Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 6

F

Fuller, Lon Luvois A Pragmatic Definition of Law

Kenneth Winston In assessing Fuller’s exchanges with Hart (e.g.,


Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA Fuller 1958), many scholars observe that, while
Fuller had the more compelling view of law, Hart
displayed greater clarity and rigor in argument. In
particular, Fuller was faulted for conflating
Introduction
descriptive and evaluative elements (the is and
the ought) in his account of law. Yet Fuller’s
The most renowned legal theorist in the United
views on this issue are widely misunderstood,
States in the middle decades of the twentieth cen-
because they are judged in terms of conventional
tury, Lon Fuller taught contract law and jurispru-
theories of meaning and not placed in the Prag-
dence at the Harvard Law School from 1939 until
matist frame that guides his analysis. Of central
his retirement in 1972. He secured his place in
importance for Fuller is the practical nature of
legal philosophy in the 1930s with three articles
intellect. The human mind does not simply mirror
on legal fictions and probing critiques of legal
an external reality, any more than human obser-
realism. His work on the reliance interest, the
vation passively registers fixed properties of inde-
doctrine of consideration, and other aspects of
pendently existing objects. Knowers are active
contract law established him as one of the most
participants in the world – selective, goal-
innovative and influential theorists in the field by
directed, valuing. And objects of knowledge con-
mid-century. His hypothetical Case of the
nect in definite (if sometimes inchoate) ways to
Speluncean Explorers, an elegant portrayal of
human sentiments, purposes, and capacities.
rival judicial philosophies, is a classic of the
Given the practical nature of intellect, defini-
legal literature. And his published exchanges
tions of social phenomena are not compelled by
with the Oxford philosopher H. L. A. Hart, in
the way the world is. Indeed, the very idea of a
the 1950s and 1960s, set the terms of debate in
true or correct definition is misguided. No defini-
jurisprudence for several generations of students.
tion gives the essential nature of an object; rather,
In this brief entry, I will focus on four
there are diverse definitions, adopted by different
connected issues in jurisprudence that preoccu-
authors concerned about different parts or aspects
pied Fuller for much of his career: definitions of
of the phenomenon. This is especially so for social
law, the internal morality of law, freedom as law’s
categories like law, since their manifestation is
ideal, and forms of legal order.
historically contingent and variable. Law as cus-
tom and law as legislation are (or have been)
# Springer Science+Business Media B.V., part of Springer Nature 2018
M. Sellers, S. Kirste (eds.), Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6730-0_201-2
2 Fuller, Lon Luvois

realities, and any definition that excluded one or The Internal Morality of Law
the other would be arbitrary.
How then do we choose? What role does def- In this account, there is no illusion that the law at
inition play in inquiry? Like the Pragmatists, any given time and place is anything other than
Fuller regards ideas as anticipatory and action what it is. In fact, Fuller was inclined to dwell on
guiding; they always mean something that does the way things can go wrong – the pathological
not yet exist, an ideal presence absent in fact cases – including most famously the parable of the
(in William James’s phrase). To develop a hapless king Rex who nobly attempts to make
thought’s meaning is to determine what direction laws for his subjects and fails, in eight ways that
it gives to human conduct. So, what is at stake in a illuminate “the morality that makes law possible”
definition of law is that it leads us to act one way (Fuller 1969, 33–94). The tenets of this morality,
rather than another. Accordingly, disagreements briefly stated, are: (1) generality: there must be
about the meaning of law are not analytic or rules; (2) publicity: the rules must be made avail-
conceptual disputes; they are disputes about able to those expected to comply with them;
what kind of professional one ought to be (Fuller (3) prospectivity: the rules must typically be pro-
1966, 2–4). Definitions of law (and conceptions of mulgated prior to when compliance is expected,
legal philosophy) encourage us to ask: “How hence not retroactive; (4) clarity: the rules must be
would the adoption of one view or the other affect intelligible; (5) non-contradictoriness: the rules
the way a lawyer, judge, or law teacher spends the must not require conflicting actions;
working day?” The preferred thought is one that (6) conformability: the rules must not require
awakens our active impulses and leads us to con- actions that are impossible to perform; (7) stabil-
duct ourselves better than we otherwise would ity: the rules must remain relatively constant over
have done. In this way, Fuller captures the inter- time; (8) congruence: the rules promulgated by
action and mutual dependence of law and a law- the lawmaker must be the rules actually adminis-
yer’s professional ethos in the creation of legal tered and enforced.
order. Why does violation of these principles consti-
Accordingly, a Pragmatic definition embodies tute moral failure? Given Fuller’s Pragmatist ori-
a teleological element combining the real and the entation, the critical issue for lawmaking is how it
ideal. To have assurance that an ideal is practical, directs the application of human energies. Build-
it must be based on the experience of actual soci- ing on John Locke’s proposition that the good
eties. At the same time, it cannot simply recapit- legislator provides intelligent guidance to rational
ulate what already exists. Rather, it extrapolates beings, Fuller describes Rex’s aim – the aim he
from existing patterns or tendencies and envisions failed to achieve – as subjecting human conduct to
them as perfected in some way. The model then the governance of rules. This aim is not chosen at
offers a critical standpoint from which to assess random. The use of rules is not instrumental to
the ongoing activity and suggest improvement. Of some other objective that Rex has in mind; it is the
course, one must not be so overly impressed by aim itself. Why? The brief answer is that
the ideal as to neglect the fact that the actual only governing by rules involves recognition of citi-
partly embodies it, and one must not be so overly zens as responsible moral agents, an idea that has
impressed by the real that one neglects the active both a descriptive and a normative component.
striving toward an ideal. On one side, law is not Descriptively, it alludes to the capacity of citizens
simply reason or justice; on the other, it is not to engage in practical deliberation and accept
simply the will of the sovereign or the interest of responsibility for their actions, which they can
a dominant social class. It is a question for inquiry do when the consequences of law-conformity or
what the exact mix is at a given historical moment law-violation are clear and known ahead of time.
(Winston 1986 and forthcoming). Normatively, it involves acknowledgment by the
lawmaker of the value of enabling citizens to
develop their moral competence and exercise
Fuller, Lon Luvois 3

moral agency. Thus, respect for the moral agency Mill’s phrase) – with the sole constraint that each
of citizens is intimately connected to the prima individual’s freedom to choose ends must be com-
facie duties of the internal morality. For a law- patible with the like freedom of others (Fuller
maker to acknowledge and act on these duties, and 1969, 162, 207, 210). One could argue that this
thus govern by rules, is to stand in moral relation is the true idea of the rule of law: Individuals are
to legal subjects. governed by rules, not persons, only if the rules
Importantly, this morality of lawmaking are truly impersonal, not directives from law-
emerges from the character of the enterprise, not makers to citizens about they must or ought to
an external source. It is not derived from a defini- do. Thus, there is a special moral quality in
tion (or concept) but from imagining the activity governing by rules if they are general in this
itself and what it takes to carry it out successfully. sense. Of course, this is an idealization of law in
The activity is carried out by certain officials – in a certain direction. By providing baselines – min-
particular, legislators, but also, secondarily, imal conditions for citizens working out a satis-
judges and lawyers. The lawmaker who labors to factory life together – law, in Fuller’s view,
make statutes intelligible, consistent, and prospec- facilitates the release of human energies in mutu-
tive is fulfilling a moral responsibility to citizens ally beneficial ways.
drawn from an understanding of why govern- The second step in getting the relationship
ments have statutes at all. Thus, the internal right is Fuller’s focus on the legislator’s task of
morality of law consists in just those standards providing mechanisms that enable citizens’
that must be honored if the right relationship choices to become socially effective. The exercise
between lawmaker and citizen is to be maintained, of effective agency – freedom, as Fuller under-
as components of the institution’s distinctive stands it – depends crucially on which institutions
mission. exist and how they function. The upshot is that
freedom consists in the availability of the institu-
tional devices by which each citizen’s choices are
The Ideal of Freedom brought into meaningful relation with the choices
of other citizens. Underlining this point, it is strik-
Fuller understands that the internal morality of ing that the only social mechanism Fuller dis-
law is neutral over a wide range of moral issues, cusses at length in his lectures on freedom is
but it is not neutral in its view of human beings. voting – joining with others in this specific form
Rather, it is committed to the proposition that of decision making (Winston 2001, 316–327). He
human beings are, or can become, responsible does not talk about religious freedom or the right
moral agents, and ought to be so treated by man- to privacy; rather, he talks about a mechanism by
agers of the legal order. How is this done? Fuller which citizens make choices together – in a dem-
offers two suggestions. ocratic, participatory way. Thus, to be free is to be
The first appears in the internal morality, in the enfranchised in this broad sense; it is to be
prominence Fuller gives to the requirement of empowered to participate in collective self-
generality. By this, he has in mind not simply government. This requires a kind of activist legis-
generality of language, referring to classes of lature, in the sense that it has a distinct responsi-
actions and persons instead of specific individuals bility to facilitate citizen engagement in the
or acts. Beyond that (and more controversially), processes of civic life.
laws have the requisite generality when they do
not embody or reflect legislators’ preferences
regarding what is good or worthwhile. Law- The Study of Eunomics
makers aim, rather, to set baselines or guideposts
and promulgate only such laws as allow or enable Fuller’s understanding of the special affinity
citizens to choose their own ends – to pursue their between law and freedom reveals another respect
own good in their own way (to borrow John Stuart in which he departs from other authors, namely, in
4 Fuller, Lon Luvois

his commitment to legal pluralism. Law is not a striving; they embody moral aspirations and
unitary phenomenon that takes the same form define moral relationships. The central task of
wherever it appears. It consists, rather, of the eunomics is to describe these models in detail
diverse set of social processes that yield authori- and assess the possibilities for their realization.
tative rules or decisions – only a subset of which is The contextual factors that enhance or impair the
found, at least in a dominant role, in any specific effectiveness of particular structures determine
legal community. The main processes that Fuller whether or not an existing social problem can be
discussed at length are adjudication, mediation, collectively managed, and how. We want to know
voting, legislation, contract, and managerial where a mechanism works and where it does not
direction (i.e., administration) (Winston 2001). and cannot be made to. Thus, eunomics is a
Each process has two principal components. branch of moral sociology, involving evaluative
First, it has a characteristic structure that makes judgments about the interplay of means and ends.
it suitable for reaching a certain kind of outcome It deals with the conditions for the effective pur-
(a decision, an agreement, a rule) and not others. suit of collective aims and ideals, as well as
The idea of this structure serves to guide the criteria for assessing their appropriateness – and
functioning of any actual institution in which the for reconstructing them – in light of available
model is operative. It is thus a limiting conception, means.
a principle of order for the arrangement of human Here, too, Fuller is concerned with what it
affairs within its domain. Second, its constitutive means to be a professional. One of his criticisms
elements include characteristic moral principles – of legal realism was that it turns lawyers into
for example, impartiality (for adjudication), masters of technique without regard to the values
equality (for contract), legality (for legislation) – they serve. For realists, law is a neutral means to
which specify the distinctive moral duties of offi- ends that originate outside itself. Realism thereby
cials, and perhaps others, who act within the excludes from the scope of professional responsi-
structure. These principles constitute the internal bility a lawyer’s duty to think about the values at
morality of the process in question. (Thus, each stake in alternative legal processes. This is con-
legal process has its own, distinctive internal trary to what Fuller believes lawyers actually do,
morality.) Like principles of due process, their which is to devise frameworks into which citi-
moral importance is largely independent of what- zens’ various interests can be accommodated in
ever connection they may have to desired ways that are fair, decent, and workable. Whether
outcomes. arbitrating a dispute, drawing up a contract, or
Although Fuller never offers a comprehensive drafting a statute, the common thread is problems
account of the forms of legal order, he coined a of human organization, and the crucial role of
term for the theoretical effort he envisioned: lawyers is to serve (in one of his favorite expres-
eunomics, which he defines as “the science or sions) as architects of social structure. Such a
study of good order and workable arrangements.” responsibility cannot be carried out without a
His essays on specific forms are his “exercises in simultaneous focus on means and ends. Thus,
eunomics” (Winston 2001). Fuller views the the lawyer’s job is not simply to think about
diverse forms dynamically, that is, not just as what legally can be done but about what ought
determinate configurations of norms or rules but to be done, all things considered.
as reasoned responses to problematic situations This is a very demanding view of the legal
common to human societies. This approach brings professional. Is Fuller similarly demanding of cit-
out their moral as well as their purposive aspects. izens? Does he expect institutional forms to gen-
Since people reflect on what they are doing, they erate moral outcomes without presupposing
construct models of possible structures, which certain qualities of citizens – civic-minded, well-
then guide the emergence of specific practices informed, self-restrained? Are institutional
and provide standpoints for evaluating their suc- arrangements meant to compensate for a lack of
cess. Thus, the models are focal points of human virtue and intelligence? Fuller’s stress is on the
Fuller, Lon Luvois 5

limits of what law can do. With his special empha- Conclusion
sis on fostering decency and fairness in human
relationships, Fuller is sufficiently confident in the In recent years, some philosophers have come to
good nature of men and women to be optimistic believe, belatedly, that Fuller was right to reject
about their ability to achieve a program of living the dichotomy of is and ought and now embrace
together. This meliorism infuses his ideas of law their admixture, at least in certain contexts. They
and democracy, and presupposes that conflicts can realize the difficulty that arises when the analytic
be resolved through discussion and public distinction between fact and value is turned into a
accountability. The role of law in these efforts is metaphysical dualism. Hilary Putnam, for exam-
more facilitative than directive. Instead of impos- ple, observes that logical empiricism and positiv-
ing prescriptive rules backed by threats or micro- ism led philosophers astray; while not referring
managing administrative agencies, legislators explicitly to Fuller’s work, he has turned for
should ensure the availability of guideposts and enlightenment to the writings of John Dewey,
mechanisms by which citizens can exercise effec- who was one of Fuller’s principal intellectual
tive and responsible choice on their own. Thus, guides (Putnam 2002). Other recent writings of
Fuller is a theorist of private much more than of importance include illuminating work on the
public law, emphasizing voluntary forms of coop- social underpinnings of legal order in everyday
eration that enable citizens to develop the moral human interaction (van der Burg 2014), and the
dispositions necessary to becoming productive reform of legal institutions so as to better realize
members of society, including the capacity to democratic ideals (Aboulafia and Shook 2012) –
make effective and responsible decisions and to the core of Fuller’s eunomics project. It is heart-
practice a democratic way of life. ening to observe that we have entered a period for
For this to work well, the affinities between rediscovering (Witteveen and van der Burg 1999)
legal rules and social expectations must be close. and reclaiming (Rundle 2012) Fuller’s pioneering
In some places, Fuller pictures law as emergent work on legal morality – evident in books, sym-
out of social practices, the articulate or formalized posia, doctoral dissertations, and journal articles
expression of pervasive and settled conventions. in countries around the world, from North Amer-
Law then does not consist only of discrete and ica, to the Netherlands, to China, and elsewhere.
readily identified official declarations; it is also
continuous with norms and understandings that
are inchoate and evolving. What lies beyond offi- Cross-References
cial notice at any moment is broader and deeper
than, and gives shape and force to, what is evident ▶ American Legal Realism
on the surface. This is not to say that legal rules ▶ Legal Pragmatism
always do or should reflect existing social norms. ▶ Procedural Natural Law
But law is embedded in social practices, and these ▶ Types of Legal Theory
practices provide a critical resource for judges and
other interpreters of legal rules – a context of
expectations, social purposes, and principles for References
deciding cases where the articulate law is indeter-
minate or pulls in opposite directions. Conversely, Aboulafia M, Shook JR (eds) (2012) Contemporary prag-
matism. Rodopi, Amsterdam
the more decision making departs from everyday
van der Burg W (2014) The dynamics of law and morality:
understandings of fair and impartial treatment of a pluralist account of legal interactionism. Ashgate,
legitimate claims, the more it must rely on coer- Farnham
cive threats and hence the less authority it has. In Fuller LL (1958) Positivism and fidelity to law – a reply to
professor Hart. Harv Law Rev 71:630–672
that state of affairs, positive law undermines
Fuller LL (1966) The law in quest of itself. Beacon Press,
sociality. Boston. (Northwestern University Press, Evanston,
1940)
6 Fuller, Lon Luvois

Fuller LL (1969) The morality of law, rev edn. Yale Uni- Winston K (ed) (2001) The principles of social order:
versity Press, New Haven selected essays of Lon L. Fuller, rev edn. Hart Publish-
Putnam H (2002) The collapse of the fact/value dichotomy. ing, Oxford
Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Winston K (forthcoming) The ideal element in law
Rundle K (2012) Forms liberate: reclaiming the jurispru- revisited. In: Modern German non-positivism: from
dence of Lon L Fuller. Hart Publishing, Oxford Radbruch to Alexy. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen
Winston K (1986) The ideal element in a definition of law. Witteveen WJ, van der Burg W (eds) (1999) Rediscovering
Law Philos 5:89–111 Fuller: essays on implicit law and institutional design.
Amsterdam University Press, Amsterdam

You might also like