Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 24

PART I

Methods and Fields of


Comparative Politics

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 11 11/29/2008 11:05:54 AM


9781412919760_Chap01.indd 12 11/29/2008 11:05:55 AM
1
The Distinctiveness of
Comparative Research
Charles C. Ragin and Claude Rubinson

INTRODUCTION engage in the development, testing, and


revision of theory – traditionally the province
Social research is inherently comparative of case-oriented research, as well as hypoth-
(Lieberson, 1985). Researchers compare the esis testing and theory adjudication – usually
relative effects of variables across cases; they seen as the province of variable-
compare cases directly with one another; oriented research. But the greatest strengths
and they compare empirical cases with of comparative methodology arise from its
counterfactual cases. But the comparative distinctiveness. Fundamentally set theoretic
method – sometimes referred to as ‘small- in nature, comparative methods presuppose
N comparison’ – constitutes a distinctive particular epistemological and theoretical
approach to understanding social phenom- perspectives (Ragin, 1987; 2000; Rubinson
ena. Frequently, comparative methods are and Ragin, 2007). Although social research-
portrayed as a ‘bridge’ between qualitative, ers conventionally conceive of social reality
case-oriented research and quantitative, in terms of tendencies and probabilities,
variable-oriented research. This interpreta- social scientific theory – like comparative
tion is certainly valid. By embracing aspects research – is predominately set theoretic in
of both qualitative and quantitative methods, nature. Frequently, however, even compara-
comparative methods can circumvent some tive researchers do not recognize the set theo-
of the limitations of both approaches. But retic character of their work.
comparative research is not merely a bridge, In the second part of this chapter, we expli-
for it has many distinctive features and cate the set theoretic nature of a number of
strengths. classic comparative studies. We identify and
We begin this chapter by reviewing the illustrate three types of set theoretic relation-
conventional view of comparative methods ships and discuss how they form the basis of
as simultaneously qualitative and quantita- three forms of comparative analysis: descrip-
tive. The moderate number of cases employed tive, constitutive, and causal. Next, we discuss
by comparative researchers allows them to the case-oriented nature of social research.

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 13 11/29/2008 11:05:55 AM


14 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE POLITICS

The set theoretic orientation of comparative and enhance statistical power (Cohen, 1988).
research invokes a case-oriented perspective: Faced with hundreds or thousands of cases,
sets are composed of elements (cases) and however, it is impossible for researchers to
comparative research is the analysis of how know the details of each case. As the cases
cases in one set relate to cases in another set. become obscured and retreat to the background,
We then discuss the issue of causal complex- variables advance to the fore. Large-N analysis,
ity. Comparative methods are especially well- then, tends to focus on variables and their
suited for the study of how combinations of relationships.
causal conditions produce particular out- The fundamental goal of variable-oriented
comes. The study of necessary and sufficient research is the production of descriptive or
conditions – a prominent concern among explanatory inferences (Brady, 2004).
comparativists – is but one aspect of compara- Descriptive inferences are produced by gen-
tive causal analysis. eralizing from patterns found within samples
We conclude our discussion of compara- (King et al., 1994). All else being equal, the
tive research by examining its formal larger a sample is the greater the researcher’s
methods. Reviewing two contemporary confidence in generalizing to a wider popu-
applications of comparative methodology, lation. Explanatory inferences are produced
we illustrate the construction and analysis of through hypothesis testing (King et al., 1994).
truth tables. Truth tables form the foundation Hypothesis testing requires a well-specified
of comparative analysis; whether explicitly theory of the relationships among variables,
or implicitly, most comparative researchers which may be confirmed or refuted by com-
construct truth tables. We demonstrate how paring the theory’s predictions against
Mill’s (1875) methods of agreement and dif- evidence. Again, all else being equal, the
ference as well as Ragin’s Qualitative larger the sample, the greater the researcher’s
Comparative Analysis (QCA) – the two dom- confidence that a relationship found in a
inant implementations of formal comparative sample does, in fact, exist in the wider popu-
methods – make use of them. QCA builds lation. As both benefit from a large number
upon and extends Mill’s methods, as we of observations, the affinity between varia-
demonstrate through analyses of causal com- ble-oriented research and quantitative meth-
plexity and counterfactual cases. ods is mutually reinforcing.
Case-oriented research and qualitative
methods, by contrast, are most useful when
applied to a small number of cases. Because
COMPARATIVE METHODS qualitative techniques leverage the research-
AS A BRIDGE er’s in-depth knowledge of cases, every addi-
tional case requires researchers to further
In describing the methodological landscape divide their attention. Examination of details
of the social sciences, it is conventional to highlights the distinctiveness of each case.
distinguish between quantitative, variable- While imposing limits on generalization and
oriented analysis and qualitative, case- thereby hindering hypothesis testing, this
oriented analysis (Ragin, 1987). There is, of focus facilitates theory development (George
course, no inherent reason that variable- and Bennett, 2005). In-depth case knowledge
oriented analysis must be quantitative and makes it easier to see which case aspects are
case-oriented analysis, qualitative (Rubinson relevant to the question at hand and how
and Ragin, 2007). Still, there is a natural these aspects fit together. This understanding
affinity, which is a consequence of the way in may be used to construct new theory or
which the number of cases influences the revise existing theory, thus generating new
research process. Quantitative techniques hypotheses for future testing.
require a large number of cases – the more, This is not to say that case-oriented research-
the better – so as to meet model assumptions ers cannot engage in hypothesis testing;

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 14 11/29/2008 11:05:56 AM


THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF COMPARATIVE RESEARCH 15

indeed, popular examples of case-oriented researchers begin their research armed with a
research include ‘crucial,’ ‘most-likely,’ and well-specified theoretical model and hypoth-
‘least-likely’ case studies that test whether a eses regarding how change in one variable
theory operates as predicted (Eckstein, 1992). affects changes in others. In contrast to these
In general, however, researchers who want to two extremes, comparativists typically begin
develop new theory tend to use qualitative, their research with a rough idea of the con-
case-oriented techniques to examine cepts, variables, and cases that are likely to
small-Ns, while those who want to test be relevant to their research question. Because
theory tend to apply quantitative, variable- comparative researchers typically study a
oriented methods to large-Ns (Ragin, 1994). moderate number of cases, it is not feasible
A consequence of this bifurcation is that to use a purely exploratory approach and
social research is characterized by a large conduct an open-ended, in-depth examina-
number of studies that examine either tion of every case. At the same time, conven-
small-Ns or large-Ns, but relatively few stud- tional hypothesis testing fails due to the
ies that examine a moderate number of cases limited degrees of freedom available. Instead,
(Ragin, 2000: 25). comparative researchers seek to answer their
Comparative research can bridge the divide research questions by examining the fit
between qualitative, case-oriented research between concepts and cases, ideas and evi-
and quantitative, variable-oriented research. dence. The notion of ‘fit’ is key. For com-
Like case-oriented methods, comparative parativists, a good theory is a middle-range
methods maintain the integrity of cases; like theory that fits the evidence well (Mjoset and
variable-oriented methods, comparative Clausen, 2007). Such a theory will identify
methods examine patterns of relationships which variables are relevant to the question
among variables. Comparative methods, at hand, explain how these variables are
then, may be used for both theory develop- related to one another, and, specify the con-
ment and hypothesis testing. With a moder- texts under which they operate.
ate number of cases (usually around 5–50), Through investigation of the fit between
it becomes possible to examine cross-case theory and data, comparativists discover
patterns while still attending to the details of areas for adjustment and improvement.
each case. In comparative research, theory Ultimately, the resulting theory must be
development and hypothesis testing interact judged on its own merits. Does the theory
in two ways. First, comparative methods may provide a compelling explanation of the
be used to develop, test, and revise a particu- observed cases? Does it explain unobserved
lar theory. Second, comparative methods or previously anomalous cases? Does it pro-
may be used to adjudicate between compet- duce observable implications and novel
ing theories. insights? Is it falsifiable? There is always a
trade-off between specificity and generality,
and theories vary in their explanatory scope.
Developing, testing, and Very specific theories may not generalize
revising theory beyond the observed cases; very general ones
may not add anything new to our understand-
Comparative methods encourage a reciprocal ing. Ultimately, whether any particular theory
relationship between theory development and is successful depends upon striking the proper
theory testing. In a strictly qualitative case- balance between specificity and generality
oriented study, researchers enter the field for the research question at hand. The advan-
armed only with sensitizing concepts, which tage of using comparative methods to develop,
they use to help them construct new theory as test, and revise theory is that they make these
they try to make sense of their cases. In a choices, considerations, and decisions
purely quantitative variable-oriented study, explicit.

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 15 11/29/2008 11:05:56 AM


16 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE POLITICS

considered relevant or not – as the ‘possi-


Adjudicating between theories
bility principle.’
A popular use of quantitative methods is to Given an initial set of cases, the researcher
adjudicate between competing theoretical first examines scope conditions in order to
perspectives. Given two or more theories that exclude cases to which the theory does not
purport to explain the same phenomenon, apply. The researcher then applies the possi-
researchers identify the variables specified bility principle in order to restrict the sample
by each theory and estimate a series of to relevant cases. Mahoney and Goertz (2004)
models using the same dataset. By examin- operationalize the possibility principle as a
ing measures of statistical significance, rule of exclusion and a rule of inclusion. The
explained variation, and model fit, research- exclusion rule, which takes priority over the
ers can determine which theory best explains inclusion rule, directs the researcher to
the outcome of interest. develop a list of ‘robust eliminatory varia-
Comparative methods may be applied to bles’ which predict the absence of the out-
this purpose as well. While the process tends come. Cases are excluded as irrelevant ‘if
to differ, the logic is the same. As the goal of their value on any eliminatory independent
hypothesis testing is the generation of explan- variable predicts the nonoccurrence of the
atory inferences (see above), the construction outcome of interest’ (Mahoney and Goertz,
of the set of relevant cases is crucial. Because 2004: 658). The inclusion rule states that
comparativists study fewer cases than quanti- ‘[cases are relevant if their value on at least
tative researchers, they typically devote much one independent variable is positively related
more attention to the task of delineating the to the outcome of interest’ (Mahoney and
set of relevant cases and then constructing Goertz, 2004: 657). We regard this threshold
their datasets. Of particular concern are as a preliminary guideline and recommend
scope and possibility conditions. Scope con- that researchers use their theoretical and sub-
ditions specify the conditions under which a stantive knowledge when specifying inclu-
theory is relevant (Cohen, 1989). Cases that sion thresholds.
do not meet a theory’s scope conditions are The proper application of scope condi-
considered irrelevant, regardless of whether tions and the possibility principle to a popu-
they exhibit the outcome of interest. Skocpol lation will produce a theoretically and
(1979), for example, limits her theory of the substantively relevant sample of both posi-
causes of social revolutions to countries tive and negative cases. If the resulting
without a recent history of colonial domina- sample is too large for comparative analy-
tion and thereby excludes the cases of Mexico sis, then researchers should select repre-
and Vietnam. Possibility conditions specify sentative cases that maximize the diversity
the conditions under which an outcome is of cases on relevant causal conditions. To
possible (Goertz, 2005; Mahoney and Goertz, adjudicate among competing theories, the
2004). For example, there are many (in fact, comparative researcher examines each case
infinite) cases of the non-occurrence of social to see if the relationships between causal
revolutions. When the outcome of interest is conditions and outcomes hold as predicted
clearly impossible, the case is irrelevant for by each theory. Theories are evaluated
the theory at hand. Irrelevant cases should be according to how well they predict both the
excluded from the data set because their presence and absence of the outcome. Like
inclusion does not benefit hypothesis testing conventional quantitative adjudication tech-
and, indeed, may hinder it (Braumoeller and niques, comparative techniques of adjudica-
Goertz, 2002; Clarke, 2002; Mahoney tion can indicate opportunities for theory
and Goertz, 2004). Mahoney and Goertz refinement by exposing the ways in which
(2004) codify the specification of possibility different theories complement one another
conditions – that is, whether cases are and might be combined.

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 16 11/29/2008 11:05:56 AM


THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF COMPARATIVE RESEARCH 17

Example: Berg-Schlosser and de Meur’s were subjected to the same historical events.
(1994) ‘Conditions of Democracy’ That some emerged as democratic and others
Social scientists have a longstanding interest as authoritarian suggests that each country
in the rise and evolution of democracy and possessed the potential for democratic break-
have developed a wide array of theoretical down. Expanding the sample beyond the
explanations for its emergence, persistence, small handful normally examined in com-
and breakdown. Observing that there have parative research provides a test of the gener-
been few attempts to adjudicate among these alizability of the theories: ‘all of the major
theories, Berg-Schlosser and de Meur (1994) “breakdown” cases with their specific pat-
test eight of the most prominent models pre- terns and the major “survivors,” including
dicting the success or failure of democratiza- some of the smaller countries which often
tion: Dahl (1971, 1989), Hermens (1941), tend to be overlooked, are considered’ (Berg-
Linz (1978), Lipset (1981), Luebbert (1987), Schlosser and de Meur, 1994: 254). At the
Moore (1966), Sani and Sartori (1983), and same time, the moderate sample size permits
Vanhanen (1984). Berg-Schlosser and de Berg-Schlosser and de Meur to interrogate
Meur (1994) construct their dataset by draw- the individual cases when seeking to make
ing from the inter-war period in Europe, sense of results. Indeed, to this end, the
emphasizing the similarities among the cases: researchers exclude certain countries from
For a study of the chances and failures of democ- the sample: ‘cases like Denmark and Norway
racy in a comparative perspective, the interwar have not been included because they were
period in Europe provides a unique setting, since found to add relatively little variation over
the cases to be considered share many common and above the conditions and relevant factors
socioeconomic and political-cultural characteris-
for a case like Sweden’ (Berg-Schlosser and
tics. Their history is relatively well researched and
well documented. The time period under consid- de Meur, 1994: 254). In contrast to conven-
eration is clearly demarcated by common events, tional quantitative methods, the inclusion of
the two world wars which significantly altered additional cases in comparative research is of
both the internal and external political landscapes no benefit unless they serve to better repre-
and set them apart from earlier and later develop-
sent the combinations of conditions present
ments. All cases can initially be designated as par-
liamentary democracies, some of them relatively in the population: Berg-Schlosser and de
well established, others more recent, and some Meur’s 1994 sample is representative not of
existing more in form than in substance. They Western European countries during the inter-
were subsequently affected by a common external war period per se but, rather, of the types of
stimulus, the world economic crisis of the late
countries that existed in Western Europe at
1920s and early 1930s. Some parliamentary
regimes survived, while others yielded to authori- that time.
tarian rule and, in particular, fascism. Prevailing For each theoretical model, Berg-Schlosser
assumptions concerning modernization and and de Meur (1994) examine whether the
progress, whether liberal or Marxist, were severely countries in their sample conform to the
shattered (1994: 253).
model’s predictions of democratic survival
The theories under investigation were versus breakdown. A model is confirmed
developed primarily through the examination when it correctly predicts the survival or
of Western European countries, and it is not breakdown of democracy. The attention to
clear that they should also apply to non- individual cases permits the researchers to
Western societies. In order to satisfy scope identify cases that partially support or contra-
conditions, Berg-Schlosser and de Meur dict a model’s hypothesis as well. Comparing
(1994), therefore, restrict their sample to 16 the successes and failures of each theory,
Western European countries. The limited time Berg-Schlosser and de Meur find the strong-
period seeks to satisfy possibility conditions. est support for, first, structural models that
All of the countries in the sample entered the emphasize socioeconomic conditions and,
period as parliamentary democracies and second, agency models that emphasize the

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 17 11/29/2008 11:05:56 AM


18 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE POLITICS

actions of individual actors. Institutional and our observations in a contingent manner:


meso-level models are only weakly sup- ‘Given certain conditions, a given effect is
ported. Complex models incorporating nine likely to occur.’ In this view, social reality is
or more independent variables were more inherently random and all social processes
likely to produce mixed results, a conse- embody a stochastic component that cannot,
quence of the diversity present among cases. even in principle, be identified, much less
Applying QCA (Ragin, 1987) to simplify modeled (Goldthorpe, 2000: chapter 7). The
their results, Berg-Schlosser and de Meur most formal versions of this approach are
(1994: 276) find the most parsimonious solu- found in probabilistic models – such as
tions to emphasize ‘basic factors like demo- regression analysis – that produce precise
cratic legitimacy and the political role of the predictions of the likely effect of one variable
military (as with Dahl) together with some upon another. In contrast to the tendential
actor-related aspects like interventions by conception of social reality, comparative
members of the upper class (for Linz)’. methods see the social world in terms of sets
Perhaps the most significant finding, how- and set theoretic relations, especially those
ever, is that the emphasis on historically that are consistent with arguments of causal
important cases such as Great Britain, necessity or sufficiency. This view motivates
Germany, Italy, and Spain has, in fact, hin- a search for invariant or at least highly con-
dered understanding of democratic persist- sistent connections between causal condi-
ence and breakdown: tions and outcomes.
But it can also be seen that countries like Finland,
Czechoslovakia, Greece, and even France are
hardly in line with the expectations of any of the Set theory in comparative research
theorists and in several instances provide direct
counterfactual examples. This result points to the Although the tendential view of reality domi-
often rather limited perspective in theory building nates social scientific discourse, most social
of some of these authors as far [as] geographical
scientific theory invokes a set theoretic notion
distribution and historical depth are concerned
(Berg-Schlosser and de Meur, 1994: 276). of reality. For example, when researchers
observe that ‘religious fundamentalists are
Bridging the worlds of case-oriented and politically conservative’ they are arguing that
variable-oriented analysis, comparative religious fundamentalists form a rough subset
methods make it possible for Berg-Schlosser of the set of political conservatives. Another
and de Meur to adjudicate among competing example: Esping-Andersen (1990) proposes a
theories, examine relations among explana- set theoretic model of the nation-state. Liberal,
tory variables, and identify cases that contra- corporatist, and social democratic countries
dict specific theories. are each a subset of the welfare capitalist
countries; together, they constitute a complete
set: The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism.
Capitalist countries are not necessarily wel-
THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF THE fare states, however. Esping-Andersen uses
COMPARATIVE METHOD the term ‘welfare’ as a modifier, indicating
that welfare states are a subset of capitalist
The greatest strengths of the comparative countries. And capitalist countries are, in turn,
method arise from its distinctiveness, not a subset of all countries.
from its facility for bridging variable-
oriented and case-oriented analysis. Social Types of set theoretic connections
researchers traditionally conceive of social The existence of a set theoretic relationship
reality in terms of tendencies and probabilis- indicates that some type of connection may link
tic relationships. That is, we generally frame distinct phenomena. This connection can take

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 18 11/29/2008 11:05:57 AM


THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF COMPARATIVE RESEARCH 19

one of three basic forms: descriptive, constitu- would have nothing like the same significance,
tive, or causal. Consider, for illustration, the above all for the social structure and all the specific
problems of the modern Occident connected with
opening observation that motivates Weber’s it. Exact calculation – the basis of everything
investigation of The Protestant Ethic and the else – is only possible on a basis of free labour
Spirit of Capitalism: ‘the fact that business (1958: 22).
leaders and owners of capital, as well as the
higher grades of skilled labour, and even more Weber’s model of capitalism, then, is a
the higher technically and commercially trained combination of six essential conditions. Such
personnel of modern enterprises are over- a model is constitutive: the elements of the
whelmingly Protestant’ (1958: 35). The puzzle model are closely intertwined and together
that motivates Weber’s analysis is explaining constitute rational capitalism. For example,
the fact that people in these occupations consti- double-entry accounting ‘is also found in the
tuted a rough subset of the set of Protestants. Far East, the Near East, and in antiquity’
His observation is not simply that there is an (Weber, 1958: 22) but contributes to ‘the
‘association’ between two variables, but that a continual pursuit of profit’ only when com-
specific connection – between certain occupa- bined with free labor.
tions and Protestantism – is remarkably con- Whenever a set-theoretic connection is
sistent (they are ‘overwhelmingly’ Protestant). interpreted as evidence that something is an
He goes on to query: ‘[W]hy were the districts ‘essential’ component, aspect, or part of
of highest economic development at the same another, it may be viewed as constitutive.
time particularly favourable to a revolution in Whether a set-theoretic relation is seen as
the Church?’ (Weber, 1958: 36). Weber notes, evidence of a constitutive versus a causal
in effect, that these highly developed districts connection is a matter of interpretation. For
constitute a subset of those opposed to the example, some might interpret the fact that
Catholic Church – that again there is a remark- the advanced industrial societies are uni-
ably consistent, almost uniform, connection. As formly democratic as evidence that ‘eco-
first presented by Weber, these two set theoretic nomic development is causally sufficient for
connections are primarily descriptive in nature democratic government.’ Others, however,
because he says nothing about why these con- might avoid making a causal argument and
nections exist. interpret this same connection as evidence
Weber’s goal in The Protestant Ethic is to that having a democratic government is an
unravel the puzzle of the set-theoretic connec- essential part of being an advanced industrial
tions between capitalism and Protestantism. society. The key distinction is in how the
Defining the spirit of capitalism as the method- connection is understood and interpreted.
ical, continuous pursuit of profit, Weber begins Constitutive analysis is central to what
by elucidating the relevant characteristics of Ragin (1992) has referred to as the process of
modern capitalism: rational calculation, entre- ‘casing.’ Researchers engage in casing when-
preneurs, credit markets, the separation of ever they attempt to delineate the conceptual
work and home, and double-entry accounting boundaries of a case or set of cases.
(Weber, 1958: 17–22).1 Each of these condi- Researchers often engage in casing as they
tions, however, has existed before and, there- attempt to identify conceptually the observa-
fore, cannot be solely responsible for capitalist tions included in their analyses. In The
exchange. It is only with the rise of the labor Protestant Ethic, Weber’s primary concern is
market – ‘the rational capitalistic organization the casing of rational capitalism. He
of (formally) free labour’ (Weber, 1958: 21) – asks, ‘What is rational capitalism? How is it
that these conditions take on a modern, capi- different from other economic systems?’
talistic character: Casing seeks to answer the questions, ‘If
For without the rational capitalistic organization of I see it, how will I know?’ ‘What are its
labour, all this, so far as it was possible at all, essential elements?’

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 19 11/29/2008 11:05:57 AM


20 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE POLITICS

An important aspect of casing is that it one set is connected to membership in


identifies the theoretically salient character- another. Weber does this by linking Luther’s
istics of the case. That capitalism involves conception of the calling to the spirit of capi-
exchange for gain is not salient because talism. By describing how the sense of call-
exchange for gain exists everywhere, at all ing combined with a worldly asceticism led
times (Weber, 1958: 17). Exchange for gain Protestants to embrace capitalist production
may be central to rational capitalism but, and exchange, Weber details how member-
theoretically, it is not decisive. The separa- ship in one set (people possessing the
tion of work and home, however, has much Protestant ethic) connects to membership in
greater theoretical salience. Although the another (people possessing the spirit of capi-
‘spatial separation of places of work from talism). Note that Weber does not claim that
those of residence exists elsewhere’ (Weber, all Protestants embraced capitalism, nor does
1958: 22), it is only under conditions of he claim that all those who embraced capital-
capitalism that this separation forces workers ism were Protestant. That is, Weber does not
to seek their livelihood on the labor market: argue for the existence of a perfect subset
‘The tendency everywhere else was for relationship at the individual level but rather
acquisitive enterprises to arise as parts of a an affinity between the two. The two rough
royal or manorial household (of the oikos), subset relations described at the outset of this
which is, as Rodbertus has perceived, with discussion are evidence of this affinity.
all its superficial similarity, a fundamentally
different, even opposite, development’ Set theory and within-case analysis
(Weber, 1958: 22, emphasis in original). Social researchers use the term ‘case study’
Thus, constitutive analysis seeks to identify in a variety of ways (Ragin and Becker,
the interconnected components of a type of 1992). Frequently, comparative research is
case – its essential features. It produces a subsumed under the term (e.g., Gerring,
litmus test for membership in the set of cases 2007: chapter 2). However, we find it useful
under observation. An observation is excluded to distinguish between within-case analysis
if it lacks any of the essential features or dis- (i.e., single case studies) and cross-case
plays any feature that is prohibited. analysis (i.e., comparative studies) as each of
Having outlined the characteristics of these forms of analysis entails distinct
modern capitalism, Weber observes that research methods. Within-case analysis
modern capitalism first took root in Protestant- focuses on singular cases. Many researchers
dominated regions. That is to say, the set of feel that because single-case studies lack a
regions where modern capitalism arose are a comparative element, they are not ‘real
subset of the set of Protestant countries. To research.’ We disagree. Case studies are par-
establish a causal connection, Weber seeks to ticularly useful in interpreting culturally or
link the rise of Protestantism with the rise of historically significant phenomenon (Ragin,
modern capitalism: 1994). Case studies of events such as the
storming of the Bastille (Sewell, 1996), the
Montesquieu says (Esprit des Lois, Book XX,
funeral of Abraham Lincoln (Schwartz,
chap.7) of the English that they ‘had progressed
the farthest of all peoples of the world in three 1991), and the rise of the English working
important things: in piety, in commerce, and in class (Thompson, 1966) are valuable because
freedom’. Is it not possible that their commercial they apply social science theory and concepts
superiority and their adaptation to free political to the study of the causes and consequences
institutions are connected in some way with that
of important moments of historical transfor-
record of piety which Montesquieu ascribes to
them? (1958: 45) mation or qualitative change.
Moreover, case studies are not necessarily
To establish causality, researchers must spec- non-comparative. There is a crucial distinc-
ify the mechanism by which membership in tion between the unit of analysis and the unit

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 20 11/29/2008 11:05:57 AM


THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF COMPARATIVE RESEARCH 21

of observation (Denton, 2007). Unfortunately, three routes to modernity; that is, his three
social researchers often use the term ‘case’ to sets of modernizing revolutions. The set of
refer to both. As King et al. (1994) point out, bourgeois revolutions culminating in democ-
a single case study may involve many obser- racy include the cases of the French
vations. Thompson (1966), for example, uses Revolution and the English and American
a variety of methods to examine and synthe- civil wars. The set of conservative revolu-
size data from a variety of sources in order to tions culminating in fascism include the
explain the emergence of English working cases of Japan’s Meiji Restoration and
class consciousness. Today it is fashionable Bismarck’s unification of Germany. Finally,
to refer to such research as ‘triangulated’ or the set of peasant revolutions culminating in
‘multi-method’ (Brewer and Hunter, 2006; communism include the Russian and Chinese
Reinharz, 1992), but case study researchers revolutions. In turn, these three sets of revo-
have always leveraged a variety of data lutions constitute a subset of what might be
sources and analytic techniques in order to termed ‘modernizing revolutions.’
confirm their findings and make sense of Hobsbawm (1967) observes that ‘[t]he
their cases. As cases exist in space and across author of a comparative analysis does not
time, implicit – if not explicit – comparisons compete with the specialists; he exploits
are inevitable. Thompson’s study covers 50 them and may have to question them.’
years and spans the whole of the country. (p. 821) Within-case and comparative studies
He invites comparison of the English work- are complementary. The set theoretic nature
ers by including separate chapters on field of comparative research requires the conduct
laborers, artisans, and weavers. Likewise, his of within-case analysis, as sets are all about
examination of worker responses compares cases – the elements contained within sets –
various forms of resistance, protest, and and the characterization of cases in terms of
working-class radicalism. By the conclusion set memberships.
of the text, Thompson has reviewed the cul-
tural and structural transformations between
1780 and 1832 that gave rise to class con-
sciousness among English workers. Causal complexity in
Thompson’s project may be understood as a comparative research
comparison between the working class of
1780, a class an sich, and the working class Conventionally, researchers do not present
of 1832, a class für sich. their causal arguments in terms of set rela-
Finally, within-case analysis is an essential tions but, rather, in terms of how causes
component of good cross-case, comparative come together to produce outcomes. Moore
research. It is for this reason that some (1966), for example, speaks of ‘three routes
researchers subsume comparative research to the modern world,’ and Skocpol (1979)
under the moniker of ‘case study.’ Good discusses social revolutions as the product of
cross-case comparison necessarily involves state breakdowns and peasant revolts. Neither
the investigation of individual cases on their author makes their sets explicit, and fre-
own terms. Indeed, a common method of quently it takes some effort to discern the set
presenting comparative research is exempli- relations. However, close analysis of most
fied by Barrington Moore, Jr. (1966) in comparative work reveals a conjunctural
Social Origins of Dictatorship and understanding of causation. In essence,
Democracy. Moore spends the bulk of the causal conjunctures involve intersections of
text reviewing the individual cases (that is, conditions, which in turn can be understood
conducting within-case analysis) and offers as set intersections.
systematic comparative analysis at the con- Moore (1966), for example, identifies five
clusion. It is here that Moore constructs his conditions for the development of democracy.

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 21 11/29/2008 11:05:57 AM


22 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE POLITICS

1. The development of a balance to avoid too strong The study of necessity and sufficiency is a
a crown or too independent a landed aristocracy. longstanding interest of comparative research-
2. A turn toward an appropriate form of commercial ers (Goertz and Starr, 2003). A cause is nec-
agriculture. essary when the set of cases exhibiting the
3. The weakening of the landed aristocracy.
cause (e.g., state breakdown) includes the
4. The prevention of an aristocratic-bourgeois coali-
tion against the peasants and workers.
entire set of cases exhibiting the outcome
5. A revolutionary break with the past. (pp. (e.g., social revolution), The presence of state
430–31). breakdown is a necessary condition for the
occurrence of social revolution. A cause is
Each of these items involves a process of sufficient when the set of cases exhibiting the
transformation: ‘development,’ ‘turn,’ ‘weak- outcome (e.g., social revolution) includes the
ening,’ ‘prevention,’ ‘break.’ When these entire set of cases exhibiting the cause or,
processes are found together, they constitute more commonly, a combination of causes
a ‘bourgeois revolution’ which is one form of (e.g., the combination of state breakdown
‘modernizing revolutions.’ However, Moore’s and peasant revolt). The combined presence
unit of observation is not the modernizing of state breakdown and peasant revolt is a
revolution – that is his unit of analysis – but, sufficient condition for the occurrence of
rather, individual countries. Countries that social revolution.
experienced the combination of these proc- Complex conditions of necessity and suf-
esses, such as England, France, and the ficiency can combine to form what Ragin
United States, are found in the set of coun- (1987) calls ‘multiple conjunctural causa-
tries that experienced bourgeois revolutions. tion.’ Multiple conjunctural causation exists
Countries that did not experience each of when a single causal condition is neither
these processes, such as India which lacked a necessary nor sufficient to produce the out-
revolutionary break with the past, are not come on its own but, rather, only in combina-
found in the set of countries that experienced tion with other causal conditions.
bourgeois revolutions. Moreover, India is not Re-examining Gamson’s (1990) social pro-
found among the set of countries that experi- test data, for example, Ragin (1989) finds
enced modernizing revolutions of any form that challenging groups (social movement
(bourgeois, conservative, or peasant), which organizations) secure new advantages for
according to Moore explains its long-term their constituents if they satisfy any one
stagnation (Moore, 1966: chapter 6). of the following combinations of causal
Skocpol’s subtitle – A Comparative Analysis conditions.
of France, Russia, and China – immediately
reveals countries as her units of observation. 1. No bureaucratic organization, middle or mixed
Searching for necessary and sufficient condi- strata constituents, no help from outsiders, and
tions of social revolution, Skocpol uncovers acceptance by antagonists.
2. Middle or mixed strata constituents, non-dis-
important subset relations. First, countries that
placement goals, and help from outsiders.
experience social revolution are a subset of
3. Bureaucratic organization, lower strata constitu-
countries that experience state breakdown or ents, non-displacement goals, and acceptance by
peasant revolt. Second, countries that experi- antagonists.
ence state breakdown combined with peasant 4. Non-displacement goals, help from outsiders, and
revolt are a subset of countries that experience acceptance by antagonists (pp. 392–93).
social revolution. The first relationship – in
which the outcome is a subset of the cause – While any one of these combinations of
identifies a relationship consistent with neces- conditions will result in the challenging
sity; the second relationship – in which the group securing new advantages, there is no
cause is a subset of the outcome – identifies one individual cause common to all combina-
that is consistent with sufficiency. tions. Mackie (1974) refers to such causes as

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 22 11/29/2008 11:05:57 AM


THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF COMPARATIVE RESEARCH 23

INUS causes because each is an Insufficient occurred. Cities in the analysis have the following
(not sufficient by itself) but Necessary com- characteristics in common: the population was
over 25,000, the steel industry was an important
ponent of a causal combination that is, itself, employer, black workers were a significant part of
Unnecessary (due to multiple paths) but the steel workforce, and the recruitment efforts of
Sufficient to bring about the outcome. the national committee reached each location
during the organizing drive. We selected cases
from Foster’s (1920) account of the organizing
drive and include only those locations that actually
participated in the strike. The final group of 16
METHODS OF COMPARATIVE cases ranges in size from single-industry towns to
ANALYSIS major multi-industry cities. (1995: 1497–98)

Comparative analysis can be formalized By conducting a case study of each city in


through the construction of truth tables, which the sample, Brown and Boswell produce the
show the connections between different com- data set shown in Table 1.1.4 ‘Recent black
binations of conditions and an outcome migration’ is an indicator of whether the city
(Ragin, 1987; 2000). Although conventional has recently experienced a large increase in
datasets may be used in their construction, the its population of young, single, black males.
columns of a truth table do not represent vari- A city is considered to have a weak steel-
ables, per se, nor do the rows represent cases. workers union (‘Weak union’) if the union
Rather, the columns of a truth table represent had previously suffered a failed strike against
sets and the rows represent relationships US Steel (the primary target of the 1919 steel
among sets, specifically, all logically possible strike). ‘Political repression’ exists when
intersections among the relevant sets. These local governments align themselves with
intersections may be understood as represent- capital rather than labor.
ing logically possible combinations of causal These three causal conditions were not the
conditions. Comparative research is the study only conditions that Brown and Boswell
of the connections between combinations of (1995) examined. Their initial truth table
conditions and outcomes. Whether implicitly included only two conditions, ‘Recent black
or explicitly, comparative researchers con- migration’ and ‘Weak Union.’ However, this
struct truth tables when they examine how configuration created a ‘contradiction’
causal conditions relate to specific outcomes. (Ragin, 1987: 113–118): five cities – Buffalo,
To illustrate the construction of a truth Chicago, Gary, Johnstown, and Cleveland –
table, we review Brown and Boswell’s (1995) all experienced recent black migration and a
analysis of how split labor markets affected history of strong unions; however, the first
interracial strikebreaking and solidarity during four cities exhibited black strikebreaking
the 1919 steel strike. After conducting case while Cleveland did not. Contradictions indi-
studies of 16 northern cities,2 Brown and cate an inadequately specified model (Ragin,
Boswell (1995) use comparative methods 1987) because identical conditions should
(specifically, crisp-set QCA) to identify three lead to similar outcomes. To resolve contra-
causal conditions that explain four forms of dictions, comparative researchers reexamine
interracial strikebreaking.3 To simplify our both their theory and their cases. It may be
discussion, we review just one of their out- that an error was made in the process of
comes: the presence of black strikebreaking casing and that the contradictory case(s) does
in the face of white worker solidarity. not properly belong to the population under
Brown and Boswell (1995) begin their investigation. More commonly, the researcher
analysis by constructing a sample of cities uncovers an additional causal condition that
that participated in the strike: explains the contradictory result. In the
Our unit of analysis is the steel-producing com- analysis at hand, Brown and Boswell
munities where relevant variation in race relations (1995) considered three variables that they

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 23 11/29/2008 11:05:57 AM


24 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE POLITICS

Table 1.1 Causal conditions and presence of Black strikebreaking


(from Brown and Boswell, 1995, Table 5)
City Recent Black Weak Political Black
migration union repression strikebreaking
Bethlehem No Yes Yes No
Buffalo Yes No Yes Yes
Chicago Yes No Yes Yes
Cleveland Yes No No No
Decatur No No Yes No
East Chicago Yes Yes Yes Yes
Gary Yes No Yes Yes
Johnstown Yes No Yes Yes
Joliet No Yes Yes No
McKeesport No Yes Yes No
Milwaukee No Yes Yes No
New Castle No Yes Yes No
Pittsburgh Yes Yes Yes Yes
Reading No Yes Yes No
Wheeling No No No No
Youngstown Yes Yes Yes Yes

suspected might affect the connection Brown and Boswell (1995) find that all but
between black migration and strong unions, one of the possible combinations is repre-
on the one hand, and black strikebreaking, on sented by at least one city; of those, two
the other: city size, whether the city was combinations are associated with the emer-
dominated by US Steel or Bethlehem Steel, gence of black strikebreaking. The causal
and local government repression. The addi- combination that is not represented in the
tion of the third condition, local government sample is referred to as a ‘remainder’ (Ragin
repression, yielded a truth table free of con- et al., 2006b) and is identified by marking the
tradictions and also was confirmed as caus- outcome with a dash (–). Remainders are
ally relevant in their case studies. common because social phenomena are
A truth table consists of one row per logi-
cally possible combination of conditions. A Table 1.2 Truth table for the presence of
truth table, then, has 2k rows, where k equals Black strikebreaking, derived from
the number of causal conditions. As the Brown and Boswell (1995: 1505, Table 5)
number of causal conditions increases, and M U R Y Cases
the size of the truth table grows exponen-
1 1 1 1 1 East Chicago, Pittsburgh,
tially, analysis become increasingly complex. Youngstown
Software packages such as fsQCA (Ragin 2 1 1 0 –
et al., 2006a) can help to manage this com- 3 1 0 1 1 Buffalo, Chicago, Gary,
plexity; nevertheless, most practitioners exam- Johnstown
ine between five and ten causal conditions. To 4 1 0 0 0 Cleveland
5 0 1 1 0 Bethlehem, Joliet,
construct the truth table, the researcher refers
McKeesport,
to the previously specified dataset and records New Castle, Reading
which combinations of causal conditions are 6 0 1 0 0 Milwaukee
associated with the presence of the outcome 7 0 0 1 0 Decatur
and which are associated with its absence.5 8 0 0 0 0 Wheeling
Brown and Boswell’s (1995) final truth table Note: M = recent black migration, U = weak union,
is presented in Table 1.2. R = political repression, Y = black strikebreaking

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 24 11/29/2008 11:05:57 AM


THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF COMPARATIVE RESEARCH 25

characterized by limited diversity (Ragin, The researcher first applies the method of
1987: 104–13; 2000). That is, many of the agreement to the positive cases exhibiting the
logically possible combinations of causal outcome. Upon identifying a causal condi-
conditions simply do not exist in reality. (We tion (or causal combination) associated with
address the issue of limited diversity, espe- the outcome, the researcher examines the
cially its relation to counterfactual analysis, negative cases to see if the absence of
in greater detail below). the outcome is associated with the absence of
the cause. Referring again to Brown and
Boswell’s (1995) truth table (Table 1.2), the
Mill’s methods of agreement method of difference reconfirms the initial
and difference conclusion that black strikebreaking is a
product of recent black migration and politi-
The classic techniques of comparative meth- cal repression. Of the five configurations that
odology are those proposed by Mill (1875). exhibit the absence of strikebreaking, none
The simplest of all comparative logics, the exhibits the presence of both recent black
method of agreement is also the most likely migration and political repression.
to lead to faulty conclusions. The logic As the indirect method of difference com-
behind the method of agreement holds that prises two applications of the method of
any given outcome will, inevitably, have a agreement, the same two limitations apply to
single cause. By examining a sample of cases both methods. The first – the threat of an
exhibiting the same outcome, a researcher omitted variable – is common to all compara-
seeks to identify the single cause that all tive research methods and, indeed, all social
cases have in common. Ragin (1987: 36) research methods. Researchers may draw the
extends this logic to encompass combina- wrong conclusion when important causes are
tions of conditions, arguing that the success- omitted. If the identified causal condition is,
ful identification of a shared combination of itself, caused by an antecedent condition, the
causally relevant conditions would also sat- researcher’s explanation will be incomplete.
isfy the method of agreement. Applying the Spurious relationships raise a similar type of
method of agreement to Brown and Boswell’s issue. If both the identified causal condition
(1995) truth table (Table 1.2), reveals that all and the outcome are caused by an omitted
instances of black strikebreaking occurred in third condition, the researcher may identify
cities characterized by recent black migra- the wrong condition as causing the outcome.
tion and political repression. According to In this latter situation, one hopes that the
Mill’s method of agreement, then, the error will be uncovered as the researcher
research will conclude that the combined examines his or her cases and when attempt-
presence of recent black migration and polit- ing to elucidate how the condition causes the
ical repression caused black strikebreaking. outcome. The second and more significant
The process by which the cause produces the limitation of the method of agreement is that
outcome remains to be explained. In the it is incapable of addressing multiple con-
absence of a well-specified theory, such junctural causation. As Mill (1875), himself,
explanations are generally best developed emphasized, when an outcome has more than
through the application of within-case meth- one cause, the method of agreement will not
ods such as process tracing. be able to identify any of them:
Mill’s indirect method of difference – That some one antecedent is the cause of a given
what Ragin (1987: 39) refers to as ‘a double effect because all other antecedents have been
application of the method of agreement’ – found capable of being eliminated, is a just infer-
ence only if the effect can have but one cause. If it
leverages negative cases (that is, cases that admits of several, nothing is more natural than
do not exhibit the outcome) in order to that each of these should separately admit of
strengthen the researcher’s conclusions. being eliminated. (1875: 474–5)

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 25 11/29/2008 11:05:57 AM


26 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE POLITICS

Qualitative Comparative Analysis Truth table reduction


The analysis of multiple conjunctural causa-
Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA, see tion involves a process known as ‘truth table
Ragin, 1987; 2000) builds upon Mill’s meth- reduction’ or ‘Boolean minimization.’ A
ods in two fundamental ways. Most signifi- reduced or simplified truth table results in a
cantly, QCA permits the analysis of multiple Boolean equation that expresses the various
conjunctural causation, addressing the great- causal combinations that are associated with
est limitation of Mill’s methods. Moreover, the presence of the outcome. Ragin (1987)
by employing counterfactual analysis, QCA details the complete minimization process;
permits a more nuanced analysis of the rela- here, we provide only an overview.6 The
tionship between causal conditions and the basic process of Boolean minimization is
presence and absence of outcomes. derived from the proposition that invariant,
Rooted in set theory, QCA uses set or close to invariant, connections exist
algebra – also known as Boolean algebra – to between explanatory conditions and out-
analyze causal configurations. Boolean alge- comes. Each row of the truth table represents
bra provides operations for analyzing and a logically possible combination of causal
manipulating sets. The most useful of these conditions. For each combination that is
operations for comparative research are dis- associated with the presence of the outcome,
cussed in Ragin (2000: 171–180) and include the truth table reduction process seeks to
set union (logical or, represented as addition) eliminate logically redundant terms. In Table
and set intersection (logical and, represented 1.2, the first and third configurations are rep-
as multiplication). Truth table configurations resented by the equations:
are represented as Boolean equations in
s
which an uppercase letter represents the MUR Y
presence of a condition while a lowercase
letter represents its absence. In Boolean s
MuR Y
notation, Row 1 of Table 1.2 is represen-
ted as: When a pair of equations is identical
except for a single causal condition, the dis-
s
M⋅U⋅R Y tinguishing term may be considered
irrelevant and can be eliminated. The mini-
which indicates that ‘The presence of black mization of these two equations, therefore,
migration in combination with a weak union produces:
and political repression is sufficient for black
s
strikebreaking.’ Just as with linear algebra, a MR Y
shortened notation may be used for multipli-
cative terms, and the above equation also which is the same result as was obtained
may be represented as: through the application of Mill’s method of
agreement: the presence of recent black
s migration and political repression resulted in
MuR Y
black strikebreaking. QCA’s methods are a
superset of Mill’s methods.
Row 5, which is read as ‘The absence of
A more complex example is provided by
recent black migration in combination with a
Stokke’s (2007) analysis of ‘shaming’ as an
weak union and political repression is suffi-
attempt to secure compliance with interna-
cient for the absence of black strikebreaking,’
tional fishing agreements. Shaming involves
is represented as:
an attempt to change a party’s behavior by
s
exposing their violations to others (in this
mUR y case, the international community). Having

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 26 11/29/2008 11:05:57 AM


THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF COMPARATIVE RESEARCH 27

conducted a series of case studies of shaming 4. Inconvenience (I): The inconvenience [to the
attempts, Stokke (2007) identifies five causal target] of the behavioral change that the shamers
conditions that affect whether shaming seek to elicit.
attempts are successful. 5. Reverberation (R): Domestic-level political costs
if shamers scandalize [the target] as a culprit.
(p. 503)
1. Advice (A): Whether the shamers can substantiate
Having conducted his case studies and
their criticism by reference to explicit advice by
identified his causal conditions, Stokke
the regime’s scientific body.
2. Commitment (C): Whether the target behavior (2007) produces a truth table which we have
violates explicit commitments. reproduced as Table 1.3.7 With five causal
3. Shadow of the future (S): The target’s perceived conditions, the corresponding truth table has
need to strike future deals and whether ignor- 32 logically possible combinations. The
ing the criticism will jeopardize such beneficial ten cases are distributed among eight con-
arrangements. figurations, resulting in 24 remainders (two

Table 1.3 Truth table for the presence of shaming, with counterfactual
conditions (based on Stokke, 2007, Table 1)
A C S I R Y Cases
1 1 1 1 1 1 1 Compliance
2 1 1 1 1 0 0 EC unilat. 1
3 1 1 1 0 1 –
4 1 1 1 0 0 1 EC unilat. 2
5 1 1 0 1 1 –
6 1 1 0 1 0 –
7 1 1 0 0 1 –
8 1 1 0 0 0 –
9 1 0 1 1 1 1 Overfishing
10 1 0 1 1 0 –
11 1 0 1 0 1 –
12 1 0 1 0 0 –
13 1 0 0 1 1 0 Mesh-size 2
14 1 0 0 1 0 0 Mesh-size 1
15 1 0 0 0 1 –
16 1 0 0 0 0 1 Krill report, Krill cap2
17 0 1 1 1 1 –
18 0 1 1 1 0 –
19 0 1 1 0 1 –
20 0 1 1 0 0 –
21 0 1 0 1 1 –
22 0 1 0 1 0 –
23 0 1 0 0 1 –
24 0 1 0 0 0 –
25 0 0 1 1 1 –
26 0 0 1 1 0 –
27 0 0 1 0 1 –
28 0 0 1 0 0 –
29 0 0 0 1 1 –
30 0 0 0 1 0 0 Loophole, Krill cap 1
31 0 0 0 0 1 –
32 0 0 0 0 0 –
Note: A = Advice, C = Commitment, S = Shadow of the Future, I = Inconvenience, R = Reverberation

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 27 11/29/2008 11:05:58 AM


28 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE POLITICS

configurations, Acsir and acsIr, characterize of determining the cause of successful


two cases each). shaming.
Half of the represented configurations are
examples of successful shaming: Complexity, parsimony, and
s counterfactual analysis
ACSIR Y In developing explanations of social life, in
s ‘telling about society’ (Becker, 1986), social
ACSir Y researchers seek to balance complexity and
s parsimony. The avoidance of crude, vulgar
AcSIR Y accounts demands that researchers recognize
s the possibility of multiple conjunctural cau-
Acsir Y sation, that there may exist a variety of expla-
nations, across cases, for the same outcome.
As the first and third equations differ only Indeed, Mill (1875) observes that, in the
with regard to the presence of commitment, social world, multiple conjunctural causation
that causal condition may be eliminated from is not the exception but the rule:
those configurations. The resulting mini- Now, in the case of political phenomena, the sup-
mized Boolean equation: position of unity of cause is not only wide of the
truth, but at an immeasurable distance from it.
s
ASIR + ACSir + Acsir Y The causes of every social phenomenon which we
are particularly interested about, security, wealth,
freedom, good government, public virtue, general
states that there are three combinations of intelligence, or their opposites, are infinitely
conditions that result in successful attempts numerous, especially the external or remote
at shaming. Observe that this solution is far causes, which alone are, for the most part, acces-
more complex and nuanced than that pro- sible to direct observation. No one cause suffices
of itself to produce any of these phenomena.
duced by Mill’s method of agreement.
(1875: 475)
The method of agreement would identify
only condition A (the presence of explicit And yet an explanation that is too particular,
advice from the scientific community) too qualified, can be as unsatisfying as one
as common to all events of successful sham- that is too general.
ing. The method of agreement, therefore, This tension between particularization and gener-
produces: alization – between literal and abstract representa-
tion – comes with the territory, I think, when
s you’re transmitting vicarious experience. A simple
A Y
chronicle of details, however graphic, locks you
into a particular time and place. You move beyond
This equation is too simplistic a solution to it by abstracting, but abstracting is an artificial
be convincing: surely the process of success- exercise, involving an oversimplification of com-
fully shaming a regime is more complicated plex realities (Gaddis, 2002: 14).
than simply having the support of the scien- This tension is particularly acute in compara-
tific community. And, indeed, application of tive research which studies both similarity
Mill’s indirect method of difference confirms and difference (Ragin, 1994). To establish set
this assertion. An examination of Table 1.3 membership and identify explicit relations
rejects the hypothesis that it is exclusively among sets, comparative researchers must
the scientific community that determines maintain the integrity and distinctiveness of
whether attempts at shaming will be success- their cases while demonstrating what they do
ful. Configurations 2, 13, and 14 are all and do not have in common. The more that a
instances of unsuccessful shaming over the researcher emphasizes the particular circum-
objections of the scientific community. stances and experiences of a case, the more
In this instance, Mill’s methods are incapable that a researcher restricts their scope and

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 28 11/29/2008 11:05:58 AM


THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF COMPARATIVE RESEARCH 29

possibility conditions, the less portable the counterfactual existed?’ Instead of running a
argument becomes. thought experiment, however, the comparative
Counterfactual analysis provides a means by researcher need only include the remainder in
which comparativists can balance particularity the analysis. Whether to incorporate a particu-
and generality. Exploring how the hypothetical lar counterfactual case is a determination that
presence or absence of a causal condition must be made upon the basis of substantive
would affect the outcome under investigation, and theoretical knowledge (Ragin and Sonnett,
counterfactual analysis is predominantly asso- 2004). Two criteria must be evaluated. Is the
ciated with case-oriented research. In fact, all counterfactual case plausible? And, if so, is it
social research involves counterfactual analysis reasonable to think that it would produce the
in some way (Lieberson, 1985) but case- outcome in question? Depending upon how it
oriented researchers tend to make their counter- affects the set relations within the truth table,
factual theorizing explicit (Fearon, 1991). In the inclusion of remainders may result in a
comparative research, counterfactual cases Boolean equation that is more parsimonious,
form the basis of thought experiments through more complex, or the equivalent of the origi-
which researchers assess a theory’s plausibility nal solution. Researchers must use their sub-
(Weber, 1905). stantive and theoretical knowledge to evaluate
Counterfactual analysis is particularly the feasibility of any solution resulting from
useful as a theory development tool the inclusion of counterfactuals.
(McKeown, 2004). Recognizing the com- Software packages such as fsQCA (Ragin
plexity of the social world, researchers tend et al., 2006a) simplify the process of con-
to be conservative when constructing theo- ducting counterfactual analysis. For example,
ries. Preferring to claim too little rather than by incorporating all remainders that produce
too much, social researchers are more likely a simpler result, fsQCA can be used to iden-
to make errors of omission rather than com- tify the most parsimonious solution possible
mission. Counterfactual analysis provides a for any truth table. Applying this procedure
means by which to test the implications of a to Stokke’s truth table (Table 1.3) produces a
theory (McKeown, 2004) and thereby assess dramatically simpler solution:
the viability of more parsimonious variants.
For any given analysis a researcher may con- s
i + SR Y
struct a variety of counterfactual cases.
Frequently, just a single causal condition is which indicates that shaming will be success-
altered; more complex analyses examine a ful when (a) it is not inconvenient for the
range of hypothetical conditions. targets of the shaming to change their behav-
Truth tables permit a systematic approach ior or (b) when future considerations and
to counterfactual analysis, one which encom- present political costs are high.
passes both simple and complex counterfactu- This solution and the previous solution of
als. As previously discussed, the social world the same truth table can be considered two
is characterized by limited diversity. In truth endpoints on a continuum that runs from
tables, limited diversity manifests itself as complexity to parsimony. Observe that the
‘remainders’ – the logically possible configu- complex solution (Acsir + ACSir + ASIR) is
rations of causal conditions that lack empirical a subset of the parsimonious solution (i +
instances. Representing ‘events that did not SR). Cases of shaming that involve the
happen’ (Lieberson, 1985: 45), remainders absence of inconvenience to the target – that
serve as counterfactual cases in comparative is, members of set i include members of sets
research (Ragin and Sonnett, 2004). Acsir and ACSir. Likewise, cases of shaming
Counterfactual analysis using remainders that invoke a shadow of the future and rever-
is straightforward: the researcher asks berations – members of set SR – include
‘How would my conclusions change if the members of set ASIR. The presence of this

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 29 11/29/2008 11:05:59 AM


30 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE POLITICS

subset relationship indicates that it is possi- intermediate solutions using counterfactual


ble to select counterfactual cases to produce analysis.8 The researcher can then adjudicate
intermediate solutions, between the parsimo- among the various solutions, selecting that
nious and the complex. one that best balances specificity and gener-
One way to derive an intermediate solution alizability given the current state of theory
is to use the technique described in Ragin and and what is known about the cases.
Sonnett (2004). Examining the term ASIR,
Ragin and Sonnett (2004) observe that ‘Causal
conditions S and R cannot be removed because
they appear in the corresponding parsimoni- CONCLUSION
ous term (SR) at the other end of the contin-
uum’ (p.16). To remove S or R would violate Comparative research is frequently seen as a
the subset relationship and, therefore, the only bridge connecting the worlds of qualitative,
candidates for removal are A and I. To discern case-oriented research and quantitative, vari-
whether either of these conditions may be able-oriented research. Focusing on a moder-
removed, the researcher must rely upon theo- ate number of cases, comparativists are able
retical and substantive knowledge. The fact to engage in both theory development (usu-
that the support of the regime’s scientific advi- ally the province of qualitative researchers)
sory board is the only condition present in all and hypothesis testing (usually the province
cases of successful shaming suggests that it of quantitative researchers). While compara-
may be a necessary condition and should be tive research can certainly be seen as a
retained. However, it does not make sense that bridge, its greatest strengths arise from its
shaming would be more likely to be success- distinctiveness. In common with the bulk of
ful when it is inconvenient (I) for a target to social science theorizing, comparative meth-
change its behavior than when it is convenient ods are fundamentally set theoretic.
(i). The causal condition I, therefore, may In contrast to conventional variable-
be dropped to produce the causal combina- oriented researchers, comparativists do not
tion ASR. seek mere associations but, rather, seek to
The same logic applies to the sets Acsir establish explicit connections among social
and ACSir. Conditions i, S, and R cannot be phenomena, conceived in set-theoretic terms.
removed because it would violate the subset To do this, comparativists maintain the integ-
relationship. Nor should conditions A, C, and rity of cases so as to identify sets that share
S be removed as each should contribute to members. Set relationships take three basic
the success of shaming. Removing condi- forms. A descriptive set relation articulates
tions c, s, and r produces the terms Ai and connections among sets but stops short of
ACSi. As the latter causal combination is a explanation. A constitutive set relation iden-
subset of the former, it may be removed, tifies essential aspects or components of
leaving Ai. The reduced terms, ASR and Ai, wholes and may be used to constitute theo-
yield the intermediate Boolean equation: retically based populations (e.g., the set of
modernizing revolutions). A causal set rela-
s
Ai + ΑSR Y tion goes beyond establishing an empirical
connection and details the causal mecha-
which is a superset of the complex solution nisms that explain how and why membership
(Acsir + ACSir + ASIR) and a subset of the in one set (the cause) is empirically linked to
parsimonious solution (i + SR). membership in another (the outcome). Causal
As long as the subset principle – that set relations often address conditions of
more complex solutions must be a subset of necessity and/or sufficiency, with a special
more parsimonious solutions – is maintained, concern for causal heterogeneity and INUS
researchers can produce a series of such causation (Mackie, 1974).

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 30 11/29/2008 11:06:00 AM


THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF COMPARATIVE RESEARCH 31

The core of causal analysis in comparative


research is the truth table, just as the core of NOTES
variable-oriented causal research is the linear
additive regression equation. These are funda- 1. We recognize that Weber also postulated more
mentally different ways of understanding the complex models of capitalism. See, for example,
social world. The configurational perspective Collins (1980), Giddens (1958), and Weber (1920).
Here, we restrict our discussion to Weber’s model
of comparative research emphasizes the search as presented in The Protestant Ethic for illustrative
for highly consistent relationships linking purposes.
combinations of causes to outcomes. The truth 2. The cities that Brown and Boswell (1995)
table models these relationships. Considering include in the analysis are: Bethlehem, Buffalo,
that comparativists typically trace their line- Chicago, Cleveland, Decatur, East Chicago, Gary,
Johnstown, Joliet, McKeesport, Milwaukee, New
age to the likes of Durkheim and Weber, the Castle, Pittsburg, Reading, Wheeling, and
introduction of truth table analysis to com- Youngstown.
parative research is relatively recent (Ragin, 3. The four outcomes that Brown and Boswell
1987). We have argued, however, that most (1995) examine are: (1) black strikebreaking (whites
comparative analysis involves truth tables, support union), (2) white strikebreaking (blacks sup-
port union), (3) biracial strikebreaking (low overall
either explicitly or implicitly. Contemporary compliance with union), and (4) biracial labor coali-
methodological developments – specifically, tion (high overall compliance with union).
the formalization of the comparative method as 4. Brown and Boswell (1995) do not actually
Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA) – present this dataset in their article. Rather, it is
aim to improve comparative research by derived from the truth table that they present as
Table 5 on page 1505. We are able to derive the
making explicit its assumptions, algorithms, original dataset from the truth table only because the
and techniques. This formalization has allowed researchers include a column listing which cities cor-
the development of software packages to respond to which causal configurations. This is one
facilitate technical aspects of comparative reason that we strongly recommend that compara-
analysis, which in turn frees researchers to tive researchers explicitly identify which cases corre-
spond to which truth table configurations. (The
concentrate on their most important task: primary reason being so that cases remain in the
getting to know their cases (Rubinson and foreground of the analysis.)
Ragin, 2007). 5. Based upon substantive and theoretical knowl-
If there is a downside to this formalization edge, the researcher may specify a threshold indicat-
and the associated development of software ing the outcome’s presence. For example, in a large
dataset the researcher may specify that the outcome
packages for comparative analysis, it is the must be present in at least three (or five or ten) cases
fear – as others have speculated (Shalev, to be recognized whereas in a small dataset the
2007) – that lowering the bar to entry will researcher may specify a minimum threshold of one
encourage the rote application of compara- case. Threshold specification relies upon the research-
tive methods. In fact, we expect the opposite. er’s in-depth knowledge of the population. For the
present discussion, we rely upon Brown and Boswell
Truth table analysis simultaneously elimi- (1995) threshold of one case, which is reasonable for
nates the most banal analytic tasks while an N of 16 cases. For additional discussion of thresh-
permitting a more sophisticated analysis of old specifications, see Ragin (2005) and von Eye
more cases in more depth. The investigation (1990).
of necessary and sufficient conditions, causal 6. Specifically, we omit a discussion of prime impli-
cant minimization (see Ragin, 1987: 95–98). Prime
complexity, and counterfactuals all become implicant minimization does not apply to the exam-
increasingly feasible through the application ples we review and does not affect our results.
of QCA, which directly implements the set 7. There is an inconsistency in Stokke’s (2007:
theoretic logic of comparative analysis. 507) reported truth table: rows 4 and 8 share the
Comparative research can, indeed, be done same configuration of causal conditions and out-
comes. Our Table 1.3 reflects this correction.
with or without formal techniques; however, 8. The software package fsQCA (Ragin et al.,
it is best done with an appreciation of its 2006a) includes procedures to facilitate such
distinctiveness. analyses.

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 31 11/29/2008 11:06:00 AM


32 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE POLITICS

REFERENCES Eckstein, H. (1992) ‘Case study and theory in


political science’, in Regarding Politics: Essays
Becker, H. S. (1986) ‘Telling about society’, in on Political Theory, Stability, and Change.
H. S. Becker (ed.) Doing things together: Berkeley: University of California Press.
Selected papers. Evanston, IL: Northwestern pp. 117–173.
University Press. pp. 121–36. Esping-Andersen, G. (1990) The three worlds
Berg-Schlosser, D. and de Meur, G. (1994) of welfare capitalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
‘Conditions of democracy in interwar Europe: University Press.
A Boolean test of major hypotheses’, Fearon, J. D. (1991) ‘Counterfactuals and
Comparative Politics, 26 (3): 253–279. hypothesis testing in political science’, World
Brady, H. E. (2004) ‘Doing good and doing Politics, 43 (2): 169–195.
better: How far does the quantitative tem- Foster, W. Z. (1920) The great steel strike and
plate get us?’, in H. Brady and D. Collier its lessons. New York: Huebsch.
(eds), Rethinking social inquiry: Diverse tools, Gaddis, J. L. (2002) The landscape of history:
shared standards. Lanham, MD: Rowman How historians map the past. Oxford: Oxford
and Littlefield. pp. 53–67. University Press.
Brady, H. E. and Collier, D. (eds) (2004) Gamson, W. (1990) The strategy of social pro-
Rethinking social inquiry: Diverse tools, test. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
shared standards. Lanham, MD: Rowman George, A. L. and Bennett, A. (2005) Case
and Littlefield. studies and theory development in the social
Braumoeller, B. F. and Goertz, G. (2002) sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
‘Watching your posterior: Comment Gerring, J. (2007) Case study research: Principles
on Seawright’, Political Analysis, 10 (2): and practices. New York: Cambridge
198–203. University Press.
Brewer, J. and Hunter, A. (2006) Foundations Giddens, A. (1958) ‘Introduction’, in M. Weber
of multimethod research: Synthesizing styles. (ed.), The Protestant ethic and the spirit of
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. capitalism. New Jersey: Prentice Hall.
Brown, C. and Boswell, T. (1995) ‘Strikebreaking pp. 1–12.
or solidarity in the great steel strike of 1919: Goertz, G. (2005) Social science concepts: A
A split labor market, game-theoretic, and user’s guide. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
QCA analysis’, American Journal of Sociology, University Press.
100 (6): 1479–1519. Goertz, G. and Starr, H. (eds) (2003) Necessary
Clarke, K. A. (2002) ‘The Reverend and the conditions: Theory, methodology, and appli-
ravens: Comment on Seawright’, Political cations. Lanham, MD: Rowman and
Analysis, 10 (2): 194–197. Littlefield.
Cohen, B. P. (1989) Developing sociological Goldthorpe, J. H. (2000) On sociology:
knowledge: Theory and method. Chicago: Numbers, narratives, and the integration of
Nelson-Hall. research and theory. Oxford: Oxford
Cohen, J. (1988) Statistical power analysis for University Press.
the behavioral sciences. New York: Lawrence Hermens, F. A. (1941) Democracy of anarchy?
Erlbaum. A study of proportional representation. Notre
Collins, R. (1980) ‘Weber’s last theory of capi- Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame.
talism: A systematization’, American Hobsbawm, E. J. (1967) ‘Review of
Sociological Review, 45 (6): 925–942. Social origins of dictatorship and democ-
Dahl, R. A. (1971) Polyarchy: Participation and racy’, American Sociological Review, 32
opposition. New Haven, CT: Yale University (5): 821–822.
Press. King, G., Keohane, R. and Verba, S. (1994)
Dahl, R. A. (1989) Democracy and its critics. Designing social inquiry: Scientific inference
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. in qualitative research. Princeton, NJ:
Denton, T. (2007) ‘Unit of observation in cross- Princeton University Press.
cultural research: Implications for sampling Lieberson, S. (1985) Making it count: The
and aggregated data analysis’, Cross-Cultural improvement of social research and theory.
Research, 41 (3): 3–31. Berkeley: University of California Press.

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 32 11/29/2008 11:06:00 AM


THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF COMPARATIVE RESEARCH 33

Linz, J. J. (1978) Crisis, breakdown, and reequili- Ragin, C. C. and Becker, H. S. (eds) (1992)
bration. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins What is a case? Exploring the foundations of
University Press. social inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge
Lipset, S. M. (1981) Political man: The social University Press.
bases of politics. Baltimore, MD: Johns Ragin, C. C., Drass, K. A. and Davey, S. (2006a)
Hopkins University Press. Fuzzy-set/qualitative comparative analysis
Luebbert, G. M. (1987) ‘Social foundations of 2.0 [computer software]. Tucson, Az:
political order in interwar Europe’, World Department of Sociology, University of
Politics, 39 (4): 449–478. Arizona.
Mackie, J. L. (1974) The cement of the universe: Ragin, C. C., Rubinson, C., Schaefer, D.,
A study of causation. Oxford: Clarendon. Anderson, S., Williams, E. and Geisel, H.
Mahoney, J. and Goertz, G. (2004) ‘The possi- (2006b) User’s guide to fuzzy-set/qualitative
bility principle: Choosing negative cases in comparative analysis [computer manual].
comparative research’, American Political Tucson, AZ: Department of Sociology,
Science Review, 98 (4): 653–669. University of Arizona.
McKeown, T. J. (2004) ‘Case studies and the limits Ragin, C. C., and Sonnett, J. (2004) ‘Between
of the quantitative worldview’, in H. E. Brady complexity and parsimony: Limited diversity,
and D. Collier (eds), Rethinking social inquiry: counterfactual cases, and comparative analy-
Diverse tools, shared standards. Lanham, MD: sis’, in S. Kropp and M. Minkenberg
Rowman and Littlefield. pp. 139–167. (eds), Vergleichen in der politikwissenschaft.
Mill, J. S. (1875) A system of logic, ratiocinative Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für
and inductive: Being a connected view of the Sozialwissenschaften.
principles of evidence and the methods of Reinharz, S. (1992) Feminist methods in social
scientific investigation, Vol. 2. London: research. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer. Rubinson, C. and Ragin, C. C. (2007) ‘New
Mjoset, L. and Clausen, T. H. (eds) (2007) methods for comparative research?’, in L.
Capitalisms compared, Oxford: Elsevier. Mjoset and T. H. Clausen (eds), Capitalisms
Moore, B., Jr. (1966) Social origins of dictator- compared. Oxford: Elsevier. pp. 373–389.
ship and democracy: Lord and peasant in the Sani, G. and Sartori, G. (1983) ‘Polarization,
making of the modern world. Boston, MA: Fragmentation and Competition in Western
Beacon Press. Democracies’, in Hans Daalder and Peter
Ragin, C. C. (1987) The comparative method: Mair (eds), Western European Party Systems:
Moving beyond qualitative and Quantitative Continuity and Change. London: Sage.
Strategies. Berkeley, CA: University of Schwartz, B. (1991) ‘Mourning and the making
California Press. of a sacred symbol: Durkheim and the Lincoln
Ragin, C. C. (1989) ‘The logic of the compara- assassination’, Social Forces, 70 (2): 343–364.
tive method and the algebra of logic’, Sewell, W. H., Jr. (1996) ‘Historical events as
Journal of Quantitative Anthropology, 1 (2): transformation of structures: Inventing revo-
373–398. lution at the Bastille’, Theory and Society,
Ragin, C. C. (1992) ‘“Casing” and the process 25 (6): 841–881.
of social inquiry’, in C. C. Ragin and H. S. Shalev, M. (2007) ‘Rejoinder: Affirming limits
Becker (eds), What is a case? Exploring the and defending alternatives to multiple
foundations of social inquiry. Cambridge: regression’, in L. Mjoset and T. H. Clausen
Cambridge University Press. pp. 217–226. (eds), Capitalisms compared. Oxford: Elsevier.
Ragin, C. C. (1994) Constructing social research. pp. 391–409.
Thousand Oaks, CA: Pine Forge Press. Skocpol, T. (1979) States and social revolu-
Ragin, C. C. (2000) Fuzzy-set social science. tions: A comparative analysis of France,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Russia, and China. Cambridge: Cambridge
Ragin, C. C. (2005, April) From fuzzy sets to University Press.
crisp truth tables (COMPASS working Paper Stokke, O. S. (2007) ‘Qualitative comparative
2004: 28) Retrieved January 21, 2008, from analysis, shaming, and international regime
http://www.compasss.org/Raginfztt_ effectiveness’, Journal of Business Research,
April05.pdf. 60 (5): 501–511.

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 33 11/29/2008 11:06:00 AM


34 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF COMPARATIVE POLITICS

Stoll, R. R. (1979) Set theory and logic. New Weber, M. (1905) ‘Objective possibility and
York: Dover. adequate causation in historical explana-
Thompson, E. P. (1966) The making of the tion’, in E.A. Shils and H.A. Finch (eds), The
English working class. New York: Vintage methodology of the social sciences. Glencoe,
Books. IL: The Free Press. pp. 164–188.
Vanhanen, T. (1984) The emergence of democ- Weber, M. (1920) ‘The origin of modern capi-
racy: A comparative study of 119 states, talism’, in R. Collins (ed.) Four sociological
1850–1979. Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum traditions: Selected readings. Oxford: Oxford
Fennica. University Press. pp. 36–57.
von Eye, A. (1990) Introduction to configural Weber, M. (1958) The Protestant ethic and the
frequency analysis: The search for types and spirit of capitalism. New Jersey: Prentice
antitypes in cross-classifications. New York: Hall.
Cambridge University Press.

9781412919760_Chap01.indd 34 11/29/2008 11:06:00 AM

You might also like