Donor-Funded Research: Permissible, Not Perfect: Mike King, Angela Ballantyne

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 5

Original research

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/medethics-2018-104966 on 18 September 2018. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on 22 September 2018 by guest. Protected by copyright.
Donor-funded research: permissible, not perfect
Mike King,1 Angela Ballantyne1,2
1
Bioethics Centre, School of Abstract refer to these three models or their use collectively
Medical and Surgical Sciences, Donor-funded research is research funded by private as donor-funding models or donor-funded research.
University of Otago, Dunedin,
New Zealand donors in exchange for research-related benefits, such We argue that they deserve serious consideration.
2
Department of Primary Health as trial participation or access to the trial intervention. Our approach in this article is to assess these
Care and General Practice, This has been pejoratively referred to as ’pay to play’ proposals against broadly accepted minimal stan-
University of Otago, Dunedin, research, and criticised as unethical. We outline three dards of research ethics to determine whether it
New Zealand is reasonable to prohibit donor-funded research.
models of donor-funded research, and argue for their
permissibility on the grounds of personal liberty, their This standard ensures consistency with how other
Correspondence to
Dr Angela Ballantyne, capacity to facilitate otherwise unfunded health research clinical research is reviewed and assessed. Our
Department of Primary Health and their consistency with current ethical standards for concern is that previous critiques have measured
Care and General Practice, research. We defend this argument against objections donor-funding against higher, perhaps aspira-
University of Otago, Dunedin that donor-funded research is wrongly exploitative, unfair tional, research ethics standards. We conclude that
9016, New Zealand; donor-funded research is prima facie permissible,
and undermines the public good of medical research.
​angela.​ballantyne@​otago.​ac.n​ z
Our conclusion is that, like all human subjects research, and ought to be regulated through Research Ethics
Received 22 May 2018 donor-funded research should be regulated via standard Committee/Institutional Review Board (REC/IRB)
Revised 8 August 2018 health research legislation/guidelines and undergo review and oversight like other research.
Accepted 22 August 2018 Research Ethics Committee/Institutional Review Board
and scientific peer-review. We expect that, measured
against these standards, some donor-funded research Argument for donor-funded research
would be acceptable. Both liberty and public good can ground a prima
facie argument for the permissibility of donor-
funded research. First individuals hold a prima facie
Introduction right to engage in free exchanges of goods, based
Demand for biomedical research funding outstrips on personal liberty interests, or personal autonomy.
supply from current funding bodies. Only a small Second, assuming this is an informed, consensual,
percentage of promising drugs ever make it into voluntary transaction between rational parties, each
drug trials to test their efficacy and safety. Deci- is better off—the donor prefers exchanging their
sions regarding which drugs to take from discovery money for access to the trial, and the researcher
to proof of concept involve a considerable amount prefers exchanging some research-related benefit
of guesswork. This provides a prima facie incen- (these vary in different models, as we later explain)
tive to find new ways to fund biomedical research. for funds that enable the trial to occur. Although
One option is raising money from private donors, neither donor nor researcher may be under a duty
in exchange for their receipt of some research-re- to engage in or offer these transactions, there is pro
lated benefit. This is not a new idea; historically tanto reason, based on the benefit of free exchanges,
patronage funded much of science and the arts. and the liberty to engage in them, that they not be
However, in modern biomedical research there are prohibited or otherwise thwarted.
some potentially important differences: the internet Second, clinical research is a public good; it
enlarges the pool of potential donors accessible to provides the evidence base for safe and effective
researchers, and facilitating aggregation of donors clinical care.6 Populations who are systematically
for a study, and donors may have an interest in excluded from, or neglected in, research are worse
being a participant in the research, rather than off than others, due in part to the lack of evidence
merely funding it. to inform their medical care. Examples include
Donor-funded research is proposed, and has been patients with comorbidities, pregnant women and
used, as a way to overcome traditional research people with rare diseases, all of which are neglected
funding limitations.1 2 The recent ‘plutocratic under the status quo of health research funding.7–9
proposal’ (PP) presented in this journal by Masters Effects of this can include increased adverse events
and Nutt is a relevant example.1 A related model and side effects, reduced length or quality of life
is one in which private donors would be offered due to undertreatment and missing out on inno-
© Author(s) (or their
employer(s)) 2018. No the opportunity to try the experimental interven- vative therapies. There are strong public interests
commercial re-use. See rights tion without participating in the trial.2 We call this in regulating research. Regulation helps ensure
and permissions. Published ‘pay to try’ (PTT) research. Previous literature has the scientific validity and social value of proposed
by BMJ. explored a similar idea, under the terminology research. Moreover, given the history of unethical
To cite: King M, ‘pay to play’ or ‘pay to participate’ (PTP) research, medical research, there is a duty to protect potential
Ballantyne A. J Med Ethics where all participants pay for access to the trial.3–5 research participants from harm.
Epub ahead of print: [please A common feature of the models we focus on is that If these donor-funding models allow
include Day Month Year]. private donors are offered an opportunity to partic- good research to occur when it otherwise would not,
doi:10.1136/
medethics-2018-104966 ipate in clinical trials they fund, or otherwise access as has been the case,1 then prohibiting this research
to the experimental intervention. Hereafter, we will forgoes both the internal value of the transaction,
King M, Ballantyne A. J Med Ethics 2018;0:1–5. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-104966    1
Original research

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/medethics-2018-104966 on 18 September 2018. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on 22 September 2018 by guest. Protected by copyright.
and its public good externalities. This provides sufficient reason wealth. The third objection questions the public good of the
to consider such proposals seriously. research, due to concerns about the social value of interventions
that would be funded, and concerns about the scientific validity
of such studies. We consider these in turn.
Three donor-funding models
Here we outline three donor-funding models, where the donor Exploitation
pays (wholly or in part) for the costs of running the trial. Emanuel et al argue that "pay-to-play research is less likely to
be a collaborative partnership than a psychological exploitation
Plutocratic proposal of individuals desperate to do anything to save their own or a
In 2017, Masters and Nutt proposed a model where one donor loved one’s life[…] Although willingness to pay might indicate
funds, wholly or largely, a phase I or phase IIa clinical trial in understanding and voluntariness by participants, it might also
exchange for participation by them (or their nominee) in the reveal unrealistic expectations and undue pressure. The chances
trial, thereby receiving the test intervention (trials comparing for success of early-phase experimental drugs are much smaller
interventions are excluded).1 The donor’s transaction with the than either researchers or laypeople think."3
researchers is mediated by a ‘matching agency’, overseen by a There are two related concerns here. First that donors may
medical charity, which screens potential donors against poten- be especially vulnerable to the ‘therapeutic misconception’,
tial clinical trials for suitability, provides ethical review of trials, thereby undermining or invalidating consent. Second that even
permitting participation only for those donors/nominees that if consent is valid, donors may be exploited because they do not
meet clinical selection criteria for the trial. receive sufficient benefit from the experimental intervention, in
exchange for their considerable investment.
Pay to try The therapeutic misconception is a problem, but this problem
An alternative version involves the private funder (or their is not unique, nor necessarily worse, in donor-funded research.
nominee) accessing the experimental intervention, not as a Empirical work shows the therapeutic misconception remains
participant in the trial, but through compassionate use exemp- deeply problematic in research, especially in cancer research and
tion alongside the trial.2 The researchers recruit trial partici- research with terminal patients. Many studies show a high expec-
pants as per standard research practice. We call models with this tation of therapeutic benefit that likely reflects both misunder-
feature PTT. standing and optimistic attitude.10 11 One study found that 68%
of patients with cancer in phase I trials of experimental drugs did
Pay to play/participate not understand that they were involved in research rather than
A further variation that has been discussed in the literature receiving standard clinical care.12 Another study found that 89%
involves individual patients paying a fee for enrolment in a clin- of early phase oncology trials participants ranked the drugs’
ical trial, with price varying with research cost. Other details, potential to help fight their cancer as a major reason for partic-
such as whether paying enrollees are randomised across control ipation.13 In fact, many researchers also share this misconcep-
and treatment arms (if present in the study design) may vary.3–5 tion; in one study, fewer than half of research providers surveyed
These models all rely on private financial donations in recognised that the main purpose of clinical trials is to benefit
exchange for access to an experimental trial or intervention. future patients.14 Informed consent and patient understanding is
In both PP and PTP, access to the intervention is contingent on challenging in all oncology trials, and in donor-funded models.
participation in the clinical trial: donors are both funders of, We suggest that the risk of therapeutic misconception might
and participants in, the research. This dual donor-participant be higher than average in PTP research. Healthy volunteers
role raises the potential for conflicts of interest. The mediation correlate research risk to the amount of payment they receive for
structure of PP aims to eliminate potential conflicts of interest by participation—volunteers assume higher payment means riskier
reducing the power each party could have to act on conflicting research.15 We might extrapolate that if participants pay to
interests. participate, they may be more likely to believe that the interven-
While the sophisticated PP model is appealing, there is tion is beneficial, despite advice to the contrary. Sipp has made
currently no national or global infrastructure resembling the a related claim that payment for participation will increase the
proposed matching agency. Much of the appeal of the PP model perceived value of the trial by the participant, thereby increasing
relies on the existence of this infrastructure. To the extent that placebo effect proportionally and threatening the trial method-
any other model, such as PTT, may benefit from this or a similar ology.4 While Sipp seems primarily worried about the impact on
infrastructure this is also a problem for them, and the estab- the scientific validity of the trial, overestimating the benefit of
lishment of this infrastructure would be valuable. In the mean- the intervention can also amount to therapeutic misconception
time, it seems likely that bilateral agreements between donors and thereby threaten consent.
and researchers will be a feature of donor-funding models, at Is the risk of therapeutic misconception sufficient reason to
least initially, as was the case for neuroendocrine cancer research prevent PTP research? Given that we permit phase I cancer
Masters successfully funded using PP.2 trials with terminal patients, where we know the therapeutic
misconception affects around three-quarters of participants, it is
inconsistent to prohibit PTP research on the speculative grounds
Objections that therapeutic misconception could be higher in these cases.
The first objection we consider aims to undermine the value of We support the conclusion by Miller and Joffe that while these
the transaction for the donor and researcher: the transaction is empirical data suggest the need for enhanced informed consent
exploitative, and therefore bad for the donor, or morally wrong, processes, it does not invalidate consent nor necessitates prohibi-
or both. The second objection claims that it is an ethically illegit- tion of phase I oncology trials.16 Consistency would demand the
imate transaction; the potential benefits and harms of research same approach for PTP research.
participation ought not to be exchanged for money, and there- Furthermore, the risk of therapeutic misconception seems
fore distributed among potential participants on the basis of vastly reduced in PTT and PP models where only one, or a small
2 King M, Ballantyne A. J Med Ethics 2018;0:1–5. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-104966
Original research

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/medethics-2018-104966 on 18 September 2018. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on 22 September 2018 by guest. Protected by copyright.
number of, funders are involved and they are paying signif- Should trial places or research-related risk be traded for money?
icant amounts, close to £1 million, to enable the trial. With a The distribution of research risk and benefit between communi-
small number of funders, researchers or the matching agency ties based on financial resources is common. Clinical research
can spend more time ensuring they understand the nature of is increasingly outsourced to contract research organisations in
the research. Rather than paying to participate in a pre-existing low-income to middle-income countries to make use of large
trial, the funder(s) are actually funding the trial to get it off the patient populations that lack access to standard medical care.20
ground. They are explicitly wearing a research funding hat, in Outsourcing research essentially allows wealthy communities to
addition to a patient or participant hat. buy their way out of research risk. Their families and children
The second concern was that such research might exploit the do not undertake the risks of drug development, yet still benefit
donor by failing to deliver sufficient benefit. The concern here from successfully developed interventions. On the reverse, high-
is that the psychological vulnerability of donors may be wrong- tech, cutting-edge research, such as surgical robotics, is likely to
fully taken advantage of (intentionally or not) for the benefit of be conducted in tertiary hospitals in high-income countries and
researchers, and research. First, we should note that potential rural patients are unlikely to have equal access to this. Research
donor participants will not necessarily be in ill-health (especially conducted in private allied health facilities is often restricted to
at the start of a study), and some may have established medical those who can pay to purchase the clinical services (eg, sleep
options still available to them.i Second, the value of the chance clinics, physiotherapy, weight management). In all these cases,
to try an experimental intervention is subjective—depending in access to research participation and distribution of research risk
part on the donor’s available resources and their level of risk depends in part on the potential participants’ socioeconomic
aversion. Just as standard research subjects must assess a trial circumstances. We do not believe donor-funding models are
to see if for them the potential benefits outweigh the potential more commodifying than research practices we already allow.
burdens; so too must donor participants make this calculation. It would be inconsistent to prohibit them while permitting the
Even if the donor benefits less than the researcher, it is not others.
clear why this imbalance is sufficient to allow others to prohibit
the transaction. Where exploitation is mutually beneficial and Public good: social value
consensual it should not necessarily be prohibited, because to A further concern with donor-funding models is that they may
prohibit such transactions would make the vulnerable party even undermine the social value of research by skewing the research
worse off, compounding their disadvantage.17 18 agenda: “pay to play research would prioritise research needs of
Neither concerns about therapeutic misconception nor the wealthy and their aliments”.3
concerns about exploitation are sufficient to rule out donor- But all pharmaceutical industry-funded research, currently
funded research. three-quarters of all clinical research, prioritises the needs of the
patients in wealthy markets.21 The global poor bear the greatest
Fair subject selection burden of disease, and have the least economic resources with
Emanuel et al refer to concern about ‘fair subject selection’ in which to buy healthcare at profitable prices; they therefore
relation to PTP research funding: “selection of research subjects represent a poor market. Only roughly 1% of total research and
should be based on the goals of the research study, including development funding is directed towards neglected diseases, and
maximising internal validity and generalisability and on the seven to eight times the funding for clinical research is directed
obligation to minimise risk”, and not on ability to pay.3 This towards diseases affecting those from high-income countries,
can be interpreted as a concern about scientific validity (which compared with low-income and middle-income countries.21 If
we address later) or about justice and fair eligibility criteria. Emanuel et al are right that skewing the research agenda towards
A well-accepted premise of ethical research is that research those who can pay is sufficient to prohibit research that deviates
risk and benefits should be fairly distributed.19 Participants or from the perfectly just pattern of distribution, much more than
populations should not be unfairly excluded from research, donor-funded research ought to be prohibited.
nor overly burdened with research participation. PTP research Furthermore, current examples of these donor-funding
restricts places on trials to those who can pay, and PTT research models have focused on rare diseases that do not rank highly for
allows donors to avoid the risk of allocation to a control group. social utility reasons or according to the size of the market, and
Before we address this objection, it is worth noting a potential therefore do not appeal to either public or private sponsors. The
tension between the previous two concerns. On the one hand, PP has explicitly been developed by Masters and Nutt to address
potential donors are characterised as sick, desperate, vulnerable the gap in clinical research funding by focusing on neglected or
and open to the therapeutic misconception. On the other hand, orphan diseases, and used successfully for this purpose.1
they are characterised as wealthy, powerful and able to purchase There will be an irreducible element of chance. Of two equally
the benefits of research participation that are unfairly denied to worthy potential drugs, only one may receive PTT or PP funding
poorer patients. It is, however, possible that donors could be because there happens to be a wealthy affected funder. While
vulnerable in regard to their health, but simultaneously powerful funding of any specific drug may be random in this manner, it
in terms of the resources they have available.ii The point here is not clear that this would be unfair, as opposed to unlucky.
is that no single simplistic characterisation of donors or the Given the vast scale of the total global investment in research
donor-researcher relationship is plausible. Therefore, arguments and development, about 90% of which is from corporate and
about the permissibility of the these funding models should public funding,21 we doubt overall that donor-funding models
not be dependent on the accuracy of these assumptions about would skew the global research agenda. Even if they did have an
donors. impact, it is not clear that this would render the research agenda
more unjust.
Moreover, if donor-funding models did objectionably skew the
research agenda, it is not clear that the free exchange of goods
i 
We thank an anonymous reviewer for this suggestion. that they constitute ought to be prohibited. As Nozick argued,
ii 
We thank an anonymous reviewer for this observation. voluntary, permissible, exchanges can disrupt any patterned
King M, Ballantyne A. J Med Ethics 2018;0:1–5. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-104966 3
Original research

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/medethics-2018-104966 on 18 September 2018. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on 22 September 2018 by guest. Protected by copyright.
distribution.22 It is not straightforward that the solution to this is of their argument. The alternative critical approach is to reject
to override individual liberty in the relevant domain, as opposed consistency, and provide argument to justify this rejection.
to other options such as funding or incentivising other research
to re-orientate the agenda. Prohibition in this case would be
an example of pre-emptive levelling down, preventing valid Conclusion
research from being conducted. We have argued for the permissibility of donor-funding models
on the grounds of personal liberty, the facilitation of otherwise
Public good: scientific validity unfunded health research and consistent application of ethical
As we have seen, some of the critiques levelled at donor-funding standards. Our concern is that the initial criticisms of private
models have concerned potential threats to the scientific validity donor research funding models appear to assess these against
of the study, for example, that patients who fund trials may aspirational rather than real-world ethical standards. There is a
attempt to influence aspects of the study design, such as eligi- compelling public obligation to ensure the scientific validity and
bility criteria, the use of placebos and randomisation. social value of research. All human subjects research should be
Scientific validity is an essential value of ethical research. If regulated via standard health research legislation/guidelines and
the study does not generate valid results it will (at best) not add undergo IRB/REC and scientific peer-review. We expect that,
to knowledge, and (at worst) cause harm to participants and the measured against these standards, some donor-funded research
public by distorting the knowledge base. As with other clinical would be acceptable. Regarding all of the potential concerns,
research, donor-funded research must undergo research ethics the PP does the best job of minimising risks; and PTT is less
review and scientific peer-review. If reviewers are not confident risky than PTP (due to the smaller number of donors and there-
that the study can be designed and administered to achieve valid fore less chance for therapeutic misconception and conflicts of
result, then they should not approve the study. It is not clear that interest). In our view, there is nothing inherently unethical about
donor-funding model designs are so risky as to be automatically these forms of donor-funded research and no good reason to
precluded from REC/IRB consideration. outright prohibit them.
Of all the potential models, PTT seems the least risky in this
respect as the funder accesses the experimental drug outside the Acknowledgements  The authors would like to thank the audience of the
trial. PTP designs present the highest risk, as all participants are Asian-Australasian Association of Bioethics and Health Law Conference, and an
also funders and therefore the potential for them to put pressure anonymous referee for their helpful feedback on this work.
on the research methodology is maximised.5 Contributors  MK and AB made a substantial, and equal, contribution to
the conception of the work, each draft, revision and approval of final content.
Minimal standards as an ethical benchmark Both authors agree to be accountable for all aspects of the work and ensure
that questions related to the accuracy or integrity of any part of the work are
Throughout this paper we have used minimal standards of
appropriately investigated and resolved.
research ethics (rather than ideal or aspirational standard) as
Funding  This research received no specific grant from any funding agency in
the benchmark by which we measure proposed donor-funded
thepublic, commercial or not-for-profit sectors.
research. We have argued by analogy that these donor-funding
Competing interests  None declared.
models should be permitted because they are consistent with
much existing permissible research—a conservative argument Patient consent  Not required.
from consistency. Critics have argued that donor-funding Provenance and peer review  Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
should be prohibited because of fundamental ethical concerns
about scientific validity, social value, therapeutic misconcep-
tion, exploitation and fair subject selection. But the nature of References
the concerns levelled at donor-funding models are not qualita- 1 Masters A, Nutt D. A plutocratic proposal: an ethical way for rich patients to pay for a
tively, nor in many cases quantitatively, different from features of place on a clinical trial. J Med Ethics 2017;43:730–6.
2 Masters A. Mosaic. 2014. A plutocratic proposal. http://​mosaicscience.​com/​story/​
currently permitted health research. plutocratic-​proposal (accessed 31 Apr 2018).
There are two alternative conclusions that are worth consid- 3 Emanuel EJ, Joffe S, Grady C, et al. Clinical research: should patients pay to play? Sci
ering. A radical conclusion is that both donor-funded research Transl Med 2015;7:298ps16.
4 Sipp D. Pay-to-participate funding schemes in human cell and tissue clinical studies.
and much of the current medical research are unethical, and Regen Med 2012;7:105–11.
should be prohibited (eg, the large proportion of pharmaceuti- 5 Wenner DM, Kimmelman J, London AJ. Patient-funded trials: opportunity or liability?
cally funded research outsourced to lower middle-income coun- Cell Stem Cell 2015;17:135–7.
tries). In our view, the radical consistency argument would be a 6 Ballantyne A, Schaefer GO. Consent and the ethical duty to participate in health data
research. J Med Ethics 2018;44:392–6.
legitimate (if somewhat ambitious) response. Alternatively, one 7 Rodriguez-Monguio R, Spargo T, Seoane-Vazquez E. Ethical imperatives of timely
could conclude that consistency should not be the determining access to orphan drugs: is possible to reconcile economic incentives and patients’
factor. With so much medical research of questionable ethical health needs? Orphanet J Rare Dis 2017:12:1.
8 Baylis F, Ballantyne A, eds. Clinical research involving pregnant women. Cham:
status already occurring, why introduce more?iii We think this is Springer International Publishing, 2016.
a relevant consideration and worthy of further debate. 9 Kennedy-Martin T, Curtis S, Faries D, et al. A literature review on the
But note that neither of these arguments have been levelled representativeness of randomized controlled trial samples and implications for the
at donor-funding models in the literature. If these critics value external validity of trial results. Trials 2015;16:495.
10 Weinfurt KP, Seils DM, Tzeng JP, et al. Expectations of benefit in early-phase clinical
consistency, they ought to acknowledge and defend the radicalism trials: implications for assessing the adequacy of informed consent. Med Decis
Making 2008;28:575–81.
11 Sulmasy DP, Astrow AB, He MK, et al. The culture of faith and hope. Cancer
2010;116:3702–11.
iii 
12 Pentz RD, White M, Harvey RD, et al. Therapeutic misconception, misestimation, and
A similar argument is made in relation to legalising recreational drugs, optimism in participants enrolled in phase 1 trials. Cancer 2012;118:4571–8.
for example, ‘marijuana may be less harmful than alcohol, but given 13 Kass NE, Sugarman J, Medley AM, et al. An intervention to improve cancer patients’
alcohol is already legal we ought not to legalise additional harmful understanding of early-phase clinical trials. IRB 2009;31:1–10.
substances’. For discussion of this view, see Wolff J. Ethics and Public 14 Joffe S, Cook EF, Cleary PD, et al. Quality of informed consent in cancer clinical trials: a
Policy: A Philosophical Inquiry, Routledge 2011, pp. 78–79. cross-sectional survey. Lancet 2001;358:1772–7.

4 King M, Ballantyne A. J Med Ethics 2018;0:1–5. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-104966


Original research

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/medethics-2018-104966 on 18 September 2018. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on 22 September 2018 by guest. Protected by copyright.
15 Cryder CE, John London A, Volpp KG, et al. Informative inducement: study payment as 20 Balbinot RAA, Bhagianadh D, da Freitas CBD, et al. Putting contract research
a signal of risk. Soc Sci Med 2010;70:455–64. organisations on the radar: an exploratory study on outsourcing of clinical trials
16 Miller FG, Joffe S. Phase 1 oncology trials and informed consent. J Med Ethics by pharmaceutical companies to contract research organisations in nontraditional
2013;39:761–4. trial regions. Amsterdam: Centre for Research on Multinational Corporations,
17 Wertheimer A. Rethinking the ethics of clinical research: widening the lens. New York: Salud y Fármacos, Centre for Studies in Ethics and Rights, 2011. (accessed 27 Apr
Oxford University Press, 2011.
2018).
18 Ballantyne AJ. How to do research fairly in an unjust world. Am J Bioeth
2010;10:26–35. 21 Røttingen JA, Regmi S, Eide M, et al. Mapping of available health research and
19 World Health Organization, Council for International Organizations of Medical development data: what’s there, what’s missing, and what role is there for a global
Sciences. International ethical guidelines for health-related research involving observatory? Lancet 2013;382:1286–307.
humans. Geneva: CIOMS, 2017. 2 2 Nozick R. Anarchy, state, and utopia. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2012.

King M, Ballantyne A. J Med Ethics 2018;0:1–5. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-104966 5

You might also like