States of Consciousness: Charles T. Tart

You might also like

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 4

States of Consciousness

Charles T. Tart
9. Individual Differences

Inadequate recognition of individual differences is a methodological deficiency that has seriously


slowed psychological research. Lip service is paid to individual differences, but in reality they
are largely ignored. Psychologists, caught up in the all-too-human struggle for prestige, ape the
methods of the physical sciences, in which individual differences are not of great significance
and the search is for general fundamental laws. I believe this failure to recognize individual
differences is the rock on which psychology's early attempts to establish itself as an introspective
discipline foundered. Following the lead of the tremendously successful physical scientists, the
early psychologists searched for general laws of the mind, and when their data turned out to be
contradictory, they quarreled with each other over who was right, not realizing they were all
right, and so wasted their energies. They tried to abstract too much too soon before coming to
terms with the experiential subject matter.
Figure 9-1. Problems arising when individual differences are ignored. Charts A, B, and C are experiential mappings
of the sort done in Figure 5-1. The other two charts are summary charts, as explained in the text.

We psychologists all too often do the same thing today, albeit in a more sophisticated form.
Consider, for example, the procedure described in Chapter 5 for mapping a person's location in
experiential space. Suppose that in the course of an experiment we measure two variables, X and
Y, in a group of subjects. To concretize the example, we can define X as the degree of analgesia
(insensitivity to pain) the subject can show and Y as the intensity of the subject's imagery.
Tempted by the convenience and "scientificness" of a nearby computer, we feed our group data
in a prepackaged analysis program and get the printout in the lower chart of Figure 9-1—a
straight line fitted to the data and indicating a highly significant (thus publishable) correlation
coefficient between variables X and Y. It looks as if ability to experience analgesia is linearly
related to intensity of imagery, that in this region of experiential space there is a straight-road
connection: if you do whatever is needed to enhance imagery, you automatically increase
analgesia.
If we distrust such great abstraction of the data, we can ask the computer to print out a scatter
plot of the raw data, the actual position of each subject instead of the abstraction for all subjects.
This new printout (lower left-hand chart of Figure 9-1) apparently reassures us that the fitted
curve and correlation coefficient are adequate ways of presenting and understanding our results.
The straight road is somewhat broad, but still basically straight. More imagery goes with more
analgesia.
We have extracted a principle (more imagery leads to more analgesia) from group data that is
based on one pair of observations from each subject. Suppose, however, that we actually go back
to our subjects and test some of them repeatedly, obtain samples over time, an experiential
mapping, of their simultaneous abilities to experience analgesia and imagery. Then we find that
our subjects actually fall into three distinct types, as shown in the upper charts of Figure 9-1.
Type A shows either a low degree of both analgesia and imagery or a fair degree of analgesia
and imagery, but no other combinations. Type B shows a low to fair degree of analgesia and
imagery or a very high degree of analgesia and imagery, but no other combinations. Type C
shows a high variability of degree of analgesia and imagery, a much wider range of
combinations.
For subjects of type C, the conclusion, drawn from the group data, of a linear relationship
between intensity of imagery and intensity of analgesia, is valid. But how many type C subjects
are included in our group? Subjects of types A and B, on the other hand, do not show a linear
relationship between analgesia and imagery. There is no straight road, only some islands of
experience. For type A subjects, analgesia and imagery cluster together at low levels or at
moderate levels of functioning, but show no clear linear relationship within either cluster. For
type B subjects, analgesia and imagery cluster at low to moderate or at very high levels, and
again show no clear linear relationship within either clustering. Indeed, subjects of types A and B
show the clustering used in Chapter 5 to define the concept of multiple d-SoCs, while subjects of
type C seem to function in only a single d-SoC.
Thus the conclusion drawn from the grouped data about relations between analgesia and imagery
in this region of experiential space turns out to apply only to some people and to misrepresent
what others experience. Indeed, the error may be more profound: people may be only of the A
and B types, but combining their results as subjects when some are in one part of experiential
space and some in another gives us a set of numbers that spans the whole range. This leads us to
the straight-road or linear relationship concept, even though that concept actually represents no
one's experience.
It is hard to realize the full impact of individual differences because of the deep implicitness of
the assumption that we all share a common d-SoC. Since we are members of a common culture,
this is generally true, but the more I come to know other individuals and get a feeling for the way
their minds work, the more I am convinced that this general truth, the label ordinary d-SoC,
conceals enormous individual differences. If I clearly understood the way your mind works in its
ordinary d-SoC, and if you understood the same about me, we would both be amazed. Yet
because we speak a common language, which stresses external rather than internal events, we are
seldom aware of these differences.
Psychologically, each of us assumes that his own mind is an example of a "normal" mind and
then projects his own experiences onto other people, unaware of how much projecting he is
doing. For example, most of us have imagery in our ordinary d-SoC that is unstable and not very
vivid, so that trying to visualize something really steadily and intensely is impossible. Some
people report that in d-ASCs their imagery is much more intense and controllable, steady. Yet
the inventor Nikolai Tesla had such intense, controllable imagery in his ordinary d-SoC. When
Tesla designed a machine, he did it in his head, without using physical drawings: nevertheless,
he could instruct a dozen difference machinists how to make each separate part, to the nearest
ten-thousandth of an inch, and the completed machine would fit together perfectly. Tesla is also
reported to have tested wear on his machines through imagery. He designed the machine by
visualization, put the imaged parts together into a complete machine, started it running in his
mind, forgot about it, resurrected the image thousands of hours later, mentally dismantled the
machine, and inspected the parts for wear to see what needed reinforcement of redesign {43}.
Regardless of how one evaluate the accuracy of such imagery, Tesla's procedure is a good
example of what for most of us is exotic imagery associated with d-ASCs, but what was for him
the imagery of his "ordinary" d-SoC.
On those occasions when we do recognize great differences in the mental functioning of others,
we are tempted to label the differences weird or abnormal of pathological. Such blanket labels
are not useful. What are the specific advantages and disadvantages under what circumstances for
each individual difference of pattern?
This tendency to project implicitly the workings of one's own mind pattern as a standard for the
working of all minds can have interesting scientific results. For example, controversy rages in the
literature on hypnosis over whether the concept of a d-SoC is necessary to explain hypnosis, or
whether the hypnotic "state" is in fact continuous with the ordinary "state," is simply a case of
certain psychological functions, such as suggestibility and role-playing involvement, being
pushed to higher levels of activity than they are under ordinary conditions. A chief proponent of
this latter view, Theodore X. Barber {4}, can produce most of the classical hypnotic phenomena
in himself without doing anything special.[1] The phenomena included in his ordinary d-SoC
encompass a range that, for another person, must be attained by unusual means. How much does
this affect his theorizing? How much does anyone's individual psychology affect his thinking
about how other minds work? Again consider Figure 9-1. Whereas A and B type people may
have two d-SoCs, one that we call their ordinary d-SoC and a second called their hypnotic state,
the ordinary range of consciousness of type C people includes both these regions. Thus it may be
more accurate to say that what as been called hypnosis, to stick with this example, is indeed
merely an extension of the ordinary range of functioning for some people, but for other people it
is d-ASC.
I cannot emphasize too strongly that the mapping of experience and the use of the concept of d-
SoCs must first be done on an individual basis. Only then, if regions of great similarity are found
to exist across individuals, can common names that apply across individuals be legitimately
coined.
This idealistic statement does not reflect the way our concepts actually evolved. The very
existence of names like dreaming state or hypnotic state indicates that there appears to a fair
degree of commonality among a fair number of individuals. Though I often speak as if this
commonality were true, its veracity cannot be precisely evaluated at the present stage of our
knowledge, and the concept is clearly misleading at times. Several d-ASCs may be hidden within
common names like hypnosis or dreaming.
In addition to the large individual differences that may exist among people we think are all in the
same d-SoC, there are sit from one d-SoC to another. In discussing stabilization processes, I
mentioned that some people seem overstabilized and others understabilized. The former may be
able to experience only a few d-SoCs, while the latter may transit often and effortlessly into d-
ASCs. Understabilized people may undergo breakdown of the ordinary d-SoC and be unable to
form a new d-ASC, unable to organize consciousness into a stable coping form. Some types of
schizophrenia may represent this understabilized mode of consciousness.
Besides the sheer number of simultaneous and reinforcing stabilization processes, the degree of
voluntary control over them is important. To the extent that your stabilization processes are too
powerful or too implicit to be altered at will, you are stuck in one mode of consciousness. These
dimensions of stabilization, control, and ability to transit from one d-SoC to another are
important ones that must be the focus of future research, as we know almost nothing about them
now.
Footnote
[1] As discussed in Chapter 12, some individuals may transit so rapidly and easily between d-
SoCs that they do not notice the transitions and so mistakenly believe they experience only one
d-SoC. This case is ordinarily difficult to distinguish from that of actual continuity through a
wide region of experiential space. (back)

You might also like