Adorno and The Name of God

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9

ADORNO and the NAME of GOD

by David Kaufmann

Thus God, the Absolute, eludes finite beings. Where they desire to name him, because
they must, they betray him. But if they keep silent about him, they acquiesce in their
own impotence and sin against the other, no less binding, commandment to name him. 1

The critique of metaphysics is by now a venerable tradition in Western thought and


has been tied since the end of the eighteenth century to the principle of emancipation.
The drive to disenchant the world -- the ongoing tendency to wrest rational control
from what previously could only be seen as blind fate -- has always been closely
associated with the Enlightenments concerted attack on the institutional privileges and
intellectual status accorded to revealed religion. The story is well known. Kant saved
faith from Hume and philosophy from dogmatism by curtailing the speculative
pretensions of the one and the reach of the other. At the same time, he submitted
religion to the court of reason and thus left space for autonomy. The Left Hegelians
(particularly Feuerbach and Marx) took the humanization of the world a step further by
reducing metaphysics to anthropology and religion to need. The history of religion
became the history of mans alienated but authentic hope, a hope that needed to be
reclaimed in the name of freedom. Nietzsche -- the apostate son of a Lutheran pastor --
launched his own, anti-Hegelian critique of metaphysics. He sought to psychologize the
urge for atemporal, necessary, and universal Truth and thus to cure the nostalgia for a
sovereign God and a sovereign Subject by revealing them both to be fictions of
grammar and bad faith. And to this day, we find the emancipatory interest in
overcoming metaphysics pursued literally by Left Hegelians and rhetorically by
Nietzscheans -- by Marxists and Heideggerians, by Leftists and Deconstructionists.

If there is any accuracy in this short and somewhat simplistic potted history of anti-
metaphysical thought, then it is worth asking how and why it is that Theodor Adorno --
aberrant Marxist, Left Hegelian par excellence, close reader and follower of Nietzsche
-- should insist on using blatantly religious tropes throughout his career. Now, it goes
without saying that metaphysics -- the study of extra-sensory reality -- is not always the
same as religion. But, from his first book on Kierkegaard to his final completed work,
the Negative Dialectics, in which he launches a critical recovery of metaphysics itself,
Adorno returns again and again to themes derived from metaphysics and theology.
Assuming that Robert Hullot-Kentor is correct when he claims that "theology is always
moving right under the surface of all Adornos writings" and that "theology penetrates
every word" of them,2 I would like to look at the use to which Adorno puts a
particularly Jewish notion of the name of God. I will argue that Adorno uses the Name
as a model for a philosophy that understands the historical conditions that constrain it
and the human needs that render it necessary.

Let us begin at the end, with a quotation from the last section of Negative Dialectics.
Adorno is discussing that peculiar dialectic of enlightenment that turns on itself with
the result that "whoever believes in God cannot believe in God" and that "[t]he
possibility represented by the divine Name is maintained by whoever does not believe."
Adorno explains:

Once the prohibition on graven images extended to speaking the Name;


now in this form it has itself come to look suspiciously like
superstition. . .This is how deeply absorbed the history of metaphysical
truth has become, that vainly denies history, that is, progressive
demythologization. This however feeds on itself just as the mythical gods
liked to devour their children. As it leaves nothing but the merely existent
behind, it flashes back into myth. For myth is nothing other than the closed
relation of immanence, of what is. 3

For Adorno, following Weber, the second commandment was the first move towards
religious rationalization, a bold attempt to free man from myth:

In the Jewish religion, in which the idea of the patriarchate rises to the
annihilation of myth, the bond between Name and being is still recognized
in the ban on pronouncing the name of God. The disenchanted world of
Judaism reconciles magic through its negation in the idea of God. The
Jewish religion will not endure a single word that would grant comfort to
the despair of all that is mortal. Hope is only tied to the prohibition against
calling on what is false as God, what is finite as the Infinite, lie as Truth. 4

If myth is the belief in the unavoidability of immanence, in the sheer ineluctable


necessity of the world as it is, then Judaism frees itself from myth by making the divine
Name transcendent -- not as part of a magic incantation that calls godly powers down to
earth but as an indication that the world could in fact be different. It is not that God
does not have a name, that therefore the transcendent is not possible. That would be
myth, the fall into immanence that monotheistic Judaism sought to escape. The
prohibition on speaking the Name maintains the integrity of the transcendent while
preventing any shortcuts towards attaining it.

But the quotation from Negative Dialectics indicates that the course of
disenchantment has not come to a rest with the Judaic victory over myth in the doctrine
of the divine Name. The negation of mere magic has in turn been demystified, has been
revealed in history to be a false positivity, a myth. The prohibition on magic, on the
attempt to harness divine power, leaves one smack in the middle of an unchangeable
world. The protection of Gods transcendence has come to look suspiciously like a
lapse into immanence, so that now only the non-believer can take the positions once
held by belief; only the nonbeliever can cleave to the hope of transcendence that
inheres in the doctrine of the Name. At this point in history -- Adornos present moment
-- faith has fled from theology, which in turn can be maintained solely by the faithless.

The apparent paradoxes that the dialectic of disenchantment brings forth are figured
linguistically by piling up negations, by avoiding the false stability of positivities. But
the hope that still lingers in the Name is not merely the residue of a double negation, of
the refusal of false hope that Horkheimer and Adorno posit in their Dialectic of
Enlightenment. It has positive content as well. This becomes clear in a short essay on
music and language, written ten years after the collaboration with Horkheimer and a
good decade before the Negative Dialectics. In it, Adorno differentiates music from
what he calls intentional language that is, the instrumental language of everyday
communication:

The language of music is quite different from the language of


intentionality. It contains a theological dimension. What it has to say is
simultaneously revealed and concealed. Its Idea is the divine Name which
has been given shape. It is demythologized prayer, rid of efficacious
magic. It is the human attempt, doomed as ever, to name the Name, not to
communicate meanings... Music points to true language in the sense that
content is apparent in it, but it does so at the cost of unambiguous
meaning, which has migrated to the languages of intentionality. 5

True language is thus not the language of meaning, of information, of


communication between people. It is the revelation of the absolute:
Intentional language wants to mediate the absolute, and the absolute
escapes language for every specific intention, leaves each one behind
because each is limited. Music finds the absolute immediately, but at the
moment of discovery it becomes obscured, just as too powerful a light
dazzles the eyes, preventing them from seeing things which are perfectly
visible.6

The most important problem with intentional language is that it wants to mediate the
absolute. It wants to subsume the particular under the universal and render it
conceptual, knowable, and thus, not absolute. The absolute is, by definition, impervious
to mediation -- it stands alone and independent. Intentional language wants to establish
a relation with the absolute, put the absolute in a relation with others. Thus it can only
offer partial, limited though conceptually clear, versions of the absolute. True language
-- like the language of music -- sacrifices the conceptually clear for the immediacy of
that which avoids mediation. Note that Adorno moves from sound to sight. Language
and music are like a blinding light that unveils a presence in its inexhaustible totality in
a flash. Unlike music and language, it is not articulated over time. It is sudden and
beyond dispute.

This dream of a language beyond intention derives directly from Walter Benjamin.
Here is Benjamin in the famously difficult introduction to his book on German tragic
drama (Trauerspiel):

Truth is the death of intention. . . The structure of truth, then demands a


mode of being which in its lack of intentionality resembles the simple
existence of things, but which is superior in its permanence. 7

Benjamin contrasts Truth with the Idealist account of knowledge (Erkenntnis).


Whereas Knowledge seeks possession of an object through representation, Truth is the
self-representation of the object, its self-revelation. 8 Truth, as the simple existence of
things, is Edenic and tied to the Adamic practice of naming:

...paradise [is] a state in which there is as yet no need to struggle with the
communicative significance of words. Ideas are displayed without
intention in the act of naming...all essences exist in complete and
immaculate independence, not only from phenomena, but, especially, from
each other.9

Paradise is a paradise of simple existence, where names offer the world up for show.
They do not mediate the essences of things, they display them. They leave everything
free and absolute.

Now, Benjamin, returns to Genesis. He talks about the names that Adam gives, not
the name of God. We have discussed the value Adorno places on the ban on speaking
Gods name. I would like to suggest that he sees an advantage in recuperating the
notion of the Name itself. In order to see what he is getting at, I would suggest that we
look briefly at the elective affinities between Adorno and Franz Rosenzweig, the
German-Jewish philosopher, whose Star of Redemption Benjamin praised, read, and
quoted, although it is not quite clear how well he understood the book he was able to
plunder so well.

Rosenzweig provides the following brief discussion of proper names:

That which has a name of its own can no longer be a thing, no longer
everymans affair. It is incapable of utter absorption into the category for
there can be no category for it to belong to; it is its own category. 10

A proper name signals an absolute particularity that cannot be subsumed in a


category or by a universal. It is not one of many, it is one of a kind and must be
addressed intersubjectively, that is, it must be treated as having dignity. My use of
Kantian language here is deliberate. That which has a proper name refuses
objectification, refuses reduction to instrumental calculations, is a cipher of the
Kingdom of Ends.

The ultimate proper name is the name of God:

The paradox of Gods being simultaneously near and remote is essentially


expressed in the fact that he has a name. Whatever has a name can be
talked about, can be talked to, according to whether it is absent or present.
God is never absent. Hence there is no theoretical concept of God. . .God
alone has a name that is also a concept; his concept is also his name. 11

This little commentary, written a few years after The Star of Redemption, marks a
noticeable shift in Rosenzweigs thinking. A proper name does not necessarily entail
that a thing should be granted dignity and thus has to be viewed as unique and free.
After all, the false gods of Palestine, such as Baal, have names. So their names do not
confer privilege, especially as one can speak them. To be fair, Rosenzweig, who is
interested in intersubjective communication, does not mention the prohibition against
speaking the Name. For him, it is central that God has a name, that God can be
addressed. Because there is no place that God is not, one cannot help addressing him:
he cannot be thematized, categorized, or subsumed under the universal, because he is
the universal. Gods name is both a particular and a category: it is his own, infinite
concept, if one can imagine such a thing. If, for Benjamin, the revelation of simple
existence through names occurred mythically in Eden, it is for Rosenzweig a mundane,
daily occurrence, and takes place in the constant renewal of the relationship between
God and man. In short, God always has his Name.

There is an obvious disparity between Adorno and Rosenzweig here. Rosenzweig


begins with the assumption that God is absolute. He wants to show, through a constant
dialectic of nearness and remoteness, that transcendence does not preclude an
intersubjective relation to God. Adorno, on the other hand, wants to apply theological
insights to a world and language that seem too immanent, too mythical. He redeploys
the theological to make an ontological point, because a true ontology is impossible in
our day.

This impossibility is historical, although it is worth remembering that in the


Dialectic of Enlightenment, Horkheimer and Adorno do claim that it is endemic to
reason itself and thus is primordial. I would like to bracket this argument by claiming
that it was formulated with the distinct polemical purpose of that book in mind -- to
outflank scientific positivism on one side and proto-Fascist irrationalism on the other;
to save modern rationality from itself and from its enemies.

The impossibility of a true contemporary ontology can be seen in the failure of the
false ones, particularly Heideggers. In the Negative Dialectics, Adorno argues that
there is indeed a moment of truth in Heideggers "fundamental ontology," although this
truth lies in the fact that it is a response to a genuine need, not in the content of that
response itself. Adorno assumes that autonomy and its concomitant -- the recognition of
difference -- have become a basic human need. A version of this need can be expressed
philosophically as "the longing that Kants verdict on a knowledge of the Absolute
should not be the end of the matter."12 An absolute is, by definition, autonomous.
Autonomy as a need is determined by social history, by the administrative
rationalization of life under capitalism. Adorno follows Marx and Lukacs in seeing that
the essence of capitalism lies in the abstractness of the exchange relationship, where all
use value is overshadowed by exchange value, all particularities are rendered equal by
the universal medium of money, and all qualities are reduced to mere quantity. This
abstractness is born of the lie that exchange value follows natural or quasi-natural laws,
not man-made directives.13 In a world geared to profit and mediated by money,
efficiency is the order of the day and smooth, well-tooled organization becomes the
distorted image of the public good. Heideggerian ontology rebels, however impotently,
against these modern conditions of heteronomy. Adorno writes:

Society has grown into the total functional context that liberalism thought
it was: what is is relative to what is other and is irrelevant to itself. The
fear of this, the dawning awareness that the subject is forfeiting its
substantiality, prepares the subject to harken to the solemn declaration that
Being, which is implicitly equated with that substantiality, survives,
incapable of being lost, the total functional context. 14

Heideggers ontology, which to Adorno seems like nothing more than a rumbling
mythology of Being, is thus an index of a real historical predicament, a reaction to a
concrete socio-historical complex. But it is a wrong reaction, because while it maintains
the truth of philosophical Idealism by rejecting the irrevocable divisions between inside
and out, fact and concept, essence and appearance, history and eternity, it projects their
reconciliation not into the future but into an unrecoverable past. It therefore leaves the
subject in the trammels of an immanence that cannot be transcended and leaves the
subject worshipping a totality -- Being -- that is just another figure in the
phantasmagoria that masks the heteronomy of modern capitalist life. 15

A true ontology, one that met its human need, would be able to return substance to
the subject and the object. It could illuminate the particular without invoking the
exchange principle of conceptual thought by submitting that particular to the de-
differentiation of the universal. The particular exceeds the universal in that it is unique,
has an element that cannot be subsumed so readily. But the concept also exceeds the
individual:

The individual is both more and less than its general definition. But
because it is only through the transumption (Aufhebung) of this
contradiction, and so through the achieved identity between the particular
and its concept, that the particular, the definite would come to itself, the
interest of the individual is not only in keeping what the general concept
steals from him, but also with the excess in the concept when it is
compared to his need.16

The universal has a surplus that the individual needs. This surplus is a promise that
is not yet fulfilled, even at the same time that the particular cannot be contained within
the constraints of the concept. In short, concept and individual are a bad fit, but there is
a utopian promise in this failure. In Adornos version of reconciliation, as in
Rosenzweigs understanding of the Name, there is a vanishing point where the
universal would be adequate to the particular and the particular would be adequate to
the universal.

Adorno is quite explicit in tying the language of philosophy as it moves


asymptotically towards the ideal of a true ontology to the doctrine of the Name:

The determinable flaw of all concepts makes it necessary to cite others


next to it: from this flow those constellations to which solely something of
the hope of the Name has passed. The language of philosophy approaches
that Name by denying it. What the language of philosophy criticizes, its
pretense to immediate truth, is almost always the ideology of a positive,
existing identity between word and thing.17

The individual concept is never adequate. Only constellations of concepts can begin
to account for the particular. Philosophy moves towards the Name -- that future
reconciliation between universal and particular -- by denying that the reconciliation has
yet taken place, by giving the lie to the ideological claim that word and thing, universal
and particular, coincide. Thus, philosophy parallels Judaism in refusing to speak the
Name.

If we see the prohibition as a question of mere refusal, we could argue that the
analogy between philosophy and Judaism, though riven with pathos, is inaccurate. Jews
do not speak the Name because they do not want to profane it; philosophy does not
speak the name because it is not yet adequate, because it is not yet the Name. This
objection makes sense if one sees the prohibition on pronouncing the Name as applying
only to the Tetragrammaton. But this is not the only name God has, a point that
Scholem (who Adorno claimed was his chief source of Judaic knowledge) 18 made clear
on a number of occasions. Scholem made much of the Kabbalistic notion that the Torah
itself not only consisted of names of God, but was itself the ineffable and
unpronounceable name of God, that opened up interpretation but could never be
comprehended by it.19 Thus not only is one not supposed to pronounce the Name, one
cannot. One can only approximate it. David Biale has shown that this notion of the
Name and of revelation goes back to Hermann Cohen whose neo-Kantian epistemology
seems to have an echo in Adornos account of asymptotic knowledge as well. 20

I have therefore argued that Adorno mobilizes a particularly theological and


particularly German-Jewish doctrine of the divine Name to describe the task of a
philosophy, based on human need, that urges towards and cannot achieve a true
ontology. The impossibility of achieving that ontology is historically derived and does
not come from a positive prohibition. But, for Adorno, truly self-reflective thought will
have to make the prohibition conscious, will have to thematize it, if it is not to fall for
the ideological blandishments of a false ontology based on immediacy. It will not be
able to retreat from ontology completely and rest with epistemology, if epistemology
means resorting to a strict dichotomy between subject and object that either deifies or
eliminates mediation.

In the present dispensation where quantitative, universalizing reason rules, the small
moves towards true ontology that philosophy can make will look like aesthetics and
will be allied to metaphysics, that is, the knowledge of the absolute. The micrological
appreciation of the nuance, of the place where the particular differs from the universal,
where its absoluteness appears, if only as a cipher, requires what Kant called the faculty
of reflective judgment.21 This faculty reasons from the individual to the universal. In
the process, it plays a game of "as if," because it sees the particular as if it were
contained under a determinate universal while knowing that this is a necessary fiction if
the particular is to be intelligible at all. For the individual (work of art) cannot be
subsumed under a law because it gives itself its own law. Because it has a form, it looks
like it should be intelligible. But that form, a cipher of freedom, seems to escape
intelligibility in the end. And so, Adorno (whose definition of metaphysics here owes
everything to reflective judgment):

Metaphysics is, according to its own concept, not possible as a deductive


context of judgments about beings. Nor can it be thought of on the model
of an absolute Otherness, which in fear despises thought... The smallest
intramundane traits would be relevant to the Absolute, for the micrological
view shatters the shells of what, measured by the subsuming cover
concept, seems to be helplessly isolated, and explodes its identity, the
delusion that it is only a specimen (emphasis added). 22

To think the absolute, to approach the absolute, cannot entail deduction, for to
reason from the particular is by definition inductive. Nor can thought of the absolute
flee from reason to some immediate apperception. Rather, it must learn to discriminate
the "smallest intramundane traits," those tiny marks of irrevocable difference that show
that it cannot be subsumed completely by the cover concept, that it is not completely
subject to an alien law.

For Adorno, modern thought, if it is to have critical, emancipatory intent, will have
to ally itself to metaphysics and draw the tropes of theology into its orbit, not as mere
ornament, but not yet fulfilled promises of reason. Adornos nicely Hegelian dictum
that "[w]hat has been cast aside but not absorbed theoretically will often yield its truth
content only later,"23 gets its demonstration in his recuperation of the Name. I have
indicated that according to this logic, critical philosophy must now draw on aesthetics
because this is the closest it can come to the unredeemed truth of ontological need. In
an essay on Brecht and Sartre, Adorno remarked that "[t]his is not the time for political
works of art; rather, politics has migrated into the autonomous work of art." 24 In an
administered world given over to profit and exchange, art and aesthetic perception will
be the only places that the solid ground of resistance that used to be mapped by
ontology and politics can be approached. To put it more simply: if politics has fled to
art, it is because ontology has fled -- beaten, beleaguered, and distorted -- to aesthetics.

Adornos crack that in psychoanalysis nothing is true except the exaggerations (as
well as betraying a keen understanding of the way meaning is derived in the analytic
process) is a deadly accurate self-description. 25 Adorno is often his most insightful
when he is most extreme. And so it is that for the brief space that remains in this essay,
I want to return to Adornos bizarre insistence on a theology without belief, on
metaphysics at the time of its disappearance. While his historical paradoxes -- that only
when theology has been banished from critical philosophy can its undigested truths
shine out -- interest me and Adornos sometimes complicated theory of the truth needs
further elaboration, it is his return to theology and metaphysics when these have been
so well established as the conservative enemies of liberation that I want to end with.

Adornos attempt to redeem the undigested and therefore emancipatory semantic


potential of Jewish theology and speculative metaphysics serves as an interesting
warning against a superstitious fear of an unmastered intellectual past and a fetishizing
confidence in the supersession of old ideas. "Metaphysics" tout court is no more the
enemy of liberation than a blind faith in historical progress is its guarantee. To banish
"metaphysics" in the name of progress might be to regress to a mythological worship of
what has merely come to exist. To put it in Adornos own words: "Progress is not a
conclusive category. It wants to disrupt the triumph of radical evil, not to triumph in
itself."26

The secret could well be that metaphysics lurking in its old haunts might pose a
danger to autonomy but that any all-encompassing prohibition on metaphysics is
always on the verge of becoming myth. The name of God is a potent idea, not if it is
just secularized to a pretty little metaphor, but if it is redeployed to a place, where,
according to its critique, it legitimately belongs. Adorno shows that the name of God is
a model for and an index of an ontology, of a metaphysical experience of the absolute,
in an era of equivalence and ineluctable mediation. There is, of course, much to be
debated in the exaggerations of Adornos thought: his now-outdated reliance on
theories of monopoly capital; his often monochromatic account of the course of
rationalization; and his language theory. Nevertheless, I remain impressed with his
guts, with his adamant refusal to give up one iota of experience to the rigorism of a
post-Kantian philosophy. While I understand Habermass scruples about the limits of
philosophy, I cannot help remembering that Habermas addresses the practice of
philosophy as a discipline, not the practice of thought itself. This being the case,
Adorno indicates that our thinking might well want to avail itself of the truths of
theology and metaphysics as long as we can see just how false they are, that is, just
how they are false.27

Footnotes
(1) Theodor W. Adorno, "Sacred Fragment: Schoenbergs Moses und Aron," Quasi
Una Fantasia, trans. Rodney Livingstone (London: Verso, 1992), p. 226.

(2) Theodor W. Adorno, Kierkegaard: Construction of the Aesthetic, trans. Robert


Hullot-Kentor (Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press, 1989), p. xi.

(3) Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, trans. E.B. Ashton (NY: Continuum,
1973) 401-2. This is a notoriously bad translation of a notoriously difficult book, and
throughout this paper I have altered Ashtons version to conform more closely with the
German original.

(4) Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. John
Cumming (NY: Continuum, 1986), p. 23. Again, I have modified this translation.

(5) Quasi Una Fantasia, pp. 2-3.

(6) Quasi Una Fantasia, p. 4.

(7) Walter Benjamin, The Origin of German Tragic Drama, trans. John Osborne
(London: New Left Books, 1977), p. 36; see also his famous letter to Martin Buber in
Gershom Scholem and Theodor W. Adorno eds., The Letters of Walter Benjamin, trans.
Manfred R. Jacobson and Evelyn M. Jacobson (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press,
1994), pp. 79-81.

(8) Benjamin, pp. 29-30.

(9) Benjamin, p. 37.

(10) Franz Rosenzweig, The Star of Redemption, trans. William W. Hallo (London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1970), pp. 188-9.

(11) Nahum Glatzer, ed., Franz Rosenzweig (NY: Schocken, 1960), p. 281.

(12) Negative Dialectics, p. 61.

(13) Here is Marx: "The various proportions in which different kinds of labor are
reduced to simple labor as their unit of measurement are established by a social process
that goes on behind the backs of the producers; these proportions therefore appear to
the producers to have been handed down by tradition." (Karl Marx, Capital, trans. Ben
Fowkes (London: New Left Books, 1976), 3 vols., I:135).
It is important to supplement this quotation with another from Adorno: "When we
criticize the exchange principle as the identifying principle of thought, we want to
realize the ideal of free and just exchange. To date, this ideal is only a pretext. Its
realization alone would transcend exchange. Once critical theory has shown it up for
what it is, an exchange of things that are equal and yet unequal, our critique of the
inequality within equality aims at equality too..." (Negative Dialectics, p. 147).

(14) Negative Dialectics, p. 65.

(15) Negative Dialectics, pp. 91-3.

(16) Negative Dialectics, p. 151.

(17) Negative Dialectics, p. 53.

(18) Theodor W. Adorno, "Gruss an Gershom G. Scholem," Gesammelte Schriften,


ed., Rolf Tiedemann, (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1986), 20 vols., XX:I 482-3.

(19) See (in order of their original composition), "Revelation and Tradition as
Religious Categories," The Messianic Idea in Judaism (NY: Schocken, 1971), pp. 292-
4; "The Meaning of the Torah in Jewish Mysticism," On the Kabbalah and Its
Symbolism (NY: Schocken, 1965), pp. 39-43; "The Name of God and the Linguistic
Theory of the Kabbalah," Diogenes 79-80 (1972-3), pp. 77-80, 173-4, 180-3, 194.

(20) David Biale, Gershom Scholem: Kabbalah and Counter-History (Cambridge:


Harvard Univ. Press, 1979), pp. 79-80, 96-7, 110-11.

(21) Cf. Negative Dialectics, pp. 44-5.

(22) Negative Dialectics, pp. 407-8.

(23) Negative Dialectics, p. 144.

(24) Theodor W. Adorno, "Commitment," Notes to Literature, trans. Shierry Weber


Nicholsen (NY: Columbia Univ. Press, 1991-2), 2 vols., II: pp. 92-3.

(25) Theodor W. Adorno, Minima Moralia, trans. E.F.N. Jephcott (London: New
Left Books, 1974), p. 49.

(26) Theodor W. Adorno, "Progress," Benjamin: Philosophy, Aesthetics, History, ed.


Gray Smith (Chicago: Chicago Univ. Press, 1989), p. 101.

(27) My thanks are due to Sharon Squassoni and Nancy Weiss Hanrahan, who read
closely and suggested well. A final note of pathos as well: my father died on October 6,
1994, a year before I wrote this. Being the quintessential German Jew that he was, he
was cremated, and his ashes scattered on the hillside behind his house. He therefore has
no headstone to honor his memory. This paper, such as it is, is for him: Thomas David
Kaufmann, 1922-1994, Proverbs I:6.

David Kaufmann's "Husbandry" appears in FlashPint #10.

You might also like