Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 60

ISSUE 124 FEBRUARY / MARCH 2018 UK £3.75 USA $7.99 CANADA $8.

99

PhilosophyNow
a magazine of ideas

War!
What you need
to know

Farewell
to Fodor

Hobbes: nasty,
brutish, short?
What’s Wrong
with Relativism?
FrAnTz
FaNoN
Edited by JEAN KHALFA and ROBERT J. C. YOUNG
Translated by STEVEN CORCORAN
The only remaining untranslated work by
major 20th-century writer Frantz Fanon,
now available in English.
www.bloomsbury.com/philosophy
@BloomsburyPhilo

Hardback | 9781474250214 | eBook | 9781474250245 | £19.99

The Ultimate Guide Series


Out Now!
UK £6.99 USA $12.99 CANADA $13.99
Philosophy Now are excited to announce
The Ultimate Guide The Ultimate Guide series: each issue a
Philosophy Now
collection of the best previously
ISSUE ONE: ETHICS
published articles we have on a given
topic, conveniently all in one place.
When apes have
their day in court

Virtue ethics and


the New Testament
Issue One, on Ethics, is your go-to
Find out: What kind
guide for moral philosophy.
of ethicist are you?

Available now at philosophynow.org/shop

ETHICS
and selected retailers.

Philosophy Now
02

9770961597055

a magazine of ideas
Philosophy Now ISSUE 124 Feb/Mar 2018
Philosophy Now, EDITORIAL & NEWS
43a Jerningham Road, 4 Sticks and Stones Rick Lewis
Telegraph Hill,
London SE14 5NQ 5 News
United Kingdom 17 Interview: Aaron James
Tel. 020 7639 7314
editors@philosophynow.org Skye Cleary asks the author about Surfing with Sartre
philosophynow.org 47 Obituary: Jerry Fodor
Daniel Hutto says goodbye to a great thinker and debater
Editor-in-Chief Rick Lewis
Editors Anja Steinbauer, Grant Bartley WAR & PHILOSOPHY
Digital Editor Bora Dogan
6 The Philosophy of War
Graphic Design Grant Bartley, Katy
Baker, Anja Steinbauer Ziyad Hayatli explains how it evolved down the ages
Book Reviews Editor Teresa Britton 10 Bergson: Rights, Instincts, Visions & War
Film Editor Thomas Wartenberg
Marketing Manager Sue Roberts Carl Strasen heeds Henri Bergson’s warnings about the war-instinct
Administration Ewa Stacey, Katy Baker 14 Asian Non-Violent Voices
Advertising Team Oidinposha Imamkhodjaeva on some Eastern kinds of pacifism
Jay Sanders, Ellen Stevens
jay.sanders@philosophynow.org GENERAL ARTICLES
UK Editorial Board
Rick Lewis, Anja Steinbauer,
Bora Dogan, Grant Bartley
War & Peace 18 The Puzzle of Patriotism
Phil Badger examines three models of patriotism
US Editorial Board but not so long. Pages 6-16 22 Free Will Is Still Alive!
Dr Timothy J. Madigan (St John Fisher
College), Prof. Charles Echelbarger, Carlo Filice is determined to argue for free choice
Prof. Raymond Pfeiffer, Prof. Massimo 25 Is Everything A Computer?
Pigliucci (CUNY - City College), Prof.
Teresa Britton (Eastern Illinois Univ.)
Paul Austin Murphy wonders whether that’s logical
Contributing Editors 26 Splitting Chairs
Alexander Razin (Moscow State Univ.) Quentin Mareuse carefully cuts some stuff up
Laura Roberts (Univ. of Queensland)
David Boersema (Pacific University) 29 Twelve Principles of Knowledge
UK Editorial Advisors George Dunseth lists twelve tests for truth
Piers Benn, Constantine Sandis, Gordon 30 Are You A Garbled Relativist?
Giles, Paul Gregory, John Heawood
US Editorial Advisors Ray Prebble won’t let relativists get away with vagueness
Prof. Raymond Angelo Belliotti, Toni 34 Why False Beliefs Are Not Always Bad
Vogel Carey, Prof. Walter Sinnott-
Armstrong, Prof. Harvey Siegel Sally Latham reports on an unusual project
Cover Image ‘Uncertain Times’ REVIEWS
© iStock.com/serazetdinov
48 Book: Experiencing Time, by Simon Prosser
Printed by The Manson Group Ltd reviewed by Heather Dyke
8 Porters Wood, Valley Road Industrial 50 Book: The Trolley Problem Mysteries, by Frances Kamm
Estate, St Albans AL3 6PZ
reviewed by Richard Baron
UK newstrade distribution through:
Intermedia Brand Marketing Ltd Knowledge, 51 Book: Anger & Forgiveness, by Martha Nussbaum
reviewed by Trevor Pateman
Tel. 01293 312001
or lack of it 52 Film: Alien: Covenant
US & Canadian bookstores through: Mini theme, pages 29-37 Stefan Bolea on humans, non-humans and gods
Disticor Magazine Distribution Services
695 Westney Road S., Unit 14, REGULARS
Ajax, Ontario L1S 6M9
Tel. (905) 619 6565
9 Philosophical Haiku: Siddhartha Gautama, the Buddha
Terence Green
Australian newstrade distribution: 38 Brief Lives: Thomas Hobbes
Gordon & Gotch pty
Level 2, 9 Rodborough Road Alistair MacFarlane says he wasn’t nasty, brutish or short
French’s Forest, NSW 2086 41 Philosophy Then: Wittgenstein & The War
Tel. 02 9972 8800
Peter Adamson looks at what Wittgenstein did in WWI
The opinions expressed in this magazine 42 The Street Philosopher: Torpid In A Taxi
do not necessarily reflect the views of Sean Moran thinks about sleeping on the job
the editor or editorial board of
Philosophy Now. 44 Letters to the Editor
56 Tallis in Wonderland: On Looking at the Back of My Hand
Philosophy Now is published by
Anja Publications Ltd Raymond Tallis finds more there than just freckles
ISSN 0961-5970 FICTION
Subscriptions p.54 58 Freedom 2199
Shop p.55 Jonathan Sheasby’s curious computer asks if freedom is real
Time Flies
Or does it? Page 48 February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 3
Editorial Sticks and Stones
“I don’t know what weapons World War III will be fought with, but trade, will make war unthinkable. But we still have a long way
World War IV will be fought with sticks and stones.” to go, and we don’t know how much time we have left. So far
(variously attributed to Albert Einstein, President Harry Truman and we have been over-reliant on sheer luck to avoid disaster.
an unnamed US Army lieutenant at the Bikini Atoll A-bomb tests) The approach of science and philosophy when confronted
with some vast human problem is always first to try to under-

I
t’s always an advantage in any philosophical debate to stand it thoroughly, then on that basis find ways to overcome
have the last word. If civilisation gets wiped out in a it. Things we comprehend can still kill us, but we stand a
nuclear war this month (and I’d love to believe that this is better chance against them. Unfortunately military
a far-fetched scenario) then perhaps future archaeologists, technology has recently advanced much faster than our under-
human or otherwise, will unearth a few scorched copies of this standing of the social and psychological forces that lead us to
magazine in the topmost layers of debris. That seems a good go to war in the first place. But other advances are happening
enough reason for this issue to have a theme of war and peace. too, more quietly, such as the application of game theory to
War has been a topic of scholarship and discussion since the prediction of military outcomes, and the study of how
ancient times. Some of the classic texts about it have been of wars start, and of the most effective ways to stop them. We
the ‘How to’ variety: books of strategy like Sun Tzu’s The Art learn, gradually. Maybe we can understand human behaviour
of War in the 5th century BC, or Clausewitz’s On War in the fast enough to avert our doom?
19th century. Philosophers have been more concerned with So how do wars break out? A pithy summary of the main
whether and when war should be waged. There have been the ways can be found in a recent article by David Welch in
starkest disagreements among them. A few thinkers (usually Canada’s Globe and Mail newspaper, in which he analyses the
not those of fighting age) have positively glorified war, or else probability of war in Korea. He says, “Generally speaking,
argued that war being sometimes inevitable, it should be there are four pathways to war: states can choose them delib-
pursued ruthlessly and singlemindedly to attain swift victory. erately on the basis of a cost-benefit calculation; they can
Conversely, there have been philosophers throughout history stumble into them inadvertently; they can be pushed into
who have been pacifists of one kind or another, arguing that them by public opinion; and they can be pulled into them by
it’s wrong to resort to violence even under the severest provo- allies.”
cation (see our article on non-violence in Eastern philo- Why would anyone choose to go to war? Certainly fear or
sophical traditions). envy often plays a part. But given that war is death, maiming,
Many major philosophers, though, have taken a middle destruction, bereavement, and horror, it’s enduring popularity
position, deploring wars but hoping to influence rulers to avoid is hard to fathom. Naturally, some philosophers have tried to
the worst excesses. In this spirit, in the Middle Ages Saint fathom it anyway. Henri Bergson was France’s most famous
Thomas Aquinas and other philosophers developed a set of philosopher a century ago, and is now sadly neglected. He
rules as to when it might be considered justified to wage war, thought in depth about these problems, and their connections
and regarding conduct during wars too. This ‘Just War Theory’ with the nature of societies, and also believed we have an
remains influential in international law even today. We’ve innate ‘war instinct’. (You can read more about his ideas in
printed a list of Aquinas’ rules. Do keep it somewhere handy in Carl Strasen’s article). Then there is patriotism; a force for
case you are ever attacked by an army of medieval monks – social cohesion and pride perhaps, and certainly not respon-
perhaps in a dream, or in a computer game, who knows? sible for all wars, but it equally certainly has fed support for
Anyway, Ziyad Hayatli in our lead article tells the history of the many. Phil Badger in his article critically examines three
philosophy of war, and of philosophy engagement in interna- models for understanding patriotism.
tional law, and brings it right up to the present. Sticks and stones may break my bones but words can never
To some extent it is a success story. Hayatli tells how hurt me, or so I’ve been told. There will always be conflict
Hugo Grotius in the 17th century saw the world as a loose and tension; Heraclitus called war the Father of All because
society of nations; Immanuel Kant later made proposals for strife pushes change forwards. But nations and factions now
international rules to avoid war in his essay Perpetual Peace. need to pursue their conflicts in ways that stop short of war.
They helped inspire the growth in international organisations Insults, ridicule, invective – the world can survive all these.
and treaties and an international legal order, and the United Sticks and stones too. But if words between nuclear powers
Nations, all of which have certainly helped to avert particular ever escalate to actions, then all our squabbles and specula-
wars. Maybe one day such institutions, and globalisation, and tions could come to an abrupt end.

4 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


• Remembering Murphy’s Law • Control cars
with your mind! (What could go wrong?)

News
• Children and chimpanzees crave revenge
News reports by Anja Steinbauer and Filiz Peach

Inventor of Murphy’s Law stage of development, Nissan prognosti- Hans Saner


Born 100 Years Ago cates that it may be ready for “practical Swiss philosopher Hans Saner has died
Does a dropped slice of toast always land application in 5 to 10 years.” The company aged 83 after a long illness. An original
buttered side down? Is the queue you gave live demonstrations of the new tech- thinker in his own right, Saner was also
choose at the supermarket checkout always nology at the Consumer Electronics Show well known for his connection with one of
the slowest moving? January saw the 100th (CES) in Las Vegas in January. Ironically, the great figures from the golden age of
anniversary of the birth of Edward A. the hi-tech show was shut down for several existentialist philosophy: Karl Jaspers.
Murphy Jr, inventor of Murphy’s Law. An hours by a power outage caused by torren- From 1962 to 1969 he was Jaspers’ last
aerospace engineer, he is reported to have tial rain. It was the first rainfall in the personal assistant at the University of
said “Anything that can go wrong, will go desert city for 116 days. No doubt Murphy Basel. He edited much of Jaspers’ later
wrong” during a frustrating set of rocket- would have been amused. work, as well as writing extensive
sled experiments in 1949 in which he was commentaries on it. Saner also authored
investigating how much acceleration the Payback Time numerous books and articles on art,
human body could withstand. As it turned How is life in a community possible? What science, religion and politics, some of
out, the sixteen painstakingly-arranged kind of social behaviour is essential? There which have been translated into eleven
sensors on the test pilot had been fastened has been extensive research into empathy in languages. They include Identity and Resis-
at the wrong angle so that no readings humans and primates, but little has been tance (1988), The Anarchy of Silence (1990),
could be taken. Murphy was irritated by known about a much more negative yet The Shadow of Orpheus (2000), and Non-
jocular interpretations of his Law; far from equally ubiquitous impulse, the desire for Optimal Strategies (2002). He also wrote a
being a fatalist he simply wanted to high- revenge on someone who has displayed number of essays on Kant, Spinoza,
light as a design principle that: “If there are antisocial behaviour. Now social neurosci- Jaspers and Hannah Arendt.
two or more ways to do something and one entists and evolutionary anthropologists Hans Saner worked as a primary school
of those ways can result in a catastrophe, from two Max Planck Institutes in Leipzig teacher in the Bernese Oberland for five
then someone will at some point do it.” have tried to find out at what age humans years in the 1950s. He then studied
develop the inclination to watch a deserved Psychology, Philosophy and German at
Of Cars and Brains punishment and if chimpanzees do the the University of Basel. He completed his
The carmaker Nissan has unveiled a same. Using puppet shows to test children’s dissertation on Kant’s political philosophy
project to help drivers execute emergency responses, they found that children develop in 1967. Saner was known for his outspo-
manoeuvres up to half a second faster by the desire for witnessing a deserved come- ken political views and was rejected for a
using brainwave interface technology. uppance around the age of six. Then, using philosophy teaching post by the Univer-
The ‘brain-to-vehicle’ interface that they a good-cop, bad-cop scenario in which sity of Bern apparently for being ‘too left
are developing recognises if a driver is zookeepers removed or supplied food to wing’. He instead became a lecturer at the
about to stop, brake, swerve or perform chimpanzees, they found that the primates Music Academy in Basel in 1979 where he
some other evasive move, and begins the had similar reactions to the older children. taught cultural philosophy until 2008.
action immediately, saving vital time. Cars “Our results demonstrate that six-year-old Saner had great faith in philosophy.
with semi-autonomous capabilities could children and even chimpanzees want to During an interview (Philosophy Now Issue
be fitted with this technology in future. avenge antisocial behaviour and that they 32) he was asked what he thought of the
Although the system is still at a fairly early feel an urge to watch it. This is where the future of philosophy. His answer was
evolutionary roots of such behaviour origi- short and sharp: “it will be needed.” He
Nissan demo at CES
nate, a crucial characteristic to manage was convinced that everybody could
living in a community,” explains Natacha philosophise. However, he thought that
Mendes, co-author of the published study in “the only difference is that trained
Nature Human Behaviour. Her colleague philosophers are often arrogant.”
Nikolaus Steinbeis adds: “We cannot defi-
nitely say that the children and chimpanzees Jerry Fodor Dies
felt spite. However, their behaviour is a One of the best-known contemporary
clear sign that six-year-old children as well philosophers of mind, the functionalist
as chimpanzees are eager to observe how Jerry Fodor, died on November 29, 2017
uncooperative members of their community at the age of 82. There is a full obituary in
are punished.” this issue.

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 5


War & Peace
The Philosophy of War
Ziyad Hayatli presents a condensed history of the philosophy of war.

term such as ‘the laws of war’ seems oxymoronic in

A nature: a contradiction in terms. On the one hand,


law is a rigid structure of rules that’s associated with
order; on the other hand, war is an activity charac-
terised by chaos and destruction. Yet there is now an under-
standing that when one goes to war, certain behaviours are
expected, and when these standards are violated, demands for
international justice are broadcast on the air, written in the
papers, and shouted through the megaphones. Institutions such
as the United Nations are chided as toothless, useless due to
their limitations. The International Criminal Court is caught
up in the debates about the laws and lawfulness of war, and they
are numerous, concerning drone warfare, artificial intelligence,
collateral damage, winning hearts and minds, chemical and bio-
logical weapons, the need for nuclear deterrence, and the very
idea of humanitarian military intervention.
This article will look at the whys and wherefores of the laws
of war from a philosophical perspective, beginning with the
natural law theories of the Middle Ages, to which we owe a sub-
stantial just war doctrine, and moving onto the Enlightenment,
during which new conceptions of state and sovereignty would
change the idea of war. There are two considerations I’d like
you to keep in mind: firstly, that wars and their consequences
tend to change the international order of things; secondly, that
ideas about the nature of war are closely tied to conceptions of
what a state is, and how states relate to one another.

Laws As Natural
Back in the Middle Ages, Western philosophy generally assumed
that morality was an inherent characteristic of mankind as a gift Hugo Grotius by Mierevel 1631
from God. Laws built upon this inherent morality were known
as Natural Laws. In regards to the laws of war, scholastics and The end of the Thirty Years’ War in 1648 saw the adoption of
theologians from Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) to Hugo Grotius this and other recommendations in what became known as the
(1583-1645) developed a substantial doctrine of ‘Just War Peace of Westphalia, by which much of Europe was transformed
Theory’ – a theory of when waging war was just, and when it from a group of hierarchical states vertically aligned under Pope
was unjust (‘jus ad bellum’), as well as what sort of behaviour was and Emperor, to horizontally arranged equal sovereign states.
just within war (‘jus in bello’). [See text box]. This also changed the nature of wars in Europe. They became
Hugo Grotius published his seminal work De Jure Belli ac what some called ‘secularised’.
Pacis (The Law of War and Peace) in 1629. For Europe, this was
a time of upheaval known as the Thirty Years’ War, in which Laws As Self-Interest
Catholic and Protestant states were warring against one another. Just three years later, in 1651, the English philosopher Thomas
In this work Grotius described the political order as a loose Hobbes published Leviathan. For a time this cemented how
international society. He also explored the basic idea of self war, and morality as a whole, was conceived.
defence as a lawful use of force, on both the private and the state The basic premise of Leviathan is that, as a matter of survival
level. His insights earned him the title ‘the father of interna- and for the sake of cohesion, the members of a society give up
tional law’. Most importantly, Grotius made recommendations certain liberties to a sovereign, who becomes responsible for
which showed a remarkable amount of tolerance, given the applying laws and protecting private property. The ideas of
political climate. One was that war waged against others just morality and the laws built upon them in this case reflected social
because of their different interpretation of Christianity is unjust. interests, especially in determining the strength and scope of

6 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


War & Peace
the power of the sovereign towards his subjects. God and natu-
ral law did not factor into this view. Although Hobbes did not
deny its existence, he believed that natural law was not what
kept people in line. As he wrote:

“For the laws of nature, as justice, equity, modesty, mercy and, in sum,
doing to others as we would be done to, of themselves, without the
terror of some power, to cause them to be observed, are contrary to
our natural passions, that carry us to partiality, pride, revenge and the
like. And covenants without the sword are but words, and of no strength
to secure a man at all.” (Part 2, Chapter 17, ‘Of Commonwealth’).

This arguably applies not only to agreements between pri-


vate citizens, but also to the international order of states. There
the ‘fear of the sword’ is maintained by a balance of power –
what prevents states from going to war is fear of consequences,
economic, political, and social. Conversely, by Hobbes’ logic,
if one sovereign state determines that going to war against
another is to its own best interest, then a war is justified for
that state.
The cynics among us may point out that this has always been
the case. During the time of the Thirty Years’ War, for instance,
there was much political self-interest in the waging of wars, Henry Dunant
despite the superficial religious justification. Nevertheless,
Hobbes made the ‘self-interest’ aspect more explicit, and pre- described receives what cohesion it has from that principle,
sented an alternative view to Grotius’s vision of a naturally which is known as ‘reciprocity’ in the international legal field.
formed ‘international society’. It’s hardly surprising then that The time-honoured tradition of respecting another state’s
while Grotius is considered the father of international law, ambassadors and envoys, even if it is a hostile power, is a legacy
Hobbes is considered the father of the ‘realist’ school of thought of this. On the other hand, Hobbes’ view that a fear of the sword
in international relations. [For more on Hobbes, see ‘Brief and balance of power is a driving force for political behaviour
Lives’ in this issue, Ed.] also holds true. Given the delicate nature of this balance, and
The natural law to which Hobbes refers in the quotation that the interests of a state are subject to interpretation by its
above, of ‘doing to others as we would be done to’, is of partic- rulers, then wars are an inescapable phenomenon.
ular significance. For the loose international society Grotius
The Birth of the Red Cross
Regardless of the legitimacy or otherwise of any given war (jus
THE RULES OF JUST WAR THEORY
ad bellum), there is a separate question of legitimate conduct
Jus ad bellum within war (jus in bello). It was this latter question that a Swiss
These are the rules for when it is just to go to war. businessman called Henry Dunant asked after he witnessed first-
1) Does the war have Just Authority (Auctoritas)? hand the horrors of war at the Battle of Solferino in 1859.
2) Does the war have Just Cause (Causa)? The Battle of Solferino was waged between the Austrian
3) Is the war being started with the Right Intentions (Intentio) Empire and Franco-Piedmontese forces in northern Italy. It
4) Is the proposed military action proportional to the situation? was described as a battle fought with “disastrous short-sighted-
5) Is there a good probability of success in achieving the war’s ness, improvisation and negligence.” It led to 6,000 dead and
aim? approximately 40,000 wounded after the two armies clashed
6) Peaceful alternatives must all have been exhausted first. amid a hail of artillery. The medical services on both sides were
overwhelmed, and the negligence of the supply corps was
Jus in bello exposed as the medical service’s transport was requisitioned to
These are the rules guiding behaviour once a war has started transport ammunition instead. Although the fighting lasted fif-
1) Discrimination: no violence towards civilians, or combatants teen hours, it took six days to remove ten thousand wounded,
who have surrendered. most of whom were carried by peasants’ carts to nearby villages
2) Proportionality: harm to lives or property must not be dispropor- with the hope of getting a little food and water.
tionate to the military advantage expected to be gained. Henry Dunant arrived in the nearby village of Castiglione
3) Responsibility: Every individual, regardless of rank, is personally on 24th June 1859, originally with hopes of gaining an audi-
responsible for any war crime that he might commit. Soldiers must ence with Napoleon III. He met instead a flood of suffering that
refuse to obey any orders that they know to be immoral was not being stemmed; and so took it upon himself to mobi-
4) No use of certain unacceptable weapons and tactics (eg rape, lize volunteers – mostly local women and girls – to provide what-
or forcing captives to fight their own side, or biological weapons). ever care they could. He sent his coachman to buy much needed

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 7


War & Peace

The Battle of Solferino, 1859

supplies from Brescia, such as cloth and material for dressings. ever, the ICRC reinvigorated and promulgated the distinction
He also encouraged volunteers to show the same level of sym- between military and non-military in a more modern and global
pathy and care for wounded enemy Austrians, and arranged for context. Now, the ICRC considers it as a core principle.
the release of Austrian doctors so that they could also tend the This philosophy of war views the state as an intangible entity
wounded. What he witnessed in the next two weeks was pub- composed of agents who fulfil its interests at every level, from
lished in his account, A Memory of Solferino. This account and soldiers to civil servants and law-makers. Given that the con-
subsequent work by Dunant led to the formation of the Inter- cept of the state has been closely linked with philosophies of
national Committee of the Red Cross in 1863. war (both ad bellum and in bello), the second half of the Twenti-
Philosophically, Dunant’s book questions how a state could eth Century would bring about fresh challenges.
be so negligent towards its own soldiers once they are of ‘no use’,
and argues for the importance of principles when fighting wars. The Twentieth Century and Beyond: New Challenges
It also emphasised the idea of preventing needless suffering. To Just as the Thirty Years’ War changed the European order, so
Henry Dunant, a combatant was an agent of the state, fulfilling the Second World War changed the world order. Grotius’s idea
a duty delegated by that state, and when that combatant is of a loose international society really came to fruition with the
wounded to the point that they’re no longer able to fulfil that subsequent creation of the United Nations in 1945. And just as
duty, they cease to become such agents. There is no further point societies always do, a global community of states sought to make
in killing, maiming, or torturing them. While war may be unpre- certain behaviours taboo. Wars of aggression and expansion-
ventable, the suffering therein can and should be constrained. ism became unacceptable. Officially, war became permissible
This way of thinking informs the principle of distinction, in only two circumstances: self-defence, or by a binding reso-
whereby military targets must be distinguished from non-tar- lution from the Security Council. Chapter VII of The United
gets. This rule was already present in Christian and Islamic tra- Nations Charter in its entirety, and particularly Article 51, makes
ditions, such as in the tenth century Peace of God Movement this point very clearly. But the so-called ‘global society of states’
in France, the St. Petersburg Declaration, and Islamic Sunni rul- has found loopholes. And the new world of decolonisation,
ings in general (see H. Shue, ‘Laws of War’ in The Philosophy of national liberation, human rights treaties, and sovereign state
International Law, S. Besson & J. Tasioulas (eds), 2010). How- self-determination introduced a new kind of entity onto the

8 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


Philosophical Haiku
international field – ‘territorial non-state actors’. These were
organisations that closely resembled states, but were not quite
states. They’re perfect vessels for states to engage in proxy war-
fare, where neither side directly engages the other. Now argu-
ing for humanitarian intervention became the new tactic.
For a long time the concept of warfare had been closely
wedded to the concept of the state, but no more as territorial
non-state actors became a significant part of the world of war.
Terms such as ‘terrorism’ and ‘freedom fighter’ entered every-
one’s lexicon. And no discussion of war is complete without
mentioning the ‘War on Terror’. The challenge of developing
a new philosophy where combatants include not only the func-
tionary of states but also terrorists or freedom fighters is very
real. The late international legal scholar Antonio Cassese called
this the ‘Freedom Fighter’s Problem’ (see his International Crim-
inal Law, 2013, 3rd ed., especially Ch. 8 on terrorism). Are ter-
rorists, or ‘combatants of a non-state actor’, different to the sol-
diers of a conventional army? If so, how and why? Do we restrict
human rights in the face of such an enemy, for the sake of
national security? Or would the reduction of human rights have
a worsening effect? These are the debates we are having today.
Cassese himself explored how the word ‘terrorism’ is sometimes
used in a manipulative way that merely reflects a state’s inter- SIDDHARTHA GAUTAMA: THE BUDDHA
ests. This is not to say that terrorism is not a real threat or a (563-483 BCE?)
genuine phenomenon, however.
The conflict in Syria is emblematic of this new world of war. All ceases to be
It has truly tested the morality of combatants, observers, and Suffering is eternal
Let go and be free
political commentators. Accusations of human rights abuses,
child conscription, and war by proxy fly around left and right.

T
On the one hand there is a despotic, merciless tyrant; on the hroughout his youth, Siddhartha Gautama was just your typical
other rebels, some of whom have highly questionable beliefs humble North Indian prince growing up in luxury and splendour
and patrons. The tyrant stands up to global imperialism and and shielded from suffering. Inevitably, given this upbringing,
proxy warfare from the ‘hypocritical West’; yet the rebels stand he was shocked to discover the suffering and death of ordinary
up to ‘tyranny’ and ‘despotism’. people beyond the palace walls. So at age twenty-nine he decided to
give up the trying existence of a prince in favour of the simpler life of a
Conclusion wandering seeker after truth. He ditched not only his wealth and the
Philosophers of war and of the rules of war ultimately divide creature comforts wealth brings, but his wife and son also (incidentally,
into two schools of thought. One is represented by the prag- he’d named his son Rāhula, meaning fetter – make of that what you
matic optimist Grotius, who believed in a loose global society will), and took to the road as a wandering ascetic (sort of like a wan-
and reciprocity; the other by the more cynical ‘realist’, Hobbes, dering minstrel, but not as much fun). But after several years of wal-
who believed that the pragmatism of self-interest leads to the lowing in austerity, denying his body sometimes even to the point of
fear of the sword and the balance of power. The justifications starvation, he decided that this wasn’t the answer either. Then, while
which a person accepts for going to war - and for particular sitting under a Bodhi tree, perhaps wondering if he’d made a terrible
actions within a war - will depend on their other convictions mistake giving up his riches, he experienced an epiphany, or more prop-
and disposition. erly, a moment of enlightenment; and so was born the Middle Way. Thus
Although, to put it mildly, not every soldier or politician in did the prince become the Buddha – meaning, the enlightened one:
history has observed the laws of war, we can recognize that and verily did he seek to spread the word that, however you look at it,
these laws have formed over time either for the interest of states life is just one long painful moment. The first ‘noble truth’ of Buddhism
or because there genuinely is an international society with some is that the fundamental character of life is suffering. Lest you find this
sort of conscience. Such laws and agreements as are found in a tad dreary, the good news is that by achieving nirvana we can escape
documents like the Geneva Convention are therefore a legal this vale of tears. And to achieve nirvana? All you have to do is cease
heritage for the world. It can be hoped that we are able to face desiring, since it is desire that causes the suffering. And you can achieve
the philosophical challenge of new concepts of war without that by following the Middle Way. That’s it. As a promise of salvation,
utterly desecrating this heritage. you might think that no one would go for it; but several hundred mil-
© ZIYAD HAYATLI 2018 lion Buddhists would beg to differ.
Ziyad Hayatli has a BA in Philosophy & Journalism, and an LLM © TERENCE GREEN 2018
Masters in International Law. He has worked for Amnesty Interna- Terence is a writer, historian, and lecturer, and lives with his wife
tional as a research assistant and Arabic interpreter. and their dog in Paekakariki, NZ. hardlysurprised.blogspot.co.nz

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 9


War & Peace

Bergson:Rights, Instincts,
Visions & War
Carl Strasen says Henri Bergson’s ideas about wars need rediscovering.
hile he is almost forgotten today, the French and our territorial instincts threatened our future as a species.

W thinker Henri Bergson (1859-1941) was perhaps


the most famous philosopher of the WWI era.
His extraordinary skills as a lecturer, and his 1907
bestseller Creative Evolution, made his visit to the US a media
It is worth looking at WWI briefly to put our current prob-
lems with terrorism into perspective. Consider the Battle of the
Somme in 1916. During the first day of combat, over 25,000 British
soldiers were killed, with some regiments having 90% causality


event and a public street nightmare. Strange as it seems to us rates. The impact of WWI on European populations was pro-
now, the first rush hour traffic jam on New York’s Broadway was found: Germany lost 15.1% of its active male population; Aus-
caused by the flood of people hoping to attend a Bergson lecture. tria-Hungary lost 17.1%; and France lost 10.5%. Yet unlike other
Bergson always approached philosophical problems by sepa- philosophers of the era, such as Bertrand Russell, Bergson was a


rating out quantitative differences – differences in degree or staunch advocate of continuing to fight WWI, because the Ger-
amount – from qualitative differences – differences in kind. Dif- mans were trying to invade his homeland, France. He was only
ferentiating differences in kind from those in degree is a bit like interested in peace after the Germans had been defeated.
the old saying in math classes that you can’t add apples to oranges. The French government enlisted Bergson’s help in 1917 in
When this sorting and sifting of types of differences between a secret mission to America. As P.A.Y. Gunther writes in A Com-
ideas is done, Bergson hopes that the philosophic knot has been panion to Continental Philosophy (1994), he was “authorized to
loosened enough to allow the circulation of understanding.
In his first two books Bergson uses this method to show how One problem is that human
space is different in kind from time, and how the brain is dif-
ferent in kind from memory. The upshot of these seemingly rights are often crushed just
arcane insights is a validation of human freedom against deter- when they are needed most;
minism, via what Bergson calls ‘la durée’ (duration) which is the
sort of extended consciousness we have when listening to music, when there’s a strong feeling
for instance. In Creative Evolution, Bergson’s insights are
extended into the flow of evolution, which is given a force of of ‘us against them’ and
its own, called the élan vital, or vital impulse. This impulse finds cruelty against a minority
manifestations in instinct and intelligence in all species. In his
last work, The Two Sources of Morality and Religion (1932) Berg- becomes justified by the fears
son finishes by pursuing how a closed society is different in kind
from an open society. So Bergson’s effort to demonstrate and of the majority.
analyze differences in kind between the dualities of space/time,
memory/brain, subjective/objective, intuition/rationality, lived
time/measured time, human/insect, open society/closed soci- promise President Wilson that if he would bring the United
ety, trace the arc of his thought, with the prize being the reunion States into the First World War on the side of the Allies, after
of religion and science. This effort in mending dualities made the war Britain and France would back the creation of a League
him Descartes’ heir, a Nobel Prize winner, and for some time of Nations, dedicated to maintaining world peace.” And indeed,
in France he was philosophy’s superhero. Of Bergson and his with Bergson adding to the tipping point, the US did enter
kindred spirit philosopher William James, President Theodore WWI, and Germany was defeated. President Wilson then saw
Roosevelt noted that “every truly scientific and truly religious his dream come to life as the League of Nations began its work,
man will turn with relief to the ‘lofty’ thought of Bergson and and Bergson became the President of the League’s International
James.” (Bergson and American Culture, Tom Quirk, 1990). Committee for Intellectual Cooperation. (Fittingly, the Com-
mittee provided the framework for a cooperative work between
War & Rights Albert Einstein and Sigmund Freud entitled Why War?. Sadly,
The Two Sources of Morality and Religion was published in 1932 after these two intellectual giants made little headway on their topic.
twenty-five years of effort. In it, among other things, Bergson Einstein hoped Freud had the solution, but Freud showed a flair
sought to understand the problem of war. Bergson was born in for the obvious by saying that throughout history conflicts have
1859, the year that Darwin’s On the Origin of Species was published. been settled with violence.)
It seemed clear to Bergson that human societies had biological The League of Nations eventually failed, in the face of rising
roots, and that the confluence of our technological development fascist aggression in the 1930s. Its successor, the UN, has at its

10 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


War & Peace
BERGSON PORTRAIT © WOODROW COWHER 2018
PLEASE VISIT WOODRAWSPICTURES.COM

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 11


War & Peace
foundation The Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Accord- stimulated into operating.
ing to Clinton Curle in Humanité (2007), the main author of the Bergson also describes here the constant interplay between
Declaration, John Humphrey, had Bergson’s The Two Sources of closed and open societies. A closed society is instinct-driven and
Morality and Religion as his inspiration. The Declaration is the values security for its elite, and sometimes, to get what it wants
archetypal human rights document, and by declaring that “recog- it goes to war, since it can seize resources to protect its selected
nition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable members. Thus closed societies are prone to starting wars: Berg-
rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of son describes a closed society as one that endlessly circles the
freedom, justice and peace in the world” it seeks to protect every- fixed point of war. An open society, on the other hand, is
one with its list of rights. unbounded: it does not limit who its members are or what they
Although Bergson was the strongest supporter of human must do. It seeks liberty, equality, and fraternity, not the pro-
rights, his vision was only partially implemented in the draft- tection of privilege.
ing of the Declaration. One problem is that human rights are Unfortunately, hoping that war can be eliminated by declar-
often crushed just when they are needed most; when there’s a ing the individual to be protected by their human rights misses
strong feeling of ‘us against them’ and cruelty against a minor- the difference in kind between open and closed societies. Adding
ity becomes justified by the fears of the majority. This happens human rights into a closed society initially seems to work, but
frequently in wartime. the two institutions won’t mix, like stirring water into oil. A
closed society bases its security on defined roles and norms of
The Human Instinct For War behavior, so when a closed society views itself as under threat
Bergson argues that the ‘war-instinct’ is intrinsic to human, animal, from ‘outside agitators’, it suspends human rights.
and insect societies. Many animals also seem hardwired with what Closed societies aren’t a mistake as such; they form from the
we would call cruelty. For example, if you supply wild birds with survival instinct, so it is pointless to belittle their supporters as
plentiful food in a bird feeder, they’ll frequently attempt to knock ignorant. But they should know that left alone, closed societies
other birds off a perch instead of simply flying to a perch that’s gravitate toward war. The best one can hope for to prevent war is
open. Why? So that a rival gets less. that the vision of a mystic with a message of love and peace will
In ancient human times a small group with access to a stream eventually permeate the closed society and move it toward being
or field and the right tools would flourish, and another group an open society, in a jolt. This jolt is the next step in Bergson’s
cut off from resources would perish. Bergson notes from this theory of the development of society.
that “the origin of war is ownership, individual or collective,
and since humanity is predestined to ownership by its structure, Of Ants & Men
war is natural. So strong indeed, is the war-instinct that it is the Philosophical theories are especially interesting when they pro-
first to appear when we scratch below the surface of civilization vide an ‘Eureka’ insight into unalike problems. Prior to writing
in search of nature. We all know how little boys love fighting. Creative Evolution, on his vacations throughout France Bergson
They get their heads punched. But they have the satisfaction of studied ants and bees. This must have seemed as an odd activ-
having punched the other fellow’s head.” (Two Sources, p.284.) ity for a philosopher. But I know why he studied insects: to try
He then observes that logic and rationality follow behind the to understand communal behaviour.
pre-thought of instincts like a caboose follows the freight train, While hiking in the jungle of Ecuador, I saw leaf-cutter ants
providing reasons for war after the war-instinct has already been cross our hiking track. They made smooth trails transporting
snipped sections of leaves relatively long distances. It looked a
bit like an aerial view of a freeway, with red carrier ants haul-
CARTOON © CHRIS GILL 2018, PLEASE VISIT WWW.CGILLCARTOONS.COM FOR MORE.

ing green leaf pieces at a steady rate, while unencumbered sol-


dier ants overtook them. The ants bypassed plants as they made
their way to a distant twenty-five foot clearing of light in the
deep green gloom of the jungle. The light was due to the seem-
ing devastation of a tree where the ants had crawled up the
branches and systematically cut the leaves from all but one of
them, where, curiously, a single intact leaf remained. “They
always leave enough for the plant to recover,” our guide noted.
I was skeptical, but found his observation mirrored in Bert Höll-
dobler and Edward Wilson’s extraordinary book The Ants
(1990): “Another broad ecological interest is whether or not
leaf-cutter ants husband their resources by directing their attacks
so not to kill off too many plants close to home. Foragers have
often been observed to shift their attentions from one tree to
another without denuding any of them” (p.623). How is this
possible? Do ants heed some current, jolt, or bolt of transmis-
sion that says “Enough! change!”?
In The Two Sources of Morality and Religion, Bergson suggests
that exactly that sort of thing happens, but on a larger scale:

12 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


War & Peace

fundamental changes in a human society’s behaviour come from using simultaneously or successively two very different methods. The
the communication of an idea in a ‘jolt’. The jolt moves a closed first would consist presumably in intensifying the intellectual work
society in the direction envisioned by mystics such as Christ, to such an extent, in carrying intelligence so far beyond what nature
Moses, or Buddha, and is translated to the masses via educa- intended, that the simple tool would give place to a vast system of
tion. As Bergson says in Two Sources: machinery such as might set human activity at liberty, this libera-
tion being, moreover, stabilized by a political and social organiza-
“We represent religion, then, as the crystallization, brought about by tion which could ensure the application of the mechanism to its true
the scientific process of cooling, of what mysticism had poured, white object. A dangerous method, for mechanization, as it developed,
hot, into the soul of man…” (p.238) “...since [mystics] cannot com- might turn against mysticism: nay more, it is by an apparent reac-
municate to the world at large the deepest elements of their spiritual tion against the latter mechanization that it would reach its highest
condition, they transpose it superficially; they seek a translation of the pitch of development... This [development] consisted, not in con-
dynamic into the static which society may accept and stabilize by edu- templating a general and immediate spreading of the mystic impe-
cation” (p.274). tus, which was obviously impossible, but in imparting it, already
weakened though it was, to a tiny handful of privileged souls which
The ‘frenzy’ of the mystic causes them to communicate a together would form a spiritual society; societies of this kind might
vision of a radically different direction to society, not based on multiply; each one, through such of its members as might be excep-
selfish reasoning. Under its influence the closed society stops tionally gifted, would give birth to one or several others; thus the
endlessly circling the fixed point of war; instead, it changes impetus would be preserved and continued until such a time as pro-
direction to become an open society, and save itself. However, found change on the material conditions impost on humanity by
the leap of the idea from the mystical visionary to everyone in nature would permit, in spiritual matters of a radical transformation.
society is sadly not inevitable. The struggle against injustice is Such is the method used by the great mystics.” (p.235.)
slow and uncertain; and even the idea of waiting for mystical
visions for social solutions is utopic at best and painfully naïve In the three large revolutions I’ve seen unfold in my lifetime,
after the horrors of two World Wars and the Holocaust. namely Nelson Mandela’s jolt to South Africa to change the
Bergson addressed this problem of the mystical vitalising of regime of apartheid, Lech Walesa and Solidarity’s role in the
society thus: collapse of the Soviet Union, and Ayatollah Khomeini’s over-
throw of the Shah of Iran’s regime, the dynamic of ‘mystical
“If mysticism is to transform humanity, it can do so only by passing frenzy’ acting upon a society has changed the behavior of its
on, from one man to another, slowly, a part of itself. The mystics are individuals in a deep way.
well aware of this. The great obstacle in their way is the same which
prevented the creation of a divine humanity. Man has to earn his Conclusion
bread with the sweat of his brow; in other words, humanity is an ani- Despite the noblest and most rational thought of humanity, war
mal species, and, as such, subject to the law which governs the ani- is an intrinsic part of life. It is not a quirk, a rare exception, or
mal world and condemns the living to batten upon the living. Since a moral lapse of the ignorant manipulated masses. Bergson’s
he has to contend for his food both with nature and with his own radical critique is worthy of study if we wish to stop endlessly
kind, he necessarily extends his energies procuring it; his intelligence circling the fixed point of war.
is designed for the very object of supplying him with weapons and © CARL STRASEN 2018
tools, with a view to the struggle and that toil. How then, in these Carl Strasen remains a dedicated amateur student of philosophy
conditions, could humanity turn heavenwards an attention which is after surviving twenty-five years in the salt mines of Silicon Valley,
essentially concentrated on earth? If possible at all, it can only be by and analytic philosophy at UC Berkeley.

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 13


War & Peace
Non-Violent Voices
Oidinposha Imamkhodjaeva assesses arguments against violence among
ancient Asian philosophies.
he quest for peace is one of the most important

T endeavours of all time and one of the oldest. Several


of the major Asian philosophical traditions have, from
ancient times, tried to find the means to justify and
achieve peace and avoid violence and war. Here I will focus on
Jainism, Daoism, and the teachings of Mo Tzu and Mencius. I
will briefly sketch the similarities and dissimilarities of their views
on pacifism, just war, and revolution. Jainists, Daoists, Mo Tzu
and Mencius were all lovers of peace in unique ways.

Jainist Non-Violence
Jainism as a philosophical movement appeared in India before
or around the same time as Daoism, Mohism (Mo Tzu) and
Mencius in China: about the sixth century BC. Jainism and
other Indian philosophical schools were markedly different in
their historic background from the Chinese schools: India was
not plunged into civil war as China was for several hundred
years. But India was affected by movements which enforced the
supremacy of the priestly Brahman class and its philosophy with
an iron fist. Jainism sprung up as a reaction against this ruling
Brahman philosophy. It emerged as a full-fledged philosophy Mahavira meditating
of non-violence during the life of Mahavira (born 599 B.C.). It
was often considered to be an offshoot of Buddhism, but it stood two inter-related methods, Nayavada, or the method of seven
out from the start as a philosophy promoting the concept of standpoints, and Syadvada, or the method of sevenfold predica-
ahimsa, meaning non-harm or non-injury, simultaneously advo- tion. The former involves showing that any statement can be of
cating tolerance, on the grounds that no one holds the absolute only limited, not absolute, validity, because all statements are con-
truth and everyone has his or her own standpoint. Ahimsa had textualized. The second method involves the recognition that
an enormous influence on other Indian schools. there are a limited number of possible types of statements that
This principle of non-violence or non-injury is based on the one can make about an object, including positive attribution, neg-
Jainist philosophical and sociopolitical worldview. Jainists divide ative attribution, and inexpressibility. By combining these two
the universe into two types of things, the living and the non- methods, the Jains developed a logic according to which any state-
living. Jainists state that each living being, not only humans, but ment at best represents a single perspective (Ekanta). In contrast,
the smallest insects, plants, reptiles and birds, has a soul, called in a more global approach, the Jains argue for the adoption of all
jiva. Non-living things, which lack a soul, are called ajiva. Because possible points of view from multiple perspectives (Anekinta).
each living being has a soul/jiva, you are forbidden to harm any Whenever Jains talk about ethics, they talk about duty, and
living being, even the smallest insect. Jainism prescribes that we they say that the highest and best duty of a human being is to
should not harm any life, and in particular we should not kill practice non-violence, recognizing that the essential feature of
any life, because all life has equal rights on this earth. You must all life is soul. Ahimsa is built into the core of Jainist philoso-
understand that if you kill any living thing, you kill a soul. phy, ethics and practice. Even though it was founded more than
The core of Jainist metaphysics is known as Anekânatavâda, or two thousand years ago, its adherents are still active in the polit-
the manyness of reality. Reality possesses innumerable qualities, ical discourse of India and worldwide. Their voice of love and
and any object possesses an infinite number of characteristics. care for the environment is influential even today.
Ordinary people cannot comprehend all the qualities of a thing.
Human knowledge is limited and relative regarding the innumer- Daoist Non-Violence
able characteristics of an object. Thus Jain metaphysics is a rela- Now let’s turn our attention to Daoism. Like Jainism, nothing
tivism, in the sense that all truths are relative to their believers. is known for certain about the founder of Daoism, Laozi (Lao
Any standpoint or statement can be only partially true, and no Tzu) – there are only legends. Daoist philosophical and politi-
statement or standpoint can claim to be absolute. This worldview cal teachings were written down and compiled by later follow-
is considered to be an extension of the Jain ethical imperative of ers. We know that Daoist monks translated Buddhist works, and
ahimsa into the field of philosophy, as a form of tolerance. that Buddhism, like other Indian philosophies, was influenced
This argument goes as follows. At the center of Jain logic lie by ahimsa. Fung Yu-lan, a famous Chinese philosopher, views

14 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


War & Peace
the preservation of life and the avoidance of injury as the start- as war horses and farmers drafted into the army. Most commen-
ing point of Daoism. But Daoist ideas of non-violence are dif- tators tend to view this statement as a utilitarian or economic
ferent. Their reasons for opposing war and favoring non-vio- argument against war. But Chapter 30 speaks not only of war in
lence were the result of the historical contexts. Daoism is com- terms of the disruption of natural patterns of life, it also makes
parable to Jainism only on a superficial level. the onto-cosmological argument when it claims that nothing is
The Dao De Jing is an ancient Chinese classic traditionally more unnatural than war due to its capacity to disrupt the ordi-
taken as a representative Daoist text. It expresses a distinctive nary courses of nature, such as farming, leading to the destruc-
philosophy from China’s Warring States Period (403–221 BC), tion of harmony and social order. Chapter 46 puts it thus:
and is one of the most influential works in the intellectual tradi-
tion of China, with hundreds of commentaries written over two “When the dao (natural way) prevails in the world,
millennia. The Dao De Jing has three basic anti-war arguments: Horses are used in the farm;
When the dao (natural way) does not prevail in the world,
1) The onto-cosmological argument: War creates a disruption of War horses are bred just outside the city walls.”
the natural pattern of things in the world.
2) The moral argument: Preserving life is morally right and killing Daoism is against all war. While the Dao De Jing does not elab-
is morally wrong. orate on warfare specifically, its opposition is implied by its world-
3) The political argument: It is wrong to employ war as a means view. Daoism advocates non-activity or non-intervention (wu-
to political gain since warfare will inflict great sorrow upon the wei). For Laozi, whoever acts, harms; and whoever grabs, lets slip.
state and its people, as well as on the ruler. Therefore the sage does not act, and so does not harm; the sage
does not grab, and so does not let slip. Laozi compares ruling a
All three arguments are presented from both duty-based and big country to cooking a small fish, and cautions against too many
utilitarian perspectives. The first two arguments are made clear changes. For him, if the rich and powerful are arrogant, they are
in Chapter 30, where it says, “After a great battle, there is an doomed. Daoism is skeptical of politics. When King Wei of Chu
ominous year of famine.” The phrase ‘an ominous year’ (xiong- asked Zhuangzi (Chuang Tzu), a famous Daoist scholar, to serve
nian) refers to a year of calamity after farm horses have been used as Prime Minister, he turned down the offer.

Laozi articulating Mohist Non-Violence


Although Mohism is not as well known as other ancient Chi-
nese schools, the Mohist contribution to the Chinese view of
warfare cannot be underestimated, since among all major
schools the most famous indictment of war comes from Mo Tzu
(480-390 BC). He condemns war both on moral grounds and
on utilitarian principles. For him, war does not pay, even for
the victor. There is nothing useful about victory, as the loss out-
weighs the spoils. Mo Tzu’s comment on the intention of the
state of Chu to attack the state of Song deserves mention here:
since Chu possessed abundant land but not a large population,
it was unwise to sacrifice what was insufficient for what was
superfluous. Moreover, attacking a state that has done no wrong
is not benevolent. It is illogical that while killing one person is
forbidden and seen as a dreadful crime, slaughtering whole
armies is accepted. Mo Tzu also criticizes the double standard
in judging domestic and international politics.
For Mo Tzu, partiality in human relations causes all the great
harms in the world, so he suggests that partiality be replaced
by universality. He proposes what he called ‘universal love’ (jian-
ai), arguing, “if men were to regard the states of others as they
regard their own, then who would raise up his state to attack
the state of another?” Only universal love will make the world
peaceful and orderly.
Although the Chinese tradition generally stresses the impor-
tance of avoiding war, the notion of ‘just war’ or ‘righteous war’
(yizhan) for the sake of maintaining order in the world, or the
idea of legitimate and sanctioned acts of violence (for example,
punishing the enemies of public order) is by no means absent.
In the Mozi (The Book of Master Mo), Mo Tzu allows for non-
offensive war in the chapter ‘Against Aggression’. There he
articulates the notion of righteous war and contends that the

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 15


War & Peace
Although Mencius argued that the validity of rulership depends
Mencius on the people’s acceptance, he does not think that the task of royal
considering
replacement should be placed in the peoples’ hands. The people
will have neither the political expertise nor the military compe-
tence to succeed in this task, and a revolution initiated by the
people will probably bring the whole nation into complete chaos.
Therefore the task should fall on the shoulders of the ministers
who originally assisted the ruler. As the famous scholar of Chi-
nese thought Angus Graham states, “Mencius is not a defender
of popular revolution. Ideally, he thinks the tyrant should be
removed by his own ministers, and, among ministers, by those of
the old fashioned kind.” (Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argu-
ment in Ancient China, 1989). These ministers themselves have to
have some qualifications: they must have the peoples’ well-being
in mind and be wise enough to make right judgments. There is
only a slight margin between legitimate overthrow and illegiti-
mate usurpation, and the margin is set by the ministers’ intent.
Confucianism has often been charged with supporting feu-
wars initiated by three sages, Yu, Tang, and Wu, should not be dalism. But we can see that Mencius would never support a form
called ‘attacks’ but ‘punishments’. He makes a distinction of feudalism that does not include a humane king, prudent min-
between ‘aggressive attack’ and ‘offensive punishment’: the isters, and contented people.
former deploys forces for the purpose of profit, whereas the
latter deploys forces for the purpose of preserving order. Conclusion
We have considered four ancient Asian philosophies that advo-
Confucian Non-Violence cated peace. The Jainists were absolutely opposed to violence
Mencius (371-289 BC), the greatest Confucian thinker after or harming even the smallest living thing. The Daoists regarded
Confucius himself, also denounces offensive wars. For him wars war as a destruction of the natural order and advocated passiv-
involve too many casualties. So although the central authority ity. The Mohists thought war was bad but sometimes necessary
may wage punitive war against a local ruler, rival states should to preserve order. The followers of Mencius also thought war
not attack one another. He regards all the wars in the Spring was bad but sometimes necessary to defend justice. All these
and Autumn period of Chinese history (722-481 BC) as unjust. ideas are relevant today.
Death is an inadequate punishment for those who launch a war. © OIDINPOSHA IMAMKHODJAEVA 2018
Those who are experts in waging wars deserve the most severe Oidinposha Imamkhodjaeva is an assistant teaching professor in
penalty. Boasting of military expertise is a grave crime. Philosophy at Penn State University. She has two PhDs!
Mencius argues that a benevolent king has no rivals in the
FURTHER READING
world because he can win the support of the people, even
oppressed people in another country. Indeed, sometimes wars Hsiu-Chen Chang, ‘On the Historicity of the Tao Te Ching’, Compar-
have to be embarked on because they are just. For Mencius, the ative Literature Studies, vol. 35, no. 2, 1998.
criterion of whether a war is just lies in how the war would ben- Christopher Chapple, ‘Sources for the Study of Jaina Philosophy: A
efit the people of the enemy country. If the people of that coun- Bibliographic Essay’, Philosophy East and West, vol. 50, no. 3, 2000.
try have been starving, freezing, exploited and abused by their Ellen M. Chen, The Tao Te Ching: A New Translation with Commen-
king then they will welcome liberation. They will not put up any tary, Paragon House, 1989.
resistance; instead, they will bring food and drink to reward the Carine Defoort, ‘The Growing Scope of ‘Jian’ 兼: Differences
incoming troops. So whoever wins the hearts of the people will Between Chapters 14, 15 and 16 of the ‘Mozi’.’ Oriens Extremus,
win the war. As Mencius says, “A humane king has no match.” vol. 45, 2005.
When King Hsiang of Liang asked how to achieve world Angus C. Graham. Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argument in
peace, Mencius pointed to unity as a solution. When asked who Ancient China, Open Court,1989.
can unify the world, Mencius answered that the one who does William G. Kirkwood, ‘Revealing the Mind of the Sage: The Narrative
not delight in killing can unite it. Rhetoric of the ‘Chuang Tzu’.’ Rhetoric Society Quarterly, vol. 22,
Another novel idea introduced by Mencius into Chinese no. 3, 1992.
political thinking is the idea of revolution. If the ruler is not D.C. Lau (trans.), Mencius, Penguin, 1970.
humane – if he abuses the people instead of taking care of their Geoffrey MacCormack, ‘The Legal Philosophy of Mo Tzu’, ARSP:
welfare – then he can be legitimately removed. This view may Archiv Für Rechts- Und Sozialphilosophie / Archives for Philosophy
appear contrary to what Confucius himself teaches, whereby of Law and Social Philosophy, vol. 79, no. 3, 1993.
the ruler is revered and the subjects always remain subjects. Stephen Mitchell, Tao Te Ching: A New English Version, with Fore-
However, Mencius defended his view by asserting that when word and Notes, Harper Collins, 2000.
the ruler is a ‘lone man’ loathed by everyone, removing the lone Jayandra Soni, ‘Basic Jaina Epistemology’, Philosophy East and
man from the throne is not usurpation. West, vol. 50, no. 3, 2000.

16 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


Interview
Surfing Skye Cleary
interviews

With Sartre Aaron James


about his new book.
Jean-Paul skill, or in attuned relations with others, but in surfing the goal is more modest
PORTRAIT PHOTO © SKYE SCHMIDT

Sartre’s not nor- done just for their own sakes. Sartre and comes by a much easier route. You
mally associated with treats this sort of individual meaning as don’t need to abandon desire, or lose your
surfing: he much preferred being in a Parisian somehow created from nothing, ex concept of self, or meditate, or even be
café than in nature; and as you say, surfing is nihilo, from one’s free choice – for very disciplined, beyond surfing regularly.
more often associated with waves than wisdom. example, to be a surfer. But that’s a mis- You grab your board and just paddle out,
My first instinct was that Albert Camus would take about the value of surfing from the motivated by your firm loving attachment
have been more connected with a Mediter- surfer’s perspective. Surfing is not to waves and surfing them.
ranean lifestyle of sun, sand, and surf. So why worthy because it’s chosen, as Sartre
Surfing with Sartre? would say; rather, it’s eminently worthy A surfer’s lifestyle, you suggest, can be an
Sartre has long passages in Being and of being chosen, and chosen for one’s antidote to consumerism and global warm-
Nothingness (1943) about why skiing exem- limited time in life, for intrinsic reasons; ing. How?
plifies freedom. At one point he pauses to in other words, just because of what it is. Since work as we now practice it cre-
note that waterskiing, a kind of ‘sliding’ ates greenhouse gasses, one way to bene-
upon water, is even better; he calls it ‘the Can ‘adaptive attunement’, the essence of fit society is to work less and do some-
ideal limit of aquatic sports’. So he’d be surfing, be applied to non-surfing realms? thing less resource-consuming instead,
the first to welcome a phenomenology of Surfing is a relationship between a such as going surfing. So, surfers aren’t
surfing. However, I think that leads you person and a wave, but it has a social ana- lazy good-for-nothing freeloaders who
away from his view of freedom toward a logue. In walking a busy city street, for should really get a job; they’re the new
more embodied, embedded, achievement- instance, you’re constantly adapting your model of civic virtue! The workaholic is
oriented perspective, such as Maurice walking, slowing, or shifting sideways – the new problem-child. I mean, an
Merleau-Ponty articulated. The surfer’s being attuned to what other pedestrians important way we might mitigate cli-
view contrasts with Sartre’s dour existen- are doing. Many skillful activities involve mate change, along with more urgent
tialism on a whole range of questions, so a form of ‘adaptive attunement’, and if measures, is to cut back the work week
Sartre is a natural interlocutor. But I do they aren’t surfing properly speaking, or and set up a basic income so that people
engage with Camus as well. not even ‘crowd surfing’, the general way can work part-time. I think a lot of
they are similar to surfing highlights a people share the surfer’s preference for
You ultimately disagree with Sartre though. key part of their meaning and value. time over money. If it can be made feasi-
So can you say something about how a surfer’s ble for them, many people would be
experience undermines Sartrean existentialism? The concept of ‘flow’ is a strong theme willing to work less and hit the lake or
A key difference is that the surfer’s throughout the book. Why is it important? the beach – or do more gardening, or art
exercise of skill – in knowing how to be When psychology and self-help books projects, or get to know their spouse, or
‘adaptively attuned’ to constant change – talk about flow, they treat it as a state of spend time with the kids, whatever. In
is valuable for its own sake as a sublime ‘optimal experience’ that can be con- economic parlance, more leisure for
and beautiful way of spending one’s lim- trolled from within by mental self-disci- everyone is potentially an efficient adapta-
ited time in life. So the act of surfing pline. That’s basically a neo-Stoic per- tion which leaves no one worse off and
can’t itself be absurd, as some existential- spective, which I believe derives from asks no sacrifice of anyone. This is the
ists accused the universe of being; at least Viktor Frankl’s account of the Stoic-like sort of climate adaption we might really
not in the sense of a conspicuous gap methods that helped people survive Nazi get used to, and so maybe actually imple-
between pretence and reality, which is concentration camps. But surfers surely ment, at least eventually. And in that
Thomas Nagel’s definition of absurdity. know something about flow, since for case, we’re definitely morally obliged to
While surfing on a crowded day can be them going with a flow is a way of life, do it, as we’d reduce the risks of pro-
absurd given our expectations of what often quite literally. And they’ll tell you found injury to future people. So who
surfing should be, the basic act of riding that flow ain’t all in the head. Flow is the could complain? I should go surfing and
a wave for its own sake has no larger pre- real, dynamic relationship – the coales- do my bit for society? Twist my arm!
tences, so it doesn’t purport to have any cence between skill and circumstance –
larger meaning that would be undercut if that emerges between surfer and wave. • Skye C. Cleary is a visiting lecturer at
it turned out that life was meaningless in It’s a kind of self-transcendence that Sto- Columbia University, Barnard College, and
some general or cosmic way. icism, existentialism or Buddhism don’t the City College of New York, and author of
Even if the universe as a whole were capture very well. Surfing also helps us Existentialism and Romantic Love (2015).
meaningless – as Sartre, the disappointed see what’s so valuable about flow, what all
romantic, would maintain – there’s still the fun and experiential enjoyment is ulti- • Surfing with Sartre: An Aquatic Inquiry into a
plenty of genuine meaning in life for a mately about. Maybe ‘adaptive attune- Life of Meaning, by Aaron James, was published
person: in surfing, in other exercises of ment’ is close to what Buddhism is after, by Doubleday in 2017.

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 17


The Puzzle Of
Patriotism
Phil Badger tries to make sense of a tangle of pride, identity and metaphysics.
“If you believe yourself a citizen of the world then you are a citizen his rooms and juggling the competing claims of principle (he
of nowhere.” was apparently no supporter of slavery) and loyalty to hearth
UK Prime Minister Theresa May, October 2016 and home. In the end, Lee chose the demands of filial loyalty
over those of abstract principle. He refused Lincoln’s offer, and
y national identity seems to me to be both con- headed south to defend a system he despised rather than take

M tingent and coincidental. Being born British,


while quite lucky in terms of my life chances and
political rights, wasn’t something of my own
doing. Therefore it is no more something for me to be proud
of than my being born in the middle of the twentieth century.
up arms against his fellow Southerners.
What are we to make of this story? Sandel’s view – one he
knows will outrage the liberal-minded – is sympathetic to Lee’s
position. He points out that for most people the feeling of con-
nection to our homes, our communities, and their histories, is
I was once told a (possibly apocryphal) story about a former what gives us our sense of who we are. This is the communitar-
Prime Minister of Belgium who, when asked if he was proud ian view. Conversely, for liberals, ideally, the individual decides
of his nationality, replied that the question was ridiculous and upon his or her principles from a position of detachment.
that he might as well be asked if he was “proud of being a man.” Lee’s story brings into sharp relief the gulf of incomprehen-
Some people will find this idea simply outrageous. For them sion that exists between the liberal and the communitarian on
there is nothing accidental about nationality. Such people hold the issue of identity. For the liberal, the notion of what we might
what I might call a ‘metaphysical theory’ of their identity: con- call ‘inherited responsibility’ is simply an absurdity: I am no more
sciously or otherwise, they feel that a kind of spiritual thread responsible for the crimes of the British Empire than a Russian
connects together those who share a particular nationality so person of my age is for those of Stalin. But for the communitar-
that they also share a set of mutual obligations and rights. ian the idea seems plausible, even obvious. Of course, the liberal
Not me. When I was about fourteen, the BBC put on one of is willing to accept that we might owe something to those who
its series aimed at educating and informing the population. In are still suffering the impact of past actions by our co-nationals
this particular case, the actors pretended to be philosophers such – for example, political chaos in the Middle East – but only to
as Plato and Socrates. I suspect that the whole thing was a ghastly the extent that we are still benefiting from them. If my grandfa-
hamfest; but for me the important thing was that a toga-clad ther robbed your grandfather, that’s nothing to do with me, so
Socrates asked his pupil “How should men live?” Putting aside long as his ill-gotten gains didn’t put me through university.
the inherent misogyny of the question, this was a crucial moment You might be feeling a little uneasy at this point. Specifically,
in my young life. First, the revelation that people actually asked you might be feeling an intuitive sympathy for the communitar-
questions like that was mind-blowing; second, the seed was ian view. You might even be thinking that there’s something psy-
planted that there could be an answer to it which pertained to chologically odd about the kind of person who can’t grasp it.
humans in general and not just to those in my own community. If so, you are in good company. In his book The Righteous
At that moment, with deference to Socrates, I became a citizen Mind (2012), the evolutionary psychologist Jonathan Haidt sees
not of a small town in northern England, but of the world. such liberals as lacking something that most people have as a
In this article I’m going to do my best to get to grips with matter of instinct. He does not precisely say we’re defective
the idea of patriotism in the most generous-spirited manner I (although he comes close), but he certainly thinks we’re evolu-
can muster. I will refrain (after now) from references to Dr tionary anomalies, born without the full range of moral intu-
Johnson, who opined patriotism to be “the last refuge of the itions possessed by others.
scoundrel” and instead examine a trio of philosophical models One of the things wrong with Haidt’s view is that he fails to
of patriotism. see that the detached liberal position is not based on an odd moral
intuition but on a kind of achievement which requires work.
Model 1: Communitarian Patriotism Many of us as children and since have indulged in national pride
In his wonderful book Justice (2010), the ethicist Michael Sandel but liberals have learnt to treat these psychological tendencies
tells a well-authenticated story about Confederate General with a certain caution and allow them only limited weight in
Robert E. Lee. Lee, it seems, began the American Civil War as wider, more universal schemes of values.
an instructor at West Point military academy, and, respected
military genius as he was, was approached by Abraham Lincoln Model 2: Contractual Patriotism
with an offer to take command of the Union armies in the Contractual theories of patriotism acknowledge the ‘accidental’
coming conflagration. The story goes that Lee asked Lincoln nature of identity yet seek to maintain that we nevertheless have
for a night to think the offer over. Lee spent that night pacing special obligations to those who share membership of our par-

18 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 19
‘PATRIOTISM’ © STEVE LILLIE 2018 PLEASE VISIT WWW.STEVELILLIE.BIZ
ticular communities. There is no notion here of there being an
actual contract. Only if you become a naturalised citizen is there
ever some kind of official ‘signing up’. Instead what is usually
invoked is a sort of implicit contract based on mutual benefit
and shared hazards.
A common way of understanding how such implicit commu- by Melissa Felder
nal loyalties develop is through considering ‘The Prisoner’s
Dilemma’. In the classic version of this thought experiment you
imagine yourself as a criminal who has been arrested with your
partner in crime. The police separate you for purposes of inter-
rogation, and you’re told that if you confess you’ll receive a
lesser punishment than if you don’t say anything and yet are
found guilty because your colleague confesses. However, the
only way you can be found guilty is if either of you confesses.

PLEASE VISIT SIMONANDFINN.COM


If neither confess, you both go scot free. Of course, the impli-
cation is that the same offer is being made to your friend. Your
decision becomes a matter of strategy. You could assume the
loyalty of your accomplice and stay silent – a position that car-
ries with it the obvious risk that he won’t stay silent; or you can
sing like the proverbial canary. What would you do?
One limitation of the standard prisoner’s dilemma is that it is

SIMON + FINN CARTOON © MELISSA FELDER 2018


a one-off situation in which neither person has any incentive to
do anything but look after their immediate interests. Other ver-
sions of the game have proposed a repeated (‘iterated’) form in
which you get to play the game over and over again, so that over
time you can punish disloyalty by giving back in kind. The most
successful strategy for establishing stable co-operation then turns
out to be initial mutual cooperation, followed by tit-for-tat.
All of this has much to do with how implicit contracts are
built up. In 1968 the economist Garrett Hardin published a
hugely influential paper called ‘The Tragedy of the Commons’,
in which he predicted ecological disaster. Commons resources
are resources not owned by any particular individual, such as fish
stocks in the ocean or communal grazing land. Hardin predicted
that these resources would be decimated because no-one would
have any incentive not to exploit them – the logic being that if I
don’t grab what I can others will and the resource will soon be
gone anyway. What Hardin got wrong, at least in part, was that
the actions of the users of commons are not one-off events. If
we both live in the same village and you let your herd of sheep
overgraze the common land, then I, the local blacksmith who
have only a couple of goats which I keep for milking, will be seri-
ously unhappy with you. This won’t much matter if you never
need a blacksmith or your shoes mending (my brother is the
local shoemaker), but you will. Our lives are a kind of iterated
prisoner’s dilemma in which, in due course, my daughter has a
pretty good chance of marrying your son. You might think twice
before ripping off one of your grandchild’s other grandparents. pragmatist position is that at the scale of the nation state things
This suggests that localism is a good strategy for producing are just too big and complex for this to work. We simply can’t
high levels of co-operation. Of course, we won’t be entirely self- build up relationships of trust based on mutual dependency with
sufficient, so we’ll establish trading relationships with outsiders people whom we will either never meet again, or increasingly,
who will win our trust or not based on a larger-scale version of never meet at all. Looking around my study there are few, if
the same iterated interactions. No doubt the definition of who any, items that I can see that are locally sourced. My bookcases
‘we’ are will be modified over time, and ultimately ‘our’ com- came from a very nice shop my partner found, but I have no
munity might become the nation state. idea where they were made, and my laptop certainly isn’t a local
The problem with this view concerns what we might call the craft product. By the same token, the reason that there are still
limits of pragmatism. In the context of our local community I fish in the North Sea is more to do with soulless regulation
might treat you fairly because I need to do so. The flaw in the achieved at the supranational level than through the iterated

20 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


contact of fishermen.
The implicit contract based on pragmatism and acquired trust Immanuel Kant,
that binds us to our fellow citizens locally is not one that ever has Prussian
the chance to evolve to the national level. From the outset nations
were governed by abstract laws and values. In the terminology
of the sociologist Max Weber (1864-1920), the local involves
Gemeinschaft (community) and the national involves Gesellschaft
(impersonal) models of social cohesion. And it gets more imper-
sonal over time as the scope and complexity of government
increases and co-operation becomes more global. Edmund
Burke’s ‘small battalions’, what we usually call ‘civil society’, have
necessarily given way to ‘big government’. For many people this
is a matter of profound regret. It’s even a problem for those pro-
ponents of the activist state who want citizens to be more than
consumers/tax payers with strong ties only to their own families.
Personally, I love paying tax when I can see it being used to
improve the community and make my and others’ lives longer,
healthier, and more secure; but this seems to some a rather pallid
basis for social cohesion, and one prone to fall apart at the least
suspicion (justified or otherwise) of freeloading, by individuals
or groups. prevented by regulation from doing so.
However, it is arguable that Kant’s approach constitutes the
Model 3: Reasonable Assent & Patriotism death knell of patriotism. On Kant’s model, ‘we’ are not those
The last model I’ll consider is associated primarily with who share geography or culture in common, but rather, those
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). Kant argued that we owe the state who reach similar conclusions about the values that define a just
our loyalty to the extent that it embodies laws that any rational society. The list of values might not entirely coincide for all lib-
being would consider just. The exact qualities and laws that such erals, but it would be surprising if they didn’t include notions
a state might have and make are a matter for serious debate; but of respect for individual autonomy, the rule of law, and democ-
the point is that if they can be agreed upon, their reasonable- racy. Regardless of minor disagreements, liberals the world
ness confers legitimacy and, therefore, obligation. over have more in common with each other than with the com-
This model of patriotism has several major advantages over munitarian conservative who lives next door to them and shares
the others. Firstly, it gets around a famous objection to the idea superficially similar cultural traditions.
of implicit contractual consent made by David Hume. Hume For liberals the power of tradition is explainable in anthro-
likens the idea of our belonging to a society to which we auto- pological rather than moral terms. My own country is mired in
matically owe obligations to the condition of a press-ganged traditional strangeness (we have, for example, a hereditary head
sailor who is provided with food, water and a bunk on a ship if of state, a partly unelected legislature, and an established church);
he works, but who was never asked if he wanted to go along for and while US citizens might see their country as a comparative
the ride. By contrast, Kant’s position is that we owe an obliga- paragon of Enlightenment rationality, they are manifestly no
tion to our society only to the extent that the society keeps a less prone to nostalgia. When Kantian rationalists do get misty-
bargain that anyone would reasonably accept, given the option. eyed – the sight of a Spitfire in flight gets me every time – it is
If the community falls short of its laws being reasonable, then not patriotism that inspires the emotion but an altogether more
our obligation to it to that extent vanishes. abstract commitment: the aeroplane is emblematic of the tri-
Of course, communitarians aren’t going to be impressed by umph of the values Nazism aimed to extinguish. I’m even moved
this, since it is the felt rather than the thought aspects of obliga- by the sight of the EU flag which, despite that institution’s mul-
tion which concern them. Indeed, they may (wrongly) see Kant’s tiple failings, represents an attempt to collectively face up to
argument as reducing identity to a consumer choice, rather than, shared challenges by societies which have huge amounts in
as he would argue, the rational duty of a rational agent. common. Cosmopolitans aren’t folk swept along by the emo-
An advantage of Kant’s position is that it gives us a way of tional impact of listening to one too many John Lennon songs,
understanding our obligations which is far more applicable to but people who have reached conclusions and committed them-
our current circumstances than one based on a shared language, selves accordingly. This is, in the end, what might make us seem
culture, or frequent interactions. Regardless of the promises of strange to many people, because it takes work to be sceptical
some politicians, the developed world will have to learn to live about the kind of tribalism that is natural to most of us. Like
with the reality of mass migration, which will only become more Edmund Burke, people tend to prefer prejudice to abstraction,
pressing as climate change renders it a necessity. Bangladesh is so that feeling, often and tragically, trumps reason. We live in a
going to sink, and globalisation is not going away either. Indeed, world where we can no longer afford to let it do so.
if we want to preserve any genuine (as opposed to a tourist theme © PHILIP BADGER 2018
park) localism, countries need to work together, since multina- Phil Badger studied social sciences, including economics, psychology,
tionals have a habit of riding roughshod over diversity unless and social policy, with philosophy, and teaches in Sheffield.

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 21


Free Will Is Still Alive!
Carlo Filice questions recent attempts to question free will.
e think we are the partial authors of our own don’t exist at the level of subatomic particles does not mean that

W lives. Most of us think: “I am more than the sum


of the circumstances that affected what I am now.
I want some credit for my accomplishments, and
will accept some blame for my mistakes.” That’s the basic reason
we care about free will. Not many of us view ourselves as pro-
liquids and solids are unreal or less real than protons or elec-
trons. The similar fact that beliefs, intentions, decisions, and
indeed all conscious-level experiences do not exist at the level
of neurons and synapses also does not make conscious phenom-
ena somehow ‘less real’ or unreal. Meanings, consciousness,
grammed robots, even if the programming were complex, subtle, freedom, or the self are like liquids in this sense: the beauty of a
and included a feature that triggered it to reprogram itself. Caravaggio painting also does not exist at the subatomic level;
Is there any good reason to overturn this self-image of par- but meaning and beauty are not thereby fictions, ultimately dis-
tial autonomy? I don’t see it. The recent slew of popular anti- solved into the micro units of physics. And our choice-making
free will literature inspired by micro-neurology or by psycho- resides amongst the higher levels.
logical research is, at best, only suggestive. At worst, it is com- The nature of the interactions among these levels of reality is
pletely confused. a thorny scientific-philosophic issue, and there is a vast literature
on the topic. The complex debates in the philosophy of mind over
Over-Enthusiastic
Reductionism Caravaggio, The Taking of Christ, 1602
Here is a sample of the confused
The painting’s beauty isn’t on the molecular level
kind:

“The 20th-century nature-nurture


debate prepared us to think of ourselves
as shaped by influences beyond our con-
trol. But it left some room, at least in the
popular imagination, for the possibility
that we could overcome our circum-
stances or our genes to become the author
of our own destiny. The challenge posed
by neuroscience is more radical: It
describes the brain as a physical system
like any other, and suggests that we no
more will it to operate in a particular way
than we will our heart to beat. The con-
temporary scientific image of human
behavior is one of neurons firing, causing
other neurons to fire, causing our
thoughts and deeds, in an unbroken chain
that stretches back to our birth and
beyond. In principle, we are therefore
completely predictable. If we could understand any individual’s brain
architecture and chemistry well enough, we could, in theory, predict ‘emergentism’, ‘supervenience’, and ‘downward causation’ have
that individual’s response to any given stimulus with 100 percent accu- not led to clear resolutions. Yet to assume that macro-level phe-
racy.” nomena are impotent and can be dismissed because they are
(‘There’s No Such Thing as Free Will’, Stephen Cave, arguably reducible to micro-level explanations that don’t feature
The Atlantic, June 2016.) them ignores deep controversies, and I dare say that most philoso-
phers who focus on these questions are not in favor of any robust
Cave’s analysis illustrates a common confusion of reality form of reduction of macro- to micro-phenomena in any case.
levels. It confuses the neural or even chemical and electromag- Micro-level changes do, of course, affect the higher levels.
netic levels of brain activity with the thought/belief/will/per- Specifically, neurons do affect person-level thoughts, feelings,
sonhood level of our experience. But people do, of course, exist and behavior. But the reverse also seems incontrovertible to me:
at multiple levels, and it’s far from established that the more the simplest way for me to initiate all sorts of subtle activity in
physical levels are ‘more real’ than the more psychological levels. my throat muscles at the level of cells and molecules is to speak,
For example, the fact that features such as ‘liquid’ and ‘solid’ and mean, the words: “I love my wife!” How I make these many

22 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


precise micro-events happen, just by stating and meaning these Presuming Only Determinism or Randomness
words, we don’t really know. That these words are themselves Patience is not our best trait. If only we could rule out free will
preceded by complex streams of muscular-cellular-molecular purely theoretically! Is there not a knockout punch available
events may or may not imply anything about the freedom of the against free will?
utterance. That depends on what we end up saying about the Maybe. Philosophers old and new have gone for the knock-
nature of the interaction between the levels. out punch by appealing to a series of arguments.
Here is an old standby: the crucial agent control needed for
Prejudiced Data Interpretation free will requires more than mere indeterminism or randomness.
A second popular source of skepticism about free will comes If one were to opt for coffee instead of tea due to some uncon-
from the field of neuropsychology. In particular, it comes from trolled mental coin-flip, we surely would not be responsible for
a series of delicate experiments claiming to show that non-con- that arbitrary decision. Indeed, arbitrarily deciding between
scious neural activity is the real decider, not our conscious voli- options in such a way could hardly be called a choice. But, the
tions. Benjamin Libet was perhaps the first to conduct such argument goes, the only alternative to absolute determinism is
experiments, in the 1980s. Many others have tried to duplicate randomness. Either way, there can be no responsible free will.
or improve on his original set-up. The evidence generated by The problem with this argument is that third options have
these experiments is interesting, but its interpretation is dis- been dismissed too quickly.
puted both by psychologists and by philosophers, a good exam- Let’s consider a robot analogy to spell out this skeptical take
ple being the philosopher Alfred Mele. Libet himself did not on free will. Imagine a robot playing poker. The robot is dealt
draw an anti free-will conclusion from his experiment. hands and has programmed instructions guiding its play. Nei-
Libet’s experiment involved people choosing to press a button ther of these aspects it chose. However, one of the programmed
and noting the time on a clock when they make the decision.
Meanwhile electrodes measure a nerve impulse setting up the
hand ready for the muscle contraction associated with the button-
pressing. Libet’s experiments showed that this nerve impulse is
fired a fraction of a second before the recorded conscious deci-
sion. Some have used this data to argue that all the neurological
activity associated with a choice happens before the choice is con-
sciously made or even independent of any conscious choice, so
showing that there is no such thing as free will.
What are the main problems with such experiments and this
interpretation of them? First, there are measurement issues,
such as determining when exactly one has fully formed one’s
conscious decision. Second, even if these measurement prob-
lems could be resolved, it is not clear that the measured ner- instructions can be: “Whenever you are undecided because you
vous activity that precedes the conscious choice is part of the face two options of equal merit, go for one of those options ran-
cause of the choice. It could instead be simply one phase of the domly.” The robot will occasionally face such circumstances. It
process, like a nervous preparation anticipating the making of will then opt randomly (it comes equipped with a randomizer,
the choice. Thirdly, such findings apply to simple motor deci- triggered by such indecision). Such choices would be done ‘on
sions, like choosing to press a button. Why should these find- its own’, as someone might say; and as these choices ‘on its own’
ings carry over to sophisticated deliberative choices which add up, its overall success or failure at the poker game (its life)
involve a complex process with many sub-decisions, such as will become more and more ‘its own’.
quitting a job, or not? Indeed, what connection is there between However, this kind of robot would not have the free will we
these simple experimental situations and the millions of inter- care about:
related choices one makes while writing a poem, planting a (1) The robot has no say over its own initial programming (as
garden, playing a tennis game, cooking a meal? neither do we); but also,
The entire area surrounding these experiments is too con- (2) The robot has no control over the outcomes of its ‘indeci-
tested to carry much weight. We will have to see what future sion choices’, since they are produced by a randomizer. Any
research shows. randomizer, internal or not, by definition yields unpredictable
Of course, even if we accept the reality of conscious phenom- outcomes not under the agent’s control. The link between non-
ena such as beliefs, desires, intentions, decisions, agency, and even predictability and agent responsibility is broken.
if we accept that they can cause changes in the physical world, So how do we add an agent-control factor to the robot, or
we could still view the whole process as deterministic. Every con- to us, without losing the non-deterministic factor in our choices?
scious decision might, in principle, be the inevitable consequence Frankly, we don’t know. The skeptic about free will is right
of the prior river of both microscopic and macroscopic events in pointing out that this agent-control factor is mysterious.
constituting our past. Might… but this apparent possibility is far However, the intellectual jump from ‘still mysterious’ to ‘non-
from having been shown as even likely. We have not even come existent’ (or, worse, ‘impossible’) gives many of us pause, if only
close to understanding and predicting the behavior of much sim- because this agent-control factor seems intimately real to all of
pler organisms, like insects. So, again, let’s wait and see. us. Cases where we exert sustained effort in the course of an activ-

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 23


gotten names; actively list pluses and minuses when facing tough
choices; actively sustain an effort against resistance.
Again, could all the active experiences be illusory? Could we
really never consciously control our attention? Perhaps. But if
we are deceived by these ‘active experiences’ we must be deceiv-
able about virtually anything.
Alternatively, are we giving too much weight to experiences
of directing our mind, will, attention, or limbs? Perhaps. But
it’s really hard not to. Our experiences of choosing are inti-
mately tied to who we are.
And who or what is the ‘I’ doing the directing, the summon-
ing, the introspecting? Mystery, again. But the solution to this
mystery is not to belittle the activity. With all the dizzying suc-
cess of science, it’s easy to forget that many aspects of our inner
experience escape its tools. Love, creativity, beauty, commit-
ments, morality, meanings, the very experiential aspect of con-
sciousness… all of these remain scientifically contentious, if not
mysterious. Do they have a place in a world that is only physi-
cal? Perhaps not; but let’s not forget that a physicalist view of the
ity make this factor especially evident. Some of us meditate, world is itself controversial. So, allegiance to physicalism cannot
aiming at fixing our attention on our breathing for minutes. It’s settle the issue. Besides, if consciousness can emerge out of non-
hard to do, but we often succeed. And the doing of this activity conscious physical nature, active powers might equally develop
– with all the monitoring, directing, and redirecting involved – out of non-active ones within conscious aspects of nature.
yields direct evidence of intimate agency at work. Riding a bicy-
cle uphill is another good example. Moreover, these experiences No Chosen Foundations For Our Choices
of intense monitoring and directing are similar in kind to those There are other philosophical attempts to knock out free will.
involved in our ordinary choosing – of whether or not to have One goes back at least as far as Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900)
the second bowl of ice cream; of quitting or staying at our job; and was recently revived by Galen Strawson. The argument is
of whether or not discussions of free will matter, etc. These that there is no meaningful form of ultimate self-making or self-
choices are felt as then-and-there up to us, especially when they programming, because one always needs preexisting motives to
conflict. They feel neither like random coin-flips inside us, nor shape your choices. In other words, you might be able to choose
like inevitable products of our character, surroundings or mental how you respond to your desires, but you do not choose the
workings, but rather, like choices. values by which you make this choice... One needs a prior pro-
gram even in order for one to meaningfully re-program oneself,
The Supposed Illusion of Agency so no genuine autonomy is possible (even in degree).
Could this feeling of being in control be an illusion? Perhaps, This either-or thinking is also subject to the type of response
but don’t bet on it. we used for the either-or of determinism/randomness. Yes, we
Again, the issues here are not new: they echo thousand-year- need prior motives to assess our motives meaningfully. But must
old debates between Buddhist and Hindu philosophers; or initial non-chosen motives always rule out transformations into
between David Hume on one side and Immanuel Kant or René semi-autonomous ones? Not so fast! What if such non-chosen
Descartes on the other. The Buddhists and Hume claim that motives are many and suitably complex; and what if they gen-
there is no introspective evidence of a core self. They claim that erate routine indecisions? These indecisions could generate the
when we look inside ourselves, we only find streams of sensa- pause, the space, for self-reflection. A complex psychology
tions, impulses, thoughts, drives, feelings, memories, so we are might produce a self-initiated (partial) reprogramming. If I am
simply a changing bundle of experiences. For a popular recent naturally both self-centered and empathetic, both curious and
example of this picture of the self, check out Sam Harris’s book cautious, the accumulation of split-decisions over time might
Free Will (2012). He repeatedly speaks of a self as a complex prompt me to develop one side of myself more than another,
stream of uncontrolled thoughts and feelings. Harris’s stimulat- and unpredictably. My own complex, non-chosen, open-ended
ing podcasts disseminate this unsubstantiated claim to millions. psychological resources might prompt some reprogramming.
This passive picture of our inner life as a stream of uncon- This reprogramming may take autonomy-building forms.
trolled elements oversimplifies our experience. Yes, many Or perhaps not. But this issue also needs to be carefully
thoughts and dreams and feelings do merely occur to us; but debated. The skeptics tend to go too fast. Much more would
not all. The very activity of introspecting – what is that? – should have to be said here.
make us pause before denying that experience provides evidence For the moment, it appears that neither science nor philos-
of our active agency. And it’s not the only activity that should. ophy has killed free will. The future is likely to remain open!
Our conscious life is a wonderfully subtle mix of passive and © CARLO FILICE 2018
active elements, of thoughts and sensations that occur to us and Carlo Filice is Professor of Philosophy at SUNY Geneseo and author of
our active interplay with these. We actively try to summon for- The Purpose of Life: An Eastern Philosophical Vision (UPA, 2011).

24 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


Is Everything A Computer?
Paul Austin Murphy computes the probabilities.

T
he term ‘computer’ is both vague and broad. Some When people say “the brain is a computer,” most of them really
people involved in the field of artificial intelligence mean that the mind-brain system sometimes and in some ways
even believe that molecules are computers. Or, more behaves like a computer. However, other people believe that the
precisely, they argue that molecules are closed physical human brain is literally a computer. So let’s put some meat on the
systems which compute. That is to say, molecules carry out infor- idea that ‘brains behave like computers’. It amounts to saying that
mation processing: they receive input, work on that input, and some processing done by brains to some extent parallels what
then produce output. Indeed, in one place I came across the fol- computers do. Indeed the brain’s own neurons process input in
lowing representation of the DNA molecule as a Turing machine: ways similar to the logic gates on a microchip. But the neuron’s
processing also has some similarities with what goes in a cell, or
Input Tape = DNA even in an inorganic or inanimate system. The crunch question
Tape Reading Head = Ribosome may therefore be: how alike are mind-brains and computers when
State Register = RNA it comes to processing highly complex tasks?
States = Amino acids Where does the idea that the brain is a computer come from?
Instruction Table = DNA codon table Firstly, there are strong links often made between brains, math-
Output Tape = Proteins ematical models and computers. Workers in artificial intelli-
(see ‘Is DNA a Turing Machine’ by Anand Mallaya, at gence are keen to tell us that physicists have created accurate
anandcv.wordpress.com) models of all aspects of physical reality, and that these models are
essentially mathematical in nature. Thus it’s only one step on
The idea of computation as omnipresent reaches its zenith from there to say that they’re also computable. Thus a computer
with what’s called pancomputationalism. This is the view that the can model and compute the whole of physical reality, including
entire evolution of the universe is a computation. That must the brain. Some go so far as to say that mathematics is synony-
mean, according to some, that God is a computer programmer. mous with computation, and through maths we can model all of
Again and again the issue of what we can or can’t call a computer reality (or at least each bit separately), including the brain. The
seems to come back to the vagueness of the word ‘computation’. argument here is, very roughly, that once we have mathemati-
One way this issue can be approached is to admit that in certain cally described all the workings of the brain, then a computer
senses the mind-brain system is indeed a computer, in that it carries could model brain processes. This makes the brain a computer,
out computations. However, all sorts of philosophers have argued they say. Other people talk about ‘simulating’ physical systems
that computation isn’t definitive of mind: it’s not necessary, or even rather than modelling them. One such person (Aaron Roth)
important, to a mind being a mind that it does computations. Or it concludes, “if the brain is a purely physical object, which is the
may be important, though only in the sense that any human mind only option consistent with our understanding of how the uni-
can do the same sort of operations that any man-made computer verse works, there is no reason it cannot be simulated.”
can do; or as the American philosopher Hilary Putnam puts it, The logic in either approach is simple:
“every ordinary open system realizes every abstract finite automa-
ton” (Representation & Reality, 1991). i) All physical objects or systems can be mathematically simu-
John Searle agrees with Putnam on this. He wrote the follow- lated/modelled.
ing about the broadness of the term ‘computation’: ii) The brain is a physical object or system.
iii) Therefore the brain can be mathematically simulated/modelled.
“The wall behind my back is right now implementing the WordStar iv) Therefore the brain is a computer.
program, because there is some pattern of molecule movements that
is isomorphic with the formal structure of WordStar. But if the wall is The problem is the slide from x being computable to x being
implementing WordStar, if it is a big enough wall it is implementing a computer. Even if the brain or its workings were computable,
any program, including any program implemented in the brain.” that wouldn’t necessarily make it a computer. Searle’s wall (or
(Philosophy in a New Century: Selected Essays, 2008) window) is digitally computable, and some subset of its
behaviour is the behaviour of a computer; but that doesn’t make
“The window in front of me is a very simple computer. Window open either the wall or window a computer. Sure, we can define ‘com-
= 1, window closed = 0. That is, if we accept Turing’s definition puter’ in such a way as to stipulate, for example that If the brain is
according to which anything to which you can assign a 0 and a 1 is a computable, then it’s a computer; and do the same for Searle’s wall
computer, then the window is a simple and trivial computer.” or window. If that wall (window, etc) is computable, then it’s a
(The Mystery of Consciousness, 1990) computer… At this rate, almost everything physical is a com-
puter. But, on the other hand, a proper computer must be able to
Of course there are certain things that computers do which systematically process input to create output. So a computer
Searle’s wall or window don’t do. There are also indefinitely mustn’t only be computable, it must also be a computer!
many things that the mind-brain does that computers can’t do. © PAUL AUSTIN MURPHY 2018
However, that doesn’t seem to stop people claiming that the Paul Austin Murphy is a writer on politics and philosophy. His
mind-brain is a computer. philosophy blog is at paulaustinmurphypam.blogspot.co.uk

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 25


Splitting Chairs
W
Quentin Mareuse distinguishes lots of ways of distinguishing things.
hen a rock breaks in two, you get two rocks. But since it cannot obviously be subdivided into different parts: all
when a chair breaks in two, you get two parts of parts of a muscle can be referred to as ‘muscle’.
a chair. Why the difference? What makes some- There is a clear difference between rock parts and chair parts
thing only a part of something else, as opposed in this respect. To use two more of Aristotle’s jargon terms, the
to a thing in its own right? two new rocks are homogeneous parts materially, as they only
Although the discrepancy initially seems enigmatic, the dif- consist of rock, and also formally, as they are the uniform arrange-
ference is also remarkably intuitive. No-one would hesitate to ments without distinct parts found in any rock. Meanwhile, the
call the two pieces of a broken rock rocks in themselves: after chair parts are heterogeneous in both matter and form each
all, many rocks are broken pieces of larger rocks. Similarly, no- piece will contain several distinct components, including the
one in their right mind would call a broken part of a chair a legs, stretcher, seat, spindle and various rails.
chair. This distinction is what has to be explained. However, the distinction between heterogenous and homoge-
Perhaps our intuition can be explained by the type-token dis- nous may not be as clear as it at first seems. If the chair were
tinction. The type-token distinction goes back to Plato and Aris- broken in such a way that the two parts following the fracture
totle, and was specifically applied by the scholastic philosophers included a solitary wooden leg, the leg would itself be homoge-
of the Middle Ages who followed in their tradition. This theory neous because all of a chair leg is chair leg, without (evident)
separates types, which are concepts or categories for a set of sim- parts itself. This indicates that simple heterogeneity may not be
ilar objects, from tokens, which are particular concrete examples what makes something merely a part of something else. We will
of those types. For instance, in the line “Rose is a rose is a rose need to look to other parts of mereology to find our answer.
is a rose” from Gertrude Stein’s novel Sacred Emily, there are
three types of words – ‘rose’, ‘is’, and ‘a’ – but ten different (Un)Interrupted
tokens of words – there are ten words in the sentence. So Another way to differentiate parts is into continuous and contigu-
although they are different tokens, with different properties, ous wholes. In continuous wholes, the parts extend without inter-
namely different sizes and shapes, the two new rocks remain the ruption, seamlessly joining into one another, whereas in con-
same type of thing (rocks) as the parent rock. Conversely, the tiguous wholes the parts are discrete entities, albeit attached to
two new parts of the chair are fundamentally different types of each other or closely bordering each other. The parent rock as
thing from the original chair, as well as two new tokens of things. well as its offspring are continuous wholes; whilst the chair, with
its distinct attached parts, is a contiguous whole. This distinc-
Mere Mereology tion would be supported by the Medieval French philosopher
In the search for the differentiating factors between the two Peter Abelard (1079-1142), who believed that natural objects
types of part, the field to which we must turn is mereology, which such as rocks are always continuous, and man-made ones such
is the philosophical study of part-whole relations. Mereology as the chair always contiguous, because only God can authenti-
has a long history, starting with the Pre-Socratic philosophers, cally fuse parts into a continuous whole.
and remains a prominent field of philosophy in the twenty-first However, although this distinction shows up a clear differ-
century. Although some philosophers, including Peter Forrest ence between the two new rocks and the two parts of the chair,
(‘How Innocent is Mereology?’, Analysis 56, 1996) , have chal- it doesn’t explain why we refer to the two new rocks as ‘rocks’
lenged mereology’s approach, the theories I employ here are rather than as ‘parts of a rock’. If the two new rocks were origi-
relatively basic and uncontroversial, and so may be considered nally simply parts in the continuous whole of the parent rock,
reliable representations of the field. they would be referred to as such both before and after the frac-
Mereology underwent serious development under Aristotle ture. Indeed, the key flaw in trying to explain the difference in
(384-322 BC), who drew one of its principal distinctions: that perception between rocks and chairs using either the homoge-
between homogeneous and heterogeneous parts. Homogeneous neous/heterogeneous distinction or the continuous/contiguous
parts are parts of the same type as an original entity, and het- distinction is that both approaches inevitably entail that the two
erogeneous parts are parts of different types from the original new rocks be considered only parts of the original parent rock,
entity. For instance, a human hand is a heterogeneous part of which seems to go against our intuitions.
the human body; and the parts of the hand are also heteroge-
nous, because it can be split up into components such as skin, No Accident
muscles, and bones, which are fundamentally different types of In his book Categories, Aristotle defined two more key philo-
thing from the hand: no-one would refer to the muscle in the sophical terms, closely related to the theory of types and tokens:
hand as ‘hand’, but rather as ‘muscle’. By contrast (at least from substantial form and accidental form. An object’s substantial form
a layman’s unscientific perspective, or from Aristotle’s proto- consists of the properties it must possess to exist as the type of
scientific perspective) muscle is a homogeneous part of the hand, object it is. For humans, this would consist of physical proper-

26 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


ELEMENTS IN TRANSITION © KEN LAIDLAW 2018 PLEASE VISIT WWW.KENLAIDLAW.COM TO SEE MORE OF KEN’S ART

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 27


The Purposes of Parts
This idea that purpose or design is at the heart of our discrep-
ancy seems attractive initially, but some flaws in this conception
are quickly found. Take the example of a detached tree leaf,
ROCK(S) © PRINCE ROY 2007

which has no obvious function once separated from the tree. If


it were lying on the ground intact, we would still call it a leaf;
but if it were ripped in two we could comfortably call the two
pieces ‘parts of a leaf’. Like the rock, the leaf lying on the ground
has no function, and like the rock it was not designed by a human,
yet its two broken pieces are ‘parts of a leaf’, not new leaves.
This difference between leaves and rocks can be accounted for
in two ways. The first way is by arguing that the leaf at least used
to have a function (providing energy to the tree), whereas a rock
has none. Secondly, the difference between broken rocks and
ties such as having a head, eyes, and a torso, and also mental broken leaves can be explained by introducing the wider concept
properties such as the ability to reason. By contrast, an object’s of form, which for Aristotle includes shape and material as well as
accidental form consists of the properties it has that are not purpose. In this particular example the key difference is that leaves
essential to its being that type of object – or we can say, prop- have to be a certain shape which they grew into, with continuous
erties which vary amongst the different tokens of that particu- boundaries and no rips or cuts, whereas rocks do not. Rocks can
lar type. For humans, this would include properties such as their be any shape. The need for a leaf to be a certain shape is deter-
height, strength, or courage. mined by its original function, and so these two elements of what
This contrast between substance and accident was applied it is to be a leaf are intrinsically linked. Function and shape are intrin-
in mereology by St Thomas Aquinas back in the thirteenth cen- sically linked under Aristotle’s four-part notion of cause. Indeed,
tury. The Angelic Doctor as he was known, believed that only the leaf’s former function is what makes the shape important.
natural objects possess substantial form, since man-made objects
(‘artefacts’) are made merely by people rearranging things that Conclusion
already exist. For him these parts can function independently To conclude, we can see that the cause of an entity in the Aris-
of the artefact’s specific purpose. totelian sense (that is, what makes something exist as it does) is
Aquinas’s theory suggests that we can tell whether a part is the key to defining whether its broken pieces are merely parts
substantial or accidental by examining the effect of the whole’s of it or tokens of the same type of object in themselves.
form on the functionality of its parts. For instance, if the form Aristotle famously claimed that there are four types of cause:
of a human ceases to exist (if, for example, the person dies), then the formal cause (a thing’s arrangement or shape), its material
their parts, such as hands, become redundant. This makes them cause (what a thing is made of), its efficient cause (which refers to
part of the substantial form of a human being. Conversely, if what happened to give rise to the thing), and its final cause (the
the form of a car ceases to exist (by running out of fuel, for end to which it directs: its purpose). For our purposes, the impor-
instance), its parts can still function: the carburettor, for exam- tant causes are material, formal and final. If the broken pieces
ple, could be transferred to another car and work fine. differ from the parent object in any of these respects, they can
Aquinas’s argument that artefacts cannot possess substantial only be considered ‘parts’ of the original object. Thus if the orig-
form is problematic. There are organ transplants. Plus, parts of inal entity has a specific shape that becomes fragmented (formal
artefacts often seem to service only that artefact and would be cause), as in a chair or leaf, the broken pieces will merely be con-
redundant without it: consider a handmade watch. Further- sidered parts. Also, if the original entity is made of a particular
more, on Aquinas’s argument, non-living substances often do (variety of) material(s), the broken pieces will be considered
not seem to possess substantial form, as their parts could easily merely parts if they do not consist of the same material(s). Or if
exist independently of the whole. Indeed, in this respect the two the original entity fulfills a specific function (final cause), the
rocks are more similar to the carburettor (an artefact) than the broken pieces will be considered merely parts if they do not
hand (a natural object), because they have their own form which themselves fulfill that function. The two new rocks remain rocks
exists independently of the whole (the parent rock), and is, in because, on all three of these criteria, which together determine
fact, the same as that of the parent rock. Meanwhile, the two the rock’s substantial form and make it the type of thing it is,
parts of the chair more closely resemble the hands than the car- they are the same as the parent rock. Meanwhile, the two parts
burettor: just as the hands lose their purpose as they become of a chair are merely parts because they have different formal
separated from the body, the part of the chair breaking off also and final (and quite possibly, material) causes compared to the
loses its purpose. So Aquinas’s ideas about substantial and acci- parent chair: they have a different type of shape from a chair,
dental form do not answer our question. But they do reveal a and each separately does not fulfil the purpose of a chair.
crucial distinction between the two new rocks and the two In summary, If two entities are essentially the same type of
broken parts of the chair. The form and purpose of the new thing, one must be considered more than a mere ‘part’ of the
rocks is the same as that of the parent rock; they are seen in the other, even if it did originate from that thing.
same way as the parent was. By contrast the parts of the chair © QUENTIN MAREUSE 2018
do not maintain the form and purpose of the original chair. Quentin Mareuse is an undergraduate at Columbia University, NYC.

28 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


Twelve Principles of Knowledge
George Dunseth outlines basic principles for knowing whether or not ideas are true.

A
s I began to think and exchange ideas I soon realised 1. Non-Contradiction
that it is important to be reasonable and rational. But Is this idea or set of ideas consistent, and therefore coherent?
I then felt a powerful need to understand what that This is the first principle of formal logic.
means. And so I began making a lifelong, constantly
revised, simple list of how all of us support our truth claims. 2. Observation
What counts as evidence for truth in rational argument? I Is this idea verified by sense observation?
have attempted to be simple, clear and exhaustive. These princi-
ples can be printed on a piece of paper and posted proudly on 3. Experimentation
your refrigerator. They apply both to the sciences and the Can this observation be repeated predictably?
humanities, since science does not have a monopoly on reason.
None of the principles are sufficient in themselves, and some 4. Testability
are clearly stronger and more warranted than others. The more Is this idea in theory falsifiable, and can its truth value be put to
of them that apply to your claim, the more warranted your truth the test? In other words, is it possible to think about this truth
claim is – we could even say, the more reasonable it is. claim being wrong?

5. Comprehensiveness: That which explains the most.


Is this the simplest explanation of the most phenomena?

6. Fit
Does this help a lot of related factors fit nicely into place?

7. Pragmatism: What works best?


Does this work? If a set of ideas works, then it is likely that there
is something true about them!

8. Intuition
Does this idea strongly inwardly demand assent?

9. Common Sense
Is this very widely, or perhaps almost universally, accepted as
true? (Many philosophers cringe here, but may I suggest that a
little regard for common sense is not unhelpful?! And like all the
principles, it cannot stand alone.)

10. History & Tradition


Does this have historical warrant – meaning that it has stood the
test of time?

11. Warranted Authority


Is this backed by a reliable testimony or source?

12. Analogy
Does this idea cohere with a related idea which is seen to be
true? Then this similarity could imply its own truth.

Finally, a word on ‘mystical’ truth claims. Mystical experience


is not in the above twelve principles of reason, since by definition
conclusions based on it are not thereby supported by reason.
However, I think it is wise to be open to the idea that there may
be truths inaccessible to reason or outside its parameters.
© GEORGE DUNSETH 2018
George Dunseth is a jazz musician in Leicester, England.

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 29


Are You A Garbled Relativist?
Ray Prebble argues that moral relativism is both incoherent and immoral.

re you a relativist? A relativist is someone who says of the traps which start to open once you start putting meat on

A things like “There are many truths, many ways of


seeing things.” Compare this with the non-relativist,
or absolutist, who says, “This is how things are, and
there are no two ways about it.” What’s your reaction to these
opposing viewpoints? If the relativist sounds decent, non-judge-
the bones of this relativist framework.
Here’s a quick tour around the trap line.

1. Did I Just Contradict Myself?


Let’s begin by looking at the idea that if morality is relative to
mental, and understanding – someone you feel a connection cultures – if one is enculturated into one’s moral beliefs, and
with – whereas the absolutist sounds biased, unforgiving, and there is nothing more to morality than that − then there is no
unthinking – someone you would avoid – then you are just the way of choosing between moral systems, and one ought there-
audience I’m aiming at. fore to respect the moral decisions of other cultures. To put it
Of course one can unproblematically be a relativist about another way, the idea is one ought not to pass moral judgements
taste in art, or in gardening, or anything involving only purely on the moral judgements of other cultures, or the actions of
subjective evaluations. But the philosophically interesting kind people from other cultures.
of relativism is cultural relativism, also known as (or is at least This is a very interesting argument, because it is both beguil-
a substantial subdivision of) moral relativism. (From now on in ingly plausible and utterly invalid. The problem is that rela-
this article, ‘relativists’ will refer specifically to moral relativists.) tivists’ moral statements, such as “One ought not to pass moral
The fact that different cultures do things differently is still judgements on the actions of people from other cultures” are
unproblematic if you’re deciding where to have dinner; but not remotely relative; they are absolute. They are meant to apply
accepting the differences can get tricky when you’re making as a moral rule to all individuals in all cultures. So, ironically,
decisions about moral issues. How ought one to think and act the central catch-cry of many moral relativists is a thoroughly
when cultures clash morally or moral systems collide? Whose absolutist moral statement, the very possibility of which their
rules should be followed; yours or theirs? How can we decide? own theory denies.
What should a nice relativist do? At best, statements about not passing judgement on other
These questions are more pertinent today than ever. Decent cultures can coherently function as representing a moral deci-
people from modern Westernised cultures often talk about the sion in one’s own culture (if for a moment we pretend there is
requirement to tolerate and respect people from other cultures. such a thing as all the members of a culture having the same
But you need to be careful that you don’t fall into one or more moral beliefs). In other words, you and the other members of

Moral relativism means slavery is just another cultural tradition

30 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


tain’s activities, pointing out that the British had made the slave
trade illegal in 1807, he might have said, “Why should I care? In
my culture slavery is acceptable. If you want to abolish slavery in
your culture, that’s up to you. Leave me alone!” This slave trader
is making moral judgements within a relativistic framework. He
is a moral relativist through and through. Yet this doesn’t restrain
him from acting appallingly towards the members of other cul-
tures. In fact, it encourages him to do so.
For another example, many writers have poured scorn on the
mental gymnastics of those cultural relativists, especially ones
also claiming to be feminists, who have justified the Hindu ritual
of sati – the practice of a wife throwing herself on her husband’s
funeral pyre – or the widespread African cultural practice of gen-
ital mutilation, in culturally relativistic terms. The scorn is well
deserved, because such tolerance involves condoning the suffer-
ing of women out of post-colonial guilt, rather than through any
Sati: Just another tradition to be respected? well-thought-out moral system. It’s relativism at its worst.
The point I am making here is that relativism leads not just to
your culture might believe such statements to be true; but contradiction, but also, sometimes, to the very kind of abhorrent
according to that very statement of belief, a member of another moral conclusions it sets out to avoid, and provides an excuse for
culture has the right to say, “Well, moral relativism is what you any sort of behaviour the members of a culture can collectively
believe in your culture; but in my culture we don’t believe that dream up. Think of the response of any authoritarian country
one ought not to pass moral judgements on the people from accused by Amnesty International of human rights abuses: “You
other cultures. We feel perfectly free to cast moral judgements have no right to judge, no right to interfere!” It is the perfect
on whomever we like, including you and your culture.” You defence against a relativist. Note also that relativism does not imply
may have experienced this very retort. any requirement to tolerate strangers in one’s midst: as Tzvetan
Further considering the statement by the relativist, “You Todorov notes, “an entirely consistent relativist may demand that
ought to be tolerant of others’ moral beliefs” – what then of the all foreigners go home, so they can live surrounded by their own
moral belief that one ought not be tolerant of others’ moral values” (On Human Diversity: Nationalism, Racism and Exoticism in
beliefs? Ought one to tolerate this moral belief? Ought one to French Thought, trans. C. Porter, 1993, p.34).
tolerate intolerance? Of course the relativist should (supposing
of course that they want to be consistent) because it is a moral 3. How Big Is ‘My Culture’?
belief; and once you accept that you ought to be tolerant of There is also the problem of what actually constitutes a culture.
others’ moral beliefs, then you are obliged to tolerate others’ Depending on how you define the term, a culture could be a
intolerance – in the name of absolute toleration! family group or a confederation of nations. But the issue
becomes crucially important when a relativist poses the ques-
2. Is That What I Mean? tion as to when the cultural walls rear up to protect a group
But let’s suppose that we accept both that moral judgements from moral criticism. Was the Manson family a cultural group?
are relative to cultures and that this relativism gives each cul- On most criteria, yes. So should we have tolerated and/or
ture some kind of protection from criticism from other cultures, respected their moral decisions, their moral system?
and let’s see where it leads. We tend to talk very airily about ‘culture’. Someone might
Now it could be that a generally agreed-upon belief in my expound knowledgeably at a dinner party about ‘Spanish cul-
culture is that dark-skinned people are inferior and that we have ture’ or ‘the culture of the Inuit’ as if a given culture has a single
the right to enslave them and use them to our benefit, and that list of beliefs and practices to which everyone adheres – which,
because of their inferiority we are not morally wrong in doing of course, is nonsense. There is a large diversity of moral think-
so. The moral beliefs of the dark-skinned people themselves ing within any culture, and one could quite validly react to any
are irrelevant (as are the beliefs of any other culture): they can claim that “This is what we do in our culture” with “Says who?”
make whatever moral judgements they like, but they have no or “What do you mean by our culture?” However, if moral right
relevance to my culture, because my moral system is distinct and wrong are to be based on cultural beliefs, there had better
from theirs, and cannot be judged by their beliefs. be some way of coming to an agreement about what these beliefs
So let’s consider the captain of a Muslim slave ship operating actually are. But haven’t we now defeated the whole point of
between Africa and the Middle East in the middle of the nine- cultural relativism? Morality is supposed to arise naturally as a
teenth century. (Some readers may feel uncomfortable at me sin- function of being part of a culture, and suddenly relativism seems
gling out Muslims. Would you have felt uncomfortable if I had to work perhaps only for an individual at any given time, or at
singled out Christians? No? Is that because you feel that one best, a small tribe living on a river bank.
ought not to pass judgement on other cultures? If so, well done: Does it make a difference if we take a temporal perspective?
You have passed the ‘Am I a garbled relativist?’ test with flying On most criteria of cultural difference, the British colonists of
colours!) If you had challenged the morality of the slaver cap- New Zealand in the nineteenth century could be said to consti-

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 31


tute a very different culture to either British or New Zealand cul- here (for this analysis I have made use of Frank Furedi’s excel-
ture in the twenty-first century. It would seem to follow that lent review in Spiked 40, 2010). First, toleration does not imply
whatever the colonists did or didn’t do, in terms of confiscating any particular power relation, much less one in which it is only
land or abusing the (non-relative) rights of the Maori, is, accord- the more powerful who tolerates the less. Many who are dis-
ing to cultural relativism, outside the bounds of moral criticism. empowered, from downtrodden wives to minority cultures, tol-
So present-day Maori cannot criticise the actions of the colonists, erate the actions of those who are more powerful, for many rea-
because Maori belong to a different culture from them. Indeed, sons, and when pressed may even sometimes maintain that this
on this line of reasoning, the Maori cannot seek redress from the is not only the safe course but the morally right thing to do.
present New Zealand government either, because the govern- And as citizens we tolerate (albeit while grumbling) the quirks
ment also belongs to another culture from the colonists. of local and central government, while recognizing their right
Are rich, clean-cut Western businessmen a different culture to have power over us. Indeed, toleration of a greater power is
from poor, dreadlocked, anti-globalisation Western activists? part of the social contract. One could also well ask Ramadan
They have staggeringly different values and accompanying why he doesn’t respect the viewpoint of people who advocate
moral systems, so the cultural relativist would surely have to merely tolerating and grudgingly accepting other cultures?
conclude that they are from different cultures – and that there- Where is his respect for that culture?
fore each is safe from the other’s criticism. Both groups have The second point is, what’s so bad about being tolerated and
been enculturated into their moral beliefs and actions; and if grudgingly accepted? After all, this could well describe how
they are relativists, they ought to stand back and respect the most academics feel about each other (on a good day). A
other’s culture. Otherwise any criticism from one side – such common perspective in academia would be, “I think your the-
as protesting and egg throwing – is simply a form of cultural ories are nonsense and your work sloppy, but I recognise your
imperialism − an attempt to impose one’s culture forcibly on right to publish your opinions.” Indeed, this attitude could be
others: to culturally colonise them. viewed as the very core of Enlightenment thinking: tolerating
what you utterly disagree with because you don’t think that
4. Toleration Vs Respect people with different opinions ought to be silenced. The same
Some relativists question whether cultural relativism implies applies to attitudes to other cultures: laws that apply equally to
toleration, or rather, respect. Early anthropologists promoted tol- all citizens, plus toleration and grudging acceptance among cul-
eration, or tolerance; but it was later argued that tolerance tural groups, could be seen as the core of multiculturalism. And
implies acting from a position of power to put up with some- this is not to be summarily dismissed. After all, it’s easy to respect
thing you condemn or think is bad, much as a parent might put someone you actually respect because you agree with their values.
up with an errant teenager. This, it was further argued, implies Tolerating someone you fundamentally disagree with and whose
a patronising cultural attitude, and still involves making evalu- beliefs and actions you despise is a monumental achievement.
ative judgements. As a result, tolerance and toleration have often Suppose however that we do accept that one ought to respect
been rejected by relativists in favour of respect. For example, the moral beliefs of others. What does this commit us to in
Tariq Ramadan, the Swiss-born Professor of Contemporary terms of decision-making and governance? This is a pressing
Islamic Studies in the Faculty of Oriental Studies at Oxford contemporary question, because the requirement to respect the
University, in The Quest for Meaning: Developing a Philosophy of beliefs of others is not simply an idea bandied about by writers
Pluralism (2010), sees toleration as a kind of ‘intellectual char- on multiculturalism. It often crops up in legislation dealing with
ity’ and therefore an insult, since
“when standing on equal footing, one Would you advocate respecting Naziism?
does not expect to be merely toler-
ated or grudgingly accepted” (p.47).
He also argues that tolerance towards
other groups is not enough because
it involves acquiescing to the prevail-
ing power relations: “Calling upon
powers to be tolerant once meant
asking them to moderate their
strength and to limit their ability to
do harm. This actually implied an
acceptance of a power relationship
that might exist between the State and
individuals, the police and citizens, or
between colonisers and colonised”
(ibid). Rather than this patronising
toleration, then, Ramadan wants
acceptance and respect from other cul-
tures.
There are two important points

32 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


moral issues where different cultures with different viewpoints
Do you think this is
are involved, such as opinions on the rights of the foetus. Respect
often becomes a legal requirement. Moreover, an enormous really wrong, or not?
amount of energy and money is put into various forms of com-
munity consultation by local and central government, where
there is an explicit or tacit requirement to respect the views of
all participants. And so the idea of respect has enormous prac-
tical implications. But what does such respect amount to? Can
I be said to be respecting someone’s views if I allow them a hear-
ing, listen to them attentively, ask for points of clarification,
and then utterly reject all their suggestions? How can you be
said to respect someone’s beliefs if you ignore what they say?
Does this mean respect entails agreeing with and acquiescing
to people? Clearly not, given that many opinions contradict
each other, and yet practical decisions need to be made.
To sum up: it’s hard to see how either ‘toleration’ or ‘respect’
helps the relativist. Indeed, the mere fact that different cultures
have different moral systems doesn’t of itself imply any sort of
moral attitude towards other cultures; and if it did imply toler-
ation or respect, then we would be obliged to tolerate or respect Aztecs’ systematic human sacrifice of war captives.
the most morally appalling cultural groups history has thrown This basic inconsistency is an essential part of what it means
up. Finally, where there is a cultural clash, while we are all busy to be a garbled relativist. A garbled relativist is someone who
tolerating or respecting each other, how is one to decide on a espouses relativism (“One ought to respect the moral beliefs of
course of action? Relativism provides no answers, no way of others”) in one breath, while issuing non-relativist statements
making a moral decision. in the next (“Tax-avoiding rich capitalists should be put up
against the wall and shot!”). Indeed, anything you say people
5. You’ve Just Ruined Everything should or should not do is a non-relativist assertion.
Having been informed that moral beliefs are just customs that It is almost inevitable that a relativist will be a garbled rela-
we have had enculturated into us, like cooking techniques, and tivist: there is always something that they will find so uncon-
that there is no absolute right or wrong, one is left with no scionably appalling that they will have to admit it really is wrong.
reason for behaving morally, apart perhaps from any sympa-
thy you might accidentally feel, or to avoid punishment or Conclusion
humiliation. Relativism, despite setting out to be decent, in You might now ask, “Do these problems with moral relativism
effect destroys morality because it gives a person no objective mean we ought not to tolerate diversity? Does this mean we
reason to be moral. And this applies to how one behaves towards ought to persecute people from different cultures for their dif-
anybody, including people from another culture, the people ferent moral beliefs?” My reply is: absolutely not. But these prob-
who live next door, one’s own family, and one’s own self. If lems do mean that a simple universal tolerance of all moral beliefs
morality is simply what people do, and there is no objective is not a viable, or even meaningful, moral code. Instead we need
authority to appeal to, then in the end it doesn’t really matter a robust framework within which to discuss clashes of moral sys-
what you do. tems – not something that falls apart as soon as you look at it.
It’s hard not to feel that this conclusion has already been So what’s the answer? What am I advocating? Bible thump-
reached by many people in modern society, especially the young. ing, threats of fire and brimstone, and a corresponding list of
Imagine constantly hearing, “Listen, there is no objective basis rules? No. I’m arguing that to put a blanket ban on criticising
for morality, but by the way, you still ought to be nice, espe- the values and moral beliefs of another culture is patronising,
cially to people who look and act differently to you.” Why should counterproductive, and dangerous. It stops discussion just when
anyone pay any attention to this? it should be starting. Really respecting people from other cul-
tures means engaging with them, taking them seriously enough
5. Nobody’s Really A Moral Relativist to question their moral decisions: Why do you think that? How
So with moral relativism you end up contradicting yourself, or can you justify doing that? What consequences will that deci-
you find yourself allowing slavery, or you eliminate any objec- sion have? Haven’t you just contradicted yourself? Does every-
tive reason for behaving decently. However, even though you one in your culture agree?
may still claim to be a moral relativist, if you dig deep enough, Morality must, in the end, be about arguing, and giving rea-
you will inevitably find some practice that you are not willing sons, and providing evidence. It cannot just be about being who
to accepts as a matter of culture, whether this be paedophilia, your culture encourages you to be.
genocide, torture or rape. Most people who claim to hold rela- © RAY PREBBLE 2018
tivist views will baulk and bail at some stage, wanting to main- Ray Prebble received his PhD in philosophy from Melbourne Uni-
tain that some action simply is wrong, even if it is practised or versity. He works as an editor, lives on a lifestyle property, and is fin-
condoned by all the members of a cultural group – such as the ishing off a book on the structure of moral thinking.

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 33


Why False Beliefs Are
Not Always Bad
Sally Latham argues that sometimes it’s better to be wrong.
t is a fairly common assumption that factually correct tion, 2013). One common depressive delusion is that one is fail-

I beliefs are to be strived for and factually incorrect beliefs


are to be avoided. In fact, for many philosophers, the very
cornerstone of the discipline is that true beliefs are good
and false beliefs are bad.
Yet this assumption is being challenged by Project PERFECT
ing to be there for others. Exaggerating one’s failing, or the
extent of one’s responsibilities, in this regard can lead to an
excessive sense of guilt. Other false beliefs include delusions of
persecution or of illness. These delusions emerge in cases of
severe depressive disorders (sometimes known as psychotic
(Pragmatic and Epistemic Role of Factually Erroneous Cogni- depression or depressive psychosis), as well as in schizophrenia
tions and Thoughts). Headed by Professor Lisa Bortolotti at the and other psychoses.
University of Birmingham, this project aims to establish whether It is important when considering the knowledge benefits of
cognitions that are in some important way inaccurate can ever depressive delusions to first distinguish them from schizophrenic
be good for us. Delusional beliefs, distorted memories, beliefs delusions. According to a paper by Giovanni Stranghellini and
that fail to reflect social realities, and so forth, are frequent in Andrea Raballo (in the Journal of Affective Disorders 171, 2015),
the non-clinical population; and are also listed as symptoms of schizophrenic delusions provide a (false) ‘revelation’ by uncov-
clinical psychiatric conditions such as schizophrenia and demen- ering new content that is unfamiliar to the person. A ‘dawn of a
tia. Project PERFECT investigates whether such beliefs could new reality’ occurs which alters the person’s perspective; for
have redeeming features. The hypothesis is that there can exist example, the ‘discovery’ that the friendly behaviour of a neigh-
false but useful beliefs. bour is all part of a plan to spy on them and ultimately harm
I will explain some of the evidence supporting this hypothesis them. In contrast, depressive delusions confirm previously
using two examples from the Project PERFECT research: firstly acquired beliefs related to the self. Nothing new is discovered,
depressive delusions, and secondly beliefs that fail to reflect social only old delusions reaffirmed. Delusions of guilt for example
inequalities. Both examples have the underlying theme that there will validate a pre-existing conviction a person has that they are
can be epistemic innocence to inaccurate or imperfect cognitions, guilty of wrongdoing.
and in that case, such distortions in belief can be beneficial. With this in mind we can start to examine the epistemic ben-
In explaining the concept of epistemic innocence in a paper efits of such delusions. To understand this, let’s refer to Jean
in Consciousness & Cognition in 2015 Bortolotti draws compari- Piaget’s Equilibrium of Cognitive Structures model, as set out
son with the ‘justification defence’ in UK and US law. This is in his 1977 book The Development of Thought.
where an act that would normally be considered criminal can Central to this model is the concept of a schema. A schema is
be justified under the particular circumstances in which it was a set of linked mental representations of the world used to under-
performed; for example, if someone knocks someone out to pre- stand new situations and how to respond to them. An example
vent serious harm they might do to themselves or others. The would be a schema about how to purchase goods in a shop, or
act brings costs, but it’s justified as an emergency response how to classify people according to gender. Schemata have evo-
because it spares greater cost that could not have otherwise been lutionary benefits in terms of the speed and efficiency of our
avoided. In this emergency situation, the otherwise criminal act information processing. When a person’s existing schemata can
is the lesser of two evils. Similarily, Bortolotti argues that inac- explain what someone experiences, the result is cognitive bal-
curate or imperfect cognitions, for example delusions or fac- ance, also known as cognitive equilibrium.
tual misrepresentations, can be epistemically innocent if: When someone is presented with a new object or new situa-
a) They provide ‘epistemic benefit’ – meaning, they’re beliefs tion, says Piaget, there are two key processes required for cog-
that can help us. nitive balance; either assimilation, whereby the existing schema
b) There is no available alternative that would confer the same is used to deal with this new object or situation; or accommoda-
benefit without higher cost in terms of knowledge or beliefs. tion, whereby the existing schema does not neatly apply and itself
(‘Epistemic’ means ‘referring to beliefs or knowledge’.) needs to be modified. The successful development of cognitive
structures is known as adaptation, and it requires both processes.
Depressive Delusions In the case of ineffective mental functioning, one of the pro-
First we’ll look at depressive delusions, the subject of paper by cesses compensates for the deficiency of the other. When equi-
Bortolotti and Magdalena Antrobus in the Unisinos Journal of librium cannot be reached it is the source of anxiety for the
Philosophy (May 2016). A partial definition of delusion is “a false person. The lack of equilibrium we may feel can be understood
belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that as cognitive dissonance, which is “the mental stress or discomfort
is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes experienced by an individual who holds two contradictory
and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof beliefs, ideas or values at the same time … or is confronted by
or evidence to the contrary” (American Psychological Associa- information that conflicts with existing beliefs, ideas or values”

34 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


(Leon Festinger, A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance, 1957). Incon- In severe depression, negative schemata can be formed early
sistency between existing beliefs and incoming information leads in life but remain dormant until activated by adverse circum-
to psychological discomfort we are naturally motivated to stances, often resulting in critically low self-esteem. Once acti-
reduce. This is one way of explaining why we strive for coher- vated, there is a bias towards interpreting new information in a
ence in our thinking. There is evidence that a prolonged state way consistent with the schema, that is, negatively at the expense
of cognitive dissonance leads to increased anxiety and symp- of positive or neutral interpretations. In some circumstances,
toms resembling post-traumatic stress disorder (see Anxiety: positive self-appraisals can actually cause discomfort and anxi-
The Cognitive Perspective by Michael Eysenck, 1992). ety and are rejected in favour of negative ones fitting pre-exist-
But what if there’s some psychological reason why an indi- ing beliefs. For example, despite having a boyfriend, Jane’s neg-
vidual cannot change her beliefs to fit in with new information? ative self-representation includes the belief that she is unlov-
For example, in cases of severe depression individuals acquire able and no-one will want her. When her boyfriend surprises
increasingly negative beliefs about themselves because their her with a thoughtful gift, this show of affection is at odds with
processing of self-related information is disrupted. Individuals her schema and causes cognitive dissonance. Rather than chang-
unable to change their beliefs will attempt to reduce mental ing her belief about herself being unlovable, she distorts the
inconsistency in other ways – for example, by reinterpreting meaning of this kind action and interprets it as an act of guilt
their experience, completely rejecting the new information, or by her boyfriend because he has been thinking about other
by seeking additional support for the previous beliefs from those women, or about leaving her. This inaccurate thinking (given
who share them. the assumption that her boyfriend does indeed love her) has
CARTOON © BILL STOTT 2018 FOR MORE, PLEASE VISIT WWW.BILLSTOTT.CO.UK

“Well, yes, we still do some animal testing”

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 35


obvious emotional and other costs. However, if these costs are
outweighed by the preservation of consistency and mental equi-
librium and the removal of anxiety caused by the dissonance
between her self-belief and the evidence, then this belief could
be epistemically innocent. The epistemic benefit of depressive
delusions can be the preservation of a coherent self-represen-
tation, even if it is a very negative one. So Antrobus and Bor-

PLEASE VISIT WORLDOFBOFY.COM


tolotti hypothesise that in cases of severe depression the dis-
torted interpretation of experience to assimilate it into an exist-
ing schema can be epistemically innocent in cases where the
cost in knowledge of the distorted negative belief is outweighed
by the benefit to that person in terms of reduced anxiety. This
is in contrast to the popular opinion that delusions always need
to be eliminated as both epistemically and psychologically costly.

IMAGE © BOFY 2018


As I mentioned earlier, there is a second condition for epis-
temic innocence – that there is no alternative that would convey
the same benefits without the costs in knowledge. In the case
of depressive delusions, people have generally formed their neg-
ative self-image through a long process of negatively-biased
learning to the point that positive information has so long been
reinterpreted or not integrated into the schemata that it is not
a practical option to update the schemata.

Beliefs That Fail To Reflect Social Realities


Let’s now consider an example concerning inaccurate beliefs
about social facts.
Negative Schemata, by Bofy
In her paper ‘Dissolving The Epistemic/Ethical Dilemma
Over Implicit Bias’ (Philosophical Explorations, Vol 20, 2017), As mentioned, the implicit bias associated with the stereo-
Katherine Puddifoot of Project PERFECT considers the issue type that women are not scientists and scientists are not women
of stereotyping, specifically, the automatic stereotyping involved sometimes brings the epistemic benefit of yielding true assump-
in implicit bias. A common definition of a stereotype is that it tions concerning random individuals. If you’re trying to work
is a widely held but fixed and oversimplified image or idea of a out which person in a room full mostly of scientists is an admin-
particular type of person or thing; for example, of females as istrator, you will sometimes be more likely to identify them if
carers/nurturers or of males as leaders. ‘Implicit bias’ refers to you focus on the females. But there are several epistemic costs
attitudes that prejudice our understanding, decisions, and of implicit bias. The first concerns distortion of memory. Research
actions in an unconscious manner. I will continue to use Pud- shows that if a person is aware of the social characteristics of an
difoot’s examples of gender, although she does use others too. individual and those characteristics fit with a stereotype, then
Ethically, the general consensus is that until we know oth- the information remembered about that individual increases
erwise we should treat all people as equally likely to possess cer- but is also biased towards the stereotype. Imagine a candidate
tain traits; for example, in their attention to detail, commit- for a top neuroscience job who had a career break for a year,
ment, nurturing, and so on. However, if we seek knowledge and but who has also completed a research visit at a prestigious uni-
understanding then our beliefs and responses should reflect real versity. If the person reading their CV [resume] knows that this
social inequalities rather than being unreflectively egalitarian; applicant is female, they are more likely to take note of her
and statistically, some social groups are more likely to possess career break because it fits with a stereotype of women being
certain features. For example, at present scientists are statisti- less vocationally committed; the research visit receives no such
cally more likely to be male (in the UK in 2014, only 13% of added memorability. The accurate belief that women are less
people working in the sciences were female, according to the likely to be scientists has the epistemic cost of distorting think-
Women In Science and Engineering campaign, WISE). There- ing about individuals to fit wider stereotypes of women. More-
fore I am more likely to have accurate beliefs if I adopt certain over, this distortion of memory is not outweighed by the increase
stereotypes; for example, if I assume a random scientist is more in remembered information. It would be better and fairer to
likely to be male than female. This has ethical implications if remember less information, but for that information to be unbi-
we want to encourage women to enter science. But as philoso- ased against the candidate.
phers seeking knowledge, is this just the price that needs to be A second epistemic cost of stereotyping is misinterpretation
paid for accurate thinking? Puddifoot argues that the best choice of ambiguous evidence. When some characteristics of an individ-
from a knowledge perspective is also best from an ethical per- ual are known and have a stereotype attached, implicit bias can
spective by demonstrating the epistemic innocence of inaccu- lead to misinterpretation of the evidence, even if the stereotype
rate thinking in some cases – for example, in thinking that sci- to some extent reflects social realities. So for example, if a female
entists are equally likely to be women. scientist makes some errors in an important presentation, this

36 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


evidence is ambiguous: it is consistent with a lack of knowledge, features may trigger a stereotype of the nurturing wife and
but also with a lack of confidence in public speaking. Yet some- mother even if they are not particularily nurturing.
one with the (accurate) belief that most scientists are male may Of course, we can work to suppress automatic bias, but this
also carry the implicit bias that scientific expertise is to be asso- takes effort that can deplete cognitive resources and therefore
ciated with men and so (perhaps inaccurately) interpret the has epistemic costs itself. Given these costs of even accurate
errors as the result of a lack of knowledge. Since the majority stereotyping, there appears to be an epistemic benefit to having
of scientists are men, the stereotypical belief does reflect social non-stereotypical beliefs that produce egalitarian responses, even
reality to an extent, but has greater epistemic costs in that this if these fail to fully reflect social realities. The strategies for avoid-
behavioural evidence is misinterpreted. ing implicit bias deserve more space than I have here, but broadly
Two further, related, epistemic costs of stereotyping are fail- speaking, either the relevant social information can be withheld
ure to notice differences between individuals and failure to notice sim- so that it cannot affect thinking, or someone can actively mis-
ilarities between members of different groups. When a stereotype is represent social reality; for example, responding as if men and
being employed, the people stereotyped are seen as group mem- women were equally represented in the sciences. Both methods
bers, and minority groups are seen as less diverse and more likely would lead to an egalitarian response, which is ethically sound,
to share characteristics than a majority group (see paper by and also avoids the epistemic costs outlined above. By actively
Bartsch & Judd in European Journal of Social Psychology 23, 1993). cultivating imperfect thinking we can avoid misremembering
So, female scientists will be seen to be more homogenous than details, misinterpreting ambiguous evidence, failing to notice
their male majority counterparts. This is costly in terms of relevant similarities or differences, failing to truth-track in terms
knowledge because it causes details about individuals, which of explanations of behaviour, and making inaccurate associa-
could affect important judgements, to go unnoticed. Addition- tions. So by shunning even generally correct stereotypes we can
ally, similarities between groups are less likely to be noticed. actually increase our chance of holding true beliefs.
For example when a scientist is a woman, any sign of lack of As in the case of delusions, for thinking that fails to accu-
commitment is spotted, but similar signs may be overlooked if rately reflect social realities to be epistemically innocent, there
displayed by her male colleagues. Once again this is an epis- must also be no alternative conferring the same epistemic ben-
temically costly omission of factual information. efits without costs. Research does show however that if people
The fourth epistemic cost identified by Puddifoot is failure are sensitive to social differences and so have beliefs that accu-
to truth-track in explanations of behaviour. When implicit bias rately represent reality, they are highly likely to engage in auto-
comes into effect, people may use the group membership of an matic stereotyping, with the costs I’ve highlighted. It appears
individual as an explanation of their behaviour if it fits the stereo- we cannot have our epistemic cake and eat it.
type, neglecting other possible explanations and relevant infor- Puddifoot argues that holding beliefs that fail to accurately
mation. In particular, an act is explained in terms of the nature represent social reality can be the lesser of two evils here. Stereo-
of the agent if the act fits the stereotype, and in terms of the sit- types that reflect at least some aspect of social reality sometimes
uation if it does not. Let us go back to the example of the female lead us to make an accurate assessment, for example that a ran-
scientist who makes mistakes in her speech. The stereotype con- domly selected scientist will probably be male. However, by
cerning scientific expertise being a male trait rather than female avoiding such stereotypes we will also avoid their pitfalls.
(whilst reflecting some aspects of social reality) means that her
errors are explained in terms of her capabilities, even if other Summary
explanations would be equally adequate, if not better. Yet when These are just two examples where imperfect or inaccurate
a male is observed to make the same errors the behaviour is beliefs have redeeming features. In the first example (delusions),
more likely to be explained through the situation – perhaps inaccurately interpreting information to fit pre-existing nega-
there was something distracting him – although in fact he may tive schemata reduces anxiety and psychological discomfort and
have simply lacked the knowledge. However, the latter expla- contributes to a coherent sense of self. In the second (stereo-
nation does not fit the stereotype of male scientific competence. types) there is sometimes more to be gained epistemically from
The fifth and final epistemic cost of stereotyping is inappro- holding beliefs that do not accurately represent social reality.
priate associations and cognitive depletion. The epistemic benefit And so, in the absence of equally effective alternatives at no
of stereotyping is that assumptions are made that accurately epistemic cost, both cases are said to be epistemically innocent.
reflect social reality. However when people stereotype they The research at Project PERFECT has important philo-
often make a host of other associations that do not reflect social sophical implications. In a discipline where truth is revered
reality. For example, the stereotype of a scientist as male may above all else, this research forces us to reassess how we under-
be associated with the belief that males are likely to have a higher stand the relative value of truth and falsity. But there are also
IQ than females, which is not true. Or the belief that females implications for how we understand mental health, forcing us
take on a more nurturing role in the family and society (which to reassess the culturally-constructed boundaries between
reflects what often happens in society) may be conflated with normal and abnormal, or healthy and unhealthy, thinking.
the belief that they are disposed to be more nurturing (which © SALLY LATHAM 2018
arguably is not accurate). We may form bias based on superfi- Sally Latham is a Philosophy lecturer at Birmingham Metropolitan
cial features that reflect a stereotype even when the majority of College.
features of that individual do not conform to that stereotype.
For example a female with typically feminine facial and bodily • For more on Project PERFECT, please visit http://projectperfect.eu

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 37


Brief Lives
Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679)
Alistair MacFarlane considers the long and thoughtful life of Thomas Hobbes.

T
homas Hobbes was one of those very rare people who arship. He returned to Chatsworth determined to become a
had a fundamental insight into what would come to major savant. During the next eighteen years he worked diligently
dominate life centuries after their death. His insight in pursuit of this goal, but produced little except a translation of
was into human agency, the capacity to use information Thucydides’ History of the Peloponnesian War, published in 1629.
to control action. Hobbes had seen that groups of people working When William Cavendish died in 1628, Hobbes accepted a
with shared information to a common purpose could generate position of tutor to the son of Sir Gervase Clinton, and remained
shared agency. He thus conceived the amazing idea of artificial peo- with the family for the next three years, two of which were spent in
ple. In Hobbes’ day this was a way of looking at large socioeconomic continental Europe. Here Hobbes developed an interest in geom-
entities such as governments and their armies. Nowadays we can etry and mathematics. This so reinvigorated his interest in philos-
look at large globally distributed and coordinated transnational ophy that from this time on it dominated his life. In 1631 Hobbes
companies in the same way. These are now widespread, exercising returned to the Cavendish household as tutor to the new Earl and
a dominant effect on all our lives. made his third visit abroad. On this visit he met Galileo in Florence
Hobbes called such a composite entity ‘Leviathan’, taking the and the circle of philosophers associated with Mersenne in Paris.
name from a mythological sea monster. In what follows it will be He also met, and severely disagreed with, Descartes.
used as a generic term for any form of large, coherent, purposive As the struggle between king and parliament began to spiral
and organised group of people. In a stroke of artistic genius the into the English Civil War (which occurred between 1642 and
original cover illustration for Hobbes’ famous book of that name 1649), in 1640 Hobbes prepared a pamphlet, Elements of Law, to
showed a giant picture of the King towering over his realm, that brief his aristocratic employers on the escalating conflict of inter-
on close inspection, turns out to be made up from lots of little ests. This was widely circulated among Royalists and greatly
people. Like real people, such Leviathans are born and die, pros- resented by Parliamentarians. Sensing the way the wind was
per or struggle, collaborate or fight, and are driven by a variety of blowing (against the aristocracy), fearful for his personal safety,
purposes, not all of which benefit the multitude of real people of and having accumulated sufficient savings for the purpose,
whom they are composed. It is an idea at once commonplace yet Hobbes fled to France, where he spent the next eleven years.
of almost unimaginable significance for our future. Hobbes, a There he wrote and in 1642 published De Cive (On The Citizen),
man whose life was dominated by fear of war and civil strife, had an exposition of his political philosophy.
seen something truly fearsome. Hobbes had gone to Paris because he saw it as a city of philoso-
phers, but a growing lack of funds persuaded him in 1645 to
Life accept a position as tutor to the exiled Prince of Wales, who had
Thomas Hobbes was born on 15 April 1588 in Malmesbury, also fled there after his father’s execution. But Hobbes steadfastly
Wiltshire. He was plagued by fear throughout his life, and joked continued his philosophy, and in 1651 published his masterpiece
that his mother fell into labour on hearing that the Spanish Leviathan. He presented a specially bound copy to his former
Armada was on its way, “so that fear and I were born twins pupil. It was to prove a shrewd investment. The Earl of Devon-
together.” His father, a poor clergyman, became an alcoholic and shire had made his peace with the new Cromwell government by
abandoned his three children to the care of his brother, who was paying a large lump sum for the return of land that had been con-
a well-to-do glover. There is no record of the identity of his fiscated as a penalty for supporting the former king.
mother. Luckily, Thomas and his elder brother and younger sis- Leviathan had given Hobbes a European-wide reputation, so
ter were well cared-for. after careful soundings among members of the new government
It soon became clear that Thomas was an exceptionally gifted who admired his work, he decided to take the risk of rejoining the
boy. He showed an outstanding ability in Latin and Greek, and Cavendish household in 1657. Although Hobbes had supported
proceeded to Oxford where, at Magdalen Hall (which later the king before the war, he had also denied the divine right of
became Hertford College) over a period of five years he thor- kings. By this argument, anyone in principle, and in particular the
oughly mastered classical literature. commoner Oliver Cromwell, could sit at the pinnacle of a
At the time aristocratic families were constantly on the look- Leviathan state.
out for promising tutors for their children, and in 1608 Hobbes Keeping an appropriately low political profile, Hobbes was
was appointed tutor to the son of William Cavendish, first Earl able to enjoy a relatively untroubled life under Cromwell’s Pro-
of Devonshire. Hobbes later became his secretary, and main- tectorate. He resumed work on his system of philosophy, pub-
tained a close relationship with the Cavendish family for most of lished De Corpore (On The Body) in 1655 and De Homine (On Man)
his life. As a member of their household he spent many years at in 1658. Hobbes’ remaining years were ones of incessant activity
Chatsworth, their country estate, or in London, meeting most of and of literary, mathematical and philosophical controversy.
the leading politicians and literary figures of his day. In 1610, After the Restoration, Hobbes’ former pupil, now Charles II,
Hobbes toured France and Italy with his pupil (also called invited him to Court and granted him a pension. From then on,
William), gaining a good insight into a life of intellect and schol- Hobbes spent most of his time in London. He finally withdrew

38 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


Thomas Hobbes
by Gail Campbell
2018

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 39


Brief Lives
from worldly affairs in 1675 and retired to Chatsworth. Hobbes artificial person transcends the individuals who may play it. Sim-
died in Hardwick Hall on December 4, 1679 at the age of 92, and ilarily, groups of people create contracts to create super-groups
was buried in St John the Baptist’s Church cemetery in Ault – councils, governments, legislatures, companies… which in
Hucknall in Derbyshire. some sense, since they are created by us and composed of our like,
must function as augmented versions of us.
Leviathan In arguing why we must surrender part of our individual free-
The essence of Hobbes great insight into how society develops dom to Leviathans, Hobbes compared that outcome with its
organisational structures lies in what in a modern context we alternative:
would call ‘agency’. It is fascinating to look at his own words
about this in Leviathan: “In such condition [as before the formation of government], there is no
place for industry; because the fruit thereof is uncertain: and conse-
“For by Art is created that great Leviathan called a Common-Wealth quently no culture of the earth, nor use of the commodities that may be
or State, (in latine Civitas) which is but an Artifiiciall Man; though of imported by sea; no commodious building; no instruments of moving,
greater stature and strength than the Naturall, for whose protection and removing; no knowledge of the face of the earth; no account of time;
and defence it was intended; and in which the Soveraignty is an Artifi- no arts; no letters; no society; and which is worst of all, continual fear,
ciall Soul, as giving life and motion to the whole body; The Magistrates, and danger of violent death; and the life of man, solitary, poor, nasty,
and other Officers of Judicature and Execution artificiall Joynts [and] brutish, and short.”
Counsellors are the Memory. Lastly, [are] the Pacts and Covenants, by
which the parts of this Body Politique [are] set together.” Leviathans are the price we pay for the advantages of civilisation.

This famous passage is now of more historical than philosoph- Legacy


ical interest, and the anatomical detail pushes the metaphor past Hobbes is generally regarded as the founder of British moral and
breaking point. But the crucial, breathtakingly simple, idea political philosophy, and as one of the greatest of English
remains: Society develops by creating entities which function as philosophers. For him, moral and political philosophy were of
super-persons, with a coherent, organised ability to set goals, rea- more than academic interest. They were of huge practical impor-
son out how to achieve them, put together huge coordinated tance too, for he saw them as a means of counteracting the civil
resources, engage with each other, and exert a dominating influ- war that was the greatest of his fears. In his day, Hobbes was an
ence over their constituent members. Most people, in modern admired all-round thinker. He made important contributions to
advanced societies, lead a multiple existence. For part of their day optics, and to a materialistic explanation of human behaviour.
they are components of a Leviathan, for the remainder they seek His uncompromising endorsement of materialism aroused the
to be themselves. hostility of religious authorities of all persuasions, who were
Where did Hobbes get this idea that people in a developed enraged by his claim that if reason by itself is to be taken as a guide
society must necessarily lead a complex multiple form of exis- to action, then God is dispensable as a source of ethics. On his
tence which is more than a mere social contract between equals? return to England after the Restoration, determined attempts
One obvious possibility comes from acting in a theatre. An actor, were made to push a Bill through the House of Commons against
when acting, is indeed an artificial person created by an author. atheism, and moves were made to investigate Leviathan. Hobbes
Moreover any number of people can act the same part, so that the accordingly burned any papers that might compromise him.
Two people I have covered in ‘Brief Lives’,
Ada Lovelace (see PN 96) and Thomas Hobbes,
Frontispiece for have had startling visions of the future. Lovelace
Leviathan (1651)
foresaw the possibilities which material agency
would open up for computing, and Hobbes fore-
saw how human agents could combine to form
superhuman agencies. As both these visions are
increasingly integrated, with huge companies
combining the use of information and manufac-
turing resources on a scale that challenges gov-
ernments, the results will dominate our future.
We face a fundamental dilemma: in seeking to
make a better future, we must place our fate in
the hands of people who share our fundamental
flaws and limitations. And as Immanuel Kant
said, out of the crooked timber of humanity
nothing straight was ever made.
© SIR ALISTAIR MACFARLANE 2018
Sir Alistair MacFarlane is a former Vice-President
of the Royal Society and a retired university Vice-
Chancellor.

40 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


IMAGE BY CAROL BELANGER GRAFTON
Philosophy Then

Wittgenstein & The War


Peter Adamson says one good thing came out of WW1.

W
orld War One has a lot to the fact that Gustav Klimt had painted his Wittgenstein went on to argue that these
answer for, including World sister, and only then realized that this must basic propositions are like ‘logical pictures’
War Two – or at least that’s be one of the famous Wittgensteins. How- of reality: the logical structure of the
what I was taught in school. Paradoxically, ever, Ludwig’s family was beset by psycho- proposition is supposed to ‘show’ the logi-
given its transformative effects, I was also logical troubles: two of his brothers killed cal structure of reality. Finally, the facts
taught in school that World War One was themselves before the war, another during pictured in these simple propositions
pointless. Our image of that war is of liter- it, and Ludwig himself frequently contem- always deal with physical reality. That is to
ally entrenched soldiers perishing in plated suicide. But the Wittgensteins were say, they express things we can learn
droves as the battle lines refuse to budge. also a prodigiously talented family, espe- empirically, in other words by going out
Yet at least one worthwhile thing did cially musically. His brother Paul lost his into the world and looking around it, or
emerge from this tragic conflict: Ludwig arm in the war, but was still able to pursue more ambitiously, by engaging in natural
Wittgenstein’s first book, the Tractatus a concert career playing pieces written for science. As Wittgenstein admitted
Logico-Philosophicus, which was composed the left hand alone. As for Ludwig, he went towards the end of the Tractatus, this
during the war while its author was serving abroad to study engineering in Manch- means that the most important things in
in the Austrian army and then detained as ester, but his interest in mathematics led life – abstractions such as morality and
a prisoner of war in Italy. him to Cambridge in 1911. beauty – cannot be shown in language.
Wittgenstein was one of the many Wittgenstein went to Cambridge on From his beginning the Tractatus’s philo-
Europeans who greeted the outbreak of the advice of Gottlob Frege, and once sophical project in technical issues about
war with excitement as well as trepidation. there he met Bertrand Russell. Frege and logic and language, Wittgenstein ends it in
He wrote in one of the notebooks he kept Russell were themselves great philoso- a kind of mysticism, dismissing the theory
during the war that “only death gives life phers, both engaged in ambitious projects of the Tractatus itself as a ladder that must
its meaning.” Accordingly, he welcomed devoted to the relationship between math- be thrown away once one has climbed up
the opportunity to look death in the face. ematics and logic. Wittgenstein at first it. The book finishes with the famous line,
He voluntarily enlisted in his native coun- impressed Russell, then began to argue “That whereof one cannot speak, thereof
try’s armed forces in 1914, but it was only with him, and finally went on to surpass one must remain silent.”
after two years as a soldier that Wittgen- him, producing new ideas about logic, lan- Did the First World War influence the
stein would see front line service. He vol- guage, and philosophy more generally. ideas of the Tractatus? A positive answer to
unteered for the most dangerous possible Wittgenstein concluded with despair that that question is given by Ray Monk, the
duty: being stationed at an observation Russell would never grasp what he was author of an entertaining and philosophi-
post at the front edge of the Austrian line trying to say. His wartime notebooks and cally rich biography of Wittgenstein. He
in no man’s land, with shells crashing correspondence with Russell and others points out that wartime experience seems
around him through the night. In his note- constantly lament that even if he should to have pushed Wittgenstein to broaden
books he chastized himself for the terror survive the war and manage to publish the his philosophical interests beyond mathe-
he felt: to fear death comes from a “false theories that would eventually be set down matics, logic, and language, to the whole
view of life.” in the Tractatus, his work might still come range of topics traditionally studied by
Whatever fear he felt within, his out- to nothing, since no one would be able to philosophy. As Monk puts it, “if Wittgen-
ward conduct could not have been more grasp its importance. stein had spent the entire war behind the
courageous. He was awarded several Given that even Frege and Russell had a lines, the Tractatus would have remained
medals and promoted to the officer class hard time getting Wittgenstein’s ideas what it almost certainly was in its first
by the end of the war. At the end of 1918 straight, I don’t have much hope of inception of 1915: a treatise on the nature
he was captured and placed in Italian pris- explaining them in this short space, but of logic.” It’s somehow appropriate that a
oner of war camps until the summer of here’s a taste of the sort of thing he wanted war that has so often been deemed mean-
1919. Here he wrote about philosophy, as to say. In the Tractatus, he argued that if we ingless pushed Wittgenstein to write a
he had done during lulls in military action. analyze our everyday language we discover philosophical work that rigorously defines
The result was the Tractatus. underpinning it a set of propositions that the very boundary between what does, and
Wittgenstein grew up in Vienna, the describe reality. The simplest proposi- does not, have meaning.
son of a fabulously wealthy steel magnate. tions express what Wittgenstein called © PROF. PETER ADAMSON 2018
To give you some idea of the circles in ‘facts’: for instance, the proposition ‘the Peter Adamson is the author of A History of
which his family moved, while he was at giraffe is tall’ just represents the fact that Philosophy Without Any Gaps, Vols 1, 2
the prisoner-of-war camp a fellow the giraffe is tall. Departing from Russell’s & 3, available from OUP. They’re based on his
detainee heard Ludwig refer casually to ideas of how propositions like this work, popular History of Philosophy podcast.

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 41


Street Philosopher
Torpid In A Taxi
Seán Moran contemplates a comatose cabbie.

O
f the crowds passing the dozing necessary privation of our positive state of reasons, the situation is worse for teenagers
Mumbai driver in my photo- wakefulness. He believed that our perceptive (or ‘screenagers’), even though they need
graph, not one person was faculty cannot withstand continuous stimu- more sleep than adults.
tempted to tickle his feet. It was lation, hence the need for hypnos (sleep) to
only right that they resisted the urge, for he allow this over-stimulated faculty to recu- Waking Duty
deserved a rest from his labours. Driving a perate from fatigue and recover its normal Disturbing our sleep patterns impairs the
taxi in the Indian city formerly known as function. After an excess of being awake we balanced Good Life described in Aristotle’s
Bombay is one job that demands an alert, need to be unawake for a while to restore the virtue ethics, but it has implications for
well-rested person. When I’m a passenger balance. Aristotle thus regarded sleep as deontological – rule-based – ethics, too.
there, I often shut my own eyes and hope having the biological ‘final cause’ or purpose These are the ethics of duty, and it’s some-
that the taxiwallah keeps his eyes wide open of preserving the organism, because of its times a person’s duty to be fully awake. Swal-
as he forces his cab through the anarchy. restorative function. This is unlike supernat- lows may be able to fly while asleep, but we
When philosophers take an interest in ural explanations of sleep, such as that of are unhappy when airline pilots attempt this
sleep, it is usually from an epistemological Pythagoras, for whom dreams conveyed feat. Even when we are technically awake,
standpoint, meaning from a concern with messages from the gods. Present day biolo- our alertness levels can vary. When we are
what knowledge is and how we might acquire gists would object to Aristotle’s principle of sleep-deprived, our cognitive functioning
it. So they ask if dreams can tell us something a ‘final cause’ though: teleological (purpose- suffers. Poor judgement caused by fatigue
(as Pythagoras, Freud, and Jung believed), or ful, goal-seeking) explanations for physical has been blamed for nuclear incidents at
whether we can’t be sure that we’re not phenomena are currently out of favour in Three Mile Island in the USA and Cher-
dreaming now (as Descartes argued). But scientific circles. nobyl in the former USSR, and the Exxon
they don’t often consider another aspect of Our taxi driver’s perceptive faculties Valdez oil spillage off the coast of Alaska.
sleep: its ethical implications. would almost certainly be over-excited after Hospital doctors routinely make life-or-
weaving through the chaotic Mumbai traf- death decisions when sleep-deprived. In
A Good Sleep fic. But the rest of us similarly endure exces- their bleary-eyed state, a misplaced decimal
The American National Sleep Foundation sive stimulation before bedtime, though point on a dosage instruction is in danger of
recommends between seven and nine hours freely chosen. More and more people are putting their patient into a permanent sleep.
of sleep for adults per day, and the saying using personal electronic devices with Philosophers are affected too. Socrates
‘Early to bed and early to rise keeps a man screens as ways of winding down at the end often stayed up all night trying to solve
healthy, wealthy and wise’ hints that sleep is of the day. It’s the contemporary version of philosophical puzzles, and was rather fond of
a significant part of The Good Life. Both reading a book or listening to the radio late-night drunken carousing too. Perhaps
our physical and mental health depend on before dropping off. Except that it doesn’t this sort of carry-on affected his judgement
sleep. This is borne out by recent studies always work. The blue component of the when he was in court on the trumped-up
showing that a lack of sleep can be respon- light from the screen stimulates what Aris- charges of impiety and corrupting the youth
sible for a range of ills, including heart totle called our ‘perceptive faculties’. Blue of Athens. When he was found guilty (after
disease and depression; and 2017 research by light is detected by special cells in the retina unwisely refusing to play the legal game), he
Oxford Economics and the UK National that trigger activity in the prefrontal and was invited to propose a suitable punish-
Centre for Social Research reveals that thalamic regions of the brain – the structures ment, such as exile from Athens. Instead he
adequate sleep is a more important factor in that regulate alertness and cognitive perfor- suggested that he be given free meals for life,
human happiness than household income. mance. The phenomenon is a powerful one: so the court condemned him to death for his
That sleep trumps wealth in the happiness blue light can even jolt people who are totally cheek. Perhaps if he’d had a few good nights’
stakes is a remarkable finding; but it seems blind into an alert state. This response has sleep, he might have been more circumspect
it would take a very large increase in salary an evolutionary origin, because locking our in court. On the other hand, Socrates was
to compensate for the loss of sleep that a new sleep/wake cycles into phase with useful such an independent-minded curmudgeon
job might involve. So if you are healthy and daylight hours has a survival value. Screens that even a night or two in the arms of
wise thanks to sleeping well, it seems there’s disrupt these natural circadian rhythms by Morpheus would probably have made no
no need to be wealthy too. triggering certain brain areas while difference. (In Greek mythology Morpheus,
Aristotle considered The Good Life to be suppressing the melatonin secretion that the winged god of dreams, was a son of
a well-balanced life. To him the flourishing would encourage sleep. The interactive Hypnos, the god of sleep.)
life is one that avoids extremes of both defi- demands of the devices intensify the effect; Prussian philosopher Immanuel Kant
ciency and excess. So the notion that six so replying to emails, responding to social said that he had been roused from his
hours’ sleep is not enough but ten hours’ is media postings, or playing a game further ‘dogmatic slumber’ over various philosoph-
too much fits nicely with his principle of a amplifies our state of perceptual arousal ical issues by the Scottish Enlightenment
‘happy medium’. sparked off by the blue light. We are not thinker David Hume. Kant wrote his
Aristotle saw sleep as a temporary but ready to sleep in this state. For a variety of masterpiece A Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

42 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


© SEÁN MORAN 2018
PHOTO

Street Philosopher

in this newly awakened state, thus sending to Woke Up we can face the following day’s challenges in
sleep a fair number of future generations of In the deontological ethics advocated by a fully-awakened condition. Our rational
philosophy undergraduates, and causing Kant in his second Critique (Of Practical selves can project us forward, though. In our
insomnia in some of the remainder. This Reason, 1788), a well-established principle is sensible state earlier in the day we can take
convoluted and dense work has what French that ‘ought implies can’. Put differently, an action to counteract our future dozy state of
dramatist Molière humorously termed action can only be your duty if it is within mind. This is easier said than done.
‘dormitive powers’ in his play The Hypochon- your power to do it. So, it cannot be the case A notion, used metaphorically, has
driac (1673). Molière was talking about that you ought to negotiate personally with recently crossed over from African-American
opium, but the term has become a more North Korea over its nuclear arsenal, for urban culture to the wider internet milieu.
general way of mocking pseudo-scientific example, unless you happen to be a world You might be enjoined to “Stay woke”, or
explanations, since saying that opium puts leader. Likewise, it cannot be your duty to perhaps asked “Are you woke?” If you correct
users to sleep because of its virtus dormitiva sleep for the recommended time if this is not the questioner’s grammar and reply, “Yes, I
is simply stating that opium causes sleep something you can do. Certainly, you can am fully awakened, thank you,” then you ain’t
because of its sleep-inducing powers – a stop drinking coffee after a certain time of woke. It has come to mean being alert to
circular explanation that actually explains day, avoid interacting with electronic injustice, discrimination and privilege in
nothing. A proper explanation would involve screens near bed-time, and do whatever it society.
a story about the drug’s interaction with takes to put you in the mood for shut-eye, If we are woke we will treat the Mumbai
opioid receptors in the brain, its effects on but there are no guarantees. You might toss cabbie as an equal and let him sleep, and ques-
neurotransmitters, and so on. In Kant’s case, and turn worrying about domestic trivia, tion the oppressive structures that deprive
an explanation of his writing’s dormitive Kim Jong-un, or the posturing of our own him of a balanced Good Life. But we might
powers might point to the length of his dear leaders. Falling asleep is not entirely still want to shut our eyes when he drives us
sentences, his opaque vocabulary, and his within our conscious control. Furthermore, up a street the wrong way, blaring his horn,
nested subordinate clauses. (In case enraged because tiredness impairs our judgement, pursued by flashing blue lights.
Kantians are roused from their slumbers by this in turn blinds us to the fact that our © DR SEÁN MORAN 2018
this and plan to come after me with pitch- judgement is affected. So we are not always Seán Moran is in Waterford Institute of Tech-
forks and flaming torches, I did say that the aware of just how tired we actually are, nor nology, and is a founder of Pandisciplinary.Net,
Critique was a masterpiece.) of the desirability of getting some sleep so a global network of people, projects, and events.

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 43


Letters
When inspiration strikes, don’t bottle it up!
Email me at rick.lewis@philosophynow.org
Keep them short and keep them coming!

Prejudice & Toleration be looking for ways to disturb the politi- morally different from instrumentalizing
DEAR EDITOR: My subject is Prejudice cal and economic balance in their favour it in (other) nasty jobs such as lavatory
& Perception, which was the theme of by destroying or subjugating some one cleaning. All involve distasteful use of
Issue 123. My question is ‘What kind of or more tolerant groups. Indeed, the the body for a rational end, earning
society do we want?’ Suppose we say we only way a mixed society can continue to money. However, defining prostitution
want a consistently tolerant society. survive in mixed mode over the long precisely enables us to assess its morality
What would that look like? It would term is to provide a mechanism that better: it is not just selling sex. It is vol-
have to be something like a body politic actively promotes tolerance. This is why untarily selling sex, and sex only, to mul-
consisting of self-defined and histori- a mandatory liberal education and expo- tiple customers. A sex slave is not a pros-
cally-defined groups who by stipulation sure to a reasonably wide swathe of the titute because she is being sold, not sell-
were tolerant of every other group who world’s culture is both legitimate and ing. Guilt lies primarily with her captors
was tolerant of them. In that society logical. This in no way precludes a vari- and secondarily with customers who
everyone is tolerant of everyone else! ety of educational modes. Amish public prefer not to acknowledge her situation.
Tolerance here can be taken to mean education can be perfectly liberal while A woman who sells sex to avoid starva-
‘satisfied with having to accept [group x] still teaching that ploughing with horses tion is also not acting voluntarily. Guilt
as a part of the community’. Notice that is a better way to live! That’s a legitimate lies perhaps not with her customers,
groups like the Nazis could not exist in tolerant social and political opinion as who keep her from starving, but with we
such a society. It is intrinsic to Nazism long as it does not advocate the destruc- who live comfortably while tolerating a
that it is not tolerant of various social tion of those who plough with tractors. world where she needs to do this. The
sub-groups, and so it could not exist in MATTHEW RAPAPORT same might apply to the woman who
plain view in such a society. It would in CALIFORNIA chooses to sell sex rather than endure
fact be logically consistent to formally unhealthy drudgery for a pittance in an
outlaw such groups. Prostitution & Free Will Asian factory while we buy cheaply the
The objection that the enforcer of DEAR EDITOR: When I read Rob Lover- products of that factory. It might also
this law could use it to suppress dissent ing’s article ‘Prostitution and Instrumen- apply to the woman who can’t get any
misses its target. Political and social dis- talization’ in Issue 123 it reminded me of other job in Europe.
agreement within the bounds of toler- a claim by Stephen Fry that the male sex Jobs involving risk to the operative or
ance is easily distinguished from intoler- drive is greater than the female so there the customer are often legal and super-
ance. “Republicans are crooks and should be prostitution to accommodate vised in many Western countries; so why
should all be voted out of office” is legit- this. My former employer also said there are brothels often illegal and unsuper-
imate political opinion: “Republicans was nothing wrong with prostitution. vised? It cannot be a simple issue of con-
should be killed” or anything of that ilk, When I asked if he would be okay with servative sexual morality, because abor-
is hate speech and might be legitimately his daughter being a sex worker he didn’t tion clinics are legal and supervised. Can
and consistently outlawed. answer. While Lovering and Fry’s asser- it be to discourage people from going to
On the other side of the social divide, tions both seem factual, neither deals brothels? Yet we hardly want to encour-
a necessary outcome in an intolerant with the personal costs to sex workers, age abortion either. Or is it rather because
society is that it comes to be dominated who prostitute themselves often to feed a influential people can imagine themselves
by a single, intolerant, group (such as drug habit or are in forced prostitution or their daughters needing abortions, but
the Nazis) because a society of compet- and under threat, many under age. not being reduced to prostitution?
ing intolerant groups is inherently Lovering likely knows and agrees with ALLEN SHAW
unstable and eventually one of the this; but perhaps this is all the more rea- LEEDS
groups comes to dominate. Notice that son not to be so verbose on the philo-
this society is also logically consistent – sophical arguments for prostitution? Digital & Trivial
just not very nice to live in for most. KRISTINE KERR DEAR EDITOR: Matt Bluemink’s
In between are societies that are a mix GOUROCK, RENFREWSHIRE. thoughts in Issue 122 on Socrates and
of tolerance and intolerance. Societies the pernicious effects of the digital age
like ours. The problem with this mix is DEAR EDITOR: Rob Lovering in Issue on our diminishing attention-spans got
that it too is unstable because the intoler- 123 argues cogently that instrumentaliz- my attention. The police have had to
ant groups will, by predilection, always ing the body in prostitution is not advise those caught up in terror attacks

44 Philosophy Now l February/March 2018


Letters
not to stand around taking pictures. alone. In Plato’s images, this is a stairway direct and nonconceptual. In the ultimate
Then there’s Twitter, so felicitously to heaven that involves the rocky climb view, reality is said to be ‘empty’ of the
named, and foreseen long before out from the Cave of ignorance. Here distinction between mind and body; so
Socrates, in the Old Testament: “The there is a hierarchy of being; and in this ultimately there is no mind-body prob-
fool takes no delight in understanding, bodily world we are at the bottom. Such lem. Yet in any given context, a Buddhist
but merely in expressing his own opin- a search for the higher Forms does not teacher might present either a dualistic or
ions.” (Proverbs 18.2) Or visit any art preclude rationality, indeed it clarifies it. a monistic view – whichever will best
gallery and watch people snapping away It could then be that the purpose of help his/her listeners move closer to that
with camera-phones but not attending to Socrates’ relentless argumentation is to final, nonconceptual understanding.
the art. Without attention to art there is illuminate, often brutally expose, the PAUL VITOLS,
no love of art, only of Selfie. And what of accepted norms of everyday thought in NORTH VANCOUVER
the love of our children, or of other peo- preparation for the final spiritual trans-
ple? At the end of his philosophical formation of finding union with the Misreading Cubism
novel, The Bridge of St Luis Rey (1927), divine. DEAR EDITOR: Stuart Greenstreet in
Thornton Wilder writes that love is the Why could Socrates not be both the Issue 122 believes that Cubism, and art
only survival, the only meaning. He questioner in the public arena and the in general, is a kind of language. This
could have been echoing St Paul’s asser- spiritual midwife to his closest followers? does not fit my experience as an artist.
tion that love is patient, kind, without Why could Socrates not be the debunker Our distant ancestors painted images
envy or self-interest – attentive, in other of accepted truths and at the same time of horses on the walls of caves that we
words – and the greatest of all virtues. the advocate of an ultimate truth? immediately recognise. They also left pat-
Paul almost certainly knew of Aristotle’s TONY PITMAN terns of dots that we do not understand.
notion of the truest love being the wish BRADFORD ON AVON, WILTSHIRE Just so, Etruscan tomb figures are famil-
for the good for others – a wish that pre- iar, although we cannot read their written
supposes attention to another person’s The Buddhist Boomerang language. The difference is that the dots
soul. Love and friendship bridge the gulfs DEAR EDITOR: I enjoyed reading Lach- and the writing are messages encoded,
between us. We must not let cramped and lan Dale’s review of The Monk and the subject to Saussure’s semiological analy-
flimsy internet connections destroy real Philosopher by Jean-Francois Revel and sis. But on the contrary we need no key to
connections and create Dystopia Now. Matthieu Ricard in Issue 122. I have not read the images because they display sig-
MICHAEL MCMANUS read the book myself, but I have prac- nificant features of the actual objects. We
LEEDS ticed and studied in one tradition of need only a few features to recognise a
Tibetan Buddhism since 1987, and I horse or a face. They are arranged not by
Pull Your Socs Up wanted to raise a couple of points. convention, but by nature, by the way
DEAR EDITOR: I write with regard to the Mr Dale believes that the Buddhist things are.
topic of ‘the real Socrates’ as raised by doctrine of karma presents a problem for A drawing of a horse has four legs –
Peter Adamson and others in Issue 122. free will. I don’t think it does. As I under- count them – like the real horse. The
As far as we know Socrates wrote noth- stand it, karma is the law that brings the word ‘horse’ has no legs. A drawing, a
ing, but his admiring pupil Plato left a consequences of our actions back to us; it caricature, or a diagram picks out promi-
weighty tribute to his master in the form does not determine what those actions nent features related in the same way as
of dialogues which have Socrates as the will be. It’s like throwing a boomerang. in life. Arrange three blobs to make an
main speaker. Yet we assume that only Once we throw it, the laws of physics equilateral triangle, with two at the top,
Plato’s so-called ‘early’ dialogues repre- determine the behavior of the boomerang: and even a tiny baby will see a face. No
sent the real Socrates. Here he is repre- but where, when, or whether we throw decoding is necessary because a real face
sented as the eccentric, often annoying, that boomerang is up to us. In the same also has two blobs at the top and one
questioner in the marketplace, on a life- way, karma does not determine our lower down. This is how perception
long quest to find out the best way to actions; it merely states that their conse- works, of objects or images alike.
live. Plato’s ‘middle’ dialogues are too quences will inevitably be visited on us. Picasso was mistaken. He drew not
often assumed to be more the thought of Another issue Mr Dale raises is the what he knew but what he saw – but he
the pupil Plato than the master Socrates. problem of consciousness: are mind and drew features seen at different times and
But there is no evidence for this assump- body two things, or one? You can find from different angles, simplified and
tion. Rather (especially these days) we support for both positions within Bud- lumped together into one image. As for
seem to prefer Socrates the questioner to dhism. But there’s a deeper issue. In Bud- the legacy of Cubism, look no further
Socrates the mystic, and yet the middle dhism, ultimate knowledge is noncon- than The Simpsons.
dialogues are preoccupied with the eter- ceptual and nondual, and any conceptual TOM CHAMBERLAIN
nal world of the Forms and the progress understanding can only be conventional LONDON & MEXICO
of the philosopher from earthly desires and provisional. Science and philosophy,
and ambitions, and beliefs derived from as conceptual undertakings, can therefore Consciousness Baffles Brains
bodily sensations, towards the true and take one only so far. A complete under- DEAR EDITOR: I really enjoy getting my
lasting happiness which lies in the appre- standing of reality is the achievement of a Philosophy Now issues, in my case from
hension of knowledge by the intellect fully awakened Buddha nature, and is our little village newsagent near Perth,

February/March 2018 l Philosophy Now 45


Letters
Western Australia. The articles generally which proposes that there is a high likeli- be said to be creative. We have thus
baffle my brain, which is why I keep buy- hood that all of reality is a computer sim- arrived at Spinoza’s substance that is self-
ing it. ulation. caused and boundless, all-encompassing,
The consciousness issue (Issue 121) The computer simulation hypothesis all-creative, and unique.
confused me completely as I’m not a relies on the idea that what we experi- ZORAN VUKADINOVIC
philosopher. But I am an experiencer. I’m ence as real could be modelled by a com- DENVER, COLORADO
missing the point of those articles as they puter, which means that it is formally
didn’t once mention how I experience mathematically describable. Moreover, if Finding Refuge
consciousness. reality is formally describable, it is also in DEAR EDITOR: I was struck by Jacques
I’ve found I cannot separate con- principle knowable. Therefore we can Derrida’s views on hospitality and immi-
sciousness from my attention: I become evaluate the computer simulation gration, described in the article about
conscious of whatever when I give my hypothesis by means of what we know him in Issue 123. He believed – as the
attention to it. I understand there are about formal systems. author of the article also did – that when
different degrees of attention, but even Kurt Gödel (1906-1978) proved that “refugees fleeing from persecutors find
so I still think consciousness is still con- all formally describable systems are their way through an opening, it cannot
nected to attention. To me that’s what incomplete. In other words, all formal be equally open to those pursuing them.”
was missing – but maybe I’m missing the systems require an outside perspective This called for a highly selective border.
point of the various theories. for their consistency or truth. This in However, in most cases the reason that
The mosquitos in Perth not only give itself is not a problem for a proponent of people flee to the place that they have
me their conscious attention from their the simulation hypothesis, because the fled to is exactly that their persecutors
spot on our bedroom wall after their ‘outside perspective’ can be provided by would not dare to follow them. For
bite/flight response: they even seem to a deceiving entity. However, the deceiv- example refugees flee to Europe because
be consciously aware of my intention ing entity itself has to be a part of a real- once inside it they are protected by
when I approach them with my PN mag- ity, which is itself either formally NATO, a force with which no such petty
azine, loosely dangling in my hand, describable or not. If not, the question is, power would attempt to reckon on their
ready to swat. Mysteriously they disap- why not? If it is, then the deceiver’s real- own turf. This therefore makes the mus-
pear into the shadows, maybe silently ity likewise also has outside require- ing in question irrelevant as petty attack-
laughing at my frustrated searching as to ments. So a simulation hypothesis has to ers would never venture to the borders of
what their level of consciousness is. admit that either: (1) Reality is not superpowers and therefore never need to
PAUL BERGIN modellable in its totality – which would have borders closed off to them. The one
PERTH, WESTERN AUSTRALIA itself mean that there is an inherent limit case in which this reasoning breaks down
to possible deception, and to the skep- is when the attacker itself is a super-
Experiencing Disagreement tic’s skepticism; or (2) There is no limit power, luckily this – mostly – isn’t a
DEAR EDITOR:Dr Steve Brewer (Letters, on deception and every conceivable real- problem at present.
Issue 123) expounded on experientialism ity can be simulated by a computer. If HENRY O’REGAN
as being his preferred explanation of endorsing (1), one needs to explain why ST ALBANS
consciousness: “In panexperientalism, a some realities are modellable while oth-
fleeting experience is generated when- ers are not. If endorsing (2), then the The Real Ethical Questions
ever physical systems exchange energy- question is, what’s left over from a union DEAR EDITOR: On the news page of
information, since they’re equivalent.'” of all computer simulations (even if there Issue 123 the first section, ‘Merger 1:
Where is the evidence that they are is an infinity of them), as Gödel’s incom- Human Brains and Animals’ highlights
equivalent? And are they identical too or pleteness theorems tell us that all (collec- some ethical questions, but misses the
is this a case of supposed cause and tions of) formal systems require an out- big one: Is it ethically permissible to use
effect? This quoted statement has the side? I want to argue that what is left animals as objects, as a means to an end,
appearance of dogma. I would like to call over is an entity that’s real and yet not in our experiments? I am personally the
Raymond Tallis to the rescue. It looks formally or independently knowable. beneficiary of such research into mental
like a case of neuromania. This means that it is conceivable only functioning and malfunctioning, but still
PAMELA WHITE through itself. But even as such, this it leaves me uneasy that experimenting
NOTTINGHAM unknowable yet inescapable portion of on other animals is done to our benefit.
reality has to have a reason for its exis- Just because they are not ‘one of us’ does
Spinozist Anti-Simulation Argument tence. This reason, however, cannot be not seem a good enough reason, espe-
DEAR EDITOR: In Issue 121, Peter outside of it, because it is not indepen- cially when we consider that experiments
Adamson gave us a history of philosoph- dently knowable. Therefore, the reason have been done on humans whenever
ical skepticism and remarked that its for its existence must be within it: in those humans were re-classified as ‘sub-
diversity does not permit us to meet it other words, it must be self-caused. human’. When we treat animals as less
with a unified response. This is a sound Moreover, because all realities, simulated important than ourselves, it seems that
conclusion. Here, I want to attempt to or not, ultimately depend on this entity, we lose sight of something important.
provide a response to the contemporary they are all related to it, and it in turn PETER DAY
version of philosophical skepticism interrelates all of them. Thereby, it can SILVER SPRING, MARYLAND

46 Philosophy Now l February/March 2018


JERRY FODOR PHOTO © PEALCO 2007
JERRY FODOR
(1935 – 2017)

J
Daniel Hutto says goodbye to a memorable
philosophical sparring partner.

erry Fodor was forever forecasting and combating a Fodor’s true and indelible intellectual legacy. Even those like
doom-and-gloom return to what he regarded as the dark myself who defend the opposite view, and lament the restoration
days of behaviourism in the philosophy of mind. Yet he and rise of mentalism cannot fail to acknowledge the great debt
never mentioned the darkness that would befall philoso- philosophy of mind owes Fodor in this regard. Fodor was a
phy at his own demise, from the loss of his systematic exploration formidable philosophical force and his influence will continue to
and defence of controversial lines of argument, his inexhaustible be felt in times to come.
intellectual energy, and his playful wit. Sadly, that day has come. For those not embroiled in these debates, no doubt Jerry
A prominent theme in his many obituaries has been to Fodor will be remembered for his cheeky – indeed, tongue-in-
acknowledge Fodor’s virtue as an unflagging philosophical cheeky – writing style more than for his substantive philosophical
opponent. He was the perfect, utterly resilient, sparring partner. theories. He had a wonderfully irreverent way of concisely setting
One could always and absolutely count on him to put forward issues on a larger canvas by introducing us to a cast of characters:
the strongest argument for the position he advanced without Auntie, Granny, Greycat, Snark, and others. His work is a wel-
quibble or qualification. Comparing him to a trampoline, Daniel come relief from more sober and serious styles of doing philoso-
Dennett spoke of our being able to see further by “jumping on phy. Although not everyone is a fan of his playful way of writing,
Jerry.” Ruth Millikan once compared him to Mister Toad in I for one wholly applaud it, as protection against taking ourselves
Wind in the Willows, observing that he blithely crashed one too seriously, and because it allows no room for arguing from
theory after another, only to rush off to the next with equal authority. His style also allows us to focus quickly and firmly on
enthusiasm and a cavalier shout of “Poop-poop!” what really matters. Rob Rupert put it well in a review, noting that
His penchant for playful adventure and dogged, serious com- “these devices allow Fodor to get at the meat of issues without the
mitment to working out a systematic philosophical position – a circuitous ado.”
revived rationalism – speaks from the pages of his many, many Fodor was generous in responding to argument, and could be
books. The constant, enduring theme of Fodor’s writings is a tough with his opponents. At the end of a prolonged exchange I
defence of mentalism (the idea that mental states are real and had with him once about the origins of intentional psychology,
causally efficacious) against the threat of behaviourism and prag- he wrote “I’ll bet a nickel (maybe even a dime; what the hell) that,
matism. Fodor is forever resisting the philosophical approaches if you assume that [children] don’t start with [an intentional psy-
of Gilbert Ryle and Ludwig Wittgenstein, root and branch. As a chology], any attempt to explain how they might acquire one
founding father and champion of the cognitive science revolu- would find itself up to its ears in circularities.” But he was equally
tion, Fodor first advanced the case for mentalism in 1968 with willing to apply the same standards to his own work, and to go
his ground-breaking Psychological Explanation. In his final effort, wherever an argument took him. This is classic Fodor, on repre-
Minds Without Meaning, co-authored with Zenon Pylyshyn in sentational theories of mind (RTM); a view he long defended:
2015, he still expresses his commitment to that vision, though
now cast in a new format. “This begins to seem a little worrying. It is perhaps tolerable that rep-
Today many philosophers and cognitive scientists depart resentational theories of mind should lead by plausible arguments to
from specific details of the various ways Fodor fleshed out men- quite a radical nativism. But it is surely not tolerable that they should
talism over the years. They may baulk at his commitment to lead by plausible arguments to a contradiction… the conclusion has to
nativism (the view that cognitive mechanisms and concepts are be that there aren’t any primitive concepts. But if there aren’t any prim-
innate); or to the idea that thinking takes place in a ‘language of itive concepts, then there aren’t any concepts at all. And if there aren’t
thought’; or to there being specialized, self-contained mental any concepts [at] all, RTM has gone West. Isn’t it a bit late in the day
modules. Nevertheless, in many cases, those departures are only (and late in the book [p.132 of 174]) for me to take back RTM? Help!”
as clearly defined as they are thanks to the comparisons that can Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. OUP (1998)
be made with Fodor’s proposals. More fundamentally, but less
obviously, Fodor succeeded in his efforts to help revive mental- Whatever we think of his views or of the famous Fodor flair
ism and establish it as the now-default mainstream position in and flourish, we should all seek to emulate his intellectual open-
analytic philosophy of mind and cognitive science. His systematic ness and honesty. He will be sorely missed, but never forgotten.
campaign of providing a series of sustained, unremitting argu- © PROFESSOR DANIEL D. HUTTO 2018
ments in favour of the idea that behind-the-scenes mental causes Daniel Hutto is Professor of Philosophical Psychology at the University
of some kind best explain intelligent behaviour is, without doubt, of Wollongong.

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 47


Heather Dyke passes time reading about a denial of
the passing of time, Richard Baron tracks what Trolley

Books Problems can tell us about ethics, and Trevor Pateman


looks at problems with anger and forgiveness.

Experiencing Time (and opinionated) defence of his position. One way of grasping the distinction
by Simon Prosser Prosser carefully explains unfamiliar terms between the A-theory and the B-theory of
and issues as they arise, making this an excel- time is to imagine a sequence of events and
IF THERE’S ONE THING WE lent introduction to issues in both the philos- to think about how that sequence of events
can all be sure about when ophy of time and the philosophy of mind for occupies time. So, imagine the entire history
contemplating the nature the general philosophical reader. of the universe, stretching from the Big Bang
of time, it’s that time Chapter 1 begins by outlining the central through the formation of our Solar System,
passes, right? Whether we’re busily engaged debate in the philosophy of time. Taking through prehistoric times, recent events,
in daily tasks, quietly absorbed in a book, their name from the philosophy of time of events going on right now, on into the
watching a sunset, remembering an John McTaggart, ‘A-theorists’ believe that unknown future. One way of thinking about
awkward encounter, or looking forward to a time as it is in itself, and not merely as it this series is to think of each event as located
holiday, our experience tells us that time seems to us, includes a distinction between in either the past, present or future, recog-
flows. We approach the future, leaving the past, present and future. Furthermore, what nising that they can be further ordered in
past behind us, always occupying the is past, present, and future is constantly terms of whether they’re in the distant past,
present, although the present is constantly changing, because time is dynamic. near past, present, near future, or distant
changing. This, we feel sure, is the nature of However, Prosser is a ‘B-theorist’, so he future. This is how the A-theorist thinks that
our temporal experience; and on the basis of rejects both of these claims. He thinks that events occupy time. But we can also think of
this experience we infer that these descrip- there is no objective distinction between the very same sequence of events as standing
tions correctly describe the nature of tempo- past, present and future, and that time is not in temporal relations to each other. Every
ral reality. That is, we take our experience as dynamic. Instead, events and moments in event in that sequence is either earlier than,
of time flowing to be veridical – we have no time are related to each other by the tempo- later than, or simultaneous with every other
reason to think we’re being deceived – so we ral relations of precedence, subsequence, event. When we order the sequence of
conclude that time really does flow. and simultaneity. B-theorists don’t deny that events in this way, this series presents no
Simon Prosser, a lecturer in philosophy at things change, but for them, change is the distinction between past, present and future,
St Andrews University, rejects this conclu- variation in properties over time, which and especially no privileged present.
sion. He thinks that time doesn’t pass, or flow. independent of our perception of it doesn’t Furthermore, there is nothing dynamic
So what does Prosser think is wrong with flow, but rather exists. Neither do B-theo- about this series; it is a static series: it eter-
this argument? He doesn’t deny that we have rists deny that we all recognise a distinction nally exists. This is how the B-theorist thinks
experiences as of the passage of time, but he between past, present and future; but they events occupy time.
does deny that the only, or even the best, think that this says more about us and our Notice however that when considering
explanation for this is that time really does perspective on time than it does about these two different ways of ordering events
flow. Experiencing Time (2016) is an extended temporal reality itself. in time, we’re imagining the very same
sequence of events. Whether we think of it
as an A-series or a B-series, the entire history
of the universe contains the very same phys-
ical events in the very same order. Prosser
uses this fact to develop his ingenious argu-
ment that we couldn’t experience time pass-
ing even if time really did pass. The argu-
ment comes in two versions: the detector
argument, and the multi-detector argument.
I will focus here on the detector argument,
which “shows that experience fails to favour
the A-theory over the B-theory; the multi-
detector argument shows that the passage of
time cannot be experienced at all” (p.33).
The detector argument asks whether
there could be “a physical device that could
detect whether or not time was passing, and
thus tell us whether or not the A-theory was
true.” (p.33) Perhaps a light would illuminate
when the device detected the passage of time.
But recall that the A-series and the B-series

48 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018 Book Reviews


Books
contain the very same physical events in the
very same order. It follows that if the light on
the detector illuminates at all, it will illumi-
nate in both A-series and B-series time. So no
physical device could detect the A-series’
passage of time. Prosser further argues that,
on any acceptable view of the relation
between mind and body, “if no physical

WATCH INSIDE © MARTELL 2007


system can detect the passage of time, then
neither can the human mind” (p.35).
Prosser spends Chapter 2 motivating,
developing, and defending his detector and
multi-detector arguments. His aim is to
undermine the A-theory which, he claims,
relies almost entirely on the fact that experi-
ence seems to tell us that time flows. But if
his detector arguments are successful, then
the passage of time cannot possibly be expe-
rienced. This arguably deals quite a blow to
the A-theory, although it is still open to A-
theorists to deny that experience is their prin-
ciple motivation. Indeed many A-theorists
appeal not to the nature of temporal experi-
ence, but rather to the fact that their view best
articulates commonsense beliefs about time.
(See for example, T.M. Crisp, ‘Presentism’, theory/B-theory debate. Prosser develops a future is approaching us, and secondly the
in The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, 2003; “dynamic snapshot theory” (p.123) of sense that the future is open – that it is as-
N. Markosian, ‘A Defense of Presentism’, temporal experience, which stands in oppo- yet undetermined. He suggests that there
Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 1(3), 2004; D.W. sition to the traditionally more dominant are features in common between the
Zimmerman, ‘The Privileged Present: view that our experience is contained in a ‘approach’ of a future event, and the
Defending an “A-theory”of Time’ in ‘specious present’ – that is, a short but approach of a moving physical object, and
Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics, 2008.) finitely extended temporal duration. that these common features may help
Having dealt what he takes to be a mortal In Chapter 6 Prosser asks, if time is not “explain why we use so many motion-related
blow to the A-theory, in the rest of the book dynamic, why do we seem to experience metaphors when talking about time” (p.xi)
Prosser turns to developing B-theory expla- change as dynamic? His answer is that expe- without these being anything more than
nations for various elements of our experi- rience misleadingly presents objects as metaphors. He explains the apparent open-
ence that would otherwise seem to favour the enduring through change, that is, as existing ness of the future in terms of the perspective
A-theory. In Chapter 3 he discusses why we wholly and completely while undergoing from which we experience the world.
think of events as past, present and future, and changes in properties. Instead of the whole Experiencing Time is a provocative, engag-
why our attitudes and emotional responses to object enduring through change in this way, ing and yet accessible exploration of the
events vary depending on whether those Prosser thinks objects are temporally many different elements of our temporal
events are past, present, or future. We all extended entities, having different temporal experience, while at the same time being a
recognise that we would feel very differently parts that possess different properties at stalwart defence of the B-theory of time.
about a painful trip to the dentist if it was different times. He says that they perdure. Prosser does a sterling job of attempting to
future rather than past, for example. In Chap- On the endurance view, a ripening tomato reconcile his preferred theory of time with
ter 4 he develops a B-theoretic account of the is a three-spatial-dimensional entity that the many features of our temporal experi-
fact that we experience events and processes exists wholly and completely at all the times ence that apparently conflict with it. He
as taking place at different rates, and as having it exists, and at earlier times it possesses the draws not just on work in metaphysics and
duration. He also gives an account of the property of being green, while at later times the philosophy of mind but also on recent
widely reported phenomenon that under the very same tomato possesses the property empirical work in psychology and cognitive
certain circumstances, time can seem to speed of being red. On the perdurance view, a science. This is a must-read for anyone
up or slow down. For example, people often ripening tomato is a temporally extended interested in the philosophy of time and the
report that time seems to slow down in a crit- four-spacetime-dimensional entity that has psychology of temporal experience.
ical situation, such as a car crash. earlier green parts and later red parts. © DR HEATHER DYKE 2018
Chapter 5 examines the question of Finally, in Chapter 7, Prosser discusses Heather Dyke has taught philosophy at Otago,
whether experience is temporally extended. two further features of our temporal experi- NZ and at the London School of Economics.
Unlike the other elements of temporal expe- ence that he believes contribute to our sense
rience Prosser discusses, this discussion that time passes. These are firstly the sense • Experiencing Time, by Simon Prosser, Oxford UP
seems largely independent of the A- that we are moving through time, or that the 2016, 240 pages, £40 hb, ISBN: 0198748949

Book Reviews February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 49


Books
turned the trolley, or refused to turn it, or acknowledges that it has its own difficulties.
The Trolley Problem
did or failed to do something equally signif- She probes some of them by considering
Mysteries
icant. In the second lecture, she concentrates examples, such as ones in which the diverted
by F. M. Kamm
on how the trolley was (or would have been) trolley not only kills one person but also
A RUNAWAY TROLLEY IS turned. Her goal is not to find out who did blocks a runaway tractor which presents an
coming up to a switch (or in what: we know that. Rather, she wants to additional threat to the five. And in the
British English, a tram is establish the scope and limits of a general second part of the book, the other philoso-
coming up to a set of points). If nothing is principle that explains why we don’t simply, phers raise specific doubts about her princi-
done, it will carry straight on and kill five and every time, want to minimize the ple. But there is also a wider concern to be
people who are working on the track. If you number of early deaths. For example, we do addressed. Can philosophical distinctions
switch the trolley to the right, they will be not accept the idea of kidnapping a healthy between results and means to their achieve-
saved but one person who is on the other person outside a hospital in order to harvest ment, and between different shapes of causal
track will be killed. What should you do? their organs to save five people in need of chain, tell us how to think about matters of
Trolley problems have been with us since various transplants. And we might accept life and death? The potential victims might
the 1970s. They continue to fascinate, people’s acting to save themselves, even if not think so. This comes out clearly in
mainly because of the scope they offer to their actions would kill more people than Kamm’s discussion of their perspective,
vary the details in the effort to discover an would be saved. where she remarks that they may permissibly
underlying rationale for our ethical deci- Although Kamm’s goal is not the same as resist actions of the fair-minded philosopher
sions. Many people would switch the course the detective’s, her focus on who turned the which determine who is to die.
of the trolley. If they are asked to justify this trolley and then on how the trolley was Another limit on the power of subtle inves-
choice, they may say that it is not as bad to turned makes perfect sense. One might tigations of the type that Kamm pursues
have only one person killed as having five expect a good deal to depend on details of comes out in the second part of the book.
killed. But if you take away the switch and the causal chain that leads to whichever Thomson wonders where all the elaborate
instead let them save the five by pushing one deaths occur. Did anyone who took action examples really lead (p.125); and Hurka finds
very fat man off a bridge into the trolley’s or stood idly by have any pre-existing that one example is too ingenious, too far
path, so that he dies, many people who responsibility, for example as the driver of from reality, for him to have much confidence
would have used the switch say they would the trolley? And was anyone actually killed in the intuition about what’s permitted that
not push him. They say this even though the by human intervention, or did people he thinks it supports (p.139). Kamm acknowl-
body count – five versus one – would be the ‘merely’ let others die? edges the difficulty, but maintains that the
same. So ‘minimize the number of early More subtly, Kamm wants to consider method still has value and can be a route to
deaths’ is not the complete underlying ratio- whether deaths result from the saving of good answers (pages.193-4).
nale. But then what is the complete ratio- lives, or from actions which are mere means So the book offers us imperfect and tenta-
nale, if there is one? to the saving of lives. She suggests a principle tive answers, and it left me worried about the
The first part of this book gives the text of of permissible harm, under which actions methods used to obtain those answers. But
two lectures by Harvard ethics professor which are followed by deaths in the first way that in itself makes it a fine example of philo-
Frances Kamm, in which she pursues this would be permitted, but actions which sophical argument. In the natural sciences,
quest for a complete ethical rationale by would lead to deaths in the second way are we expect answers. In philosophy we expect
considering many more trolley problem vari- not. Switching the trolley away from the debate, a deeper understanding of questions,
ants than the basic ones. In the second part, track with five people would itself be the and answers which teach us something even
Judith Jarvis Thomson, Thomas Hurka, and saving of five lives, so it is permitted. Push- when they are inadequate, as well as when
Shelly Kagan challenge both some of Kamm’s ing the fat man off the bridge would be a they strike us as correct.
conclusions and some of her methods. She in death as a mere means to the saving of five This is a complex book, and it is not the
turn responds to their comments. lives, so it would not be permitted. first book that a student of trolley problems
In the first part, Kamm distinguishes Kamm does not proclaim her principle to should read. But it will not be the last book
between the choice to switch course being be the complete answer, and wisely so. She to read either. The lively way in which it
in the hands of the driver of the trolley and
its being in the hands of a bystander. She
then adds variants in which there are extra
choices, such as sacrificing yourself, or
different ways in which people may die, such
as rockfalls. She also brings in cases in which
there is no trolley, but some other reason
why action or inaction will affect who will
die, such as life-saving medical treatment
that spreads a dangerous gas to other people.
The reference in the book’s title to
‘mysteries’ reflects Kamm’s approach. A
detective in a murder mystery wants to know
who did the deed, and how it was done. In
the first lecture, Kamm concentrates on who

50 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018 Book Reviews


Books
makes plain that the last word is not yet to ate behaviour or worse, and we feel the need which Mandela won over the Springboks
be had is one of its virtues. to seek apology or in some other way basi- (pp.234-37), for example, could be seen as
© RICHARD BARON 2018 cally stick up for ourselves, our dignity, or strategic – the work of a man who had read up
Richard Baron is a philosopher in London. His our status. She canvasses various on winning friends and influencing people –
website is www.rbphilo.com approaches, and these fall into the cate- or as the expression of his personality.
gory of strategic action rather (This leads her to point out that
• The Trolley Problem Mysteries, by F. M. Kamm, than communicative action Mandela was a real sports fan,
Oxford University Press, 2016, xii + 256 pages, £19.99 (they’re Jürgen Haber- not a fake one.) But it’s
hb, ISBN 978-0-19-024715-7 mas’s terms, but others arguable that in Chapter
make the same distinc- 5 she’s quite happy with
tion). In strategic pure strategic action
Anger & Forgiveness action, we do not aim which is possibly
Martha Nussbaum to say what we think insincere or untruth-
THIS BOOK BY ONE OF AMER- or express what we ful, in non-intimate
ica’s leading philosophers feel, but rather, aim everyday relation-
originated in Martha Nuss- to get someone else to ships. This is more
baum’s 2014 John Locke improve their consistent with her
lectures at Oxford University. It’s very wide- behaviour by saying or overall welfarist position
ranging, starting in Ancient Greece and doing whatever seems than any prying into
ending in the liberation struggles and civil most likely to work, even if people’s souls to test their
rights movements of twentieth century that involves telling lies. So, for sincerity. The problem I find with
India, USA, and South Africa. It stays example, in order to discourage a stranger her very strong expression of forward-
throughout with a few key concepts – anger, on a plane giving unwanted help getting her oriented welfarist views is that though they are
forgiveness, gratitude, punishment, justice. cabin bag into the overhead locker, Nuss- meant to be both politically progressive and
Nussbaum characterises her overall ethical baum says (falsely), “I’m terribly sorry. That consistent with a liberal pluralism of the kind
and political vision as essentially ‘welfarist’, suitcase contains fragile items, and I’d rather articulated by John Rawls, they have a general
indebted both to utilitarians (specifically J.S. handle it myself so that, if anything should paternalistic (or maternalistic) feel, so that
Mill) and liberals (specifically John Rawls). happen, I would know that I’m responsible people may to some degree be manipulated or
From this very general position she tries to and not you” (p.148). Quite a speech, but infantilised by them. The exchange over the
discourage any idea we might have of anger this is a pure example of strategic rather than suit and tie I sketched could be construed this
as being a virtue of some kind. She’s also very communicative action. In the present way too. Also, when writing about difficult
critical of conditional forgiveness. If there is instance, communicative action might colleagues (pp.154-160), Nussbaum charac-
to be punishment, it should not be as back- involve saying, “No thank you. I prefer to terises one as a “selfish genius two year-old”
ward-looking retribution or payback, but as do it myself” – which is a polite way of saying (p.159) and others as suffering from “infantile
forward-looking deterrent. “I don’t want your help.” narcissism” (p.160) and who have to be
Nussbaum partitions her discussion in We act in this kind of strategic way all the handled accordingly – that is, handled strate-
terms of areas of social life: the intimate rela- time in our non-intimate everyday relations, gically as patients rather than communicatively
tionships of family and close friendship; the but its ethical dubiousness emerges the as agents. Sometimes this will work, but at
non-personal relationships of daily life, moment we switch the context to that of other times it will cause offence and invite
where we meet other people as waiters, trav- intimate relationships, since we rely on anger when the ruse is seen through. In inti-
ellers on the same plane, drivers on the same people close to us to say what they think and mate relationships, if you give the other cause
road; the more enduring but non-intimate express what they feel, not least because inti- to think you are treating them as a patient not
relationships we have with people such as mate relationships become deserts if people an agent, you’re in deep trouble. Likewise,
work colleagues; the world of criminal don’t do so. So, suppose a wife knows her treat the Springboks patronisingly as patients
justice, where the courts act for those who husband hates wearing a suit and tie but and you will be told to get lost.
have been wronged and against those who wants him to dress up for an occasion which Although I have this small area of doubt,
have wronged them; and the more historic might be important for his career or their this is a very impressive, wide-ranging, much
worlds of revolutionary justice, where social standing. She hits on the strategy of reflected-upon work of moral and political
fundamental social re-orientation is at issue. saying, “Why don’t you wear a suit and tie philosophy, with much of which I am in
She focusses on the civil rights struggles in this evening? It makes you look so hand- cheerful agreement.
America, the campaign for Indian indepen- some.” The strategy may work, but it © TREVOR PATEMAN 2018
dence, and the re-organisation of South involves dishonesty about her intentions and Trevor Pateman studied with Richard Wollheim
Africa achieved by the ANC and Nelson that’s high-risk in an intimate relationship, and Roland Barthes. Their influence can still be
Mandela. The discussion is packed with and over time can be very damaging to it. found in his books Materials and Medium: an
examples and is readable throughout. Nussbaum herself edges towards a discus- Aesthetics (2016), and Prose Improvements
I had one general disquiet that emerged sion of this problem when she writes admir- (2017), on prose fiction and creative writing.
when I read the Chapter 5, on the Middle ingly in Chapter 7 of the ways in which Nelson
Realm of non-intimate everyday relation- Mandela brought important white groups • Anger & Forgiveness: Resentment, Generosity,
ships. Here Nussbaum discusses cases where onside in the transition to majority rule in Justice, by Martha C. Nussbaum, OUP USA, 2016,
people have angered us by their inconsider- South Africa. She realises that the ways in 336pp, $24.95/£16.99, ISBN 978-0199335879

Book Reviews February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 51


A L I E N
C O V E N A N T
Stefan Bolea talks of madness, antihumanism, and the
Film
“And just as paganism was to give way before
arrival of the new gods.
city. From now on the story takes an inter- obedience’ because our fears of the
Christianity, so this last God will have to esting philosophical turn and I won’t unknown as well our hopes of reward would
yield to some new belief. Stripped of aggres- rehearse the plot details, preferring to draw be greatly diminished.
sion, He no longer constitutes an obstacle to on the film’s philosophical themes. David is Walter’s doppelgänger: they are
the outburst of other gods; they need only different generations of the same make of
arrive – and perhaps they will arrive.” Rebellion & Madness In Space android. While David is more creative and
(E.M. Cioran, The New Gods, 1974). The android David is the main character of has a propensity towards disobedience,
the movie. His role might be compared to Walter has been upgraded to provide more

R
idley Scott’s 2017 film Alien: that of Milton’s Lucifer or Mary Shelley’s reliability and fidelity. This adjustment in
Covenant is the second Alien creation resembles the genesis of angels
The android David has the whole
prequel and the sixth title overall compared with that of humans. Although
from the Alien series. It’s a sequel world in his hands the angels were clearly superior beings, they
to Prometheus (2012), a production praised were inclined to rebel against their Creator
for its stunning visual quality. Alien: and provoke a state of what the Romanian
Covenant contains references to poetry from philosopher Lucian Blaga has called ‘theo-
Milton to Shelley; to classical music anarchy’, a kind of divine disorder. The
(Wagner); to the history of religions (espe- humans by contrast are like the next gener-
cially Gnosticism); and to psychology (both ation androids – more inclined to serve and
Freud and Jung). But most of all, Alien: worship after being equipped with the virus
Covenant can be understood as a meditation of anxiety and the biological duty to die.
upon the ideas of Friedrich Nietzsche and In a Jungian sense, David is Walter’s
Emil Cioran’s antihumanism. shadow, a version of the archetype of the
After a prologue, the movie follows the enemy, the evil stranger, or the devil. In this
journey of the starship Covenant, which is context we can discuss psychosis. David
carrying 2,000 comatose colonists to the wrongly attributes the poem Ozymandias to
planet Origae 6. It is set in 2104, eleven years Byron (it’s one of Shelley’s), and Walter
after the events in Prometheus. The ship is comments: “When a note is off, it eventu-
damaged in an accident, and the android ally destroys the whole symphony.” Walter
Walter (Michael Fassbender) wakes the is here using Arthur Schopenhauer’s defini-
crew. The captain has burned to death in his tion of insanity, understood as a disturbance
stasis pod, leaving Oram (Billy Crudup) in unnamed monster in Frankenstein. David’s of memory. The Romanian Schopenhaue-
charge. The death of the original captain sets rebellious nature is obvious in the preface rian poet Mihai Eminescu (who himself
the tone for a state of anxiety, hesitation, and during an opening conversation with his eventually died in a mental institution) also
disorder, and Oram has difficulty asserting creator, trillionaire Peter Weyland (Guy uses musical imagery to speak of insanity:
his authority. Pearce), when he says, “You seek your “All the lyre’s chords are broken, and the
Against the recommendation of the orig- creator; I am looking at mine. I will serve minstrel man is mad.” Moreover, the musi-
inal captain’s widow (played by Katherine you, yet you are human. You will die, I will cal metaphor of madness is a direct refer-
Waterton), the new captain decides to not.” This echoes the famous role reversal ence to Wagner’s prelude ‘Entry of Gods
investigate a radio signal picked up from a in Frankenstein where the monster says, into Valhalla’ from Das Rheingold (1854) –
nearby planet. Oram leads the exploration “You are my creator, but I am your master; which is played at the beginning and the end
of this Earth-like planet, which contains – obey!” It reminds me also of Hegel’s of Covenant (proving that this interpretation
vegetation but seems devoid of animal life. dialectical shift in The Phenomenology of has managed to capture at least some of the
Two members of the crew are infected by Spirit (1807), where the slave becomes the intentions of the creators of the movie).
alien spores and later killed by the creatures master of the master. Wotan, the ruler of the gods, is seen by Jung
that burst from their bodies, and things The mortality of his ‘father’ is the crux of as a darker version of Dionysus, Nietzsche’s
rapidly go downhill. At this tricky juncture, David’s defiance. Without death, there archetype of chaos. Jung wrote, “Wotan is
up pops David (Michael Fassbender again), would be no anxiety: one might say that all the noise in the wood, the rushing waters,
an android who was one of the central char- forms of fear sing a hymn to death. Without the one who causes natural catastrophes,
acters of Prometheus, and who has been this anxiety, our relationship towards the and wars among human beings.” The Swiss
stranded on the planet since the events of divine (the Father of fathers, the King of psychiatrist also claimed that Nietzsche has
that film. He scares the aliens away and leads kings) would be transformed. We would no had a ‘Wotan experience’ that foreshad-
the crew to the temple of a nearby ruined longer feel inclined to play the ‘comedy of owed his descent into madness.

52 Philosophy Now l February/March 2018


ALIEN COVENANT IMAGES © 20TH CENTURY FOX 2017

Film
himself. “But am I not a false accord / Within
the holy symphony?” asks Baudelaire, again
echoing the musical imagery of madness.

Android Devil, Or God


Eventually Oram breaks the spell and shoots
the neomorph. In the same scene, Oram
Alien Antihumanism man ceases to be human – “I was man and I speaks of the devil: “David, I met the devil
The most important theme of the movie is no longer am now,” observes Cioran – but when I was a child. And I’ve never forgotten
the problem of antihumanism, a concept I use cannot aspire to the heroic status of the Über- him.” This alludes to Nietzsche’s assertion
in a slightly different sense than Michel mensch. The not-man is a sort of shadow of the that the so-called ‘higher men’ would see the
Foucault’s. The French philosopher spoke of ideal, a Platonic form relegated to the under- Übermensch as a devil. An important issue
the death of a certain concept of humanity world. The not-man could fail even worse connected with antihumanism is ‘creation-
following the demise of God: “Man would be than the human being because its status is ism’, in the sense of ‘having an appetite for
erased like a face drawn in sand at the edge of more intricate and ambiguous: “I am no creation’. The devil is traditionally seen as a
the sea.” However, poets such as Baudelaire longer human… What will I become?” decreator. In the Garden of Eden he hijacks
and Lautréamont and philosophers such as The key scene from Alien: Covenant takes God’s influence by inspiring disobedience in
Stirner, Nietzsche and Cioran add misan- place after a neomorph (a species of alien) Adam and Eve. Yet we see in David a devil
thropy – dislike of mankind – to their antihu- severs the head of one of the Covenant’s who aspires to overcome his condition, who
manistic project. While Foucault alluded to crew. David surprises the neomorph feeding, wants to create as God creates, when he saves
the downfall of man understood in a certain then starts looking at its face (it doesn’t have an alien embryo so that the aliens can be
type of way, and to the arrival of a non- eyes) with awe and pity. This scene is signif- recreated. More precisely, David is one of
humanistic system of reference, some post- icant because it’s two different kinds of not- Cioran’s new gods. Just as Christianity
Romantic poets and philosophers see them- men looking at each other: it’s a meeting demonized the gods of antiquity, the new
selves as agents of destruction – of what Niet- between non-human and non-human unmedi- gods will vilify the Christian God. This
zsche called ‘active nihilism’ – and would like ated by human intervention. David’s gaze demonization would be accomplished with
to finish with the saga of humanism alto- into the abyss of an even more radical inhu- the death of the idea of resurrection, so that
gether through a Schopenhauerian process manity – into the shadow of his shadow – mortality defeated even Jesus: “Christ will
of universal death. Moreover, Nietzsche revives Baudelaire’s ‘looking-glass of the not harrow Hell again: He has been put back
spoke of the Übermensch [‘overman’ or shrew’, the mirror of unidentification where in the tomb, and this time he will stay there,”
‘superman’] as an overcoming of the tradi- a schizophrenic sees something other than notes Cioran. One could say that humans
tional man, a sort of transgression of normal believe they believe in God, but truly believe
humanity, and Cioran referred to the not- only in death.
man – a psychological mutation of the The android who has overcome the
species, a being who is human only from a profound anxiety of death is a created creator
biological perspective. The Übermensch and who aspires to the divinity of his creators’
the not-man can both be seen as possible Creator. David’s appetite for creation thus
paths for humanity’s evolution. They are also transforms him into an equal of Goethe’s
a metaphor for the current impasse of Prometheus:
humanism: the feeling that the human
species is in a certain biological sense dying, “Here sit I, forming mortals
and that biotechnological enhancement in After my image; a race, resembling me,
the near future will transform humanity to To suffer, to weep,
the core. To enjoy, to be glad,
Cioran’s not-man might be a subtler and And thee to scorn,
more complicated idea than the Übermensch. As I!”
They are both ‘beings of overcoming’; but if
Nietzsche’s concept has a upwards and some- © DR STEFAN BOLEA 2018
what utopian quality, Cioran’s notion raises Stefan Bolea earned PhDs in both Philosophy
the pessimistic possibility of a more dystopian and Literature from the University of Cluj-
transgression of humanity. The not-man is Napoca, Romania. He is the editor-in-chief of
the infernal abyss of the Übermensch: the not- the online magazine Egophobia: egophobia.ro

February/March 2018 l Philosophy Now 53


Subscribe to Philosophy Now
philosophynow.org
6 IDEA-PACKED ISSUES FOR £15.50/US$32

With a subscription to Philosophy Now you can save up to


30% off the newsstand price, have your copies delivered
to your door and enjoy unrestricted access to our online
content. Subscribe today at philosophynow.org or fill
out and return one of the coupons below.

Subscription inquiries: email subscriptions@philosophynow.org or phone 01959 534171


To tell us about a change of address, please email addresschange@philosophynow.org

UK / Rest of World United States


Name Name _____________________________________________
Address Address ___________________________________________
___________________________________________________
Email Email ______________________________________________
Subscribe to Philosophy Now for 6 issues (1 year)
Subscribe to Philosophy Now for 12 issues (2 years) Subscribe to Philosophy Now for 6 issues ($32)
UK 15.50/28 (GBP)
Canada 37/69 (CAD) Subscribe to Philosophy Now for 12 issues ($59)
New Zealand 49/93 (NZD)
Australia 40/75 (AUD) Starting with Issue #124/Issue #125 (delete as appropriate)
Europe 23/42 (EUR)
Rest of World 21/37 (GBP)

Starting with Issue 124/Issue 125 (delete as appropriate) Buy back issues on CD (please circle)
Vol.1/Vol.2/Vol.3/Vol.4
Buy back issues on CD (please circle)
Buy back issues in PRINT (please specify issue numbers)
Vol.1/Vol.2/Vol.3/Vol.4
______________________________________
Buy back issues in PRINT (please specify issue numbers)
Buy _____ binders to hold back issues (insert quantity)
______________________________________
TOTAL AMOUNT PAYABLE: $_________
Buy _____ binders to hold back issues (insert quantity)
Please make your check payable to ‘Philosophy Documentation
TOTAL AMOUNT PAYABLE: _________ Center’ or fill in your details below:

Please make your cheque payable to ‘Philosophy Now’ or fill in your Card no.
Mastercard /Visa /Maestro card details below: Expiry_________________ Security Code__________
Card no. Name on card _______________________________________________
Expiry__________________ Security Code___________ and send it to: Philosophy Documentation Center,
Name on card _______________________________________________ P.O. Box 7147
Charlottesville, VA 22906-7147
and send it to: Philosophy Now Subscriptions
U.S.A.
Kelvin House, Grays Road,
Westerham, Kent TN16 2JB,
(You can also order on 800-444-2419 or email pkswope@pdcnet.org)
United Kingdom

54 Philosophy Now ● December 2017/January 2018


Digital Editions and Back Issues
Digital Editions (see philosophynow.org/digital)
Website Subscriptions
Print subscriptions to Philosophy Now don’t include Kindle, Nook, app content etc but do include access to our website which has
2,500+ articles from past issues. Password is available on request or is sent automatically if you subscribe online. We also sell
website subscriptions separately, from our store at philosophynow.org/shop

IP-based online access is available for schools and colleges – visit philosophynow.org/institutions

App Philoso
phy Now
Available in the Apple App Store and Google Play store. Free sample issue included.

Kindle
Buy a single issue or an ongoing subscription. (30 day free trial)

Nook
Available on Barnes & Noble’s Nook reader and the Nook app. (14 day free trial)

Zinio
There is also an edition for the Zinio app on iPad and Android. Single issue or ongoing subscription.

Back Issues in Print T-shirts


Issue 121 Radical Consciousness: Panpsychism; Neutral Monism; IIT;
Quantum Collapse / Trump’s Language / Rawls Brief Life / Foucault We now sell Philosophy Now T-shirts on Amazon. They
Issue 122 Socrates & Plato, on vision, love, memory, politics & Facebook / make great birthday presents. The shirts are made, sold and
Zizek interview / Cubism / Experience machines / Pirsig’s Quality dispatched by Amazon.com. Available only in the USA, com-
Issue 123 Anti-Prejudice: Derrida, Hate Speech, Homelessness, Prostitution,
Education / Kant & Humanity / Lebowski review / Right from Wrong ing to the rest of the world soon.

We also still have copies of these earlier back issues: The shirts cost $18.00 each.
Issues 2, 39-44, 46, 47, 55-80, 82, 84, 85, 87-89, 91-120
There are four designs so far,
For full details and tables of contents of all back issues, please
visit our online shop at philosophynow.org/shop with more following soon.
Each is available in a variety
Back issues cost £3.75 each if you live in the UK (inc p&p) or of colors and sizes. To visit
US$10/C$10/A$10/NZ$12/£6.50 elsewhere via airmail. For the Philosophy Now T-shirt
every three back issues you buy, we’ll give you a fourth for free shop on Amazon.com, please
(please tell us which you would like). type this shortened address
exactly:
Binders: Our smart green Philosophy Now binders each hold 12
magazines. UK£8.75, US$25, A$27,C$27, NZ$34, or Rest of http://amzn.to/2fKrwPF
World £15.

PDFs: Available for purchase from our online shop


BACK ISSUES VOLUME TWO

Philosophy Now
a magazine of ideas

Back Issues on CD
BACK ISSUES

Philosophy Now has been published since 1991, so it is hardly surprising that we’re often asked for back Philosophy Now
a magazine of ideas
Issues 21-40

issues which have long since sold out. Therefore we’ve put our first eighty issues onto four CDs in
PDF format.
Issues 41-60
VOLUME THREE

Vol. 1: Issues 01-20; Vol. 2: Issues 21-40; Vol. 3: Issues 41-60; Vol. 4: Issues 61-80
Single vol. (1, 2, 3 or 4) UK£15 US$23 Can$35 Aus$35 NZ$40 RoW£17
Two volumes: UK£25 US$40 Can$55 Aus$55 NZ$65 RoW£30
Three volumes: UK£35 US$55 Can$75 Aus$75 NZ$90 RoW£40
Four volumes: UK£45 US$69 Can$95 Aus$95 NZ$115 RoW£51

December 2017/January 2018 ● Philosophy Now 55


On Looking at the
T allis Back of My Hand
in
Wonderland Raymond Tallis finds unexpected depths of knowledge.

I
have recently been staring at the back body: the mystery of what we might call there is more to it than I can see; and the
of my hand: an innocent, inexpensive ‘ambodiment’. In what follows, I want to visual appearance of my hand – for example,
pastime that has provoked some argue that this oddness is a key to our ability, the shadows between the wrinkles on the
thoughts I would now like to share with baffling to many philosophers, to perceive knuckles – discloses that there is more to it
you. They touch on our relationship with objects as existing independently of our than I can directly feel. We thus have the
our own bodies, and on the puzzle of our perceptions and located in an external cross-sensory equivalent of the depth
knowledge of the external world, which world. You may think this a bold, even perception afforded by binocular vision – in
enigma has exercised many philosophers, outrageous, claim, but stick with me. this case, two sensory modalities as opposed
not least David Hume and Immanuel Kant. to two eyes. The object perceived in two
The peculiarity of our relationship to our A Handy Double-Take different ways simultaneously thereby has an
bodies is captured in a famous passage from When I look at the back of my hand I see an ontological depth – a depth of existence –
Jean-Paul Sartre’s novel Nausea (1965), object that I know from immediate experi- that reveals it as being more than what is
where the protagonist Roquentin says: ence has parts that lie beyond what I now provided by a single sense.
see, belonging to my hand’s undersurface You may be inclined to say, “So what?
“I see my hand spread out on the table. It is and its interior. I can, for example, feel my When I examine a cup, I can also feel tactile
alive – it is me. It is lying on its back. It currently invisible palm through the pres- properties I can’t see.” I need therefore to
shows me its fat underbelly. It looks like an sure on its flesh of the table on which it is clarify in what way the experience of our own
animal upside down. The fingers are the resting. Or I can directly intuit its interior bodily parts is unique.
paws. I amuse myself by making them move courtesy of a variety of sensations such as its Whereas lifting and looking at a cup give
about very quickly, like the claws of a crab weight and warmth, and sometimes through different experiences of it, together indicat-
that has fallen upside down… I feel my localized experiences such as pains. These ing that each sensory modality yields an
hand. It is me, these two animals moving testify to an ‘in here’ hidden from the vision experience of something that is more than
about at the end of my arms.” (pp.143-4). that discloses the hand as ‘out there’, and that experience, the different senses do not
indeed, hidden from everyone else. You have such a fundamentally different angle
The metaphysical scandal of this strange cannot sense my pain. I cannot sense yours. of approach as is the case with my body.
and estranging encounter with our closest It is worth reflecting on this a With the cup there is nothing that corre-
lieutenant, our primordial means of bit further before we proceed to sponds to the double aspect of the ‘from
getting a grip on the world, my larger claims. When I directly without’ of my visible hand plus the ‘from
suggests that further feel the hand that I am also looking within’ of my hand apprehending its
digging may yield at, I am in receipt of parallel streams of warmth or weight or feeling discomfort.
philosophical experience which are each exposed by the When I observe the colour of my veins I can
treasure. other as incomplete. see that I am seeing something that cannot
be felt; and when I am feeling the warmth
of my hand, I am aware of being aware of
something that lies beyond my or anyone
else’s gaze. The peculiar dissociation
between a distance receptor such as vision
and the immediate awareness arising out of
the hand’s sensation of itself is particularly
evident when my hand is in action: I can feel
but cannot see the effort in the grip.
Therefore, when I look at my hand, or
indeed other body part, I have experience of
an object that exceeds or (to use a term
beloved of phenomenologists) ‘transcends’
Roquentin’s any sensory perception of it. Vision, which
fascinated horror exposes The warmth of, or the pres- locates the object as ‘out there’ is comple-
the oddness of the connection between sure on, or a pain in, my mented by proprioceptive (felt body) aware-
the ‘I am’ of the subject and the ‘it is’ of his hand, betrays that ness that illuminates the ‘in here’ of the

56 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


object, and which is not accessible to anyone argument. Let me deal with the most pressing.
else. I suffer my body in the way that you Firstly, that this knowledge-from-within
cannot. Moreover, while my seeing my body argument might not withstand Cartesian
can be terminated by closing my eyes, my doubt. René Descartes finds a bedrock of
feeling it (particularily when it is in pain) certainty in the fact that he is thinking: I
cannot be extinguished by voluntarily clos-
ing down a sensory pathway. This is why
cannot without self-contradiction entertain
the thought that I am not thinking. This is
T allis
tactile and proprioceptive experience his famous cogito argument – ‘I think there-
in
locates my body firmly in my subjectivity,
albeit on the edge of objectivity, while
seeing it locates it at a distance from subjec-
tivity. This double status is reflected in the
fore I am’. But the scope of what is beyond
doubt as delivered by this argument is
severely limited. I can be certain only that I
am a thinking being – or that there are
Wonderland
way we refer to our bodies or parts of them thoughts happening – not that I am an biology, biochemistry of his living stuff.
as possessions – ‘my body’, ‘my hands’. embodied thinking being. Since, however – as
These two fundamentally different modes P.F. Strawson pointed out in Individuals Existential Reassurance
of access reveal the ontological depth of my- (1959) – identity depends on unique occu- What is most importantly granted to me
body-as-object. pancy of a location in space and time, it is through my ambodiment is what we might
not possible to confine the ‘I’ of that ‘I am’ call ‘existential reassurance’: that the world is
A Good Body Of Evidence to thoughts, or indeed, perceptions, because populated with objects that exist in them-
Now to the large claims. Starting with the they do not occupy space. So if I have an selves and are more than my, or anyone
human body will direct us away from a identity (in short, if ‘I’ is to have a reference, else’s, experiences of them. The phenome-
murky path that has led many otherwise and I am to have token experiences and nologist Maurice Merleau-Ponty expressed a
sensible thinkers to find our knowledge of token thoughts), then I must be embodied. thought similar to this when he asserted that
material objects, even the status of objects ‘I [the subject] am’ requires that ‘it [the “the very idea of the ontological dimension
themselves, problematic. I am thinking for body] is’. And this is equally true, by the way, of objects must be traced back to… the
example of David Hume’s opinion in his of the very sense organs by which I perceive constitution of the object in our (bodily)
Treatise on Human Nature (1738) that the world: they, too, must be located in a experience.” In virtue of the ‘I am’ that grows
‘bodies’ – by which he means objects gener- body localized in space and time in order to in and haunts, and appropriates, and
ally – are mere fictions constructed out of have particular content – so that I see this distances itself from, this body, I have a sense
sense impressions; or Willard Van Orman rather than that. As an individual who expe- of an ‘it is’ applicable to my body and thence
Quine’s assertion in Two Dogmas of Empiri- riences the world from a viewpoint, I cannot to material objects beyond my body. The
cism (1951) that objects are ‘cultural posits’ be mistaken that my body exists. combination of first-person being or ‘am-
fashioned out of ‘irritations on our sensory All right, you concede, we can be certain ing’ my body and experiencing it as an object
surfaces’ and on a comparable ‘epistemolog- about the existence of one type of material – most strikingly when I look at myself in a
ical footing’ as Homer’s gods. Or as Kant object that transcends sense experience: the mirror – awakens the sense of the ‘being-in-
(woken by Hume out of his ‘dogmatic slum- bodies of conscious human beings. But what itself’ of the world that surrounds me.
ber’) argued, we cannot know any ‘thing-in- about sticks and stones and mountains? Can Next time you look at the back of your
itself’ by unaided perception. He conse- we really know that they, too, are real? Yes; hand, give it a second, philosophical, look.
quently postulated that only the activity of for if my body with its interacting parts were You may find there’s more to it than meets
the mind itself gives us the impression of real but the things it acted upon were merely the eye.
stable objects in a coherent world. fictions or posits, there would be a rather © PROF. RAYMOND TALLIS 2018
The fundamental puzzle here is that if lopsided coupling between a real physical Raymond Tallis’ Of Time and Lamentation:
objects really are more than constructs out body and a world of fictional items. Reflections on Transience is out now. His
of experiences we could not directly experi- I am not claiming that I have full knowl- Logos: The Mystery of How We Make
ence them as such; so what on earth could edge of my body as an object from within in Sense of the World will be out this Spring.
justify the belief that the world is made up virtue of ‘aming’ it. The
of items made up of stuff that is more than penetration of ‘I am’ into
(and hence lies beyond) our experience? the ‘it is’ of my body is
The answer lies in our body, which is limited. Much of my own
experienced from within and without. This flesh is a place of darkness
gives the human body the ontological depth to me, and most of the little
we require of all real, experience-indepen- I know of it is not accessed
dent, objects. Our body has the ontological through introspection.
depth of a being that is more than just the What happens at the level
sum total of my and others’ experiences of of organs, muscles and
it, in virtue of being both an object of exter- bones, and cells, is hidden
nal perception and experienced from within. from me until I open the
This means the one object that could not be relevant textbook. To be
a Humean ‘fiction’ or a Quinean ‘posit’ is the body of Raymond
our own body. Tallis is not to have privi-
I can envisage several objections to this leged access to the physics,

February/March 2018 ● Philosophy Now 57


Freedom 2199
Jonathan Sheasby discovers some unexpected perils of AI.
teve sat in his B38, a sleek grey capsule descending deep robot hippy?” yelled the irate miner, arising as he did so – then

S down into Novus’s core, plummeting like a hammerhead


shark in pursuit of its prey. Our hero experienced an
increased sense of disorientation as the speed
at which he was travelling jeopardised his already
rather tenuous connection with reality.
wishing he hadn’t as his head banged the roof of his sinking cell.
“Ahhh…” iterated the computer calmly, “We knew we’d
encounter some rather futile resistance on the path to
enlightenment. You must realise that this situa-
tion can only be escaped through a little
The interior of the pod reverberated, thought on your part - a little cognition of
increasing its occupant’s unease as he which you are entirely capable.. You see,
glanced at the coloured windows which, everyone begins to philosophise at some
comfortingly, or perhaps discomfort- point, just as you did when you wondered
ingly, revealed nothing of the capsule’s whether I was a ghost in a machine…”
surroundings. “You read my mind? Now that’s def-
“Want a mint?” asked the disembod- initely a breach of my human rights!”
ied voice of the IDEX, his electronically opined the indignant Steve. “I refuse to
generated companion for the journey, answer your question. I’ll stay here for-
programmed to put its passenger at ease ever if I have to. I’ll sweat it out. My mental
with light-hearted solicitous questions of freedom’s more important to me than every-
this nature. Steve’s stomach churned with the thing – my own life, even.”
downward motion of his vessel. He found him- “Okay, as you wish. You are free to choose,
self wondering whether IDEX Sam was, in some lit- after all.” Steve wondered whether there was more
eral sense, a ghost in a machine. His musings were inter- than a hint of irony in his self-appointed jailer’s statement,
rupted by a rather surreal turn of events when IDEX Sam asked, but kept this thought, as best he could, to himself. He began
apparently at random: “Are you completely free, Steven?” recklessly banging buttons and pulling levers in the hope of
“What?” yelped Steve, more than a little phased by this escaping the control of his self-righteous and conceited captor;
unorthodox line of questioning, never before heard from an but upon realising the futility of his struggle he sat back breath-
IDEX. Their sole purpose was to comfort and distract the ing heavily, his energy spent.
miners as they journeyed to their place of work each day, taking The seconds passed ever so slowly in silence; and as they did,
their minds off their sense of powerlessness as they dropped as much as he tried to not think, Steve was horrified to find him-
through the churning, lightening-wracked cloud layers of an self wondering whether he was free in the very situation he was
alien planet. He was also a tad disconcerted by the formal in. He was surely still free to think what he wanted to, wasn’t
manner in which he was now being addressed by his simulated he? But if so, then why, without any physically imposed restraint,
companion, who had previously tended to salute him affection- or any electrode attached to his brain or chip inserted therein,
ately as ‘mate’ or ‘Ste’. He hadn’t been called ‘Steven’ since he was he now venturing to answer the question he had been
was a child being reprimanded by his mother or aunt for some instructed by the machine to address, and which he was so
misdemeanor or other. strongly opposed to answering for the sake of the very freedom
Unbeknownst to Steve, or indeed most of the other miners he held so dear? Then, to the conflicted miner’s simultaneous
travelling in the other capsules that day, hackers had infiltrated horror and relief, IDEX Sam explained, “Steve, you are free to
the Viecorps mainframe. It could have been worse: these tech- go – as in fact you always have been. I’ve not actually interfered
nological law-breakers were merely part of a rather austere with your journey one iota: I merely played a little benevolent
albeit impassioned sect who felt impelled to force humankind trick on you in order to lead you further along the path of self-
to attain a higher, more reflective mode of existence. realisation.” With that the door opened, at the same time it did
“There’s no point your working mindlessly each day until every single day.
you die without having considered the deeper questions of life,” Steve stepped out into the blinding artificial light of Novus’s
said the proselytising reconstituted IDEX Sam: “And so before interior, shaking his head and attempting to focus his eyes on
I let you leave this vehicle, I’m afraid you’re going to have to the armed retainers of Viecorps, evidently sent forth to rescue
seriously address at least one of them.” him, albeit redundantly. Although uncertain whether or not his
Desperately clinging to his seat as if grasping his very sanity, rights had been violated during his ordeal, Steve felt convinced
Steve exclaimed, “But you can’t force me to think; that’s against that he would be thinking about freedom much more carefully
my human rights!” in future.
“That particular rather valueless right has been temporarily © JONATHAN SHEASBY 2018
suspended. For your own good, you understand.” Jonathan Sheasby is a writer living in the sometimes free and alien
“Who the hell are you to decide what’s in my interests, you world of London. He works for Westminster Council.

58 Philosophy Now ● February/March 2018


Information philosophy is the first
new method of philosophizing
since logical positivism and
analytic language philosophy in
Philosophy Now
the early twentieth century.
The I-Phi website at
Most App-ealing!
informationphilosopher.com
offers resources on over 300
philosophers and scientists
who have contributed to the
great problems in philosophy, There’s a Philosophy Now app for Apple and Android
physics, biology, psychology. devices. Download for free (it includes one free sample
Resources include reprints of issue) then buy a subscription within the app to read the
major articles and excerpts magazine. App subscriptions include a month’s free trial. All
from books of each thinker. our back issues are available for purchase within the app
too. Purchased issues can be downloaded to your device for
Proposed solutions to those great
offline reading. Please see Apple’s App Store or Google Play
problems and some puzzles and paradoxes from
for details.
ancient and modern metaphysics are here.
informationphilosopher.com/problems (Please note: when you purchase
metaphysicist.com/problems an app subscription you are buying
it from Apple or Google, and it
Information philosopher lectures are streamed as does not include a Philosophy Now
live video 8pm BT every weekday at youtube.com/ print or website subscription.
infophilosopher and on facebook.com/ infophilosopher. Similarly, our print and website
Past lectures are at informationphilosopher.com/lectures. subscriptions do not include an
app subscription. For print/website
subscriptions please see p.54 or
PDF versions of chapters of I-Phi books are downloadable visit philosophynow.org)
free from informationphilosopher.com/books.
For more info: bobdoyle@informationphilosopher.com

Available at and booksellers worldwide

Dahlian Kirby

Counselling
available

I am a qualified humanistic/existentialist counsellor.


I currently have appointments available including
some evenings and Saturdays.

Existential counselling explores problems from a


philosophical perspective. I work with each
individual to help them consider how to work
through their concerns and move towards a more
authentic life.

I am a member of the British Association for


Counselling & Psychotherapy. I have an MA in Ethics Hardback | 9781474298339 | £20.00
eBook | 9781474298346 | £19.99
and a PhD in Philosophy from Cardiff University. I’m
also a past contributor to Philosophy Now. Everyone judges and is judged. Why is this so? And can we
find true understanding amidst all the confusions, misfires and
I offer counselling via Skype, email & telephone. I insecurities? Ziyad Mirar provides an honest exploration of the
also offer counselling face to face in North East paradox of judgement in the contemporary world.
England. Please email me: info@dahliankirby.com
or visit my website at www.dahliankirby.com
www.bloomsbury.com/philosophy
@BloomsburyPhilo

You might also like