Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 13

The American Journal of Bioethics

ISSN: 1526-5161 (Print) 1536-0075 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/uajb20

The Precautionary Principle and the Tolerability of


Blood Transfusion Risks

Koen Kramer, Hans L. Zaaijer & Marcel F. Verweij

To cite this article: Koen Kramer, Hans L. Zaaijer & Marcel F. Verweij (2017) The Precautionary
Principle and the Tolerability of Blood Transfusion Risks, The American Journal of Bioethics, 17:3,
32-43, DOI: 10.1080/15265161.2016.1276643

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2016.1276643

Published online: 16 Feb 2017.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 12

View related articles

View Crossmark data

Citing articles: 8 View citing articles

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=uajb20

Download by: [University of Newcastle, Australia] Date: 20 February 2017, At: 04:51
The American Journal of Bioethics, 17(3): 32–43, 2017
Copyright © Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
ISSN: 1526-5161 print / 1536-0075 online
DOI: 10.1080/15265161.2016.1276643

Target Article

The Precautionary Principle and the


Tolerability of Blood Transfusion Risks
Koen Kramer, Sanquin Blood Supply Foundation and Wageningen University and
Research Center
Hans L. Zaaijer, Sanquin Blood Supply Foundation
Marcel F. Verweij, Wageningen University and Research Center

Tolerance for blood transfusion risks is very low, as evidenced by the implementation of expensive blood tests and the rejection
of gay men as blood donors. Is this low risk tolerance supported by the precautionary principle, as defenders of such policies
claim? We discuss three constraints on applying (any version of) the precautionary principle and show that respecting these
implies tolerating certain risks. Consistency means that the precautionary principle cannot prescribe precautions that it must
simultaneously forbid taking, considering the harms they might cause. Avoiding counterproductivity requires rejecting
precautions that cause more harm than they prevent. Proportionality forbids taking precautions that are more harmful than
adequate alternatives. When applying these constraints, we argue, attention should not be restricted to harms that are human
caused or that affect human health or the environment. Tolerating transfusion risks can be justified if available precautions have
serious side effects, such as high social or economic costs.
Keywords: donor blood safety, MSM and blood donation, opportunity costs, precautionary principle, risk, risk-based decision-
making, transfusion-transmissible infections

THE PRECAUTIONARY PRINCIPLE IN hepatitis C had been a known risk of blood transfusion
CONTEMPORARY BLOOD SAFETY DECISION MAKING and blood product infusion since the mid 1970s. Following
Since its introduction in environmental policymaking in the developments in hepatitis B testing in the early 1970s, it
1980s, the precautionary principle has become increasingly had gradually become recognized that 80–90% of all trans-
influential in public health issues, including the safety of fusion-transmitted hepatitis cases involved an unknown
donor blood. The principle’s proper interpretation and appli- causative agent. However, acute hepatitis C infections typ-
cation have been debated extensively, however, which has led ically involved only mild symptoms, and the serious
to the development of alternative definitions. The “Rio” defi- effects of chronic infection remained unrecognized for sev-
nition states that “where there are threats of serious or irre- eral more years (Institute of Medicine [IOM] 1995). Hepati-
versible damage, lack of full scientific certainty shall not be tis C was hence considered an acceptable side effect of
used as a reason for postponing cost-effective measures to pre- blood transfusion and plasma product use, which meant
vent environmental degradation” (United Nations Environ- that ensuring product availability at reasonable costs
mental Programme [UNEP] 1992), whereas, for example, the superseded safety concerns (IOM 1995; Krever 1997; Feld-
“Wingspread” definition states that “when an activity raises man and Bayer 1999). While the seriousness of chronic
threats of harm to human health or the environment, precau- hepatitis C gained recognition, however, securing supply
tionary measures should be taken even if some cause and and containing costs remained dominant concerns. For
effect relationships are not fully established scientifically” example, the implementation of surrogate testing (by
(SEHN 1998). Various institutions have consolidated their screening for the presence of antibodies to the hepatitis B
own interpretation of the principle in official guidelines (e.g., core antigen or of heightened alanine aminotransferase
Commission of the European Communities [CEC] 2000). levels) was delayed because of its costs and because false-
The precautionary principle caught the attention of positive test results would result in donor losses (Alter
donor blood safety policymakers after the AIDS and hepa- et al. 1981; Krever 1997). A similar stance was taken when
titis C crises of the 1980s and 1990s (Stoto 2006; Epstein AIDS emerged. In contrast to hepatitis C, AIDS was con-
et al. 2013). Originally labeled “non-A-non-B” hepatitis, sidered severe, but decision makers underestimated the

Address correspondence to Koen Kramer, Sanquin Blood Supply Foundation, department of Blood-borne Infections (BOI). Plesmanlaan
125, 1066 CX, Amsterdam, the Netherlands. E-mail: K.Kramer@sanquin.nl

32 ajob
The Precautionary Principle and Risk Tolerability

possibility and frequency of AIDS transmission through unreasonably expensive. But forgoing safety measures that
blood products. Arguing that transfusion transmissibility would add some safety, no matter how marginally, means
was “unproven” or that the risk was “one in a million,” tolerating some risk. Can tolerating risks be squared with
they held that only firm evidence that AIDS threatened the precautionary principle at all? And if so, is cost con-
transfusion recipients could justify disrupting standard tainment a morally sound reason to tolerate transfusion
practice (IOM 1995; Krever 1997; Feldman and Bayer risks?
1999). But even when cases of AIDS in hemophiliacs and In this article we argue that some risk tolerance is legit-
transfusion recipients accumulated, decision makers imate when applying the precautionary principle to blood
remained reluctant to introduce safety measures (such as safety, sometimes even to contain costs. After distinguish-
universal exclusion of high-risk groups such as gay men, ing various versions or interpretations of the precautionary
anti-HBc surrogate testing, and heat treatment of plasma principle (second section), we offer a number of con-
products) that might offend donors, threaten product straints (or meta-principles) that any version, interpreta-
availability, or add costs. tion, or application of the precautionary principle should
When decision makers finally agreed that thorough observe (third section). These constraints forbid taking (or
safety measures were necessary, thousands of transfusion prescribing) safety measures that are (i) sufficiently haz-
and plasma product recipients had already been infected ardous to be forbidden by the precautionary principle
worldwide. Various inquiries following the AIDS and hep- itself; (ii) more harmful than the hazards they avert; or (iii)
atitis C crises concluded that blood services (and regula- more harmful than alternative adequate safety measures.
tors) had responded negligently. Not only had decision While satisfying these constraints clearly requires tolerat-
makers failed to take adequate action when the risks of ing some risks, what type of risks they cover crucially
AIDS and hepatitis C had become undeniable—they had depends on the interpretation of “harm,” which is there-
also taken insufficient precautions at earlier stages (IOM fore discussed next (fourth section). Finally, we consider
1995; Krever 1997; Feldman and Bayer 1999). whether safety measures can be harmful in virtue of hav-
Blood safety policymaking has subsequently embraced ing high opportunity costs (fifth section). We conclude that
the precautionary principle. The principle has, for example, applying the precautionary principle requires considering
been invoked to justify leukocyte depletion and donor deferral what will be sacrificed in the name of (blood) safety.
policies against variant Creutzfeld–Jakob disease (vCJD) in
the United Kingdom and Canada (Turner 2006; Wilson et al.
2003; Wilson et al. 2007), hepatitis B virus nucleic acid testing
(NAT) in the United States (Blood Products Advisory Com- VERSIONS OF THE PRECAUTIONARY PRINCIPLE
mittee [BPAC] 2009), and various safety measures against We have already noted that the precautionary principle is
West Nile virus in North America (Vamvakas et al. 2006). The defined in various ways—and as Table 1 shows, we have
precautionary principle has also been invoked to reject or criti- only seen the tip of the iceberg. This is an immediate and
cize initiatives to change the lifetime deferral of male donors obvious difficulty in answering whether “the” precaution-
who have had sex with other men (MSM) into a temporary ary principle sanctions high blood safety expenditures. In
(e.g., 1-year or 5-year) deferral. this section we probe the differences between formulations
The application of the precautionary principle to blood (definitions, versions, interpretations, applications) of the
safety is nevertheless controversial. A main charge against precautionary principle and discuss what the lack of a
the precautionary principle is that it is unrealistically intol- common definition means for how the principle applies to
erant of risks and therefore requires unreasonable sacrifi- blood safety issues.
ces in the name of safety. In the interpretation of several A primary distinction can be made between versions
countries (including the United States and Canada), the or interpretations of the precautionary principle as (i) a
precautionary principle only allowed relaxing MSM defer- “rule of choice,” (ii) a “procedural requirement,” or (iii) an
rals if proof could be offered that risk would not increase “epistemic principle” (Ahteensuu and Sandin 2012; cf.
at all (Leiss et al. 2008; Vamvakas 2011a; cf. Galarneau Hartzell-Nichols 2013). The difference between these inter-
2010). As a result, MSM deferrals have been relaxed only pretations is whether the precautionary principle is taken
recently and, according to gay-rights activist groups, half- to prescribe certain (i) actions, (ii) decision-making proce-
heartedly. The principle is also taken to sanction very high dures, or (iii) beliefs (or belief-like attitudes). Differences
safety expenditures (Hergon et al. 2005; Wilson 2011; Cus- and overlaps between “rule of choice” versions can then
ter and Janssen 2015). Growing concern over the high costs be mapped by means of a structural account of the precau-
of blood safety (e.g., Schippers 2014) is hence matched by tionary principle (Manson 2002; Sandin 2004; Ahteensuu
increasing unease with the precautionary principle. Recent and Sandin 2012). On this account, versions of the precau-
decision-making frameworks—notably those proposed by tionary principle arise from varying elements in a common
Wilson (2011) and by the Alliance of Blood Operators structure. The first slot in this structure is a harm condi-
(2015)—recognize both safety and cost containment as tion, which refers to some kind of adverse event, for exam-
legitimate concerns but leave important issues unad- ple, to “catastrophic risks,” to “serious or irreversible
dressed. Containing costs requires discontinuing or not damage,” to “very costly and/or irreversible con-
introducing safety measures that are considered sequences,” or merely to “harm.” The second slot, the

March, Volume 17, Number 3, 2017 ajob 33


The American Journal of Bioethics

Table 1. Definitions and accounts of the precautionary principle in literature on transfusion safety policy.
Definition References
“Where there is uncertainty as to the existence or extent of risks to Farrugia (2002, 277)
human health . . . institutions may take protective measures without
having to wait until the reality and seriousness of those risks
becomes fully apparent.”
“Where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage to the Moreno (2003, 840), Wilson et al. (2003, 90)
environment, lack of full scientific certainty should not be used as a
reason for postponing cost-effective measures to prevent
environmental degradation.”
“Complete evidence of risk does not have to exist to institute measures Wilson et al. (2003, 90), Wilson et al. (2007, 181),
to protect individuals and society from that risk.” Wilson (2011, 179)
“Even in the absence of scientific certainty, . . . measures need to be Hergon et al. (2005, 273)
taken to face potential serious risks.”
“Preventive action should be taken when there is evidence that a Turner (2006, 318)
potentially disease-causing agent is or may be blood borne, even
when there is no evidence that recipients have been affected. If
harm can occur, it should be assumed that it will occur. If there are
no measures that will entirely prevent the harm, measures that may
only partially prevent transmission should be taken.”
“The balancing of the risks and benefits of taking action should be Vamvakas et al. (2006, 106)
dependent not only on the likelihood of the risk materializing but
also on the severity of the effect if the risk does materialize, the
number of persons who could be affected, and on the ease of
implementing protective or preventative measures. The more
severe the potential effect, the lower the threshold should be for
taking action. . . . If there are no measures that will entirely prevent
the harm, measures that may only partially prevent transmission
should be taken.”
“For situations of scientific uncertainty, the possibility of risk should Alter (2008, 97)
be taken into account in the absence of proof to the contrary . . .
[and] measures need to be taken to face potential serious risks.”
“If there is concern about a possible or potential risk, even if it is yet Pereira (2008, 352)
unproven, then precautionary interventions are implemented.”
“Actions that might harm the environment should not be undertaken Dodd (2010, 956)
unless the proponents of those actions [can] establish that they [are]
harmless.”
“When a purported risk presents a threat of “serious or irreversible Vamvakas (2011b, 11)
damage,” complete evidence of risk does not have to exist to justify
the institution of measures to protect individuals and society from
that risk.”
“When an activity raises threats of harm to human health or the Wilson (2011, 179)
environment, precautionary measures should be taken even if some
cause and effect relationships are not fully established scientifically.
In this context, the proponent of an activity, rather than the public,
should bear the burden of proof.”
“Proactive action [should] be taken to prevent or minimise threats to Farrell (2012, ch. 7)
human health or the environment, notwithstanding the absence of
full scientific certainty about the nature and scope of such threats.”
“If there is a risk, no matter how small, the (blood) operators should Menitove et al. (2014, 754)
seek to mitigate that risk . . . in the absence of evidence,
precautionary steps should be taken.”
Note. For overviews of definitions in other areas, in particular environmental policy debates, see, e.g., Sandin (1999) and Trouwborst (2006).

34 ajob March, Volume 17, Number 3, 2017


The Precautionary Principle and Risk Tolerability

knowledge condition, specifies an extent of plausibility A number of competing conclusions could be (and
that this adverse event will come to pass. It may require have been) drawn from the observation that interpreta-
that the harm is “(theoretically) possible,” “suspected,” or tions of the principle differ. Some have argued that the
“not proven not to occur.” The third element concerns the principle is simply too ill-defined to be of use to policy-
precautions that should be taken if the harm and knowl- making and that it should therefore be discarded (see San-
edge condition are met. It may either specify which quali- din et al. 2002). Others have attempted to establish the
ties precautions should have (e.g., being “cost-effective” or superiority of one of the principle’s definitions or interpre-
having “little risk of causing harm”) or identify particular tations. We think that it is preferable and realistic, how-
precautions (e.g., “banning” or “developing alternatives ever, to allow varying formulations across different
for” hazardous activities). Finally, the fourth slot concerns contexts. First, different versions of the precautionary prin-
the force with which precautions are prescribed: Taking ciple may fit different decision-making styles. In particu-
them may be mandatory, recommended, or merely lar, decision makers may prefer more general or more
permitted. specific interpretations of the precautionary principle:
The knowledge condition is typically conceived as a whereas general versions are intuitively plausible and rela-
minimal amount of plausibility that harm will occur. Inter- tively flexible, more specific interpretations provide more
pretations also differ, however, on what extent of uncer- concrete guidance (cf. Hartzell-Nichols 2013). Second, we
tainty must remain to apply the precautionary principle. cannot expect that a single version will have ethically
Some scholars call only the management of theoretical risks acceptable implications in strongly diverging domains.
(where the possibility of harm occurring has not been Simply importing a version of the precautionary principle
proven) “precautionary,” which suggest that managing from environmental policy-making into blood safety poli-
proven risks requires a different approach. Others hold that cymaking is dubious, for example, because the hazards
while the precautionary principle does apply to proven involved differ (Moreno 2003). This may mean that blood
risks if these are unquantifiable, risk–cost–benefit analysis is safety policymaking should adopt a customized version of
preferable when facing quantifiable risks (see, e.g., Resnik the precautionary principle (Wilson et al. 2003). Third,
2003). Yet others have defended applying the precaution- countries may want to set their “own level of protection,
ary principle even to quantifiable risks (Hansson 1999; . . . depending on [their] economic situation and socio-
Munthe 2011; Steel 2015).1 political priorities” (Von Schomberg 2012, 148; cf. CEC
Blood safety policymakers and scholars have invoked 2000). What amount of protection is reasonable against
the precautionary principle to justify precautions against transfusion-transmissible infections, for example, may
all these types (theoretical, proven but unquantifiable, and depend on cultural values and on the amount of resources
quantifiable) of risks.2 It has been applied (i) when facing available for donor blood safety and other important socie-
infections which had not been shown to transmit through tal goals (cf. later discussion in fifth section). It would be
transfusion, as with variant Creutzfeld–Jakob disease (cf. unrealistic, for instance, to require the same level of pre-
Wilson et al. 2003; Turner 2006); (ii) when the probability caution in the blood systems of high and low income coun-
of exposure to infections that were known to be transfu- tries. Fourth, it may be sensible to allow (or combine)
sion-transmissible was highly uncertain, as with West Nile different versions of the precautionary principle even
virus (Vamvakas et al. 2006); and (iii) when the frequency within one context, depending on the magnitude of the
of transfusion-transmission would, by all plausible esti- risks faced in particular cases. This would enable meeting
mates, be very low, as with hepatitis B breakthrough infec- more serious hazards with stricter precautions and less
tions and Q-fever (BPAC 2009; Forland et al. 2012). serious hazards with milder ones (Wilson 2011; Steel 2015).
Allowing multiple versions or interpretations of the
precautionary principle does not mean that every version
1. The principle has for example been interpreted as a “maximin”
should be accepted. In the following section we outline
decision-making strategy (i.e., choosing the option where the min-
imal outcome value is highest) (Hansson 1999; Munthe 2011; Steel
three constraints or “meta-principles” that should be
2015). Another strategy is to weight negative outcome values and observed in precautionary policymaking. The fourth and
probability estimates unequally when quantifying risks: Precau- fifth sections discuss the scope of these constraints and
tion then requires assigning more weight to relatively serious out- explore their implications for the question whether (or to
comes than to relatively probable ones (Munthe 2011). what extent) precautionary decision making should be
2. It must be conceded that these types of risk, while neatly separa- sensitive to the costs of safety.
ble in theory, are difficult to disentangle in practice. Rarely are all
possible outcomes and their probabilities accurately known, as
“pure” quantifiable risk would require; the probabilities of some
possible outcomes are typically uncertain, and ignorance of some CONSTRAINTS ON THE PRECAUTIONARY PRINCIPLE:
possible outcomes is usual as well (Hayenhjelm and Wolff 2012). CONSISTENCY, AVOIDANCE OF
Furthermore, because proof is often neither conclusive nor entirely COUNTERPRODUCTIVITY, AND PROPORTIONALITY
absent, there is also a gray area between “proven” and
“theoretical” risks. By classifying risks, therefore, one typically This section presents three general constraints on versions
simplifies the decision-making situation (Hayenhjelm and Wolff (interpretations, applications) of the precautionary princi-
2012). ple. First, consistency requires that (any version of) the

March, Volume 17, Number 3, 2017 ajob 35


The American Journal of Bioethics

precautionary principle does not simultaneously prescribe hazards thus leads to inconsistent recommendations. The
safety measures and, considering the potential harms same conclusion follows if it is taken to cover very small
involved in those measures themselves, advise against harms (Trouwborst 2006; Munthe 2011). For example, a
them. Second, avoidance of counterproductivity requires vaccination is always somewhat uncomfortable, so if the
that recommended safety measures are no more harmful precautionary principle required avoiding even mild dis-
than the hazards they avert. Finally, proportionality requires comforts, it could not consistently recommend providing
that precautions are no more harmful than alternative ade- vaccines as a precaution against some emerging disease.
quate precautions. A common response is to limit the principle’s scope to
Some preliminary qualifications are in order. First, sufficiently credible and serious hazards, as specified in
these constraints are not intended as complete guidance knowledge and harm conditions (Sandin et al. 2002;
on defining or applying the precautionary principle. The Trouwborst 2006; Steel 2015). The principle might, for
constraints are important because they point at reasonable example, require “reasonable grounds for concern” or
limits of precaution and thus affect the question of when “some scientific evidence” that “significant” or “serious”
risks should be tolerated. Second, we acknowledge that harm is impending (cf. second section). Precautionary
these constraints have appeared, in some form or other, in measures can then be recommended consistently if the
guidelines or commentaries on the precautionary principle hazards they introduce are not credible or serious enough
(e.g., CEC 2000; Steel 2015). The current article explicitly to “trigger” the principle.
defines the constraints with “harm” as a central notion. Even accounts of the precautionary principle with rela-
This helps in answering when (transfusion) risks should tively strict knowledge and harm conditions may not
be tolerated even on the precautionary principle, namely, always evade inconsistency, however (Trouwborst 2006;
when taking precautions against those risks would accord- Steel 2015). Cases have been offered where meeting serious
ing to our constraints be unjustifiably harmful. and credible hazards seemed to require equally hazardous
The present section shows that these constraints must precautions. While such “risk–risk trade-offs” are no
be respected to avoid powerful and commonly raised exception when facing environmental risks (e.g., Hansen,
objections against the precautionary principle. There has von Krauss, and Tickner 2008; Hansen and Tickner 2013),
been little question that these objections are serious if they the introduction of alternative hazards may be especially
apply; debates have focused on whether they apply. Lack- common when addressing public health risks. Spraying
ing a universally accepted account of the precautionary DDT to combat malaria, for instance, involves public
principle, however, the question must be whether particu- health hazards because DDT might be toxic or carcino-
lar versions (definitions, interpretations, applications) of genic (Goklany 2001). Similarly, it has been suggested that
the precautionary principle can avoid them. These objec- precautions against credible and serious infectious transfu-
tions thus set constraints on how to interpret the precau- sion hazards posed credible and serious threats to transfu-
tionary principle: Only interpretations of the principle that sion recipients: Chemicals employed in some pathogen
avoid these objections are defensible (cf. Munthe 2011; inactivation procedures might be carcinogenic, for exam-
Steel 2015). ple, and donor deferral policies against vCJD could cause
A first objection is that the precautionary principle is serious supply shortages (AuBuchon and Petz 2001; Vam-
inconsistent (or incoherent), in that it simultaneously pre- vakas 2011b; Wilson 2011). Candidate precautions against
scribes and forbids certain safety measures. This applies if AIDS and hepatitis C were in the 1980s also rejected with
the precautionary principle undermines its own prescrip- reference to the risk–risk trade-offs they involved, in par-
tions because the very safety measures it prescribes ticular the risk that supplies of donor blood would prove
involve unacceptable hazards (Steel 2015). The precaution- insufficient. The conclusion would be that the precaution-
ary principle then offers contradictory recommendations, ary principle often fails to offer consistent recommenda-
for example, to ban and not ban the use of asbestos in car tions, especially when facing threats to public health.
brakes. Because contradictory recommendations fail to As Daniel Steel points out, though, whether applying
help (or even paralyze) decision making, inconsistency is the precautionary principle leads to inconsistent prescrip-
not just a logical but also a practical flaw (Manson 2002; tions depends not only on (i) the version of the precaution-
Trouwborst 2006; Steel 2015). ary principle that is applied but also on (ii) which
Because we can always envisage some scenario in particular precaution is considered and on (iii) the context
which precautions lead to serious harm, inconsistency is and characteristics of the hazard faced (Steel 2015). Ver-
allegedly inescapable when applying the precautionary sions of the precautionary principle that yield inconsistent
principle (cf. Sunstein 2005). For example, if the precau- results systematically, because they have very permissive
tionary principle required avoiding any risk to transfusion harm and knowledge conditions, should be rejected. But
recipients, then it would oppose maintaining lifetime MSM inconsistency can also result from considering only inap-
deferrals just as much as relaxing them: Maintaining indef- propriately hazardous precautions even though less haz-
inite deferrals may erode prospective donors’ willingness ardous alternatives are available (Goklany 2001; Hansen,
to disclose MSM behavior and thus involves risk too (cf. von Krauss, and Tickner 2008; Steel 2015). When arriving
Food and Drug Administration [FDA] 2015). Applying the at inconsistent recommendations, therefore, decisional
precautionary principle to very implausible or improbable paralysis can be avoided by attempting to identify

36 ajob March, Volume 17, Number 3, 2017


The Precautionary Principle and Risk Tolerability

precautions that can be recommended consistently. If But is this really a new objection? How can following
donor blood is dangerously short in supply, for example, the precautionary principle create more harm than it pre-
partially effective precautions that do not threaten product vents, if consistency already forbids taking precautions
availability can be considered (IOM 1995). Allowing autol- that are unacceptably likely to be unacceptably harmful?
ogous donations for elective surgery and stimulating (mild One obvious possibility is that decision makers fail to rec-
to moderate) hemophiliacs to return to cryoprecipitate3 ognize inconsistency because they simply overlook some
may have been consistent risk-management options when side effects of the precautions they implement. Another
facing AIDS (Feldman and Bayer 1999). Finally, excep- possibility is that decision makers explicitly interpret the
tional circumstances may preclude offering consistent rec- precautionary principle as dismissing the relevance of cer-
ommendations. Even when applying a version of the tain types of harm. If the principle is taken to cover harms
precautionary principle that generally yields consistent to the environment but not harms to the economy, for
prescriptions, no consistent recommendation may in the example, shutting down the economy and blocking inno-
circumstances be derivable because every possible deci- vation may be a consistent way to stop environmental deg-
sion (including doing nothing) involves credible and seri- radation. Also, if the precautionary principle is interpreted
ous risks. This might not be a decisive problem for the as applying to infectious risks of blood transfusion only, it
precautionary principle. There simply might not be a rea- is not inconsistent to implement pathogen inactivation
sonable response when addressing certain risks implies procedures that severely compromise the clinical effective-
introducing equally serious and credible hazards. Some ness of blood products.
(qualitative) difference between risks can usually be identi- These cases can indeed be addressed by reconsidering the
fied, however, and a version of the precautionary principle role of consistency in precautionary decision making. The pre-
that cannot handle every uncertain situation can still have cautionary principle’s susceptibility to inconsistency, while
practical value (cf. Saner 2002; Steel 2015). previously identified as a problem, can be exploited to halt the
The preceding discussion has clear implications for rash introduction of inconsistent precautions and to force deci-
what risks should be tolerated even on the precautionary sion makers to consider less hazardous alternatives (e.g., Steel
principle. To avoid systematic inconsistency, first, the pre- 2015). Candidate precautions should be explicitly checked for
cautionary principle can only apply to hazards that meet consistency by applying the precautionary principle to its
certain minimal conditions of plausibility and seriousness. own recommendations; precautions that fail this check are
Thus, taking precautions against implausible or mild haz- likely to cause more harm than they prevent and should not
ards cannot be justified by appeal to the precautionary be implemented. Such a check is particularly potent if the pre-
principle. Second, relatively serious and credible risks may cautionary principle is taken to cover various types of harm
have to be tolerated if effective precautions would them- (cf. Sandin et al. 2002; Munthe 2011; see also later discussion
selves pose equally serious and credible risks—some level in fourth section). Moreover, available knowledge should
of risk must remain even if certain partially effective pre- where possible be exploited to identify bandwidths of credible
cautions can be taken consistently. outcomes or to characterize risks qualitatively (Steel 2015). If
A different type of objection against the precautionary we can be confident that some emerging pathogen will affect
principle is that following it has harmful consequences. It has 0 to 100 immunodeficient transfusion recipients (or that it
been charged to cause harm, for example, by stifling innova- poses an “improbable and small-scale” risk) and that a donor
tion (Holm and Harris 1999; Resnik 2003), by deadlocking the deferral policy will leave 50 to 150 patients without direly
economy (see Trouwborst 2006), and by requiring safety needed emergency care (or that it poses a “credible and seri-
measures that are so expensive that they reduce overall well- ous” risk), for instance, we can conclude that introducing the
being (Nollkaemper 1996; Sandin et al. 2002). Whereas incon- deferral would be inconsistent.
sistency is a logical and pragmatic problem (because the Still, even precautions that pass a serious consistency
prescription to take and not take some precaution is contradic- check may prove counterproductive. The precautionary prin-
tory and fails to guide decision making), these are moral ciple allegedly has worse consequences than traditional deci-
charges referring to undesirable consequences of applying the sion-making approaches, in particular cost–benefit analysis,
precautionary principle. Their most general and forceful point because it rejects risk neutrality (cf. Hansson 1999). Risk neu-
is arguably that the precautionary principle is counterproduc- trality means treating chances with equal expected outcomes
tive, that is, that following it is more harmful than not follow- as equally acceptable, regardless of any differences in the
ing it (and adopting some other decision-making approach probabilities and outcome values that determine their
instead). expected outcomes (Hansson 1999; Munthe 2011). Taking a
1% chance of losing €1000 would, for example, be equivalent
to taking a 100% chance of losing €10. The precautionary prin-
ciple, on the other hand, is on a common interpretation risk
3. Cryoprecipitate had been the preferred blood plasma derivative
averse: It treats losses as more significant than gains and
to stop bleeding in people with clotting disorders until factor VIII focuses on the prevention of relatively large rather than rela-
was mass produced. Because the production of cryoprecipitate tively probable losses (Hansson 1999; Munthe 2011). Meta-
required pooling of fewer donations, it was less likely to transmit phorically speaking, it would advise against taking a 50/50
AIDS than factor VIII concentrate chance of either winning or losing €100 and would prefer a

March, Volume 17, Number 3, 2017 ajob 37


The American Journal of Bioethics

100% chance of losing €10 over a 1% chance of losing €1000 will typically require wasting more false positive donations
(Hansson 1999; Munthe 2011). In accordance with its stress on than testing selectively (based on donors’ risk profiles) or
avoiding strongly negative outcomes, it would sometimes testing pooled donations. This difficulty can be addressed
even require actions with inferior expected outcome values— by requiring that precautions are proportional in a second
introducing moderately harmful safety measures against rela- sense: The more serious and credible the hazards faced, the
tively improbable risks, for example, and banning innovations more effective must precautions be in order to be
that promise to improve the lives of many people but also “adequate” (Trouwborst 2006; Von Schomberg 2012).
pose credible threats (e.g., experimental drugs). If so, follow- Determining when risks are reduced adequately clearly
ing the precautionary principle rather than some risk-neutral requires judgment on when risks are tolerable. This may
decision-making approach will probably be counterproduc- involve comparing the residual risk to an explicit threshold-
tive in the long run. level for tolerable risks, although this threshold should be
The charge that following the precautionary principle sensitive to the specifics of the hazard and the decision-mak-
is counterproductive has been countered by empirical ing context (Von Schomberg 2012). In any case, since pro-
arguments—by enumerating cases where precautionary portionality supports selecting the least harmful precaution
action could have avoided catastrophes (European Envi- that reduces risks to some tolerable level, it forbids extreme
ronment Agency [EEA] 2001; 2013; Steel 2015); by down- risk-intolerance. This shows that the precautionary principle
playing the number or impact of cases where does not forbid temporary MSM deferrals simply because
precautionary measures were taken unnecessarily (Han- they involve some risk; it might be argued that temporary
sen, von Krauss, and Tickner 2008; Hansen and Tickner deferrals reduce risk to a tolerable level while indefinite
2013; Steel 2015); and by pointing out advantageous side deferrals have more harmful side effects. Thus, discussion
effects of precautionary measures, such as impulses to on when risks are tolerable cannot be silenced by invoking
innovation and the economy (Trouwborst 2006). While the the precautionary principle.
question whether specific versions of the precautionary This article does not aim to determine which versions
principle are counterproductive may only be answerable of the precautionary principle meet the above constraints
in the long run, some guidance for particular precaution- when applied to blood safety issues. That would require a
ary policies can be offered. careful and largely empirical account of the hazards,
One obvious strategy is to introduce precautions provi- uncertainties, and candidate precautions faced. The
sionally while monitoring their effects (cf. CEC 2000). Because article’s aim is more abstract: to trace some general criteria
precautions are typically introduced in uncertain times, they for applying the precautionary principle to blood safety
may prove to be unnecessary, ineffective, or unexpectedly that relate to risk tolerance. These criteria can then be used
harmful. Provisional precautions that prove counterproduc- as heuristics when (re)interpreting or applying the precau-
tive over time can be withdrawn, adapted or replaced.4 tionary principle. As we have formulated them, however,
A second strategy to avoid counterproductivity (but that the constraints offered include “harm” as a central con-
is also relevant as a criterion for choosing between overall cept, which must therefore be clarified.
beneficial precautions) is to take proportional precautions.
This requirement has two complementary faces. First, one
should select the least harmful from among adequate or
effective precautions—we should refrain from shooting a fly THE NOTION OF HARM AND THE SCOPE OF THE
with a cannonball, to invoke a common expression, when a PRECAUTIONARY PRINCIPLE
fly swatter would do just as well (Steel 2015). The idea of The notion of “harm” not only figures in the precautionary
“adequacy” is of course conceptually challenging. Alterna- principle itself, but is also central to aforementioned con-
tive safety measures will rarely reduce risks to an exactly straints on that principle’s application. Consistency
equal degree, and safety measures that reduce risk more requires that (a version of) the precautionary principle
effectively do not necessarily dominate less effective safety does not prescribe precautions that it simultaneously for-
strategies, because they may have more objectionable side bids taking, considering the harms they might cause.
effects. For example, testing blood donations for the pres- Avoidance of counterproductivity means that safety meas-
ence of viral RNA or DNA is most effective when per- ures should not cause more harm than they prevent.
formed on all individual donations, but this testing strategy Finally, proportionality advises against taking safety meas-
ures that do more harm than alternative adequate safety
measures, even if they avert more harm than they cause.
4. Note that withdrawing precautions that have proven counter- How “harm” is interpreted is hence crucial for the applica-
productive may be severely complicated by the decision-making tion of (the precautionary principle and) our constraints. If
context. Removing blood safety precautions may expose decision
being deferred from blood donation can be said to harm
makers to liability, may be forbidden by regulations they are
under, or may be politically sensitive (with regard to MSM defer- MSM, then maintaining lifetime MSM deferrals may be
rals, see, e.g., Wilson et al. 2014). Especially if these same pressures disproportionate, counterproductive, or even inconsistent.
encourage precautionary action whenever new infections arise, Similarly, our constraints may forbid implementing expen-
the continuing expansion of the blood safety arsenal is an under- sive blood safety measures if such measures can be consid-
standable consequence. ered harmful qua being costly (see fifth section). The

38 ajob March, Volume 17, Number 3, 2017


The Precautionary Principle and Risk Tolerability

current section therefore discusses the scope of this notion. Given the complexity of natural processes and the ubiquity
By rejecting proposals to equate “harm” with (i) wrongful of human influences, most phenomena should strictly
damage, (ii) human-caused damage, or (iii) damage to the speaking be classified as “mixed”—various phenomena
environment or human health, we end up with a broad non- associated with global warming, for example, depend not
normative concept. only on greenhouse gas emissions but also on environmen-
It is common to distinguish between a normative (or mor- tal feedback mechanisms (Trouwborst 2006). A similar
alized) and a nonnormative sense of “harm.” The nonnorma- point can be made for transfusion-transmissible infections.
tive sense is often spelled out as “loss of welfare” or “setback When a transfusion recipient is infected with HIV and
of interests” (Feinberg 1984; Holtug 2002), but “damage,” develops AIDS, should we say that the blood bank (or the
“injury,” and “negative change” are also nonnormative sub- donor, or the physician who provided the transfusion)
stitutes for “harm” (Trouwborst 2006). “Harm” in the norma- caused his disease or that the virus did and that the blood
tive sense signifies, in addition, that this damage is caused by service merely failed to prevent the infection? We can
wrongful acts or omissions (Feinberg 1984; Holtug 2002). apparently identify the blood service’s failure to screen out
Understanding “harm” in a normative sense may be appro- the infectious donation as the cause only by presupposing
priate in such contexts as criminal law (Feinberg 1984; Holtug that the blood service should reasonably have prevented
2002). Should we also understand “harm” normatively when the infection (Verweij and Kramer 2016). Classifying such
applying the precautionary principle, thus limiting it to dam- harms as either “caused” or “not prevented” is thus hardly
ages that qualify as wrongful, or should we understand it in a morally neutral (cf. Feinberg 1984).
broader nonnormative sense? Finally, the actual application of the precautionary princi-
We do not know any definitions or accounts of the precau- ple employs a wider interpretation of “harm.” Legal docu-
tionary principle that incorporate an explicitly normative ments and international treaties often use “harm”
notion of “harm.” The principle’s scope is sometimes limited interchangeably with “injury,” “damage,” or “adverse effect”
to human-caused damages, however (Ahteensuu 2007; Sandin and do not restrict its use to damages resulting from human
1999), and justifying this restriction in a deontological spirit agency (Trouwborst 2006). Moreover, the precautionary prin-
yields a tacitly normative notion of harm. The precautionary ciple has been invoked to justify precautions against hazards
principle is on a deontological construal an extension of our that seemed primarily natural rather than anthropogenic, for
duty to limit the negative effects of our own (individual and example, the spread of West Nile virus by mosquitos (Tickner
collective) actions; it expresses that this duty also applies 2002). Where the precautionary principle is applied to (pri-
when our actions merely risk causing damage (Hourdequin marily) nonanthropogenic damages, such damages must also
2007; John 2011). Performing hazardous activities without tak- qualify as “harms” when applying our constraints.
ing adequate precautions violates this duty and any damages We thus suggest that the precautionary principle’s notion
that ensue are hence wrongful, but there is no comparable of “harm” should cover nonanthropogenic and nonwrongful
wrong in failing to address hazards that do not derive from damages. Whether some damage, injury, or adverse effect is
our (individual or collective) agency. Precautions that address within the principle’s scope should depend on its seriousness
anthropogenic hazards are therefore easier to justify than pre- and not on its causal background or moral character. There is
cautions that address nonanthropogenic hazards—especially no conceptual ground to exclude “natural” hazards that have
if the precautions concerned are coercive (cf. Jensen 2002). Jus- far-reaching negative consequences from the scope of the pre-
tifying the precautionary principle along these lines suggests cautionary principle. Judging how serious harms are is mor-
that any “harms” it prescribes us to prevent must be anthro- ally sensitive, of course, and anthropogenic harms may be
pogenic, in which case its notion of “harm” would be tacitly particularly serious from a moral perspective. But if a broad
normative. nonnormative interpretation of “harm” is adopted, the rela-
There are good reasons for applying the precautionary tive seriousness of various (potential) harms can be negotiated
principle more broadly, however, and thus for accepting a within the process of applying the precautionary principle.
wider interpretation of its notion of “harm.” First, even if Moreover, restricting attention to environmental or
the prevention of (primarily) anthropogenic harms is con- human health damages is unfounded given that value judg-
sidered especially important, it does not follow that nonan- ments are indispensable when applying the precautionary
thropogenic harms should be ignored altogether. There principle (cf. Saner 2002; Cranor 2004; Ahteensuu 2007).
might be a stricter responsibility to prevent the spread of a Applying the precautionary principle only makes sense if
dangerous contagious disease that has been laboratory we consider certain things worth protecting, and the poten-
bred rather than naturally arisen, for example, but it is per- tial side effects of precautionary measures must be consid-
fectly reasonable to consider precautionary measures in ered less serious (or much less plausible) than damages to
the latter case as well. Even though noncoercive precau- those valuable things. Damages to the environment or
tions will be easier to justify from a nonconsequentialist human health are often particularly serious because they
perspective than coercive alternatives, preventing nonan- involve a noncompensable loss of intrinsic value, but it does
thropogenic damages is at least prima facie right. not follow that even small-scale or mild effects on the envi-
Second, a strict distinction between anthropogenic and ronment or human health are necessarily more serious than
nonanthropogenic damages is difficult to maintain in prac- other harms. While lifetime deferrals do not threaten MSM’s
tice and in principle (Trouwborst 2006; Hourdequin 2007). physical health, for example, they may harm MSM in some

March, Volume 17, Number 3, 2017 ajob 39


The American Journal of Bioethics

other sense (e.g., psychologically), in which case our con- the well-being or interests of more people suffer setbacks,
straints apply. The respective harms to transfusion recipients or those setbacks are more serious, than need have been
and MSM should be balanced with reference to a broader the case. Interventions with high opportunity costs may
account of what makes one more serious than another, even be considered (pro tanto) harmful if they are overall
which must include a discussion on how exclusion from beneficial. Implementing one intervention often means
blood donation affects MSM’s well-being or legitimate inter- that we are no longer in a position to reap the benefits of
ests. One might still conclude such harms involved are some other intervention, potentially with other beneficia-
small compared to the risk of contracting a transfusion- ries. The inherent tragedy of allocating scarce health care
transmissible infection, but at least MSM’s legitimate con- resources is that almost every decision sets back the inter-
cerns will be taken into account. ests or well-being of some people.
The opportunity costs of implementing some precaution
may often be difficult to determine. First, the financial impact
of the precaution itself may be unclear, for example, if price
COSTS AS HARMS
developments of precautionary measures are difficult to fore-
We have argued (in the third section) that avoiding inconsis- cast. Second, it may be unclear how the ability to address other
tency, counterproductivity, and disproportionality requires harms will be affected, in particular because precautionary
tolerating certain risks. How does this affect the question measures may be funded from flexible rather than fixed budg-
whether the precautionary principle sanctions escalating ets. Blood services may, for example, forward the costs of
blood safety expenses? This section argues that precautions additional precautions to hospitals, insurance companies, or
can be considered harmful—and thus inconsistent, counter- funding authorities (such as a ministry of health). In such a
productive, or disproportionate—in virtue of having high scheme, implementing expensive blood safety measures
opportunity costs. The point is not that expensive precautions barely affects blood services’ ability to fund other activities—
are necessarily unjustifiable. Rather, construing costly precau- the financial effects instead spread through the wider health
tions as (pro tanto) harmful allows integrating cost considera- care system, where their impact is more difficult to pinpoint
tions into a precautionary framework: When checking but is real nonetheless (cf. Custer and Hoch 2009). Finally, a
whether particular precautions meet our constraints, the ques- meaningful comparison of alternative interventions may be
tion must be raised of how harmful those precautions are on impossible if their respective costs and benefits are very uncer-
account of their opportunity costs. tain. If it is entirely unclear whether some serious infection is
Donor blood safety measures are in most Western coun- transfusion-transmissible and how many patients would be at
tries funded collectively, for example by taxation schemes or risk, for example, precautions against transfusion-transmis-
health insurance. Because resources are necessarily limited, sion of that infection are difficult to compare against alterna-
however, allocating more resources to one service (e.g., blood tive interventions against serious health risks.
safety measures) means that less resources are available for Uncertainty is rarely this absolute, however (cf. the sec-
other services (e.g., cancer research or collectively funded ond and third sections of this article). It may be possible to
orphan drugs). Choosing which services to make available judge that the resources required to address one hazard
and which not to fund is therefore inevitable. The notion of could be used to address more serious risks or harms
“opportunity costs” applies when choosing to expend resour- instead. One important conclusion is that the precautionary
ces on one intervention or program means forgoing the oppor- principle does not justify blood safety measures with very
tunity to fund and reap the benefits of alternative unfavorable cost-effectiveness ratios—which sometimes
interventions (Custer and Hoch 2009; Custer and Janssen exceed €1,000,000 per quality-adjusted life-year saved (e.g.,
2015). It refers to the benefits thus forgone, which can be non- Borkent-Raven et al. 2012). While cost-effectiveness calcula-
monetary and can include (e.g.) lives or QALYs (quality- tions do involve some uncertainty, the cost-effectiveness
adjusted life years) lost (Custer and Hoch 2009; Custer and ratios of some blood safety measures are unfavorable on all
Janssen 2015). Thus, while opportunity costs are generally a plausible estimates, which means that allocating health care
function of monetary costs—because the monetary costs of an funds differently would most likely prevent more harm.
intervention determine which benefits of alternative interven- Unless transfusion-transmitted infections can be considered
tions have to be forgone due to a lack of financial resources— especially serious from an ethical point of view (cf. Verweij
they need not be costs in the monetary sense. and Kramer 2016), such blood safety measures cannot be
Interventions can arguably be harmful in a nonnorma- recommended consistently and will probably prove counter-
tive sense qua having high opportunity costs.5 This is clear- productive. Another conclusion is that relatively expensive
est if the intervention that must be forgone would have precautions can be considered disproportionate when
prevented mortality or significant morbidity. If alternative cheaper adequate alternatives are available. In the Nether-
interventions would have secured more lives or health lands, for example, testing donor blood against exotic infec-
benefits than the interventions actually implemented, then tions such as West Nile virus, Chikungunya, and Chagas is
currently considered disproportionate because the universal
5. Some allocations of public health care funds may even be 4-week deferral of donors who traveled outside Europe ade-
wrongful and thus harmful in a normative sense. We do not pur- quately reduces risks at lower costs (and with an acceptable
sue this thought here, however. impact on supply).

40 ajob March, Volume 17, Number 3, 2017


The Precautionary Principle and Risk Tolerability

Such examples cannot conceal that our constraints leave Alter, H. J. 2008. Pathogen reduction: A precautionary principle
various issues open to interpretation: how serious the hazards paradigm. Transfusion Medicine Reviews 22 (2):97–102.
addressed by alternative interventions are, for example, and Alter, H. J., R. H. Purcell, P. V. Holland, et al. 1981. Donor trans-
when precautions can be considered adequate. Normative aminase and recipient hepatitis: Impact on blood transfusion serv-
views will affect how such issues are decided, so applying our ices. Journal of the American Medical Association 246 (6):630–34.
constraints requires normative argumentation no less than
AuBuchon, J. P., and L. D. Petz. 2001. Making decisions to improve
applying the precautionary principle itself does. Still, our con-
transfusion safety. In Policy alternatives in transfusion medicine, ed. J.
straints, the broad analysis of “harm,” and the notion of
P. AuBuchon, L. D. Petz, and A. Fink, 193–226. Bethesda, MD:
opportunity costs offer useful resources for normative discus-
American Association of Blood Banks.
sions on precaution and its price.
Blood Products Advisory Committee. 2009. Transcript of 94th meeting.
Available at: http://www.fda.gov/advisorycommittees/committees
meetingmaterials/bloodvaccinesandotherbiologics/bloodproductsad
CONCLUSION
visorycommittee/default.htm (accessed March 29, 2016).
The precautionary principle does not support zero toler-
Borkent-Raven, B. A., M. P. Janssen, C. L. van der Poel, et al. 2012.
ance for transfusion risks: Blood safety precautions that
Cost-effectiveness of additional blood screening tests in the Neth-
are inconsistent, counterproductive, or disproportionate in
erlands. Transfusion 52:478–88.
view of their side effects should be forgone. Nor can the
precautionary principle be invoked to dismiss considera- Commission of the European Communities. 2000. Communication
tions like the interests of MSM and the costs of safety. The from the commission on the precautionary principle. Available at:
precautionary principle only supports focusing on the pre- http://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal-content/EN/ALL/?
vention of transfusion-transmissible infections, while uriDCELEX:52000DC0001 (accessed March 29, 2016).
downplaying the relevance of other types of harm, on the Cranor, C. F. 2004. Toward understanding aspects of the
presupposition that transfusion-transmissible infections precautionary principle. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 29:
are somehow especially serious. This presupposition can- 259–79.
not be taken for granted without misapplying the precau- Custer, B., and J. S. Hoch. 2009. Cost-effectiveness analysis: What
tionary principle. Rather, the importance of blood safety it really means for transfusion medicine decision making. Transfu-
should be debated frankly and critically. sion Medicine Reviews 23 (1):1–12.
Custer, B., and M. P. Janssen. 2015. Health economics and out-
comes methods in risk-based decision-making for blood safety.
FUNDING Transfusion 55:2039–47.
Dodd, R. Y. 2010. Prions and precautions: Be careful for what you
This work was funded by Sanquin Blood Supply Founda- ask. Transfusion 50:956–8.
tion, a not-for-profit organization.
Epstein, J. S., H. W. Jaffe, H. J. Alter, et al. 2013. Blood system
changes since recognition of transfusion-associated AIDS: Blood
system changes since AIDS. Transfusion 53:2365–74.
CONFLICT OF INTEREST
European Environment Agency. 2001. Late lessons from early warn-
ings: The precautionary principle, 1896–2000, ed. P. Harremo€es et al.
The authors declare that they have no conflicts of interest
Luxembourg: Office for Official Publications of the European
relevant to this article. &
Communities.
European Environment Agency. 2013. Late lessons from early warn-
REFERENCES ings: Science, precaution, innovation, ed. D. Gee, et al. Luxembourg:
Publications Office of the European Union.
Ahteensuu, M. 2007. Rationale for taking precautions: Normative
choices and commitments in the implementation of the precau- Farrell A-M. 2012. The politics of blood: Ethics, innovation and the regula-
tionary principle. Risk & Rationalities (Conference Proceedings), tion of risk [eBook]. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Queens’ College, Cambridge, UK. Available at: http://www.kent. Farrugia, A. 2002. The regulatory pendulum in transfusion medi-
ac.uk/scarr/events/ahteensuu.pdf (accessed December 18, 2014). cine. Transfusion Medicine Reviews 16 (4):273–82.
Ahteensuu, M., and P. Sandin. 2012. The precautionary principle. In Federal Drug Administration. 2015. Revised recommendations for
Handbook of risk theory, ed. S. Roeser, R. Hillerbrand, P. Sandin, et al., reducing the risk of human immunodeficiency virus transmission by
961–78. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer. Available at: http:// blood and blood products. Available at: http://www.fda.gov/down
www.springerlink.com/index/10.1007/978-94-007-1433-5_38 loads/BiologicsBloodVaccines/GuidanceComplianceRegulator
Alliance of Blood Operators. 2015. Risk-based decision-making yInformation/Guidances/Blood/UCM446580.pdf (accessed
framework for blood safety. Available at: https://allianceofbloo March 29, 2016).
doperators.org/media/115522/rbdm-framework-2-april-2015- Feinberg, J. 1984. The moral limits of the criminal law volume I: Harm
v11-for-website.pdf to others. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

March, Volume 17, Number 3, 2017 ajob 41


The American Journal of Bioethics

Feldman, E. A., and R. Bayer (eds.). 1999. Blood feuds: AIDS, blood, Menitove, J. E., J. L. Bennett, P. Tomasulo, et al. 2014. How safe is
and the politics of medical disaster. Oxford, UK: Oxford University safe enough, who decides and how? From a zero-risk paradigm to
Press. risk-based decision making. Transfusion 54 (3pt2):753–57.
Forland F., H. De Carvalho Gomes, H. Nokleby, et al. 2012. Appli- Munthe, C. 2011. The price of precaution and the ethics of risk (eBook).
cability of evidence-based practice in public health: Risk assess- Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.
ment on Q fever under an ongoing outbreak. Euro Surveillance 17 Moreno, J. D. 2003. “Creeping precautionism” and the blood sup-
(3):1–6. ply. Transfusion 43:840–42.
Galarneau C. 2010. Blood donation, deferral, and discrimination: Nollkaemper, A. 1996. ‘What you risk reveals what you value,’
FDA donor deferral policy for men who have sex with men. Ameri- and other dilemmas encountered in the legal assaults on risks. In
can Journal of Bioethics 10:29–39. The precautionary principle and international law, ed. D. Freestone
Goklany, I. M. 2001. The precautionary principle: A critical appraisal of and E. Hey, 73–94. The Hague, The Netherlands: Kluwer Law
environmental risk assessment. Washington, DC: Cato Institute. International.
Hansen, S. F., and J. A. Tickner. 2013. The precautionary principle Pereira, A. 2008. Risk management. In Transfusion microbiology, ed.
and false alarms—Lessons learned. In Late lessons from early warn- J. A. J. Barbara, F. A. M. Regan, and M. C. Contreras, 341–61. Cam-
ings: Science, precaution, innovation, ed. D. Gee, P. Grandjean, S. F. bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Hansen, et al., 17–45. Copenhagen, Denmark: European Environ- Resnik, D. B. 2003. Is the precautionary principle unscientific?
ment Agency. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences
Hansen S. F., M. K. von Krauss, and J. A. Tickner. 2008. The pre- 34 (2):329–44.
cautionary principle and risk–risk tradeoffs. Journal of Risk Sandin, P. 1999. Dimensions of the precautionary principle.
Research 11 (4):423–64. Human and Ecological Risk Assessment: An International Journal 5
Hansson, S. O. 1999. Adjusting scientific practices to the precaution- (5):889–907.
ary principle. Human and Ecological Risk Assessment 5 (5):909–21. Sandin, P. 2004. The precautionary principle and the concept of
Hartzell-Nichols, L. 2013. From “the” precautionary principle to precaution. Environmental Values 13 (4):461–75.
precautionary principles. Ethics, Policy & Environment 16 (3):308– Sandin, P., M. Peterson, S. O. Hansson, et al. 2002. Five charges
20. against the precautionary principle. Journal of Risk Research 5 (4):
Hayenhjelm, M., and J. Wolff. 2012. The moral problem of risk 287–99.
impositions: A survey of the literature. European Journal of Philoso- Saner, M. A. 2002. An ethical analysis of the precautionary princi-
phy 20:E26–51. ple. International Journal of Biotechnology 4 (1):81–95.
Hergon, E., G. Moutel, N. Duchange, et al. 2005. Risk management Schippers, E. I. 2014. Ministerieel plan bloedvoorziening 2015–
in transfusion after the HIV blood contamination crisis in France: 2017. Available at: http://www.tweedekamer.nl/kamerstukken/
The impact of the precautionary principle. Transfusion Medicine detail?idD2014D32795 (accessed March 29, 2016).
Reviews 19 (4):273–80.
Science and Environmental Health Network. 1998. Wingspread
Holm, S., and J. Harris. 1999. Precautionary principle stifles dis- statement on the precautionary principle. Available at: http://
covery. Nature 400:396. www.sehn.org/wing.html (accessed March 29, 2016).
Holtug, N. 2002. The harm principle. Ethical Theory and Moral Prac- Steel, D. 2015. Philosophy and the precautionary principle: Science, evidence,
tice 5 (4):357–89. and environmental policy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Hourdequin, M. 2007. Doing, allowing, and precaution. Environ- Stoto, M. A. 2006. The precautionary principle and emerging bio-
mental Ethics 29 (4):339–58. logic risks: Lessons from human immunodeficiency virus in blood
Institute of Medicine. 1995. HIV and the blood supply: An analysis of products. Seminars in Hematology 43:S10–2.
crisis decisionmaking. Washington, DC: Institute of Medicine Sunstein, C. R. 2005. Laws of fear: Beyond the precautionary principle.
National Academy Press. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Jensen, K. K. 2002. The moral foundation of the precautionary Tickner, J. A. 2002. The precautionary principle and public health
principle. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 15:39–55. trade-offs: Case study of West Nile virus. Annals of the American
John, S. D. 2011. Risk and precaution. In Public health ethics, ed. A. Academy of Political and Social Science 584:69–79.
Dawson, 67–84. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Trouwborst, A. 2006. Precautionary right and duties of states. Boston,
Krever, H. 1997. Final report: Commission of inquiry on the blood sys- MA: Martinus Nijhof.
tem in Canada. Ottawa, ON, Canada: Canadian Government Turner, M. L. 2006. Transfusion safety with regards to prions: Ethi-
Publishing. cal, legal and societal considerations. Transfusion Clinique et Biolo-
Leiss W., M. Tyshenko, and D. Krewski. 2008. Men having sex gique 13 (5):317–19.
with men donor deferral risk assessment: An analysis using risk United Nations Environment Programme. 1992. Rio declaration on
management principles. Transfusion Medicine Reviews 22:35–57. environment and development. Available at: http://www.unep.org/
Manson, N. A. 2002. Formulating the precautionary principle. documents.multilingual/default.asp?doc
Environmental Ethics 24 (3):263–74. umentidD78&articleidD1163 (accessed March 29, 2016).

42 ajob March, Volume 17, Number 3, 2017


The Precautionary Principle and Risk Tolerability

Vamvakas, E. C., S. Kleinman, H. Hume, et al. 2006. The devel- Von Schomberg, R. 2012. The precautionary principle: Its use within
opment of West Nile virus safety policies by Canadian Blood hard and soft law. European Journal of Risk Regulation 2:147–56.
Services: Guiding principles and a comparison between Can- Wilson, K. 2011. A framework for applying the precautionary principle
ada and the United States. Transfusion Medicine Reviews 20 to transfusion safety. Transfusion Medicine Reviews 25 (3):177–83.
(2):97–109.
Wilson, K., K. Atkinson, and J. Keelan. 2014. Three decades of
Vamvakas, E. C. 2011a. Relative risk of reducing the lifetime blood MSM donor deferral policies: What have we learned? International
donation deferral for men who have had sex with men versus cur- Journal of Infectious Diseases 18:1–3.
rently tolerated transfusion risks. Transfusion Medicine Reviews
Wilson, K., I. Graham, M. Ricketts, et al. 2007. Variant
25:47–60.
Creutzfeldt–Jakob disease and the Canadian blood system
Vamvakas, E. C. 2011b. Decision making in transfusion medicine. after the tainted blood tragedy. Social Science & Medicine 64
Bethesda, MD: American Association of Blood Banks. (1):174–85.
Verweij, M. F., and K. Kramer, 2016. Donor blood screening and Wilson, K., M. Wilson, P. C. Hebert, et al. 2003. The application of
moral responsibility: How safe should blood be? Journal of Medical the precautionary principle to the blood system: The Canadian
Ethics. Published Online First: February 11, 2016. doi:10.1136/ blood system’s vCJD donor deferral policy. Transfusion Medicine
medethics-2015-103338 Reviews 17 (2):89–94.

March, Volume 17, Number 3, 2017 ajob 43

You might also like