Hines - Popper's Methodology

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

Popper's Methodology of Falsificationism and Accounting Research

Author(s): Ruth D. Hines


Source: The Accounting Review, Vol. 63, No. 4 (Oct., 1988), pp. 657-662
Published by: American Accounting Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/247905 .
Accessed: 15/06/2014 09:10

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Accounting Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The
Accounting Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 195.34.79.174 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 09:10:22 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
THE ACCOUNTING REVIEW
Vol. LXIII, No. 4
October 1988

Popper's Methodology of
Falsificationism and
Accounting Research
Ruth D. Hines

ABSTRACT: Popper's falsificationism is apparently being adopted as an ideal by accounting


researchers. For example, Christenson [1983] has criticized Watts and Zimmerman's [1978,
19791theories for not conforming to Popper's approach. This paper argues that Popper's fal-
sificationism should not be viewed as an attainable ideal by accounting researchers, and that
standard of rigor and research and experimental design are sufficient to support Christenson's
criticisms without recourse to Popper's methodology.

I
OPPER' S [1959] falsificationist meth- Hume [1888] first articulated the major problem that
this point of logic presents for empiricism. An associated
odology represents an attempt to deficiency of confirmationism or verificationism, fur-
solve a particular logical problem. ther rendering it an extremely weak form of testing,
The problem is that observations which relates to the fact that every false statement has an in-
definite number of factually correct consequences. Thus,
are in accordance with a theory cannot there will always be many observations available to
be taken to "confirm" or "prove" that support a false theory. For example, prior to Einsteinian
theory. Accepting a theory because of theory, everything in the observable world seemed to
confirm Newtonian theory. In fact, as Leibniz [1677]
the existence of confirming evidence showed, it can be logically demonstrated, that any finite
commits the fallacy of "affirming the number of observations can be accommodated within an
consequent" and is a well-recognized indefinitely large number of different explanations. As
Lakatos [1978, p. 991 states: "Creative imagination is
error of logic.' Popper's approach de- likely to find corroborating novel evidence even for the
pends upon the point that the falsity most 'absurd' programme, if the search has sufficient
of universal statements can be logi- drive."
cally deduced from singular statements.
Therefore, Popper prescribed that the- The author gratefully acknowledges the helpful com-
ments on previous versions of this paper of Charles
ories be negatively framed: theories Christenson, the anonymous reviewers, George Foster
should state the type of observation(s) and participants in a Macquarie University Workshop in
that refute them (and, hence, would be Accounting and Financial Management. The author has
also benefitted from the comments of Bob McLaughlin
decisive observations), rather than posi- and participation in his seminars in Philosophy of Sci-
tively state those observations which ence at Macquarie University.
would support or confirm them. The
strength of Popper's falsificationist ap- Ruth D. Hines is SeniorLecturer in Ac-
proach derives from the fact that, while counting and Financial Management at
it is logically fallacious to affirm the con- Macquarie University.
sequent, it is logically correct to deny the
consequent (the logical rule of modus Manuscript received November 1985.
Revisions received June 1986, August 1987. April
tollens). 1988, and July 1988.
The view that Popper's falsificationist Accepted May 1988.

657

This content downloaded from 195.34.79.174 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 09:10:22 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
658 The Accounting Review, October 1988

methodology represents a scientific ideal confirmationist tests does not constitute


appears to be gaining popularity with a refutation or falsification of a theory.
accounting researchers. For example, It seems that the confusion among
McKee et al. (1984, pp. 647, 651-652] some accounting researchers about falsifi-
and Watts and Zimmerman [1986, pp. 2, cationism stems from the belief that the
8-10, 12] make favorable references to framing of an hypothesis in the "null"
Popper. Recently, Christenson has based form is a form of falsificationism. How-
a critique of work on the positive ac- ever, this is incorrect. Such framing rep-
counting theory of the Rochester School resents merely an approach to testing
on its inconsistencies with the guidelines samples, and represents a form of con-
offered by Popper's falsificationist ap- firmationism rather than falsification-
proach. The absence of a formal pub- ism: rejection of the null provides some
lished reply-from the Rochester School support for a theory but failure to reject
or elsewhere-appears to leave the im- the null does not imply acceptance of the
pression that it is appropriate to hold null, or falsification of the theory-it
empirical work up to the standards of merely implies a failure to obtain con-
Popper. The purpose of this Note is to firmationist support for a theory. In-
clarify the meaning of Popper's falsifica- deed, testing the null hypothesis fre-
tionist approach and to argue that it is quently represents a very weak form of
not a practical evaluative guideline for confirmationism. When a test of signifi-
empirical work in accounting. It is im- cance rejects the null hypothesis, all that
portant that these arguments be made is inferred is that the obtained sample
and understood because acceptance of results are unlikely to have occurred by
Popper's falsificationism as an attain- chance. Only if the experimental design
able ideal and the consequent evaluation is such that it rules out all competing
of empirical work solely from this per- explanations to the tested theory, can it
spective has the potential to arbitrarily be stated with some confidence that the
and harmfully limit the nature and data does provide confirmatory evidence
domain of accounting research. It is the for the tested theory.
intent of this Note to help forestall such
WITHPOPPER'S
DIFFICULTIES
harm. It is important to distinguish the
FALSIFICATIONISM
purpose of this paper from a defense of
the positive theory work that was the At the logical level, Popper's falsi-
subject of Christenson's critique. ficationist approach has encountered
some difficulties. For example, the as-
POPPER'SFALSIFICATIONISM: sumption that a falsifying observation
A CLARIFICATION will persist is itself an inductive assump-
There appears to be confusion among tion, based on experience that the same
accounting researchers concerning Pop- events or observations have persisted in
per's falsificationism. For example, the past and, hence, will persist in the
McKee et al. [1984, pp. 651-652] state
I This point does not detract from the importance of
that their study represents an attempt to
McKee et al's [19841 results. Indeed, given the logical
refute Watts and Zimmerman [1978]. weakness of confirmationism, the doubt that McKee et
This is not correct; their study represents al. [1984] throw on Watts and Zimmerman's [1978] own
an attempt to confirm them. In fact, confirmatory results, and their own failure to confirm
Watts and Zimmerman's [1978] theory using an alterna-
they were unable to confirm them.2 tive data set, casts serious doubts on the correctness of
However, the failure of verificationist or Watts and Zimmerman's theory.

This content downloaded from 195.34.79.174 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 09:10:22 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Hines 659

future (see Salmon [1966, pp. 21-27] and theories, he either plunges into some log-
Quinton [1967, p. 399]). ical blunder, or distorts history to fit
If these logical difficulties are ignored his rationality theory." When account
because there is no answer to this prob- is properly taken of scientific history,
lem of induction, it can be asked whether it emerges that "history falsifies falsi-
Popper's criteria constitute either a satis- ficationism" [Lakatos, 1978, p. 1231.
factory set of ideal criteria for theory Kuhn's [1970] famous work is an histor-
assessment and/or an accurate descrip- ical/sociological investigation of the way
tion of the selection process by which science and scientists proceed, and it
scientific theories are adopted in prac- clearly demonstrates that Popper's falsi-
tice. Popper held that ideal criteria for ficationism bears no relation to the way
scientific-theory assessment could be es- things "really happen" in science. "No
tablished by fiat or convention, that is, process yet disclosed by the historical
without reference to the way in which study of scientific development at all
science is actually practiced. His concern resembles the methodological stereotype
was with normative rules, as Christenson of falsification..." [Kuhn, 1970, p. 77].
[1983, p. 8] notes. This concern meant There are no scientific theories from
that Popper did not require his a priori which all anomalies or falsifying obser-
rules to adequately or correctly describe vations have been eliminated. Feyera-
the way in which scientific practice bend [1978, pp. 69-161] analyzes in great
actually proceeds. However, as Lakatos detail the work of Galileo, ". . who was
[1978, pp. 123-138] discusses, it is prob- faced by an embarrassing amount of
lematic to establish the suitability or prima facie refuting instances, who was
superiority of a set of normative criteria.unable to explain them for he lacked
Indeed, since Popper, the divorce of nor- the necessary knowledge..." (p. 159).
mative and historical (descriptive) ac- Copernicus' theory, which Galileo resur-
counts of theory appraisal has been rected and extended to eventually replace
rejected by leading philosophers of the Ptolemaic system, was riddled with
science, such as Kuhn, Feyerabend, inconsistencies and refuting observa-
Lakatos, and Laudan. Lakatos [1971, p. tions. Newtonian theory was beset by
91] states, "philosophy of science with- counterinstances [Kuhn, 1970, pp. 77-
out history of science is empty; history 91; Feyerabend, 1978, pp. 59-63; and
of science without philosophy of science Lakatos, 1978, p. 701. Bohr's atomic
is blind." It, therefore, seems appro- theory was introduced and retained in
priate to question whether Popper's the face of precise and unshakable con-
method is a descriptively valid account trary evidence [Feyerabend, 1978, p. 56
of the way that research proceeds in and Lakatos, 1978, pp. 55-58].
science. Therefore, it does not seem reasonable
to base a large part of the criticism of the
HISTORY "FALSIFIES" FALSIFiCATIONISM
positive theory on the fact that there are
Lakatos [1978, p. 1271 states, "Logic some instances (or firms) that are incon-
derForschung (Popper's Logic of Scien- sistent with it (see Watts and Zimmer-
tific Discovery [1959]), on the whole, man [1978, p. 125] for a detailed list that
is dryly abstract and highly ahistorical." indicates those firms which voted on the
Lakatos [1978, p. 127] continues, "Where Financial Accounting Standards Board's
Popper does venture to remark casually Discussion Memorandum on General
on the falsifiability of major scientific Price Level Adjustments in the opposite

This content downloaded from 195.34.79.174 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 09:10:22 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
660 TheAccountingReview,October1988

direction to that predicted by their the- hence, no individual hypothesis or the-


ory). Indeed, as Christenson [1983, p. 8] ory is conclusively falsifiable. This
points out "From a strictly logical point problem of the jointness of testing, is
of view, a proposition is falsified not by referred to as the Duhem problem (see
experience but only by the acceptance of Duhem [1954]).
another proposition with which it is logi- In accounting research, for example,
cally inconsistent." From this perspec- market efficiency research has generated
tive it appears there are presently no many anomalies (see Foster [1984]; Lev
well-articulated complete theories re- and Ohlson [1982]; and Ricks [1982]),
garding accounting method preferences but researchers in the area have not
and/or choices besides the positive the- viewed the efficient markets hypothesis
ory of the Rochester School. as falsified, because of, inter alia, the
THE DUHEMPROBLEM
impossibility of locating the source of
the "falsification" within the maze of
In Popper's infrequent references to premises which is effectively tested by a
the history of science, he turned anoma- capital market efficiency test [Hines,
lies, or refuting observations, into "cru- 1986a]. A capital market efficiency test
cial experiments" and then exaggerated jointly tests premises concerning data
their immediate impact on the history of quality; assumptions relating to transac-
science [Lakatos, 1978, p. 127]. Great tion cost estimation; whether informa-
scientists have almost never accepted tion is good/bad; the timing of events
refutations as being decisive, because of and information release; a specific asset
important problems and reservations pricing model; measurement theories,
which so frequently in reality accompany instruments and procedures, and so on.
a refuting instance. Feyerabend, Kuhn, Indeed, Foster [1984, p. 169] and Lev
and Lakatos illustrate amply that a "re- and Ohlson [1982, p. 274] prefer to call
futing" observation may disagree with a efficient markets hypothesis counter-
theory for a variety of reasons and observations "research puzzles" and
hence, in practice, a "refuting" observa- "surprise results" respectively, rather
tion does not necessarily "logically" than "anomalies" or "falsifications."
refute a theory.
COMMENTS
CONCLUDING
A major problem in considering a
refuting observation is that a theory con- The various methodologies developed
sists of a complex of refutable universal by philosophers of science are relevant
statements, rather than a single refutable to accounting and finance research
statement like, "All crows are black." as organizing, heuristic, and analytical
Furthermore, to permit testing, more frameworks. However, to believe that
statements than those of the tested there is a single "ideal" methodology,
theory are involved-the theory must be and/or to finally judge theories against
augmented by auxiliaryassumptions, such such a methodology, is ill-advised. If the
as laws and theories governing mea- dangers of scientism can be appreciated
surement and the use of instruments. Ini- by researchers early in the methodolog-
tial conditions, such as description of the ical debate within accounting and fi-
experimental set-up, must also be added. nance literature, then research may per-
If a prediction that follows from these haps be saved from the dogmatism and
joint premises turns out to be false, then many diversions of resources that have
all that can be logically concluded is that resulted in other fields of inquiry and
at least one of the premises is false and, from an unwarrantedreverencefor science

This content downloaded from 195.34.79.174 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 09:10:22 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Hines 661

and "the scientific method" (see Berger Hopwood [1983]; Mintzberg [19791;
[1966, p. 24]; Burrell and Morgan Nord [1986]; Tomkins and Groves
[1979]; Mackenzie [1977]; McHugh [1983]; and Zeff [1983]), there appears
[1971]; and Schuster [1984]). For exam- to be little researchpresentlyproceeding
ple, Mackenzie [1977] argues that be- on the development of alternative
haviorism failed largely because it was a theoriesto positive theory.
research program devoted to the pursuit In concluding, this Note is not in-
of "objective" methods, to the exclusion tended to suggest that there are no cri-
of consideration of the fundamental on- teria againstwhich positive theoriescan
tological status or nature of behavior, be evaluated. The author believes that
namely its dependency upon mental (i.e., Christenson's[1983]criticismsof Watts
internal and, hence, not readily observ- and Zimmerman'stheoriesremainvalid
able) processes. Similar criticisms have withoutrelianceon Popperbecausestan-
been made of research programs in so- dards of rigor and good experimental
ciology such as the Berger and Kellner design are sufficient to support that
[1981] critique of the "cult of quantifi- Watts and Zimmermanshould have: (i)
cation" in sociological research: "a posi- avoided the use of crudeproxiessuch as
tion that any sociological propositions the use of firm size to operationalizethe
that cannot be couched in mathematical concept of "politicalcosts"; (ii) avoided
terms are 'soft,' unscientific, and use- the use of unrealisticassumptionsin their
less" (p. 126). explanatorytheorizing;(iii) investigated
Indeed, Mintzberg [1979] and Zeff their anomalies; (iv) clarified whether
[1983, 1986] suggest that accounting re- theirtheorieswereuniversalor probabil-
search may already be constrained by a istic, and if the latter,explainedon what
repression of criticalness and creativity, conceptualgroundsthey should be held
caused by a commitment to using rigor- to be so; (v) if probabilistic,they should
ous statistical procedures that are in- have statedthe proportionof anomalous
correctly perceived by accounting re- observationswhich would be consistent
searchers to be "the scientific method." withtheirtheories,andhencethe propor-
This may be one reason why, despite tion beyond which counterobservations
calls by accounting researchers for the wouldthreatentheirtheorieswithdiscon-
development of alternative theoretical firmation,and (vi) rigorouslytestedtheir
perspectives on accounting which would theories against competing hypotheses
require alternative methods (see Burchell rather than merely presenteddata that
et al. [19801; Cooper and Sherer [19841; were(partially)consistentwith them.
Chua [19861;Hines [1986a, 1986b, 1988];

REFERENCES
Berger, P. L., Invitation to Sociology: A Humanistic Perspective (Pelican Books, 1966).
, and H. Kellner, Sociology Reinterpreted (Penguin, 1981).
Burchell, S., C. Clubb, A. Hopwood, J. Hughes, and J. Nahapiet, "The Roles of Accounting in Organiza-
tions and Society," Accounting, Organizations and Society (No. 1, 1980), pp. 5-27.
Burrell, G., and G. Morgan, Sociological Paradigms and OrganisationalAnalysis: Elements of the Soci-
ology of Corporate Life (Heinemann, 1979).
Christenson, C., "The Methodology of Positive Accounting," THEACCOUNTING REvIEW(January 1983),
pp. 1-22.
Chua, W. F., "Radical Developments in Accounting Thought," THE AccOuNTINGREVIEW (October
1986), pp 601-632

This content downloaded from 195.34.79.174 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 09:10:22 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
662 The Accounting Review, October 1988

Cooper, D. J., and M. J. Sherer, "The Value of Corporate Accounting Reports: Arguments for a Political
Economy of Accounting," Accounting, Organizations and Society (No. 3/4, 1984), pp. 207-232.
Duhem, P., La theorie physique, son objet et sa structure (1906). English translation of second (1914)
edition: The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory (Princeton University Press, 1954).
Feyerabend, P. K., Against Method (Verso, 1978), originally published by New Left Books, 1975.
Foster, G., "Capital Market Efficiency: Definitions Testing Issues and Anomalies" in M. J. R. Gaffikin,
Ed., Contemporary Accounting Thought (Prentice-Hall, 1984), pp. 151-180.
Hines, R. D., "Financial Accounting Theory Appraisal, " Working paper (School of Economic and Finan-
cial Studies, Macquarie University, Sydney, Australia, March 1986a).
,"The Emerging Sociopolitical Research Program in Accounting: A Contribution to its Concep-
tual Foundations," presented at the Conference of the British Accounting Association (Aberystwyth,
Wales, April 1986b).
, "Financial Accounting: In Communicating Reality, We Construct Reality," Accounting,
Organizations and Society (No. 3, 1988), pp. 251-262.
Hopwood, A. G., "On Trying to Study Accounting in the Contexts in Which it Operates," Accounting,
Organizations and Society (No. 2/3, 1983), pp. 287-305.
, "The Tale of a Committee that Never Reported: Disagreements on Intertwining Accounting with
the Social," Accounting, Organizations and Society (No. 3, 1985), pp. 361-377.
Hume, D., A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford 1888), reprinted from the original 1739 edition and
edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge.
Kuhn, T. S., The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (University of Chicago Press, 1970).
Lakatos, I., "History of Science and Its Rational Reconstruction," in R. C. Buck and R. S. Cohen, Eds.,
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume 8 (Reidel Publishing Co., 1971), pp. 91-136.
- "The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes," in J. Worrall and G. Currie, Eds.,
Philosophical Papers, Volume 1 (Cambridge University Press, 1978).
Leibniz, G. W., Leibniz Selections, P. P. Wiener, Ed. (Scribner, 1677).
Lev, B., and J. A. Ohlson, "Market-Based Empirical Research in Accounting: A Review, Interpretation,
and Extension," Supplement to Journal of Accounting Research (1982), pp. 249-322.
Mackenzie, B. D., Behaviourism and the Limits of Scientific Method (Routledge and Kegan Paul, Ltd.,
1977).
McHugh, P., "On the Failure of Positivism," in J. D. Douglas, Ed., UnderstandingEverydayLife (Aldine
Pub., 1971), pp. 320-335.
McKee, A. J., T. B. Bell, and J. R. Boatsman, "Management Preferences Over Accounting Standards:
A Replication and Additional Tests," THE ACCOUNTINGREVIEW(October 1984), pp. 647-659.
Mintzberg, H., "An Emerging Strategy of 'Direct' Research," Administrative Science Quarterly (Decem-
ber 1979), pp. 582-589.
Nord, W. R., "Towards an Optimal Dialectical Perspective: Comments and Extensions on Neimark and
Tinker," Accounting, Organizations and Society (No. 4/5, 1986), pp. 397-402.
Popper, K. R., The Logic of Scientific Discovery (Basic Books, 1959).
Quinton, A., "Popper, Karl Raimund" in P. Edwards, Ed., Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume 6 (Mac-
millan and Free Press, 1967), pp. 398-401.
Ricks, W., "Market Assessment of Alternative Accounting Methods: A Review of the Empirical Evi-
dence," Journal of Accounting Literature (1982), pp. 59-99.
Salmon, W. C., The Foundations of Scientific Inference (University of Pittsburg Press, 1966).
Schuster, J. A., "Methodologies as Mythic Structures: A Preface to the Future Historiography of Meth-
od," Metascience (1984), pp. 15-36.
Tomkins, C., and R. Groves, "The Everyday Accountant and Researching His Reality," Accounting,
Organizations and Society (No. 4, 1983), pp. 361-374.
Watts, R. L., and J. L. Zimmerman, "Towards a Positive Theory of the Determination of Accounting
Standards," THE ACCOUNTINGREVIEW(January 1978), pp. 112-134.
, and , "The Demand for and Supply of Accounting Theories: The Market for Excuses," TBE
ACCOUNTING REVIEW (April 1979), pp. 273-305.
, and , Positive Accounting Theory (Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1986).
Zeff, S. A., "Editorial: A Retrospective," THE ACCOUNTING REVIEW (January 1983), pp. 129-134.
""Tre-ndsin Accounting Education in the United States," presented at the Conference of the Ac-
counting Association of Australia and New Zealand (Adelaide, South Australia, August 1986).

This content downloaded from 195.34.79.174 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 09:10:22 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like