Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 17

Descartes’s Ontology Vere Chappell

The Meditations may have moved epistemology to the of thinking’ which have no actual existence. But in the
center of modern philosophy, but Descartes himself Fifth Meditation, mathematical objects are held to be
conceived it as a work of metaphysics: “Meditations things ‘that have their own true and immutable natures
on First Philosophy” was his title for it. Still, the meta- [which are] not invented by [any human being] or
physics in the Meditations is mostly of the special dependent on [his] mind’ (VII. 64).
variety: natural theology, cosmology, and rational psy- Questions about the relation between the ontology
chology. There is not much general metaphysics or laid out in the Principles and that, implicit if not
ontology in it. Descartes does sometimes make onto- expressly stated, of the Meditations, provide one reason
logical remarks, as when he says in Meditation Three for examining the text of the relevant Principles passage
that ‘the mode of being by which a thing exists objec- quite carefully. Another reason is that this text by itself
tively in the intellect by way of an idea, imperfect is problematic. Descartes’s presentation in Articles 48
though it may be, is certainly not nothing’ (VII. 41). and following is rather sketchy and disorganized, and
And he appeals to various ontological principles in his meaning is often unclear and indistinct. It is sur-
arguing for the existence of God: for example, that prising that scholars have paid so little attention to this
‘there must be as much “reality” in the . . . cause as in passage, and that some have read it so superficially.
the effect of that cause’ (VII. 40) and that ‘existence is There has, it is true, been some discussion of the
a perfection’ (VII. 67). But he undertakes no purposeful apparent conflict between the Principles account of
investigation of being qua being, no systematic survey mathematical objects and that of the Meditations; but
of the modes and categories of being. the parties thereto have reached no consensus.
This neglect of ontology is remedied somewhat in the This paper has two parts. In the first I spell out and
Principles. Here, in the articles comprising the final elucidate the ontology expressed in Principles I.48–70,
third of Part I, Descartes does list and distinguish the explicating the text of this passage and resolving the
basic kinds of things he supposes there to be. He also interpretive problems it presents as they arise. In the
articulates a number of ontological doctrines which are second I consider the relation between the Fifth
at best only implicit in the Meditations. I say ‘at best’ Meditation account of mathematical objects and that of
because it may be questioned whether Descartes actually the Principles. I shall argue that there is really no
held certain of these doctrines at the time he wrote the conflict between these two accounts since the former
Meditations. In any case, some portions of the ontology can be assimilated to the latter. A question I am not
presented in the Principles cover topics that receive no going to deal with in this paper is that of the extent to
mention in the Meditations: the status of eternal truths, which the ontology of the Principles is implicit in the
for one. And in at least one instance Descartes takes a Meditations, as opposed to being a later construction.
position in the later work that seems directly to conflict And of course a full treatment of Descartes’s ontology
with a doctrine stated in the earlier one. I refer to his would have to consider ontological doctrines expressed
account of universals in the Principles, within which or presupposed in works other than the Meditations and
category he includes the numbers and figures which are the Principles. But that is a task for another paper.
the objects of mathematical inquiry. By this account, Before beginning my examination of Principles
these entities are merely ideas in the mind, mere ‘modes I.48–70, I need to settle some terminological matters.

Topoi 16: 111–127, 1997.


 1997 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.
112 VERE CHAPPELL

First, ontologists require some way of referring, pre- senses the word ‘mode’ often is followed by an ‘of ’-
or extra-theoretically as it were, to all or any of the clause, but the prepositional object is different in dif-
things that in some sense or other have being, to the ferent cases. When the mode mentioned is either an
items that are originally there to be divided up into onto- attribute in general or a special sort of attribute (as in
logical categories. In English the word ‘thing’ can be the first and second of the senses just listed), the object
used for this purpose; so can the common nouns ‘being’, to which it is attributed via ‘of ’ is a substance; thus
‘entity’, and ‘item’. But ‘thing’ is not a good word to ‘mode of my mind’ and ‘mode of an extended sub-
use in discussing Descartes’s ontology. The reason is stance’. By contrast, when it is a species or form of
that he tends to take its Latin equivalent, res, to mean something more general (third sense), the object is
substantia, and hence to restrict it to the members of an attribute; thus ‘mode of extension’ and ‘mode of
one ontological category. Nor is there any noun other thinking’ (or ‘thought’). (There appear to be no restric-
than ‘thing’ that Descartes regularly uses as an extra- tions as to what modes in the fourth sense may be modes
categorical general term. His standard way of making of.) The situation is complicated by the fact that
these pre-theoretical references is via pronouns and Descartes uses the phrase ‘mode of thinking’ itself in
pronominal phrases – omnia, alia, ea quae . . . , quae- two different ways. In one the word ‘mode’ occurs with
cunque . . . , etc. – a usage that is natural and the third sense and the ‘thinking’ refers to an attribute,
perspicuous in Latin but awkward and often ambiguous so that the whole phrase stands for a species of thinking:
in English. In this paper I follow the English custom of perceiving or willing, or doubting, imagining, judging,
using common nouns in this connection, ‘being’, etc. In the other, the ‘mode’ has the fourth meaning, and
‘entity’, and ‘item’, but not ‘thing’. ‘Thing’ I reserve, the phrase is equivalent to ‘way of regarding’, ‘manner
as Descartes largely does, for substances. of conceiving’, or some such. In my discussion I shall
Second, Descartes sometimes uses the terms have occasion to use the word ‘mode’ in all but the first
‘attribute’, ‘affection’, ‘mode’, ‘quality’, and ‘property’ of its four senses, and the phrase ‘mode of thinking’ in
interchangeably, as if they all stood indifferently for both of its two. I will do my best to make clear on each
entities of one general category. But sometimes he such occasion which sense is being employed.
distinguishes these terms by restricting some of them
to certain subdivisions of this general class. In what
follows I have opted for the latter practice. Thus I use I. Exposition of Principles I.48–70
‘attribute’ and ‘affection’ as more general terms
covering the whole class of entities in question, and My exposition is keyed to the accompanying charts. I
restrict ‘mode’, ‘quality’, and ‘property’ to the specific distinguish three sections within this passage, com-
subclasses to which Descartes sometimes – but only prising Articles 48, 51–56, and 57–59, respectively. The
sometimes – applies them. remaining Articles, from 60 to 70, refine and illustrate
Finally, the word ‘mode’ is particularly protean in but do not really extend the basic scheme that Descartes
Cartesian texts. Apart from the two uses just noted, (1) presents in 48–59. In addition, there is a portion of
as a synonym for ‘attribute’ and (2) for marking the Descartes’s ontology which, though not explicitly stated
members of a subclass of attributes, two others are in the passage, can easily and naturally be extrapolated
commonly found. In one of these, (3) a mode is a from it: this too is represented on my charts. The levels
specific variety or form, a species, of something more I refer to in my exposition correspond to the lines of
general; in the other, (4) it has the ordinary non-philo- text on each chart, counting from the top.
sophical meaning of ‘manner’ or ‘way’. In all of these
DESCARTES’S ONTOLOGY 113

A. Section One: Article 48

Objects of Perception

Eternal Things-and-
Truths Affections-of-Things

omni-generic uni-generic

intellectual material

Substances Attributes Substances Attributes


= Minds = Bodies

ref to ref to ref to


Minds M-B Unions Bodies

Appetities Emotions Sensations

1. Level one: ‘whatever falls under our perception’ own term from the Meditations. Note further that they
Descartes identifies his initial subject matter as have no existence outside our, that is, human thought.
‘whatever falls under our perception’. By doing so he Descartes does not say that we human beings create
is not of course restricting it to the objects of sense per- these truths: they need not be the products of our
ception. He gives the term ‘perception’ its maximum minds. But it is in our minds and only there that they
scope, using it to cover every way in which a human ‘reside’.
knower may apprehend or be aware of something. One might well wonder how any mere object of
We still might wonder whether the field of the human thought, any entity existing in and only in a
perceivable, even in this extended sense, exhausts the human mind, could also be eternal. To be eternal is to
whole field of being for Descartes. Does he hold that be outside time, but human minds exist within time.
the subject matter of ontology extends beyond what can Descartes sometimes used the word ‘eternal’ to mean
be humanly perceived, that there are entities apart from not ‘timeless’ but ‘everlasting’; but even if what he
those that we can think or be aware of ? There is cer- means here is ‘everlasting’, it is hard to square a truth’s
tainly no indication in our passage that he does, and I having that attribute with its having existence solely in
know of no text in any other work that points to this human thought. Descartes held that all human souls,
position either. once created, never thenceforth cease to exist; but he
did not hold that any human soul began to exist at the
2. Level two: ‘things or affections of things’ vs. beginning of time. This is a problem I shall address in
‘eternal truths’ Part II of this paper.
This is Descartes’s first division within the field of the The other category that Descartes introduces at this
perceivable, and here again the question arises: does this second level is ‘things or affections of things’. This is
division exhaust the field? That is, does it exhaust even not one single category but a compound of two, things
this field, never mind the (perhaps more extensive) field on the one hand, affections of things on the other.
of being? Again, there is nothing in the Principles Descartes eventually distinguishes these two, but not
passage to suggest that it does not. until he reaches level five of his initial classificatory
Turning to the terms of the division, let us first scheme (in Section One), and then only implicitly; and
consider eternal truths. Descartes says that these ‘have it is not until Section Two of the passage that he gives
no existence outside our thought’, implying that they do them their proper names, ‘substances’ and ‘attributes’
exist within our thought. He must regard them, there- respectively. In the meantime he treats them as one
fore, as mere ‘objects of thought’, entia rationis, to use (and I shall henceforth refer to this compound via
the Scholastic term, or ‘objective beings’, to use his the hyphenated title ‘things-and-affections-of-things’),
114 VERE CHAPPELL

though some statements he makes at levels three and two summa such genera); and he identifies them as the
four apply to one of the two categories and not to the genus of ‘intellectual things’ and that of ‘material
other. things’. One question that arises here is whether
Descartes takes eternal truths to be objects of Descartes is claiming that every being in both of these
thought, that is, objective beings, in our passage. It genera has – or is – each of these most general entities,
might be supposed that he regards things-and-affections- that is, has existence, number, and duration and is a sub-
of-things as entities existing outside human thought, that stance. Or is his claim merely that at least one being in
is, as actual beings (to use a Cartesian term found in the each genus has or is each of these general entities? The
Meditations). The fact is that he does consider many answer is obviously the latter. It may be that every being
things (i.e. substances) and many affections of things has existence (actual or objective) and number (at least
(i.e. attributes) to be actual beings, but not all of them. the number one) for Descartes. But not every intellec-
In Section Three (Article 57) of the passage, he intro- tual or material being is a substance, since some are
duces a distinction between attributes which are ‘in attributes. And God, who Descartes later says is a
the very things of which they are said to be attributes’ thinking substance (Article 54), cannot have either
and those which are ‘only in our thought’. The same duration (since He is eternal) or order (since He is
distinction may be made, I believe, among substances, simple). But then it follows that these most general
though Descartes takes no notice of it here (this is the entities cannot be identified with the transcendentals of
main point of the extrapolation I referred to earlier). But Scholastic philosophy, as at least one recent commen-
this is just the distinction between actual beings and tator has suggested.1 For the transcendentals are all
objective beings, between those that exist outside and supposed to be ‘convertible with being’.
those that exist within our thought. I shall have more From what are Descartes’s omni-generic entities dis-
to say about this distinction later on. tinguished? Since there are only two genera of things,
the only alternatives (for a thing or an affection thereof )
3. Level three: ‘the most general things’ vs. those to being found in all genera are (1) being found in
confined to one genus exactly one of these two, and (2) being found in neither
Descartes does not say much about these ‘most general of them. But the latter is evidently not an option for
things’, in Article 48 or elsewhere in our passage, Descartes. On the one hand, there is not only no genus
although he invokes examples of them on several occa- of beings as such, but no genus of things-and-affections-
sions. The examples he gives here are ‘substance’, of-things, or of substances, or of numbered or enduring
‘duration’, ‘order’, and ‘number’; later he appears to things, given that the genera of intellectual and material
add ‘existence’ (Article 56) and perhaps ‘time’ (Article entities are the highest genera there are; and on this
57) to the list. We see at once that none of these, save point Descartes is in accord with Scholastic doctrine.
substance itself, is properly a thing; they are rather On the other hand, there are no things or affections
attributes, that is, affections of things. But there is no of things existing outside genera, no extra-generic
mislabeling here. The field that Descartes is dividing such entities. The things-and-affections-of-things other
at this level is still the compound ‘things-and-affections- than those that are omni-generic, therefore, must be
of-things’. ‘uni-generic’.
Duration, number, order, existence – we have no
trouble conceiving these as attributes, and Descartes 4. Level four: intellectual vs. materials things
clearly does so conceive them. But we do encounter dif- Descartes distinguishes his two ‘summa genera of
ficulty in trying to think of substance as a thing, that things’ at the same time that he says that there are two
is, as a substance. This difficulty can be resolved, as we of them. He does not at this point cite any basis or prin-
shall see in due course. In the meantime I shall merely ciple for drawing the distinction: he merely names the
assume that Descartes’s category of ‘most general two genera and gives examples of items included in
things’ includes both substances and attributes. each of them. It needs to be noted again that though he
Descartes says that these most general entities calls what he is distinguishing ‘things’, he means
‘extend to all genera of things’; I call them, therefore, ‘things-and affections of things’; and in fact the items
‘omni-generic’ entities. He then immediately informs us he cites as examples of ‘intellectual things’ and
that there are only two ‘genera of things’ (or at least ‘material things’ are all of them attributes. For he
DESCARTES’S ONTOLOGY 115

describes them as ‘things . . . pertaining to’ substances, these entities, which are in fact attributes, constitute
to ‘mind or to thinking substance’ in the one case, and a separate ontological category, a distinct kind of
to ‘extended substance [or] to body’ in the other. This attribute, apart from and on a par with the intel-
is one of his standard ways (and one of the Scholastics’ lectual and material attributes which are to be
ways too) of specifying attributes. referred solely to the mind and solely to the body,
respectively. On this reading, Descartes would not
5. Level five: substances vs. attributes be a dualist but a ‘trialist’, as John Cottingham has
Although Descartes mentions substances in describing put it, at least regarding attributes.2 Alternatively, it
the items, that is, the attributes, that belong to the genera could be Descartes’s view that these entities belong
of intellectual and material things, he does not explic- to one or the other of the two categories, and differ
itly say that these substances also belong to these from its other members only at some sub-categorical
genera. But there is no doubt that he holds that they level.
do. Furthermore, although the distinction between sub- My own position is that Descartes holds the latter of
stance and attribute that I represent him as introducing these two alternatives, as is shown on my chart. I take
at level five of my exposition is not in fact explicitly the ‘others’ in question to belong ontologically to the
made by him, at that point or anywhere in Article 48, category of intellectual attributes, and not to constitute
it surely is fair to claim that the distinction is implicit a distinctive third kind of attribute. They differ from the
there. other members of this category in that they require
causes of both the mental and the material kinds in order
6. Level six: certain other [things] that we to exist, whereas the other intellectual modes require
experience in ourselves none but mental causes. (Correspondingly, attributes in
Having distinguished intellectual from material things, the material category require none but material causes.)
Descartes cites ‘certain others [that] we experience in But it is not the kind of cause an entity has that deter-
ourselves’. But his text at this point is obscure, and mines the ontological category it belongs to, at least at
commentators have had different opinions as to its the level of the categories of intellectual and material
import. The main point at issue is the status of these beings. For causes according to Descartes operate across
‘others’, which, Descartes tells us, include appetites, these categorical boundaries.
emotions, and sensations. These, he says, ‘are not I know that this position needs defending, but I shan’t
to be referred either solely to the mind or solely to defend it here, since to do so would divert me from the
the body, but arise from the close and intimate union task of surveying Descartes’s whole ontology.3
of our mind with the body’. This could mean that

B. Section Two: Articles 51–56

Things-and-Affections-of-Things

Substances Attributes

constant variable

principal non-principal Qualities Modes

uncreated created uncreated created created created created


?
uni-gen omni-gen uni-gen uni-gen uni-gen omni-gen uni-gen omni-gen uni-gen omni-gen uni-gen
? ?
G S M B d i m nn i m nn i m nn i m
116 VERE CHAPPELL

1. Level one: things-and-affections-of-things too. And so are the attributes of created substances the
In Article 51, Descartes returns to the ground he has creatures of God.
covered in Article 48 and begins tracing a different
path through it. The new scheme he produces is not in 4. Level three: constant vs. variable attributes
conflict with the earlier one; rather, it interpolates new Descartes next moves to consider attributes, making a
divisions within it and adds detail under existing divi- number of divisions among them and adding, along the
sions. The resulting structure can be mapped on to that way, details to his account of substances. From now on,
Section One in different ways; the way I have chosen however, my discussion will proceed in a somewhat dif-
is shown by my charts. ferent order from that of his presentation.
The division between (what I call) constant and
2. Level two: substances vs. attributes variable attributes is merely implicit in Descartes’s text,
This time through, Descartes draws the distinction but it is presupposed by two divisions that he does make
between substance and attribute explicitly, and indicates explicitly.
the basis on which he does so. By a substance, he An attribute is constant iff it is never absent from
says, we understand ‘a thing which so exists that it the substance that possesses it, that is, in the case of an
requires no other thing for its existence’. Implicit in enduring substance, iff it inheres in or is exemplified by
this formula is a definition of an attribute as a thing that substance at every moment of its existence. It is
which does require another thing for its existence, important to notice that this definition is satisfied by
and this is spelled out in a clause added to the two different kinds of attribute for Descartes, those he
French translation of the Principles (at Article 51): calls principal attributes and those I am calling omni-
‘things [that] are of such a nature that they cannot generic ones. Thus not only extension in a corporeal
exist without other things, we . . . call . . . attributes’ substance and thinking in a mind, but ‘existence and
(IXB.47). duration in an existing and enduring thing’ are constant
There are well-known problems with these defini- attributes.
tions. At the least it seems that, in order to understand A variable attribute, by contrast, is either one that
them, we must already have some understanding of the an enduring substance has at certain times and lacks at
terms being defined. We need to know what a substance others, an attribute that is gained or lost; or else it is one
and what an attribute is, and to grasp the specific (non- that, though never lost, undergoes change in the course
causal) kind of dependence the one has upon the other. of its existence. Thus if an apple turns from green to
As Descartes might have put it, we need to understand red, its greenness is a variable attribute according to the
that special way of depending in which attributes are first clause of the formula just stated; its color is one
wont to depend on substances. according to the second.

3. Level five: uncreated vs. created substances and 5. Level four: principal vs. non-principal attributes
attributes In Article 53, Descartes lays down a fundamental prin-
Immediately upon defining substance, Descartes pro- ciple of his ontology. A substance, he declares, has
ceeds to distinguish one particular substance, God, from many attributes, ‘but for each substance there is one
‘all other substances’. The latter, he says, are the ‘crea- principal property, which constitutes its nature and
tures’ of God, whereas God himself is uncreated. His essence, and to which all the others are referred’. By
point is that God is the only being that strictly satisfies ‘one’ principal property here Descartes means ‘one
his definition of substance. Instead of concluding, exactly’, not ‘one at least’; and for a property to ‘be
however, that it is false or inaccurate to call creatures referred to’ another, he tells us two sentences later, is
substances, Descartes announces ‘that the term “sub- for it to ‘presuppose’ it (Latin praesupponere). But
stance” does not apply univocally’ to them and to God, when he says that ‘all’ the other properties of a sub-
meaning that God and created things are substances in stance are referred to its principal one, he does not mean
different senses of the word. ‘all’ without qualification. He means all of its uni-
We should note that not only is God an uncreated generic properties, for the point does not hold, for
for Descartes, but that His attributes must be uncreated example, for existence or duration. From the fact that
DESCARTES’S ONTOLOGY 117

something exists, nothing whatsoever follows as to what squares on its sides’, and from what he says about it,
its principal property is. viz. that it belongs to ‘all and only’ right-angled trian-
The principal property of minds, of course, is gles’, that properties meet the same condition that
thought; of bodies it is extension; and Descartes fre- essences do: they are attributes without which the sub-
quently, throughout his writings, identifies thought and stances possessing them cannot exist. The Aristotelians
extension as the essences of these substances, respec- of course have a similar problem of distinguishing
tively. He has some trouble defining the term ‘essence’, essences from properties. But they also have more
however. One problem is to distinguish essences from resources for dealing with this problem than Descartes
omni-generic attributes, since these too are always has at his disposal: a richer conception of essence
present: a substance (that once has them) never lacks grounded in a theory of scientific explanation. Note that
them. And not only does it never lack them in fact but I say: resources for dealing with the problem, not for
it could not lack them and still exist. Indeed, Descartes successfully solving it.
goes so far as to say (in Article 62) that a substance
and its duration are distinguished merely ratione, which 6. Level four: qualities vs. modes
means that the substance ‘cannot be understood without’ In Article 56 Descartes notes that he has been using the
that attribute. This is exactly what he holds about the terms ‘quality’ and ‘mode’ as synonyms for ‘attribute’.
distinction between a substance and its essence: a body But these terms, he announces, also have a narrower
or a mind cannot be understood as lacking extension or use, in which they apply only to a restricted subclass
thought, respectively. of attributes – those I call variable attributes. Descartes
So then what is the difference between an essence then undertakes to distinguish modes and qualities from
or nature and an omni-generic attribute for Descartes? one another. Unfortunately, his attempt to explain the
For one thing, an essence or principal attribute deter- narrower use of these terms is unilluminating. When,
mines a genus of things, indeed a highest genus (there he says, ‘we consider a substance to be affected or
being only two such attributes), in the sense that the modified [variari] by [its attributes], we call [these
class containing all and only the substances that attributes] modes; when it can be designated as such and
have it constitutes a genus, whereas an omni-generic such [talem] by this modification we call them quali-
attribute does not. Again, the essence of a substance is ties’. Cottingham in his translation puts an Aristotelian
entailed by each of its uni-generic attributes – or, to spin on the last part of this statement by rendering talem
put it in a more Cartesian way, the concept of the one ‘a substance of such and such a kind’, and if Descartes
is contained in that of the other – whereas its omni- were invoking an Aristotelian theory of species and
generic attributes are not so entailed. These are not of genera here, it would be appropriate to interpret his
course surprising points, since they are built into words in this way. But I see no justification for
Descartes’s definitions of these terms ‘genus’ and ‘uni- Cottingham’s reading in the text itself, and no other
generic’. reason to think that Descartes is alluding to Aristotle
Distinguishing essences from omni-generic attributes here.
is one problem we encounter in trying to define Descartes gives no example of qualities in the
‘essence’ in the Cartesian sense. But it is not the only narrower sense and (I believe) never uses the term
such problem. For omni-generic attributes are not the ‘quality’ again in this sense, in the Principles or else-
only non-principal constant attributes that Descartes where. Hence I shall having nothing specific to say
recognizes. There are also those that fall under the tra- about these qualities. The situation is different, however,
ditional Aristotelian heading of ‘properties’. Descartes with respect to modes. Not only does Descartes often
does not mention these properties until he comes to use the word ‘mode’, in the narrow way; he also gives
discuss universals, in Article 59: they constitute one of several examples of modes in this sense; so we are able
the five types of universal that he says are ‘commonly to get quite a firm grip on his conception of them. Thus
listed’. Nor does he provide any characterization of in Article 61 he cites as examples of modes proprie
them even then. But it is clear from the example he dicta the square shape and the motion of a square
gives, viz. ‘that the square on [the] hypotenuse [of a moving stone. In Article 64 he says that thought and
right-angled triangle] is equal to [the sum of ] the extension, which have been identified as the principal
118 VERE CHAPPELL

attributes of minds and bodies respectively, ‘can also be substance. On the other hand, the term ‘thinking’, pre-
taken as modes of substances, in that one and the same sumably, is not applied univocally to God and his crea-
mind can have many different thoughts, and one and the tures; and this could mean that God and they can’t
same body’ can have, at different times, many different belong to the same genus after all. (c) It is clear that
sizes and shapes. He then makes it clear that it is the Descartes’s main examples of omni-generic entities,
different thoughts and the different sizes and shapes duration, number, order, and existence, fall into the
themselves that are the modes of the substances ‘in category of constant non-principal attributes, although
which they inhere’. he has no common name for them (which is why I
Finally, in Article 65, he lists ‘intellection, imagina- label them ‘nn’ on my chart). But what are the uni-
tion, recollection, volition, etc.’ on the one hand, and generic members of this category? One answer is, the
‘all shapes, the positions of parts, and the motions of Aristotelian ‘properties’ that he includes among the
parts’ on the other, as ‘modes of the things in which ‘five common universals’ in Article 59. This is plau-
they inhere’ – that is, of thinking and extended sub- sible, given his example there, and on the assumption
stances respectively. The text here is a little confusing, that such properties are to be found not only in geo-
in that Descartes first describes the items on the first list metrical entities but also in bodies and minds. (d) In the
as ‘modes of thought’ and those on the second as case of qualities, nothing is clear: whether they are all
‘modes of extension’. This is a case in which he is using omni-generic, all uni-generic, or come in both varieties.
the word ‘mode’ in two different senses, without any (e) And it is clear, finally, that all of Descartes’s
indication that he is doing so. The point he wants to examples of modes, which we surveyed a moment ago,
make in the Article is that intellection and the other are uni-generic. But are there any other modes that are
items he lists are modes in the sense of attributes (i.e. omni-generic, and if so, what are they? Here again is
in the second of the four senses I distinguished earlier). one possible answer: there are such modes, and they are
But he identifies the items in question by referring them modes of number or order in the way that a particular
to the more general principal attributes of which they thought and a particular shape are modes of thinking
are species, calling them modes of the latter (in the third and extension. (Note the shift in sense between the first
sense of ‘mode’). ‘modes’ and the other two in the foregoing sentence.)
One further point about modes and qualities. In God The latter, Descartes says, are modes of the substances
there are attributes, Descartes observes, but no modes to which they belong; and so, we might say, are the
or qualities, because in God there is no variation. Hence, former. But what would such a mode of number or of
as is shown on my chart, the only modes and qualities order be? How about a particular number or order, for
there are, are created ones, that is, ones belonging to example, the number two and the order in a straight
created substances. line? (I am not sure that this move would work for
duration, much less for existence.)
7. Level six: omni-generic vs. uni-generic attributes The most vexing question that arises at this level,
and substances however, concerns substances rather than attributes.
Descartes’s distinction between omni- and uni-generic There is no doubt that all the substances Descartes iden-
attributes, first introduced in Section One of our tifies as such, created and uncreated, are uni-generic,
passage, is invoked on several occasions in Section though we have not yet determined which genus it is
Two. We encounter problems, however, when we try to that the uncreated substance, along with its attributes,
fit this distinction into the more elaborate system of dis- belongs to. What is uncertain is whether there are
tinctions that Descartes constructs in Section Two. any substances that Descartes would recognize as omni-
Some points are clear enough, but others are not. (a) generic. In favor of an affirmative answer is the fact that
It is clear that no principal attribute is omni-generic, Descartes includes ‘substance’, along with ‘duration’
since it is principal attributes that determine the genera and ‘number’, on his list of ‘most general things’ when
there are. (b) It also is clear that an uncreated attribute he first introduces this category. Furthermore, it is
must be uni-generic, since it is a principal attribute. But obvious that the term ‘substance’ applies to both minds
to what genus does it belong? One possibility is, to the and bodies (and that it does so univocally). On the other
genus of intellectual entities, since God is a thinking side, although duration and number are attributes, it
DESCARTES’S ONTOLOGY 119

sounds gibberish to say that substance is a substance. despite Descartes’s characterization of him as a thinking
Second, even if we can allow this substance to be a sub- substance.
stance, we are hard put to say which substance it is. It I come now to the created substances, first the
cannot be God, or any body or mind, since these are mysterious, omni-generic ‘substance’, then individual
all uni-generic. And what other substances are there for minds and bodies, and finally the different varieties of
Descartes? Finally, it appears that an omni-generic sub- created attributes. The first I pass over, pending my dis-
stance would have no principal attribute. But this cussion of universals. About minds and bodies I have
violates Descartes’s fundamental requirement that every only one point to add to what I have already said about
substance have exactly one principal property. them, viz. that each individual mind is, as Descartes
I think I know how to answer this question, but I need affirms in Article 60, ‘really distinct [both] from every
to lay out Descartes’s theory of universals before doing other thinking substance and from every corporeal sub-
so. stance’. This last point is one that Descartes explicitly
argues for in the Sixth Meditation. Here he seems to
8. Level seven: God, minds, and bodies and the regard it as a straightforward consequence of the onto-
attributes thereof logical doctrines he has been presenting.
We come now to the level at which individual sub- As for the created attributes, about them I have
stances and fully specified attributes appear. Let us run nothing to add to my earlier accounts of them. But there
through their various categories in the order in which is a further point about the whole scheme I have been
they are represented, left to right, on my chart, begin- presenting. It is that this scheme could be continued;
ning with God. that is, the categories of substances and attributes at
God is of course the uncreated substance, the one and which we have arrived could be further subdivided. Or
only such substance there is, and all the divine attrib- at least some of them could. We could introduce sub-
utes are uncreated too. Every divine attribute, moreover, genera of bodies and of modes, certainly, though the
is a principal attribute. This might seem surprising, for other cases aren’t so clear. But there is this interesting
isn’t existence a divine attribute, and yet doesn’t it difference, from the Cartesian perspective, between the
‘extend to all genera of things’? The answer is, Yes and two tasks of subdividing bodies and subdividing modes.
No. God’s existence is one of his attributes, but his exis- The former Descartes would likely assign to the natural
tence is special, as is his thinking and the substance he scientists, physicists and biologists as we should now
is: the term ‘existence’ is not said univocally of God call them; whereas the latter he might still regard as a
and of the created beings existing in genera. Descartes proper pursuit for ontologists. There is certainly a basis
states explicitly of God’s existence (in the Fifth in his works for distinguishing, within the category of
Meditation) that it ‘pertains to [His] essence’ (VII.68), modes, subcategories of ‘standing’ as opposed to
and the same is true of every one of his attributes. That ‘occurring’ properties, ‘dispositions’ vs. ‘states’, ‘activ-
is why every divine attribute is a principal attribute. ities’ vs. ‘events’ (my terminology, not Descartes’s),
We might even conclude, in view of Descartes’s insis- among others. And these are, I believe he would grant,
tence in the Third Meditation on the ‘unity’ and ‘sim- ontological distinctions.
plicity’ of the divine attributes, that these all reduce
somehow to one single attribute. In any case, it is clear
that the divine attributes are not only uni-generic, as we C. Section Three: Articles 57–59
have already noted they are, but unique to the single
individual substance who is God. This suggests an The chart representing this third Section continues that
answer to the question raised earlier, concerning the of Section Two; its first six levels coincide with levels
genus to which God belongs. It is that his genus too is two through seven on the attribute side of the Section
unique to God, that he is its only member. If so, we Two chart.
cannot place God in the genus of thinking beings,
120 VERE CHAPPELL

Attributes

constant variable

principal non-principal Qualities Modes

uncreated created created created created


?
uni-gen uni-gen omni-gen uni-gen omni-gen uni-gen omni-gen uni-gen
? ?
d i m nn i m nn i m nn i m
? ? ?
a o a o a o a o a o a o a o a o a o a o a o a o
? ? ? ? ? ?
p p u p p u p p u p p u p p u p p u p p u p p u p p u p p u p p u p p u

1. Level seven: actual vs. objective attributes ‘objective’ sense. In this sense an idea is, as he puts it
In Article 57 Descartes distinguishes those attributes in the Preface to the Meditations, ‘the thing that is
which ‘are in the very things of which they are the represented by’ an idea in the first sense, insofar as this
attributes’ from those which are ‘only in our thought’. ‘is not supposed to exist outside the intellect’ (VII.8).
This is the distinction between what I call actual and We might also say that an objective being is the
objective attributes, and as my chart shows it cuts across object of an idea (in the first sense) or what the idea is
all the other distinctions among attributes. Thus, for an idea of, except that these expressions also are
each individual attribute that exists actually, there is – ambiguous, as is ‘object of thought’. For we can and
or rather could be – an objective attribute that matches often do think or have an idea of something that exists
or mirrors it; and for each attribute that exists objec- outside our thought, for example, the actual sun. In that
tively, there is or could be an actual attribute that case it is entirely proper to describe the actual sun as
matches or mirrors it. The qualification ‘could be’ is the object of our thought, or as that which our idea is
necessary because the attributes that happen to exist in an idea of. Thus when we describe an objective being,
the world do not correspond one to one with those that for example, the objective sun, as the object of an idea,
human beings happen to think of. On each side there are we have to mean something different. Descartes appeals
some that have no counterparts on the other: attributes to this distinction in the First Reply to explain the
that people think of but are non-existent in actuality, and meaning of ‘idea’ in the second sense just noted, that
actually existing attributes that no one ever thinks of. in which an objective being is an idea. An idea of the
But there is no attribute found in either the objective sun, he says, ‘is the sun itself existing in the intellect,
or the actual realm which could not have a counterpart not of course existing formally, as it does in the sky, but
in the other. existing objectively, that is in the way in which objects
I use the term ‘objective being’ to stand for an entity are wont to be in the intellect’ (VII.102–103). (Note that
that exists in someone’s mind when he or she thinks of Descartes uses this term ‘formally’ as a synonym for
something. Of course a thought is such an entity, but ‘actually’ in the Third Meditation, e.g., at VII.41.)
that is not what I mean. Another such entity is a Perhaps it would be more illuminating to describe an
Cartesian idea, but this term ‘idea’ is ambiguous as objective being as the internal object of an idea or
Descartes uses it. In one sense he gives the word, an thought, or as its content, as philosophers nowadays
idea is an occurrence in a mind, a mental event or ‘oper- sometimes do. Descartes does not use these expressions,
ation of the intellect’. This he calls the ‘material’ sense but he does speak of ideas, in the sense of mental occur-
of the word, and in this sense ideas are not objective rences, as ‘containing’ entities which turn out to be
beings either, though they are thoughts. But objective objective beings.
beings can be identified with ideas in the other sense Internal objects of thought, contents of ideas, ideas
in which Descartes uses the word, which he calls the themselves as objects existing in our minds – these of
DESCARTES’S ONTOLOGY 121

course have been the subject of philosophical contention is the idea that is the first or basic universal; and the
for many centuries. Some philosophers have argued that name is called a universal name because it designates
there simply are no such entities; some commentators this idea. As for the ‘mode of thinking’ which gives rise
have claimed that Descartes did not believe in them. For to the universal idea, Descartes must mean by that the
my part, I believe that Descartes did believe in them, abstract or general way of thinking, the key to which
and further that it is no philosophical sin to do so. I also he evidently takes to be selective attention. Notice how
believe – and here am acting on the belief – that much like Locke Descartes sounds in this passage.
Descartes’s theory of objective being can be used to illu- Of course the similarity between Descartes’s and
minate his doctrine of universals. Locke’s view of universals is only partial. Locke holds
Before proceeding to that, I need to note that that when we ‘form’ an idea of two upon seeing two
although Descartes introduces the distinction between stones, we are in effect creating that idea: it first comes
actual and objective beings in his discussion of attrib- to be in our minds by the process of abstraction.
utes, it is clear that the same distinction can be extended Descartes, however, believed that ideas such as that of
to substances. I shall provide details of this extrapola- two are innate, having been installed in our souls by
tion, as I call it, just below. God at the time he created them. Hence the idea of two
is already there when we see the two stones, and what
2. Level eight: particular vs. universal attributes the ensuing abstraction process effects is not the
Descartes does not say a great deal about universals in creation of that idea but merely its discovery or activa-
the Principles, but it is past doubt from what he does tion: abstraction brings it not into being but into con-
say that he regards them, all of them, as mere objects sciousness. (Descartes elaborates on this theme in his
of thought, that is, as ideas in the objective sense and Reply to Gassendi’s Objections at VII.382.) Descartes
hence as objective beings. True, he doesn’t quite express does not mention his doctrine of innate ideas in his
this in so many words. What he says (in Article 58) is discussion of universals, or anywhere in this part of
that when number, for example, ‘is considered not in the Principles. But he does do so earlier in the same
any created things but only in the abstract or in general, work (VIIIA.9, 13), and there is no reason to suppose
it is no more than a mode of thinking’, and the same that he is abandoning it here. We must therefore append
holds, he continues, for ‘all [the entities] we call uni- this doctrine to his account of abstraction in order to
versals’. Here the term ‘mode’ must be understood as reach a full understanding of the Cartesian theory of
having the fourth of the senses I distinguished earlier, universals.
and the phrase ‘mode of thinking’ the second of its Having laid out this theory in general terms,
two senses. Even so, Descartes’s meaning is far from Descartes proceeds to apply it to the ‘five common
obvious. But then he goes on, in Article 59, to explain universals’ of the Aristotelian tradition: genus, species,
how these universals ‘come about (fiunt)’. They do so, differentia, property, and accident. Only the last three
he says, ‘from the fact that we use one and the same of these are universals in the category of attributes; for
idea for thinking of all the individual [entities] which genus and species, as we shall see, are substance
are similar to one another’. We then ‘apply one and the universals (another source for my impending extrapo-
same name to all the things represented by this idea, lation). But there is no reason to think that these three,
which name’, he says, ‘is universal’. It might appear together with the constant non-principal attributes exem-
from this last remark that it is only the name and not plified by number and duration, are the only universal
the idea that is universal. But this appearance is dis- attributes that Descartes recognizes. There must in fact
pelled by Descartes’s description of an example of this be universal attributes in all the categories of attributes
process. ‘When we see two stones and attend not to their that have been distinguished, essences as well as modes,
nature but only to the fact that they are two, we form both uni- and omni-generic. To generate a universal
(formamus) the idea of their number, which we call two; principal attribute all we have to do is think of thought
and later when we see two birds or two trees and or extension ‘in general or in the abstract’; a universal
consider not their nature but only that they are two, we mode results when we think in this same way of imag-
recall (repetimus) the same idea as before, which thus ination or rectilinear motion; and so for the others.
is universal’. And so, he adds, ‘we designate this All universals are objective beings for Descartes;
number by the same universal name of two’. Hence it hence all actual beings are particular. This is not an
122 VERE CHAPPELL

unusual view when the beings in question are sub- sometimes think of these particular substances, and
stances. But Descartes introduces his theory of univer- when we do we have ideas of them, ideas in the objec-
sals as a theory about attributes; and since according to tive sense, so that for each actual substance we think
that theory only attributes in our thought are univer- of there is an objective substance existing in our mind.
sals, the contrasting attributes in things must be partic- Hence there are objective as well as actual substances.
ular. And this is an unusual view: not many philosophers Now we can think of substances individually, in which
have held it. It may not seem implausible that some case the ideas we have of them are as particular as they
Cartesian attributes, for example, modes such as indi- are. Or we can think of substances generally and in the
vidual occurrent thoughts and motions of bodies, should abstract, and when we do our ideas of them are uni-
be regarded as particulars. But even the essence of a versal. We can think of the whole genus of minds or
particular mind, the essence that Descartes says is in bodies, or of some species of them, in this way, in which
that mind, is a particular in his view; it is an attribute, case the idea we have, the universal that exists in our
but one that is unique to that one mind. By contrast, thought, just is that genus or species.
the essence that one mind shares with others, indeed Can we also apply this ‘mode of thinking’ to God;
with all minds, is found in our thought; it is there and that is, can we think of God in this abstract and general
only there that that universal attribute exists. way? If so, then when we do so think of Him, we have
All universals are objective beings, that is, ideas in a universal idea of God, an objective universal God
the objective sense of the word. But it doesn’t follow existing in our intellect. It may be questioned whether
that all objective beings are universals, that is, that every we can have such an idea of God; for uniqueness is not
idea we have is the idea of a thing or things considered only a necessary property of God, it is entailed by each
abstractly or generally. We often do think of things indi- of his other properties, hence by any property which is
vidually and as particulars, and the ideas by means of included in any idea we have of God. But what this
which we do this must be particular too. This point means is not that we cannot think of God abstractly at
holds not only for particular substances – Descartes’s all; only that we cannot so think of him clearly and dis-
sun in the sky and its objective counterpart – but also tinctly. So there is, or could be, a universal God existing
for attributes. Since actual attributes are particular for in a human mind, as my chart shows.
Descartes, and since we can think of them as such, there There is only one problem that remains to be solved,
must be objective attributes that are particular as well. the problem we noted earlier concerning omni-generic
substances. The problem is that there are reasons both
3. Extrapolation: universal substances for and against supposing that such entities are included
The account of universals that Descartes gives in the in the Cartesian ontology. The main reason against sup-
Principles is cast and illustrated in terms of attributes. posing this is that every substance Descartes mentions
But it is reasonable to extend this account to cover sub- – God and every mind and body – is uni-generic. Now,
stances as well, as I have mentioned several times now. however, having considered Descartes’s account of uni-
Most of the details of this extrapolation can be gathered versals and the extension of that account to substances,
from my chart. we can see, first, that all the substances that Descartes
mentions are particulars, and second, that there are,
Substances besides these, substances that are universal, for example,
uncreated created
the genus mind or that of body. And we can also see
that there is nothing to keep Descartes from recognizing
uni-gen omni-gen uni-gen a universal substance itself, that is, an idea of substance
which applies to all particular (created) substances, both
God Substance Minds Bodies minds and bodies. This universal substance would
indeed be omni-generic, since it would extend to all
a o o a o a o
genera of substances. Hence our problem is solved if
p p u u p p u p p u Descartes does recognize this universal substance. And
I see no reason to believe that he does not.
As the chart shows, no actual substance is a uni- This concludes my exposition of the Principles
versal, neither God nor any mind nor any body. But we passage. I turn now to the apparent discrepancy between
DESCARTES’S ONTOLOGY 123

Descartes’s account of universals, including numbers sufficient to distinguish it from nothing’ (Kenny, 1970,
and figures, in this passage, and what he says about p. 699), but is different both from actual existence and
mathematical objects in the Fifth Meditation. from existence or being in thought. Kenny calls this
third kind of being ‘being given’ (dari) (Kenny, 1969,
p. 21).
II. The objects of mathematics Kenny bases his case for Descartes’s Platonism (or
Meinongianism) almost entirely on the Fifth Meditation.
According to the Principles, universals are merely He makes no mention of Descartes’s discussion of uni-
‘modes of our thinking’, which is to say, ideas in human versals in the Principles, so of course he takes no notice
minds. They are ideas in the objective sense of the word, of the conflict between its view of mathematical objects
and hence objective beings, though Descartes does not and the one he attributes to Descartes. By contrast, Alan
use this terminology here. Among the examples of uni- Gewirth finds both Platonism and Aristotelianism in
versals he cites are ‘the number we call two’ and ‘the Descartes, the one in the Fifth Meditation (and the First
figure . . . we call . . . triangle’. To be sure, this number Reply to Objections), the other in Principles One (and
and this figure can turn up as modes of individual the Fifth Reply) (Gewirth, 1970, p. 678). Gewirth’s
material substances. But in this case they are particu- Platonic Descartes, however, is not the extreme realist
lars, as much so as are the substances in which they that Kenny’s is. Gewirth has Descartes holding that
inhere. The universal two or triangle is the number or ‘mathematical entities have their own determinate
figure considered, as Descartes says, ‘simply in the natures or essences regardless of whether any such
abstract or in general, and not in any created things’ entities exist’ (Gewirth, 1971, p. 299), but not that these
(Article 58). And it is this two and this triangle that entities enjoy some kind of being other than that of
belong to the subject matter of pure mathematics. existence, nor that they are, as Kenny puts it, ‘real
In the Fifth Meditation, however, Descartes charac- thing[s] lacking only the perfection of actual existence’
terizes the objects of ‘pure and abstract mathematics’ as (Kenny, 1970, p. 697). Nor is Gewirth’s Aristotelian
‘things which even though they may not exist anywhere Descartes the explicit, thoroughgoing conceptualist
outside me still cannot be called nothing; for although that the Principles passages show him to be. To his
in a sense they can be thought of at will, they are not Descartes Gewirth attributes the ‘Aristotelian doctrines’
my invention but have their own true and immutable that ‘mathematical essences are quantitative “abstrac-
natures’. ‘When, for example, I imagine a triangle’, he tions” from natural substances’ and that ‘mathematical
goes on, ‘even if perhaps no such figure exists, or has essences in their “ontological” status are not indepen-
ever existed, anywhere outside my thought, there is still dent of physical existents’ (Gewirth, 1970, p. 678), but
a determinate nature, or essence, or form of the triangle not the doctrine that these entities are ideas existing in
which is immutable and eternal, and not invented by me people’s minds. It is thus not surprising that Gewirth
or dependent on my mind’ (VII.64). The implication of finds it ‘not too difficult to reconcile [the] Aristotelian
these remarks is that, though geometrical figures may doctrines of Descartes with his Platonic [ones]’
exist in human minds, they must have some way of (Gewirth, 1971, p. 299). For the doctrines that Gewirth
being in addition to and independent of such existence: has in mind are indeed logically compatible. But it is
otherwise they could not have essences which are not on account of Descartes’s holding these doctrines
eternal and immutable. that there is a conflict within his thought, at least not
This at any rate is how this passage has been inter- the conflict that I am concerned with. Besides which,
preted by certain commentators, most notably Anthony Kenny claims that Descartes does not hold the
Kenny. In one article Kenny calls Descartes’s philos- ‘Aristotelian doctrines’ that Gewirth attributes to him;
ophy of mathematics ‘thoroughly Platonic’ and declares and I agree with Kenny on that.
Descartes to be ‘the founder of modern Platonism’ On Gewirth’s view of Descartes, there is no real
(Kenny, 1970, pp. 692–693). Elsewhere Kenny com- conflict between the Principles and the Fifth Meditation
pares Descartes’s view of mathematical objects to that concerning the status of mathematical objects. But
of Meinong (Kenny, 1967, p. 155; Kenny, 1969, p. 25). Gewirth fails to grasp the full import of Descartes’s
In both cases Kenny’s point is that for Descartes a position, at least that of the Principles. On Kenny’s view
triangle, for example, has ‘a kind of being that [is] the conflict is real, but Kenny himself fails to address
124 VERE CHAPPELL

it: he doesn’t consider the Principles position. Another entities [must be] distinct from God, since they stand
recent scholar who has tackled these issues is Tad in a causal relationship to him’ (Kenny, 1970, p. 696).
Schmaltz. Unlike Kenny, Schmaltz does consider the And of course Schmaltz’s Descartes is at odds with the
Principles position; and unlike Gewirth, he does under- author of the Principles regarding the ontological locus
stand its conceptualist message, a message he rightly of numbers and figures. According to the former, such
associates not with Aristotle but with Gassendi and things are in God; for the latter, they are in human
Locke. For Schmaltz the problem is to find a reading minds.
of Descartes that ‘avoids the Scylla of Kenny’s Platonic Schmaltz’s interpretation does have some virtues.
interpretation without thereby falling into the Charybdis For one thing, it provides an easy explanation of the
of the abstractionist interpretation’ (Schmaltz, 1991, eternality of mathematical objects, a feature Descartes
pp. 162–163). By ‘abstractionist’ here Schmaltz means explicitly and repeatedly attributes to them. Offsetting
‘conceptualist’, and he attributes this interpretation such advantages, however, is the fact that Schmaltz is
– mistakenly, as I believe – to Gewirth, as well as unable to cite a single Cartesian text in direct support
to Martial Gueroult. According to Schmaltz, mathe- of his position. And his efforts to show that various texts
matical entities are neither independent real beings nor and historical precedents support his reading indirectly
merely ideas in human minds but something else: viz., are at best unconvincing, and in some cases are seri-
immutable essences belonging to the essence of God. ously flawed.
Indeed, Schmaltz goes so far as to claim that Descartes Is there then no way of reconciling Descartes’s
‘identifies [these] immutable essences with God account of universals in Principles I.57–59 with what
himself’ (Schmaltz, 1991, p. 135). he says about the objects of mathematics in the Fifth
One might object to Schmaltz’s interpretation on the Meditation? Must we suppose that he held and pub-
ground that it is not the immutable essences of numbers lished two contradictory doctrines within a three-year
and figures that Descartes takes to be the objects of the period – or else that he radically changed his view some
mathematician’s inquiry, but numbers and figures them- time between 1641 and 1644? My own belief is that
selves, the immutable entities that have these essences. the doctrines in question are perfectly consistent, and
Kenny makes the same point against Gewirth (Kenny, that, despite appearances, they can be reconciled,
1970, p. 692); and it is true that the texts of both without either violating or ignoring the plain meaning
Meditation Five and Principles I.57–59 specify trian- of Descartes’s texts. I shall now proceed to show how
gles and not their essences as the targets of mathemat- such reconciliation is to be accomplished.
ical concern. (Note that by treating figures and numbers My reconciliation project is in fact quite simple: it
as entities that have essences Descartes must be can be completed in two steps. The first is to note the
regarding them as substances – abstract and universal close affinity that Descartes posits between the objects
ones but substances nonetheless.) But this point is of mathematics and eternal truths. In the ontological
hardly damaging to Schmaltz’s position. For as we have scheme of the Principles, entities of both these kinds
seen, Descartes holds that an entity and its essence are are assigned to the general category of objective beings;
neither really nor modally distinct, and that it is only but the affinity I have in mind is more intimate than that.
ratione that they can even be distinguished. So the dif- Descartes discusses eternal truths at several places in
ference between saying that the mathematician studies his writings. Outside the Principles, his most striking
figures and numbers and saying that he studies the claim about them is that they are created by God, and
essences of figures and numbers is inconsequential. that they would not have the content they do, or even
A more significant difficulty with Schmaltz’s inter- exist, had not God indifferently chosen to establish
pretation concerns the relationship of the mathemati- them. They are, Descartes sometimes says, the product
cian’s objects to God. Schmaltz agrees with Kenny in of God’s free decrees, and they depend absolutely on
maintaining that such objects are, in Descartes’s view, God for their being and nature. Now in a number of
the creatures of God. But for Kenny Descartes takes passages Descartes explicitly links eternal truths to
them, once created, to be distinct from their creator, mathematical objects. Some such truths, he is wont to
whereas Schmaltz’s Descartes conceives them to be say, are truths about (Latin de) numbers and figures, or
identical therewith. On this point Schmaltz cannot be about the essences thereof. More to our purpose, he indi-
right: as Kenny points out, ‘Descartes’s mathematical cates that these objects, no less than the truths about
DESCARTES’S ONTOLOGY 125

them, are the creatures of God. Thus in responding to eternal truths must also consist in his creation of human
Gassendi’s Objections, he says that both ‘the essences minds containing such truths. We should have no trouble
of things’ and ‘the mathematical truths which we can extending the doctrine of innate ideas to cover eternal
know about them’ were ‘originally established (condita) truths, considering that Descartes often applies the term
by’ God and hence that neither is ‘independent of ’ him ‘idea’ to propositions as well as to simple concepts (cf.
(VII.380). Again, in an early letter to Mersenne he states III.395, 417). And in any case he frequently cites truths
that God ‘is no less the author of creatures’ essence than – sometimes calling them ‘axioms’ or ‘common notions’
he is of their existence’, and goes on to characterize this – as examples of items that we ‘are born with’ or that
essence as ‘nothing other than the eternal truths’ (I.151). have been ‘placed in’ us by God: on one occasion he
Both Kenny and Schmaltz, as we have seen, interpret explicitly says that ‘mathematical truths . . . are all
Descartes as definitely holding what these passages inborn in our minds’ (I.145). So the same considerations
suggest: that God has created not only truths about that account for the immutability and objectivity of the
triangles, for example, but triangles (or their essences) objects of mathematics account also for the
themselves. On this point I think we must agree with immutability and objectivity of the truths that hold of
them. them, and indeed of the eternal truths in general.
The second and final step is to recall the connection This view of eternal truths bears some resemblance
I noted earlier between Descartes’s account of univer- to a thesis defended in a recent article by Jonathan
sals and his doctrine of innate ideas. The former entails Bennett. Bennett’s topic is not the ontology of
that mathematical objects are objective beings, which is Descartes’s eternal truths but their modality. His
to say, ideas in human minds. The latter explains how problem is to understand how such truths can be the free
these ideas came to be in the minds that have them, creations of God and yet be true of necessity. To solve
viz. by being placed there originally by God. What I this problem, Bennett argues, we must attribute to
now wish to claim is that, for Descartes, God’s creation Descartes a ‘conceptualist’ or ‘subjectivist’ analysis of
of numbers and figures consists in his creation of modality. On this analysis the necessity of a truth is
minds containing the ideas of numbers and figures. taken to consist in our being unable to conceive its being
Mathematical objects just are ideas, according to the false, so that modal facts are reduced to facts about our
ontology of the Principles; and God creates them, mental capacities. Hence God is responsible for these
according to the doctrine of innate ideas, by including modal facts because he is responsible for our minds’
them within the minds that are the direct products of his having the capacities they do: ‘God created modal truths
creative action. These ideas need not be consciously by making us unable to conceive of impossibilities’
present to the minds in which they are housed, either (Bennett, 1994, p. 646). Bennett’s view of Descartes’s
from the beginning or at every moment thereafter. understanding of the modal status of eternal truths thus
They may exist originally or intermittently as uncon- parallels my view of his conception of their ontolog-
scious dispositions, as Descartes acknowledges in his ical status; and it was in fact while reading Bennett’s
Comments on Regius’s Programma (VIIIB.357f., 361). article that my view first occurred to me.4
But doesn’t this position destroy the objectivity of math- It should be clear that the reconciliation I am
ematics by making its objects differ from mind to mind? proposing is not one of compromise. I am not claiming
And doesn’t it render these objects mutable, since minds that Descartes’s true doctrine of mathematical objects
grow and wither and the ideas within them change? No, either combines or lies between the conceptualism of
for Descartes holds that God installs the same ideas in the Principles and the Platonism of the Fifth Meditation.
every mind that he creates; and no again, since the ideas Rather, I am denying that the view expressed in
that God makes to be innate in us are constant and never Meditation Five is Platonic: I am in effect assimilating
change. So the position I am attributing to Descartes that view to the position of the later work. And I think
secures both the objectivity and the immutability of a close reading of the text of Meditation Five bears me
mathematical objects. out. Nothing in that text amounts to an explicit state-
If I am right about Descartes’s conception of the ment that triangles have any being apart from human
objects of mathematics, then given the affinity between minds. What is said is that a triangle may not exist
them and eternal truths, what holds for the one must ‘anywhere outside me’ or ‘outside my thought’, and that
hold also for the other. Hence God’s creation of the its nature or essence is not ‘invented by me’. Descartes
126 VERE CHAPPELL

does add that the triangle’s essence is not ‘dependent on existed from the beginning of time, even if he did
my mind’; but what he means is merely that it is not my believe that every mind that is created exists forever
own creation, or indeed the creation of any human after its creation. This means that he would have had
being. He does not in this passage make the positive to grant that there was a time at which no universal
claim that this essence (and its possessor) is the creation numbers and no truths about such numbers existed,
of God, or that it is, in that sense, dependent on God – because there were no minds for them to exist in.
a claim he does make, in exactly those terms, in other Bennett avoids this objection (or its analogue) by
texts, as we have seen. But he does not deny, here or claiming that the term ‘eternal’ in the phrase ‘eternal
anywhere, that triangles and their essences depend in truths’ means no more than ‘unchanging’ and thus picks
another sense on the minds in which, as ideas, they have out the same property that ‘immutable’ does (Bennett,
been created, and to which, as attributes, they belong. 1994, pp. 663–665). I think that Bennett may be right
‘Depend’ in this other sense stands for the relation that about this. But Descartes also speaks of God’s having
any attribute bears to the substance that houses it; and created such truths ‘from all eternity’ (I.152). This
in that sense, according to the Principles, mathemat- might suggest that these truths have been around, so to
ical objects do depend upon human minds. speak, either from the beginning or as long as God
My position is that Descartes believes that mathe- himself has; and if so the objection is applicable after
matical objects, that is, the universal numbers and all. Strictly, however, what God does from all eternity
figures that constitute the subject matter of the mathe- is will or decree that the truths in question obtain, and
matical sciences, are objective beings residing in minds, it is his acts of will or decrees that are contemporaneous
and that they have come to be where and as they are with him: indeed, Descartes says, these decrees are not
by the creative action of God. But I am not claiming really distinct from God himself (V.166). But the crea-
that there are for Descartes no real numbers and figures tures that come to exist by God’s decrees, whether truths
in the material world, and that mathematics is merely a or human minds or the whole universe, are distinct both
mental construction that is imposed arbitrarily on an from God and from the pertinent decrees. (Schmaltz’s
indifferent reality. On the contrary, I am sure that failure to appreciate this point is one of those flaws in
Descartes believed that God creates not only minds his argumentation that I alluded to earlier.) And though
having mathematical ideas residing in them but also the decree may be issued at (or ‘before’) the beginning
bodies having numbers and shapes inhering in them, of time, the creature does not begin to exist until the
bodies possessing mathematical properties and standing decree is, as Descartes says, ‘enacted’ (V.166).
in mathematical relationships. The difference is that the Descartes has, as far as I can see, no way of meeting
products of this latter creation are particulars; and this objection without admitting that by calling them
although the mathematician’s results apply to these eternal he did not mean that either the truths or the
entities, the true objects of his study are the universals objects of mathematics themselves exist from all
which are the fruits of the former creation. eternity. He cannot claim that these entities exist implic-
I have argued that the immutability of mathematical itly or potentially in God’s decrees, which are eternal in
objects, and of eternal truths too, is provided for on the whatever sense Descartes takes that term to have. For
view that I am taking of them. But Descartes maintains these decrees are in, or rather are, God himself, and
that these entities are eternal as well as immutable, and Descartes is clear that nothing belonging to God is
I have not yet said anything about their eternality. implicit or potential. Nor does the Cartesian ontology
Indeed, it may be objected that these entities cannot be provide any place for potential or merely possible
eternal if they really are merely ideas in human minds, beings as such: for Descartes, any entity that is not
even if ideas are taken to include (the contents of ) long- actual is an objective being, and hence requires the exis-
term unactualized dispositions as well as (of ) occur- tence of at least one human mind. I see no way, there-
rent events. This is obvious if ‘eternal’ means ‘timeless’, fore, of allowing entities (other than God) that are
for no human mind exists outside of time. But the objec- strictly and literally eternal within the confines of
tion has force even if ‘eternal’ is taken, as it frequently Descartes’s ontology. The objection stands; but the con-
is by Descartes, to mean ‘sempiternal’ or ‘everlasting’. clusion I draw from it is not that either Descartes’s
For Descartes certainly held that no human mind has ontology or my rendition of it must be rejected, but
DESCARTES’S ONTOLOGY 127

rather that the objects and the truths of mathematics are References
not, for Descartes, strictly and literally eternal.5
Bennett, Jonathan: 1994, ‘Descartes’s Theory of Modality’,
Philosophical Review 103, 639–667.
Broughton, Janet and Mattern, Ruth: 1978, ‘Reinterpreting Descartes
Notes on the Notion of the Union of Mind and Body’, Journal of the
History of Philosophy 16, 23–32.
1
See Schiffer, 1976, p. 22 et passim. Chappell, Vere: 1994, ‘L’homme cartésien’, in Jean-Marie Beyssade
2
Cottingham attributes such ‘trialism’ to Descartes in Cottingham, and Jean-Luc Marion (Ed.), Descartes. Objecter et répondre,
1985, although he does so on the basis of texts other than this one Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, pp. 403–426.
in the Principles. Other scholars have taken the stronger position that Gewirth, Alan: 1970, ‘The Cartesian Circle Reconsidered’, Journal
Descartes is a trialist regarding, not (or not merely) attributes, but of Philosophy 67, 668–685.
substances, i.e. that he recognized three distinct kinds of substances, Gewirth, Alan: 1971, ‘Descartes: Two Disputed Questions’, Journal
at least in some texts; see Broughton and Mattern, 1978, Hoffman, of Philosophy 68, 288–296.
1986, and Schmaltz, 1992. Hoffman, Paul: 1986, ‘The Unity of Descartes’s Man’, Philosophical
3
In another paper, however, I have defended the view that Descartes Review 95, 339–370.
is a dualist regarding substances against the claims of Hoffman et Kenny, Anthony: 1968, Descartes: A Study of his Philosophy, New
al. that he espouses substance trialism: see Chappell, 1994. York: Random House.
4
Bennett has since informed me that he is ‘much in agreement’ with Kenny, Anthony: 1969, ‘Descartes’s Ontological Argument’, in
my ontological extension of his position, and that he ‘strongly agrees’ Joseph Margolis (Ed.), Fact and Existence, Oxford: Blackwell,
with my ‘dissolution of the worry’ about the Fifth Meditation. pp. 18–36.
5
Shorter versions of this paper were read at (1) the Early Modern Kenny, Anthony: 1970, ‘The Cartesian Circle and the Eternal Truths’,
Philosophy Conference, in honor of Willis Doney, at Dartmouth Journal of Philosophy 57, 685–700.
College, July 1995; (2) the Sixth Annual Philosophy Conference at Nolan, Lawrence: 1997a, Descartes’s Theory of Essences. PhD
the University of California, Riverside, January 1996; and (3) the Dissertation, University of California at Irvine.
University of Western Ontario, April 1996. I am grateful to my Nolan, Lawrence: 1997b, ‘The Ontological Status of Cartesian
auditors on those occasions for helpful suggestions and criticisms. Natures’, Forthcoming.
At the Riverside Conference I was delighted to learn that views very Schiffer, Stephen: 1976, ‘Descartes on his Essence’, Philosophical
like mine on the status of Descartes’s mathematical objects had been Review 85, 21–43.
arrived at quite independently by Larry Nolan, who was then com- Schmaltz, Tad M.: 1991, ‘Platonism and Descartes’s View of
pleting his dissertation at Irvine. Nolan gives an elegant statement Immutable Essences’, Archiv für die Geschichte der Philosophie
and a persuasive defense of these views, not only in his dissertation 73, 129–170.
(Nolan, 1997a) but in a paper (Nolan, 1997b) he had read the previous Schmaltz, Tad M.: 1992, ‘Descartes and Malebranche on Mind and
May at a conference at Stanford, and which is now in the course of Mind-Body Union’, Philosophical Review 101, 281–325.
being published.
University of Massachusetts, Amherst

You might also like