Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 27

Faculty of Law, University of Lucknow

ABSTRACT
Machiavelli’s work has constituted the object of
research and analysis from two relatively
opposite perspectives: the historical one and the
moral one. The former sees Machiavelli as “truly
a man of his time” (A. Gramsci), excessively
preoccupied by the problem of unifying Italy.
The latter harshly judges him on the grounds
that he is amoral and that he promotes cynicism
and cruelty. Between the two, there is another
perspective, the scientific one. In its view,
Machiavelli has in mind the creation of a
positive political science. Machiavelli was read
and interpreted in different ways. Some saw The
Prince as a code for tyranny and cynicism.
Others, on the contrary, saw in it a scientific
work of incontestable worth, even an expression
of humanism. These two views constitute the
extremes of the numerous interpretations
available. According to the ethical and political
aspect, Machiavellian thought is a polarised
one, as Croce and Gramsci have pointed out. We
subscribe to the view that considers as too
simplistic the attempt to analyse Machiavelli’s
work according to the triad: moral, immoral,
POLITICAL SCIENCE amoral, because understanding it necessitates
the use of nuances and subtleties.

Niccolò Machiavelli: The Father of Parantak Yadav


Modern Political Science B-30, 2nd Sem,
LL.B (Hons) Integrated.

Under the Guidance of Prof. D.C. Mishra,


University of Lucknow
Table of Contents

1) INTRODUCTION

2) WHO WAS NICCOLÒ MACHIAVELLI?

3) MACHIAVELLI’S INTENTIONS

4) MACHIAVELLI’S PHILOSOPHY

5) MACHIAVELLI – THE FATHER OF MODERN POLITICAL SCIENCE

i) The Object of Political Study

ii) The Method of Political Science

iii) The Autonomy of Politics

6) MACHIAVELLI – A POLITICAL PHENOMENOLOGIST

7) THE NATURE AND THE “LAWS” OF POWER

8) MACHIAVELLI AND THE POLITICAL MACHIAVELLIANISM

9) MACHIAVELLI’S ACTUALITY: CONTRIBUTION TO THE

DEVELOPMENT OF MODERN POLITICAL SCIENCE

10) BIBLIOGRAPHY

1|Page
Politics have no relation to morals.

If someone were determined to find a powerful metaphor or an accurate image to


describe Niccolò Machiavelli’s work and influence in the world of political thought, he
or she would most likely make use of words such as: turning point, crossroad point or
turning table. Undoubtedly, he is considered as a prominent figure among political
thinkers; many would go as far as to name him the founder and the father of modern
political science, just as Aristotle had fulfilled that role for Ancient Greece. The
Prince, published in 1532, became a constant reference and inspired different avenues
in political research.
Machiavelli’s contribution to this field was so important that thinkers who followed
him approached politics much differently than those who had preceded him. His work
and renown became an incessant reference for all authors, whether they agreed with his
principles or disapproved them.
The Prince illustrates a new understanding of politics and political ethics, distancing
itself from the views which had dominated the political scene up to that point: the
Aristotelian and the Christian ones. Although radically different in many respects,
including the origin of political power, these two paradigms shared one important
aspect, namely the belief that any political endeavour or figure should prioritise the
welfare of the citizens as the supreme goal of politics.
Thus, Aristotle claimed that it was incumbent upon the State and upon any political
official to seek to achieve what was good for the community, for the polis; he went as
far as to term this good “the greatest good in the realm of practical life”, or simply “the
supreme good”. Undeniably, helping one citizen was desirable, but the Greek
philosopher thought it much more preferable, infinitely more uplifting to do good for
an entire nation or for a city.1 The Apostle Paul, in his Epistle to Romans, chapter 13,
talks about the “dignitary’s” role and political authority, calling him, in unequivocal
terms: “God’s servant for your welfare”.
Machiavelli dissociated himself from these models, rejecting both the
importance of the eternal values treasured by Aristotelians and that of God as source of
authority – to which Christian tradition held firmly. The Prince depicts a state where
the prosperity of common citizens is no longer a primary objective for political
institutions and officials. What should prevail is the preservation and consolidation of

1
ARISTOTEL, Etica Nicomahicǎ, Antet, Bucureşti, 1988, p. 8.
2|Page
the state, which has become an end in itself, a goal per se. Furthermore, state reason (as
Louis XIV would later proclaim) became the most notorious exponent of political
absolutism. It is no wonder then that the goal of politics was politics itself. As for the
political dignitary, his purpose is redefined in terms of struggle for supremacy and
responsibility to defend and strengthen the state at all costs.
The Machiavellian paradigm would govern the entire modern political thinking,
overshadowing outbursts, such as Immanuel Kant’s, who could not imagine how
someone would tailor political morality based on the ruler’s interest. And that is
precisely what Machiavelli had done.

1. WHO WAS NICCOLÒ MACHIAVELLI?

A brief introduction is necessary to acquaint us with a highly debated person of all


political thinking. Francis Bacon, who created the inductive method, considered that
we should “thank Machiavelli and the writers of his king for having openly signalled
what people usually do, and not what they should do, and for having done that without
dissimulation”. There were numerous authors, however, who saw in him the
embodiment of everything that is evil in politics for he persuaded Cesare Borgia to
enact the massacre at Sinigaglia, where many of Cesare’s enemies were slain. Some
authors would go as far as to call him the post-mortem counsellor of so many tyrants
such as Napoleon, Hitler or Mussolini, the latter having actually written a Prelude (a
sort of preface) for The Prince. Lenin is said to have taken with him a copy of this book
when he was exiled to Finland, due to his confrontation with the tsarist army; it was
there that he wrote The State and the Revolution. Then who was this character who was
seen in such different lights?

Niccolò Machiavelli was born in Florence in 1468 in a family that was traditionally
seen as belonging to middle aristocracy. His father had been a public servant, a sort of
lawyer in the Republic of Florence, and his mother was a housewife. His older brother
allegedly disappointed his family because of his mediocrity, so all hopes turned towards
young Niccolò: his mother would have wanted him to become a clergyman, while his
father would have preferred him to be a lawyer as well.
Not many details are known about his childhood and adolescence. He seems to have
followed the courses of an appreciated grammar school and he learned Latin; as a matter
of fact, knowing Latin was essential for becoming a public servant in the Florentine

3|Page
Republic, for it was the cultural language, but also the official language of
administration.
Machiavelli’s life became more relevant after the year 1498, when, although barely 29,
he managed to secure an important job with the help of a friend who held a position of
authority in the first chancellery of the Republic. Therefore, Niccolò successfully
occupied the position of chief of the second chancellery, an office which he would keep
for 14 years, until the advent of the de Medici family, which accused him of conspiring
and had him removed from his office. This incident nearly cost Machiavelli his life, but
fortunately, he was released and forced to withdraw to his small property Albergarccio,
near San Casciano. It is there that he wrote The Prince, in just a few brief months, while
taking a break from writing another book which critics view as his most notable one
when it comes to political research: Discorsi sopra prima deca di Tito
Livio (Discourses On the First Decade of Titus Livius or, most commonly known
as Discourses on Livy). In this great book about the Roman historian, Machiavelli
proves his worth as a historian and political scholar; “great reader of ancient works”,
he was called by Charles Benoist, and he deserves this title.
It is relevant to mention that during his office years (1498-1512), Machiavelli had many
diplomatic relations with other Italian cities, as well as with a number of European
courts or chancelleries: France, Germany, Spain, etc. His reports during these
diplomatic missions once again highlight his abilities as a careful observer of political
figures, events and inside stories, as well as his extraordinary literary talent.
Machiavelli’s intellectual preoccupations reveal his Renaissance-like spirit, as that was
the prevalent direction of the day; thus, Machiavelli was a political scholar, a public
servant, a diplomat, a negotiator, a military strategist and a writer. His most famous
work, which actually brought him renown, was De Principatibus, a short political treaty
that would create such strong reactions, both positive and negative, both from political
scholars and from people who have never actually read much politics at all.
In the Romanian culture, Mihai Eminescu and Ion Luca Caragiale were counted as his
admirers. The former actually translated fragments of The Prince, while the latter
admitted that Machiavelli had a powerful influence on his work.

4|Page
2. MACHIAVELLI’S INTENTIONS
When it comes to understanding Machiavelli’s intentions for writing De
Principatibus, posterity found itself involved in yet another heated debate. According
to some exegetes, Machiavelli must have elaborated this text with the sole purpose of
gaining de Medici’s goodwill, and thus with the intent of winning back the job that he
had lost once the infamous family seized the power.For fellow Italians of the
20th century, historians or simple patriots of no academic claim, Machiavelli’s purpose
is explicitly stated in the title of the last chapter: An Exhortation to Liberate Italy from
the Barbarians, which indicates that he had been animated by patriotic feelings and
intentions. In this view, he was most likely seeking to compile a guide for the person
that would possess the qualities and the capacity to unite Italy and to free it from the
foreign conquerors – from the barbarians, as he calls them. Other scholars, such as
Ernest Cassirer, shared the opinion that Machiavelli had had a much larger audience in
mind: he was addressing himself to the world and the world took notice of him.
It seems difficult, if not impossible, to know beyond a shadow of a doubt which
are an author’s true intentions, unless he cares to enlighten us himself. Fortunately, in
Machiavelli’s case, we discover some revelatory passages in his political writings and
in his personal correspondence.
We shall start by taking a close look at some fragments of correspondence
between Machiavelli and his trusted friend, Francesco Vettori. A sharp contrast
dominated their situation at the time when these letters were exchanged. Machiavelli
had been removed from the headship of the second chancellery of the Florentine
Republic and was living a secluded life in San Casciano; he was now facing poverty,
exclusion, oblivion and virtual house arrest, while Vettori was holding the position of
Ambassador of the Republic of Florence at Rome, and had ample dealings with the
Pope himself. A particularly interesting letter, dated December 10, 1513 (thus,
immediately after The Prince was finished) depicts Machiavelli’s daily activities, his
expectations and inner struggles in very eloquent terms. Moreover, the fragment we are
about to look at encapsulates a declaration of his intention and a portrayal of his method,
which will be later explained in explicit terms in chapter XV of De Principatibus. His
tone is overtly frank, propensity which Machiavelli displayed until the end of his life
and which brought about many unjust accusations; yet one cannot but feel the weight
and the sadness of such an honest confession:

5|Page
“When evening comes, I return home and I step in my study; I leave my
daily garments on the threshold, for they are stained with mud and clay,
and I drape myself in kingly, courtly robes. Now that I’m adequately
dressed for the occasion, I step in the ancient sanctuaries of people of
old; being lovingly welcomed by them, I fill up on nourishment that was
made for me solum and for which I was born. I am not ashamed to
converse with them and ask them the causes of their deeds, and they, in
their generosity, answer my questions; for four hours I feel no boredom,
I forget all sorrow, I don’t fear poverty, and death isn’t frightening
anymore […]. And, since Dante says that keeping what you have
understood is not science, I wrote down what I had stored in my mind
during these long conversations with them and I have put together a
booklet, De Principatibus, in which, as much as can, I go to length in
thinking about these things and I discuss about what a principality is,
about the different types, about how to secure one and the reasons why
they are lost. And if you ever enjoyed some of the trifles I wrote, this
writing should not be disagreeable to you. To a prince, and especially to
a new prince, it should be useful… […] I would wish that these Medici
gentlemen started using me again, even if I had to carry rocks at first; if,
later on, I didn’t manage to win their goodwill, I’d be terribly upset with
myself; if this booklet of mine were read, it will be obvious that I have
not wasted the fifteen years I spent learning the art of governing; and
everyone should desire to make use of someone who has gained their
experience at someone else’s expense. As for my honesty, no one should
question it, for I have always kept my word, and it would not be the time
to start breaking it now.”
Out of this long passage taken from the letter to Vettori, we can deduce relatively easily
which were Machiavelli’s intentions and expectations when he decided to write The
Prince, and, furthermore, which was, in fact, the method he used. We say intentions,
for he had at least two in mind when he took a break from writing Discorsi, in order to
dedicate himself to The Prince. The first one, the more immediate, was his craving to
return to the former employment, or to any other political position, irrespective of the
sacrifices that would be required of him. He saw himself as destined to such a position
and his fourteen years of experience, coupled with his attested professionalism

6|Page
represented strong arguments for his cause. The second goal, although more remote,
was by no means less important: “the liberation of Italy from the hands of the
Barbarians” – he dedicates the last chapter to this objective. The Italy of Machiavelli’s
time was divided into a multitude of small republics, states or principalities, which were
constantly engaging each other in military combat; useless to say that this made them
vulnerable, an easy prey for the great powers that dominated Europe at that time: the
Kingdom of France, the Kingdom of Spain and the German Empire.
Machiavelli would have greatly desired for a ruler to emerge, one who would be bold
and determined, one who would free Italy and unite the principalities under one banner.
Some critics argue that this was, in fact, his greatest wish. For a period of time, it
became apparent to Machiavelli that this prince was none other than Cesare Borgia,
whom he knew personally, having met him during the time when Machiavelli was
commissioned by the Counsel of the Ten, the most important political institution of the
Florentine Republic. Cesare was the son of Pope Alexander Borgia, and had been
appointed head of the pontiff’s army by his father.
What can be said of the third interpretation, namely that Machiavelli simply wanted to
write for anybody interested in learning about politics? A strong argument for this view
is found at the beginning of chapter XV, where he declares that he wants to write “useful
things for those who understand them”. So, who was he thinking of? Obviously, we do
not have an explicit answer; however, it would not be difficult to conjecture it. He could
share his great love and passion for politics with those who dealt with this field: political
figures and state leaders, for they had the background knowledge to understand his
claims. His declared intention was to draft methods of acquiring and securing a state
and to describe how it can be lost; therefore, he was addressing himself to political
leaders.
Others believed that Machiavelli addressed himself to anyone interested in politics,
even the proletariat, in which Antonio Gramsci, a socialist Italian scholar, identified the
“modern prince”. After all, the fate of a text is often different from the author’s original
intentions. As for Machiavelli, his letters and his correspondence reveal a man
interested firstly in regaining his status as a public servant; secondly in the liberation of
Italy from the hands of the barbarians; and thirdly in the formulation of a political lesson
that was the product of his personal experience coupled with the extensive reading of
ancient historians – the two major sources that have underpinned his reflection.

7|Page
What Adam Smith’s book The Wealth of Nations was for political economy, we can
confidently say that The Prince constitutes for political thought, namely a founding
seminal work, a political paradigm, if we are to accept that this concept, consecrated by
Tomas S. Kuhn in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, deserves to be extended to
the sphere of humanities. The publication of this relatively short work, marked a radical
change in the perception of politics, power, state, political figures and in the
understanding of their purposes; furthermore, it imposed ipso facto a new method of
political research and analysis. This new perception and interpretation of politics
dominated with authority the modern era, making Machiavelli an unavoidable reference
point in the history of political science and philosophy.
As for his Discourses, Machiavelli offers an explanation, in the introduction to the first
book, after having drawn his readers’ attention to the importance of possessing
historical knowledge, which would enable people to learn important lessons about
practical and political life. Unfortunately, many ignore to do so, therefore, he states:
“[…] willing to set straight this wrong judgement, I thought it would be
good to write some things about those books belonging to Titus Livius,
which escaped the rigour of time, things which I, being aware of both
old and new times, believe to be important in order to understand them
better; thus, so that those who read these lines be able to truly make the
most of having studied history.”
Consequently, if the aim of The Prince was to offer a practical guide to those who
dabbled in politics, writing about Titus Livy, a well known historian of ancient Rome,
was meant as a warning sign about the importance of knowing history for life in general
and political life in particular.

3. MACHIAVELLI’S PHILOSOPHY:

This issue is under controversy, similarly to the very personality and work of the author
of The Prince. Some critics will think that Machiavelli was a practical spirit, a man
interested exclusively in the fate of his country, an analyst of the contemporary political
scene in Italy, displaying a refractory attitude towards any philosophical speculation.
Machiavelli himself seems to confirm such a viewpoint when, at the beginning of
chapter XV of The Prince, he openly expresses his preference for the concrete truth of
facts, to the detriment of “mere fancy” of any philosophical speculation. Therefore,

8|Page
considering a system of philosophical thought or a philosophy in the systematic
conception is out of the question.

Nevertheless, a careful look on the entire Machiavellian work will unveil the existence
of a vision about the universe, man and history, which, in a broad understanding, could
be assimilated to philosophy. In fact, a careful study of philosophical thought would
unveil the fact that any political system of thought has its premises either in a view
about the world (cosmology) or in a view about history or mankind. With Machiavelli,
we encounter all of these, to different degrees. Of course, Machiavelli never manifested
the intention to elaborate a philosophical system or doctrine. His philosophy is rather
implicit, disseminated in his work and more often than not dissimulated behind some
affirmations which seem to discourage and disqualify any speculative attempts to
philosophise. However, paradoxically, Machiavelli’s conception is built on a certain
view about the universe, history and mankind.
Machiavelli has adopted the understanding according to which there is no real change
in the universe. Or rather, as a well-known quote from the biblical book Ecclesiastes,
by the wise king Solomon goes: “There is nothing new under the sun”.
Machiavelli deems that the universe remains the same and that there are no fundamental
changes within. Furthermore, he extends this view on history and human understanding.
History is a continual repetition of what has already happened and people remain
basically unchanged, no matter what. It is true, however, that Machiavelli considers fate
as responsible for half of the actions that happen in history, the other half being the
product of human endeavour. One could therefore think that people – and especially
political people, princes, state leaders – are free to fashion history. However, despite
any amount of freedom a man could have, and especially the state leader, the one who
possesses that overwhelming energy that Machiavelli calls virtu (according to the
Roman understanding of the word), this man will never succeed in changing anything
essential about history or the universe.
“People can help fate, but they cannot oppose it”, we read in the Discourses. In fact,
Machiavelli states: “fate blinds people, when it does not want that they oppose its plans”
(Discourses II, 29). In the world, the proportion between good and evil stays
unchanged. History keeps repeating itself again and again, even though people are born
and die, their nature does not change. “No matter how you choose them, people remain
evil”. This is the view on which Machiavelli builds his understanding of politics. In
other words, in order to master the evil that resides in the unchanging human nature,

9|Page
we need an even greater evil, embodied in the prince, the state leader. We could call
this situation “the remedy of evil through evil”, using a metaphor that belongs to Jean
Starobinski. This is the premise that underlies the Machiavellian doctrine about politics,
state and power. As men are evil, people of goodwill would stand no chance as long as
others are not men of goodwill as well. The famous ethics of power draws its roots from
this pessimistic view on human nature.
Is this remark born of general observation, personal experience or simply prejudice? It
would probably be a bit of everything. People that he came in contact with must have
revealed to him the truth which was apparent to the Apostle Paul when he declared that
“I want to do good, but evil is glued to me”. Contrary to Machiavelli though,
Christianity affirms that man can be changed, restored; in truth, the Christian doctrine
advocates bringing remedy to evil by doing good. Machiavelli delimits himself in this
respect not only from Christian thought, but also from the liberal thinking to which
some critics, such P. Manent, will try to affiliate him. In the liberal view, man is a
mixture of good and evil. As Jean Baechler said, in the article dedicated to liberalism
in the Encyclopaedia Universalis: “Man is an angel of light and a demon…” For
Machiavelli, though, man will always remain evil, as his nature cannot be changed.
This is, in essence, the philosophy which has guided Machiavelli. Gramsci believes that
any human has a philosophy, by the simple fact that he uses language which is in
essence an abstract means of communication. But when it comes to Machiavelli, he is
not a philosopher in only the general way that Gramsci proposed; nor is he a philosopher
in the consecrated sense of the word. Rather, despite his claimed rejection of
speculation, Machiavelli allows to be guided by life experience which is to say that he
incorporates a certain vision on life and universe, history and mankind which plays a
more important role in the development of his political theories than had previously
been believed.

4. MACHIAVELLI – THE FATHER OF MODERN POLITICAL SCIENCE

“Just as Galileo’s dynamics founded modern physics, Machiavelli laid the foundations
of a new political science”2, said Ernst Cassirer, the renown author of The Myth of the
State. What would enable us to consider Machiavelli as the founder of a new political
science? And what does it mean, in fact, to establish a new science? According to a

2
Ernst CASSIRER, Mitul Statului, Institul European, Iaşi, 2001, p. 170.
10 | P a g e
classic paradigm – illustrated in the majority of traditional textbooks – to establish a
discipline would primarily mean four things:

1. The clear delimitation of a distinct field/area of competence, research and


investigation – thus, of the object of the new discipline; this presupposes
establishing which phenomena belong to it;
2. The identification of the method through which that field, once circumscribed,
can be investigated and analysed;
3. The identification (the discovery) of the inner working of these phenomena;
4. The process of establishing that particular discipline into a larger system of
knowledge such as, in our case, humanities.

Did Machiavelli do all these things? It is obvious that a “yes or no” answer to such a
question would be impossible. True enough, Machiavelli has never initiated formal
proceedings to establish a political science; The Prince does not constitute an
epistemological enterprise. Nevertheless, Machiavelli’s work can be considered as one
of the founding blocks, just as Adam Smith’s The Wealth of Nations was seen as the
groundwork of political economy, despite its lack of epistemological content.
Similarly to Adam Smith, Machiavelli was not a theoretician or a science philosopher;
such endeavours were foreign to him. However, his approach led, in later centuries, to
a certain epistemological and methodological understanding of what the very field of
political science was and the type of method employed to investigate and analyse this
field. But perhaps the most important step was made when he postulated the autonomy
of politics in relation to other spheres of human manifestation, such as religion and
morality, action which numerous experts later deemed as a capital action for the
investigation and understanding of what was specific for political science. Furthermore,
by presenting politics in close correlation with the necessity to understand human nature
and psychology, Machiavelli opened a way for later generations to make connections
between the proper political science and other disciplines such as anthropology,
psychology, etc. In fact, it was agreed upon that one could not truly study politics
without incorporating the study of disciplines dealing with human nature.

11 | P a g e
4.1. The Object of Political Study

Until Machiavelli, the research regarding politics aimed to identify the best social and
political order (thus, in Antiquity, Plato was looking for the perfect, ideal city, and
Aristotle for the desired, preferable city; in the Middle Ages, thinkers were seeking the
Christian Republic, RespublicaChristiana, based on biblical principles). In his
work The Republic, Plato’s concern was to discover and describe the ideal, perfect city,
while Aristotle took another approach, distancing himself from his mentor. He
performed a literal empirical research on political regimes existing in Ancient Greece,
hoping to define the traits of the desirable city, ruled by middle aristocracy and capable
of satisfying its needs fully, without outside connections or help.

As for the theologians-philosophers of the Middle Ages, they were interested in


identifying the Respublica Christiana, founded and based on biblical principles. Even
Dante, who, according to some historians, made the transition from the Middle Ages to
modern times, was still preoccupied in identifying that universal monarchy, that utopia,
which would govern the entire world.
Machiavelli drastically alters these research avenues. As he explicitly and
bluntly declares in the beginning of chapter XV of The Prince, he is not even remotely
interested in those “republics and principalities which no one ever saw and no one ever
knew they existed in the real world”.3 It appears that the author of The Prince deems
more appropriate to seek the truth of concrete facts than mere fancy. What interests
Machiavelli in fact is the way in which political power can be seized and through it, the
methods that should be used to preserve and strengthen the state. But be warned, both
political power and the state are perceived as having a strong bond with the political
ruler, his personality and his abilities.
Accordingly, one can easily infer what constitutes the object of political science. In fact,
there are three capital aspects which define the object of this discipline: Power, State
and Political Figure (the state ruler, especially). We shall expound on these three themes
in order to understand what Machiavelli’s reflection about them consisted of.
 Power – Machiavelli did not use the term power in a formal sense, therefore we will
never find a definition of it. Nevertheless, he understood the nature and the intricate
workings of power. He perceived it as a specific human phenomenon, as a living
relationship, a psychological one. To analyse power meant to understand people as

3
Niccolò MACHIAVELLI, Principele, (in vol. Mǎştile puterii, Editura Institutului European, 1997), p. 92.
12 | P a g e
they are, and their way of relating, without idealising them. “In truth,” says
Machiavelli, “there is such a major difference between how people live and the way
they should live, that he who leaves aside what is for what it should be, sooner finds
out how people perish than how they succeed”.
 State – Machiavelli is the first one to have made the state the favourite object of
political research. According to Sartori, “Machiavelli was the first to have
objectified the State as an impersonal entity and has used the modern political
denotations of the term – even though in an incidental, isolated way. In
Machiavelli’s time, political forms were still known under the generic name
of regnum and civitas (if they were republics)”.
In a footnote for chapter 3, Sartori made new remarks about the idea of State as seen by
Machiavelli. “Until Machiavelli, the term of ‘state’ generally meant status, social
position. The term describes a political entity for the first time in the first line of The
Prince: ‘All states and powers which have exercised or are exercising control over
individuals are either republics, either principalities’. The new meaning appears again
in this passage: ‘When the Roano Cardinal said that Italians do not understand war, I
answered that the French do not understand the State.’4 Nevertheless, both in
the Discourses and in the Florentine Histories, Machiavelli used the term of ‘state’ in
a medieval sense. He even made a distinction between two types of state: the
principality (which was the most common form of government during his time) in The
Prince, and the republic in Discourses on the First Decade of Titus Livy.”
 The Political Figure (the political ruler, the one who holds the power and exercises
it): the author of The Prince has paid much attention to this character, to such an
extent that he often gives the impression that power, in its true, living sense, is
embodied by the ruler, especially in the case of the principality. As a matter of fact,
the state seems to identify itself with the person who is in charge of it. As Sartori
would remark: “Machiavelli observed a different state of things, in which the
political endeavour seemed to coincide with the nature of its prince […] in those
times, politics and the prince were synonymous”.
Therefore, in Machiavelli’s view, what determined the destiny of a state, of a
principality were two main things: Fortuna (Luck, Fate) and the prince’s abilities.
Consequently, political Power, the State and the Political Figure are the three major
aspects around which the field of political research is defined. Following in his

4
Giovanni SARTORI, Teoria democraţiei reinterpretatǎ, Polirom, Iaşi, 1999, p. 72
13 | P a g e
footsteps, later researchers would equate the object of political science either with
political power or with the state.

4.2. The Method of Political Science

If regarding the object of political science Machiavelli leaves us to discover the state of
the things without making clear-cut remarks, he is much more straightforward about
the method. In some passages, Machiavelli makes direct reference to the method used
in political research. Firstly, in chapter XV of The Prince, where we see the
“phenomenological” perspective of his political analysis, we notice his concern for
empiric facts, that verita effetualle dela cosa, in direct opposition to any speculation of
utopia. It could be argued that, from this point of view, Machiavelli applied the
empirical or inductive method, which had been previously applied by Aristotle
in Politics, and which would later on be formulated by Francis Bacon.

Other relevant texts about method are found in the Discourses, especially those
passages that underline the importance of knowing the past in order to understand the
present; in other words, he draws our attention to the vital necessity of historical
knowledge for understanding the present. Such a text can be found, for example, in the
Preamble of Book 1 of his discourses.
Knowing the past has relevance not only for theoretical awareness but also for practical
applications. Furthermore, knowing the past helps one anticipate the future. Machiavelli
does not hesitate to lament the fact that even political people and analysts ignore the
past.
Machiavelli did not invent a new method, or, better said, he invented one starting from
means and methods already in use. In fact, he blended the psychologist’s observation
skills with the effort of knowing the past and with the talent of the writer who
communicates with ease. And he did this better than philosophers could do. By
analysing facts, events, circumstances and people of the past, and by making use of
analogy, Machiavelli understood better than the majority of philosophers what exactly
Politics, the State and the Political Figure were. Moreover, he expressed this
understanding in a highly accessible and intelligible style. These qualities represented
the strongest point but also his weakest, as many could approach his text and criticise
it.
However, Machiavelli had only one thing in mind: to present the truth of the matter and
to communicate useful things for the benefit of those capable of grasping them. Charles
14 | P a g e
Benoist calls him “a great reader of ancient things and a great observer of modern
things”. This quote catches Machiavelli’s method really well. In rigorous terms, this
method is a combination – following a unique recipe – between observation (of facts,
events, circumstances, people), analogy (past and present), psychological intuition, all
of these enhanced by the capacity to express clearly and simply what others were trying
to say in sophisticated, obscure, philosophical ways. That is why Machiavelli’s method
and ideas could be easily grasped not only by political thinkers but also by political
figures in general who did not hesitate to take on his ideas and advice and to attempt to
put them into practice in new situations and circumstances.

4.3. The Autonomy of Politics

One of Machiavelli’s major contributions consists in what we could call the autonomy
of politics. Machiavelli was the first author who understood politics as something
distinct, a phenomenon set apart, with specific reasoning and interests, rules and laws.
Until Machiavelli, no one has dared to make such a clear-cut distinction between
religion and morality. He is the first also to consider that politics cannot be reduced to
other activities. This step can be seen as immensely important for the establishment of
modern political science.

5. MACHIAVELLI – A POLITICAL PHENOMENOLOGIST Avant la Lettre

There are two main ways in which politics can be (and, indeed, has been) approached.
The first one is the philosophical approach, inaugurated by Plato, which tried to answer
the question: “What should politics be like?” The other perspective, the
phenomenological one, tries to understand and present politics as it really is. What is
political phenomenology and why can Machiavelli be thought of as its founder?

Etymologically, the term “phenomenology” refers to the study of phenomena; therefore


it means “the science of phenomena”. Mutatis mutandis, political phenomenology
would study political phenomena. Machiavelli ignored this term, therefore he never
used it; this is because was coined only in 1764 by the German mathematician and
philosopher Johannes Lambert, in a work called Neus Organonum (4 volumes). The
term then has grown to have a brilliant ‘career’ in modern and postmodern philosophy,
being employed by renown philosophers such as Kant, Fichte, Hegel (modern times),
Heidegger, Husserl, Sartre (during the 20th century). In the past century Husserl was the

15 | P a g e
phenomenologist par excellence. His name is associated with the creation of
phenomenological method and what is known as “transcendental phenomenology”.
It is self evident that Machiavelli has very little to do with the way the above
mentioned authors understood phenomenology. However, there exists in Husserl’s
writing, a principle which Machiavelli illustrated in The Prince: “It is not from
philosophers, but from deeds and actual problems that the impulse for research should
start”.5
Machiavelli illustrated this point of view, especially in The Prince, where he declares
himself against all speculations and fancies in favour of the verita effetuale della
cosa. Nevertheless, the distinction between his method and that of Husserl is immense.
Machiavelli has observation of real life, events and people as his starting point, while
Husserl demands that the real world be suspended, or practically annihilated.
Machiavelli’s approach is closer to the etymological meaning of the term, that of
phenomenology as the study of phenomena. The best way to express his approach
remains verita effetuale della cosa.
Machiavelli had everything going for him that would enable him to be considered a
political phenomenologist avant la lettre. Firstly, he was an excellent observer of facts,
events, political circumstances and people in general (either in political power or not).
Secondly, he was intimately connected with the historical past and endowed with an
acute sense of history (which is exactly what Charles Benoist perceived when he called
him “a great reader of old things and a great observer of modern things”). Thirdly, he
was a very bright psychologist, capable of understanding and guessing what lay behind
the political rulers’ behaviour and actions. Fourthly he was a gifted writer, having an
ease for translating his observation in terms that were accessible. He had been equipped
by the Creator with the capacity of observing, understanding and describing things
which might have gone unnoticed by others. Both The Prince and the Discourses on
the First Decade of Titus Livy represent an incontestable illustration of this
extraordinary capacity.

5
Edmund HUSSERL, Filozofia ca ştiinţǎ riguroasǎ, Editura Paideia, Bucureşti, 1994, p. 73.
16 | P a g e
6. THE NATURE AND THE “LAWS” OF POWER

The phenomenologist’s task does not end at observing and describing events,
circumstances, people or the historical past. A true phenomenologist must try and be
capable to grasp what lies behind all these. He also must be capable of deciphering, in
the end, their essence, the essence of politics, or as Julien Freund says, the nature and
the “laws” of power. This is something that Machiavelli managed to achieve, unlike
any other scholar before him.

It is worth noticing that he was the first to understand power as an essential human
phenomenon because it depends on the psychology, behaviour, interests and actions
specific to people. Fate has its place in the equation of power, but daring people can
force destiny’s hand to achieve their goals.
At the same time, if we follow Machiavelli’s thought closely, we shall surmise that
power is a special phenomenon, an out of the ordinary relation, based on the fact that
some give orders (dispositions) and others hear and execute them. “Obedience is the
real school of politics”, said Aristotle, opinion which was later on adopted as well.
Whoever understands the reason why people obey and submit themselves has a great
understanding of the mystery of power.
Machiavelli, however, disagreed with this view and claimed that the real mystery of
power is hidden in the capacity of the leader to impose himself before the crowd, by
any necessary means. Power resides thus in manipulating people and playing games
with their minds. Cesare Borgia, the Duke of Valentino, was the real man of power, and
Machiavelli describes him as being “so quick to anger and, at the same time, so capable,
and he knew how one can win people or how to destroy them”.6
Political Power was thus a psychological relation, and those who had it exerted, by any
possible means, an influence on the minds and behaviour of others until the latter would
do whatever the former wanted. The power relation was tense, however, for both sides
were suspicious of each other and were ready to clash, despite the apparent calmness.
“In any republic”, noticed Machiavelli, “there are two parties: the party of the strong
and that of the people; all laws favouring freedom are born out of their
opposition”.7 Machiavelli placed a stronger accent on the selfish nature of Power, rather
than on its social side.

6
See Mǎştile puterii, p. 67.
7
Discorsi, I, 4.
17 | P a g e
Perhaps Machiavelli’s greatest discovery and contribution in political phenomenology
consisted in the identification and description of the “laws” of Power (where “laws”
stand for the relatively stable tendencies manifested in its behaviour and actions).
 The first “law” is that of self-preservation. Power represents a living organism, a
lively body which, once brought into being, acts as any living body would do. And
as we know, the law of living organisms is self-preservation;
 The second law is that of growth. Any power has the tendency to grow. This was a
natural course in Machiavelli’s view; as such, he did not try to come up with ways
to slow it down. At the opposite spectrum, liberal thinkers were exceptionally
preoccupied with how to limit power and the practical ways to achieve this goal.
 The third law is that of concealment or appearance. Machiavelli was particularly
interested in how to keep up appearances. In chapter XVIII, entitled “How a Prince
Should Respect His Word”, he dealt with this aspect of concealing truth. Power is
shrewd; and a political man must conceal his shrewdness so that, under the
impression of being honest, he must ready himself to be exactly that kind of person
whom people expected him to be. Appearances are of major importance in politics.
“But you must know how to hide your fox-like nature in different ways, to pretend
and never expose yourself, because people are so naïve and they submit so easily to
present needs so that the one who cheats will always find someone willing to be
cheated.” In Machiavelli’s view, a prince must not necessarily have all the traits that
people see in him or expect of him, but it is absolutely necessary to appear as though
he were in possession of them. Therefore, a prince must “seem charitable, true to
his word, kind, having integrity and being religious and actually be that”.
 The fourth law of is that of corruption. Aristotle foresaw and debated it
in Politics, raising the alarm on its effects. Later on, the English historian Lord
Acton expressed it bluntly: “Power corrupts; absolute power corrupts absolutely”.
Machiavelli sees corruption as a sort of fatality: “There are no laws, no state
organization to slow corruption down!”8 And even if people are not corrupt, power
will corrupt them inevitably. Therefore, “it is not sufficient that the people are not
corrupt, for, in a short while, an absolute authority will corrupt them, making friends
and allies”.9 Political power holds the germ of corruption; consequently, sooner or
later, the whole society will be contaminated by this malady, with all the

8
Discorsi, I, 18.
9
Discorsi, I, 33.
18 | P a g e
consequences which this entails. A rich testimony of political history attests to the
fact that power not only is corruptible, but it corrupts the people.
 Finally, the fifth law, which Machiavelli sensed and illustrated (or legitimised),
even though he did not explicitly name it, is the Law of the State Reason. Louis XIV
would later consider it as the first law of politics, which suited his preference for
absolutism.
About this concept (raggione di stato), introduced by Jean Bottero and discussed by
one of Machiavelli’s contemporaries, the historian Guicciardini, it can be said that it
places the state above the individuals and the selfishness of power above the interests
of the few. The state is always right and its actions are always justified, irrespective of
the consequences it has on individuals. The founding premise is that the state is
everybody’s exponent, or at least, that of the majority; thus, its actions will always be
more important than individual actions. The “laws” of power have motivations in the
human nature and psychology, which are related to the fact that political power is not a
concept, an abstract notion, but a living reality, a relation. When power is made abstract,
it hides its true face and conceals the way to the identification of its laws. Of course,
we must not perceive these laws of power as inexorable tendencies, some that cannot
be controlled, tempered down, calmed. The laws of power are not the same as the laws
of nature, but this does not mean that we can ignore their presence, action and
consequences. In Machiavelli’s view strong people, especially those gifted with virtue,
can control even Destiny, if they are determined enough to do it. Political power being
a human phenomenon, the laws of power always act through people.

7. MACHIAVELLI AND THE POLITICAL MACHIAVELLIANISM

Although its name was inspired by the Italian scholar, Machiavellianism as a political
attitude and phenomenon does not start and end with the one who lent his name to the
concept. As a matter of fact, the Italian thinker inspired the word and promoted a type
of Machiavellianism, but the phenomenon had long preceded him. Charles Benoist
considered that it would continue to do so after Machiavelli’s death in a concept that is
called “perpetual Machiavellianism”10, for it is tightly connected to the nature of human
life, society and history. The same author stated that “there are different types of

10
Charles BENOIST, Le Machiavélisme, tome III, Plon, Paris, 1936, p. 4.
19 | P a g e
Machiavellianism: true versus false, initiated by Machiavelli himself versus stemmed
from his disciples or his enemies”.11

Machiavellianism isn’t present only in politics; it invades other spheres of human life
too. Benoist, quoting various authors in the third volume of his work Le Machiavélisme,
includes a pietistic Machiavellianism, a literary one, a theological one, a juridical one,
etc. Tomassini considers that Ovid’s The Art of Loving could have represented an erotic
Machiavellianism, while Balzac saw a marital one. D’Alembert evokes the spectre of a
historical Machiavellianism, “which is a manner of practising the past”. The essence of
political Machiavellianism is aptly summarised in the maxim: “the ends justifies the
means”, or as Benoist says: “Qui veut la fin veut les moyens”. Barthélemy-Saint-
Hilaire, in the well-known Dictionary of Politics, under the coordination of Maurice
Block, defines Machiavellianism as “the sacrificing of all principles in the name of
interest; the violation of all moral laws to success”.
Machiavellianism does not constitute a doctrine to be applied; rather, it is an
ideological-spiritual reflex of a social-political society which deliberately ignores
morality and for which only the end result is significant, irrespective of the means that
were employed to reach that end. In fact, there exists also a theoretical
Machiavellianism, present in different political or philosophical doctrines: (that of
Nietzsche, Spengler, etc.)
J. Burham includes Dante, Machiavelli, Mosea, Sorel, Michels, and Pareto among the
theorists of Machiavellianism; however, the list remains open. The American author,
follower of the technocratic alternative, appreciates their open spirit and the sincerity
with which they approach issues. “The Machiavellians are the only to have spoken the
whole truth about power. Other authors have told us the truth only about groups other
than those on behalf of whom they speak. They present us with all the facts: the primary
practical purpose for all leaders consists of serving their own interest, of maintaining
their own powers and privileges. No exception! No theory, no promise, no goodwill,
no religion, not even morality will slow power down”.12
Far more grave and dangerous than theoretical Machiavellianism is the practical one,
materialised in the actual discrepancy between the declared purpose of political activity

11
Ibidem (tome I, Plon, Paris, 1907, ed. III), p. 2.
12
James BURNHAM, The Machiavellians, Defenders of Truth, Gateway Editions, Washington, 1987, p.
246.
20 | P a g e
and the means that are employed to reach it, which is revelatory of the politicians’
duplicity and (more or less acknowledged) immorality.
This practical Machiavellianism reached its pinnacle during fascist and totalitarian
regimes – although its theoretical side was rejected, making this doctrine belong to
“political realism”. Those who hold this view adopt theses of traditional
Machiavellianism, such as the state as a purpose in itself, the pre-eminence of state
reason, the separation between politics and morality (the political a-morality),
morality’s inefficiency, the imperfection of human nature, etc. They do this without
having critically examined the original Machiavellian precepts and they go even further
by adding new theses, such as the need to understand politics as a struggle for power,
and the appreciation of conflict in order to obtain supremacy.
In the view of political realists, the primary indicator in the sphere of international
relations is the concept of interest, defined in relation to power. This idea is strongly
connected to the very core of politics and it is not affected by circumstances, or at least
not in a significant way. According to H. Morgenthau, the main theoretician of this
orientation, morality and politics should be considered separately, as each has its own
standard. Ethics judges action abstractly, according to the degree of conformity with
the moral law, while politics looks at an action through its consequences. Therefore,
the moralist asks: “Is politics in concordance with moral principles?” while political
realists ask a question that is altogether different: “How can this politics affect the
power of the nation? Or, according to different scenarios, the power of the government,
congress, party, etc.?”13
It is not difficult to detect the similarities between political realism and “classical”
Machiavellianism concerning both the way in which they address problems and their
methodology. The latter is defined by Morgenthau as “the process of observing facts
and conferring a meaning according to reason”, where, naturally, reason is equated with
political realism.
The essential criterion of judging political actions consists in the measure of success.
For “what is important to know,” explains the American author, “if we want to
understand external politics, are not mainly the motives of a state man, but his ability
to understand the essential elements of external policy, as well as his political capacity
to transpose what he has learned into a successful political action”. The self-evident

13
Hans MORGENTHAU, Politics among Nations, in Hoffman, S., Contemporary Theory in International
Relations, St. Martin, New York, 1965.
21 | P a g e
consequence is that “morality judges the moral quality of motivation, while political
theory judges the political qualities of the intellect, reason and action. A policy that
looks down on the role of force in the name of moral values and commandments is
condemned, in the vision of political realists, to failure”.14
Postulating the autonomous nature of politics, attempting to separate this from other
spheres of human activity, and seeking to liberate political action from moral
censorship, all these are false theses. They ignore the holistic character, the integrated
system of society and, as well, the need to see the human being as a unitary entity. From
a practical and strategic point of view, there is room for using any means in order to
achieve one end: efficiency. Or, under the circumstances in which nowadays political
powers have the means to bring about the annihilation of the entire human civilisation,
an attitude such as the one described above will bring about inacceptable risks.

8. MACHIAVELLI’S ACTUALITY: CONTRIBUTION TO THE


DEVELOPMENT OF MODERN POLITICAL SCIENCE

Machiavelli’s work has constituted the object of research and analysis from two
relatively opposite perspectives: the historical one and the moral one. The former sees
Machiavelli as “truly a man of his time” (A. Gramsci), excessively preoccupied by the
problem of unifying Italy. The latter harshly judges him on the grounds that he is amoral
and that he promotes cynicism and cruelty. Between the two, there is another
perspective, the scientific one. In its view, Machiavelli has in mind the creation of a
positive political science. Andrei Otetea, a Romanian historian, remarked: “Niccolò
Machiavelli built a system that summarises the experience and the political thinking of
his time through sheer observation and practice, as well as through studying Titus
Livy”.15

Historical research comes to confirm Antonio Gramsci’s view that Machiavelli had
been a man of his time. He wrote: “We need to consider Machiavelli as a necessary

14 Ibidem. In his book, The Theory of Democracy, Giovanni Sartori shows that, among the things that

differentiate the realistic and the legalistic view on politics, it is the use of power that makes a capital

difference: for the latter, force is kept as a last resort, whereas for the former, it is prima ratio (Giovanni

Sartori, op. cit., p. 30).

15
Andrei OŢETEA, Scrieri istorice alese, Dacia, Cluj, 1980, p. 19.
22 | P a g e
expression of his time, tightly connected to the conditions and demands of his time,
which resulted
1. from the internal struggles of Florence and from the special structure of the state,
which could not rid itself of the archaic remains of a feudalism that had become a
nuisance;
2. from the struggle between Italian states for a balance within the Italian territory,
balance that was prevented by the Pope’s existence, by municipal organisation and
not a territorial one;
3. from the struggles between Italian states for European balance; thus from the
contradictions between the need for an internal, Italian balance and the demands of
European states that were competing for hegemony”.16
“Through Machiavelli, as it was said, political science starts out on a new path, with
thoroughly new perspectives”.17 Despite his declarations about the interest in the verita
effetuale della cosa, Machiavelli thought under the speciae aeternitatis. His conception
had the universal as its goal and this made him a man belonging to the Renaissance,
and he left beyond a new perspective on how to judge politics.
The Romanian historian Oţetea remarked: “The Renaissance brought an understanding
about science, coupled with a new view on society and on the art of governing”. 18 He
could be easily called a modern day Aristotle. “Machiavelli’s greatest merit”, notices
Horkheimer, “is to have recognised,19 very early, the possibility of a political science
which, in his view, corresponded with the new physics and the new psychology, and
that he expressed its fundamental traits in a simple, exact way”.
Of course, Machiavelli is not original through its topic as many before him had studied
politics and had done it so brilliantly, coming up with original works. What is original
about Machiavelli’s perspective is his method of approaching the political
phenomenon: “Machiavelli invents a realistic theory of politics. He bases the very
ethical principles on the principles of politics which, in turn, rely ontologically on the
dialectic of purposes and means […] He is looking for cause and effect, believes in
experience, in the lesson of history, in actions. He discovers the psychology of people
and that which is permanent about it. He studies the universe of intent and action”.20

16
Antonio GRAMSCI, Note sul Machiavelli, Editura Politicǎ, Bucureşti, 1987, p. 19.
17
George USCǍTESCU, Proces umanismului, Editura Politicǎ, Bucureşti, 1987, p. 208.
18
Andrei OŢETEA, Scrieri istorice…cit., p. 19.
19
Theodor W. ADORNO, Max HORKHEIMER, Dialectic of Enlightenment, Allen Lane, London, 1973, p.
16.
20
George USCǍTESCU, Proces umanismului…cit., pp. 209-210.
23 | P a g e
The author of The Prince can be seen as one of the most profound political
psychologists for he grasped human nature’s negative side, its vices, dark passions and
hidden effects, reaching a deep level of scepticism, on which he built his
Machiavellianism. One thing is clear, though: “Machiavelli did not invent shrewdness,
treason or political crime. But he deduced a theoretical principle out of the political
practice, a universally valid norm and he conjured a decisive proof for the secularisation
of thinking”.21 Machiavellianism as a practical political attitude is a despicable and
dangerous phenomenon. However, it is not Machiavelli who is responsible for it.
Machiavelli made an error when he tried to separate politics and morality, and
to establish an ethics in conformity with the interests and maxims of power. He was
wrong in justifying absolute power, state reason as reason per se, and as a supreme
principle of governing. But, unveiling the intimate mechanism of power, the hidden
face of politics, without deformation and excuses, without illusions and compromise,
he forewarned people more than any creator of deforming utopias ever did. He shatters
the view that politics would pursue general good, as well as the belief in the sacred,
divine power. We could say that he humanises politics, placing it in a truer light and,
through that, he helps us adopt a more realistic attitude, in conformity with truth and
reality. Burnham said: “if people generally understood what Machiavelli had
understood about the mechanism of power, they wouldn’t still be disappointed in
accepting leadership and they would know the necessary steps to take in order to stand
up to it”.22
The observation of real political facts is Machiavelli’s prime method; however, this has
brought about the awareness that careful researching of historical truth represents an
indispensable source of knowledge as that which is essential, general, repetitive in
politics stands out as a gold nugget would. In fact, Machiavelli thought politics under a
double aspect: science and art. Political man is similar to a sculptor who shapes a
wonderful creation out of an amorphous material. Politics is creation, not just technique
and craft; it requires exceptional qualities from its leading figures who would then
model it according to their knowledge and virtues. It is no wonder then that one of the
most famous Renaissance historians, Burckhardt, believed that “out of all political
architects, Machiavelli is the greatest, without a doubt, without objection”.23

21
Andrei OŢETEA Scrieri istorice…cit., p. 19.
22
James BURNHAM, The Machiavellians…cit., p. 77.
23
Jacob BURCKHARDT, Civilizaţia Renaşterii în Italia, vol. I, Editura pentru Literaturǎ, Bucureşti, 1969,
p. 70.
24 | P a g e
We have already established that Machiavelli was read and interpreted in different
ways. Some saw The Prince as a code for tyranny and cynicism. Others, on the
contrary, saw in it a scientific work of incontestable worth, even an expression of
humanism. These two views constitute the extremes of the numerous interpretations
available. According to the ethical and political aspect, Machiavellian thought is a
polarised one, as Croce and Gramsci have pointed out. We subscribe to the view that
considers as too simplistic the attempt to analyse Machiavelli’s work according to the
triad: moral, immoral, amoral, because understanding it necessitates the use of nuances
and subtleties.
Perhaps we are not exaggerating at all when we say that, of all political thinkers,
Machiavelli has become the less redundant, as many of his intuitions, observations and
judgements still remain true. He saw politics for what it was, vice and all, schemes and
all. What we could reproach him is that he stayed within the realm of politics
exclusively, leaving aside the intersection points, the opening gates to ethical and
cultural aspects of life. That is the reason why his work seems somewhat incomplete,
although necessary. Even if we prefer Kant and his case for humanity, Machiavelli is
crucial for understanding that politics does not take into account subjective wishes and
moral reasons, for it contains its own ends and reasons.
“Machiavelli brings about a radical change in the European political thought; new
concepts emerge, new perspectives arise with the evolution of modern political
reality”.24 We must therefore admit that without his honest, blunt and realistic spirit, we
might have remained in the false paradise of illusions and utopia, without ever knowing
the true face of politics.

Men judge generally more by the eye than by the hand, for everyone can
see and few can feel. Every one sees what you appear to be, few really
know what you are.
- Niccolò di Bernardo dei Machiavelli

24
George USCǍTESCU, G., Proces umanismului…cit , pp. 220-221.
25 | P a g e
Bibliography

ADORNO, Theodor W., Max Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment, Allen Lane,


London, 1973.
ARISTOTEL, Etica Nicomahicǎ, Editura Antet, Bucureşti, 1988.
BENOIST, Charles, Le Machiavélisme, tome III, Plon, Paris, 1936.
BURCKHARDT, Jakob, Civilizaţia renaşterii în Italia, vol. I, Editura pentru
Literaturǎ, Bucureşti, 1969.
BURNHAM, James, The Machiavellians, Defenders of Truth, Gateway Editions,
Washington, 1987.
CASSIRERC, Ernst, Mitul Statului, Institutul European, Iaşi, 2001.
GRAMSCI, Antonio, Note sul Machiavelli, Editura Politicǎ, Bucureşti, 1987.
HUSSERL, Edmund, Filozofia ca ştiinţǎ riguroasǎ, Paideia, Bucureşti, 1994.
MACHIAVELLI, Niccolò, Principele, (in vol. Mǎştile puterii), Institutul European,
Iași, 1997.
MORGENTHAU, Hans, “Politics among Nations”, in Stanley
HOFFMAN, Contemporary Theory in International Relations, St. Martin, New York,
1965.
OȚETEA, Andrei, Scrieri istorice alese, Dacia, Cluj, 1980.
SARTORI, Giovanni, Teoria democraţiei reinterpretatǎ, Editura Polirom, Iaşi, 1999.
USCĂTESCU, George, Proces umanismului, Editura Politicǎ, Bucureşti, 1987.

26 | P a g e

You might also like