Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 2

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 42 (2011) 372–380

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa

Hermeneutical contributions to the history of science: Gadamer on ‘presentism’


Oscar Moro Abadía ⇑
Memorial University of Newfoundland, St. John’s, NL, Canada A1C 5S7
Instituto de Filosofía-CSIC, Albasanz 26-28, 28037 Madrid, Spain

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Keywords: This article examines how Hans G. Gadamer’s philosophical hermeneutics can contribute to contempo-
Presentism rary debates on the concept of ‘presentism’. In the field of the history of science, this term is usually
Whig history employed in two ways. First, ‘presentism’ refers to the kind of historiography which judges the past to
Philosophical hermeneutics
legitimate the present. Second, this concept designates the inevitable influence of the present in the
Gadamer
interpretation of the past. In this paper, I argue that both dimensions of the relationship between the
present and the past are explored by Hans G. Gadamer in Truth and Method and other texts. In the first
place, Gadamer’s critique of historicism calls into question the anti-presentist ideal of studying the past
for ‘its own sake’. In the second place, Gadamer’s thesis that all understanding inevitably involves some
prejudice poses the question of the inherent ‘‘present-centredness’’ of historical interpretations. By exam-
ining Gadamer’s hermeneutics, I seek to provide historians with new arguments and perspectives on the
question of ‘presentism’.
Ó 2011 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

1. Introduction the first place, ‘presentism’ is a term generally employed to desig-


nate and denigrate the kind of historiographical approach in which
During the last fifty years, the concept of ‘presentism’ has been past science and scientists are judged and evaluated in the light of
extensively used by philosophers and historians of science. In the modern knowledge. In this setting, ‘presentism’, ‘whig history’ and
case of the history of science, ‘presentism’ is a polysemous word ‘anachronistic history’ are frequently considered as synonymous
which can adopt different meanings depending on the context. (e.g. Kragh, 1987, p. 93; Nickles, 1995, p. 151; Stocking, 1968
For instance, the notion of ‘whig history’, which is often equated [1965], p. 4; Trout, 1994, p. 39). Furthermore, most historians agree
to that of ‘presentism’ (e.g. Mayr, 1990; Pickstone, 1995, p. 203, that the best way to counteract this kind of ‘presentism’ is studying
pp. 301–302; Hull, 2000, p. 71; Jardine, 2003, p. 125), can refer the past ‘in its own terms’. In the second place, ‘presentism’ also re-
to ‘‘the distortion wrought by describing and evaluating past sci- fers to the many ways in which the present influences the interpre-
ence from the perspective of present science’’ (Hardcastle, 1991, tation of the past, including the fact that historians are constricted
p. 323), to ‘‘the imposition of our categories on the deeds and by the linguistic, conceptual and cultural codes of their time. In this
works of past agents who lacked such categories’’ (Jardine, 2003, case, specialists also use the notions ‘present-centredness’ and
p. 126) and to ‘‘the belief that any historian who becomes profes- ‘present-mindedness’ to refer to this condition of historical re-
sionally interested in current problems commits the sin of being search (Ashplant & Wilson, 1988, p. 253; Brush, 1995, p. 220;
a ‘Whig historian’ ’’ (Graham, 1981, p. 5). While not seeking to deny Cunningham, 1988, p. 367; Wilson & Ashplant, 1988, p. 11).
the polysemous nature of ‘presentism’, I have distinguished two In this paper I argue that the analysis of these two dimensions of
primary ways in which historians have used this concept: (A) the relationship between the present and the past is at the heart of
‘Presentism’ as a kind of historiography and (B) ‘Presentism’ as an Gadamer’s hermeneutical project. Hans G. Gadamer (1900–2002)
inherent trait of historical research (Moro Abadía, 2009, p. 55). In was a central figure in the development of philosophical

⇑ Address: Memorial University of Newfoundland, St. John’s, NL, Canada AIC 5S7.
E-mail address: oscar_moro_abadia@yahoo.es

0039-3681/$ - see front matter Ó 2011 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2010.12.003
O.M. Abadía / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 42 (2011) 372–380 373

hermeneutics, a version of hermeneutics also explored by authors In the second part, I compare the different ways in which
such as Paul Ricoeur and Gianni Vattimo. Professor of philosophy Gadamer and historians of science in the 1980s and the 1990s
at the universities of Leipzig and Heidelberg, Gadamer presented posed the question of the ‘present-centredness’ of history. I argue
his main ideas in Wahrheit und Methode, a book translated into Eng- that in both cases the emphasis on the present-mindedness of his-
lish under the title Truth and Method in 1975 (Gadamer, 2006a torical practice was, up to a point, a reaction against the excesses of
[1960]). He also devoted numerous papers, talks and interviews historicism. In the case of Gadamer, he argued that the historicist
to explain his views on hermeneutics. Most of these materials were ideal of understanding the past ‘in its own terms’ was impossible
compiled in the second volume of Gesammelte Werke (Gadamer, to achieve for ‘‘all understanding inevitably involves some preju-
1986) and appeared in English scattered throughout many books dice’’ (Gadamer, 2006a [1960], p. 272; GW I, p. 274). For instance,
and readers1. While philosophical hermeneutics has been the object Gadamer argued that historical interpretations are prejudiced by
of many remarkable analyses (e.g. Dostal, 2002; Figal, 2000; Figal, the tradition in which they take place, the language in which they
Grondin, & Schmidt, 2000; Grondin, 1994 [1991], 2003 [1999]; occur and, of course, the present from which they emerge. In this
Malpas, Arnswald & Kertsche, 2002; Palmer, 1969; Wachterhauser, point, Gadamer was certainly close to those authors who stated
1985, 1994, 1999), there is little scholarship on Gadamer’s contribu- that ‘‘the historian, in seeking to study, reconstruct and write about
tion to ‘presentism’. Furthermore, most papers on this topic do not the past, is constrained by necessarily starting from the perceptual
cite Gadamer (e.g. Ashplant & Wilson, 1988; Graham, 1981; Hall, and conceptual categories of the present’’ (Ashplant & Wilson,
1983; Hardcastle, 1991; Hull, 1979; Mayr, 1990; Pearce Williams, 1988, p.253). However, Gadamer differed from these historians in
1975; Pickstone, 1995; Russell, 1984; Tosh, 2003; Wilson & Ashplant, that he did not interpret this conditionedness as a limitation of his-
1988; see, however, Jardine, 2003, p.135; Moro Abadía, 2008, 2009). torical knowledge. On the contrary, he sought ‘‘to rehabilitate the
This omission is surprising given some evident analogies between concept of prejudice and acknowledge the fact that there are legit-
Gadamer’s hermeneutics and contemporary debates on ‘presentism’. imate prejudices’’ (Gadamer, 2006a [1960], p. 278; GW I, p. 281). In
A couple of examples can illustrate this point. During the same years other words, according to Gadamer, the fact that history is inevita-
that Thomas Kuhn proclaimed that ‘‘insofar as possible the historian bly present-prejudiced is not an obstacle for historical understand-
should set aside the science that he knows; [he/she] should try to ing but, rather, it is the condition of historical knowledge.
think as they [past scientists] did’’ (Kuhn, 1977 [1968], p. 110), I conclude by arguing that Gadamer’s philosophical hermeneu-
Gadamer argued that ‘‘every historical moment must be understood tics can encourage historians of science to think about ‘presentism’
in itself and cannot be submitted to the measures of a present which in new and productive ways. First, Gadamer develops in great de-
may be extrinsic to it’’ (Gadamer, 1979 [1963], p. 120). Similarly, tail some of the arguments used by historians to evoke the many
some of the arguments put forward by historians of science in the faces of ‘presentism’. In this sense, philosophical hermeneutics
1980s and the 1990s to demonstrate the inevitable ‘present- can be a source of inspiration to think more critically about this to-
centredness’ of historical inquiry had been extensively examined by pic. Second, Gadamer’s perspective on ‘presentism’ is not that of a
Gadamer in Truth and Method (Gadamer, 2006a, [1960]). For instance, historian, but that of a philosopher. For this reason, Gadamer’s
the idea that ‘‘the conceptual apparatus available to historians will be viewpoint can inspire historians to think about ‘presentism’ be-
(or include) that of the present’’ (Pickstone, 1995, p. 205) is reminis- yond the limits defined by their own tradition.
cent of Gadamer’s belief that the historian is ‘‘a child of his time who Before proceeding to the analysis, two methodological notes are
is unquestioningly dominated by the concepts and prejudices of his in order. In the first place, this article establishes a systematic com-
own age’’ (Gadamer, 2006a [1960], p. 397; GW I, p. 400). parison between Gadamer and the ‘historians of science’, the latter
The central purpose of this article is to analyze philosophical divided into two groups according to the definition of ‘presentism’
hermeneutics through the lens of the ‘presentist’ debate. In partic- they endorse. I appreciate that the broad category of ‘historians of
ular, I seek to determine the similarities and differences that can be science’ implies a monolithic and simplistic representation of
established between Gadamer’s approach to this question and that much more nuanced views (for instance, some of the authors I in-
of the historians of science. To do so, I examine Gadamer’s position clude in this group are not historians of science, but philosophers
on the two main problems posed by the concept of ‘presentism’. In of science). However I consider this reductionism justified for
the first part, I relate the definition of ‘presentism’ as a misleading two reasons. First, I cannot analyze each historian of science sepa-
historiographical approach to Gadamer’s critique of historicism. To rately in the parameters of a paper. Second, the authors mentioned
begin, Gadamer does not ‘‘dispute the fact that controlling the pre- in this paper endorse one of the two aforementioned definitions of
judice of our own present to such an extent that we do not misun- presentism. The second consideration refers to the fact that the
derstand the witnesses of the past is a valid aim’’ (Gadamer, 1976 comparison between Gadamer and historians of science can some-
[1966]: p. 6, GW II: 222). On this point, Gadamer was not far from times produce the erroneous impression that they established a
the ‘new’ history of science that, in the 1960s, rejected ‘whig his- veritable dialogue. However, as I explain in the conclusion, this
tory’ and called for an approach seeking to understand past texts interpretation is not accurate. For this reason, it is important to
in their historical context. However, Gadamer diverged from these remember it is I who compares the ideas of Gadamer with those
historians in the way in which he considered the accomplishment of historians.
of such a task. In fact, Gadamer called into question the historicist
ideal of studying the past ‘in its own terms’ for such a model pre- 2. Gadamer on ‘Whig history’: the critique of historicism
supposed that ‘‘in understanding history one must leave one’s own
concept aside and think only in the concepts of the epoch one is The first usage of the concept of ‘presentism’ among English-
trying to understand’’ (Gadamer, 2006a [1960], p. 398; GW I, p. speaking historians is inextricably linked to the emergence of the
400). This positioning is ‘‘not only impossible but manifestly ab- ‘new’ history of science in the 1960s. It was at that time when a
surd’’ (Gadamer, 2006a [1960], p. 398; GW I, p. 400), for historians new generation of Anglo-Saxon historians defined an innovative
cannot go beyond their own time. To illustrate Gadamer’s critique program characterized by a number of features, including a focus
of historicism, I reconstruct his dialogue with Dilthey. on the paradigms or worldviews orienting scientific research, an

1
In this article, I refer both to Gadamer’s original publications and to their English translations. Following a long-established convention, I use in this paper the abbreviation
GW to refer to Gadamer’s Gesammelte Werke (Gadamer, 1986) and GS for Dilthey’s Gesammelte Schriften (Dilthey, 1959–1968).

You might also like