Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 5

Device-independent certification of non-classical measurements via causal models

Ciarán M. Lee1, ∗
1
Department of Physics and Astronomy, University College London, Gower Street, London WC1E 6BT, UK
Quantum measurements are crucial for quantum technologies and give rise to some of the most
classically counter-intuitive quantum phenomena. As such, the ability to certify the presence of
genuinely non-classical measurements in a device-independent fashion is vital. However, previous
work has either been non-device-independent, or has relied on post-selection. In the case of entan-
glement, the post-selection approach applies an entangled measurement to independent states and
post-selects the outcome, inducing non-classical correlations between the states that can be device-
independently certified using a Bell inequality. That is, it certifies measurement non-classicality
not by what it is, but by what it does. This paper remedies this discrepancy by providing a novel
notion of what measurement non-classicality is, which, in analogy with Bell’s theorem, corresponds
to measurement statistics being incompatible with an underlying classical causal model. It is shown
arXiv:1806.10895v1 [quant-ph] 28 Jun 2018

that this provides a more fine-grained notion of non-classicality than post-selection, as it certifies
the presence of non-classicality that cannot be revealed by examining post-selected outcomes alone.

Quantum measurements are a key resource behind theorem. The modern treatment of which utilises the
most quantum technologies [1] and, moreover, they re- classical causal model framework to unify Bell’s original
veal some of the most startling non-classical features of assumptions [9–11]. Composite states are thus said to
quantum theory [2, 3]. Indeed, performing joint quan- be non-classical if the correlations generated by locally
tum measurements on composite systems is a key fea- measuring each composite system are inconsistent with
ture behind quantum teleportation, superdense coding, an underlying classical causal model.
metrology, cryptography [4], quantum repeaters [1], and This paper remedies the discrepancy between the
quantum networks more generally. Hence the ability treatment of non-classicality in quantum states and mea-
to certify the non-classical nature of quantum measure- surements. In analogy with Bell’s theorem, a joint quan-
ments is vitally important for the functioning of quantum tum measurement is said to be non-classical if the cor-
technology and additionally, for understanding some of relations generated by performing it on local prepara-
the fundamental differences between quantum and clas- tions on each composite system are inconsistent with an
sical physics. Moreover, as the manufacturers of quan- underlying classical causal model. In the following sec-
tum measurement devices may not always be trusted, tion this classical causal model is introduced and a non-
such certifications should be device-independent. That linear inequality on any distribution generated by it is
is, they should rely only on output measurement statis- derived. Violation of this inequality entails that the ob-
tics rather than any intrinsic quantum properties, such served correlations are in conflict with the classical causal
as knowledge of the underlying Hilbert space dimension. model. As the inequality depends only on observed out-
Previous work on the certification of quantum mea- put statistics, it is manifestly device-independent. Ad-
surements falls into two categories. The first uses wit- ditionally, it will be demonstrated that this inequality
nesses to certify the presence of non-classical measure- provides a finer-grained notion of joint measurement non-
ments [5–7], but is manifestly not device-independent. classicality for general quantum measurements than the
The second is device-independent, but requires post- post-selection approach of Ref. [8], discussed above, as
selection to certify the presence of a quantum measure- it certifies the presence of non-classicality that cannot
ment [8]. In the case of entanglement, such certifica- be revealed by examining correlations arising from post-
tion is accomplished by exploiting the fact that applying selecting the outcomes of measurement alone.
an entangled measurement to two initially independent Certifying non-classical measurements.— Recently,
entangled states and post-selecting the outcome induces tools and techniques from the classical causal models
entanglement between the states, which can then be cer- framwork have begun to see myriad applications in quan-
tified device-independently by violating a Bell inequal- tum information [9–16][26]. In this framework, the in-
ity. This method hence detects quantum measurements puts and outputs of agents measurement and prepara-
through their action on states. That is, it certifies an tion devices are represented by nodes in directed acyclic
entangled measurement through what is does, not what graphs (DAGs), with the arrows denoting the causal re-
it is. This is in stark contrast with entangled states, lationship between nodes. The structure of each DAG
whose non-classicality is easily certified through the vio- encodes conditional independence relations [27] among
lation of a Bell inequality. Such violation implies a denial the nodes. For instance, the no-signalling conditions
of (at least one of) the assumptions underlying Bell’s P (A|X, Y ) = P (A|X), and P (B|X, Y ) = P (B|Y ), fol-
low directly [9] from the structure of the DAG from in
Fig.1. Indeed, the sructure of the DAG specifies all the
conditional independences between the nodes [17, 18]. In
∗ Electronic address: ciaran.lee@ucl.ac.uk short, every relation between the inputs and outputs of
2

Result 1. A distribution P (a, b, c0 c1 |x, y) generated by


the DAG of Fig. 1 satisfies:
p p
|M | + |N ≤ 1,
1 0 1 1
P P
with M = 4 xy hAx By C i, N = 4 xy hAx By C i, and
X
hAx By C i i = (−1)a+b+ci P (a, b, c0 c1 |x, y).
abc0 c1

Note that, in contrast to standard Bell inequalities,


FIG. 1: DAG representing classical causal model the inequality presented above is non-linear in the joint
distribution P (a, b, c0 c1 |x, y). This is due to the indepen-
dence of Alice and Bob’s preparations.
the different agents are specified by the DAG. The proof of Result 1 is similar to the derivation of
Consider three agents Alice, Bob, and Charlie. Al- the bilocality inequality from Ref. [19], with a few keys
ice and Bob both have devices which prepare a quantum differences. First, in the case considered here, the hidden
state from some ensemble of states, given a choice be- variables can a priori depend on the choice of prepara-
tween different ensembles. Charlie has a measurement tion. That is, it does not follow from the DAG of Fig. 1
device which jointly measures the states prepared by Al- that P (λ1 |x) = P (λ1 ). Lastly, Alice and Bob have prepa-
ice and Bob. The actions of these devices are represented ration devices, rather than measurement devices.
in a black-box manner. Alice and Bob’s devices have a Proof. Given the structure of the DAG from Fig 1, it
classical input x, y (the choice of different ensembles) re- follows that P (a, b, c0 c1 |x, y) decomposes as
spectively, and a classical output a, b (the state prepared)
respectively. Here it is assumed that a, b, x, y ∈ {0, 1}. ZZ
Charlie has no classical input, as his device only performs dλ1 dλ2 P (a|x)P (b|y)P (c0 c1 |λ1 λ1 )P (λ1 |x)P (λ2 |y).
a single measurement, but has a classical output C index-
ing the possible measurement outcomes. It is assumed in Define hAx i = Pa (−1)a P (a|x), hBy i = b (−1)a P (b|y),
P P
this section that C takes four values and hence is indexed and hC i iλ1 λ2 = c0 c1 (−1)ci P (c0 c1 |λ1 λ2 ). It follows from
by two bits, C = c0 c1 ∈ {00, 01, 10, 11}. Preparing and
the above decomposition that one can write hAx By C i i as
measuring states in this manner gives rise to a conditional
probability distribution P (a, b, c0 c1 |x, y). ZZ
In analogy with Bell’s theorem, a classical model for dλ1 dλ2 hAx ihBy ihC i iλ1 λ2 P (λ1 |x)P (λ2 |y).
P (a, b, c0 c1 |x, y) is described by the DAG in Fig. 1, where
λ1 , λ2 are unobserved, independent random variables. If
the correlations generated by performing Charlie’s mea- This, together with |hC i iλ1 λ2 | ≤ 1, implies
surement on Alice and Bob’s preparations are consis-
tent with the DAG of Fig. 1, then they are said to Z
|hA0 iP (λ1 |0) + hA1 iP (λ1 |1)|

be classical. That is, they are mediated by the hid- |M | ≤ dλ1 ·
den random variables λ1 , λ2 . One might wonder why 2
Z 
there are two hidden variables, rather than one. This |hB0 iP (λ2 |0) + hB1 iP (λ2 |1)|
· dλ2 .
is due to the independence
P of Alice and Bob’s devices: 2
P (a, b|x, y) = c0 c1 P (a, b, c0 c1 |x, y) = P (a|x)P (b|y). If
the correlations between Alice, Bob, and Charlie were 0 0
√ |N |. For
One can similarly bound
√ √ z, w, z , w ≥
√ any real
mediated by a single hidden variable, then Alice and 0 0 0
0, the inequality zw+ z w ≤ z + z w + w is valid0
Bob’s marginal distribution would not be independent. [19]. Hence

sZ  
p p |hA0 iP (λ1 |0) + hA1 iP (λ1 |1)| |hA0 iP (λ1 |0) − hA1 iP (λ1 |1)|
|M | + |N ≤ dλ1 + ·
2 2
sZ  
|hB0 iP (λ2 |0) + hB1 iP (λ2 |1)| |hB0 iP (λ2 |0) − hB1 iP (λ2 |1)|
· dλ2 +
2 2
sZ sZ
   
≤ dλ1 max |hA0 iP (λ1 |0)|, hA1 iP (λ1 |1) · dλ2 max |hB0 iP (λ2 |0)|, hB1 iP (λ2 |1) ≤ 1 
3

The bound from Result 1 can be classically saturated. ments through their action on states, by showing that
To see this, consider the following. Let x, y be inde- for each fixed measurement outcome the induced corre-
pendent, uniformly distributed random bits. Let Alice’s lations are non-classical. In the current work a novel
(Bob’s) device output a = x⊕1 (b = y ⊕1) with probabil- method has been introduced which certifies general mea-
ity one, and let λ1 (λ2 ) equal a ⊕ 1 (b ⊕ 1) with probabil- surement non-classicality not through what it does, but
ity one. Let Charlie have two independent and identically what it is. These two approaches coincide for entangled
distributed random bits µ0 and µ1 . When both µ0 and µ1 measurements [8], but do they coincide for general non-
equal zero, Charlie’s device outputs (c0 , c1 ) = (λ1 ⊕λ2 , ν) classical measurements? That is, if a measurement is
with probability one, where ν is another random bit. non-classical in the sense that it violates the inequality
When µ0 and µ1 equal one, Charlie’s device outputs from Result 1, are the correlations induced between Alice
(c0 , c1 ) = (ν, λ1 ⊕ λ2 ) with probability one. When and Bob’s devices on post-selection of Charlie’s outcome
µ0 6= µ1 Charlie’s device outputs (c0 , c1 ) = (λ1 , λ2 , ) always non-classical? It will now be shown that, surpris-
with probability one. When µ0 = µ1 = 0 it follows by ingly, the existence of a separate classical model for each
a straightforward calculation that M = 1 and N = 0, post-selected measurement outcome does not imply the
and when µ0 = µ1 = 1, M = 0 and N = 1. In all measurement is classical in the sense of Fig. 1.
remaining cases M = N = 0. As the probability that Note that given the realisations of Alice and Bob’s de-
µ0 = µ1 = 0 is r2 and the probability that µ0 = µ1 = 1 vices involving steering using projective measurements on
is (1 − r)2 , where r = P (µ0 = 0) = P (µ1 = 0), all points an ancilla, introduced in the previous section, it follows
2 2
p N ) =p(r , (1 − r) ) can be achieved. The boundary
(M, that non-classical correlations between Alice and Bob’s
|M | + |N = 1 is thus classically saturated. preparation devices are equivalent to non-classical corre-
Quantum violation.— Recall that Alice and Bob’s de- lations between projective measurements performed on
vices prepare a state from an ensemble of two states, their ancillas.
given a choice between two possible ensembles. A simple Now, consider the following. Allow Charlie to perform
quantum realisation of Alice’s (Bob’s) device is to pre- a noisy Bell state measurement with noise parameter p
pare a maximally entangled |ψ − i state between Alice’s and post-select on an arbitrary fixed outcome. If Alice
(Bob’s) system and an ancilla, and perform a measure- and Bob each have their own Bell state, then Cahrlie’s
ment on the ancilla to prepare a state on Alice’s (Bob’s) joint measurement on two of their systems induces a noisy
system. Given two distinct measurements that can be Bell state—with the same noise parameter p—between
performed on the ancilla, there are two distinct ensembles Alice and Bob’s ancilla. For instance, if Charlie post-
of states to which Alice’s (Bob’s) system can be steered. selects outcome E00 = p|ψ − ihψ − | + (1 − p)I/4, then Alice
The specific measurement outcome prepares a fixed state and Bob’s ancilla will be in the p|ψ − ihψ − | + (1 − p)I/4
from the ensemble associated with that measurement. state. Hence, classically simulating Charlie’s joint noisy
Now, consider the correlations generated by perform- Bell measurement on Alice and Bob’s preparations is
ing either (σZ + σX )/2 (for x = y = 0) or (σZ − σX )/2 equivalent to classically simulating local projective mea-
(for x = y = 1) on Alice and Bob’s ancilla and perform- surements on Alice and Bob’s ancilla’s in the induced
ing a ‘noisy’ Bell state measurement on Charlie’s sys- noisy Bell state. As shown in [20], such correlations can
tem {Ec0 c1 }, where Ec0 c1 = p|ψc0 c1 ihψc0 c1 | + (1 − p)I/4, be classically simulated for p < 0.66. But, as shown in
where {|ψ00 ihψ00 |, |ψ01 ihψ01 |, |ψ10 ihψ10 |, |ψ11 ihψ11 |} is the previous section, the non-post-selected measurement
P Bell state measurement. As Ec0 c1 ≥ 0, ∀c0 c1 , and
the is non-classical as long as p > 1/2. To summarise, the
c0 c1 Ec0 c1 = I, it is a valid measurement. The correla- following has been shown:
tions generated here are the same as those considered in
Section III A of Ref. [19], namely: Result 2. The existence of a separate classical model for
each measurement outcome—adhering to the constraints
P (a, b, c0 c1 |x, y) = imposed by Fig. 1—does not imply the measurement is
1
 n (−1)c0 + (−1)x+y+c1 o classical in the sense of Fig. 1.
1 + p(−1)a+b .
16 2
An intuitive explanation of this result could be that, as
p p √
From this one obtains |M | + |N = 2p, providing a Charlie’s measurements outcomes can overlap on certain
quantum violation for p > 1/2. states, classical models for each individual measurement
Post-selection.— Ref. [8] demonstrated that the pres- outcome cannot always be combined consistently.
ence of an entangled measurement can be certified in Generalisation to n systems and 2k outcomes.— The
an device-independent fashion using post-selection. This inequality from Result 1 will now be generalised to al-
was achieved by exploiting the fact that performing an low for n systems, k choices for the each preparation
entangled measurement on two initially independent en- device—each of which have two possible outcomes—and
tangled states and post-selecting the outcome induces 2k possible outcomes for Charlie’s joint measurement, in-
entanglement between the states, which can then be cer- dexed using k bits c0 · · · ck−1 . Result 1 corresponds to the
tified device-independently by violating a Bell inequal- n = k = 2 case. As before, the classical causal model is
ity. This method hence detects entangled measure- depicted in Fig. 2.
4

 i1/n
· · · + hAjk−1 ip(λj |k − 1) − hAj0 ip(λj |0) dλj .

The following upper bound holds:

1  j j

hA0 ip(λj |0) + hA1 ip(λj |1) +

2 
· · · + hAjk−1 ip(λj |k − 1) − hAj0 ip(λj |0) ≤ k − 1.

Hence, one has
FIG. 2: DAG for composite joint measurement n Z
Y 1/n
n
S≤ (k − 1) dλj =k−1 
j=1
Result 3. A distribution
Conclusion.— This paper has introduced a novel no-
P (a1 , . . . , an c0 · · · ck−1 |x1 , . . . , xn ), tion of non-classicality for joint quantum measurements.
This notion took its cue from Bell’s theorem and the
with ai , cj ∈ {0, 1} and xi ∈ {0, . . . , k − 1}, generated by
device-independent certification of entangled quantum
the DAG of Fig. 2 satisfies the following inequality:
states by stipulating a joint quantum measurement to be
k−1
X non-classical if the correlations generated by performing
1/n it on local preparations are inconsistent with an under-
S := |Ii | ≤ k − 1,
i=0 lying classical causal model. A non-linear inequality was
then derived as a witness for this inconsistency: a vi-
Pi+1
where, Ii = 21n x1 ,...,xn =i hA1x1 · · · Anxn C i i, for i ranging olation entails non-classicality. This inequality bounded
from 0 to P k − 1, with Aik = −Ai0 and hA1x1 · · · Anxn By i = the classically generated correlations achievable with this
P bi + nj=1 aj P (a , . . . , a c · · · c
causal model. In future work it would be interesting to
(−1) 1 n 0 k−1 |x1 , . . . , xn ). investigate the corresponding bounds for LOCC, unen-
Proof. Given the decomposition of the distribution tangled, and entangled measurements, as was done in
over the agents preparations and Charlie’s measurement, the semi-device independent case by Ref.’s [5, 6].
Moreover, this approach was shown to provide a
P (a1 , . . . , an c0 · · · ck−1 |x1 , . . . , xn ), more fine-rained notion of non-classicality than the post-
selection method of Ref. [8]. That is, there exists quan-
implied by the structure of Fig 2, it follows that tum measurements which admit a classical hidden vari-
able model for each post-selected measurement outcome,
n  Z X n
Y 1 
but which are nevertheless non-classical and violate the
|Ii | ≤ hAjxj ip(λj |xj ) dλj ,

2
inequality from Result 1. It would be interesting to de-
j=1 x =1 j
termine if a quantum protocol exhibiting an information-
theoretic advantage due to this discrepancy existed. That
where hAjxj i = aj (−1)aj P (aj |xj ).
P
is, can an agent with access to the entire collection of cor-
It was shown in Ref. [21] that, for cki ∈ R+ and m, n ∈ relations generated by a quantum measurement gain an
N, the following holds: advantage over an agent who only has access to a post-
m Y
n i+1
selected subset of those correlations?
1/n
X
cki ≤
Y
c1i + c2i + · · · + xm
1/n
. In future work, connections between the notion of non-
i
i=1 i=1
classicality introduced here and that of contexuality dis-
k=1
cussed in Ref. [11] will be explored.
Applying this result to S =
Pk−1 1/n
|Ii | yields Acknowledgements.— CML thanks Dan Browne for
i=0
helpful discussions and J. J. Barry for encouragement.
hYn Z
1  j This work was supported by the EPSRC through the
j
S≤ hA0 ip(λj |0) + hA1 ip(λj |1) + · · · UCL Doctoral Prize Fellowship.

j=1
2

[1] N. Sangouard, C. Simon, H. De Riedmatten, and [2] C. Branciard, N. Gisin, and S. Pironio, “Characterizing
N. Gisin, “Quantum repeaters based on atomic ensembles the nonlocal correlations created via entanglement swap-
and linear optics,” Reviews of Modern Physics, vol. 83, ping,” Phys. Rev. Lett., vol. 104, no. 170401, 2010.
no. 1, p. 33, 2011. [3] M. D. Mazurek, M. F. Pusey, R. Kunjwal, K. J. Resch,
5

and R. W. Spekkens, “An experimental test of non- states,” Physical Review A, vol. 73, no. 6, p. 062105,
contextuality without unphysical idealizations,” Nature 2006.
communications, vol. 7, p. ncomms11780, 2016. [21] A. Tavakoli, P. Skrzypczyk, D. Cavalcanti, and A. Acı́n,
[4] C. M. Lee and M. J. Hoban, “Towards device- “Nonlocal correlations in the star-network configura-
independent information processing on general quan- tion,” Physical Review A, vol. 90, no. 062109, 2014.
tum networks,” Physical Review Letters, vol. 120, no. 2, [22] C. M. Lee and J. H. Selby, “Deriving grover’s lower bound
p. 020504, 2018. from simple physical principles,” New Journal of Physics,
[5] T. Vértesi and M. Navascués, “Certifying entangled mea- vol. 18, no. 093047, 2016.
surements in known hilbert spaces,” Physical Review A, [23] C. M. Lee and J. H. Selby, “A no-go theorem for theories
vol. 83, no. 6, p. 062112, 2011. that decohere to quantum mechanics,” arXiv preprint
[6] A. Bennet, T. Vértesi, D. J. Saunders, N. Brunner, and arXiv:1701.07449, 2017.
G. Pryde, “Experimental semi-device-independent cer- [24] C. M. Lee and M. J. Hoban, “Bounds on the power of
tification of entangled measurements,” Physical Review proofs and advice in general physical theories,” Proc. R.
Letters, vol. 113, no. 8, p. 080405, 2014. Soc. A, vol. 472, no. 2190, p. 20160076, 2016.
[7] J. Bowles, N. Brunner, and M. Pawlowski, “Testing [25] C. M. Lee and M. J. Hoban, “The information content
dimension and nonclassicality in communication net- of systems in general physical theories,” arXiv preprint
works,” Physical Review A, vol. 92, no. 2, p. 022351, arXiv:1606.06801, EPTCS 214, 2016, pp. 22-28, 2016.
2015. [26] For connections between related notions of causality and
[8] R. Rabelo, M. Ho, D. Cavalcanti, N. Brunner, and quantum information, see [22–25]
V. Scarani, “Device-independent certification of entan- [27] Here the faithfulness condition is being assumed, see [9,
gled measurements,” Physical Review Letters, vol. 107, 17] for a discussion.
no. 5, p. 050502, 2011.
[9] C. J. Wood and R. W. Spekkens, “The lesson of causal
discovery algorithms for quantum correlations: Causal
explanations of bell-inequality violations require fine-
tuning,” New Journal of Physics, vol. 17, no. 033002,
2015.
[10] R. Chaves, R. Kueng, J. B. Brask, and D. Gross, “Unify-
ing framework for relaxations of the causal assumptions
in bell’s theorem,” Phys. Rev. Lett., vol. 114, no. 140403,
2015.
[11] E. G. Cavalcanti, “Classical causal models for bell and
kochen-specker inequality violations require fine-tuning,”
Phys. Rev. X, vol. 8, p. 021018, Apr 2018.
[12] J.-M. A. Allen, J. Barrett, D. C. Horsman, C. M. Lee, and
R. W. Spekkens, “Quantum common causes and quan-
tum causal models,” arXiv preprint arXiv:1609.09487,
2016.
[13] R. Chaves, J. B. Brask, and N. Brunner, “Device-
independent tests of entropy,” Phys. Rev. Lett., vol. 115,
no. 110501, 2015.
[14] R. Chaves, D. Cavalcanti, and L. Aolita, “Causal hi-
erarchy of multipartite bell nonlocality,” arXiv preprint
arXiv:1607.07666, 2016.
[15] J. B. Brask and R. Chaves, “Bell scenarios with commu-
nication,” Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and The-
oretical, 2017.
[16] C. M. Lee and R. W. Spekkens, “Causal inference via
algebraic geometry: Feasibility tests for functional causal
structures with two binary observed variables,” Journal
of Causal Inference (DOI: 10.1515/jci-2016-0013), arXiv
preprint arXiv:1506.03880, 2017.
[17] J. Pearl, Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed., 2009.
[18] J. Henson, R. Lal, and M. F. Pusey, “Theory-
independent limits on correlations from generalized
bayesian networks,” New Journal of Physics, vol. 16,
no. 113043, 2014.
[19] C. Branciard, D. Rosset, N. Gisin, and S. Pironio,
“Bilocal versus nonbilocal correlations in entanglement-
swapping experiments,” Physical Review A, vol. 85, no. 3,
p. 032119, 2012.
[20] A. Acı́n, N. Gisin, and B. Toner, “Grothendieck’s con-
stant and local models for noisy entangled quantum

You might also like