods,
was always more or less under the aristocratic government of the senate, in spite of the
gradual growth of democratic institutions (the Lat. optimates is the equivalent of
hpcarot). There is, however, one feature which distinguishes these aristocracies from
those of modern states, namely, that they were all slave-owning. The original relation of
the slavepopulation, which in many cases outnumbered the free citizens, cannot always
be discovered. But in some cases we know that the slaves were the original inhabitants
who had been overcome by an influx of racially different invaders (cf. Sparta with its
Helots); in others they were captives taken in war. Hence even the most democratic states
of antiquity were so far aristocratic that the larger proportion of the inhabitants had no
voice in the government. In the second place this relation gave rise to a philosophic
doctrine, held even by Aristotle, that there were peoples who were inferior by nature and
adapted to submission (Oka SOUXo); such people had no "virtue" in the technical civic
sense, and were properly occupied in performing the menial functions of society, under
the control of the tipto-roc. Thus, combined with the criteria of descent, civic status and
the ownership of the land, there was the further idea of intellectual and social superiority.
These qualifications were naturally, in course of time, shared by an increasingly large
number of the lower class who broke down the barriers of wealth and education. From
this stage the transition is easy to the aristocracy of wealth, such as we find at Carthage
and later at Venice, in periods when the importance of commerce was paramount and
mercantile pursuits had cast off the stigma of inferiority (in Gr. favavvia). It is important
at this stage to distinguish between aristocracy and the feudal governments of medieval
Europe. In these it is true that certain power was exercised by a small number of families,
at the expense of the majority. But under this system each noble governed in a particular
area and within strict limitations imposed by his sovereign; no sovereign authority was
vested in the nobles collectively.

Under the conditions of the present day the distinction of aristocracy, democracy and
monarchy cannot be rigidly maintained from a purely governmental point of view. In no
case does the sovereign power in a state reside any longer in an aristocracy, and the word
has acquired a social rather than a political sense as practically equivalent to "nobility,"
though the distinction is sometimes drawn between the "aristocracy of birth" and the
"aristocracy of wealth." Modern history, however, furnishes many examples of
government in the hands of an aristocracy. Such were the aristocratic republics of Venice,
Genoa and the Dutch Netherlands, and those of the free imperial cities in Germany, Such,
too, in practice though not in theory, was the government of Great Britain from the
Revolution of 1689 to the Reform Bill of 1832. The French nobles of the Ancien Regime,
denounced as "aristocrats" by the Revolutionists, had no share as such in government, but
enjoyed exceptional privileges (e.g. exemption from taxation). This privileged position is
still enjoyed by the heads of the German mediatized families of the "High Nobility." In
Great Britain, on the other hand, though the aristocratic principle is still represented in the
constitution by the House of Lords, the "aristocracy" generally, apart from the peers, has
no special privileges.

You might also like