Epistemology PDF

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 6

Epistemology 23

Ratcliff R (1990) Connectionist models of recognition Ratcliff R and McKoon G (2000) Memory models. In:
memory: constraints imposed by learning and Tulving E and Craik FIM (eds) The Oxford Handbook of
forgetting functions. Psychological Review 97: 285±308. Memory, pp. 571±581. New York, NY: Oxford
Ratcliff R, Van Zandt T and McKoon G (1995) Process University Press.
dissociation, single-process theories, and recognition Rolls ET and Treves A (1998) Neural Networks and Brain
memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 124: Function. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
352±374.

Epistemology Intermediate article


Joseph Cruz, Williams College, Williamstown, Massachusetts, USA

CONTENTS
What is epistemology? Epistemology and cognitive science

Epistemology is the philosophical study of what is been fueled by skeptical doubts about the veracity
required in order to have rational beliefs and know- of our senses or the trustworthiness of our
ledge. Both traditional a priori methods of philoso- reasoning. Not all philosophers are persuaded,
phy and a posteriori methods of cognitive science however, that thoroughgoing skepticism allows
have been brought to bear on this question.
for, or requires, a response. As a result we often
find in contemporary epistemology the attempt to
account for epistemic achievements in a way that
WHAT IS EPISTEMOLOGY? does not necessarily offer a reply to the skeptic.
Epistemology answers to a daunting variety of Construed another way, epistemology aims
senses in the humanities and the social sciences. to investigate specific domains of knowledge or
Even when we restrict our attention to epistemol- rational belief. Some aspects of the philosophy of
ogy as it is understood in contemporary Anglo- science may thus be understood as constituting a
American philosophy, the only uncontroversial subfield of epistemology. This kind of research may
claim we can make is that epistemology is an at- be narrowed to particular sciences, such as the phil-
tempt to make sense of the possibility, nature, and osophy of psychology or the philosophy of cogni-
limits of human intellectual achievement. Typic- tive science (or physics, or biology, to name two
ally, the epistemologist does this by trying to illu- more prominent areas). Efforts to understand the
minate the difference between knowledge and nature of explanation in cognitive science ultim-
opinion, or the difference between good reasoning ately fall under the umbrella of epistemology,
and poor reasoning. This project is distinct from though such efforts lie at the intersection of philoso-
merely giving a descriptive account of what people phy of science and philosophy of mind and have
claim to know or to believe reasonably. Instead, thereby taken on a robust theoretical autonomy.
epistemologists try to understand what it is really Another distinction may be drawn between epis-
to know or really to believe reasonably, even if temology oriented towards individuals and episte-
people routinely fail to know or are frequently mology oriented towards social institutions or
irrational. Moving beyond the descriptive details practices. Some philosophers claim that there are
of knowledge or belief formation to what people social practices that positively or negatively influ-
ought to believe is a normative philosophical ence the formation of knowledge or rational belief.
enterprise. A strong version of this view is where knowledge
Construed one way, epistemology aims to or rationality is exhausted by socially-mediated
understand general and ubiquitous elements of factors. This position has currency in some fields
human inquiry, such as perceptual knowledge or of the humanities, but the epistemologists who
inductive inference. This project has sometimes interact most frequently with the cognitive sciences
24 Epistemology

tend to reject the most radical forms of social epis- Unfortunately, the `goodness of reasons' ap-
temology. proach to knowledge seems susceptible to a curi-
We shall concentrate on the general construal of ous kind of problem that shows that true beliefs for
individual epistemology and its relation to cogni- which we have good reasons still might not count
tive science. as knowledge. I may believe and have very good
reasons to believe, for instance, that `Mary owns a
Honda'. I could then, for the purposes of teaching
Knowledge a logic course, create a variety of compound
What is knowledge? One sort of knowledge is the sentences involving my belief that Mary owns
kind expressed by `that' clauses. For instance, we a Honda. Suppose I propose that `Mary owns a
may say `Carlos knows that Oaxaca is in Mexico'. Honda OR Sally is in Paris' even though I do not
This kind of knowledge is called propositional have any idea where Sally is. In the normal case, if I
knowledge, as it is a proposition ± in this case, know one half of this disjunctive compound sen-
`Oaxaca is in Mexico' ± that is known. Another tence, then I know the entire sentence since arbi-
kind of knowledge is that expressed by `how to' trary disjuncts cannot change the truth-value of the
clauses. Thus, we may say `Carlos knows how to entire sentence no matter how improbable they are.
ride a bicycle'. This second kind of knowledge Now imagine that, contrary to my excellent evi-
is called procedural or nonpropositional know- dence, Mary does not own a Honda, and, com-
ledge. The bulk of attention in contemporary pletely coincidentally, Sally is in Paris. It then
epistemology has been on propositional know- seems that my belief in the whole expression
ledge, but this emphasis should not be viewed as `Mary owns a Honda or Sally is in Paris' is true
making a claim about which kind is more import- (Sally's being in Paris makes it so) and is something
ant in human cognition. that I have good evidence for (since I have good
Beliefs are thought to be the primary psycho- evidence that Mary owns a Honda even though she
logical entities that are candidates for propositional does not). The problem is that we would not be
knowledge. Of course, not every belief is an in- inclined to attribute knowledge to me, though the
stance of knowledge. Carlos may believe that three conditions for knowledge ± true belief with
Oaxaca is in Mexico, but his merely believing it good reasons ± have been satisfied.
does not seem to be enough to make it an instance This is called the Gettier problem, after the
of knowledge. Carlos cannot know that Oaxaca is author of the short article that sparked contempor-
in Mexico if it is false that Oaxaca is in Mexico. So ary interest in it (Gettier, 1963). The Gettier problem
one additional thing required for a belief to be has inspired many putative solutions, counter-
knowledge is that the belief be true. formulations, and modified putative solutions.
At least since Plato, epistemologists have There is no agreement on how the Gettier problem
thought that true belief, while necessary, is still is to be solved within the goodness of reasons ap-
insufficient for knowledge. One way of appreciat- proach, but many epistemologists think that what
ing this is to note that beliefs that are accidentally the problem reveals is that there must be some
true are not knowledge. Suppose that Carlos is fourth condition to ensure that truth and good
guessing that Oaxaca is in Mexico. In that case, his reasons will be tied together in knowledge. Alter-
belief does not seem to count as an instance of natively, the puzzle may show that the concept of
knowledge. One prominent and historically im- knowledge is ill-defined. The Gettier problem has
portant way of pursuing the distinction between by no means crippled epistemology. Even if know-
accidentally true and nonaccidentally true belief is ledge is not a concept that epistemologists can
to rely on the goodness of the reasons for the belief. characterize in any simple way, issues in epistemol-
So, if Carlos' belief that Oaxaca is in Mexico is both ogy having to do with the nature of reasons and
true and based on his having visited that state, we belief remain.
are likely to have a case of knowledge (assuming, We shall turn to these issues shortly, but first it
for this example, that his visiting Oaxaca is a source should be noted that there are accounts of know-
of good reasons). On this conception of knowledge ledge that do not rely on the goodness of reasons
three central projects of epistemology emerge. First, approach. Some of these are pursued because they
the epistemologist must determine what constitute seem to offer a way to avoid the Gettier problem,
reasons. Second, she or he must offer a general while others seem to hold greater promise in
account of what makes some reasons good. And defeating skepticism. We can divide these accounts
third, the epistemologist must illuminate the nature of knowledge that do not rely on the goodness of
of the relationship between reasons and beliefs. reasons into two categories. One is where beliefs
Epistemology 25

are calibrated to the truth in a way that can be what a belief must have, in addition to truth, in
characterized by epistemologists even though order to yield knowledge.
the relation between belief and truth may not in- How should we undertake evaluations of beliefs
volve reasons (Nozick, 1981). The knower does not in terms of justification or rationality or warrant?
have knowledge by virtue of having reasons for a The goodness of reasons strategy for investigating
belief; rather, a belief is an instance of knowledge if knowledge again affords a persuasive framework.
certain metaphysical or logical facts about the rela- We may study the reasons for a belief in order to
tion between belief and truth are satisfied. make some judgment about whether that belief is
The second category is contextualism, which epistemically positive. Furthermore, if rationality
maintains that the truth of attributions of propos- or warrant are graded notions, the strategy may
itional knowledge vary from context to context allow us to advance a scale that appeals to the
(DeRose, 1995). For instance, we may properly comparative goodness of the reasons for a belief.
claim that Carlos knows that Oaxaca is in Mexico Thus, we may account for judgments of `more ra-
in mundane conversational contexts while the tional' or `more warranted' belief.
same claim would be improper in the rarified con- There seems to be an immediate problem,
text of a university seminar on skepticism. De- though, with employing the strategy of reasons for
veloping contextualist theories of knowledge assessing epistemically positive belief along the
requires an elaboration of what makes some con- dimensions of justification or rationality. A belief
texts more demanding than others as well as a will inherit the epistemic status of the reasons for it,
systematic treatment of changes in context. so we must in turn determine whether the reasons
for a belief are themselves rational or justified. This
threatens a regress of reasons that must be resolved.
Justification, Rationality, and Warrant Responding to this regress has been instrumental in
So far we have been identifying epistemology with crystallizing issues in the recent history of episte-
the elucidation of knowledge. Being an instance of mology, even if the regress problem no longer occu-
knowledge, however, is not the only epistemically pies the most crucial role in contemporary
positive characteristic a belief might have. We may epistemological research. Deflecting the regress of
be interested in having good reasons for our beliefs reasons argument does not by itself answer the
without insisting that such beliefs be instances question of what makes a reason justified or ra-
of knowledge. The possibility of independently ex- tional. An answer to the structural question seems
ploring epistemically positive beliefs that fall short like a necessary first step, but it cannot be a com-
of knowledge was implicit above when the three plete theory of epistemically positive beliefs.
central projects regarding reasons (their nature,
what makes some good, and what their relation- The structure of the belief corpus:
ships are) were proposed. In spite of their potential foundationalism and coherentism
independence from knowledge, though, all three of Two responses to the regress problem that differ on
these projects are typically conceived against the the structure of the belief corpus are foundational-
background of treating truth as the fundamental ism and coherentism. The foundationalist claims
aim of epistemic reasoning. Good reasons are that there is a set of basic beliefs that do not require
therefore often understood in the first instance to reasons to explain their epistemically positive
be reasons in favor of taking a belief to be true. nature because of some special characteristic(s)
Maintaining a close link between the goodness of that they have. The epistemic credentials of beliefs
reasons approach and truth is a deep commitment that are not foundational are due to a traceable
in epistemology, and explains the confidence in the lineage through reasons, from basic beliefs via a
connection between rationality and knowledge. basing relation that must be illuminated by the
Still, some epistemologists have offered accounts foundationalist. Thus, the justification relationship
that sever the link by treating good reasoning as in the foundationalist picture is asymmetrical.
wholly unconnected to the truth. Foundationalists have attempted to develop
The most prominent properties of epistemically axioms of goodness for foundational beliefs. Can-
positive beliefs discussed by philosophers are jus- didates for axioms include the claim that beliefs
tification and rationality. These labels carry with about how things appear are intrinsically epistem-
them some connotative differences. Except where ically positive. In a like fashion, foundationalists
the distinction is crucial, in this essay we will will need to provide enough axioms for founda-
read `justification' and `rationality' as synonyms. tional beliefs to account for the credentials of all
Warrant also has some currency in describing epistemically positive beliefs.
26 Epistemology

Modulating the claim that the regress of reasons will be consistent with the claim that agents can
must end in intrinsically epistemically positive access their reasons. Most of the combinations of
beliefs can complicate the foundationalist picture. answers to these challenges have been defended in
It is an open question whether reasons for beliefs the internalist literature.
must themselves be beliefs. If not, then it is possible Internalism originates in three related concerns.
that the foundational reasons are other cognitive First, one of the projects that sometimes accompan-
states such as perceptual states or memory states. ies an assessment of epistemically positive belief is
In contrast to foundationalists, coherentists to illuminate how one might improve one's beliefs.
maintain that no beliefs are intrinsically epistemic- If improvement is to be possible, it needs to be
ally positive (Bonjour, 1985). By their lights, every possible to determine which belief among many
belief relies on other beliefs for its epistemic status. candidate beliefs is most epistemically positive,
One (controversial) argument for coherentism is and it has seemed that the epistemic agent person-
that the foundationalist's putative axioms of good- ally needs to be able to make the judgment. Second,
ness require an argument to show that they are justification (though not rationality) has often been
good, and any such argument will rely on further viewed as at least partly a matter of fulfilling a
beliefs, indicating that the axioms are not founda- distinctly epistemic duty. Fulfilling a duty seems
tional after all. On one reading of coherentism, to require that one be able to do the things that duty
beliefs are epistemically positive based on a lineage requires. In order to secure the means to an intel-
of reasons in a structure that may ultimately loop lectual duty, an epistemic agent will need to be able
back onto itself. There may be no need, however, to to reflect on her or his condition and on the re-
trace reasons in a way that is circular. One might sources available. Third, recall that the ability to
instead claim that a belief is epistemically positive answer the skeptic is sometimes thought to be a
in the case of its being a member of a coherent belief crucial component of epistemology. The only
corpus without pursuing particular reasons in a answers that the epistemic agent can give, though,
linear fashion. are ones that are available on reflection.
Coherentists discharge the task of revealing what
makes some reasons good by claiming that cogent Epistemic externalism
arguments can be given for the high epistemic cre- Thinking of the epistemic agent as able to deter-
dentials of beliefs, and further arguments can be mine when beliefs are epistemically positive is
given in favor of the cogent arguments. not demanded by the overarching goal of episte-
mology. Though the philosopher may state the
Epistemic internalism conditions that must be met for a belief to be epi-
Despite their differences on the structure of the stemically positive, the epistemic agent may not be
belief corpus, the foundationalist and coherentist able to make assessments of particular beliefs. Thus
strategies traditionally agree on a different issue: one might reject internalism and not expect the
reflective, careful agents are able to make assess- right philosophical account of epistemically posi-
ments of their own beliefs in order to determine tive belief to enable meliorative, duty-oriented, or
whether they are epistemically positive. This is skeptic-answering evaluations to take place. This is
called the internalist conception of epistemic justifi- the externalist view in epistemology.
cation or rationality. For example, process reliabilism ± the best-known
In order to defend internalism in detail, the epis- externalist view ± to a first approximation claims
temologist needs to specify what is meant by the that what confers positive epistemic status on a
claim that agents can determine whether there are belief is that it be produced by a psychological
good reasons for their beliefs. A number of inter- process that reliably produces true belief (Gold-
acting but independent issues arise here. One chal- man, 1979). Though the reliability of a psycho-
lenge is deciding whether the epistemic agent must logical process is often opaque to the person
be able to determine that reasons are good, versus employing that process, process reliabilists think
the less strict demand that the agent merely be able that the reliability of belief-forming processes can
to determine what the reasons are. Another chal- be uncovered by cognitive science or by other kinds
lenge is whether the agent must be able to deter- of empirical inquiry.
mine what her or his good reasons are for a belief, The motivations for defending an externalist
versus the much less demanding constraint that the position are diverse. One simple motivation is the
agent must be able to determine that she or he has impulse to tie justification and rationality directly
good reasons for a belief. A third challenge is de- to truth via an appeal to truth-sensitive proper-
ciding what sort of effort on the part of the agent ties such as reliability. In this connection, the
Epistemology 27

externalist's commitment to truth as the central passed. Intuitions ground philosophical inquiry in
goal of justified belief looms large. Externalist the- our pre-theoretic understanding of epistemic con-
ories can be neutral on the question of the structure cepts, and allow a bridge to the long history of
of the belief corpus, and instead attempt to tackle philosophical theorizing on the same topics. But
more directly the issue of epistemically positive intuitions may need to be adjusted in light of
belief. other considerations. There is much debate as to
Another motivation that is prominent in discus- what the other sources of constraint may be. It is
sions of externalism is the role of causal factors in within a particular answer in this debate that there
belief formation. It has seemed to many episte- is the most cross-fertilization between epistemol-
mologists that, in order to be justified or rational, ogy and cognitive science.
a belief has to have both an evidential and a causal
relation to the reasons for it. Incorporating this EPISTEMOLOGY AND COGNITIVE
causal element seems to require some of the spe-
cialist's insight into the causes of our beliefs, and
SCIENCE
that is in tension with the internalist's impulse to Some epistemologists maintain that a sensible div-
insist that it is the epistemic agent personally who ision of labor in understanding justification and
is in a position to determine the epistemic status of rationality is that philosophers investigate the
her or his beliefs. normative elements of belief formation, while
cognitive scientists study how we actually form
beliefs. To the extent, however, that philosophical
The Methods of Epistemology intuitions about epistemic concepts need to be con-
In traditional epistemology, the standard of cor- strained by the empirical (a posteriori) details of
rectness for epistemological questions appeals to belief formation, cognitive science will play a sig-
intuitions about epistemic methods or particu- nificant role in epistemology. Theories of rational
lar cases of belief. For example, that beliefs form- belief that incorporate a significant empirical com-
ed under favorable perceptual conditions in a ponent are categorized under the label of `natural-
healthy observer are justified is a principle that ized epistemology'.
we may intuitively certify. So, a non-skeptical ac-
count of justification should in this view be
designed to accommodate intuitions about beliefs
Naturalized Epistemology
formed under favorable perceptual conditions. Cognitive science gives epistemologists detailed
Alternatively, a theorist may take particular in- and empirically robust accounts of the origins of
stances of an intuitively epistemically positive belief. This is relevant to epistemology if we are
belief ± the belief that this shiny Macintosh apple persuaded that a belief is rational only if it bears
is red, for instance ± and attempt to build a theory the right causal relation to the reasons for it. Em-
that respects this intuition. A successful theory of pirical details will also be important in part because
justification will yield the result that such beliefs philosophical intuitions are likely to be misleading
are justified unless there is some other overriding with respect to the nuances of belief formation.
consideration that would result in the retraction of For example, intuitively it seems that inductive
the judgment that the belief is justified. Such beliefs reasoning on the basis of small samples would not
are called `prima facie justified' in order to high- be a method for forming epistemically positive
light the fact that new information about the beliefs. It has been argued, however, that induction
situation might change intuitions about the jus- on the basis of small samples is epistemically de-
tifiedness of the belief in question. Many episte- fensible in reasoning involving natural kinds
mologists have exploited both kinds of intuition (Kornblith, 1993). It is only through the insight of
by seeking to balance methods and cases. cognitive scientific accounts of how reasoning
There are reasons to be dissatisfied with the interacts with kind concepts that this unintuitive
methodology of epistemology, not the least of method will appear epistemologically sound. Other
which is that the use of intuitions alone can insights from cognitive science that have been rele-
seem to be a precarious or even spurious basis for vant in epistemology include vision research, re-
theorizing. Intuitions might be thought to be too search on deductive reasoning, and research on
subjective or theory-laden. There was a period in memory.
Anglo-American philosophy when philosophy was Process reliabilism advocates a proprietary role
viewed as wholly conceptual (a priori) analysis. The for cognitive science in epistemology. Once causal
strong commitment to that position has long since factors are deemed relevant in understanding
28 Epistemology

justification, and once it has been determined that explain the difference between merely describing
justified beliefs are the product of reliable psycho- how people reason (which would always be par-
logical processes, cognitive science enters into epis- ticular performances of reasoning) and the norma-
temology to provide the details of psychological tive account of how people ought to reason. The
processes in terms of their reliability (Goldman, explanatory credentials of this account appeal dir-
1986). ectly to its success in linguistics and related areas of
Naturalized epistemology is often identified psychology and artificial intelligence research.
with externalism. Depending on how issues of
access to reasons are resolved, though, it is possible
References
to maintain an internalist theory that carves out a
role for empirical research on belief formation. Ar- Bonjour L (1985) The Structure of Empirical Knowledge.
tificial intelligence models of cognition have been Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
employed in epistemology to investigate how com- DeRose K (1995) Solving the skeptical problem. The
plex patterns of reasoning interact in order to yield Philosophical Review 104: 1±52.
Gettier E (1963) Is justified true belief knowledge?
intuitively justified beliefs (Pollock and Cruz, 1999;
Analysis 23: 121±123.
Thagard, 2000). The rules or norms of reasoning Goldman A (1979) What is justified belief? In: Pappas G
at each step of reasoning may be unintuitive (ed.) Justification and Knowledge, pp. 1±14. Boston, MA:
owing to their complexity, but the whole reasoning D. Reidel.
process may be counted as rational because it Goldman A (1986) Epistemology and Cognition.
yields an intuitively justified conclusion. This pos- Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
ition can be internalist by maintaining that epi- Goldman A (1992) Epistemic folkways and scientific
stemic agents will be able to determine in their epistemology. In: Liaisons, pp. 155±175. Cambridge,
own cases whether their reasoning is good, even MA: MIT Press.
though the norms of reasoning generally will be Kornblith H (1993) Inductive Inference and Its Natural
inscrutable. Ground. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Nozick R (1981) Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
The Cognitive Science of Epistemology Pollock J and Cruz J (1999) Contemporary Theories of
Knowledge, 2nd edn. Lanham, MD: Rowman &
Finally, we consider another way to conceive of the Littlefield.
relationship between epistemology and cognitive Thagard P (2000) Coherence in Thought and Action.
science. Cognitive science may step back from phil- Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
osophy and investigate epistemology itself. There
are two plausible targets of investigation: concepts Further Reading
and methods. First, cognitive science might investi-
gate how people employ the concepts of justifica- Alston W (1989) Epistemic Justification: Essays in the Theory
of Knowledge. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
tion, knowledge, or good evidence in the same
Bernecker S and Dretske F (eds) (2000) Knowledge:
way that nonphilosophical concepts are studied Readings in Contemporary Epistemology. New York:
(Goldman, 1992). Drawing conclusions from such Oxford University Press. [This anthology collects many
research is a delicate matter, however, since it has of the most important articles in contemporary
seemed to philosophers that there is no way to epistemology.]
uncover the genuine normative character of epi- Dretske F (1981) Knowledge and the Flow of Information.
stemological concepts by merely studying their Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
psychological status. Foley R (1993) Working Without a Net: A Study of Egocentric
Second, cognitive science might investigate the Epistemology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
method of employing a priori intuitions to address Goldman A (1993) Philosophical Applications of Cognitive
epistemic questions. A specific instance of this sug- Science, chaps 1 and 2. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Goldman A (1999) Knowledge in a Social World. New York,
gestion is that we should think of epistemic intu-
NY: Oxford University Press.
itions as analogous to grammaticality judgments in Harman G (1999) Reasoning, Meaning, and Mind.
linguistics (Pollock and Cruz, 1999). Reasoning on New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
this view is the product of an underlying rational Lehrer K (2000) Theory of Knowledge, 2nd edn. Boulder,
competence, but actual cases of reasoning might go CO: Westview Press.
wrong due to resource constraints. If the analogy Plantinga A (1993) Warrant and Proper Function.
could be successfully developed, it would help New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

You might also like