Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 26

Working Papers Series, Paper WP-06-01

Objective Functions in Agricultural Decision-Making:


A Comparison of the Effects of Expected Utility, Regret-
Adjusted Expected Utility, and Prospect Theory
Maximization

Carlos Laciana1, Elke Weber2, Federico Bert3, Guillermo Podestá,4


Xavier González,1 and David Letson 4

1
Facultad de Ingeniería, Universidad de Buenos Aires
2
Center for Research on Environmental Decisions, Columbia University
3
Facultad de Agronomía, Universidad de Buenos Aires
4
Rosenstiel School of Marine and Atmospheric Science, University of Miami

This document series presents work in progress. Please do not cite this work without contacting the
authors. Contact: Dr. Elke Weber (euw2@columbia.edu). The research was supported by an NSF
Biocomplexity in the Environment grant (BE-0410348), an NSF grant under the Decision Making under
Uncertainty Initiative (SES-0345840), and a NOAA Human Dimensions grant (GC04-159).
ABSTRACT

Simulated outcomes of agricultural production decisions in the Argentine Pampas


were used to examine objective functions with greater psychological plausibility
than expected utility (EU) maximization, in particular, regret-adjusted expected
utility and prospect theory value maximization. For each objective function, we
provide the distribution of production enterprises on a hypothetical 600 ha farm
optimal for either land owners or tenants (owners are subject to an optimization
constraint that reflects a crop-rotation regimen). We provide an explicit
functional form for each objective function, propose an equivalent, but more
mathematically-tractable formulation for the prospect theory value-function
maximization, and explore a broad parameter space. Optimal enterprise
allocation differs for the three objective functions and for different parameter
values, especially for land tenants, whose enterprise allocation is less constrained.
The effects of regret are minor compared to the effects of loss aversion and gain-
loss reference point of prospect theory. Our results demonstrate in a non-
laboratory decision context that psychologically plausible deviations from EU
maximization matter. They can be used to explain observed land allocation
decisions inconsistent with EU maximization and to identify segments of decision
makers who differ in decision objectives or optimization constraints as the result
of socioeconomic/demographic or psychological differences.
DRAFT

1. INTRODUCTION outcomes is determined entirely by the final


wealth they generate regardless of context,
1.1 Historical evolution of theories of i.e., that it is an absolute or reference-
rational choice independent construct. Yet, decision-makers’
evaluation of outcomes appears to be
The objective function or choice criterion that
influenced by a variety of relative
decision makers seek to optimize has been the
comparisons (Kahneman 2003). In one such
object of theoretical and empirical
comparison, decision-makers contrast the
investigation for centuries (Machina 1987;
outcome of their decision to what might have
Starmer 2000; Schoemaker 1982). The first
happened had they made a different choice.
candidate, introduced in the mid-17th century,
When, for the same state of the world, the
was the maximization of expected monetary
expected outcome of an action compares
values. This concept soon encountered
unfavorably with the expected outcome of a
problems because it conflicted with the
different (counterfactual) action, decision-
intuition of educated decision makers, as in
makers experience regret. Regret theory,
the so-called St. Petersburg paradox, where
independently introduced by Loomes and
people pay only a small amount of money for
Sugden (1982) and Bell (1982), introduces
a game of infinite mathematical expectation.
the effect of anticipated regret as a correction
To resolve the St. Petersburg paradox,
to classical utility theory. It formalizes the
Bernoulli (1954/1738) proposed that people
process by which decision-makers experience
maximize the expected utility of wealth rather
regret about their action if their realized
than expected monetary value, postulating
outcome is worse than the counterfactual
that money and wealth have diminishing
outcome, or rejoice if their realized outcome
returns. The work by von Neumann and
is better. Consistent with a negativity effect
Morgenstern (1944, 1947) provided an
found in many judgment domains (Weber
explicit formulation of expected utility (EU)
1994), feelings of regret are stronger than
and an axiomatic foundation. Subsequent
feelings of rejoicement. Since people
extensions and variations are described by
anticipate experiences of regret, they choose
Schoemaker (1982). The EU utility model has
such that their course of action minimizes
been central in the analysis of choice under
anticipated post-decisional regret. That is,
risk and uncertainty. It has been successful
regret theory predicts that people act not to
not only because of its compelling axiomatic
maximize expected utility but to maximize an
foundation and ability to describe economic
expected utility that has been modified by
choices, but also because of its mathematical
consideration of anticipated regret.
tractability (Woodward 1998).
Minimization of anticipated decision regret is
Despite its obvious strengths, EU a goal frequently observed, even if it results
maximization as the (sole) objective of risky in lower material profitability (Markman et
choice has encountered some opposition in al. 1993).
recent years. There is both experimental and
Prospect theory (Kahneman Tversky 1979)
real-world evidence that individuals often do
and its modification, cumulative prospect
not behave in a manner consistent with EU
theory (Tversky Kahneman 1992; Fennema
theory (Camerer 2000; McFadden 1999),
Wakker 1997) currently have become the
including the classical demonstrations
most prominent alternatives to EU theory.
referred to as the Allais (1953) and Ellsberg
Prospect theory formalizes another relative
(1961) paradoxes. A central assumption of
comparison observed when decision makers
EU theory is that the utility of decision
evaluate the utility of decision outcomes. Its

1
DRAFT

value function v is defined in terms of relative and prospect theories. Formulations of these
gains or losses, that is positive or negative three objective functions are applied to a real-
deviations from a reference point. Value world optimization problem in agricultural
therefore is determined by changes in wealth, management. EU maximization is a widely
rather than reference-independent states of used criterion in agricultural economics, and
wealth as in utility theory (Kahneman 2003). thus is a useful benchmark against which to
Furthermore, the value function for losses is compare the results of other objective
steeper than the value function for gains, functions. Given the increasing evidence that
resulting in a sharp kink at the reference affective processes play an important and
point. This feature of the value function often decisive role in many decision
models the phenomenon of loss aversion, i.e., situations (e.g., Damasio 1995; Loewenstein
the observation that the negative experience et al. 2001) and the fact that the feeling of
or disutility of a loss of a given magnitude is regret probably has important learning
larger than the positive experience or utility functions, we explore the implications of
of a gain of the same magnitude. Empirical introducing a regret correction to expected
studies have consistently confirmed loss utility. Finally, we consider prospect theory
aversion as an important aspect of human for its ability to resolve the Allais and
choice behavior (Schmidt Zank 2005; Ellsberg paradoxes and to accommodate other
Camerer 2005). Rabin (1998) emphasized the phenomena inconsistent with EU theory,
growing importance of loss aversion as a including real-world choice behavior in
psychological finding which should be diverse contexts (Camerer 2000). Prospect
integrated into economic analysis. In theory has received limited attention in the
particular, loss aversion is the most important agricultural economics or agricultural
explanation for phenomena such as the decision-making literature. Collins et al.
endowment effect (Thaler 1980), the status (2001) used prospect theory to re-interpret
quo bias (Samuelson Zeckhauser 1988; changing risk preferences in grass seed
Johnson Goldstein 2003), and the equity growers, and Reusser et al. (2004) used it as
premium puzzle (Benartzi Thaler 1995). In one of their models when examining how
another deviation from EU theory, prospect uncertainty propagated throughout an agent-
theory predicts that risk attitudes depend on based model. Eggert and Martinsson (2004)
how a problem is framed, in particular, that elicit the risk preferences of commercial
risk-averse behavior will predominate if fishers and find them more consistent with
outcomes are perceived to be gains (with a prospect theory than EU. We argue that as
concave value function), but that risk-seeking proven and mathematically tractable
behavior will predominate if outcomes are alternatives to the EU model become
perceived to be losses (with a convex value available, agricultural and resource
function). Finally, prospect theory differs economists along with other economists
from EU theory in the way it handles should begin to consider alternative objective
probability information, although this is not functions and to explore how they might
relevant to the work presented here. improve analysis and insight (Woodward,
1998).
1.2 Objective functions considered in this
study 1.3 Objectives and contributions
In this paper we compare and contrast the The main objective of this paper is to
objective functions or choice criteria examine the nature and magnitude of
associated with EU, regret-adjusted utility, differences in the agricultural production

2
DRAFT

decisions identified as “optimal” by each function) will allow researchers to


maximization of the objective functions identify different segments of decision
associated with EU, regret, and prospect makers who might differ in objective
theory. Most studies comparing these choice functions or optimization constraints as the
models have focused on (often hypothetical) result of socioeconomic/demographic or
monetary lottery choices in laboratory psychological differences.
studies. It is important to determine the
extent to which these choice theories make 1.4 A case study: agricultural production
different prescriptions for or predictions of decisions in the Argentine Pampas
behavior in more complex, real-world Our case study targets agricultural production
contexts and to understand the nature of these in the Pampas of central eastern Argentina.
differences. Much is at stake, since those We focus on agricultural decision-making in
deviations matter a great deal in terms of the Pampas for several reasons. (1) In non-
what we need from agriculture, such as rural centrally planned economies like Argentina,
incomes, food security, export earnings and agricultural production decisions are
agro-environmental amenities. overwhelmingly made by individual decision-
makers (farmers, professional farm managers,
The paper makes three types of contributions.
technical advisors). The ability to predict
(1) We provide explicit functional forms for
optimal decisions at the individual level and
objective functions for which accepted forms
to model differences in (presumably optimal)
do not exist (e.g., for regret theory). For
observed decisions as resulting from either
functions that are incompatible with widely
differences in objective functions or in
used optimization tools, we develop
parameter values within the same objective
equivalent but more tractable formulations.
function, therefore, has much utility. (2)
For instance, the discontinuity in the
Agricultural production involves a variety of
derivative of prospect theory’s value function real-world decisions, with important
provides a problem for the GAMS
economic consequences and thus is a useful
optimization software (Gill et al., 2000)
test bed for the exploration of the
widely used by economists. Although other implications of alternative choice theories and
algorithms can handle such discontinuities, their objective functions. (3) The annual
they tend to get unstable solutions and users cycle of agricultural production provides rich
are warned to verify results. Whether explicit opportunities (i.e., ready replications and
functional forms for objective functions do variations) for the study of real-world
not exist or are in need of improvement, it is decisions. (4) The collection of agricultural
important for the decision analytic statistics is common and institutionalized in
community to agree on common formulations many countries therefore data about
in order to allow for the replication and agricultural production decisions are more
comparison of results. We hope that our available and more reliable than decisions in
paper will contribute to such standardization. other sectors. (5) The scale of production
(2) It provides a mechanism to explain systems in the Argentine Pampas and
observed land allocation decisions that are available technology are very similar to those
inconsistent with EU maximization with of other important production regions (e.g.,
reference to alternative objective functions. the American Corn Belt), which makes our
(3) Its identification of the agricultural results applicable to a broader set of regions.
production decisions that are optimal with
respect to the three objective functions (for a
broad range of plausible parameter values for

3
DRAFT

2. OBJECTIVE FUNCTIONS q (defined in the same way as for expected


CONSIDERED utility) can be written as
n

∑ p {u (w ) − k g (Δu )}
2.1 EU maximization
RTEU (q ) = i i i . (3)
We define a risky prospect i =1

q = ( p1 , w1 ;....; pn , wn ) as the ensemble of


This expression depends not just on possible
possible wealth/outcomes wi with associated outcomes/wealth wi , but also contains an
probabilities pi that are non-negative and add additively separable regret function that is
up to one. A common formulation (Hardaker increasing in the difference between the
et al. 2004, p. 104) states that a decision- utilities of the realized and unrealized
maker evaluates the expected utility of outcomes. The correction to utility due to
prospect q as anticipated regret is captured by the
difference
EU (q) = ∑ pi u ( wi ) . (1)
i Δui = u ( wmax ) − u ( wi ) , (4)
The real-valued utility function u (⋅) is given by
where wmax is the maximum outcome that
Pratt (1964) as:
could have been realized in state of the world
⎧ w1− r i, under a counterfactual action. The
⎪ if r ≠ 1
u ( w) ∝ ⎨1 − r , (2) difference Δui must be ≥ 0. Factor k ,
⎪⎩ ln w f r =1 initially introduced by Loomes and Sugden
(1982) and subsequently used by Braun and
where r is the coefficient of constant relative Muermann (2004), weights the effect of
risk aversion (CRRA). CRRA implies that regret.
preferences among risky prospects are
unchanged if all payoffs are multiplied by a The regret function g (⋅) in Eq. 3 needs to
positive constant (Hardaker et al., 2004). The increase as a function of Δui . To obtain a
curvature of the utility function, defined by
parameter r , captures all information more specific functional form for g (⋅) , Braun
concerning risk attitude. and Muermann (2004) proposed three
desirable properties for it:
2.2 Regret-corrected expected utility
maximization g (0) = 0 , (5a)

A formulation for the expected value of the g ′( Δu ) > 0 ∀Δu , and (5b)
utility of outcomes corrected by anticipated g "(Δu ) > 0 ∀Δu , (5c)
regret was presented by Braun and Muermann
(2004), who called this function Regret-
where g ' and g '' indicate, respectively, the
Theoretical Expected Utility (RTEU). Their
formulation is applicable to continuous states first and second derivatives d d Δu . The first
of the world, whereas our application condition (Eq. 5a) states that when the
provides discrete states of the world difference with respect to the optimum value
corresponding to different cropping cycles. is null there is no regret. The second
The discrete form of RTEU for risky prospect condition (Eq. 5b) states that g (⋅) ought to be
an increasing function, implying that when

4
DRAFT

the difference between the counterfactual parameter, that separates perceived gains
option and the chosen option increases, regret from perceived losses. The value of this
also must increase. difference is defined by

Although the first two requirements seem v ( Δw) = h( Δw) Δw


α

reasonable, we see no compelling arguments (8)


for the third condition (Eq. 5c).
Function h(Δw) is the step function
Furthermore, Laciana et al. (2005) showed
that this condition cannot apply if regret
⎧ 1 if Δw ≥ 0
theory is to produce the pattern of preferences h(Δw) = ⎨
⎩ −λ if Δw < 0 (9)
described by the Allais (1953) paradox. To do
so, Laciana et al. (1995) show that function
g (⋅) must instead satisfy the condition where λ is a parameter ( λ > 1 ) that reflects
the degree of loss aversion. The exponent α
g ′′( Δu ) < 0 ∀Δu . (5d) in Eq. 8 ranges between 0 and 1 and describes
the nonlinearity of the value function,
Laciana et al. (2005) propose the following therefore accounting for the degree of risk
explicit form for function g (⋅) that satisfies aversion (concavity) in the gain region and
the first two conditions posed by Braun and risk seeking (convexity) in the loss region.
Muermann (2004) and the modified third
The evaluation of risky prospects is based on
condition. 1
subjective probability weights that do not
always correspond to the objective
g (Δu ) = 1 − β Δu , (6) probabilities. Tversky and Kahneman (1992)
propose the nonlinear function Ω ( p )
where parameter β ( 0 ≤ β < 1 ) must be fitted
from experimental results and describes the pγ
decision maker’s sensitivity to the magnitude Ω ( p) = (10)
( )
1
p γ + (1 − p )
γ γ
of Δui , with a more differentiated response
for larger values of β .
to model the subjective weight of event
2.3 Prospect theory’s value maximization probabilities, which overweights objective
probabilities below 0.3 or so and
In prospect theory (Kahneman Tversky underweights larger probabilities. The value
1979), the subjective value of a prospect is of Ω ( p ) depends on positive parameter γ ,
defined as:
that must be empirically estimated.
V (q ) = ∑ Ω ( pi ) v (Δwi ) , (7)
i
3. CASE STUDY DETAILS
where Δwi represents the difference between
In this paper, we identify agricultural
outcome wi and a reference point wref , a free production decisions that are optimal under
different objective functions. The set of
1
The function proposed by Laciana et al. was decisions examined are related to the
intended to reproduce specifically the pattern production of cereals and oilseeds in the
of preferences presented by Allais (1953). Pampas region of central-eastern Argentina,
one of the most important agricultural regions

5
DRAFT

in the world (Hall et al. 1992). In this section, options for the study area. Each enterprise
we first describe the production systems in involves the combination of (a) a given crop
this region. We then define a set of cropping (maize, full-cycle soybean and wheat
enterprises that encompasses a realistic range soybean), (b) various agronomic decisions
of management options and initial soil (cultivar/hybrid, planting date, fertilization
conditions for the typical crops in the region, options), and (c) a set of initial conditions
namely maize, soybean, and a wheat-soybean (water and nitrogen in the soil at planting)
doublecrop. Next we describe how yields and that result from previous production
economic returns are simulated for each decisions. That is, several enterprises may be
cropping enterprise using historical climate associated with the same crop, although
data, biophysical models, and realistic cost involving different management options.
estimates. These results are used as input to Management variables and their simulated
different optimization procedures, described levels for each cropping enterprise defined
in Section 4. are listed in Table 1.

3.1 The area of study 3.3 Simulation of yields: agronomic models


The climate, soils, and cropping systems of Yields for each enterprise were simulated
the Argentine Pampas have been using the crop models in the Decision
characterized by Hall et al. (1992). In Support System for Agrotechnology Transfer
particular, we focus on the region near package (Jones et al. 1998): Generic-CERES
Pergamino (33º 56' S, 60º 33' W), the most (Ritchie et al. 1998) for maize and wheat, and
productive subregion of the Pampas (Paruelo CROPGRO (Boote et al. 1998) for soybean.
& Sala 1993). Two characteristics of These models have been calibrated and
agricultural production in the study region validated under field conditions in several
have implications for the optimization production environments including the
described below. First, agriculture in the Pampas (Guevara et al. 1999; Meira et al.
Pampas is market-oriented and technology- 1999; Mercau et al. 2001). The information
intensive. As a consequence, a broad required to run the DSSAT models includes:
spectrum of agronomic management options (i) daily weather data (maximum and
exists and can be explored in the optimization minimum temperature, precipitation, solar
process. Second, a considerable proportion of radiation), (ii) “genetic coefficients” that
the area currently farmed is not owned by the describe physiological processes and
farmers exploiting it. Very short land leases developmental differences among crop
(usually one year) provide incentives for hybrids or varieties, (iii) a description of crop
tenants to maximize short-term profits via management, and (iv) soil parameters,
highly-profitable crops. In contrast, land including soil moisture and N content at the
owners tend to rotate crops to steward long- beginning of simulations. Historical (1931-
term sustainability of production and soil 2001) daily weather data for Pergamino
quality. Given the differences in decision- provided information re category (i). Genetic
making goals and constraints between land coefficients, the management options that
owners and tenants, we model the two groups defined the enterprises, and likely ranges of
separately. initial soil conditions were provided by
Asociación Argentina de Consorcios
3.2 Crop enterprises Regionales de Experimentación Agrícola
We defined 64 different cropping enterprises (AACREA), a non-profit farmers’ group
that reflect a realistic range of cultivation (similar in goals to the US Agricultural

6
DRAFT

Table 1. Management variables and their simulated levels for each cropping enterprise defined. The
64 different enterprises are the result of combining different levels of each variable considered. For
instance, the 24 enterprises involving maize result from combing one genotype, two planting dates,
three doses of N fertilizer, one row spacing, two levels of initial soil water, and two levels of initial
soil N, and (1 x 2 x 2 x 2 x 3 x 1 = 24).

Crop
Management variables Wheat -
Maize Soybean
Soybean
Scorpion
N 3901
Genotype DK 752 (wheat)
DM 4800 DM 4800 (soy)
15 Sep 25 Oct 10 Jun1
Planting date
15 Oct 15 Nov 10 Jul1
50 0 40 (wheat)
Fertilizer added
75 60 (wheat)
(kg N ha-1)
100 80 (wheat)
0.70 0.35 0.19 (wheat)
Row spacing (m)
0.70 0.52 0.52 (soy)
Available soil water at 80 80 70
planting (%) 100 100 90
Available soil N at 50 40
50
planting (kg N ha-1) 70 60
Number of enterprises 24 16 24

Extension Services) that partnered with us in region. We computed net economic returns
this study. per hectare π ij for year i and enterprise j as
the difference between income and costs:
Simulations assumed no irrigation, a very
infrequent practice in the Pampas. For each π ij = Yij Pj − ( F j + Vij + Si + Ti ) .
enterprise, 70 simulated yields were obtained (11)
(one for each cropping cycle in the 1931-
2001 historical record used). Gross income per hectare (Yij Pj ) were the
product of simulated yield for a year and
3.4 Simulation of economic outcomes enterprise (Yij ) and a constant output price
Economic outcomes were simulated for a for each crop ( Pj ) . Assumed output prices
hypothetical 600-hectare farm, the median were the median of 2000-2005 prices during
size of AACREA farms in the Pergamino the month when most of the harvest is

7
DRAFT

marketed (April, May, and January for maize, high costs of land around Pergamino, is that
soybean, and wheat, respectively). After the entire 600-ha area of the hypothetical
deducting export taxes charged by the farm is cultivated.
Argentine government, these prices were
78.9, 166.0, and 112.0 US $ ton-1 for maize, (iv) Income tax (Ti ) applies equally to land
soybean and wheat, respectively. owners and tenants and was computed as
follows:
Four different kinds of costs were involved in
the computation of net returns per hectare: ⎧b(π − a ) + c if π ≥a
Ti = ⎨ (12)
(i) Fixed costs ( F j ) for enterprise j are ⎩ c if π < a,
independent of yield. For land owners, fixed
where a is a threshold income above which
costs included: (a) crop production inputs
farmers pay an average tax rate b = 0.32.
(e.g., fertilizer, seed, field labors), and
Below a , farmers pay a minimum tax
(b) farmer’s salary, health insurance, and a
assumed to be 59.33 $ ha-1. To simplify
fixed fiscal contribution. For land tenants,
calculations, an average annual income π of
fixed costs also included (c) land rental
177.5 $ ha-1 (57.6 $ ha-1) was assumed for
(assumed to be 232.5 $ ha-1, equivalent to the
owners (tenants).
price of 1.4 tons of soybean) and
(d) management costs (12 $ ha-1).

(ii) Variable costs (Vij ) are a function of yield 4. OPTIMIZATION


PROCEDURE
on year i for enterprise j . These costs
included: (a) harvesting costs, estimated as A whole farm production model was used to
8% of gross income (Yij Pj ) , identify optimal decisions for the objective
(b) transportation costs (about 10 $ ton-1), functions associated with EU, regret, and
(c) sales tax and commissions, estimated as prospect theories. The choice variable in the
G
8% of gross income. Variable costs were the optimization is the vector x = ( x1 ,...., x64 ) that
same for land owners and tenants. includes the area in the 600-hectare
hypothetical farm allocated to each of the 64
(iii) Structural costs ( Si ) are applicable only alternative cropping enterprises considered.
to land owners and covered: (a) maintenance Different land amounts allocated to the 64
of farm infrastructure, (b) real estate taxes, enterprises were considered by the
and (c) management and technical advice. optimization of each objective function. The
Structural costs are independent of farm optimization was performed using algorithm
activities or enterprise yields. For the sake of MINO5 in the GAMS software package (Gill
simplicity, however, they were approximated et al., 2000).
following a criterion used by AACREA: they
were a percentage (23%, 18%, and 20% for 4.1 Wealth and income
maize, soybean and wheat-soybean For comparability, all objective functions are
respectively) of income per ha after expressed in terms of a decision-maker’s
subtracting variable costs (Yij Pj − Vij ) . wealth, either in an absolute sense (for EU
Because structural costs are incurred even if and regret-adjusted EU), or as a difference
part of the farm is not cultivated, an implicit from a specified reference level (in prospect
but not unreasonable assumption, given the

8
DRAFT

theory). The total wealth of a decision-maker G


where x * = ( x1* ,...., x6*4 ) indicates the
in year i is proportion of land allocated to each enterprise
that maximizes the value of EU.
wi = w0 + π i , (13)
4.3 Regret-corrected Utility Optimization
where w0 is the decision-maker’s initial G
The goal is to obtain the decision vector x ∗
wealth (i.e., prior to production decisions for G
that maximizes the function RTEU ( x ) given
year i ) and π i is the farm-wide income
by Eq. 3:
during year i , after deducting costs. Farm-
wide income π i is calculated as: G G
max x RTEU ( x ) = RTEU ( x * ) . (18)
m
π i = ∑ x jπ ij , (14)
This maximization is performed in the same
j =1 way as for expected utility.

where π ij is the net margin for year i and 4.4 Prospect Theory Value Optimization
enterprise j (Eq. 11) and x j is the amount of In prospect theory, value is defined by
land allocated to enterprise (i.e., a
j changes in wealth rather than reference-
G independent states of wealth. Outcomes wi
component of the land allocation vector x ).
are evaluated as gains or losses with respect
4.2 Expected Utility Optimization to a reference value wref :
The expected utility (Eq. 1) of final wealth
Δwi = wi − wref . (19)
can be expressed as:

G n
G One plausible reference value of wealth that
EU ( x ) = ∑ pi u ⎡⎣ wi ( x ) ⎤⎦ , (15) determines whether a farmer thinks of another
i =1
wealth level as a gain or a loss is the income
where pi is the probability of a given climate wr that a farmer could achieve with minimal
effort (e.g., by renting his/her land) added to
scenario for year i . A climate scenario is
the decision-maker’s initial wealth :
defined as the climate conditions over an
entire production cycle. We assume that all
wref = w0 + wr . (20)
climate scenarios in the historical record have
the same probability, i.e. pi = 1 , where n is
n Combining Eqs. 13 and 19 with Eq. 20 we
the number of cropping cycles in the obtain:
historical climate data (in this case, 70 years).
Therefore, we can write Δwi = π i − wr . (21)

G 1 n G
EU ( x ) = ∑ u ⎡⎣ wi ( x ) ⎤⎦ . (16)
The total value function for prospect theory
n i =1 (Eq. 7) then can be rewritten as:

The next step is the optimization G n


G
V ( x ) = ∑ Ω ( pi ) v ⎡⎣ Δwi ( x ) ⎤⎦ . (22)
G G i =1
max x EU ( x ) = EU ( x * ) , (17)

9
DRAFT

As for previous objective functions, all conservation and control of pests and
climate scenarios are assumed to have the diseases. In contrast, land tenants seek high
same probability (i.e., pi = 1 ), therefore profits during short leases (usually one year)
n and thus usually select enterprises with the
Ω ( pi ) is independent of i . Rewriting Eq. 22, greatest economic returns. The clear
we obtain differences in enterprise allocation between
land tenure regimes suggest that we explore
G ⎛1⎞ n G optimal decisions separately for land owners
V ( x ) = Ω ⎜ ⎟ ∑ v ⎡⎣ Δwi ( x ) ⎤⎦ , (23) and tenants.
⎝ n ⎠ i =1
With three major cropping systems (maize,
which indicates that the constant Ω 1 ( n) is soybean, and a wheat-soybean double crop)
irrelevant for the optimization; thus one needs the rotation advocated by AACREA allocates
about 33.3% of the land to each of these
not worry about the functional form of Ω.
cropping systems in a given year. To allow
The optimization is performed in a way
owners some flexibility in land allocation, we
analogous to Eq. 16:
introduced two constraints in the optimization
G G procedure: land assigned to a crop could be
max x V ( x ) = V ( x * ) . (24) no less than 25%, or more than 45% of the
farm area. These constraints did not apply to
Optimizing the value function with the land tenants, who could allocate the entire
GAMS software (Gill et al., 2000) available farmed area to a single crop. The lack of
to us was problematic because of the allocation constraints is consistent with the
discontinuity of function h ( ⋅) (defined in observed increase in mono-cropping of
Eq. 9) at Δwi = 0 (where prospect theory’s soybean that has occurred in the Pampas in
the last few years (Satorre 2005).
value function has a sharp kink and is not
differentiable). To address the problem, we 4.6 Parameter space explored for each
used a continuous function h (⋅) that is objective function
numerically equivalent to h(⋅) :
As discussed in Section 2, each objective
function has a set of parameters. In some
h ( x) = 1 ⎡⎣1 − λ + (1 + λ ) tanh ( ρ x ) ⎤⎦ (25) cases, the value of a given parameter
2
characterizes a personality characteristic (e.g.,
where ρ is an arbitrary parameter such that degree of risk aversion or loss aversion) that
ρ > 1 ; large values of ρ (we used ρ =10) may vary among decision-makers. In other
cases, there are no widely accepted values for
reproduce function h(⋅) more closely.
a parameter, therefore a broad range of
Justification for this approximation can be plausible values must be considered. In this
found in Laciana and Weber (2005). section, we describe and justify the central (or
nominal) parameter values; the full set of
4.5 Optimization constraints values explored is listed in Table 2
As previously mentioned, allocation of land
to cropping enterprises differs for land
owners and tenants in the Pergamino region.
Land owners tend to adhere to a rotation of
crops that offers advantages for soil

10
Table 2. Range of parameters considered for each objective function.

Objective Parameter Land owners Land tenants


Function
Nominal value Values explored Nominal value Values explored

Expected Initial wealth ( w0 ) 1400 $ ha-1 700, 800, 900, 1000, 1000 $ ha-1 700, 800, 900,
Utility 1100, 1200, 1300, 1000, 1100, 1200,
1400, 1500, 1600, 1300, 1400, 1500,
1700, 1800, 1900, 1600
2000, 2100, 2200,
2300, 2400
Risk aversion 1 -0.5, 0, 0.5, 1, 2, 3, 4 1 -0.5, 0, 0.5, 1, 2, 3,
coefficient ( r ) 4
Regret-corrected k - 0.155, 0.3595, 0.564 Same as for land owners
Utility
β - 0, 0.0005, 0.005, 0.05, Same as for land owners
0.1, 0.2, 0.3, 0.4, 0.5,
0.6, 0.7, 0.8, 0.9
Prospect Theory Reference wealth 232.5 $ ha-1 100, 175, 232.5, 325, 20 $ ha-1 5, 10, 20, 30, 40,
Value Function ( wr ) 400, 500 50, 60, 70, 80
Risk aversion ( α ) 0.88 0.6, 0.65, 0.7, 0.75, Same as for land owners
0.8, 0.85, 0.88, 0.9, 1
Loss aversion ( λ ) 2.25 1, 2.25, 3, 3.5, 4, 4.5, Same as for land owners
5, 5.5, 6
DRAFT

4.6.1 Expected Utility. and 0 ≤ β < 0.9 . With the exception of w0 ,


all parameter values were the same for
The expected utility function has two owners and tenants.
parameters: (i) the decision maker’s initial
wealth w0 and (ii) the risk-aversion 4.6.3 Prospect Theory Value Function.
coefficient r . Initial wealth w0 is defined as
The value function is defined by (i) a
liquid assets. For land owners, this quantity
was estimated as 40% of the value of the farm reference wealth wr that separates outcomes
land. The definition is based on the perceived as gains and losses, (ii) a risk
assumption that a farmer will not sacrifice aversion parameter α , and (iii) a loss
future income potential by selling crop land, aversion parameter λ that quantifies the
but can borrow up to 40% of his/her land relative impact of gains and losses. For land
value. The 1994-2003 average value of land owners, wr was estimated as the income
for Pergamino was 3541 $ ha-1 easily-achieved by renting the land instead of
(http://www.mlb.com.ar/nota_arre3.asp), farming it. This value of wr was estimated to
making w0 equal to 1400 $ ha-1 (3541 $ ha-1
be 232.5 $ ha-1 (a rental fee of 1.4 ton ha-1 of
x 0.4). For land tenants, we assumed a w0 soybean times a price of 166 $ ton-1). For land
value of 1000 $ ha-1, the liquid assets required tenants, wr was estimated as the income
to finance two complete cropping cycles (i.e., obtained by placing the tenant’s initial wealth
in case of a total loss in one cycle, the farmer ( w0 = 1000 $ ha-1, as described for EU) in a
still has capital to fund a second cycle). For
bank for six months (the duration of a
the risk-aversion coefficient r , we followed
cropping season) at an annual interest of 4%
Anderson and Dillon’s (1992) classification:
(representative of current rates in Argentina).
0.5 is hardly risk averse; 1.0, somewhat risk
averse (normal); 2.0, rather risk averse; 3.0, The nominal wr value, then, was 20 $ ha-1.
very risk averse; and 4.0, extremely risk For the risk-aversion parameter α and the
averse. We also included risk-seeking loss-aversion parameter λ , we used the
behavior and risk indifference by also values of 0.88 and 2.25, respectively, that
considering r values of –0.5 and 0.0. The were estimated by Tversky and Kahneman
range of r values was the same for owners (1992) for both owners and tenants, but also
and tenants. explored other values (Table 2).

4.6.2 Regret-corrected Expected Utility.


5. RESULTS
The regret-corrected expected utility has the
same parameters as the EU model ( w0 and This section describes the land allocations
r ), and for which we used the same ranges. It (i.e., the proportion of land assigned to
also has two other parameters: a factor k that different enterprises) identified as optimal for
weighs the regret, and parameter β each objective function. The cropping
enterprises selected during the optimization
associated with the regret function g (⋅) (see
procedure (only seven out of 64 possible
Eq. 6). Appropriate bounds for k and β enterprises) are shown in Table 3. The table
were derived by Laciana et al. (2005) to also shows the mean economic returns (profit
ensure that regret theory reproduce the pattern after subtracting all costs) and their standard
of preferences described by the Allais deviation (S.D.) over the 70 simulated
paradox. These ranges are 0.155 ≤ k ≤ 0.564 cropping cycles.

12
Table 3. Cropping enterprises selected during the optimization procedure (only seven out of 64 possible enterprises were selected). The
combination of management variables that define each enterprise is shown. The table also shows the mean economic returns (profit after
subtracting all costs) and their standard deviation (S.D.) over the 70 simulated cropping cycles. Results are presented both for land owners
and tenants. For the wheat-soybean double crop, the superscripts a and b indicate values for wheat and soybean, respectively.

Enterprise Enterprise management Economic returns for Economic returns for


ID owners ($ ha-1) tenants ($ ha-1)

Genotype Planting Fertilizer Row Available Available Mean S.D. Mean S.D.
date added (kg spacing soil water soil N at
N ha-1) (m) at planting
planting (kg N ha-1)
(%)
Maize
Ma21 Sep 15 100 113.2 106.8 6.8 157.7
Ma23 DK752 Oct 15 75 0.70 100 70 116.5 84.1 5.8 128.6
Ma24 Oct 15 100 116.3 90.1 9.8 135.8
Full-cycle soybean
Soy14 DM4800 Oct 25 0 0.52 100 50 188.1 60.7 69.4 89.0
Wheat-Soybean
SW19 Scorpiona Jun 10 40 162.1 83.4 62.3 121.7
0.19a
SW20 & Jun 10 60 90 60 167.3 84.7 72.3 122.5
0.52b
SW21 DM4800b Jun 10 80 168.8 85.0 77.6 122.0
DRAFT

5.1 EU Maximization
Figure 1. Land allocation (as proportion
5.1.1 Land owners of the hypothetical 600-ha farm) that
maximizes expected utility for land
The enterprise allocation that maximized owners. The selected combination of
expected utility for land owners was constant enterprises is constant for all initial wealth
for the full range of initial wealth and risk w0 and risk aversion r .
aversion values explored (Fig. 1). The
maximum area allowed for one crop by the
optimization constraints defined for owners
(45% of total land) was allocated to full-cycle
soybean Soy14, the enterprise with the
highest average economic returns
-1
(188.1 $ ha , Table 3). Conversely, the
minimum area required by constraints (25%)
was for maize, the crop with lowest average
profits. Ma23, the enterprise with the highest
average profits for this crop (116.5 $ ha-1)
was selected; another maize enterprise, Ma22,
had similar mean profits but a higher
dispersion of outcomes (implying higher risk)
and thus was not picked. The remainder of
the area (30%) was allocated to the wheat-soy Fig. 2 has three panels with increasingly
enterprise SW21, which had average profits higher levels of risk aversion r (from top to
between those of full-cycle soy and maize bottom). In each panel, the optimal allocation
(168.8 $ ha-1). The stability of results for all of land is shown as a function of initial
parameter combinations illustrates the wealth w0 . For a risk-neutral decision-maker
importance of constraints associated with ( r = 0; Fig. 2, upper panel), the optimal
maintaining a crop rotation: these constraints action was to allocate the entire area to the
clearly override any financial or personality double crop enterprise SW21; this result is
characteristics of a decision-maker. constant for the entire range of values
considered for w0 . Because the decision-
5.1.2 Land tenants maker is risk-neutral, the selection of SW21
was based only on its higher mean profit
For land tenants, only two enterprises (full-
relative to Soy14 (77.6 $ ha-1 vs. 69.4 $ ha-1),
cycle soybean Soy14 and wheat-soybean
and ignored the higher risks associated with
SW21) were involved in the maximization of
the considerably larger dispersion of profits
expected utility. Because of the markedly
for this enterprise (122.0 $ ha-1 vs. 89.0 $ ha-1
lower economic margins of maize enterprises
for Soy14). When moderate amounts of risk
(due to the combination of rental costs for
aversion are considered ( r =1.5; Fig. 2,
tenants and low maize prices) and the lack of
middle panel), the optimal action involved
constraints requiring a minimum area for
diversification of enterprises for most values
maize, the optimization did not select any
of w0 . For low w0 , diversification is highest:
enterprise involving this crop. Relative
proportions of the selected enterprises 60% of the land was allocated to SW21 and
depended on the combination of parameters. 40% to Soy14. As w0 increases (and, thus,
decision makers can afford higher financial

14
DRAFT

Figure 2. Land allocation (as proportion of w0 range. However, there was a minor effect
the hypothetical 600-ha farm) that of w0 : for initial wealth below 1100 $ ha-1,
maximizes expected utility for land Soy14 (less profitable, but also less risky)
tenants. The three panels show the results occupied a slightly higher area than SW21
for risk neutrality ( r =0, upper panel), (more profitable but riskier). This allocation
moderate risk aversion ( r =1.5, middle was reversed for higher w0 values.
panel), and pronounced risk aversion
( r =3.0, bottom panel), in each case plotted 5.2 Regret-Adjusted Expected Utility
as a function of initial wealth w0 . Maximization
5.2.1 Land owners

The enterprise allocation that maximized


regret-adjusted expected utility was the same
as that for EU (Fig. 1). That is, no effects of
anticipated regret were noticeable for any
combination of parameter values. The lack of
discernible regret effects is again due to the
strong constraints imposed on optimal
solutions by the owners’ modeled adherence
to crop rotation.

5.2.2 Land tenants

The same two enterprises involved in the


maximization of EU for tenants also
maximized regret-adjusted expected utility:
full-cycle soybean (Soy14) and wheat-
soybean (SW21). As for EU, the optimal
proportions of these enterprises varied with
the combination of parameters. Fig. 3 shows a
matrix of panels combining selected values of
regret parameters k (increasing from top to
bottom) and β (increasing from left to right).
In each panel, the optimal allocation of land
is shown as a function of risk aversion r .
risks), the proportion of land assigned to
SW21 increased until this enterprise occupied In the first row of Fig. 3, there was no regret
the entire area, resembling results for risk- effect (as k = 0), thus results coincided with
neutrality. Even with CRRA, absolute risk those for EU. This row can be used as a
aversion declines with rising wealth. Finally, reference to understand the effects of
for a highly risk-averse decision-maker anticipated regret. A dashed vertical line in
( r =3.0; Fig. 2, bottom panel), the optimal each panel indicates the r value at which the
land allocation was fairly conservative, as optimal action switched from a monoculture
crop diversification (comparable proportions of SW21 to an enterprise diversification that
of SW21 and Soy14) prevailed throughout the also included Soy14 when no regret existed.
In the top row of Fig. 3, this switch occurred

15
DRAFT

Figure 3. Land allocation (as proportion of the hypothetical 600-ha farm) that maximizes
regret-corrected expected utility for land tenants. The different panels correspond to
combinations of regret parameters k (increasing for top to bottom) and β (increasing from
left to right). In each panel, the optimal allocation of land is shown as a function of the risk
aversion coefficient r.

for r slightly below 1. As we move down optimal outcomes results in considerable


the columns of Fig. 3, parameter k increases regret (left column of Fig. 3).
indicating progressively higher degrees of
anticipated regret. That is, the decision-maker As we move along the columns of Fig. 3,
gives increasing importance to the fact that a increases in β indicate higher sensitivity in
better option can exist. To avoid anticipated the experience of regret to the magnitude of
regret, the decision-maker becomes more ∆u (as implied by the functional form of g (⋅)
risk-seeking. This result is illustrated by a in Eq. 6). For instance, if we focus on the
displacement in the location of the switch center row of Fig. 3, we see that for a
towards enterprise diversification, which constant k value, the switch to enterprise
occurred at higher r values (above 1.0) than diversification occurred at lower r values as
when regret did not exist. This displacement β increased. That is, β has an effect
is most noticeable for lower β values, for opposite to that of k . For high β values
which any kind of deviation (∆u) from

16
DRAFT

(Fig. 3, right column), the effects of regret the value function is convex thus higher α
were mostly unnoticeable and results seemed values indicate higher risk aversion. In turn,
to coincide with those for EU (because regret the likelihood of being in the domain of gains
only becomes noticeable for large values of or losses is partly a function of wr . Fig. 5
∆u). A preliminary conclusion is that, at least displays histograms of the difference
for the combination of parameters explored, (π ij − wr ) between economic profits and wr
anticipated regret seemed to be a second-
order effect and did not change substantially for three maize enterprises (Ma21, Ma23, and
the results based on expected utility theory. Ma24) and three wr values (100, 230, and
325 $ ha-1). As wr increases, the proportion
5.3 Prospect theory
of negative differences (i.e., economic
5.3.1 Land owners outcomes perceived as losses) for an
enterprise is higher. Indeed, when
The land allocation that maximized prospect wr =325 $ ha-1 (bottom row of histograms),
theory’s value included, for all parameter
outcomes for all three maize enterprises are
combinations, full-cycle soybean Soy14 as
negative.
the enterprise with the largest area.
Conversely, enterprises involving maize The top left panel of Fig. 4 ( wr =100 $ ha-1
(three different ones were selected: Ma21,
Ma23, and Ma24) occupied the smallest area. and λ =1.00) serves as a reference to discuss
The wheat-soy double crop (in most cases, the consequences of varying prospect
enterprise SW21, but also SW20) occupied theory’s parameters. In this panel, the optimal
the remaining area. These results are enterprise allocation was the same as that for
consistent with the relative average EU maximization for land owners: 45% of
profitability of each crop. Fig. 4 shows a Soy14, 30% of SW21, and 25% of Ma23 (see
matrix of panels combining different values Fig. 1). The similarity with EU results is due
of prospect theory parameters wr (reference to two facts. First, because λ =1.00, there is
no loss aversion (i.e., gains and losses are
wealth, increasing from top to bottom) and λ valued equally by the decision-maker).
(loss aversion parameter, increasing from left Second, because wr is low, most of the
to right). In each panel, the optimal allocation
of land is shown as a function of risk outcomes are positive (gains).
preference parameter α .
In the top middle panel of Fig. 4, λ has
To interpret results in Fig. 4, one must increased to its nominal value of 2.25,
understand interactions among prospect indicating that losses of a given magnitude
theory’s parameters. In particular, we focus have more than twice as much impact as
on risk preference α and reference wealth gains of the same magnitude. The reason that
this increase in loss aversion has no impact on
wr , as their interaction may produce
the optimal land allocation is that reference
apparently counterintuitive results. The effect wealth is low ( wr =100 $ ha-1), which means
of risk preference parameter α depends on
whether the decision-maker perceives to be that the economic profits for the various
operating in the economic gains or losses enterprises are mostly higher than wr and are
domains. In the gains domain, the value thus perceived as gains. With few losses,
function is concave (as for expected utility), degree of loss aversion cannot be expected to
and higher α values indicate lower risk have much impact on land allocation.
aversion. Conversely, in the domain of losses,

17
DRAFT

Figure 4. Land allocation (as proportion of the hypothetical 600-ha farm) that maximizes
prospect theory’s value function for land owners. The different panels correspond to
combinations of wr (reference wealth, increasing from top to bottom) and λ (loss aversion
parameter, increasing from left to right). In each panel, the optimal allocation of land is shown
as a function of the risk preference coefficient α .

Moving now to the top right panel of Fig. 4, and a choice of SW20 over SW21 is a more
loss aversion increases to λ =3.50. In this conservative strategy. Although the statistics
panel, there is a switch between two of the of outcomes are fairly similar for both
wheat-soybean enterprises (SW21 and SW20) enterprises (Table 3), the proportion of
as a function of α values. Below the nominal negative outcomes (data not shown) is lower
α value of 0.88, SW20 is chosen whereas, for SW20 than for SW21, making it a more
above 0.88, SW21 is the selected enterprise. attractive choice when losses are valued more
Again, because wr is low (100 $ ha-1), most than three times higher than gains. In
outcomes will be perceived as gains, thus contrast, for higher α values risk aversion
lower α values imply higher risk aversion decreases, and the decision-maker selects the

18
DRAFT

Figure 5. Histograms of the difference between net economic returns and prospect theory’s
reference wealth (π ij − wr ) for land owners. Results are shown for three maize-related
enterprises (Ma21, Ma23, and Ma24), and different reference wealth values (in $ ha-1). The
histograms display the simulated outcomes for 70 cropping cycles.

enterprise with higher economic returns losses and low values of α are associated
(SW21) even though it is riskier. with risk-seeking behavior. In contrast, as α
increases, the decision-maker becomes more
As we move down the rows of Fig. 4 to risk-averse and the less risky Ma23 option is
higher reference levels wr, the main effect is a selected.
switch between maize enterprises (mostly
Ma23 and Ma24, but Ma21 also appears). For 5.3.2 Land tenants
α < 0.88, Ma24 tends to prevail; for
α > 0.88, Ma23 is selected. The gross The land allocation that maximized prospect
margin of both maize enterprises is similar theory’s value function for tenants involved
but the variability of Ma24 (90.1 $ ha-1) is two enterprises: full-cycle soybean (Soy14)
higher than the corresponding value for Ma23 and wheat-soybean (SW21). As in previous
(84.1 $ ha-1). As wr values increase, maize cases, the specific proportions of these
enterprises depended on the combination of
outcomes come to be encoded mostly as
parameters.

19
DRAFT

The top left panel of Fig. 6 ( wr =10 $ ha-1 and increases, risk seeking decreases and the
λ =1.00) can be used as a reference to discuss selected allocation becomes diversified as
the consequences of varying prospect loss aversion now takes effect, with a higher
theory’s parameters. In this panel, there is no proportion of the less variable enterprise
loss aversion. Also, a low level of reference Soy14.
wealth puts more outcomes into the domain
When loss aversion is even stronger, as in the
of gains, where low α values make a
right panels of Fig. 6 ( λ = 3.50), it starts to
decision-maker more risk-averse. As a result,
take over and dictates diversification across
a diversified land allocation including two
the whole range of α, and even more so for
enterprises (Soy14 and SW21) is selected. As
higher levels of reference wealth, as more
α increases and the decision-maker becomes
outcomes are in the domain of losses and
less risk-averse, the allocation switches
hence subject to loss aversion.
towards an increasingly higher proportion of
SW21 (until mono-culture is reached), where
SW21 has a higher margin but also is riskier.

As we move along the top row of Fig. 6, loss


6. DISCUSSION
aversion increases and we see a mixture of Our results demonstrate in a non-laboratory
the two dominating enterprises in the central decision context that psychologically
and right top panels. Nevertheless, there is a plausible deviations from EU maximization
higher proportion of Soy14 which, despite matter. The optimal allocations for land
having lower average profit than SW21, owners dictated by some parameter
shows lower variability of outcomes. combinations of prospect theory (namely the
allocation of some land to SW20, Ma24 or
If we move down the left column of Fig. 6,
Ma 21; see Fig. 4) for example, are not
the switch from diversification to a
predicted by any parameter combination in
monoculture of SW21 begins at progressively
either EU or regret-adjusted EU
lower values of α . This is due to the fact that
maximization. As another example, prospect-
as wr increases, an increasing proportion of
theory value maximization allows tenants to
outcomes are perceived as a loss where α allocate a much greater proportion of land to
denotes risk-seeking. Risk-seeking to neutral Soy14 than EU maximization (compare
decision-makers choose the riskier option Figs. 6 and 2). Given that an increasing trend
(SW21) in search of higher profitability, and towards a monoculture of soybean has been
thus enterprise selection in the bottom-left observed on the part of tenants in the
panel is identical to that of risk-neutral EU Argentina Pampas (Satorre 2005), prospect-
maximizers (top panel in Fig. 2). theory value maximization seems to be a
plausible explanation.
This pattern is also apparent in the middle
bottom panel of Fig. 6, where we now also Another general observation about our results
have loss-aversion (λ = 2.25). Its high is that deviations from behavior predicted by
reference wealth ( wr = 80 $ ha-1) implies that EU maximization as the result of anticipated
a high proportion of outcomes are perceived regret minimization are far less pronounced
as losses. For low α values, the decision- than deviations as the result of loss aversion
maker is more risk-seeking and thus selects and of different risk attitudes in the domain of
riskier enterprises in search of higher profits gains and losses, embodied in prospect
to get out of the domain of losses. As α theory. For land owners, whose choices are

20
DRAFT

constrained by the crop rotation regimen that see that different objective functions shape
is in their long-range interest, EU and RTEU the nature of this tradeoff in different ways.
optimization predict the same land allocation. In particular, more risk-averse land allocation
For tenants, the main effect of minimizing is encouraged by the individual difference
anticipated regret is to delay diversification at parameter r , reflecting degree of risk-
lower levels of risk aversion. aversion, and by lower initial wealth w0 in
both EU and RTEU optimization. In contrast,
Optimization of any utility or value function
in prospect-theory value optimization, such
reflects a tradeoff between the expected
behavior is encouraged by a lower reference
profits of an enterprise and its risk or
wealth (that divides the perception of returns
dispersion of outcomes. It is interesting to

Figure 6. Land allocation (as proportion of the hypothetical 600-ha farm) that maximizes
prospect theory’s value function for land tenants. The different panels correspond to
combinations of wr (reference wealth in $ ha-1, increasing from top to bottom) and λ (loss
aversion parameter, increasing from left to right). In each panel, the optimal allocation of land
is shown as a function of the risk preference coefficient α .

21
DRAFT

into gains vs. losses) and much more by the ACKNOWLEDGMENTS


individual difference parameter λ , reflecting
degree of loss aversion, than by individual The research was supported by an NSF
difference parameter α , reflecting risk Biocomplexity in the Environment grant (BE-
preference, and equivalent to EU’s r . 0410348), an NSF Center grant under the
Similarly, less risk-averse land allocation is Decision Making under Uncertainty Initiative
encouraged by different processes and (SES-0345840), and a NOAA Human
parameters under the three objective Dimensions grant (GC04-159). F. Bert is
functions. For EU maximization, both supported by a doctoral fellowship from
parameters r (less risk aversion) and w0 Argentina’s Consejo Nacional de
(greater initial wealth) are deciding factors Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas
(top panel and right end of middle panel of (CONICET). The authors are grateful to the
Fig. 2). In RTEU optimization, greater weight management, technical advisors and farmer
placed on anticipated regret (parameter k ) members of the Asociación Argentina de
also encourages greater risk taking at lower Consorcios Regionales de Experimentación
levels of risk-aversion (left side of bottom left Agrícola for their commitment to this
panel in Fig. 3). In prospect-theory value research.
optimization, on the other hand, less risk-
averse land allocations come about when the
decision-maker has no loss aversion but a low REFERENCES
reference value, resulting in most outcomes
being perceived as losses for which choices Allais, P.M. 1953. Le comportement de
are either risk-seeking or at best risk-neutral l'homme rationnel devant le risque:
(bottom left panel of Fig. 6). Critique des postulats et axiomes de l'école
americaine. Econometrica 21 503-546.
6.1 Relevance of results
Anderson, J.R., J.L. Dillon. 1992. Risk
We envision three main applications of the analysis in dryland farming systems. Farm
work presented here. First, an improved Systems Management Series, No. 2. Rome,
understanding of individual differences in FAO.
preferences and objective functions allows for Bell, D.E. 1982. Regret in decision making
the development of agronomic advice tailored under uncertainty. Operations Research 30
to the personality characteristics of different 961–981.
types of farmers. Such advice will be more
Benartzi, S., R.H. Thaler. 1995. Myopic loss
effective than the common “one size fits all”
aversion and the equity premium puzzle.
technical recommendations. Second,
Quarterly Journal of Economics 110 73-92.
knowledge of individual preferences may be
helpful to guide the framing and to assess the Bernoulli, D. 1954/1738. Exposition of a new
acceptability of regional or national policies theory on the measurement of risk.
of agricultural sustainability (for example, Econometrica 22(1) 23-36 (Translation of
policies that encourage crop diversification). D. Bernoulli, 1738, Specimen theoriae
Finally, an understanding of production novae de mensura sortis, Papers of the
decisions in agriculture may contribute to Imperial Academy of Science of Saint
comprehension of a range of related issues, Petersburg 5 175-192).
such as adoption of technological innovations Boote, K.J., J.W. Jones. 1998. Simulation of
and adaptation to climate change. crop growth: CROPGRO model. R. M.
Peart, R. B. Curry, eds. Agricultural

22
DRAFT

Systems Modeling and Simulation, Marcel in agriculture. CABI Publishing,


Dekker, pp. 651 – 692. Cambridge, Massachussets. 332 p.
Braun M., A. Muermann. 2004. The impact Johnson, E.J., D. Goldstein. 2003. Do
of regret on the demand for insurance, defaults save lives? Science 302 1338-
Journal of Risk and Insurance, 71 737-767. 1339.
Camerer, C. 2000. Prospect Theory in the Jones, J., G. Tsuji, G. Hoogenboom, L. Hunt,
wild. D. Kahneman, A. Tversky , P. Thornton, P. Wilkens, D. Imamura, W.
eds. Choice, Values, and Frames, Bowen, U. Singh. 1998. Decision support
Cambridge University Press, New York, system for agrotechnology transfer. Tsuji,
pp. 288-300. G., Hoogenboom, G., Thornton, P. (eds.).
Camerer, C. 2005. Three cheers— Understanding Options for Agricultural
psychological, theoretical, empirical—for Production, Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp. 157–
loss aversion. Journal of Marketing 177.
Research 42 129-133. Kahneman, D., A. Tversky. 1979. Prospect
Collins, A., W.N. Musser, R. Mason. 2001. Theory: an analysis of decision under risk.
Prospect theory and risk preferences of Econometrica 47 263-292.
Oregon seed producers. American Journal Kahneman, D.A. 2003. Perspective on
of Agricultural Economics 73(2) 429-435. judgment and choice: mapping bounded
Damasio, A. 1995. Descartes' error: Emotion, rationality. American Psychologist 58 697-
Reason, and the Human Brain. Avon 720.
Books, New York. Laciana, C.E., E.U. Weber. 2005. A
Eggert, H., P. Martinsson. 2004. Are reformalization of the Prospect Theory
Commercial Fishers Risk Lovers? Land value function with a well-defined first
Economics 80(4): 550-560. derivative. Under review, Operations
Ellsberg, D. 1961. Risk, ambiguity and Research.
Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Laciana, C.E., E.U. Weber, X.I. González.
Economics 75(4) 643-79. 2005. A parameterization of Regret Theory
Fennema, H.P., P.P. Wakker. 1997. Original based on the Allais paradox. Under review,
and cumulative prospect theory: A Journal of Risk and Uncertainty.
discussion of empirical differences. Journal Loewenstein, G.F., E.U. Weber, C.K. Hsee,
of Behavioral Decision Making 10 (1) 53- E. Welch. 2001. Risk as feelings.
64. Psychological Bulletin 127 267-286.
Gill, P.E., W. Murray, B.A. Murtagh, M.A. Loomes, G., R. Sugden. 1982. Regret theory:
Saunders, M. Wright. 2000. an alternative theory of rational choice
GAMS/MINOS, In: GAMS-The Solver under uncertainty. The Economic Journal
Manuals. GAMS Development 92 805-824.
Corporation. Machina, M.J. 1994. Review of: Generalized
Hall, A.J., C.M. Rebella, C.M. Ghersa, J.P.H. Expected Utility Theory: The Rank
Culot. 1992. Field crops systems of the Dependent Model (Norwell, Mass., Kluwer
Pampas. Pearson, C.J. (ed.). Field Crops Academic). Journal of Economic Literature
Systems: Ecosystems of the World, vol. 18. 32 1237-1238.
Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp. 413–449. Markman, K.D., I. Gavanski, S.J. Sherman,
Hardaker, J.B., R.B. M. Huirne, J.R. M.N. McMullen. 1993. The mental
Anderson, G. Lien. 2004. Coping with risk simulation of better and worse possible

23
DRAFT

worlds. Journal of Experimental Social Schoemaker, P.J.H. 1982. The expected


Psychology 29 87-109. utility model: its variants, purposes,
McFadden, D. 1999. Rationality for evidence and limitations. Journal of
economists? Journal of Risk and Economic Literature 20 529-563.
Uncertainty 19 73-105. Starmer, C. 2000. Developments in non-
Paruelo, J., O. Sala. 1993. Effect of global expected utility theory: the hunt for a
change on Argentine maize. Climate descriptive theory of choice under risk.
Research 3 161–167. Journal of Economic Literature 18 332-
Pratt, J.W. 1964. Risk aversion in the small 382.
and in the large. Econometrica 32 122-136. Thaler, R.H. 1980. Toward a Positive Theory
Rabin, M. 1998. Psychology and economics. of Consumer Choice. Journal of Economic
Journal of Economic Literature 36 11-46. Behavior and Organization 1 39-60.
Reusser, D.E., M. Hare, C. Pahl-Wostl. 2004. Tversky, A., D. Kahneman. 1992 Advances
Relating Choice of Agent Rationality to in prospect theory, cumulative
Agent Model Uncertainty - an representation of uncertainty. Journal of
experimental study. Pahl-Wostl, C., Risk and Uncertainty 5 297-323.
Schmidt, S., Rizzoli, A.E. and Jakeman, von Neumann, J., O. Morgenstern. 1944.
A.J. (eds.). Complexity and Integrated Theory of Games and Economic Behavior.
Resources Management. Transactions of Princeton University Press, Princeton.
the 2nd Biennial Meeting of the Weber, E.U. 1994. From subjective
International Environmental Modelling and probabilities to decision weights: The
Software Society, iEMSs: Manno, 2004. effect of asymmetric loss functions on the
Ritchie, J., V. Singh, D. Godwin, W. Bowen. evaluation of uncertain outcomes and
1998. Cereal growth, development and events. Psychological Bulletin 115 228-
yield. In: Tsuji, G., G. Hoogenboom, P. 242.
Thornton (eds.). Understanding Options Woodward, R.T. 1998. Should agricultural
for Agricultural Production, Kluwer and resource economists care that the
Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, pp. 79– subjective expected utility hypothesis is
98. false? Meeting of the American
Satorre, E.H., 2005. Cambios tecnológicos en Agricultural Economics Association,
la agricultura actual. Ciencia Hoy 15 24 - August 2-5, 1998, Salt Lake City, Utah.
31. http://agecon2.tamu.edu/people/faculty/wo
Samuelson, W.F., R.J. Zeckhauser. 1988. odward-richard/paps/AAEA98-
Status Quo Bias in Decision Making. Uncertainty.pdf. (23 January 2006).
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 1 7-59.
Schmidt, U., H. Zank. 2005. What is loss
aversion? Journal of Risk and Uncertainty
30 157-167.

24

You might also like