Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 200

SYNTHESE LANGUAGE LIBRARY

TEXTS AND STUDIES IN


LINGUISTICS AND PHILOSOPHY

Managing Editors:
ELISABET ENGDAHL, University of Wisconsin
JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Florida State University, Tallahassee
ST AN LEY PETERS, Stanford University

Editorial Board:
EMMON BACH, University of Massachusetts at Amherst
JOAN BRESNAN, Stanford University
JOHN LYONS, University of Sussex
JULIUS M. E. MORAVCSIK, Stanford University
PATRICK SUPPES, Stanford University
DANA SCOTT, Carnegie-Mellon University, Pittsburgh

VOLUME 23
BOOLEAN SEMANTICS FOR NATURAL LANGUAGE EDWARD L. KEENAN
University of California at Los Angeles

and

LEONARD M. FALTZ
Arizona State University

BOOLEAN SEMANTICS
FOR
NATURAL LANGUAGE

D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY


A MEMBER OF THE KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS GROUP

DORDRECHT/BOSTONjLANCASTER
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data

Keenan, Edward L. (Edward Louis), 1937-


Boolean semantics for natural language.
TABLE OF CONTENTS

(Synthese language library; v. 23)


Bibliography: p.
Includes index. PREFACE xi
1. Semantics (Philosophy) 2. Logic. 3. Algebra, Boolean.
I. Faltz, Leonard M., 1940- II. Title. III. Series.
B840.K43 1984 160 84-22349 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW
ISBN-13: 978-90-277-1842-6 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-6404-4
001: 10.1007/978-94-009-6404-4 1. Sketch of the Semantics 1
1.1. Characterizing English Denotations and Entailments 1
1.2. Characterizing Possible Semantic Systems for Natural
Language 14
2. On the Relation between English Form and Logical Form 17
Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, 3. An Ontological Innovation 29
P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, Holland.
PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC
Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada
by Kluwer Academic Publishers, A. The Core Language, L
190 Old Derby Street, Hingham, MA 02043, U.S.A.
1. Syntax of the Core Language L 31
In all other countries, sold and distributed Defining CAT 31
by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, Defining Vand PEv 36
P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, Holland. DefiningL 36
Remarks on the Definitions 37
2. The Semantics for L 41
Defining the Types for L 42
The Type for Po or Formulas 43
The Types for N, fl, and Nprop 46
Eliminating the Universe 52
Characterizing TN 52
Completeness of boolean algebras 52
Atomicity of boolean algebras 56
All Rights Reserved Defining TN Without a Universe 59
© 1985 by D. Reidel Publishing Company
Softcover reprint of the hardcover I5t edition 1985 Defining Proper Noun Denotations without U 62
No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or The Ontology and Some Basic Types for L: Summary 62
utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, Discussion 63
including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and
Why should TN Be Complete and Atomic? 73
retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner.
Defining TDet 81
viii T ABLE OF CONTENTS

Defining the Types for the Pn's 87


Defining TP n , all n 100
Defining Types for Predicative Hierarchies in General 102
Summary Definition of the Types 103
Defining Interpretations for L 104
Advantages of the Generalized Entaihnent Relation 107
A Concluding Remark on Comparative Ontologies 109
To our parents Proofs of the Theorems III
Edward L. Keenan, Edith C. Keenan, Notes 116
Joseph Faltz, Charlotte L. Faltz PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC
B. Extending the Core Language
1. Modifiers 118
Adjective Phrases 118
Comparative Adjectives 134
Predicate Adjectives 139
Proofs of Theorems from This Section 142
2. Predicate Modifiers 150
Proofs of Theorems from This Section 171
3. Predicatives 177
Preliminary Remarks on Case Marking 178
Transitive Common Noun Phrases 181
Modifiers of n-place Common Nouns 184
Some Relations Between Nominals and Predicates 185
Subcategories of N n 189
Transitive Adjective Phrases 190
Ditransitive Verb Phrases (P 3 s) 192
Prepositions and Predicate Modifier Hierarchies 196
Prepositions as Formers of Predicate Modifiers 196
Prepositions as Verbal Extensors 201
4. Valency Affecting Operations 202
Passives 202
A Generalized Passive Operator 203
Sentence level views 205
Predicate level views 208
Generalizing Passive 212
Agent Phrases 216
Extending Passive to Nominals and Other Predicative Hierarchies 221
TABLE OF CONTENTS ix

Nominals 221
Passive Adjectives? 224
Passive Prepositions?? 226 PREFACE
5. Extending and Subcategorizing the Class of Determiners 227
Numerical Determiners 228
Non-Logical Determiners 235
Characterizing 'Logical' Determiners 238 In the spring of 1978, one of the authors of this book was sitting in on a
Vague Determiners 242 course in logic for linguists given by the other author. In attempting to
Determiners Compared to Other Categories 244 present some of Montague's insights in an elementary way (hopefully avoid-
Generalizing Determiners 246 ing the notation which many find difficult at first), the authors began dis-
Extending Possessive Determiners 248 cussions aimed towards the construction of a simple model-theoretical
6. Variables and Variable Binding Operators 250 semantic apparatus which could be applied directly to a small English-like
The Lambda Operator 254 language and used to illustrate the methods of formal logical interpretation.
The Reflexive Operator 258 In these discussions two points impressed themselves on us. First, our task
The Relative Clause Operator 262 could be simplified by using boolean algebras and boolean homomorphisms
7. Non-homomorphic Predicates? 267 in the models; and second, the boolean approach we were developing had
Numerical Predicates 267 much more widespread relevance to the logical structure of English than we
Collective Predicates 268 first thought. During the summer and fall of 1978 we continued work on the
Reciprocal Predicates 268 system, proving the more fundamental theorems (including what we have
Intensional Predicates 268 come to call the Justification Theorem) and outlining the way in which an
intensional interpretation scheme could be developed which made use of the
PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC boolean approach (which was originally strictly extensional). We presented
our findings in a monograph (Keenan and Faltz, 1978) which the UCLA
1. Introduction to the Intensional System 272 Linguistics Department kindly published as part of their series called Occa-
Proofs of the Theorems 279 sional Papers in Linguistics; one of the authors also presented the system at
2. The Intensional System for the Core Language 282 a colloquium held at the Winter Meeting of the Linguistic Society of America
Proofs of the Theorems 307 in December 1978.
Notes for IL2 308 On the basis of encouragement from colleagues as well as our own sense
3. The Intensional Logic for APs 308 of the value of the boolean semantic approach, the authors decided to publish
Proofs of the Theorems 331 the system in book form. Originally we had hoped to create a reworked
4. Predicate Modifiers and Prepositions in the Intensional System 333 version of the 1978 monograph, improving on matters of exposition and
5. Variables and Variable Binding Operators in the Intensional clarity only. As we progressed, however, we found more and more ways to
System 342 extend and improve the theory, so that the present book is to all intents
6. Sentential Predicates in the Intensional System 353 and purposes an entirely new work. Herein will be found, for example, a
Syntax of Sentence Taking Predicates 354 way of defining an ontology without the need of a set (the 'domain of
A Semantics for Sand S-Taking Predicates 358 discourse' U) whose elements are not directly denotable by expressions in
Formal Definitions of the New Types 363 the language; a deeper discussion of determiners; a deeper and more general
Lexical Constraints on the Interpreting Function m 364 presentation of the interpretation of modifiers; a more general discussion
Subcategories of S-Taking Predicates 366 of the theorems relating to the intensional system; a discussion of case
xi
x TABLE OF CONTENTS xii PREFACE

Argument Categories in Addition to Rand S 368 marking; and, generally, what we hope is a clearer picture of the pervasiveness
Extraposition 372 of boolean structure in the semantics of natural language.
Loose ends remain; however, we have resisted the temptation to delay
BIBLIOGRAPHY 377 publication of the book until all the developments and extensions we could
possibly conceive of were worked out and included. As it is, we have delayed
INDEX 379 this book enough; it seemed high time to make available to the scholarly
community a complete presentation of the current state of our system, since
so much had been developed beyond the versions hitherto available. We hope
that this book may be the foundation for further work on and in the boolean
semantics framework.
During the time that we have been working on the theory of boolean
semantics, we have been fortunate to have had the help and advice of friends
and colleagues. It is our pleasure to thank the following people for their
contributions, criticisms, and encouragement: Emmon Bach, Filippo Beghelli,
Scott Busby, David Gil, William La dusaw, Susan Mordechay, Larry Moss,
Richard Oehrle, Barbara Partee, Stan Peters, Maureen Schmid, and Jonathan
Stavi. Our apologies to any persons we may have inadvertently omitted.
Our special thanks to Vimal Graham and Cathy Mullins for typing the manu-
script, and to the National Science Foundation for funding portions of the
work herein under grant BNS 79-14141.

July 1983
BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 3

whatever (3b) claims of an individual is claimed as well by (3a), and, in fact,


more is claimed by (3a).
BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW Similarly, the two place predicate (P 2) hug and kiss is more informative
than the P2 hug in the sense that, whenever two individuals are related in the
way that hug and kiss says they are, then they are also related in the way
hug says they are.
Much of this work uses the notation and concepts of boolean algebra. Neither Our examples suggest that for most any category C, a conjunction of
the notation nor the concepts are particularly difficult to learn, nor does expressions e and e' of category C is more informative than (more exactly:
this work presuppose any basic familiarity with them. Nonetheless a sudden at least as informative as) either of the conjuncts taken alone. And this
immersion might prove chilling to some, so we are presenting here a rather is basically correct. Thus the compound Adjective Phrase in (4a) is more
lengthy introduction designed to explain what we think is most novel about informative than that in (4b) in the sense that for any noun n, an individual
our work and what the motivations were which led up to it. which has the property expressed by tall and handsome n of necessity has
Section 1 below concentrates on what we think are the most substantive the property expressed by tall n.
aspects of our work which are new. These aspects primarily concern the
nature of the denotations of natural language expressions and the semantic (4) a. tall and handsome
relations, such as entailment, which are defined in terms of them. They are b. tall
largely, though not entirely, independent of the syntactic form of the English
representations we propose. For this reason the semantic contribution of this Similarly the compound determiner in (Sa) below is more informative than
work is rather naturally adaptable to other forms of natural logic, such as, that in (Sb) in the sense that for any noun n, the properties which some but
by and large, the various proposals of Montague. (In fact, as noted in the not all n's have must all be properties which some n's have.
text, we have relied on Montague at certain crucial points.)
Section 2 below concentrates on the syntactic form of our English repre· (5) a. some but not all
sentations which do contain some novel features, such as the absence of b. some
linear order of exrpessions.
Finally, Section 3 points out one difference between our work and all Of course the expressions in a category which bear the informativeness
other semantic work for natural language, namely a change in the basic relation to each other are not limited to conjunctions and single conjuncts.
ontology of standard logic, one which has no effect on which expressions In general, for example, an expression e is more informative than a disjunc-
entail which others, but which does pertain to the formal elegance and tion (e or e'). Classically for example a sentence e entails a disjunction (e or
linguistic suggestiveness of the system. e') of sentences. And, for e, e' of category PI, it is obvious that an individual
which has the property expressed by e must have the property expressed by
1. SKETCH OF THE SEMANTICS
(e or e'); e.g., (6a) below entails (6b):

1.1. Characterizing English Denotations and Entailments (6) a. John is crying.


b. John is either crying or laughing.
Our work situates itself squarely within the tradition of model theoretic
semantics for natural language: we provide semantic representations for a Of somewhat greater linguistic interest is the fact that our pretheoretical
fragment of English and interpret them in such a way so as to account for our intuitions of informativeness (or semantic containment) are not limited to
pretheoretical judgments of semantic relatedness of English expressions. expressions related by the traditional boolean connectives (and, or, and not).
More explicitly, the basic criterion in terms of which our proposals, and those For example, modifiers create expressions which, typically, are intuitively
2 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 4 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW

of any form of model theoretic semantics for natural language, are to be more informative than the expressions they modify. Thus the PI in (7a)
evaluated is given by: below is more informative than that in (7b): any individual of which the
former holds must also be one of which the latter holds.
(1) Criterion of Logical Adequacy
Expressions e and e' of a natural language are judged by speakers (7) a. sing loudly
to be semantically related in a certain way if and only if their b. sing
formal representations are provably related in that way.
Similarly the Common Noun Phrase tall student is more informative than
The fundamental relation we, and others, endeavor to represent is the entail- student: the individuals with the former property must be a subset of those
ment (= logical implication, logical consequence) relation. Classically it holds with the latter property. The AP phrase very tall is more informative than
between expressions e and e' of category Sentence. Pretheoretically we say tall, etc.
that sentence e entails a sentence e' if and only if (iff) e' is true whenever e Now, since the various pairs of expressions which bear the informativeness
is; that is, whenever the world is the waye says it is then it is also the way e' relation to each other are of quite different grammatical categories and thus
says it is. For example, trivially we judge pretheoretically that (2b) below is are semantically interpreted in different ways, it is not obvious that we can
true whenever (2a) is. represent the fact that these different pairs of expressions have a property
(2) a. John is a linguist and Mary is a biologist. in common (that of the first being at least as informative as the second)
b. John is a linguist. in a uniform way. However, the boolean approach to semantics taken here
yields a completely natural solution to this problem, one which we explicate
Thus, given that (2a, b) lie in the fragment of English we intend to represent, below.
it follows that our system would be descriptively inadequate if we could not Notice that the problem here is not substantially different from explicat-
show that our representation for (2a) formally entailed our representation ing the sense in which the boolean connectives and, or, and not have the
for (2b). same meaning regardless of whether they combine with Sentences, PI'S,
In fact, anticipating slightly, we may note here that one novelty in our AP's, full Noun Phrases (John and every student), or any other sorts of
semantics is that it permits a natural and intuitive generalization of the expressions. Within linguistics, early approaches to this problem claimed that
entailment relation to expressions of category other than Sentence. To see we have only one and, or, and not by claiming that, in one way or another,
this pretheoretically, let us slightly reformulate the intuition of entailment sentences exhibiting conjunctions of expressions of category other than
as follows: e entails e' iff e contains all the information in e' (and possibly Sentence were somehow elliptical or shortened forms of more complex
more). In the case where e and e' are sentences, this intuition tells us that e sentences in which the and overtly conjoined sentences. Thus (8a) below
claims everything that e' does, and possibly more. So if the world is the was to be transformationally derived from (8b) in early versions of trans-
way e says it is we are guaranteed that it is the way e' says it is; that is, e formational grammar.
entails e' on the original intuition. And conversely, if the world is the way
e' says it is whenever it is the way e says it is, then clearly e has all the infor- (8) a. John (both) lives in New Jersey and works in New York.
mation of e' (and possibly more). So the intuition in terms of informativeness b. John lives in New Jersey and John works in New York.
coincides with the standard one for the case where e and e' are sentences.
But the intuition now covers expressions of other categories as well. However (as logicians realized much sooner than linguists) this approach
Pre theoretically, for example, the one place predicate (P 1 ) in (3a) below cannot be successfully carried through for the general case where Noun
contains all the information in (3b). In particular, Phrases other than ones denoting individuals are used, in the sense that the
meaning of the derived or elliptical construction is not in general the same
(3) a. walk and talk as that of the one it is elliptical for (derived from). Thus (9a) and (9b) below
b. walk are not paraphrases:
BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 5 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 7

(9) a. Some student (both) lives in New Jersey and works in New York. various pairs of expressions discussed earlier bear an informativeness relation
b. Some student lives in New Jersey and some student works in one to the other. All boolean algebras exhibit a partial ordering relation
New York. defined on the domain of the algebra in terms of the meet (or jOin) operation.
This relation is normally symbolized ~ and pronounced 'less than or equals'.
Obviously (9b) can be true in a situation in which (9a) is false and so is not It may be defined as follows: for all x, y in the domain of a boolean algebra,
a paraphrase of (9a). x ~df y iff the meet of x with y is in fact x. Equivalently, we could define
The approach we take to this problem is substantially different from the x to be ~ to y iff the join of x with Y is y. (The equivalence of these defini-
syntactic shorthand approach sketched above. It involves what we consider tions follows from the axioms which the meet and join functions are required
a significantly 'deeper' analysis of the nature of the denotations (= inter- to satisfy.)
pretations) of natural language expressions. As this analysis provides the Now, it turns out that the informativeness relation discussed earlier is
basis for the most significant innovations of our system as compared with in effect just the boolean less than or equals relation. More explicitly, for e
other proposals for model theoretic semantics for natural language, we shall and e' expressions in any boolean category C (one whose type is the domain
sketch it in outline here, leaving the full substance of the innovations to the of a boolean algebra), e is at least as infonnative as e' iff for every model,
body of this work. the denotation of e in that model is ~ to the denotation of e' in that model.
The basic idea is the following. In all model theoretic approaches to Thus, any boolean category will posses an 'entailment' relation among its
natural language, we associate with each category C of expressions a set expressions, and that fact is entirely due to the fact that the expressions of
of possible denotations, here called Tc or the type for C, defined in terms that category take their denotations in a set with a boolean structure - a
of the semantic primitives of the model. In standard first order extensional structure which itself is motivated by the desire to directly interpret conjunc-
logic (EL), the primitives of a model are two: a non-empty universe of tions, disjunctions, and negations of expressions in that category.
discourse U, and a set of two truth values, taken here as {a, I}. Models may While the need to directly interpret boolean combinations of expressions
thus differ according as they choose different U's. Once a universe U is in a category is the most obvious and direct motivation for taking the type
chosen, however, the types (sets of possible denotations) for categories are for that category to be the domain of a boolean algebra, it turns out not to
fixed, for they are defined in terms of U and the set {a, 1}, henceforth be the only motivation, nor even the 'deepest' one. 'Deeper', or perhaps
called 2. The type for Sentence (and Formula) is taken to be 2, and the more surprising, motivations concern the fact that we can say insightful
type for the individual constants and variables is taken to be U. The type things in boolean terms about the meanings of various expressions which
for one place predicates is the power set of U; so a PI will be interpreted are not obviously boolean in nature - that is, which do not involve and, or,
as a subset of U, intuitively the set of entities in U of which that PI holds or not or their various infinite analogues, such as every, some, no, always,
in that model. Similarly, the type for P2 would be the power set of U X U, sometimes, never, etc. As one sort of example, consider the semantics of
i.e. U 2 , the collection of all sets of ordered pairs over U. In general, TP n , Adjective Phrases (AP's).
the type for the n-place predicates, is the power set of n-tuples over U, un. The most productively formed AP's have the semantic property of being
(Equivalently, we can think of Tpi as the set of functions from U into 2; restricting in the sense that, booleanly speaking, skillful artist is ~ to artist
and more generally, TP n will be the set of functions from un into 2.) Finally, (but not apparent artist or fake artist). To say that the ~ relation holds
the type for the n-place function symbols is the set of functions from un among the above expressions amounts to saying that in any model, every
into U. individual with the skillful ( tall, female) artist property also has the artist
Notice, now, that the semantic primitives of EL, namely U and 2, have property - something which need not be the case when skillful is replaced
quite different statuses. Since U is an arbitrarily selected set, required only by AP's like apparent or fake; see Part II for details.
to be non-empty, it cannot be assumed to have any structure at all. We These facts are represented in our system as follows. The syntax of our
cannot, for example, assume that the elements of U bear any given relation logic uses sub categorization features such as +restricting to form subcategories
to each other. On the other hand, the set 2 is a set with a boolean structure of categories. Thus AP +rest is a (sub) category of AP in our system, one to
6 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 8 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW

- one which is on some approaches made quite explicit and on others is just which skillful, etc. belong but apparent, fake, etc. do not. In general, as
informally adumbrated by saying that the element 1 of 2 is understood as AP's syntactically combine with Common Noun Phrases, denoted simply
true, and the element 0 is understood as false. These latter informal remarks N in our system, to form Common Noun Phrases, all AP's are semantically
serve to ground our intuitive understanding of a formal statement that one interpreted by functions from TN into TN. TN, like most other types in our
or another formula is interpreted as I (or 0). But what do these statements system, is a set on which boolean operations are defined. We then define the
mean interal to logic itself? One thing they mean is that a conjunction of type for the restricting AP's to be the set of functions f from TN into TN
formulas (or sentences) is interpreted as 1 just in case each conjunct is so such that for allp E TN, f(P) <po
interpreted; in all other cases a conjunction is interpreted as O. This conforms In this way, then, we say what makes restricting AP's different in meaning
to our pretheoretical intuitions in that a conjunction of formulas is only from non-restricting ones. Note that we say it directly in terms of what sorts
regarded as true if each conjunct is; otherwise it is false. Similarly, a disjunc- of objects the restricting AP's may denote. Moreover, the constraint on their
tion of formulas will have value 1 iff at least one disjunct has value 1; and denotations is naturally given in purely boolean terms - it is thus something
a negation of a formula has value 1 iff the formula negated is interpreted we could not say as easily if TN were not a set with a boolean structure.
as having value O. More of boolean interest can be said concerning AP's. For example, there
A more mathematical way to say all this is just to say that the set of is a naturally felt semantic distinction between 'merely' restricting AP's like
truth values must possess at least two distinct elements, call them the zero tall and AP's we call absolute (or intersecting), such as male and female.
and unit elements, and must have two binary functions, called meet and Syntactically, the former naturally compare and have superlative forms
join, and one unary function, called complement, defined on it. The meet (taller than, less tall than, tallest, least tall) whereas the latter do not naturally
and join functions are defined by the standard truth tables for conjunction form comparatives and superlatives. (If we say that Mary is more female
and disjunction respectively, and the complement function is defined by the than Sue we shift our interpretation of female from an AP absolutely desig-
truth table for negation. Then, in defining how complex formulas take their nating sex to one referring to properties characteristically or stereotypically
denotations as a function of those of their parts, we stipulate that a conjunc- associated with female individuals.)
tion of formulas is always interpreted as the meet of the interpretations of Semantically, there is a marked difference in logical behavior between
the conjuncts; that of a disjunction as the join, and that of a negation as the merely restricting AP's and absolute ones. Thus (lOa) below entails (lOb),
complement. whereas ( 11 a) does not entail ( 11 b).
Basically what this says is that the type for formulas is a boolean algebra:
it is a set with two distinguished elements on which are defined meet, join, (10) a. John is a female artist.
and complement functions which satisfy the (very stringent) axioms of b. John is a female individual.
boolean algebra (which we give explicitly in Part I of this work); and these (11) a. John is a tall artist.
functions are used in giving the interpretations of conjunctions, disjunctions, b. John is a tall individual.
and negations of formulas.
Now, on the approach we develop, in distinction to EL, essentially all It turns out (see Part l.B for details) that the constraint on the functions
types (with a few exceptions of some interest) are sets with a boolean struc- from TN into TN needed to interpret absolute AP's so that the entailment
ture. Thus, we can directly interpret conjunctions, disjunctions, and negations in (10) holds is again naturally given in boolean terms. In fact, an even
in most categories by taking them to be the appropriate meet, join, and more surprising result ensues: the type for the absolute AP's turns out,
complement functions of the interpretations of the expressions conjoined, extensionally, to be isomorphic to the type for the Common Noun Phrases,
disjoined, or negated. The sense in which we have only one and, or, and not N. So, up to isomorphism, we cannot distinguish absolute AP's from common
is explicated on the grounds that they are always interpreted as the meet, nouns. This semantic fact correlates with some interesting syntactic prop-
join, and complement functions in whatever set we are looking at. erties of these AP's in English: namely, absolute AP's include those AP's
In a similar way we can now explicate what we mean by saying that the which in many respects function syntactically like common nouns. For
BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 9 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 11

example, they combine with determiners to form full NP'S (N's in our is uniquely determined by the boolean operations (intersection, etc.) once
notation). Thus, (12a) is acceptable English while (12b) is decidedly un- the individuals are given. Somewhat more cognitively, we may say that a
grammatical. speaker can comprehend any NP denotation provided he knows what the
individuals are and what it means to take boolean functions of them, that is,
(12) a. Two males entered Mario's pizza shop at 6 p.m. what it means to take intersections, unions, and complements.
b.* Two taIls entered Mario's pizza shop at 6 p.m. More forma1ly, to say that a1l sets of properties can be generated from the
individuals by taking intersections, etc. is to say that the set of individuals,
We have, then, a non-obvious correlation between English surface form and the possible proper noun denotations, is a set of (complete) generators
logical form (semantic representation) which, to our knowledge, has not been (c-generators) for TN. Moreover, it turns out that the type for proper nouns
explicitly noticed before in the literature. is not merely a set of c-generators for TN, it is a minimal such set: provably,
While much more could be said (and is, in the relevant sections of this no subset of TN which is strictly smaller than the set of individuals can be
book) concerning the boolean nature of AP meanings, let us turn to two a set of c-generators for TN. We can, in fact, assess in a general manner just
other examples of semantically interesting properties of natural language how sma1l a subset of TN the type for proper nouns is. It turns out that in
expressions which are boolean, although not obviously so. Let us consider a model of n individuals (n not necessarily finite) there are 2(2 n ) sets of
here first other extensional predicates and their full NP (N) arguments. properties, i.e. possible f.i denotations. So, in a world of only 4 individuals,
Among the N's we treat in Part I, the Extensional Logic, are not only there are over 65,000 possible f.i denotations (65,536 to be exact)! In general,
proper nouns like John, Mary, etc. but also N's formed from Determiners then, the possible proper noun denotations constitute a very sma1l portion
(Dets) and Common Nouns Phrases, N's, such as every student, no student, of the complete set of possible f.i denotations. It is a sort of testimony to
at least three students, etc. In addition, of course, boolean combinations of the power of boolean operations that from such a small set the entire large
N's are N's, e.g. John and every teacher, John and (but) not every student, set can be computed.
either exactly two students or (else) exactly five students, etc Classically, Moreover, the proper noun denotations not only determine booleanly
the proper nouns constitute a syntactically definable subcategory of full what sets of properties can be referred to by arbitrary f.i's, there is a sense
NP's (i.e. N's), denoted here N +prop' In our system, then, the set of possible which we can make explicit in which they also determine what we can say
proper noun denotations will be a subset of the possible N denotations. In (in first order) about f.i denotations. What we can say about f.i denotations
fact, it turns out to be a subset with a very special semantic property, one is given by the set of one place predicate denotations, Tp I' Syntactically
naturally statable in boolean terms, and to our knowledge only statable in PI'S combine with N's to form Sentences, so semantically they can be repre-
boolean terms. We can thus characterize the meaning of the subcategorization sented by functions from TN into the type for Sentence (extensionally, the
feature +proper, and this characterization turns out to be interesting in the set {O, I}). In a model of n individuals, the total number of such functions
intensional logic (formulated in Part II) where other argument categories would be 2 raised to the power 2(2 n ), an incomprehensibly large number
(e.g. S, PI) are used in addition to N. even for very small values of n.
To get an informal feel for the semantically characteristic property of But are all such functions possible (first order) PI denotations? The answer
proper nouns consider first that we (extensionally) interpret proper nouns, is clearly no. Imagine, for example, a model in which John and Mary are
following Montague (1970), as sets of common noun denotations, called interpreted as different individuals. Then it will follow that the expressions
here (extensional) properties. Loosely, we represent John as the set of 'his' John, Mary, and John and Mary all have different denotations. If PI denota-
properties, e.g. doctor, non-vegetarian, tallest surgeon, etc. Let us refer to tions were arbitrarily selected functions from TN into the type for Sentence,
these sets of properties as individuals. They are not arbitrary sets of proper· Ts, then we might interpret a PI such as sleep by a function which assigned
ties, but rather must meet certain boolean conditions. For example, if John the John and Mary set of properties value 0 (false) but assigned the John set
has the doctor property he cannot also have its boolean complement, the value 1 (true) and the Mary set value 1. But this is obviously not possible,
non·doctor property, and conversely. Further, if he has both the properties for then (13a) below would be true and (I3b) false.
10 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 12 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW

p and q he must have the property of being both a p and also a q, and con- (13) a. John is sleeping and Mary is sleeping.
versely. For example, John must have the doctor property and also the lawyer b. John and Mary are sleeping.
property iff he has the property of being both a doctor and a lawyer. A similar
condition involving disjunctions holds, too. Note that the characterization of (NB: in our semantics we do not in fact represent tense and aspect. We have
just which property sets constitute individuals (possible proper noun denota- included it in our illustrative examples in this section, holding it constant
tions) are given solely in terms of the boolean structure on TN, the set of across relevant examples, for naturalness.)
Common Noun Phrase denotations. We return to this point in a different Obviously enough, (13a) and (13b) must have the same truth value. This
context below. amounts to saying that an arbitrary PI denotation cannot assign truth values
Individuals, then, are sets of a certain sort, namely, sets of properties. arbitrarily to N denotations; i.e., not all functions from TN into Ts are
It is natural to interpret conjunctions of individual denoting expressions possible (first order) PI denotations. But how can we characterize which
as the intersection of the sets denoted by the two (or more) expressions. of these functions are possible PI denotations? The answer is surprisingly
Thus, the expression John and Mary will denote the properties common elegant in boolean terms. From the example given above we may observe
to John and Mary. Similarly, we interpret John or Mary as denoting the that a PI denotation must assign to an intersection (meet) of N denotations
union of the John individual with the Mary individual. And, not Mary (as the truth value obtained by applying the function separately to each of the
it occurs for example in John but not Mary) will denote the set theoretic N denotations over which the meet was taken - we obtain a truth value
complement of the Mary individual, that is, the set of properties not in in each case - and take the meet of the resulting truth values in the truth
the Mary individual. value algebra Ts. Symbolically, we want to require that PI denotations
Clearly, then, the set of possible N denotations will include not only the preserve meets; i.e.
sets which meet the conditions of being individuals, but also those sets
obtainable from individuals by taking intersections, unions, and complements. (14) sleep(John and Mary) =sleep(John) and sleep(Mary).
Further, we want to be able to take arbitrary intersections and unions, not
just finite ones. Thus, we want every student to denote the properties com-
Drawing the functions which can interpret sleep from those from TN into
mon to the individuals with the student property, that is, the intersection
TS which meet this condition, we guarantee that (13a) and (13b) above
of all those individuals regardless of how many there happen to be. Similarly,
are logically equivalent. Similarly, we want a possible sleep interterpretation
some student will denote the union of the individuals with the student
to preserve joins (15) and to preserve complements (16).
property.
We may naturally wonder just how many of all the sets of properties can
be obtained from individuals by taking complements and arbitrary inter- (15) sleep(J ohn or Mary) = sleep(J ohn) or sleep(Mary)
sections and unions? The answer (Section A in Part I) is that any set of (16) sleep(not(every student)) = not(sleep(every student))
properties can be obtained in this way. So, we will want Til to be the set
of all sets of properties, that is, the power set of TN. Functions from a (boolean) algebra into another which preserve the boolean
We note further (Section A of Part I) that the power set of a non-empty operations in the above sense are called homomorphisms. Thus, we take TPI
set determines a paradigm case of a boolean algebra. Specifically, for A a to be the set of (complete) homomorphisms from TN into Ts. How many of
non -empty set, the power set of A, which we denote by A *, is the domain them are there? In a model of n individuals, there happen to be just 2n such
of a boolean algebra where the zero and unit elements are respectively the functions, the same as the number of (extensional) properties in a world of
empty set, 0, and A, and the boolean meet, join, and complement operations n individuals. This is exactly what we expect of first order predicates; that is,
are respectively set theoretic intersection, union, and complement (relative the first order predicates correspond one for one to sets of individuals, or
to A). The boolean < relation is provably just the subset relation. eqUivalently to the functions from individuals into 2. More formally, we will
Thus we have informally shown that the full set of possible N denotations prove (a generalized version of) the Justification Theorem given below:
BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 13 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 15

(17) For every function f from the individuals on TN into 2 there Pz's, etc. have in common which distinguish these types from the types for
is exactly one (complete) homomorphism from TN into 2 whose other categories? We have already seen that the (first order extensional)
values on the individuals are the same as f Pl's are homomorphisms. In fact, the Pz's are homomorphisms as well.
For example, the Pl's in (2la, b) below clearly hold of the same individuals
(To say that a homomorphism is complete is just to say that it preserves and thus are extensionally the same, whence the Pz kiss must preserve meets:
arbitrary meets (intersectjons in the case at hand) and arbitrary joins (unions),
not just finite ones.) Thus any property of individuals uniquely determines (21) a. kiss some student and every teacher
a possible PI denotation, and conversely. b. kiss some student and kiss every teacher
It turns out then that the individuals, the possible proper noun denota-
tions, are indeed an exceedingly special set of jiJ denotations. They are not Let us ask then what categories are such that their types are sets of homo-
only a set of complete (c) generators for TN, they are free, in that PI deno- morphisms (defined by their values on the individuals). We find not only
tations can take their values freely, in any way we like, on individuals; then, the n-place Predicates among these, but a few other categories as well. In
their values on all the other sets of properties are uniquely determined by particular, the type for 'transitive' AP's like fond (o/), jealous (a/), etc. which
the fact that PI denotations are complete homomorphisms. Thus, modulo combine with N's to form ordinary AP's such as fond of John, jealous of
the boolean operations, the proper noun denotations determine not only some student, etc. consists of homomorphisms. For example, the property
what the full set of jiJ denotations is, they also determine what can be said a teacher has if he is fond of either John or Mary must be the same one he
about them (in first order - see Part I.B for a discussion of various sorts has if either he is fond of John or he is fond of Mary. Thus, loosely, we want
of higher order predicates and their homomorphic nature). the equation below to hold, whence fond of preserves joins:
Let us emphasize finally that the above discussion not only presents a
very special semantic property of proper noun denotations, that of being (22) fond of (John or Mary) = (fond of John) or (fond of Mary).
a set of complete, free generators for TN, it has thereby also revealed a rather
special property of TN itself, namely, that it is an algebra which has a set of Similarly, 'transitive' common nouns, the 'relational' nouns of philoso-
such generators. 'Most' boolean algebras do not have that property. In fact, phers, such as friend (a/), colleague (a/), etc. are semantically homo-
those which do are provably just those which are isomorphic to power sets morphisms. Thus, for example, an individual has the property of being a
of power sets, and thus have cardinality 2(2n) for some cardinal n. friend of either John or Mary iff he has the property of being a friend of
It is reasonable to ask whether the types for any other categories in our John or a friend of Mary, so friend (a/) preserves joins.
system also have individuals (Le. complete, free gnerators). In the extensional Finally, certain extensional prepositions seem to behave homomorphically
logic in Part I the answer is no. In particular, the types of Modifier categories on their N arguments. Thus, if someone works in [either New York or
like AP's and Adverb Phrases and Prepositional Phrases are not algebras Chicago], then he works either in New York or in Chicago, and conversely.
with individuals. Similarly the types for the n-place Predicates do not have Hence, we want in [New York or Chicago 1 to be extensionally the same PP
individuals. And finally, the type for Determiner is not such an algebra. modifier of work as in New York or in Chicago whence in preserves joins.
However, the intensional logic in Part II does present some categories Similarly, taking no as short for not a, we have in no bar (i.e. in [not (a bar)])
whose types do have individuals. This is the case for the category S, which = not [in a (any) bar], so in preserve complements.
syntactically includes expressions like those italicized in (18) below: Let us define then a boolean algebra to be a Predicative Algebra iff its
elements are homomorphisms. We may then by extension call a category
(18) a. John believes that Fred is a linguist. a Predicative category if its type is a Predicative algebra. The (extensional)
b. John believes either that Fred is a linguist or that Mary is a categories thus characterized as Predicatives then are the n-place Predicates,
biologist. transitive AP, transitive Common Noun, and Preposition. This class does
c. John believes that Fred is a linguist but not that Mary is biologist. appear to be a reasonably natural syntactic class. For example, it largely
14 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 16 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW

Similarly the type for the category of infinitival nominals, which we represent coincides with those categories whose expressions may show agreement
formally as Pl , and which includes the expressions italicized in (I9) below, with features of Argument categories such as person, number, and gender.
also have individuals: We have then given two sorts of semantic types needed for a natural
language semantics: Argument algebras (ones with individuals) and Predi-
(19) a. To study in the summer is difficult. cative algebras (ones whose elements are homomorphisms). We note the
b. To (both) stand on your hands and sing the national anthem is Predicative algebras we use are not in general algebras with individuals,
difficult. and that Argument algebras never have homomorphisms as elements.
c. (Both) to stand on your hands and to sing the national anthem Are there yet other types of algebras we need for natural language seman-
are difficult. tics? A reasonable place to look is at Modifier categories like AP, Adverb
Phrase, and Prepositional Phrase. These categories are always interpreted by
It appears then that categories which function as arguments of predicates functions from one algebra into itself. These functions are most commonly,
are characterized by types with individuals (see Part II for a discussion of but not always, as we pointed out earlier, restricting; moreover, these algebras
what the individuals are in the Sand Pl algebras). Other major classes of have subalgebras of absolute or intersecting functions which are isomorphic
categories such as Modifiers, Predicatives, and Specifiers (= Determiners) to the domain of the functions. If we define an algebra to be a Modifier
do not have types with that semantic property. algebra just in case its elements are restricting functions from an algebra into
itself, and if we define a category to be a Modifier category just in case its
type is a Modifier algebra, we find that extensionally we identify the AP's,
1.2. Characterizing Possible Semantic Systems for Natural Language
Adverb Phrases, and PP's as modifiers. Again, this seems a rather natural
The above discussion provides the first step in characterizing constraints syntactic class.
on possible semantic systems for natural language. Let us define a boolean We note that algebras of restricting functions do not have individuals,
algebra to be an Argument algebra iff it has individuals (a set of complete nor are they algebras of homomorphisms (the only function which is both
free generators). Then we can say of natural logics that they must include restricting and a homomorphism is the identity function). So, Modifier
some Argument algebras among their types. Let us further define a category types are in principle distinct from the types of Argument categories and
of a language to be an Argument category iff its type is an Argument algebra. Predicatives.
We can now state a non-obvious correlation between syntactic form and Thus, we can begin to make some substantive claims about what sorts
semantic representation: the categories whose types are Argument algebras of denotation types we need in a natural logic: at the very least, we need
(N, S, etc.) are just those which receive case marking, trigger verb agreement, Argument algebras, Predicative algebras, and Modifier algebras. Are there
and are affected by syntactic operations like Passive and Raising. Note that any others?
these latter two operations do in fact affect all the 'bar' categories we have The only category with productively formed members in the extensional
discussed: logic we propose which we have not yet considered is that of Determiner
(Det). Syntactically, Dets combine with Ns to form N's, and include ex·
(20) a. The President is believed to be a jelly bean addict. pressions like every, at least two and at most six, John's, no student's etc.
b. That Fred stole the money is believed to be false. Semantically, then, Dets will be interpreted by functions from properties
c. To study in summer is believed to be difficult. into sets of properties, i.e. from TN into TN. But are just any such functions
possible Det denotations in English? We argue here, based on Keenan and
Do the other sorts of categories we have consiered also have types with Stavi (I981) and Barwise and Cooper (I980), that only functions which meet
(booleanly) distinguished properties? The answer appears to be yes, though a condition we call conservativity are possible Det denotations. Essentially,
many specific points remain to be worked out. Consider for example the these are just the functions f which make the equation below true, thinking
n-place predicates. Are there semantic properties which the types for Pl's, of student and vegetarian as arbitrary properties:
BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 17 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 19

(23) [(students) are vegetarians iff [(students) are both students of English meanings are simply ignored by us. In particular, this is true for
and vegetarians. tense and aspect marking. The reader may think of sentences in our formal
system as being intended to hold at a point (or interval) of time. For cases
Obviously, every student is a vegetarian iff every student is both a student where entailments are justified, the points (or intervals) of time are held
and a vegetarian; similarly, exactly two students are vegetarian iff exactly constant across entailing and entailed sentences.
two students are both students and vegetarians; John's dog is a vegetarian Of more theoretical and sometimes methodological import, there are
iff John's dog is both a dog and a vegetarian, etc. two reasons why we have chosen to make our LF's distinct from English
The conservativity condition appears to characterize elements of TDet. surface forms (SF's). First, it is our judgment that the SF's of different
Let us then (somewhat tentatively) define an algebra of functions from a languages differ more than the minds of the speakers of those languages.
set A into its power set A * to be a Specifier algebra iff its elements are just It is thus reasonable, we feel, to expect that what we can say across languages
the conservative functions from A into A *. is more similar than the specific means used to say it. Hence, we expect
On this definition, just what categories will turn out to be Specifier that LF's, for languages, that is, meaning representations, are more similar
categories? So far, only Det itself. Therefore, it may be that Det is a rather than their surface forms are. For example, we expect that the LF's needed
special category and its type rather unique among the types we need to for English and Japanese differ less than the SF's needed for English and
represent natural language denotations; or it may simply be that we have Japanese. Consequently, we have tried to eliminate from our LF's properties
not looked hard enough to find other sorts of specifiers: or perhaps we have of English SF's which are obviously not fairly general across languages -
not yet formulated the notion of a Specifier with sufficient generality. A provided, of course, these properties are not semantically significant and so
more general definition might allow us to represent Dets as simply a rather need not be referred to by the interpreting function. In particular, we do not
special case of Specifiers and yet include other categories as well. Com- represent in our LF's agreement phenomena, case marking on Argument
plementizers such as that, whether, etc. show some similarities to Dets, but do categories (but see Part I.B for some discussion of case marking determination
not seem very productively formed; AP's also show some similarities to Dets by predicates), or, more surprisingly perhaps, word order. Thus our LF's,
and are more productively formed, but we have so far not found a convincing while possessing a fairly rich constituent structure, do not define a linear
formulation to include Modifiers and Specifiers as special cases of something (word) order relation on their terminal elements. Derived expressions in our
more general. (See Keenan and Stavi, op. cit., for some discussion.) system are formed by taking sets over simpler expressions. Thus, the LF
we use to represent the meaning of (24a) is given in (24b), where, as usual,
curly brackets are used as in set theory.
2. ON THE RELATION BETWEEN ENGLISH FORM AND
LOGICAL FORM (24) a. Every doctor likes some female patient
As indicated at the beginning of this Introduction we have emphasized initially b. s
the nature of the objects which interpret English expressions, as that is the fii~S!fii
aspect of our semantic proposals which is perhaps most new. That discussion /~ --~-
may leave the reader with the (incorrect) impression that the purpose of fii/N N (S/N)!N N
our semantic work was to see just how much of English semantics we could -~
N/N N
squeeze into a boolean format. In fact, however, our motivation was quite
~
other. The boolean nature of our semantics emerged slowly and painfully at N/N N
first and then by leaps and bounds during the course of our work. Neither I
N/N
author began this enterprise with any particular awareness of boolean algebras. abs
Rather, our work began with a desire to provide a semantics for natural
language which was comparable in expressive power to the intensional logic {{every, doctor}, {like, {some,
I
{female, patient}}}}
18 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 20 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW

of Montague (l973) (henceforth PTQ) but which was explanatorily more We note here that our logical syntax employs the slash notation in a standard
adequate according to certain criteria we discuss briefly below. way: expressions of category X/Y combine with ones of category Y to form
In Section 1 above we formulated the basic criterion of Logical Adequacy ones of category X. In addition, however, we form derived categories in two
for natural logics: they must correctly represent our pretheoreticaljudgments other ways: first, we use (a limited set of) features to form subcategories,
of semantic relatedness among the expressions of the naturallanguage(s) we as in N/Nabs, abbreviated APabs, for absolute adjective phrases; and second,
are studying. This criterion is basically the criterion of descriptive adequacy we have adopted (and adapted) the bar notation of current linguistic theory,
as the term is used in Linguistics (Chomsky, 1965). Given a semantic system thereby representing a category difference between e.g. {female, patient}, aN
of some reasonable degree of descriptive adequacy, we may consider it or Common Noun Phrase, and {some, {female, patient}}, a f.i or full Noun
explanatorily adequate to the extent that it is useful in accounting for aspects Phrase.
of language other than the judgments of semantic relatedness which directly Note that while word order, case marking, and verb agreement are not
motivate the system. marked in (24b) it is trivially easy (up to choice of tense) to construct the
What are some of these other aspects of language? The overwhelmingly English sentence whose meaning is intended to be represented by (24b).
most obvious one is that speakers use English expressions with the particular We have not attempted in this work to rigorously define the read out func-
meanings they do in fact have. More specifically, speaker/hearers usually tion which would formally associate LF's with the English forms they are
correctly understand the utterances they hear and produce, even though intended to represent. For most cases of LF's which illustrate what is new
these are often novel in the sense of never having been heard or uttered by about our system, the value of that function at a given LF is obvious, as in
the relevant parties before. That is, in some reasonable sense, speaker/hearers (24b) above. Fully specifying that function, however, would require that
have learned and can use the (by and large) correct meaning representations we enter many details of agreement and word order phenomena which are
for English expressions; moreover they can do this in 'real time' - time spans irrelevant to our principle goal of representing English meanings. We note
appropriate for the conduct of everyday social intercourse. We might note without example here that our logical syntax covers a larger fragment of
as well, a point analogous to one stressed in the early syntactic literature in English than e.g. PTQ, and that characterizing the corresponding SF's of
generative grammar, that children learn at a rather young age not merely to English is considerably more difficult than in that work.
produce well formed Le. grammatical expressions of English, they learn to A second reason for a disparity between SF and LF here lies with the
use them meaningfully - to assert things they intend as true, to deny and nature of English ambiguity. Semantically ambiguous forms, as judged
contradict what other have said, to make inferences on the basis of what pre theoretically , can not be directly interpreted. If a sentence S could be
others have said, etc. both true and false in a given state of affairs then we could not even define
We should like then our semantic theory to represent explicitly the asso- an entailment relation, since we could argue that the sentence both entailed
ciation between English expressions and the objects we use to represent itself (trivially, it is true if it is true) and that it didn't entail itself (since we
their meanings, called here logical forms (LF's). Obviously, the most direct have a case where it is true and also false). We must therefore associate
way of achieving this would be to use the English expressions themselves different LF's with each 'reading' of an ambiguous expression. For example,
as the objects which we formally assign denotations to (interpret). The we represent the classical quantifier scope ambiguities in sentences like
spirit of our proposals is thus more consonant with the approach taken in (2Sa) below by the two LF's, (2Sb) and (2Sc).
Montague (l970) (henceforth EFL) than with that of PTQ.
The LF's we use, then, will resemble ordinary English in a great many (2S) a. Every student read a book
respects, which we discuss below. But our LF's are not identical to English b. (every student) (read (a book))
surface forms (to the extent that we know what they are). The disparity c. (a book) (Ax ((every student) (read x)))
is justified here on both practical and theoretical grounds. On practical
grounds, we must acknowledge that the meaning system of English is much Note that here, and elsewhere, we normally use ordinary parentheses rather
richer than we know how to represent, so some overtly expressed aspects than curly brackets when using expressions of our formal language. The
BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 21 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 23

structure in (25b) above, basically isomorphic to that in (24b), represents (28) a. Fred is hard to believe that the University would fire.
the reading in which every student has wide scope over a book. For most b. to (Ax (believe that the University fire x)).
speakers this is the most natural reading, and the structure we use for it
corresponds very well to the observable English surface form. Another sort of case where we want lambda derived Pn 's are the Raising
(25c), on the other hand, represents the reading where a book has wide to Object cases. Thus, following believe in (29) below, we have first an Nand
scope over every student. The syntactic structure of (25c) corresponds much then a P l infinitive, of which the N is the understood argument.
less well to that of (25a) than does (25b), and is clearly syntactically more
complex than (25b). The sub expression (Ax «every student) (read, x))) is (29) John believes Fred to have stolen the money.
a P 1 , i.e. an expression of category SIN; semantically it takes the denotation
of a book as argument yielding as value a sentence denotation. In several languages, however, the 'raised' N, Fred above, need not function
Despite this poor correspondence to SF, however, we have decided to live as the subject of the main predicate of the P l infmitive. Thus in languages
with structures like (25c) in our system. The reasons are largely, but not as diverse as Chicewa (Trithart, 1977), Fijian (Gordon, 1978), and Kipsigis
entirely, practical. The alternative, instantiated in PTQ, is to handle quantifi- (Jake and Odden, 1979) we can form raising pairs like those illustrated in
cation or 'NP insertion' as a substitution rule, generating distinct LF's which (non-) English below:
grossly resemble (25b) but which code in some way the order in which the
N's every student and a book are put into the structure. This would make (30) John believes the money that Fred has stolen it.
the LF's and consequently the interpreting function for the language as a
whole much more complicated. We chose not to countenance these com- Note that a pronoun remains in the position from which the money was
plications (exemplified in the translation function of PTQ) since the focus raised, the complementizer remains, and the clause is finite. In these respects,
and contribution of our monograph does not concern variable binding such clauses in those languages do not differ at all from the case where the
operators (though we include three such in our system). In short, we do not embedded subject is raised. And these structures can be represented in the
want to complicate the things we are interested in in favor of something same way as the subject raising ones, provided we have a way of representing
we are not. the expression following the money above as a PI (that would take the
Note further that the substitution rule by itself, and the resulting analysis money as argument). And that is precisely what the lambda operator affords
trees, still requires the use of variables or 'place holders' of infinite numbers us: (31) below is such aPl.
(it obviously doesn't matter whether we write them as hen or x n), still
requires some coindexing mechanism, and most awkwardly, still yields LF's (31) (AX (Fred stole x)).
which do not approximate well to the independently motivated SF's in
English. As regards this latter point we refer the reader to Partee (1975) in There remains a final disparity between our LF's and SF's they are in·
which the attempt to relate the analysis trees of PTQ to the sort of labelled tended to represent, one which in English concerns only a limited range of
bracketings used in defining ordinary syntactic operations in English is structures. Consider that for three-place Predicates in English at least two of
unsuccessful. Both approaches, then, appear to yield LF's with poor corres- the arguments must linearize on the same side of the P3 in surface structure.
pondence to SF's. We feel that the reason for this poor correspondence is Different linear orders will be compatible with different constituent struc-
that NP scope differences in natural language are not in fact coded or in tures at LF, but since the preferred linear order often depends on the relative
general reflected in the derivational history of an expression. If so, we have surface size of the arguments, it will happen that sometimes the constituent
a situation where we need something in LF which really doesn't correspond structure we assign to a LF does not match with the preferred linear order.
to anything in SF. Similar statements hold for various ways of forming syntactically complex
Moreover, in (weak) favor of our approach we would like to suggest the P2 's - the preferred order of argument and modifier, for example, is again
following two points. subject to very surfacy constraints.
22 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 24 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW

First, there does appear to be a correlation, in many simple cases, between For example, among the subcategories to which verbs like find and con-
the preferred reading of an expression and the LF which most closely corres- sider belong is one which combines with AP's to yield ordinary fj taking
ponds to it syntactically. We have already illustrated this in (25a, b). A P 2 's. The orders illustrated in (32a, b) are both acceptable, but only (32a)
somewhat different case is that illustrated by: is immediately compatible with the constituent structure of the LF we
assign it.
(26) John is looking for a unicorn.
(32) a. I find unacceptable the proposal put forward by the chairman.
(26) is arguably ambiguous according as a unicorn is within the scope of b. I find the proposal put forward by the chairman unacceptable.
look for or not. The most natural reading is where it is in the scope of look
for, in which case it is understood non-transparently (not implying the In (32) the a-structure is perhaps somewhat better than the b-one, but as the
existence of a unicorn), and it is this reading which is represented by our fj argument (the proposal . .. ) is replaced by less 'heavy' ones the a-structure
LF (isomorphic to (25b» which corresponds constituent for constituent decreases in acceptability. For example, choosing it for the fj argument
to (26). The transparent reading of (26) in which a unicorn is outside the renders the a-structure ungrammatical.
scope of look for is the one for which we must use the lambda operator. We are simply not concerned in this work with arguing whether one
If further investigation continues to support the claim that the less structure in (32) is more basic than the other. We refer the reader to Keenan
accessible readings are ones whose LF is more complicated, that fact may (1982b) for evidence from universal grammar supporting the existence of
perhaps serve as an explanation for the lesser degree of accessibility. a surface operation called Argument Attraction which reorders an argument
A second possible advantage of using the lambda operator directly in our of a headed Pn to be adjacent to the head. We note without example here
LF's is that the structures they create may prove to be useful in representing that a considerable diversity of structures may, depending on word order
properties of natural language other than scope ambiguities. Note that our conventions in the language, yield structures which are inputs to that re-
lambda operator syntactically derives an n+ 1 place predicative from an ordering process. Various examples arise during the course of this work.
n-place one, where the argument category of the derived predicative is given In summary then, our LF's do exhibit certain regular divergences in form
by the type of the variable used with lambda. (We treat sentences as D-place from the SF's they represent, but typically these divergences are sufficiently
predicates - a sentence combines with zero arguments to form a sentence.) regular to make the computation of the SF quite easy given a LF. Further-
There appear to be a variety of cases where we want LF's for such derived n+ 1 more, we note below a variety of often non-obvious ways in which the LF's
place predicates which do not involve inserting lV's into expressions. we employ do present properties of SF's, and thus we consider that we have
One such case in English involves unbounded 'Tough Movement'. Sen- achieved to a significant extent the goal of representing the association of
tences (27a, b) below illustrate respectively the case where we want predicates (surface) form and meaning in English.
like be tough, easy, difficult, etc. to take P 1 infmitives as arguments yielding First of course, for a great many cases of even fairly complex SF's, we
Po's (Sentences) and where we want to allow them to take P 2 infinitives find that their constituents are in a one-to-one correspondence with those
as arguments yielding P 1 's whose argument category is the same as that of of the LF's we use to represent their meanings. Now, our LF's are com-
the P2 from which it is derived. positional, in the sense that the interpretation of syntactically complex
expressions is given as a function of the interpretations of their constituents.
(27) a. To believe that Fred would steal the money is hard. Consequently, we satisfy the following (strong) form of the Fregean condi-
b. That Fred would steal the money is hard to believe. tion to a large extent:

(Note then that S's as well as ordinary lV's can undergo 'Tough'). We want, (33) The Fregean (Compositionality) Condition
then, the expression following hard in (28a) below to be a P2 infinitive, which An English expression e is derived from expressions ej, ... , en
it will be, semantically, if it is represented with the use of a lambda operator if and only if the interpretation of e is explicitly given as a
as in (28b). function of the interpretations of ej , ... , en.
BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 25 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 27

It is basically the satisfaction of this condition which allows us to account system concerns the regularity in surface coding properties agreement
for how speakers comprehend novel utterances: if they know what the and word order in particular - of the function-argument relation defined
parts mean, and if they know how structures derived in that way take their at the level of LF. As regards word order, not having marked it at LF allows
meanings as a function of their parts, then they can figure out what the us to state generalizations concerning the regularities in the ways in function-
whole means. For example, as we mentioned earlier, we form boolean com- argument structures are linearized in the world's languages. For example,
binations (conjunctions, disjunctions, and negations) in almost all categories. the most widespread word order type - the verb final languages - may be
The derived expressions are directly interpreted as a function of the inter· characterized as follows: Predicatives follow their arguments, Modifiers
pretation of the conjuncts, disjuncts, etc. that they are derived from. If they (and Dets) precede. Just the opposite word order assignment holds for the
were derived by 'reducing' sentences, we could not in general give the correct rigorous verb initial languages, viz VOS ones like Fijian, Ineseno Chumash,
interpretation of the derived structure as a function of what it was derived Malagasy. VSO and SVO languages generally follow the pattern for VOS
from. ones with the exception of the position of the subject which occurs some-
Secondly, syntactically similar structures are interpreted in semantically what more to the left than predicted. Note that since we have many categories
similar ways. This condition can be formulated more rigorously in a variety of Predicatives, Arguments, and Modifiers these generalizations represent a
of special cases, but a few examples will be sufficient to indicate the non· fairly large number of specific claims about word order regularities. And
trivial sorts of correspondences it covers. of course these generalizations are only possible if we can actually give
As a first case, distinct expressions of English having the same grammatical properties that Predicatives, for example, have in common. This we have
category must be represented by expressions in the logic having the same done in semantic, in fact boolean, terms. We refer the reader here to Keenan
category and thus interpreted as elements of the same type. So, items of the (1979) for more detailed discussion. Here we only stress that there are
same category denote the same type of thing; and conversely, items in regularities in the way our function-argument structures are expressed in the
different categories denote differently. Thus, following the lead of Montague SF's of the world's languages. So, to the extent that apprehending these
(1970) here, proper nouns and quantified noun phrases (John and every function-argument relations is important to understanding the meaning of
man respectively) are both expressions in category fl in the logic and thus expressions we can say that languages do provide fairly regular observable
both denote sets of properties. Of course, since the proper nouns form a means in surface for expressing these relations. (Needless to say, of course,
subcategory of fl, they take their denotations in a proper subset of TN. On other quite independent phenomena such as contraction and cliticization also
the other hand (in distinction to some forms of Montague Grammar), since affect word order regularities in surface.)
common nouns and Pl's are syntactically distinct categories in English, As regards agreement phenomena, the following claim receives good sup-
they will be syntactically distinct in the logic and thus have distinct types. port from our function-argument assignment at LF: Expressions offunctions
(Extensionally, TN and Tpl are disjoint but isomorphic; this isomorphism may agree with expressions of their arguments. So Predicatives may show
does not hold in our intensional logic, though TN there is isomorphic to a agreement with their Arguments (by 'may' here we mean that there are some
subcategory of Pl.) languages in which they do show such agreement), and Modifiers and Dets
As another somewhat more novel case (as compared to the semantics may show agreement with their arguments. We again refer the reader to
of PTQ) note that Pl's and P2 's are distinct but in many ways very similar Keenan (1979) for supporting data and justification for the claim that the
categories in English. For example, lexically simple elements in both categories agreement of function expressions with argument expressions is not an
are traditionally called verbs; expressions in both categories commonly arbitrary regularity of natural language. There it is presented as a special
enough across languages exhibit agreement with their arguments (Pl's with case of the Meaning-Form Correlation Principle given below:
their subjects, P2 's with their objects). Both may 'host raising' to their
argument position; i.e. Pl's like is certain, raise to subject, and P2 's like (35) The Meaning-Form Correlation Principle
believe raise to object. Similarly, the common forms of Equi are ones in For X and Y categories, the form of expressions of category X
which it is controlled by arguments of Pn's; i.e. it is the subject argument may depend on (vary with) the form of expressions of category
26 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 28 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW

of the PI want to leave which controls the reference of the infinitival phrase, Y in a structure E if the meaning of the expressions of category X
whereas in persuade (John) to leave it is the object of the P2 which controls depends on (varies with) those of category Y in that structure.
it. Both PI'S and P2 's in many languages undergo Passive, such as Latin,
Turkish, commonly in Uto-Aztecan, etc. Finally, both accept certain sorts Note that there is an intuitive sense in which the 'meaning' of a function
of adverbial modification. (34a) below illustrates the case where the P l expression may depend on that of its argument; namely, what the function
examine the patient is modified by individually (Le. the doctors acted in- 'does' to the argument may vary with properties of the argument. Standard
dividually); (34b) illustrates the case where the P2 examine is so modified examples from mathematics are, say, the absolute value function, where
(so the patients were treated individually), and (34c) is properly ambiguous the value of the function varies systematically according as the argument is
as to the scope of individually. positive or negative. Similarly, rounding off functions are of this sort. A more
arbitrary example would be a function f which sends a number x to x 2 if
(34) a. The doctors examined the patient individually. x is odd and to x 3 if x is even.
b. The doctor examined the patients individually. Similarly, in natural language we find that the expressions we have in·
c. The doctors examined the patient individually. terpreted by functions exhibit this sort of variation with respect to their
arguments. For example, a PI like run implies both internal movement
Given these strong similarities, then, we expect that PI'S and P 2 's will and external movement (i.e. relative to other things) when the argument
be interpreted in semantically similar ways. And this is the case in our system. expression denotes animate things. So, if a horse runs we understand (without
Extensionally, both are functions of a very similar sort, namely homomor- further qualification) that both his parts move and that he changes location
phisms, with the same domain, TN. They differ only with regard to their relative to other things (however momentarily). But if the argument expres-
range algebras. Consequently, we are able to formulate several of the pro- sion is a mechanical object, the sense of external movement is absent: watches
cesses mentioned above in a fully general way, that is, for Pn's in general, or cars may run without changing location. And, for the rather more special
regardless of whether n has value 1 or value 2. (See e.g. the treatment of cases of things like faucets and noses, neither internal nor external movement
Passive in Part LB.) Note that the uniform semantic treatment of Pn's is in of the object is intended; rather something else of an appropriate sort is
marked distinction to the treatment in PTQ. understood to move out of the object.
More generally, the classification of the sorts of algebras needed for Analogous claims hold for modifiers. A strong animal is one which can
natural language given earlier determine somewhat farther reaching corres- exert a lot of force; but a strong chair or wall is an object that can withstand
pondences between SF and LF. Thus, while Argument categories like N, S, a lot of force, etc.
and the various Pl 's are syntactically distinct, they clearly exhibit, as pointed In general, then, we adjust our interpretation of function expressions to
out earlier, syntactic similarities. And within our approach their types are suit the nature of the argument they are applying to. Note the similarity
semantically similar in a non-obvious way - they have free generators called here to the reinterpretation of expressions used in everyday metaphors,
individuals. Similarly, the various categories of Modifiers, e.g. AP, AdvP, discussed in Faltz (1982). Typically it is the function expression which
and PP exhibit syntactic similarities (but also differences) which are repre- gets interpreted in some non-literal way rather than the argument expression.
sented in our system by the (semantic) similarities of their types - the If we say that John exploded when he heard the news we do not alter our
major subcategories here are always interpreted by restricting functions, interpretation of John but we likely alter our interpretation of explode
and subcategories of those by absolute (intersecting) functions. It is unsur- (though we could intend it literally). Similarly, in a shaky proposal it is the
prising, then, to find regular means of converting expressions in one category function expression shaky whose sense is adjusted to the nature of proposals;
to another. For example, the -ly function in English (slow ~ slowly) basically proposal is understood in its ordinary literal sense.
expresses the isomorphism between restrictive AP's and restrictive Adverb A further related class of cases here concerns various forms of 'fixed
Phrases. expressions' such as idioms and proverbs. Often enough all expressions are
A third and yet more general correspondence between SF and LF in our non·literal in proverbs, as in the early bird gets the worm. In many cases of
BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 29

idioms, however, we find that certain expressions are interpreted literally and
PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC
others non-literally. However, the former are typically Argument expressions,
the latter function ones. Thus, in he jumped from the frying pan into the A. The Core Language, L
fire, the entire PI is non-literally interpreted (usually) but its argument he
is interpreted in an ordinary literal referential way.

In this section we present an elementary formal language L, called the core


3. AN ONTOLOGICAL INNOVATION
language, whose associated semantics is rich enough to illustrate the major
In one respect, namely, the choice of semantic primitives, our approach innovations we propose. Syntactically the language L is intended to represent
differs strongly from all other approaches to model theoretic semantics for the basic predicate-argument structure of (first order) English. The English
natural language. categories represented in L are: Common Noun Phrase (man, student, etc.),
Recall that in EL (standard extensional logic, to which we limit ourselves Full Noun Phrase (John, every man, etc., a category which includes Proper
here for illustrative purposes) a model contains two semantic primitives, Noun Phrase as a subcategory), Determiner (every, some, etc.), One Place
the set of truth values and the universe of discourse U, in terms of which the Predicate (sleep, walk, etc.), Two Place Predicate (hug, kiss, etc.), and
possible denotations of all expressions in the language are defined. Now, EL Sentence (sometimes referred to a Formula or as Zero Place Predicate).
has the property referred to in Keenan (I 982b) as ontological perfection: Essentially all categories of L are boolean in that complex members can be
the semantic primitives are themselves possible denotations for expressions recursively formed from simpler ones by taking combination with and, or,
in the language, truth values being denotable by sentences (formulas), and and not all derived expressions are directly interpreted as a function of the
the elements of U (entities) being denotable by individual constants (proper interpretation of their immediate constituents.
nouns) and individual variables.
However, once EL has been enriched along the lines of Montague (1970,
1. SYNTAX OF THE CORE LANGUAGE L
1973) the resulting logic is no longer onto logically perfect. In particular,
proper nouns and individual variables now take their denotations in the To define the core language L we shall define first a set CAT of category
set of what we have called individuals, sets of properties (common noun names, and second, relative to a set V of basic vocabulary defined by listing,
denotations) which meet certain conditions. Thus, no expressions in English we shall define a set PEv of possible expressions over V. Then we shall
take their denotations (via the translation function, in PTQ) in U itself. This associate with each name C in CAT a set n(G) of possible expressions called
actually seems mysterious. Why should the meanings of expressions be the category named by C. A category then is a set of expressions, and L is
defined ultimately in terms of something which we can not refer to in prin- defined to be the union of these sets.
ciple and so in some sense cannot know? Why should the denotation of a
syntactically unanalyzable expression such as John be given as a function of
an entity which no proper part of John denotes? (Extensionally recall, John Defining CAT
is translated in Montague grammar as (AP) (P(j)), where oj' denotes in U). The elements of CAT are built up recursively from two primitive category
U then seems mysterious, a kind of noumenal world of entities which names 'N' and 'P', which we may think of as nominals and predicates respec-
underlies the phenomenological world of individuals. On our approach, tively. 'N' for example will turn out to name the category of (zero place)
U has been eliminated altogether, and the resulting (extensional) logic is common noun phrases. It will include expressions like man, woman, etc. 'P'
ontologically perfect. The key to eliminating U is, un surprisingly perhaps, will name the category of formulas, which we regard as zero-place predicates.
boolean. Recall that on Montague's (extensional) approach, the type for Complex category names are formed from simpler ones by the use of slashes
common nouns is the collection of subsets of U, and thus constitutes a power (J), bars C), and sub categorization features. We provide a quick illustration
set boolean algebra. Individuals, proper noun denotations, are particular of this notation below.

31
30 BOOLEAN SEMANTICS: AN OVERVIEW 32 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

subsets of that algebra. It turns out that we can define those subsets in purely Given that N is a category name (we drop the use of single quotes where
boolean terms without reference to U at all. Further, it is a standard theorem it is clear from context that we are talking about the symbol and not the
of boolean algebra (see Part I for details) that power set boolean algebras category it names) we may form the category name N using the bar notation.
are completely characterized (Le. up to isomorphism) by satisfying two N will name the category of full noun phrases, including members like every
additional boolean requirements: completeness and atomicity. man, John, John and every man, etc. From the category name N we may
Thus, on our approach, the semantic primitives of a model are taken to form the name Nprop , which will name a subcategory of the category named
be an algebra of truth values as before together with another algebra P of by N, namely the category of proper noun phrases, which includes expres-
properties, required to be complete and atomic. Noting that the truth value sions like John, Mary, etc.
algebra 2 is also complete and atomic, we now have a more uniform set of Finally, given that Nand N are in CAT, we may use the slash notation to
primitives - two boolean algebras of similar sorts. Moreover, the system is fOrm the category name NIN which names the category of expressions which
ontologically perfect, since the algebra P is the type for the common noun combine with expressions of category N to form expressions of category
phrases. Individuals are defined as subsets of P which satisfy certain boolean N. This category will include expressions like some, all, some but not all,
conditions, and provably, as in the spirit of EL, P is isomorphic to the power etc. and will sometimes be abbreviated as Det, for Determiner.
set of the individuals on P. So up to isomorphism we can still think of a Below we give a formal definition of CAT. We use f/J to denote the empty
property as being a set of individuals; the only difference now is that in- set, and for any set W, W* denotes the power set of W, that is, W* =df {K:
dividuals are defined in terms of properties, whose boolean nature is directly K ~ W}. And standardly, for any ordinal n ~ 1, wn will denote the set of
justified by judgments of entailment in natural language, rather than the all sequences of n elements of W. We note that the full generality of the
other way around. notation given below will not be utilized in the syntax of the core language
This approach then provides a simplification of the ontology (= semantic itself, but it will be used in various of the extensions of that language to be
primitives) of a natural logic. Moreover, it suggests the following interesting proposed later.
question: is there any sense in which common noun denotations, properties,
are linguistically more basic than proper noun ones, individuals? In Part LA DEFINITION l. SFL, or the set of subcategorization features of L, is
we answer this question in the affirmative. {{proper}} .

DEFINITION 2. CAT, or the set of category names of L, is the least set of


finite sequences chosen from SFL U {'N', 'P', '/" '-', ,)" '('} which satisfies
conditions (i) through (iv) below:

(i) 'N' E CAT and 'P' E CAT


(ii) if X E CAT and f E SF L then J
E CAT, where J
abbreviates
the sequence (X, f>
(iii) if X E CAT then X E CAT, where X abbreviates the sequence
(X, -)
(iv) if X E CATn and Y E CATn, any ordinal n ~ 1, then (XIY) E
CAT

Discussion of the Definition


(i) The notation for subcategories mentioned in clause (ii) above requires
that f be a non·empty set of features. In writings we shall normally omit
SYNTAX OF THE CORE LANGUAGE L 33 SYNTAX OF THE CORE LANGUAGE L 35

the set brackets. As the core language L is extended we shall add more ele- with AP's to form PI'S. Moreover once prepositional phrases (PP's) such as in
ments to SFL rob bing it of its currently trivial character (there is only one the garden are added to L it is a simple matter to extend the category of be to
element, {proper}, in SFL as currently defined). <PI, PI, PI) / <.ii, AP, PP). Somewhat more interestingly, consider the case
(ii) In clause (iv) above X and Yare both n-ary sequences of elements of PP's themselves. They appear to combine with PI'S to form PI'S, i.e. sing
of CAT. For the case where n = 1 this rule coincides with the standard one and sing in the garden are both expressions of category Pl. We shall argue
in categorial grammar, since then CAT n is just CAT I which is in effect just further that PP's should also be allowed to combine directly with P 2 's to
CAT, so X and Yare elements of CAT and XIY names the category of expres- form P 2 's, i.e. we shall treat both find and find in the garden as P2 's 1. The
sions which combine with ones of category Y to form ones of category X. natural suggestion then is that PP's may combine generally with Pn 's to form
Consider now the case for n = 2. Then X is a sequence of two category Pn's. We may then assign such expressions to the category X/X, where X is
names, say (XI, X2>' Similarly Y = (Y I , Y2>, and XIYis (XI, X 2>/ (Y I , Y2>. the infinite sequence <PI, P2, .•. ). More speculative but possibly deeper
Expressions in the category named by this complex symbol will combine uses of this notation will be presented in the intensional logic (Section II).
with ones of category Y I to form expressions of category XI, and they will (v) The notation in Definition 2 for deriving complex category names
combine with ones of category Y 2 to form expressions of category X 2 • And from simpler ones is semantically motivated. Specifically, in the semantics
more generally for X, Y E CATn, expressions of category XI Y will combine for L we will associate with each C E CAT a set of possible denotations
with expressions of category Yi to form expressions of category Xi, all (relative to a model) for expressions in the category named by C. This set
i (1 < i < n). The utility of this notation, which will not be used in the will be called the type for C and denoted Te. Now the types we associate
core language but will be used in various of its extensions, will be illustrated with complex category names are defined in terms of those we associate
shortly. with the names they are derived from. In general in L the following depen-
(iii) In terms of the slash notation in clause (iv) we may define certain dencies hold: the type for a category of the form ~ will be a subset of Tx,
natural classes of category names which will be useful both in the syntax the type for X; just which subset is determined by the interpretation of the
of L, and, more importantly, in the semantics for L, These classes will be features in f. The type for a category of the form X will be (Tx)*, the power
called predicative hierarchies. set of Tx. (This dependency will be somewhat generalized in the intensional
logic.) And the type of a category of the form X/Y will be some set of
DEFINITION 3. For all C E CAT and all non-negative integers n, functions f whose domain is the union of the TYi' for all Yi in the sequence
Y, whose range is U TXi' and whose value at any y is in TXi if Y is in TYj"
(i) Co =df C and (vi) Notice finally a technical usage in Definition 2. We define CAT to be
(ii) Cn+l =df Cnlfil the 'least' subset of a certain set satisfying certain conditions. Formally the
least subset of a set A satisfying some conditions F is the intersection of all
For each C E CAT, the set of Cn as defined above will be called the predica- the subsets K of A satisfying these conditions. Having given the definition
tive hierarchy generated by C and denoted PHc. in this way we must of course show that the intersection is in fact a set
The elements on the left side of the equality sign above are new category satisfying F. In the case at hand the proof is easy and will be omitted.
names introduced into our notation for convenience. Thus Co 'abbreviates' In defining the language L itself we shall have occasion to use a somewhat
C, CI abbreviates Colfil, etc. Intuitively an expression of category Cn+l will more complicated form of taking 'least' sets. Specifically we shall define a
combine with an expression of category N to form a en. 'Ultimately' then a naming functon n from CAT into the sets of possible expressions over the
Cn+1 combines with n + I expressions of category fil to form a Co, that is, a basic vocabulary V. n will be defined to be the least function satisfying
C. Thus Cn is the category of n-place C's. In particular Pn is the category name certain conditions. In general the use of 'least' here is to be interpreted as
for n-place predicates. So Po (= P) is the name for the zero place predicates, follows. Given sets A and B, consider the set G of functions from A into B*,
i.e. the formulas. PI (= PolN) is the name for the one place predicates, P2 the power set of B, which satisfy certain conditions K. The least function
(= PdN) the name for the two place predicates, etc. And in general, the from A into B * satisfying K is, by definition, that function f whose value
34 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 36 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

predicative hierarchy generated by P, namely {Pn: n ;;;;. O} is the set of n-place at each a E A is the intersection of the g(a), taken over all g E G. This clearly
predicate categories of L. defmes f to be a function from A into B*, but of course we must prove that
Notice of course that other categories besides P determine predicative f so defined satisfies K.
hierarchies. That generated by N, namely {No, N I , ... } is the set of n-place
common noun phrases. No of course is just N. NI is No/N. In the extensions
Defining V and PE V
of L we propose expressions like friend (of), cousin (of), etc. will have this
category. They will thus combine with full noun phrases like John, every DEFINITION 4. V, or the basic vocabulary of L, is the set
student, etc. to form No's like friend of every student, etc. And these expres-
sions, like lexically simple No's, will combine with determiners like a, every, {and, or, not, John, Mary, man, woman, student, bachelor,
etc. to formNs, e.g. a/riend of every student, etc. existent, sleep, exist, die, walk, laugh, kill, kiss, hug, be, every,
Similarly in extensions of L the category N/N, abbreviated AP for Adjec- all, a, some, no, the}
tive Phrase, determines a predicative hierarchy. API for example will include
To define the possible expressions over V recall from the Overview that
'transitive' adjectives like fond (of), jealous (of), etc., which combine with
derived expressions in this system, in distinction to many others, are not
full noun phrases to form complex adjective phrases, APo's, like fond of
formed by concatenation but merely by taking sets of simpler expressions.
Mary, etc.
Thus our representation for John is sleeping will be the set {John, sleep} and
The notion of a predicative hierarchy is both a technically useful one
not the string ('John"sleep").
and one which makes a substantive suggestion concerning how complex
expressions may be formed in semantically regular ways from simpler ones
DEFINITION 5. PE v, or the set of possible expressions over V, is recursively
in natural language. Technically, it allows us to extend L by big steps easily
defined by the following conditions:
giving a more adequate approximation to the complexity of natural languages.
In particular once we have provided a semantics for a category C, we have (i) Ifx E V then x EPE v .
a regular way to assign interpretations to Cn's for every n, regardless of (ii) If Y~ PEv is finite then YEPEV'
what category C is. In particular given a semantics for en the semantics
we associate with Cn +l is determined. We illustrate this in L with the most Definition 5 could have been given somewhat more rigorously, but in fact
productive case of predicatives, the Pn's. In more substantive terms it seems its exact nature plays little role in what follows. 2 We need PEv simply to
that natural languages actually avail themselves of this operation of forming provide a domain inside of which the categories of L may be defined.
a Cn + 1 from a Cn , independently of the nature of C. Thus our notation Let us sketch the argument that {John, {kiss, Mary}} is an element of
suggests, correctly, that we may expect to find one place common nouns, PEv. From Definition 4 we have that kiss and Mary are elements of Vand
one place adjectives, etc. in languages. so in PEv by (i). Thus {kiss, Mary} ~ PEv and so by (ii) is an element
(iv) Let us consider now the advantages of our generalized notation for of PEv. Since John E V and so in PEv by (i), we have that {John, {kiSS,
forming slash categories. In the simplest cases, subject to some restrictions, Mary}} is a subset of PEv and so in PEv by (ii). On the other hand PEv
it allows us to represent expressions which, naively, have more than one abounds with absurdities such as {and, {{ {and}}}. Such possible expressions
category. Consider for example be. On the one hand it appears to be a P2 , will not be in any category named by any CECAT and thus will not be
combining with an N such as a student to form a PI is a student (which we expressions in L.
write as be a student since verb agreement is not represented in the system).
On the other hand it combines with AP's like female to form PI'S like be
Defining L
female. In our notation then we may assign be directly to the category
(P I, PI> / <Ft, AP> rather than having to say for example that English has two The categories of L will be those subsets of PEv named by the naming
be's, one which combines with N's to form PI'S, the other which combines function n defined below:
SYNTAX OF THE CORE LANGUAGE L 37 SYNTAX OF THE CORE LANGUAGE L 39

DEFINITION 6. n is the least function from CAT into (PE v )* satisfying Recalling that within a constituent linear order is not defined we might also
the conditions given in (i) through (iv) below: represent this expression as (student every) sleep or sleep (student every). But
we could not use every sleep student or student sleep every.
(i) Lexical Conditions (vii) In illustrating examples of complex expressions we shall sometimes
{John, Mary} ~ n(Nprop ) use lexical items of English not included in V when it is obvious to which
{nwn, wonwn, student, bachelor, existent, individual} ~ n(N) category they belong. Thus we may consider that English expressions like
{sleep, exist, die, walk, laugh} ~ n(Pd John greeted and either hugged or kissed Mary are represented in L as illus-
{kiss, hug, be, have, kill} ~ n(P2) trated in (3):
{every, all, a, some, no, the} ~ n(N/N)
(ii) Subcategory Conditions (3) Po
For all CE CAT and alltE SFL, n(9) ~ n(C)
(iii) Conditions on Functional Applications
For all ordinals k :> 1, all X, Y E CATk, and all e, e' E PE v, if
e E n(X/y) and e' E Yi, Yi the ith term in the sequence Y, then P2
{e, e'} E n(Xi), Xi the ith term in the sequence X.
P2
~ P2
(iv) Conditions on Boolean Combinations
For all C f Nprop in CAT, all e, e' E PEv,

i'll'
if e E n(C) and e' E n(C) then {e, and, e'} E n(C), iiprop N prop
{e, or, e'} E n(C), and {not, e} E n(C).
I
John greet and hug or kiss
I
Mary
We note without proof that n as defined is in fact a function from CAT into
(PEV)* which satisfies conditions (i) through (iv). (viii) As an exercise in our notation the reader may find it instructive
to construct representations for the following English sentences: Not every
DEFINITION 7. Cat, or the categories of L, = {n(C): CE CAT} student is sleeping, Every man kissed a woman, John is a man, John is not
a man, John but not Bill read the book, Some student was singing and danc-
DEFINITION 8. L = UCat ing, Some student was singing and some student was dancing. Note that
not every student may be generated in two different ways on our syntax:
(not (every student», in which not combines with an ii to form an ii, or
Remarks on the Definitions
«not every) student), in which not combines with a Det (= iilN) to form
(i) We shall henceforth use the elements of CAT to refer to the categories a Det.
(elements of Cat) which they name. Thus we shall write man EN rather than (ix) Finally it is instructive to contrast the syntax of L with that of stan-
nwn En(N). dard first order logic (FOL) as regards its similarity to English.
(ii) Note that and, or, and not are not members of any category. Such
expressions will be called syncategorematic. The only syncategorematic (4) a. Eng: John loves no student
elements of Vare and, or, and not. L: (John (love (no student»)
(iii) It follows from Definition 6 that the only non-empty categories FOL: (Vx) (student (x) - 7 not (love (John, x»)
of L are N, R, Nprop , N/N, Po, PI, and P 2 . Of these, all but Po have lexical b. Eng: John but not Bill kissed Mary
members, that is elements which are also in the basic vocabulary V. In the L: (John and (not Bill» (kiss Mary)
extensions of L we propose other categories will become non-empty in either FOL: (kiss (John, Mary») and (not (kiss (Bill, Mary)))
38 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 40 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

of two ways: one, we shall add new items to V and new lexical conditions Intuitively L-representations of English correspond much more closely
(rules) assigning them to categories currently empty, and two, a few new to English than do those of FOL. Perhaps the most striking difference is that
types of rules (conditions) will be added allowing us to form derived expres- 'Quantifiers' like every, no, etc. in L combine directly with common nouns
sions in Pn for all finite n, as well as N n for all finite n. to form full noun phrases as in English, whereas quantifiers in FOL are
(iv) The categories mentioned in clause (iv) of Definition 6 will be called necessarily constructed with a variable and do not form constituents with
boolean categories. Thus all categories of L are boolean except Nprop . Note common nouns. Thus (4a) and its L-representation contain no variables,
that by the Subcategory rule (clause (ii) of Definition 6) all elements of whereas its FOL-representation does. Note that in this respect L resembles the
Nprop are al~o elements offl. Thus the expression {John, and, Mary} is an languages used in Montague Grammar and this resemblence is not accidental:
element of N but not of Nprop. The formal argument that this is so is as in the semantics we use for quantified N's we have availed ourselves of
follows: By lexical rule both John and Mary ~e elements of Nprop. By the Montague's basic intuition which enabled him to treat John and every man as
subcategory rule then both are elements of N; thus by the rule of boolean having the same (gross) logical category. Note also in this regard that treating
combinations {John, and, Mary} is an element of N. We may represent this quantifiers as formula level operators in FOL forces it to render complex
argument informally by the following (unordered!) tree: noun phrases as formulas combined by logical connectives with others for-
mulas. Thus the FOL-representation of (4a) uses a connective, -.. (if-then)
(1) N not present in the English sentence or its L-representation. Note that the
FOL-representation of (4a) contains four properly embedded formulas,
N N whereas neither (4a) nor its L-representation contain any.
A second major difference between Land FOL concerns the productivity
I I of the boolean operators and, or, and not. L, like English, allows essentially
N prop N prop
all categories to form complex members with these operators. FOL on the
I I other hand, and by and large Montague Grammar as well, restrict these
John and Mary operators to formulas. Thus the L-representation of (4b) is largely isomorphic
to (4b)3 whereas its FOL representation again contains a multiplicity of
(v) Similarly the unordered tree in (2) below represents the argument that properly embedded formulas. As noted in the Overview, one of the innova-
{ {every, student}, sleep} is an expression in L of category Po (Formula). tions of our semantics is the provision of a general method for interpreting
and, or, and not regardless of the category of item they combine with. The
(2) Po semantics needed to do this turns out to be enlightening as regards the
-~ semantics of many categories not apparently related to the boolean operators,
N Pj (=Po/N) such as adjective phrases, n-place predicates, and predicative hierarchies
-~ generally.
N/N N In these respects, English resembles L more closely than it resembles FOL.

every
I I
student sleep
On the other side of the ledger, English shares with FOL but not with L the
structure of linear order. However, in the face of the massive differences
between the syntax of English and the syntax of FOL, the presence of linear
(vi) In presenting complex expressions of L certain liberties will be taken order in the latter does not seem to confer upon it a great deal of similarity
with our notation in the interests of readability. In particular we will com- to English.
monly use ordinary parentheses instead of curly brackets; outer parentheses Overall then, noting principally the absence of tense and aspect marking in
will often be omitted, as will commas. Thus the expression represented in L, it appears that the semantic structures represented by L can be integrated
(2) above will usually be presented informally simply as (every student) sleep. rather easily into a general grammar of English. Considering only the limited
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 41 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 43

fragment of English we have (so far) intended to represent it should not be Second, the ontological primitives of our system do not include entities
difficult for example to define an interpreting function from English into or individuals, i.e. proper noun denotations. Proper noun denotations, hence-
L which associates with English sentences L-structures which represent forth called individuals, are characterized in terms of common noun deno-
their meanings. tations, henceforth called extensional properties (or more simply, properties,
We turn now to the semantics of L. as these are the only kinds of properties considered in L). In our presentation
of the types we shall provide a basic justification of this point. Here we
simply note without discussion that taking properties rather than individuals
2. THE SEMANTICS FOR L
(or entities) as primitive simplifies the ontology of L compared to that of
We shall provide a semantics for L in two steps. First, we shall associate other systems and permits a better correspondence between English forms
with each category C of L a set of possible denotations for expressions in and the logical forms of L. It does not however change the class of valid
that category called the type for C and denoted Te. As indicated earlier, arguments representable in L. Thus L is a strictly first order extensional
the types for complex categories will be given in terms of the types of those logic which differs from classical logic (for the moment) only in not providing
categories from which they are formed. The types for the primitive categories, for non-trivial uses of variable binding operators. We shall of course extend
No (= N) or the zero place common noun phrases, and Po or the zero place L to include these, in which case then all arguments shown to be valid in
predicates (formulas), are defined directly, not in terms of other types, and classical logic are valid in L. As we further extend L of course its expressive
thus constitute the semantic primitives, or as we shall sometimes say, the power will exceed that of classical logic.
ontology, of L.
Once the types are defined we shall define the notion of an interpretation The Type for Po or Formulas
of L. Basically this will be a function m which associates with each expression
e in a category C some element of the set Te subject of course to certain In standard first order logic (FOL) the formula denotations are given by
conditions. In particular the value of m at complex expressions such as the set {O, 1} of truth value (0 = false, 1 = true). The identity of these two
John and Mary, every student, etc. will be determined by its values at the objects is irrelevant to the logic; it is sufficient that they are distinct and that
expressions the complex ones are formed from. On the other hand, the values one of them is designated as true, the other as false. It is important to realize
of m at lexically simple expressions can be any element of the corresponding however that the set of truth values in FOL is always treated as possessing
types, subject only to certain lexical constraints. Thus some lexical symbols, a boolean structure, though different formulations of FOL differ with regard
such as every, exist, etc. are intuitively logical constants, and will be inter- to how explicitly they codify this structure in the formal statement of
preted by m as designated members of their types. Further, the value of m the semantics for complex formulas. But all approaches must say in one way
at certain lexical symbols is constrained relative to that of others, e.g. the or another that a conjunction of formulas is true iff each conjunct is true,
interpretation of bachelor is not independent of that of man, etc. a disjunction is true iff at least one of the disjuncts is true, and a negation
As will be clear in what follows, the most fundamental step in defining of a formula is true iff the formula negated is false. Thus, details of formalism
a semantics for L lies in the definitions of the types. Once they are given, aside, all approaches may be described as ones in which formulas are inter-
the interpretations of expressions by elements in the types is very largely preted as truth values, i.e. an interpreting function for the language, which
obvious. we call m, maps formulas into {O, I}, a set we henceforth refer to simply
Before defining the types it will be well to recall the basic descriptive as 2. And all approaches say in effect that where Sand T are formulas,
m(S and T), the interpretation ofthe conjunction of S with T, is given as some
adequacy criteria in terms of which we evaluate whether a proposed semantics
for a fragment of English is adequate or not. This criterion is simply that the function, call it /I, of m(S) and meT). The function is defined of course
entailment relations among sentences of English must be correctly charac- by the standard truth table for conjunction. Explicitly, writing the function
symbol between its arguments, we have that (1/1 1) = 1, and (1 /I 0) =(0 /I 1)
terized. For example, pretheoretically, (Sa) below is judged to entail (5b),
= (0 /I 0) = O. Then the defmition of the interpretating function m applied
but the converse entailment fails.
42 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 44 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

(S) a. Some student is both singing and dancing. to conjunctions of formulas is given by m (S and T) = m (S) II m (T). Similarly
b. Some student is singing. the interpretation of disjunctions is given by m(S or T) = m(S) v meT),
where V is the following binary function on truth values: (0 V 0) = 0 and
Informally, to say that (Sa) entails (Sb) is just to say that (Sb) is true when- (0 v 1) = (1 v 0) = (1 v 1) = 1. Finally, m(not S) is defined to be (m(S»)',
ever (Sa) is; that is, if the world is the way (Sa) says it is, we are guaranteed where the' function (called complement) is defined by l' = 0 and 0' = 1.
that it is the way (5b) says it is. The converse, however, fails: it is certainly Thus in FOL, the set of truth values is taken to be a set with two distinct
possible that some student is singing without there being any student who elements on which are defined two binary functions, II and v, which we
is both singing and dancing. Now L provides representations for these sen- shall call meet and join respectively, and one unary function', called here
tences, and in the semantics for L we formally define an entailment relation. complement. This just says that the type for formulas in FOL is a boolean
If our semantics is adequate for these English sentences it must be the case algebra of a particularly simple sort. To see this let us give a formal definition
that our formal representation of (Sa) formally entails that for (Sb) but not of a boolean algebra:
conversely. To the extent that this is not the case our semantics is incorrect.
We might note here that one enlightening aspect of our semantics is that DEFINITION 9. (3 is a boolean algebra iff (3 is a six-tuple ([3, Oil, lil' I\il' V il' ' (3)
it provides basic semantic relations (e.g. entailment) for essentially all cate- where B is a non-empty set called the domain of the algebra (3, Oil and lil are
gories, not just Po. Thus a more general, informal, way of saying that (Sa) elements of B, called the zero and unit elements respectively, II il and v il are
above entails (Sb) is to say that the information in (Sb) is contained in that binary functions on B (Le. functions from B X B into B) called meet and
of (Sa). To claim (Sa) is to claim everything in (Sb), and something more join respectively, and ' il is a unary function on B called complement, which
besides. Let us say then that (Sa) is more informative than (Sb). satisfy the following conditions. (We omit the subscript (3 in the statement of
And notice now that in the same intuitive sense, the P l of (Sa), namely the conditions): For allx,Y, z EB,
is singing and dancing, is also more informative than that in (Sb), is singing,
i.e. is singing and dancing says more about an arbitrary individual than (a) 0 f 1
does is singing. Similarly compare common noun phrases like man and tall (b) x IIY =Y II X (Commutativity Laws)
man. Intuitively the latter has more information in it than the former; any xvy=yvx
individual which has the property expressed by tall man necessarily has the (c) (x II (y V z» =(x II y) V (x II z) (Distributivity laws)
property expressed by man. (x v (y II z» =(x v y) II (x V z)

°
Thus in the semantics we provide, we define an informativeness relation (d) Complement laws
which obtains among elements e and e' in any boolean category. This relation (x II x') =
coincides with classical entailment when e and e' are chosen from the category (x v x') = I
Po. (e) Laws of zero and unit
(x v 0) = x
(x II 1) = x
Defining the Types for L
Our definition of the types is given quite simply in a single paragraph (p. (We shall adopt here the common practice of referring to a boolean algebra
103). That presentation, however, has two properties which will be unfamiliar by the name we use for its domain. In cases where we have different alge-
to some readers. First it uses certain elementary concepts of boolean algebra, bras with the same domain this would lead to confusion, but such cases
ones which in fact are all familiar from set theory, but which may appear will not arise in this paper.) The reader may easily verify that the set 2
unfamiliar when given in the more general notation of boolean algebra. (= {O, I}) is (the domain of) a boolean algebra, where the zero and unit ele-
Consequently our presentation of the types will include what we hope is ments are 0 and 1 respectively, and the meet, join, and complement functions
a minimally sufficient explication of the boolean concepts used. are defined by the standard truth tables for conjunction, disjunction, and
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 45 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 47

negation respectively. Assuming these definitions we may state this formally of individual constants, approximately the proper nouns of natural languages,
as follows: and the range of the individual variables. In our terminology then FOL takes
the type for Nprop as U, a semantic primitive.
Common nouns, not distinguished from P1 's in FOL, are thought of
as subsets of U, or equivalently functions from U into 2. On the former view,
To verify the truth of (6) we must show of course that the boolean axioms a N such as man will be interpreted as a subset of U and the predicate man
are satisfied. Clearly O2 f 12 since we defined O2 to be 0 and 12 to be I, and will hold of an entity x just in case x is a member of that subset. On the
these two elements of 2 (= {O, I}) were taken as distinct. So axiom (a) is latter view, man holds of x iff the function man is interpreted as maps x onto
satisfied. The other axioms are easily seen to hold by examining cases. For 1. For simplicity of presentation let us adopt for the nonce the former view,
example, the first commutativity law states that for all x, y E 2, (x /I y) is in which man is a subset of U. Then the set of possible denotations of N's
the same element of 2 as (y /I x). Clearly is both x and yare 1 then the (= Pi'S) is U*, the power set of U, that is the collection of all the subsets
definition of /I in the algebra 2 tells us that (x /I y) = 1 and (y /I x) = 1, so of U. Note that u* includes both f/J, the empty set, and U itself, (taken 1= f/J).
they are equal. If either x or yare 0 then (x /I y) is 0 and so is (y /I x), so In our terminology, then, TN =TPl = U* in FOL.
again (x /I y) =(y /I x). The other axioms are easily checked the same way. Notice, now, that power sets are examples of boolean algebras par excel-
We might note in passing that 2 is the smallest boolean algebra, in the lence. Indeed much of the development of modern boolean algebra has been
following sense. According to Definition 9, every boolean algebra B contains inspired by their use as abstractions or generalizations of ordinary set theory.
at least two elements, namely 0 and 1. The algebra 2 contains only these two Thus note:
elements. Any algebra which is fundamentally distinct from 2 must have some
elements in addition to these two. 4 (7) For S a non-empty set, (S*, f/J, S, n, u, ') is a boolean algebra,
We have just seen that the set 2 of the possible interpretations of formulas where S* is the power set of S, the zero element of the algebra is
of FOL can be regarded as a boolean algebra. We now take this algebra 2 to the empty set f/J, the unit is S itself, meet is ordinary intersection,
be our set Tpo' that is, the type for formulas for our language L. join is union, and complement is set theoretic complement rela-
We might ask, why go to the trouble of formally specifying Tpo as a tive to S.5
boolean algebra? One answer that we can give now (others will come later)
is that boolean algebraic structure will represent the semantic generalization To see that the six-tuple in (7) above is a boolean algebra note first that the
we need in order to interpret boolean combinations in essentially all cate- zero and unit, f/J and S respectively, are elements of S*, the domain of the
gories in a uniform way. Whenever the type for a category C is a boolean algebra, since each is a subset of Sand S* is the collection of all the subsets
algebra we will always interpret conjunctions of expressions in C as the meet of S. Further n, u, and' are functions of the right degree on S*, e.g. n maps
of the interpretations of the conjuncts. Similarly disjunctions will be inter- pairs of elements A, B E S* onto A n B, those elements of S which are in
preted as joins, and negations as complements. both A and B; thus A n B is a subset of S and so an element of S*. To see
For example, if TN is a boolean algebra, then the interpretation of the that the boolean axioms are satisfied we note first that since S was taken
N John and Mary can be taken to be the meet of the interpretations of the as non-empty, f/J 1= S, i.e. the zero and unit elements of the algebra S* are
N's John and Mary. Similarly, if TPI is a boolean algebra, then the inter- distinct. The remaining axioms are elementary truths of set theory. E.g. the
pretation of sing and dance can be taken to be the meet of the interpretations first distributivity law just states (A n (B U en= (A n B) U (A n C) for all
of sing and of dance. Similar statements can be made for expressions of elements A, B, C E S*.
various categories constructed with or and with not. Consequently by taking TN in FOL to be U*, we have in effect taken it
One conseql.!ence of such an approach can be seen immediately. Namely, to be a boolean algebra, specifically a power set algebra. Again of course
the axioms of boolean algebra will guarantee that certain pairs of expressions we might ask why go to the trouble to specify that U* is a boolean algebra
will have identical interpretations. For example it follows from the first under the set theoretic operations given above. The answer is essentially the
46 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 48 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

distributive law that the interpretation of (John and (Bill or Harry)) is the same as the one we gave earlier to the comparable question concerning Tp o.
same element of TN as the interpretation of «John and BilT) or (John and Here we may only note that if, e.g., sing and dance are interpreted as subsets
Harry)). This is empirically correct; for example, because these two expres- of U, then we can within the framework of FOL define boolean combinations
sions must have identical interpretations, it will follow that the formulas of P1 's in a natural way. For example sing and dance would just be interpreted
«John and (Bill or Harry)) (read the book)) and «(John and BilT) or (John as the intersection of the set which interprets sing with that which interprets
and Harry)) (read the book)) must have the same truth value. dance. Thus sing and dance would hold of an entity x iff x was in that set,
Note, therefore, that in L (and in English) the meaning of and (and or which from the definition of intersection is so just in case x is in each of the
and not) is not simply some way of relating sentence meanings. Rather, sets over which the intersection is taken, that is, x is in the sing set and also
the meaning of and is much more general and much more abstract, for in the dance set. And this is just to say that sing and dance holds of x iff
it relates meanings drawn from essentially any type. Its meaning is category both sing does and dance does. So taking the type for P1 as a boolean algebra
independent, since no matter what type is chosen, and relates pairs of mean- allows us to generate boolean combinations of P1's and to directly interpret
ings from that type in the same way, namely, in the way expressed by the them as meets, joins, and complements. 6
meet operation in boolean algebra. Analogous claims hold of course for or Consider now the more problematic type for R. FOL as we have noted,
and not. They express ways we think about things of whatever type rather has no such category, although it does have the equivalent of a subcategory
than 'intrinsic' properties or relations of things themselves. This suggests that of it, Nprop . It is clear however that we could ~t merely modify the syntax
the meanings of and, or, and not are a direct reflection of properties of the of FOL t~ create more complex elements in N prop , however, since U, the
human mind. As George Boole wrote many years ago, they represent 'Laws of txpe for N prop , is simply not big enough to provide denotations for complex
Thought' (Boole, 1854). In any event, even if the reader is not prepared to N's like every man. Imagine for example a U with just two members, say
extrapolate with us from the ubiquity of and, or, and not to laws of thought, John and Bill, and let man be interpreted as U itself (so everything which
he must concede that very few expressions of natural language may combine exists in that universe is a man). Then if all complex N's were to take their
with elements of almost any category to form derived elements in that denotations in U, every man would have to denote either John or Bill, say
category, and that in consequence we are motivated to find an interpretation John. Then every man is John would be true, which it obviously isn't since
for these elements which does not depend on the specific denotations of the Bill is a man and he is not John.
elements in the categories they combine with. We shall achieve just such a On the other hand, since John and every man are both syntactically N's
characterization of the meanings of and, or, and not by taking the types for we want them to take their denotations in the same type in order that we
most categories to be boolean algebras. The algebra used for formulas thus may give the interpretations of sentences as a function of their form.
represents only a very special case of a general semantic property of human A solution to this problem was provided by Montague (1970), a solution
languages. which we essentially adopt, but with certain changes. Let us, following
While we shall have more to say about the type for Po later let us now Montague's intuition for the moment, think of proper nouns not as denoting
consider the somewhat trickier types for N, N, andNprop . elements of U, but rather as denoting the collection of subsets of U which
contain a fixed element. Specifically, proper noun denotations, which we shall
now call individ1!£lls, may be defined by the following temporary definition:
The Types for N, N, and Nprop
To present these types let us consider first, in so far as possible, the corres- DEFINITION 10. For all x E U, Ix =df {K ~ U: x E K}. Ix will be called
ponding types in FOL. In addition to 2, FOL takes as a semantic primitive the individual generated by x. We then define Tjljprop to be {Ix: x E U}.
a non-empty set U called the universe of discourse. Elements of U will be
referred to here as entities. As U can be any non-empty set it possesses Note that each element of an Ix is a subset of U, that is an element of
essentially no structure, in distinction to 2 which possesses a rich if minimal TN = U*. So each Ix is itself a subset of TN, and thus a member of (TN)*, the
boolean structure. Semantically U is taken as the set of possible denotations power set of TN. Referring neutrally to the elements of TN as (extensional)
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 49 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 51

properties, we may thus think of the denotation of John as the set of prop- THEOREM 1. For all q E TN (= U*), {q} = n{Ix: x E q}n n{(Ix )':
erties which hold of some fixed element of U. And obviously enough the xf-q}.
elements of U are in a one-to-one correspondence with the set of individ-
uals. For given each x in U there exists an individual Ix . If x and yare dis- In summary then, Montague's approach to this problem, which we shall refer
tinct elements of U then Ix and Iy are distinct individuals, since Ix contains to for the nonce as EFOL (Extended First Order Logic), consists in the fol-
{x} as a member but Iy doesn't, and Iy contains {y} as a member, but Ix lowing: The semantic primitives are two: U and 2, the latter being a boolean
doesn't. algebra and the type for Po, the former being any non-empty set. The type
Now given this one-to-one correspondence it is trivial to modify the for N is U*, the type for fit is (TN)* (= (U*)*), and TN rop = {Ix: x E U}.
semantics of the Pn's. PI'S for example can be thought of as subsets of the Stated thus, this approach is precisely that takeJ in Keenan and Faltz
set of individuals (rather than subsets of U, the set of entities): equivalently (1978). EFOL suffers at least from two serious drawbacks however, one
they are functions from the set of individuals into 2. Thus for each predicate ontological and the other linguistic. Ontologically we may note that U is no
of entities on the old view we have a corresponding predicate of individuals longer the type for any category of English (or of L). No expressions denote
on the new view: we just replace the statements mentioning entities x by elements of U. Yet denotations for common nouns, proper nouns, and
statements mentioning individuals Ix. complex noun phrases are all ultimately defined in terms of U. Thus the
So far it just seems that we have copied over the old semantics in a more interpretations of many basic expressions in English are defined in terms of
complicated notation. But now we can achieve the goal of interpreting proper semantic entities which we cannot in principle refer to in English, whence our
nouns and complex N's in the same type. For example given that John and knowledge of these entities must be remote at best. U rather appears now as a
Mary are interpreted as individuals, say Ix and Iy respectively, we may now kind of noumenal world of entities which 'supports' the phenomenological
interpret John and Mary as Ix n Iy , the set of properties which Ix (John) and world of individuals. U then is an essential mystery on this approach and the
Iy (Mary) have in common. Similarly John or Mary can be interpreted as the ontology which comprises it is essentially mysterious. In the extension of this
union of Ix with I y , the set of properties true of John or of Mary. Finally, approach we propose below the mysterious U is eliminated completely,
not John can be interpreted as (Ix)', the set of properties which John does though proper nouns, full noun phrases, and common nouns otherwise
not have. preserve exactly the character they have on the mysterious approach.
Similarly, if we allow unbounded intersections and unions, we can interpret Linguistically EFOL has to some extent thrown the baby out with the
words like every and a. To see how this is done, let p be the subset of U bathwater. It has achieved on the one hand a better correspondence between
which interprets man. Then every man will be the set of properties which English forms and logical forms by interpreting elements of a same category,
all the individuals with the man property have in common. Formally, every John and every man, as elements of a same type, TN. On the other hand,
man denotes nUx: p E Ix}. In a parallel fashion, we can say that a man it formally treats lexically simple expressions, e.g. John, as semantically
denotes the set of all those properties each of which holds of at least one complex. Thus the interpretation of John is given as a function of something,
individual with the man property (that is, at least one man). Formally, a man namely an element of U, but in violation of our version of Compositionality
denotes U{Ix: p E Ix}. Note that a property p is a member of an individual in the Overview, John is not derived from anything which denotes this
Ix iff x E p, since p is a subset of U and Ix is the set of all the subsets of U element of U. This dependency is made explicit in (extensional) versions
which contain x as a member. Thus we might also write the denotation of of Montague Grammar in which John is translated into CAP) (PU», itself
every man above n{Ix: x E p}, and analogously for a man. interpreted as the set of properties which hold of the denotation of j.
In discussing these denotations we have referred to unbounded inter- On the approach we propose below there is no motivation for translating
sections and unions. As these operations will come up again, let us give a John into a syntactically complex expression in order to interpret it. All
more formal definition of them: expressions are interpreted directly; the interpretation of John is simply an
arbitrary element of the type for Nprop , and is not given as a function of the
DEFINITION 11. Given a set B, let K be a collection of subsets of B. interpretation of any other expression.
50 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 52 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Then, Eliminating the Universe (I)


a. nK =df {x EB: for all k E K, x E k} and
Eliminating U from the ontology of EFOL will necessitate alternate defini-
b. UK =df {x EB: for some k EK, x E k}.
tions for TN and Til as these are directly defined in terms of U. Once
Thus an object is in the intersection of a collection of sets just in case it is this is done, the typl1-~~ iii is defined, as before, to be (TN)*. Our intent
in each set over which the intersection is taken. And it is in the union" of a here is to eliminate U in such a way that these two types nonetheless have
collection of sets just in case it is in at least one of the sets over which the the same semantic properties they have in EFOL. Thus we will not alter the
union is taken. Notice also the followirtg useful notation. For K as above, class of valid arguments in the system, but only simplify the ontology and
n
we orten write nK as k E Kk and UK as Uk E Kk. improve the correspondence between logical forms and surface forms. On the
Consider now what the type for il should be on this view. It must include other hand, once the alternate formulation is given, it will admit of some
as elements all the individuals, as proper nouns are among the il's and they natural generalizations which will allow us to significantly enrich the class
denote individuals. As noted these individuals are subsets of TN, thus ele- of valid arguments we can characterize. Moreover our intuitive understanding
ments of (TN)*, the power set of TN. Moreover we want TN to be closed of the semantics of common nouns and hence of other types constructed
under complements and unbounded intersections and unions in order to from the type for common nouns will be enriched. That is, our semantics
provide denotations for negative il's such as not a student (= no student), will point out semantic properties of common nouns which have not to our
not every student, etc. and for universally quantified il's like every student knowledge been previously noted.
and existentially quantified il's like a student. Thus we want TN not only Conceptually the elimination of U will proceed in three steps: First, and
to include all the individuals but also all the sets of properties obtainable most fundamentally, an alternate characterization of TN must be found. Then
from individuals by taking complements, and unbounded intersections and TN will then be taken as a primitive instead of U. Next individuals (proper
unions. We will see in a moment that the sets obtained in this way constitute noun denotations), will be defined as subsets of TN which satisfy certain
all the sets of properties, that is, all the subsets of TN. So on this approach conditions. Crucial here is that these conditions are stated solely in terms of
we must take TN to be the power set of TN. the boolean structure of TN and thus do not require any antecedently exist-
Before proving that any set of properties is in fact obtainable from the ing universe of discourse to 'support' them. Finally, Til will be defined as
individuals by intersections, unions, and complements we note first that before, namely as the power set of TN regarded as a boolean algebra via (7).
e.g. unions of two or more distinct individuals are not themselves individuals.
For example, where x and yare distinct elements of U, Ix U Iy will contain
Characterizing TN
both {x} and {y} as members, and thus there can be no z E U such that
every element of Ix U I; has z as a member. For one of x, y must be different In EFOL TN is, as we have seen, a power set boolean algebra. Now it turns
from z, hence one of {x}, {y} will fail to contain z as a member. By similar out that power set algebras (we drop boolean where clear from context) are a
reasoning Ix n Iy is not an individual, nor is (Ix)'. Hence takingintersections, special case of boolean algebras which are characterized by two additional
unions, and complements of individuals yields new'sets,of properties (ones properties they meet over and above those required of boolean algebras in
which are not possible proper noun denotations). What·we want to show is general. Namely, they are complete and atomic. Below we define these
that any set of properties can be built up from the 'individuals by taking notions, noting the important fact that they are defined solely in terms of
intersections, unions, and complements. the primitives of boolean algebra. Then TN will be primitively taken as an
Now if Q is a set of properties then Q is clearly identical to the union of arbitrary complete and atomic algebra. As such it will possess exactly the
its unit sets, i.e. Q = U{{q}: q EQ}. SO if each unit set {q} can be built boolean structure of a power set algebra, but need not literally be the power
up from the individuals set theoretically then so can Qjust by taking unions set of some set.
of the unit sets. We state the results for unit sets below as a theorem (proof
at the end of this section). Completeness of boolean algebras. Let (S*, 0, S, n, u, ') be a power set
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 53 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 55

algebra as defined in (7). Since S * is a collection of sets, the subset relation, lub's for D they must be identical. Thus if a subset of an algebra has a glb
~, is defined on S*. Note that the subset relation is definable solely in terms (lub) it is unique. The following theorem is then straightforward:
of the structure of the algebra. For example, for all A, B E S *, we may
define A ~ B iff A Ii B =A. The reader can check that ~ so defined coincides THEOREM 3. For x, y elements of an arbitrary algebra B, (x II y) is the
exactly with the subset relation as standardly defined. Moreover for any glb for {x, y} and (x v y) is the lub for {x, y}.
boolean algebra a comparable boolean relation is defined as follows:
Thus in any algebra certain subsets always have a glb and a lub, in particular
DEFINITION 12. Let {3 = (B, 0,1, II, v, ') be an arbitrary boolean algebra. those subsets of the form {x, y }. In fact all finite subsets of an algebra have
Then for all x, y EB, x ~y iff x II y = x. a glb and a lub. Thus if D = {d 1, d 2 , ••. ,dn } is a finite subset of B a straight-
forward induction proof shows that ( ... (dill d 2 ) II ... II dn ) is the glb for
Note that from Definition 12 it follows that the boolean relation, ~, is the D. Replacing II by v above we obtain a lub for D.
subset relation, ~, in a power set algebra: since the meet operation in such We might point out here two special cases of finite sets which might be
an algebra is just set theoretic intersection, we have that for A, BE S*, A ~ B confusing in this regard. Consider first the empty set, (/J. It is a finite subset
iff A Ii B = A by Definition 12, whence by the set theoretical equivalence of any algebra. The glb of (/J is the unit element 1. It is trivially a lb since
noted above we infer that A ~ B iff A S B. The reader may check that the I ~ every element of (/J is vacuously true. It is the glb since if y is a lb for
following object language theorems concerning the boolean ~ relation follow (/J then y ~ 1 since every element in the algebra is ~ 1 (Theorem 2a). Similar
from the axioms of boolean algebra together with Definition 12 (Proofs at reasoning shows that the zero element is the lub for (/J.
the end of this section.) Secondly, consider unit sets. From Theorem 2 above, choosing x andy to
be the same element we have that the set {x, y} is just {x}. Thus from the
THEOREM 2. For all x, y, z E B, B the domain of a boolean algebra, theorem we have that (x II x) is the glb for {x} and (x v x) is the lub for {x}.
Note that the Idempotent Laws, x = (x II x) and x = (x v x) are object lan-
(a) o~x andx~ 1 guage theorems of boolean algebra. Thus x is the glb for {x} and x is also
(b) x ~x (Reflexivity) the lub for {x}.
(c) ifx ~y andy ~x then x =y (Antisymmetry) However, while every finite subset of an algebra has a glb (lub) it is not
(d) if x ~ y and y ~ z then x ~ z (Transitivity) necessarily the case that every infinite subset of an algebra does. If even the
(e) (x II y) ~x and (x II y) ~y infinite subsets of an algebra have glb's and lub's that algebra is said to be
(f) x~(xvy)andy~(xvy) complete. Formally,
(g) ifx~yandx~zthenx~(yllz)

°
(h) ifx~zandy~zthen(xvy)~z DEFINITION 15. A boolean algebra B is complete iff for every subset D of
(i) x ~y iff (x II y') = B there is an element x E B such that x is a glb for D, and there is an element
G) x ~ y iff (y v x) =y. y EB such thaty is a lub for D.

Since the theorems above hold in all boolean alegbras, they hold in par- (We note without proof that if every subset D of B has a glb then every subset
ticular for power set algebras. For example, taking X and Yas elements of D has a lub, and conversely.)
a power set algebra S*, (e) guarantees that (X Ii Y) ~ X and (X Ii Y) ~ Y. Note that every finite algebra (i.e. one whose domain is finite) is complete
Similarly from (f) we have that X ~ (X U Y) and Y ~ (X U Y). since any subset of it must be fmite, and from what we indicated earlier,
In an arbitrary algebra, the relation ~ cannot be identified necessarily every finite subset of an algebra has a glb and a lub. However not all infinite
with any otherwise definable relation on the elements. However, by abuse algebras are complete (see Mendelson (1970), p. 161 for examples). But all
of language, if x ~ y (x andy elements of some arbitrary alegbra B), we may power set algebras, whether finite or infinite, are complete. Specifically let
54 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 56 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

say that x is contained in y, or that y contains x, even though there is no S*, the domain of a power set algebra, be infmite and let K be any subset of
true sense of containment involved. Another, perhaps less misleading way S*. So each k E K is a set, i.e. an element of S* and thus a subset of S. It is
of describing this relation is to say that y dominates x. easily seen that nK is a glb for K. Since nK is the set of all the elements
Note that Theorems (b)-(d) above state that the boolean relation is a in S which are in each k E K, nK is clearly a subset of S and thus an element
partial ordering relation. (a) says that the zero element of the algebra is a of S*. Moreover it is a lb for K, since for any k EK, each element of nK is
minimal element (provably unique) in this ordering and that the unit element in k, so nK E k, for each k E K; thus nK is a Ib for K. Now suppose that
is the maximal element (provably unique) in the ordering. 7 And Theorems Y is a Ib for K. So each y E Y is in each k in K. But nK is the set of all the
(e) and (f) say that meets and joins behave in a regular way with respect to elements in each k in K, thus y E nK. As y was arbitrary in Y, then Y ~ nK,
the ordering. Specifically, taking meets forms smaller (or at least not greater) and thus nK is the greatest of the lb's for K. Analogous reasoning shows
elements than what you started with, and taking joins forms bigger elements. that UK is the lub for K. Thus an arbitrary subset K of S * has both a glb
In fact somewhat more can be said here. Let us define: and a lub, so S* is complete.

DEFINITION 13. For B an arbitrary boolean algebra andD any subset of B, A tomicity of boolean algebras. Let us turn now to the second characteristic
property of power set algebras, atomicity.
(a) a lower bound (1 b) for D in B is an element x E B such that for
alldED,x<d; DEFINITION 16. For B an arbitrary boolean algebra,
(b) an upper bound (ub) for Din B is an element x EB such that for
all d ED, d <x. (a) an element x E B is an atom iff (i) x =/= 0 and (ii) For all y E B, if
Y ~ x then either y = 0 or y = x.
It follows immediately from Theorem (2e) that for all elements x, y in an (b) B is atomic iff for all non-zero elements x in B there is an atom
algebra B, (x A y) is a lower bound for {x, y}; and from Theorem (2f) it y EB such thaty ~x.
follows that (x v y) is an upper bound for {x, y}. In fact, (x A y) is the
largest of the lb's for {x, y} and (x v y) is the smallest of the ub's for {x, y }. Some algebras have no atoms at all and thus are clearly not atomic. Others
Formally, have atoms but still fail to be atomic since there are some elements which
dominate no atom. Power set algebras however are always atomic. For let
DEFINITION 14. For B an arbitrary boolean algebra and D any subset of S* be a power set algebra and let K be a non-zero element of S*. Then
B, K =/= f/J, since f/J is the zero element of S*, so K has at least one member, say k.
Since K is a subset of S then {k} is also a subset of S and thus an element
(a) an element x E B is a greatest lower bound (glb) for D iff (i) x of S *. And clearly {k} ~ K. Now we claim that {k} is an atom. Clearly it
is a lb for D and (ii) for all y E B, if Y is a lb for D in B then is not f/J, satisfying clause (i) in Definition (16a). Now suppose that Yin S * is
y<x; a subset of {k}. If Y is not empty then the only member of Y is k, otherwise
(b) an element x E B is a least upper bound (lub) for D iff (i) x is Y g; {k}. Thus if Y is not empty then Y = {k}, so either Yis f/J or Y= {k},
an ub for D and (ii) for all ub'sy for D, x <yo satisfying the second clause of Definition (I 6a). Thus the unit sets in a power
(c) if D has a glb it is denoted AD; if it has a lub it is denoted VD. set algebra are atoms, and for any non-empty element K of a power set
We often write Ad E Dd for AD and Vd E Dd for VD. algebra there is an atom {k} ~ K, so the power set algebra is atomic.
The illustration of atoms in power set algebras should help to clarify the
Note that if both x and z are glb's for D then necessarily x is z. For by clause intuition behind the notion of an atom. Basically an atom is a smallest non-
(i) in (a) above each of x and z is a lb for D, so by clause (ii) x < z and z <x, zero element of an algebra. Nothing in a boolean algebra is strictly smaller
thus by antisymmetry (Theorem 2c), x = z. Similarly if x and z are both than an atom except the zero element. So, loosely, an atom is a non-trivial
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 57 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 59

element of an algebra with no proper parts which are non-trivial. We note the Now let us consider the atoms of F2/X' For f E F2/X to be an atom it
following useful theorems regarding atoms in an algebra: must be different from the zero function and whenever g ~ f then either g
is the zero function or g is f. We claim that for each x E X, the functions fx
THEOREM 4_ Let B an arbitrary algebra and b an atom in B. Then, defined below are atoms of F2/X.

(a) For all x EB, either (b /\ x) = 0 or (b /\ x) = b. DEFINITION 17. For ally EX, fx(y) = 12 if Y =x and fx (y) = O2 ify:fx.
(b) For all x E B, either b ~ x or b ~ x' but not both.
(c) For all c EB, if c is an atom of Band c f b then (b /\ c) = O. Clearly fx is not the zero function since it maps x onto 12 and the zero
function maps all elements of X onto O2 • Now suppose that g ~fx' so for all
As the concept of an atom will play some role in the sequel, it might be y EX, g(y) ~fx(Y). For any y different from x, g(y) =fx (y) =O2 • (Other-
useful here to illustrate an atomic algebra whose elements are not sets and wise g(y) = 12 and so g 'ff, contrary to the assumption). So g and f have
thus whose atoms are not unit sets. identical values at all y :f x. Now consider their values at x. If g(x) =0 then g
is the zero function in F2/X. If g(x) :f 0 then g(x) = 1 = fx (x), so g and fx
THEOREM 5. Let X be a non-empty set and let F2jX be the set of all func- have the same values at all arguments, so g = fx. Thus fx is an atom.
tions with domain X and range included in 2 (= {O, I}). Then (F2/X, 0,1, /\, We can now show that F2/X is atomic. Let f be any nonzero element of
V, ') is an atomic boolean algebra, where the zero element is that function in F2/X. Since f is nonzero, there must be at least one element x of X such that
F2jX which maps each x E X onto the zero element of 2; the unit element f(x) = 1. We now claim that the atomfx is contained inf. For, ify :j:.x,fx(Y)
is that function mapping each x E X onto the unit element in 2; and the = 0 ~ f(y) (by part (a) of Theorem 2); and fx (x) = 1 ~f(x), since f(x) = 1
meet, join, and complement operations are defined as follows: for all func- (by part (b) of Theorem 2). Thus, Ix (y) ~ feY) for every element y of X,
tions!. gEF2/X, and all x EX, whence fx ~f. This shows that F2/X is atomic.
We might point out that the algebra F2/X is also complete, and that in
(a) (f /\ g) (x) =(f(x) /\2 g(x) and fact F2/X is isomorphic to the power set algebra X*.
(b) (fv g)(x) =[(x) V2 g(x) and
(c) (f')(X) = (f(X))' 2 .
Defining TN Without a Universe
First let's understand the definition. The zero element in F2/X, which we We have seen above that all power set algebras are both complete and atomic;
might have denoted OF2jX were it not so cumbersome, is clearly a function and in EFOL we took TN to be a power set algebra, U*, and thus to be a
from X into 2. It maps each x E X onto the zero element of 2 (namely 0). complete and atomic algebra. Note now the following standard result:
Omitting subscripts, as we have, we may write O(x) = 0, which looks con-
fusing, since the '0' on the left of the equation refers to a function from X THEOREM 6. A boolean alegbra B is complete and atomic iff B is isomorphic
into 2, and the '0' on the right refers to an element of 2. We prefer to clear to a power set algebra.
up this confusion verbally, as we have just done, rather than use the less
confusing but more awkward notation OF2/X (x) = O2 • Similarly the unit For the import of this theorem to be clear let us consider first exactly what is
element of F2jX as defined is clearly a function from X into 2. So the unit meant by an isomorphism between two algebras. Intuitively an isomorphism
and zero elements of the algebra are elements of the domain of the algebra is a way of saying that the two algebras have exactly the same structure.
as required. To give an example, suppose we define an algebra TF whose domain has two
Now consider the meet, join, and complement operations on F2/X. To elements, the letter t and the letter f, where 't' is the unit element and '/'
define a function from X into 2 we must state the value of that function at the zero. Intuitively TF has the same structure as the algebra 2 we have taken
each x in the domain X of the function. If [ and g are elements of F2/X, as the type for formulas. It would be completely pointless for example to
58 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 60 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

namely functions from X -+ 2, we define (f 1\ g) to be that function in F2/X argue that TF is in any way better or worse than 2 as a type of Po. The reason
whose value at any x E X is [(x) 1\2 g(x). Thus (f 1\ g) maps x onto the ele- is that the only properties of Tpo used in the logic are its boolean ones. For
ment of2 obtained by forming [(x), an element of2, andg(x), an element of example we make use of statements such as "the meet of the zero element
2, and then taking the meet of these two elements in the algebra 2. Similarly of Tpo with the unit is the zero element". But all such statements hold in 2
([ V g) maps each x onto the element of 2 obtained by taking the join in 2 iff they hold in TF. Hence the two algebras are equally good candidates
of [(x) with g(x). And fmally f' is that function from X into 2 whose value for being the type for Po. The only differences between them concern the
at any x is the element of 2 formed by looking first at [(x), an element of identity of the objects in their domains, i.e. what it is that makes the letter
2, and then taking the complement in 2 of that element. t different from the number one. And these differences are irrelevant in
'Thus the meet and join operations as defined on F2/X are binary functions determining which arguments are represented as valid in L.
mapping pairs of functions in F2/X onto a third function in F2/X. And I as It is perhaps even more obvious that the identity of the elements in U (and
defined is a unary function fromF2/X into F2/X. thus U*) is irrelevant to the logic, since U is just any non-empty set. All
Now let us sketch a proof that the algebra defined in Theorem 5 satisfies that is relevant for characterizing the valid arguments in L concerning U* is
the axioms of boolean algebra. Note first that the zero and unit elements its structure as a power set. E.g. it is relevant that it has a minimal (zero)
are distinct. To show that two functions are distinct it is sufficient to show and maximal (unit) element, that it has atoms, etc. But the actual identity
that they have different values at at least one argument. Since X is taken to of the elements of U* is irrelevant. Thus we may take as a type for N any
be non-empty let x be an element of X. Then O(x) = O2 and 1(x) = 12 , Thus object which has the boolean structure of a power set algebra. And the
the zero and unit functions have different values at x, since the zero and unit theorem above states that the complete and atomic algebras are exactly the
elements of 2 are distinct. Let us illustrate the proof that the other axioms class of algebras having the structure of power set algebras. We conclude that
hold with the example of the first distributive law. For f, g, h arbitrary the complete and atomic algebras are exactly the class of objects which may
elements of F2/X we must show that ([ 1\ (g v h)) is the same function as be appropriately taken as the type for N.
«(f II g) V (f v h)), that is we must show that they have the same value at Note that this class properly includes the power set algebras. For example,
every argument. Let x be arbitrary in X. Then, it includes the algebra F2/X, which is not a power set algebra: its elements
are functions, not subsets of one set. However, F 2/ X is isomorphic to a power
([ 1\ (g v h)) (x) =[(x) 1\ (g v h) (x) Def of 1\ in F2/X
set algebra (X*); that is, the algebraic structure of F 2 / X is identical to the
=[(x) 1\ (g(x) v hex)) Def of v in F2/X algebraic structure of some power set algebra.
=([(x) 1\ g(x)) V (f(x) 1\ hex)) Distrlbutivity in 2 Let us sketch out the proof of Theorem 6. We begin with a formal defini-
= (f 1\ g) (x) V (f 1\ h) (x) Def of 1\ in F2/X tion of the notion isomorphism.
= «(f 1\ g) V (f 1\ h))(x) Def of v in F2/X
Thus [1\ (g v h) and ([ 1\ g) V (f 1\ h) take the same value at an arbitrary DEFINITION 18. For Band D domains of arbitrary boolean algebras,
argument and hence are equal. (a) i is an isomorphism from B onto D iff i is a one-to-one function
The other axioms are proven similarly. Thus F2/X as defined is a boolean from B onto D such that for all x, y E B,
algebra. (1) i(xlly)=i(x)Ai(y) [ipreservesmeets]
Consider now the boolean:';; relation on F2/X. By defmition we have that (2) i(xvy)=i(x)vi(y) [i preserves joins]
[:';;g iff (f 1\ g) = [, all!, g in F2/X. And note,
(3) i(x') = (i(x))' [i preserves complements]
([ 1\ g) =[ iff for all x EX, (f 1\ g) (x) = [(x) Identity for functions (b) B is isomorphic to D iff there exists an isomorphism from B
iff for all x E X,f(x) 1\ g(x) =[(x), Def 1\ in F2/X ontoD.
iff for all x EX,f(x) :';;g(x) Def:';; in 2
Note that in (1 )-(3) above meets, joins, and complements on the left side
Thus [:';; g in F2/X iff for all x EX,f(x) :';;g(x) in 2. of the equations refer to these operations in B since x and yare elements of
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 61 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 63

B. On the right they refer to the corresponding operations in D, since i(x) DEFINITION 20. Relative to an ontology (P, 2) we define the types for
and i(y) are elements of D. Note further what it means to say, as we have Po, N, N, and Nprop as follows:
in (1 )-(3), that i preserves the boolean operations. It says that whenever an
element z of B is related in some boolean way to others, say z =(x v (y 1\ w» (a) Tpo =df 2.
then i(z) is related in exactly the same way to i(x), i(y), and i(w). Thus no (b) TN =df P.
element z in B has any boolean property not possessed by i(z) in D. So in ( c) TN =df P*, regarded as a power set boolean algebra.
terms of the boolean structure we cannot distinguish between Band D. The (d) TN prop =df Ip, the set of individuals onP.
following theorems regarding isomorphisms then are unsurprising:

Discussion
THEOREM 7. Let i be an isomorphism from B onto D. Then,
In presenting our conception of an ontology and the types as defined in
(a) i(OB) =On and i(IB) =In· Definition 20, we have relied on the reader's awareness of the advantages
(b) x ~B y iff i(x) ~ iCy). of EFOL as a system of semantic representation for natural language and
(c) x is an atom of B iff i(x) is an atom of D. presented our system as one which preserves EFOL's nice properties but
(d) i preserves unbounded meets and joins, i.e. For K <:;;; B, i(l\.K) = which is ontologically less objectionable and linguistically more in accordance
I\. {i(k): k E K} and i(VK) = V {i(k): k EK} where these equa- with the Principle of Compositionality. But that mode of presentation suffers
tions are interpreted to mean that if the meet (join) on the left from at least one serious shortcoming: it fails to reflect the novelty and
exists, (i.e. if K has a glb (lub) in B), then the meet (join) on the naturalness of the basic ontology. More specifically it does not provide any
right exists and the equation holds. direct motivation for the ontology or the types in terms of representing
(e) the function i-I from D into B defined by i-I (d) = b iffi(b) = d valid arguments of English, and it fails to suggest that such an ontology
is an isomorphism from D onto B. Thus B is isomorphic to D iff would be naturally arrived at by direct reasoning concerning the pretheoretical
D is isomorphic to B, and we write B ~ D. judgments of semantic relatedness of English expressions.
Consequently we would like to ask the reader, now equipped with the
Let us now indicate the essential steps in the proof of Theorem 6. Going first necessary boolean apparatus, to reread Definitions 19 and 20 as though
from right to left, let B be isomorphic to a power set algebra S *. By (e) above they were presented on page 1 of the Semantics for L section of this paper.
let [be an isomorphism from S* onto B. Then {[(x): x an atom of S*} is A great many questions should arise concerning the naturalness and intuitive

,I
the set of atoms of B by ( c) above. Now, if x is a nonzero element of B, then
(x) is a nonzero element of S*, and so contains an atom, say {s}. But
then [( {s}) is an atom of B (by Theorem 7c); call it b. Moreover, by (7b),
support for our ontology and types. Just what are the properties we take
as primitive? Why should they form a boolean algebra much less a complete
and atomic one? Are proper noun denotations really 'cognitively more com-
b ~ x. Thus, every nonzero element of B contains an atom, and so B is atomic. plex' than common noun denotations as our types suggest? What specifically
To show B complete, let [be an isomorphism from B onto S* and let K any are the atoms of TN? Can they be naturally expressed in English or are they
subset of B. Then {f(k): k E K} is a subset of S* and has a glb, say z. [-I (z) just as mysterious as the elements of U were in EFOL? Below we answer
is the glb for K in B. these and some related questions.
Going from left to right, the case of greater interest for us, let B be a com- (i) Ontologically speaking just what are these properties which we take
plete and atomic algebra. We must show B to be isomorphic to a power set as primitive? To be sure we cannot require of a primitive concept in a system
algebra. that it be definable, otherwise it wouldn't be a primitive. But isn't it reason-
Let AB denote the set of atoms of B. Since B is atomic and IB is not the able to have some intuitive idea what properties are in the same sense in
zero element there is at least one atom in B, so AB = ~. Thus (AB)* is the which, when we give a semantics for the language of arithmetic, we have
domain of a power set algebra. We show that B is isomorphic to (AB )*. some idea what numbers are, or what points are in the language of Euclidean
62 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 64 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Define a function f from B into (AB)* as follows: For all x EB,f(x) =df geometry, or what sets are in the language of set theory? The basic query
{b E AB: b < x}. Clearly f is a function from B into (AB)*, and it is stan- here seems to us a natural one, at least it is a query which has occurred to
dard to show that f is one-to-one, onto, and that it preserves meets, joins, us more than once. Any sort of thorough answer to the query of course
and complements. would carry us much farther into epistemology and philosophy of science
Thus a complete and atomic algebra can always be thought of as the and mathematics than we need to go in order to provide a semantics for a
power set of its atoms (though the atoms of course need not be sets, as was fragment of English.
illustrated for the algebra F2/X given earlier). So here we shall just present several answers to this query which contrast,
In view of Theorem 6 then we may take TN to be simply an arbitrary we think favorably, our ontology with that of standard FOL which takes
complete and atomic algebra. It mayor may not be a power set algebra but a universe of discourse U as primitive rather than P.
it is isomorphic to a power set algebra and thus possesses exactly the boolean First let us countenance the following 'snap' reaction to the contrasting
structure of such algebras. Note that we have defined the type for N solely ontologies: "The standard ontology (U primitive) is natural, since elements
in terms of its boolean properties; thus we no longer need an antecedently of U may be common concrete objects of everyday experience, like John,
existing set U in order to define TN. Moreover defming individuals in terms Mary, etc. These are obviously fundamental elements in our cognition,
of the boolean structure of TN is now quite easy. relevant to our survival, etc., so it is natural that more complex, abstract
things like properties should be understood in terms of them - say they
should be sets of them anyway."
Defining Proper Noun Denotations Without U
Part of this reaction is at best a quibble of our choice of the word property.
In EFOL recall the individual generated by x E U was {K ~ U: x E K}. We might have named TN anything we liked. We call its elements properties
Noting the triviality that x E K iff {x} ~ K we may equivalently define since they will be denotations of common nouns like man, woman, etc. and
Ix to be {K ~ U: {x} ~ K}. Note that {x} is an element of U* (= TN on traditional usage in philosophy and rhetoric sanctions that man determines
this view). In fact it is an atom. And the subset relation is just the boolean a property, the property of being a man. Of course other categories, such as
< relation for power set algebras. So taking TN as an arbitrary complete and the category of verb phrases, also determine properties in this sense; and to
atomic algebra we may give an equivalent (non-temporary) definition of anticipate our development we might point out that in L, TN will turn out
individual as follows: to be isomorphic to the type for P l , as well as to the type for 'absolute'
adjectives, such as male, female, etc. which also traditionally determine
DEFINITION 10. For B any boolean algebra and b any atom of B, Ib, or the properties.
individual generated by b, =df {p E B: b < p}. We denote by IB the set But it is decidedly not the case that elements of TN in our system have
{Ib: b an atom of B} and refer to its elements as individuals. to be abstract objects. They can be any sort of objects we like. All that is
relevant about them is that they are a boolean set, that is a set with a specific
We may then define the type for proper nouns as h N , the set of individuals sort of boolean structure. The identity of the elements of TN is irrelevant
on TN. Thus we have defined individuals solely in terms of the boolean to the use we make of TN in the logic. Consider for example an algebra whose
structure of TN, the properties, eliminating all reference to U. These results two elements are Ronald Reagan and Francois Mitterand, taking Reagan
are formally summarized below. as the zero element and Mitterand as the unit. The values of the boolean
operations are uniquely determined on the zero and unit; the resulting
algebra is of course complete because it is finite, and it is atomic, Mitterand
The Ontology and Some Basic Types for L: Summary
being the only atom. (The algebra is of course isomorphic to 2.) So this
DEFINITION 19. An ontology, or set of semantic primitives, for L is a pair algebra is a possible choice of TN, and its elements are clearly concrete
<P, 2) where P is an arbitrary complete and atomic boolean algebra called the objects of everyday experience. One might of course think it strange usage
(extensional) properties, and 2 is the boolean algebra 2, called truth values. to call Reagan a property, in particular the zero property, of an algebra.
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 65 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 67

But in fact all that is strange is that we overtly identified the zero element denoting phrases are formed from property denoting phrases, e.g. this man
of the algebra with something characterized by properties irrelevant to from man, etc., whereas the converse process is only sporadic (cf. gerry-
the algebra, e.g. being the President of the United States, being a former mander). This fact is curious on a view in which properties are thought of
movie actor, etc. To see that this is what is peculiar about the usage, consider as defined in terms of individuals but is reasonable on the converse view, the
a comparable example from the language of arithmetic. Let us take as a one suggested by our ontology.
model of arithmetic the standard set theoretical one in which the set of These considerations are of course speculative, but recognizing them as
'numbers' (the universe of discourse) is the set whose members are ~, {~}, such, let us pursue a further speculation along these lines before returning
{fl>, {~}}, etc., and the numeral zero in the language of arithmetic is inter- to the hard core reality of boolean algebra. Namely, consider the following
preted as 0. One mayor may not find this peculiar depending on mathe- global scenario for the development of cognitive capacities in the child.
matical habit. But consider a different but equally good model of arithmetic Initially his visual perception of the world is unorganized - he falls, bumps
whose elements are the following sequences of letters: r, rm, rmm, etc. into things, etc. He must learn to assess heights, depths, and distances. Little
In this model zero names the letter r. It is peculiar to say that zero is the by little he learns to partition his visual field into increasingly refined classes
18th letter of the English alphabet because we seem to be attributing to - objects which move are distinguished from objects which don't, ones
zero properties which are not arithmetical ones. The only arithmetically which make noises from ones which don't, later ones which bite from ones
relevant property of zero in arithmetic is that it is the least element of the which don't, ones which are edible from ones which aren't, etc. It is only
ordering of the universe of discourse. What those elements are is irrelevant. at a stage later than this that the child learns to discriminate one particular
Any set which possesses the right kind of ordering (i.e. linear ordering, object to the exclusion of the others in the class to which that object belongs.
non-dense, least but no greatest element, etc.) can be the basis of a model Such discrimination is, relatively speaking, not of primary relevance. We do
of arithmetic. It is pointless to attempt to distinguish among them for the of course have some need to discriminate among the individual humans who
same reasons that it is pointless to distinguish between TF and 2 as models affect our lives early, and we do assign them proper names. But few of us
of sentence denotations in logic. find it useful to discriminate among our pet goldfish and probably none of
So far then two conclusions: one, elements of TN are not necessarily us has any serious sense of the identity of the potato we had for dinner
more or less abstract than elements of U. Two, we have no business being tonight as opposed to the one we saved for tomorrow.
concerned at all with the identity of elements in a mathematical structure. We recognize of course that our child development scenario is speculative
The only properties of relevance are those determined by the structure and superificial, but it does have some plausability. It reasonably suggests
defined on the set. that it is of primary survival value to discern properties of objects rather
But what about the brute force claim that individuals are somehow cogni- than their absolute identity. The man in a tree who perceives a tiger kill an
tively more basic than properties, so the latter should be defined in terms of antelope is more likely to survive if he learns from the experience that tigers
the former, as in FOL but not in L? Let use note first the following mildly kill things rather than if he merely learns that that tiger killed something.
interesting result: In FOL TN (= TP 1 ) is defined to be the power set of U, It would seem then that the burden of proof in the matter lies with those
which is itself the denotations for proper nouns and thus constitutes the set who want to claim that individuals are somehow cognitively primary.
of individuals in FOL. In L of course individuals are defined in terms of Let us turn now to the matter of justifying the boolean nature of TN
properties, just the opposite from the direction of definition in FOL, but (= P) and of defining individuals in terms of the boolean properties of P as
it is still the case that TN is indistinguishable from the power set of the we have done.
individuals in L. Thus, (ii) Why should TN be a boolean algebra? We will show here that the
boolean nature of TN and the concomitant definition of TN prop follow
THEOREM 8. P (= TN) is isomorphic to (/p)*, the power set of the individ- naturally and directly from pretheoretical consideration of the valid argu-
uals on P. The function sending each pEP to the set of individuals it is a ments of English.
member of is an isomorphism. The ultimate basis for our reasoning here is that we intend TN to provide
66 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 68 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Now, what can we make of the claim that individuals are somehow cogni- denotations for English common noun phrases. These will include not only
tively more basic than properties? What evidence could be brought to bear? elements such as man, student, woman, etc. but ultimately more complex
One can imagine psycholinguistic tests that could be brought to bear, but N's such as: non-student, tall man, tallest student in the class, tall and hand-
we know of no solid results in this area. One suggestive piece of evidence some student, smart but not very hard-working student, woman who John
would be if the records of child language acquisition clearly showed that knows, student taller than every teacher, student who is taller than some
children learned many proper names first and only later learned common teacher, woman who John knows best, first man who landed on the moon,
nouns and verb phrases. Assuming they use the name meaningfully this would man who was the first President of the U.S., and even individual who is Bill.
suggest that they have understood proper noun denotations before common Thus we shall argue that to represent correctly the valid arguments into which
noun ones, suggesting that in fact they do form their concepts of common such expressions enter they must take their denotations in a boolean set.
noun denotations in terms of proper noun denotations. But the little evidence We shall refer to their denotations non-commit tally as properties, and justify
we have seen (see Bloom, 1973) while incomplete, strongly suggests the then that such properties should be elements of a complete atomic boolean
contrary. Early utterances include many property denoting expressions such algebra.
as cookie, baby, chair, etc. and few if any expressions which are unequivocally We shall furthermore accept the reasons given earlier for taking proper
individual denoting. The best candidate here is Mommy but even in the earliest noun denotations as sets of properties (principally to allow that John and
stages of Bloom's corpora Mommy is used to refer to individuals other than every man take their denotations in the same type). We shall refer non-
the child's mother. Moreover the early utterances include frequent uses of committally to proper noun denotations as individuals. Obviously we do
'determiners' such as no and more whose use clearly presupposes the ability not assume for this discussion Definition 10 given earlier; indeed it is the
to recognize an object as a member of a class. reasonableness of such a definition we are trying to justify on pretheoretical
There is moreover somewhat better documented, though still circumstan- grounds.
tial, evidence of a purely linguistic sort supporting the primacy of property Taking individuals as sets of properties does of course provide a natural
denoting phrases over individual denoting ones. Namely, in very many lan- way to represent the idea that individuals 'have' or fail to have certain prop-
guages (Hebrew, Malagasy, commonly in American Indian languages, Bantu, erties according as these sets contain or fail to contain these properties as
etc.) the expressions which function as proper nouns are syntactically and members. All languages have basic ways of saying that an individual has or
morphologically derived from property denoting expressions. For example, does not have a certain property. For example to state in English that the
Lakhota names familiar from American history are Sinte Gleska ('Spotted individual John has the vegetarian property we say simply John is a vegetarian_
Tail'), Mahpiya Luta ('Red Cloud'), and Tatanka Iyotaka ('Sitting Bull'). Thus we want such a sentence to come out true in some state of affairs just
Similarly consider Hebrew names Aryeh 'lion', Dov 'bear', Zvi 'male deer', in case in that state of affairs the vegetarian-property is an element of the
etc. In Malagasy proper names are productively formed with a proper name John-individual.
particle and verb phrases, adjective phrases, and common nouns, translating The example also illustrates that properties determine PI denotations.
literally into English as e.g. 'Mr. born on a lucky day', 'Mr. noble and yellow', That is, given the interpretation of vegetarian the interpretation of the PI
etc., e.g. Ramanandraibe = Ra + manana + rai + be = 'Mr.' + has + father + big, be a vegetarian (we ignore verb agreement as always) is obviously determined
'Mr. has many children', etc. In fact historically many proper names in as the PI denotation which holds of an individual just in case that individual
English are derived from common nouns: Smith, Butcher, Carpenter, etc. has the vegetarian property. Moreover if vegetarian and Republican are inter-
Last names, being the most recently innovated, are the most transparent in preted as different properties in some state of affairs then be a vegetarian and
this regard of course, but dictionaries also give etymologies for first names. be a Republican must be interpreted as different PI'S in that state of affairs;
E.g. the first author is happy to report that Edward comes from Anglo conversely, if be a vegetarian and be a Republican are interpreted as different
Saxon ead 'riches' + weard 'guardian, protector'. Similarly Leonard < OHG elements of Tp I then vegetarian and Republican must be interpreted differ-
Lewenhart = lewe 'lion' + hart 'strong' = 'strong as a lion'. ently. Somewhat more generally if e is a (first order, extensional) PI then the
It seems extremely general moreover across languages that individual property which e predicates of individuals is expressed by an N of the form
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 69 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 71

individual who e 's, e.g. is singing' holds of John iff the property expressed example that (14a) will be logically equivalent to (14b) since the property
by individual who is singing is a member of John. Note that vegetarian and determined by the Pi in (14a) will be pM(qJr) and that of (14b) will be
individual who is a vegetarian are logical synonyms. (pMq)J(pMr), and distributivity guarantees that these are the same elements
Since properties can be thus viewed either as the interpretations of N's or of TN.
as objects determined by the interpretations of PI'S, we shall feel free, in our
discussion of the nature of properties, to make use of both N's and P l 's in (14) a. John is a vegetarian and either a Republican or a Democrat.
giving illustrations of pretheoretical judgments which must be represented b. John is either a vegetarian and a Republican or a vegetarian and
by any logically adequate semantic system. a Democrat.
To show that TN should possess a boolean structure let us begin by We leave it to the reader to construct an example showing that the second
considering what property John should have in order for (8) to be true: distributivity law should be satisfied by M and J (Le. pJ(qMr) = (pJq)M(pJr).
(8) John is both a vegetarian and a Republican. Another property that M and J share with boolean meets and joins re-
spectively is idempotency. That is, in any boolean algebra, (x 1\ x) = x and
If be a vegetarian determines a property, say p, and be a Republican a prop- (x V x) = x. Similarly in TN we have that pMp = P and pJp = p, trivially, since
erty q, then clearly the property determined by the P l of (8) is dependent e.g. pMp is the property an individual has just in case he has both p and p,
upon, that is, is some function of, p and q. Let us call that function M and that is, just in case he has p. Analogously for J.
denote the property determined by the P l of (8) by pMq. Then qMp will Consider now the property John must have for (15) to be true:
be the property determined by the P l of (9) below:
(15) John is not a vegetarian.
(9) John is both a Republican and a vegetarian.
Clearly which property this is depends on which property the vegetarian
Clearly we are motivated to take M as a commutative function guaranteeing property is. Let us denote it then Np, where vegetarian denotes p.
that pMq and qMp are the same element of TN, for if we do then (8) will To see how p and Np are related note first that we want (16a) to be
be true just in case (9) is, which is correct. logically true and (16b) to be logically false.
Notice now that p, q and pMq may all be different properties. But these
properties cannot be randomly distributed among the individuals (the proper (16) a. Either John is a vegetarian or John is not a vegetarian.
noun denotations). Specifically, since we are going to define individuals as b. John is a vegetarian and John is not a vegetarian.
sets of properties, we must guarantee that whenever an individual has both
of p and q then it also has pMq and conversely. The direct motivation for this These judgments tell us first that, since vegetarian is an arbitrarily selected
constraint on individuals is that (10) is logically equivalent to (9), that is, element of TN, we want p to be different from Np, for any property p. For
(10) entails (9) and conversely. suppose that p and Np were the same property, say q. Then either the John
individual has q or he doesn't. If he does, then (16b) is true, contradicting
(10) John is a vegetarian and John is a Republican our pretheoretical judgement that (16b) must be false. And if John doesn't
have q, then (16a) must be false, contradicting our intuition that it is true.
Thus we shall require that any I <;;:; TN which is a proper noun denotation
We conclude then that p t Np, for allp. This guarantees, note, that TN must
satisfy the following condition:
have at least two elements; for given that it is not empty (we want elements
(11) For I ~ TN, if IE TN prop then for all p, q E TN, of N to have denotations after all) we have that for each element p of TN
pEl and q E I iff (PMq) E I. there is a distinct elementNp in TN.
Further, for each p E TN, the distribution of p and Np in individuals
This says in effect that pMq is the property an individual has iff he has (or is not random. Thus we judge (I7a) to be logically equivalent to (17b);
is) both p and q. and Similarly for (18a) and (18b).
70 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 72 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Note that there is further motivation for wanting to define the function (17) a. John is not a vegetarian.
M on TN. Consider for example complex Ns of the form tall student. Since b. It is not the case that John is a vegetarian.
tall student denotes a property, as does student, it is reasonable to interpret (18) a. John is a vegetarian.
adjectives like tall as functions from properties into properties. Letting f be b. It is not the case that John is not a vegetarian.
the tall-function, then, and letting s be the property which interprets student,
[(s) will be the property which interprets tall student. Similarly let g be the These judgements will be guaranteed if we constrain the sets of properties
function which interprets the adjective handsome, so handsome student is which can interpret proper nouns to meet the condition given below:
interpreted by g(s). Now what property should interpret tall and handsome
(19) If I ~ TN is an individual then for allp E TN,
student? Obviously enough an individual has that property iff he has both
p E !iff Np tf. I.
the tall student and the handsome student property. That is, [tall and hand-
some] student is interpreted by f(s)Mg(s). Thus we are motivated to define Thus Np is the property an individual has iff he does not have p. Note that
M on TN in order to provide denotations for N's expressed by combining the condition pEl iff Np tf. I is logically equivalent to either pEl or Np EI
simple N's with conjunctions of adjectives. but not both. This latter rendition makes it immediate that (16a) is logically
Next, in analogy to the above discussion, consider the property John true and (16b) logically false.
must have in order for (12) to be true. Additional motivation for defining the N function on the type for com-
mon nouns comes directly from the common noun modifier non-. Inter-
(12) John is either a vegetarian or a Republican.
preting non- as the function N we have for example that non-student is
This too is a property which depends on both p and q (the vegetarian and interpreted by N(s) when student is interpreted by s. Thus by (19) an in-
Republican properties respectively), but of course the dependency is not dividual will have the student property iff he does not have the non-student
in general the same as in (9). So we want another binary function, call it property. This correctly guarantees for example that John is a non-student
J, to be defined on TN. Since (12) is logically equivalent to John is either entails it is not the case that John is a student.
a Republican or a vegetarian we are motivated to require that J also be Un surprisingly the function N we have described will turn out to satisfy
commutative, Le. that pJq = qJp, all elements p, q of TN. And since p, q, and the boolean axioms for complements. To see this consider what property
pJq may all be different properties, we shall impose the constraint below on John must have for (20) to be true.
what subsets of TN may count as proper noun denotations:
(20) John is either a vegetarian or not a vegetarian.
(13) If J ~ TN is an element of TNprop
then (pJq) E I iff either pEl or q E I. Intuitively the property must be one which all individuals have, since no
matter what individual we think of John as denoting (20) is true, in fact
Thus pJq is the property an individual has iff he has at least one of the two logically true as it is judged to entail and be entailed by (16a) above. Let
properties p and q. As in the case for M, we are additionally motivated to us then denote the property which all individuals have by 1TN' or simply
define J on TN to provide denotations for N's formed with disjunctions of 1 where clear from context. Arguably it is the denotation of the common
adjectives. Thus correct entailments are predicted if we take tall or handsome noun individual (or entity, or existent).
student to denote f(s)Jg(s) under the interpretation conventions given a Note however that we are already committed to representing the denota-
moment ago for tall and handsome. tion of the PI in (20) by pJ(Np). Thus, we want pJ(Np) = 1 to hold; moreover
M and J are beginning to smell suspiciously like boolean meet and join this holds no matter what property p is chosen. E.g. be either a Republican
functions; at least they are both binary functions and both commutative. or not a RepUblican also holds of every individual. Thus pJ(Np) = 1 holds
Further it is easy to see that each should distribute with respect to the other. of all elements p in TN. But this is just one of the complement laws which
Specifically if we require of TN that M and J distribute then we predict for are required to be satisfied in any boolean algebra.
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 73 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 75

Analogously let us define 0TN to be the property an individual John has property. And suppose that John has z. Thus for every woman W, John is
just in case (21) is true: a man taller than W. Clearly then we can infer that John has the property
expressed by man taller than every woman, namely p; thus an arbitrary lower
(21) John is both a vegetarian and not a vegetarian. bound z for K is contained in P, which is just to say that p is the glb for K.
Now, K can be arbitrarily large, depending on how many individuals with
Clearly this property is one that no individual has, since (21) is judged logically the woman property there are. We thus want P to provide glb's for arbitrary
equivalent to (l6b) and thus logically false. So we have that pM(Np), our sets of properties in order to guarantee the existence of interpretations for
denotation for the PI in (21), must be 0; and since the choice of p was property denoting phrases such as man taller than every woman.
arbitrary, we have that pM(Np) = 0, all p E TN satisfying the other axiom Correspondingly we must impose a somewhat stronger 'meets condition'
of complements. on individuals than (11). That is, suppose that for every woman W, John
Note further that N(I) = 0, since if 1 is in all individuals then N(1) is in
has the property of being a man taller than W. Then he must also have the
none by (19), and thus N(1) is the property John has if (21) is true, that is,
property expressed by man taller than every woman. But the finite meets
it is 0. And since for all p E TN, P ! Np, we have that 1 :f N(I) =0, so the condition which (11) imposes on individuals is not strong enough to guarantee
axiom requiring that the unit and zero elements be distinct is satisfied. this. That is, there exist subsets I of certain algebras which satisfy the condi-
For the remaining two axioms, pM(l) = p and pJ(O) = p it is sufficient tion that {p, q} ~ I iff p II q E I but which do not satisfy the condition that
to note for example that (22a) is logically equivalent to (22b): K ~ I iff AK E I, for K an arbitrary subset K of the algebra. Formally, then,
(22) a. John is a Republican. we shall require:
b. John is a Republican and either a vegetarian or not a vegetarian. (24) The Meets Condition
If I ~ TN is a proper noun denotation then for each K ~ TN,
The property expressed by the PI in (22b) is just pM(l), so if pM(l) is
K ~Iiff AK EI.
p the logical equivalence of (22a) and (22b) is correctly predicted. Inter-
changing and and or in (22b) yields of PI which determines the property We leave it to the reader to construct the analogous argument that every
pJCO); the equivalence of C22b), as modified, and C22a) shows that pJCO) = p, subset of TN should have a lub. Specifically we want the property which
thus satisfying the final axiom. interprets man taller than some woman to be the lub for the set K given
Thus we have shown that direct consideration of valid arguments from above. And similarly we must constrain individuals to meet the stronger
English supports the correctness of taking TN as a boolean algebra and of joins condition:
taking individuals to be subsets of TN satisfying conditions (11), (13), and (25) The Joins Condition
(19). As the functions M, J and N were shown to satisfy the boolean axioms
If I ~ TN is a proper noun denotation then for all K ~ TN,
we shall henceforth refer to them by the ordinary boolean names, fI, v, and I
K nIf r/J iffVKEI.
respectively.
We have then justified that TN should be a complete algebra and that
elements of TN rop should be subsets of TN satisfying the Meets, Joins,
Why Should TN Be Complete and Atomic?
and ComplemenfConditions, the latter restated formally below:
We have yet to justify that we want TN to be a complete and atomic algebra.
(26) The Complements Condition
To see this, let us consider the ~ relation we have defined on TN.
If I ~ TN is a proper noun denotation then for all p E TN,
By definition, for all elements p, q in TN' P ~ q iff (p 1\ q) =p. But just P EIiffp' '1-1.
what does it mean to say (p 1\ q) = p? Given (11), (13), and (19), which
constrain the sets of properties which can constitute individuals, we can show These three conditions turn out, perhaps surprisingly, to fully characterize
that one consequence of (p 1\ q) = P is that the set of individuals with p is a individuals as defined earlier. Recall that for each atom b in TN, we took
74 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 76 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

subset of the set of individuals with q. For, suppose that pEl. Then, since I b, or the individual generated by b, to be {p E TN: b .:;;; p}. Let us now
p = p 1\ q, we have that p v q E I, and so by (11), q EI. It will also turn out define individuals as follows:
that the converse of this is true as shown below in Theorem 11.
The relation ..;; will naturally be used in the semantics of extensional DEFINITION 21. For all I <: TN. I is an individual iff I satisfies the Meets,
adjectives. In particular, we want to draw the functionsfwhich can interpret Joins, and Complement Conditions.
APs like tall, female, etc. from those functions f from TN into TN which
meet the condition that for all p E TN, f(P) ..;; p. Thus the tall student The theorem below says that the two definitions are equivalent:
property f(s) will be ..;; to the student property s, guaranteeing that any
individual with the tall student property will have the student property, THEOREM 9. Assume that TN is a complete and atomic algebra. Then for
and hence guaranteeing that sentences like all tall students are students I <: TN, I satisfies the Meets, Joins, and Complements Conditions iff there
are logically true, which is correct. (Of course not all APs will be interpreted exists an atom b E TN such that! = lb.
by functions which meet this condition, e.g. alleged, fake, etc.; but many
natural classes of APs do meet this condition, in particular, all those which The significance of this theorem is that the notion of an individual is con-
can be treated extensionally. Note that alleged is not extensional in the sense ceptually independent of the notion of an atom. We have not yet for example
that if the same individuals are murderers as thieves, so thief and murderer justified that TN should even have any atoms, much less be atomic. Suppose
have the same extension, it does not follow that the alleged thieves and for example that we allowed TN to be an atomless algebra (there are many
the alleged murderers are the same individuals. Hence alleged cannot be such). Then Theorem 9 says that there would simply be no individuals on TN.
represented as a function from property extensions into property extensions.) Thus one (but not the only) motivation for wanting TN to have at least some
See Section B for further discussion. atoms is that we want to provide denotations for proper nouns, and if there
Now, why do we want TN to be a complete algebra? That is, why now are no atoms there will be no such denotations. Hence the notions of an
do we want any set of properties to have a glb? The general answer is that individual does not rely crucially on some 'mysterious' notion of an atom.
if we place this requirement on TN then we correctly characterize many valid (Moreover as we shall see below atoms are in any event not mysterious;
arguments. many ordinary common nouns are naturally intended to be interpreted by
Specifically let p be the property which interprets man taller than every atoms.) So let us sketch the crucial steps in the proof of Theorem 9.
woman, and for each individual W with the woman property, let Pw be Proof. Let I be a subset of TN satisfying Meets, Joins, and Complement.
the property man taller than W. We claim that p is the glb for {Pw: Wan Show there is an atom b E TN such that I =lb.
individual with the woman property}. Call this set K. That p is an lb for K is Since trivially I <: I, we have by Meets that 1\1 E I. We claim
seen by the fact that pretheoretically (23a) below entails (23b): (a) 1\ I is an atom and (b) 1= lb, where b is the atom 1\ I.
(23) a. John is a man taller than every woman and Mary is a woman. (a) 1\ I is an atom
b. John is taller than Mary.
We must show that 1\1 f 0 and that for all p E TN if P .:;;; 1\1 then either p = 0
If (23a) is true then p is a member of the John individual. Since p is an lb or p = 1\1.
for K then p";; PMary' the property of being a man taller than Mary. Hence Suppose that 1\ I = O. Then 0 E I and since 0 = 0 II 1 we have that 0 II 1 E I,
PMary is an element of the John individual since from what we said above, whence by the Meets Condition, I E I. But I = 0', so both 0 and 0' are in I,
p ..;; PMary guarantees that the set of individuals with p is a subset of those contradicting the Complements Condition. Hence 1\1 f O.
with PMary' Thus, by taking P to be a lower bound of K, the entailment in Suppose now that p .:;;; 1\1. Assume p f O. We must show that p = 1\1.
(23) is predicted. Trivially either pEl or p rf. I. Suppose first that pEl. Then 1\1";;; p since 1\1
Now, why should p be a glb of K? Suppose that z is an lb for K and thus is an lb for I. Thus since p .:;;; 1\1 by assumption and 1\1";;; p, we have by
every individual with z also has Pw, for each individual W with the woman antisymmetry of";;; that p =1\1.
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 77 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 79

Suppose alternatively that p ~ I. Then by the Complement Condition (27) Extensionality: for all properties p and q, p = q iff the set of indi-
pi E I, so 1\ I ..;;; pi since 1\ 1 is an lb for I. But p ..;;; 1\ 1, so by the transitivity viduals which contain p is the same as the set which contain q.
of ..;;;, p ..;;; p'. Thus (p 1\ pi) = p. But (p 1\ pi) = 0, whence p = 0, contradicting
the original assumption that p f o. Thus pEl, and by the above then p =1\ I. Our intent all along has been that L be an extensional logic in this sense,
Thus for all p E TN, if P ..;;; 1\1 then either p = 0 or p = 1\1, whence 1\1 is and we have informally used this assumption in reasoning about properties
an atom. above. For example, we argued above that if the vegetarian property was
not the zero property then it held of at least one individual. This assumes
(b) I=IM. of our course that if two properties are different then they hold of different
Let pEl. Then 1\1";;; p since 1\1 an lb for I. Thus p ElM, the set of q such individuals. Our assumption of extensionality here is one of simplification.
that 1\1";;; q. So I ~ 1M. Letp ElM. Then I\I";;;p. Suppose that p ~I. Then We first present a language L to represent properties of English in so far as
by the Complements Condition, pi E I, so 1\1 ..;;; p'. But from 1\1 ..;;; p and they can be represented in an extensional system and then, in Part II, we
1\1 ..;;; p' we conclude that 1\1";;; (p 1\ pi) = 0, so 1\1 = 0, contradicting that shall extend the semantics of L to include properly non-extensional con-
1\1 is an atom, sh()wn in (a) above. Hence pEl, so 1M ~ I. Combining (i) structions. For the nonce then we want L to be extensional, and it is perhaps
and (ii) we infer that I =1M. reasonable to prove that we have succeeded. The proof moreover is enlighten-
ing in a surprising way. It will show that the extensionality assumption is
This completes the first half of the theorem. The other direction, that each in a certain sense equivalent to the assumption of the atomicity of TN. And
Ib satisfies the Meets, Joins, and Complement Conditions, is unsurprising and this in turn suggests a novel approach to intensional logics, allowing these
given at the end of this section. to be constructed without the cumbersome apparatus of possible worlds.
Consider now the justification that TN should have atoms, and moreover To establish this let us first note the following standard result in boolean
be atomic (every non-zero element of TN should dominate an atom). We have algebra:
seen above that a proper noun denotation I possesses at least one atom,
namely 1\1. And it is easy to see that it cannot have more than one atom. THEOREM 10. Let B be a complete boolean algebra. Then B is atomic iff
For if say band d are distinct atoms in I then by Meets, (b 1\ d) E I. But for allp EB, p = VAp (where Ap =df {b EB: b is an atom and b ';;;p}).
(Theorem 4c) the meet of distinct atoms is 0 and by the argument in (a) Proof. Assume first that B is not atomic. We show that there exists apE B
above, 0 cannot be an element of any I. Thus, each individual contains which is not identical to the join of the atoms it dominates. Since B is not
exactly one atom. atomic there exists a p which is non-zero and which dominates no atoms.
From this it is easy to show that an atom is a property which is contained So Ap = f/J for that p, so VAp = 0, thus VAp t= p, which was taken as not 0.
in exactly one individual. For, let p be an atom, and suppose that p is con- Assume now that B is atomic and let p E B be arbitrary. We show that
tained in 11 and 12 • By Theorem 9,11 = Ib 1 and 12 = Ib 2 , where b 1 and b 2 p = VAp. Since p is an upper bound for Ap we have that VAp ';;;p, since VAp
are atoms. Since 11 contains the atoms p and b 1, we conclude that p = b 1, is the least upper bound for Ap. We must show then that p .;;; VAp, whence
by what we have just shown above. Similarly, since 12 contains the atoms by antisymrnetry, p = VAp.
p and b 2 , we have p = b 2 . But this means that b 1 = b 2 , whence 11 = 12 . Suppose p ~ VAp. Then (Theorem 2i) p !\ (VAp)' t= 0, and so since B is
Conversely, if p is a property which is contained in exactly one individual, atomic, there is an atom b';;; p A (VApY, whence b';;; p and b';;; (VAp)'. So
then we can show easily that p must be an atom, provided we assume that by a general law of boolean algebra VAp .;;; b' (i.e. in all algebras we have
TN is atomic. For, by Theorem 9 above, there is exactly one atom b such that x';;;y iff y' .;;; x'). But b is an atom';;; p, so b EAp, thus b ';;;VAp which is
b ..;;; p. Now, p must actually be equal to b. For, if b ..;;; p but p f b, then an upper bound for Ap. Thus by transitivity of';;;' b .;;; b', so b A b' =b. But
(p 1\ b') f 0 (for, if (p 1\ b') = 0, thenp";;; b (Theorem 2i), whence p = b, by b 1\ b' = 0, so b = 0, contradicting the assumption that b was an atom. Hence
the antisymmetry of ";;;). There must therefore be some atom c such that p';;; VAp proving the theorem.
c ..;;; (p 1\ b'). But then c ..;;; p (Theorem 2e and transitivity of ";;;), so that
78 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 80 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

P E Ie; and C f b (since C ~ b' (by Theorem 2e and transitivity of ~), whence Note crucially that if B in Theorem 10 is not atomic then it contains a
C f\ b = 0 (by Theorem 4c)); if C = b, then C f\ b = 0 implies that c = b = 0, property which is not identical to the join of its atoms. We may now prove
which is impossible if c and b are atoms). Thus, p would be a member of the that L is extensional. In fact we show something slightly more general:
individual Ie as well as h, contradicting the assumption that p was a member
of exactly one individual. THEOREM 11. For all p, q E TN, P ~q iff {I: p EI} ~ {I: q EI}.
And we are motivated to require that TN have such properties for several Proof. Suppose p ,;;;; q and assume pEl. Then p = (p 1\ q) E I, whence
reasons. As mentioned, if TN has no such properties then there are no individ- by the Meets condition on I, q E I. So {I: p E I} ~ {I: q E I}. Suppose
uals on TN and thus proper nouns would have no denotations, i.e. they could now {I: p E I} ~ {I: q EI}. Assume contrary to what we want to show that
not be interpreted. Moreover motivation for atoms is more directly supported p 1 q. Then p 1\ q' f 0, whence there is an atom b ,;;;; p 1\ q', so b ~ p and
by the existence of common noun phrases which are clearly intended to b ~ q', so P E Ib and q' E Ib, whence by the Complement condition on
denote properties which just one individual has. Examples are: tallest student, individuals, q rf lb· So {I: p E I} C1 {I: q EI} contradicting the supposition.
first man who set foot on the moon, man who was the first President of the Thusp ~q.
US., etc. Note of course that such expressions may fail to denote atoms.
Suppose for example that no one ever set foot on the moon. Then first man COROLLARY 1. L is extensional. Viz.: For all p, q E TN, P = q iff {I: p EI}
who set foot on the moon would denote a property which no individual had, = {I: q EI}.
namely O. However it is clear that the intended use of such common noun Proof p = q iff p ,;;;; q and q ,;;;; p from which the corollary follows im-
phrases is that they denote properties which just one individual has, so we mediately.
want TN to provide such properties: otherwise they would have to denote 0,
which is incorrect. Moreover some common nouns will of necessity denote Note that the proof of Theorem 11 crucially uses the fact that TN is atomic.
atoms. For example, individual who is John is a property which John and no If TN were not atomic then TN would contain a p f 0 which dominated no
other individual has. Thus we want TN to provide atoms, and atoms are not atoms. Thus p and 0 would dominate the same atoms and thus be distinct
at all mysterious in the way that elements of U were in EFOL. Namely they properties in the same individuals, contradicting the corollary and thus the
are the intended denotations of many ordinary expressions in English such as theorem. So given that TN is taken to be a complete algebra we can see that
tallest student, etc. the atomicity requirement on TN is equivalent to Extensionality. And this
Moreover it also seems reasonable to require that TN be atomic. That fact suggests a novel approach to non-extensional logics: Namely, we simply
is, if vegetarian denotes a non-zero property then it is a property which relax the requirement that TN be atomic. We may still require that it have
some individual has. Interpret John as such an individual. Then vegetar- atoms, and thus by the remark made earlier, it can have as many individuals
ian who is John is a property which only John has and is thus an atom. as we like. But such a TN would allow that distinct properties determine the
And it ought to be an atom less than or equal to the vegetarian property, same sets of individuals, and this is in fact realistic. Thus it seems reasonable
since every individual who has the vegetarian-who-is-John property clearly that we predicate something different of John when we claim he is a doctor
has the vegetarian property. So any non-zero property should contain an than when we claim he is a thief, even if it happens that the doctors and the
atom. thieves are 'accidentally' so to speak the same individuals. So in such a TN
This completes our informal justification that TN should be a complete doctor and thief could be interpreted as different properties but still be
and atomic algebra and that individuals on TN should be those subsets of members of the same individuals. Thus we have an approach to non-exten-
TN which satisfy the Meets, Joins, and Complements Conditions, which sional logics which does not invoke the more problematic and not fully
means that the individuals are just the Ib'S defined earlier. satisfactory (see Part II) notion of possible worlds. We are currently pursuing
Further, our definitions guarantee that L satisfies a further adequacy this approach to intensional logic but are not yet confident enough of the
criterion, namely, extensionality, in the sense of (27): details to include this presentation here.
Let us note finally that Theorem 11 has another useful corollary:
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 81 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 83

COROLLARY 2. For K any set of individuals there is exactly one property (28) a. Some but not all students attended the meeting.
PK which is in just the individuals in K. b. Some students but not all students attended the meeting.
Proof. By the Theorem 11 there cannot be two such properties so it
suffices to show that there is at least one. Define PK =df V {b E P: b is an We shall then want to define the boolean operations on To et pointwise. But
atom and 1b E K}. Let 1 arbitrary in K. Then 1 = 1b for some atom b, and this of course does not mean that TOet = Fp*IP' it only means that To et is
since PK is an upper bound for the set of those atoms, b .;;;; PK' whence by closed under the pointwise operations. That is, whenever f and g are in To et ,
Theorem 11 PK E1b =1. Thus for all1EK, PK E1. then so are f 1\ g, f v g, and f' as well as 0 and 1, where these operations and
Suppose next that 1 tf. K, say 1 = 1b o ' and that PK E 1b o ' Then, by the elements are defined as in the pointwise algebra.
Joins condition, since PK = V1b Eo' K b, we must have bE 1b o for some b So in fact the natural definition of To et for Det as given is to take it as
such that 1b E K. But then 1b o would contain two atoms (b and b o ; they the boolean closure of the interpretations we need for the lexically simple
cannot be equal since 1b E K and 1b o tf. K), contradicting the discussion Dets. That is, we take the functions we need to interpret the lexically simple
following Theorem 9. Dets we have endowed L with, and add to that set all the functions we can
obtain from them by adding 0 and 1 and taking all combinations of meets,
The significance of Corollary 2 is that we can define an element of TN joins, and complements. Let us formally defme the operation of taking
just by specifying what individuals it is in, and we can specify that set of boolean closures, as this will prove a useful general way of defining types
individuals in any way we like. (it will be used again in the intensional logic in Part II). As we are only
We return now to the definitions of the other basic types for L. interested in complete algebras we just give the definition for that case.

DEFINITION 23. For B a complete algebra and K a subset of B, K is com-


Defining TDet (= TR/N) pletely B-closed iff (i) 0, 1 E K and (ii) for all b E B, if bE K then b' EK,
Having taken TN as a complete and atomic algebra P and TR as its power set and (iii) for G ~B,ifG ~Kthen I\G EK and VG EK.
algebra P*, we shall interpret elements of Det (= NIN) as functions from P
DEFINITION 24. For B a complete algebra and K ~ B, BK, or the complete
into P*. We might take TDet to be Fp*jP, the entire set of functions from
Pinto P*. But should we? Are there not perhaps some constraints on what n
B closure of K, =df {G ~ B: K ~ G and G is completely B-closed}
functions from properties into sets of properties can be interpretations of
extensional English Dets? TIIEOREM 12. For B a complete algebra, K a subset of B,
On the face of it there would appear to be severe constraints. All the
elements of Det in L are intuitively logical constants; that is, every for exam- (i) BK is completely B-closed and
ple cannot be randomly interpreted in TDet no matter what set we take TDet (ii) BK is the domain of a complete boolean algebra, where the 0 and
to be. There is only one function from Pinto p* which can interpret every. 1 are the same as in B and meets, joins, and complements are the
It might seem then that we could simply define the interpretations of ele- operations in B restricted to BK. Moreover, if G ~ BK then the
ments of Det and define T Det to be the set of functions so defined. But this glb (lub) of Gin BK is identical to its glb (lub) in B.
approach is both unfeasible and uninteresting. It is unfeasible since even
in L we have some ways of forming complex Dets, namely by boolean com- The algebra BK so defmed is called the (complete) subalgebra of B generated
binations. E.g. not all, some but not all, etc. are syntactically complex ele- by K, and K is called a set of (complete) generators for BK.
ments of Det and their denotations are not the same as any of the lexically Thus we might reasonably define To et to be the complete subalgebra of
simple members of Det. More importantly we shall in the sequel extend the pointwise algebra Fp* IP generated by the denotations of the lexically
Det so as to include expressions which are not logical constants. For example" simple Dets. And this approach is in fact adequate for L, but not for the
possessives such as John's and no student's as they occur in e.g. John's extensions of L we shall propose. To account for the extensions of L we
82 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 84 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

car was stolen, no student's car was stolen, etc. will be analyzed as Dets. shall investigate briefly the properties which denotations of simple Dets
Anticipating somewhat, we would like to define TDet so as to be large have in common and then take the set of functions from Pinto p* which
enough to provide denotations for these non-logical Dets. The issue then is have those properties as the generators for TDet. Let us then consider first
whether the variety of non-logical Dets in English justifies taking TDet as the denotations of the lexically simple Dets of L.
the entire set of functions from Pinto p* or not. If not, we would like to
give substantive constraints on the meanings of extensional English Dets. DEFINITION 25. every is that function from Pinto p* such that for all
We shall in fact claim that such constraints can be given. We refer the reader pEP, every (p) = n{I: p EI}'! ranging over individuals.
to Keenan and Stavi (1981) for a detailed justification of this point, only
giving the broad outlines of that investigation here. In defining interpretations for L we shall require that each, every and all be
Consider first however one apparent argument in support of taking TDet interpreted by every. (So we treat each, every and all as logical synonyms
to be Fp*IP' Namely, that set of functions is naturally regarded as a boolean here, ignoring the slightly subtle differences between them as they are not
algebra, called a pointwise algebra, and it is the case that the boolean opera- easily represented in a first order logic.) Thus every student will be inter-
tions in that algebra are the natural interpretations for boolean combinations preted as the value of the every function at the student property, namely
of English Dets. Let us first define pointwise algebras and note a few of the intersection of the individuals which have the student property. So every
their basic properties. student denotes the set of properties which the individual students have
in common.
DEFINITION 22. Let D be the domain of a boolean algebra and B any non-
empty set. Then (FD IB, 0, 1,1\, V, ') is a boolean algebra, where: DEFINITION 26. a is that element of Fp*/p which sends each pEP to
Up Ell.
(i) FD IB is the set of functions with domain B and range included
in D, and for allf, g EFDIB and all x EB, We will interpret both a and some by a. So a student will denote the set of
(ii) O(x)=ODandl(x)=lD, properties which at least one individual student has.
(iii) (f 1\ g) (x) = [(x) I\D g(x), ([ v g) (x) = [(x) vD g(x) and (j')
(x) = (j(X))'D' DEFINITION 27. no = (a)'

FD IB so defined is easily seen to be a boolean algebra; it is called the point- So no student then, by the pointwise definition of I , will denote the com·
wise algebra from B into D. We note further that if D is a complete algebra plement in p* of a student, namely the set of properties which fail to be in
then so is FDIB. If K is any subset of FDIB then the function fK which any individual with the student property.
maps each x in B onto 1\ {k(x): k E K} is the glb for K; lub's are defined
analogously. Moreover if D is atomic then so is FD/B. For each atom d ED DEFINITION 28: the is that function which maps ponto Ip if P is an atom
and each element b E B, then function fd,b which sends b to d and all other and onto f/J otherwise.
elements of B to OD is an atom of FD/B.
Thus we may regard Fp*!p as a complete and atomic boolean algebra. Thus the student will denote the unique individual with the student property
And the operations so defined are in fact the natural interpretations of and, if there is exactly one individual with that property. Otherwise it will denote
or, and not as applied to Dets. E.g. the pointwise definitions say that (not all) the empty set.
(student) denotes the same element of p* as does not (all student). Similarly, Note that of the lexically simple Dets in L, no is somewhat exceptional
(some but (not all)) (student) will be synonymous with «some student) in that its denotation is naturally given as a boolean function of another
but «not all) (student)), which seems correct, e.g. (28a) is clearly logically simple Det, a. If we define TDet to be the boolean closure of any set which
equivalent to (28b). includes a that set will then include no. So we need not guarantee that no
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 85
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 87
has a denotation in TDet by specifically including it among the generators;
it is sufficient to include a. We might note in passing that it can be reasonably subset of Fp*jp. Specifically, where n is the number of atoms of P, the
argued on the basis of pairs like ever/never, one/none, either/neither, etc. cardinality of TDet =2(3 n ) and the cardinality of Fp*/p =2(4 n ).
that no is bi-morphemic, consisting of a negative morpheme n- and a base
-0. Historically this is correct, no being the pre consonantal form of Anglo- For example, if P has only 2 atoms (and thus two individuals) there are
Saxon nan deriving ultimately from ne 'not' + an 'one'. 23 2 = 2 9 = 512 logically possible determiner denotations. But there are
In any event, excluding no let us consider the properties that the other 242 = 2 16 = 65,536 elements in Fp */p. So even for very small P most functions
simple determiner denoations have in common. There turn out (Keenan and from Pinto P* are not possible extensional Det interpretations in English.
Stavi, 1981) to be two which are sufficient to provide a rich enough set of
generators for English extensional Dets: that of being increasing and that of Defining the Types for the Pn 's
being weakly conservative. We define these notions below:
We shall first define the type for PI (= Po/N) in terms of those for Po and
DEFINITION 29. For K a subset of a boolean algebra B, R; then we generalize the definition to yield, for each n > 0, a type for
Pn+l in terms of those for P n and R. A final generalization allows us to
(i) K is increasing iff for all x, y EB, if x ~y and x E K then y E K; construct types for any predicative hierarchy {en: n ;;;. O} once the type
(ii) K is decreasing iff for all x, y E B, if x ~y and y E K then x E K. for Co has been given as a complete and atomic algebra. Note that Tpo has
(iii) For all [E FB * IB, [is increasing iff for all x E B, [(x) is increas- already been given as the complete and atomic (ca-) algebra, 2.
ing;fis decreasing iff for all x EB, [(x) is decreasing. As PI'S will be interpreted by functions from TN (= P*) into Tpo (= 2)
we may wonder, in analogy to the query raised for TDet, whether just any
THEOREM 13. function from p* into 2 is a possible interpretation for a first order exten-
(i) For B an arbitrary algebra, sional PI or not. If so, we will take the type for PI to be F2/P*, the entire
(a) and B are both increasing and decreasing subsets of B, and are
C/J
set of functions from p* into 2. But if not, then being a first order exten-
the only subsets with this property sional predicate imposes non-trivial conditions on what functions from R
(b) Arbitrary unions and intersections of increasing sets are increasing denotations into truth values may be their interpretations. And in fact, it
(ii) An individual on B is an increasing subset of B (since if pEl and is easy to see that this latter option is correct. Consider for example that
p ~ q then p = p 1\ q EI, so by Meets, q E/). (29a) entails (29b), and that (29b) and (29c) are judged logically equivalent.
(29) a. John spoke.
From Theorem 13 it is immediate that the simple determiner denotations b. Either John or Mary spoke.
(except no) are increasing, as their values are always increasing subsets of P. c. Either John spoke or Mary spoke.
Note further that many fairly simple non-logical Dets will also be interpreted
by increasing functions. For example, consider John's. John's car will denote That (29a) entails (29b) says that spoke cannot be interpreted by a randomly
the individual with the car property which John 'has' if there is just one, selected element of F2/P*. For if the spoke-function assigns the denotation
otherwise it will denote the empty set. Thus the value of John's at p is either of John value 1 then it must assign the denotation of John or Mary value 1,
an individual or the empty set, in any event an increasing set, so John's is otherwise we could have a situation in which (29a) is true and (29b) false.
an increasing Det denotation. Somewhat more formally, let John and Mary be interpreted by individuals
The property of being (weakly) conservative is a somewhat less obvious Ix and Iy respectively. Then John or Mary is interpreted by Ix v Iy (= Ix U I y ,
one: since joins are unions in power set algebras, and Ix and Iy are elements of
the power set algebra P*). Then the truth values of the sentences in (29)
DEFINITION 30. For B a boolean algebra and[EFB*IB, are represented as in (30) below, using f to represent the function from p*
into 2 which interprets spoke.
86 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 88 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

(i) f is weakly conservative iff for all x, y E B, (30) a. [(Ix) ('John spoke')
if x Ef(y) then (x Ay) Ef(y) b. [(Ix v ly) ('John or Mary spoke')
(ii) fis conservative ifffor aU x, y EB, x Ef(y) c. ([(Ix) v [ely)~ ('John spoke or Mary spoke')
iff (x A y) Ef(y).
To say then that (29a) entails (29b) is to say then that if [assigns value 1 to
Formally it is not hard to show that every, a, and the are weakly conservative.
Ix then it must assign value 1 to Ix U Iy; thus f is not an arbitrary element
To see this intuitively suppose that p is a property which every student has.
of F2/P*. Moreover the logical equivalence of (29b) and (29c) says that the
Then clearly every student has p A the student property, that is every student
truth value [ associates with a join of individuals must be the same as the
is both a p and a student. Similarly if some student is a p then some student join (in the truth value algebra) of the ones it associates with each of the
is both a p and a student; ditto for the student. And if p is a property of
individuals consider separately. That is, (30b) and (30c) above must be
John's car then so is p A the car·property, i.e. John's car is both a p and a identical elements of 2, otherwise there could be a situation in which one
car, so John's is weakly conservative. We might note that being increasing was true and the other false. We may say then that [preserves (finite) joins
and weakly conservative are completely independent properties. For example, in the sense that it maps a join of N denotations onto the corresponding
the function f defined by f( x) = {I B } , all x E B is increasing but not weakly join in the truth value algebra. Note that the N .denotations need not be
conservative; the function g defined by g(x) = {y E B: y :( x} is weakly individuals. For example (31 a) is logically equivalent to (31 b) and every
conservative but not increasing. On the other hand, note that if f is weakly student (as well as every teacher) denotes an intersection of individuals,
conservative and increasing thenfis conservative. For suppose (x A y) Ef(y).
a set which is not in general an individual.
Then x must be in feY) since (x A y) :( x and f is increasing. Thus in fact
the simple Det denotations above are all conservative (and increasing). (31) a. Either every student or every teacher spoke.
In Keenan and Stavi (op. cit.) it is shown that if we define TDet to be b. Either every student spoke or eve'ry teacher spoke.
the subalgebra of Fp*/p generated by the increasing and weakly conservative
functions in that set we obtain a set large enough to provide denotations for Let us formally define the concept of 'preserving joins' and then require
an exceedingly large class of extensional Dets in English. We refer the reader that elements of TP 1 be functions which preserve joins.
to that work then for the empirical justification of the adequacy of the
following definition: DEFINITION 32. Let Band D be boolean algebras, and f. a function in
FD/B' Then,
DEFINITION 31. TDet = the subalgebra of Fp*/p generated by the set of
increasing and weakly conservative functions in Fp*/p. (i) [preserves finite joins iff for all x, y EB,f(x v y) =[(x) v fey),
(ii) [preserves (arbitrary) joins iff for all K ~ B, if K has a lub in B
And we may note the following theorem: then (f(k): k E K} has a lub in D and [(VK) = V{f(k): k EK}.

THEOREM 14. TDet = {fEFp*/p;fis conservative} To see that we want P 1 interpretations to preserve (arbitrary) joins consider
first the glb's and lub's for arbitrary subsets K of 2:
We might also note that our definition of conservative coincides with that
of lives on its arguments taken as the defining property of English Dets (32) K /\K VK
in Barwise and Cooper (1980). On our view, as pointed out above, it is C/J 0
a theorem that a determiner lives on its arguments. Note finally the following {O} 0 0
theorem: {l}
{O, I} 0
THEOREM IS. For complete and atomic algebras P, TDet is a (very) proper
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 89 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 91

Thus the join of a bunch of truth values is 1 iff 1 is one of the elements preserve meets, joins, and complements. These are just the (complete) homo-
over which the join is taken; otherwise it is zero. And the meet of a bunch morphisms fromP* into 2. Formally let us define:
of truth values is 0 just in case 0 is one of those over which the meet is
taken; otherwise the meet is 1. And to see that we want PI interpretations DEFINITION 35. For Band D boolean algebras and h EFD/B'
to preserve (arbitrary) joins consider that we want the truth value of (33a)
below, expressed in (33b), to be identical to that expressed in (33c): (i) h is a homomorphism from B into D iff h preserves finite meets,
finite joins, and complements.
(33) a. A student spoke
(ii) h is a complete homomorphism from B into D iff h preserves
b. f(V {I: s E I} ) (f ranges over individuals, and s is the student
arbitrary meets, arbitrary joins, and complements.
property)
c. V{f(I): s EI}
We may note without proof that if h is a function from B into D which
Now (33c) is 1 just in case one of the elements f(J) is 1, that is, just in case preserves complements and finite meets then h also preserves finite joins
there is an individual with the student property who spoke. Clearly we want and is thus a homomorphism. Similarly if h preserves complements and
the truth value which the spoke-function associates with the denotation of arbitrary meets then it also preserves arbitrary joins and is thus a complete
a student, represented directly in (33b), to be identical to the truth value homorphism. (Moreover the two previous claims may be modified by replac-
represented in (33c). Otherwise for example (33b) might be 1 and (33c) 0, ing everywhere 'meets' by 'joins' and 'joins' by 'meets' and remain true).
which would mean that a student spoke was true even though no individual Some further unsurprising properties of homomorphisms are given by:
student spoke, which is intuitively incorrect.
We shall require then that functions which can interpret PI'S of L be ones THEOREM 16. For h a homomorphism from B into D,
which preserve joins. An analogous argument shows that we also want these
functions to preserve meets. Thus (34a) and (35a) are judged logically equi- (i) h(OB) = OD and h(IB) = ID.
valent, so we want the truth values expressed in (34b) and (35b) to of neces- (ii) For all x, y EB, if X';;;;B Y then hex) ~ h(y)
sity be the same:
We might note further that for B a finite algebra the homomorphisms from B
(34) a. A student and a teacher spoke into any algebraD are all complete, so the homomorphisms and the complete
b. f( V 11\ V J) homomorphisms coincide. But for B an infinite algebra this need not be the
sEI tEl
(35) a. A student spoke and a teacher spoke case. In fact, for B an infinite complete and atomic (ca) algebra, there are
very many homomorphisms which are not complete homomorphisms. In
b. f(s ~ / ) 1\ f(t ~ I J)
addition we may note that any isomorphism (see Definition 18) from B onto
Here of course 'f' denotes the interpretation of spoke, 's' that of student, 't' D is of course a homomorphism and provably a complete homomorphism.
that of teacher, Vs E I 1(= U{I: s E I}) that of a student, etc. Similarly we We shall in general denote the set of complete homomorphisms from an
want the spoke-function to preserve arbitrary meets, as we want the truth algebra B into an algebra D by HD/B. And we shall define the type for PI
value of (36a) below, expressed directly in (36b), to be the same as that in to be H2/P*, the set of complete homomorphisms from TN into Tpo.
(36c). But if we define Tp i to be H2/P* have we guaranteed that PI interpre-
tations are in a one-to-one correspondence to the properties TN? More
(36) a. Every student spoke generally, are the elements of H2/P* just the one place predicates of stan-
b.f(s~IJ) dard first order logic? To see that they are, consider that to define a PI in
FOL we must state exactly what individuals they hold and fail of. And
c. 1\ f(I)
SEI Theorem 17 below says that this is exactly how we define elements of H2/P*.
90 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 92 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

(36c) of course is just a notational variant of 1\ {f(I): s E I}, and a meet of THEOREM 17. (The Justification Theorem, JT). For P and B any complete
a set of truth values is 1 iff each of the values in the set is 1. Thus every and atomic algebras and f any function from Ip, the set of individuals on
student spoke will be true in L iff each individual with the student property P, into B there is exactly one complete homomorphism hf from p* into
spoke, which is intuitively correct. If the spoke-function were not required B which agrees with f on the individuals, i.e. such that hf(l) = f(!), all
to preserve infinite meets then the truth values denoted in (3 6b) and (36c) individuals I.
could be different, say (36b) is land (36c) is O. But then spoke would hold
of the denotation of every student even though there was some individual The significance of the JT is that we can define a P 1 homomorphism just by
I with the student property of which the spoke-function failed (since (36c) is stating its values on the individuals, and we may do that in any way we like.
a meet of a set of truth values and thus has value 0 iff 0 is in the set, that is, E.g. we may say, let h be that element of H2/P* which maps each individual
iff [(I) = 0 for some individual I with the student property). Formally then I onto 1B. We have explicitly stated what h does to the individuals, and the
let us define: JT says that there is exactly one element of H2/P* which has a fixed set
of values on the individuals. As JT is slightly more difficult to prove than
DEFINITION 33. For Band D boolean algebras and[in FD/B, other theorems we have presented up to now we give the proof in two steps,
Lemma 1 and Lemma 2 below:
(i) [preserves finite meets iff for all x, y E B, [(x 11 y) = [(x) 11 [(y). LEMMA 1 (Uniqueness). Let P, B be arbitrary ca-algebras and hand k com-
(li) [preserves (arbitrary) meets iff for all K ~ B, if I\K exists then plete homomorphisms from p* into B such that for all individuals IE Ip,
I\{f(k): k EK} exists and [(I\K) = 1\ [(k). h(!) = k(!). Then h = k, that is, for all Q EP*, h(Q) = k(Q).
kEK
Proof. Note first that for any q EP, h( {q}) =k( {q}); since,
And we shall require of elements in Tp 1 that they preserve meets as well
as joins. Finally note that we also want first order extensional PI'S to preserve h( {q}) = h(
qEJ
n I n q7=OJ (I')) Theorem 1
complements; that is, the truth value which the spoke-function assigns to =qEJ
A h(!) 1\ /) h(I') h preserves meets
the complement of an N denotation should be the opposite (= complement) q7=J
of the value it assigns to the N denotation itself. E.g. the denotation of not = A h(!) 1\ !; (h(!))' h preserves complements
qEI q7=J
(every student) is the complement of that of every student, and we want the
spoke-function to assign these sets opposite truth values as denotations. This. = A k(f) 1\ !; (k(I))' h(f) = k(f), all I by
qEJ q7=J
assumption
guarantees for example that (37a) and (37b) are logically equivalent.
= k( A lI\ !; (I')) k preserves meets and
qEI q7=J
(37) a. (not (every student)) spoke. complements
b. not [(every student) spoke]. =k( {q}) Theorem 1

Formally then we may define: Whence for any Q E P*,

h(Q)=h( U
qEQ
{q}) Q=q~Q{q}
DEFINITION 34. For Band D boolean algebras and [E FD IB, [preserves
complements iff for all x E B, [(x') = [(x))' =qEQ
V h( {q}) h preserves joins

Of course the complement sign on the right hand side of the equation above =qEQ
V k({q}) h( {q}) = k( {q}) by above
refers to complements in D since [(x) is an element of D; on the left it refers =k(Q) k preserves joins
to complements in B.
We want then to limit Tp 1 to those functions from p* into 2 which Thus h =k.
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 93 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 95

Thus there cannot be two different complete homomorphisms from p* into natural one-to-one way to elements of TN' note that we may consider a
B with the same values on the individuals. Now let us show that any way of complete homomorphism from p* into 2 as a function which assigns a set
assigning values in B to the individuals extends to a complete homomorphism. of properties Q value 1 iff a fixed property p is a member of Q. Formally,

LEMMA 2 (Existence). For P, B arbitrary ca-algebras andfany function from DEFINITION 36.
Ip into B, there is a complete homomorphism hf from p* into B such that
(i) For all pEP (= TN) define a function fp from p* into 2 by:
hf(J) =f(I), all individuals I E I p.
fp(Q)= 1 ifpEQandfp(Q)=Oifp~Q
Proof.
(ii) Fp =df {fp: pEP}
(i) givenfas above, define a function hf fromP* into B by:
'J
hf(Q) = q Q (q ~ If(J) 1\ q ~ I (f(I))'), all Q EP* THEOREM 18.Fp =H2/P*
Note that Fp and H2/P* are both subsets of F2/P*. The straightforward
hf as defined is clearly a function from p* into B. We must show that hf is proof of Theorem 18 is sketched out at the end of this section.
a complete homomorphism and that hf extends f. Now, we want to regard TPi as a boolean algebra since we want to provide
interpretations for boolean combinations of Pi'S, e.g. (both) sing and dance,
SUBLEMMA. For all atoms b E B, define Pb E P by: Pb EI iff b ~f(J), all (either) sing or dance, not sing, etc. The definitions of the meet, join, and
individuals I in Ip. Then, for all Q E P*, and all atoms b E B, b ~ hf(Q) iff complement operations on TP i will have to be made with some care, as we
Pb EQ. 8 must guarantee for example that our representation for (38a) does not entail
Proof. Let Q and b arbitrary as above. Then, that for (38b).
'J
b ~ hf(Q) iff b ~ q Q (q ~ I f(I) 1\ q ~ I (f(I»)') Def of hf (38) a. Each student was either singing or dancing.
b. Either each student was singing or each student was dancing.
iff 3q E Q, b ~ 1\ f(I) 1\ /). (f(I)' b is an atom
qEI q"F1 Thus the interpretation of sing or dance cannot be handled pointwise on P *
iff 3q E Q, b ~ 1\ f(J) and b ~ /). (f(I»' since then the interpretation of sing or dance would map any set of properties,
qEI q"F1
say the interpretation of every student, onto the join in the truth value
iff 3q E Q, ('VI) (q EI -+ b ~f(I) algebra of the values obtained by applying each disjunction to that set. That
and ('VI) (q tf:-I-+b ~ (f(I)' is, (38a) and (38b) would be logically eqUivalent, which is incorrect. On the
other hand, boolean combinations of Pi'S do behave pointwise on individuals.
iff 3q E Q, ('VI) (q EI -+ b ~f(I)
Thus (39a) below is logically equivalent to (39b).
and (VI) (q tf:-I -+ b tf:-f(J»
iff 3q E Q, ('VI) (q EI +--+ b ~f(I) (39) a. John was either singing or dancing.
b. Either John was singing or John was dancing.
iff 3q E Q, q =Pb
Note further that in (38a), sing or dance does behave as a homomorphism.
iffPb E Q.
For each student will be interpreted as the meet (= intersection) of the
(ii) hf extends f, i.e. hf(J) =f(J), all individuals I. individuals with the student-property, and the truth value which sing or
dance associates with that meet is the one obtained by applying it to each
We show that for all I, hf(I) and f(I) dominate the same atoms of B, whence of the individuals over which the meet was taken - obtaining a truth value
they are the same element of B by, essentially, Theorem 11. in each case - and taking the meet of the resulting truth values. Thus each
For an arbitrary atom b EB, student was singing or dancing is true just in case for each individual I with
94 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 96 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

b ';;;f(J) iff Pb EJ Def ofPb the student property, I was singing or dancing, that is, I was singing or I was
iff b';;; hf(J) Sublemma dancing. And given that we may defme a PI homomorphism just by stating
its values on the individuals, and that should be clearly done pointwise as
(iii) hf preserves complements. per (39), we may then define the sing-or-dance homomorphism as that one
Let Q arbitrary inP*, b an arbitrary atom inB. Then, whose value at an individual I is the join of the value of the sing-homo-
morphism at I with the dance-homomorphism at I. Formally:
b';;; hf(Q') iff Pb E Q' Sublemma
iffPb ~ Q Def of' DEFINITION 37. TP 1 = H2/P*, regarded as a boolean algebra where 0, 1, /\,
v, and' are define pointwise on the individuals as follows:
iff b "" hf(Q) Sublemma
b is an atom. (i) 0 is that element of H2/P* which maps each individual I onto O2 ,
iff b';;; Chf(Q))'
the zero element of 2;
Thus hf(Q') = (hf(Q))' since these two elements of B dominate the same (ii) 1 is that element of H2/P* which maps each I onto 12 ;
atoms and B is complete and atomic. and
(iv) hf preserves meets (iii) for all h, k EH2/P*,
(a) (h /\ k) is that element of H2/P* such that for all individuals I,
Let K an arbitrary subset of P*, b an arbitrary atom EB. (h /\ k) (I) =h(I) /\ k(I);
Then, (b) (h v k) is that element of H2/P* such that for aliI, (h v k) (I) =
h(f) v kef); and
b .;;; hf(I\K) iff b .;;; hfCnK) 1\ = n in power set algebras (c) (h') is that element of H2/P* such that for all I, (h') (I) =(h(I))'.
iffPb E nK Sublemma Of course the meet, join, and complement signs on the right of the equations
iff 'Vk EK, Pb E k Defofn in (iii) refer to these operations in 2, since h(1) and k(f) are elements of 2.
iff 'Vk EK, b';;; hf(k) Sublemma By the JT (h /\ k), (h v k), and h' above are well defined elements of TP 1 =
H2/P* since there is exactly one element of H2/P* with a given set of values
iff b is a lb for {hf(k): kEK}, Def oflb on the individuals and in each case we have stated what their values on the
iff b';;; 1\ htCk) Def of glb individuals are. Crucially, then, the boolean operations on Tp 1 are not
kEK
defined pointwise on p* itself, but only on the subset of p* consisting of the
Thus hf(I\K) = I\k E K hf(k) since these two elements of B dominate the individuals. By the JT this is sufficient.
same atoms and B is complete and atomic. As the application of these definitions in particular cases can sometimes
Since hf preserves meets and complements it also provably preserves be tricky, let us first show that (40) below, our representation for (39a),
joins. Thus hf is a complete homomorphism which extends f, proving the is logically equivalent to (41), our representation for (39b).
theorem.

l----L----
(40) John (sing or dance)
Note that the JT does not require that B be the minimal algebra 2. It is
-sufficient that B is a ca-algebra. Thus we have as a special case of JT that (a) ) j
im element of Tp 1 '" H2/P* is defined by stating its values on the individuals
in any way we like, which is just to say that TP 1 is the set of one place
(b) ~(SVd)
predicates of standard first other logic. (c) (s v d)(J)
To see formally that the elements of TP 1 as defined correspond in a (d) = s(I) v d(I)
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 97 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 99

In line (a) we indicate that John is interpreted as some individual I; sing and requires that of each individual with the student property, either he is singing
dance as PI homomorphisms sand d respectively. In line (b) sing or dance is or he is dancing. Thus (f) in (42) can be 1 in models where (f) in (43) is O.
interpreted as the PI homomorphism (s v d). In line (c) the truth value of Thus (42) and (43) are not logically equivalent on our semantics.
the entire sentence is represented as (s v d) (I), the value of (s v d) at the As a further exercise in this notation we invite the reader show the follow-
individual I. Line (d) indicates that this value is the same as s(I) v deI), ing: (not [(every man) sing]) is logically equivalent to ([not (every man)]
joins now of course taken in the truth value algebra. The equality is directly sing), and neither is equivalent to [(every man) (not sing)] . «no man) sing) is
justified by our definition of v in the PI algebra - namely pointwise on equivalent to «not (a man» sing); «some student) (sink and swim») is not
individuals. equivalent to [(some student) sink] and [(some student) swim] .
Returning now to the defmition of TP 1 note that we must prove that
(41) (John sing) or (John dance)
the boolean operations 0, I, II, v, and I as defined actually satisfy the axioms
(a)
I I I I of a boolean algebra. Let us in fact show more:
I~S I~d
(b) s(I) d(I) THEOREM 19. Tp 1 as defined is a complete and atomic algebra.
Proof sketch
(c) sCI) v d(I)
Here the interpretations of John, sing, and dance are as before, as indicated (i) Tp 1 is a boolean algebra.
in line (a). Line (b) says that truth value of (John sing) is given by s(I), the
value of the sing homomorphism at the individual John; similarly d(l) gives We have already shown that 0 and 1 are well defined elements of H2/P* =
the value (John dance). And line (c) says that the value of (41) is the join TP 1 as are (h II k), (h v k), and h' whenever hand k are in H2/P*. To show
of these two truth values. As line (c) here is identical to line (d) in (40) it that the operations as defined satisfy the axioms of a boolean algebra let us
is clear that (40) and (41) will be represented by the same truth value when illustrate the proof that the complement law (h II h') = 0 holds. We must
their lexical components are interpreted the same. That is, (40) and (41) show that (h II h') and 0 have the same values on all elements of P*. By the
will be logically equivalent. JT (uniqueness) it is sufficient to show that they have the same values on the
Consider now the trickier case of (42), our representation for (38a) and individuals given that both (h II h') and 0 are complete homomorphisms from
that of (43), our representation for (38b), which must turn out not to be p* into 2. Let I be an arbitrary individual. Then,
logically equivalent.
(hllh')(I) =h(I)II(h')(I) pointwise def of II on individuals
(42) (every student) (sing or dance)
=h(I) II (h(!)' pointwise def of ' on individuals
I
(a) every~st
I
l~J =02
=0 (I)
complement laws in 2
defO in Tp 1
(b) every(st) (s v d)
As I was arbitrary, (h II h') (/) = O(I) for all I, so by the JT (h II h') = O. The
(c) = sf n
E I
I other axioms are proven analogously.

(d) (s vd)( nIl) To show TPI complete, note first the following lemma:
sf E

(e) =sf EA I (svd)(I) LEMMA 1. For B any ca-algebra, h, k any elements of HBjP*,
(f) = A (s(I) v d(I))
sf E I h ,;;;; k iff for all individuals I, h(I) ,;;;; k(I).
98 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 100 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Here line (a) gives the interpretations of the lexical expressions in (42). Line Proof.
(b) says that every student is the value of the every-function at the student
h<"k iff hAk=h def of <"
property, and sing or dance is the join of the sing-homomorphism with the
ill (W)«hllk)U)=hU» JT
dance-homomorphism. Line (c) gives the value of every student as the inter-
iff ('fIf) «h(f) II kef»~ = hU» pointwise def of II on individuals
section of the individuals with the student-property. Line (d) says that the
iff ('fII)(h(I) <" k(f) def<" in B
truth value of (42) is the value of (s v d) at this intersection. Line (e) is
justified since (s v d) is a homomorphism and thus maps an intersection of (ii) Tp i is complete
individuals onto the meet in the truth value algebra of the values obtained
Let K be a subset of H2/P*. Define hK in H2/P* by hK U) = 1\ {k(I):
by applying (s v d) to each of those individuals. Line (f) replaces (s v d) (I)
k E K}, all individuals I. Since 2 is complete, {kef): k E K} has a glb in 2;
by s(I) v dCl), which we may do by the definition of v in join in P the Pi
by the JT hK is a well-defined element of H2/P*. It is routine to show that
algebra since the argument of (s V d) is an individual. Note crucially that
hK is the glb for K. Similarly fK defined by fK U) = V {kef): k E K} is the
since (s V d) is a homomorphism its value at nst E I I is determined to be lub for K in Tp i . Thus TP I is complete.
I\st E I (s V d) (I). It would simply be false to say in general that its value
at nst E I Iwas e.g. s(nst E I I) V denst E I I). (iii) Tp I is atomic.

(43) «every student) sing) or «every student) dance) For all individuals f and all atoms x E 2, define iI, x in H2/P* by fJ, x (J)
[ I I = x if J = f, fJ, x (J) =0 if J f f. Each fI, x is easily shown to be an atom and
(a) every sf s every st d any non-zero element of H2/P* is easily shown to dominate an atom. Thus

e~V(st) e~'ist)
Tp 1 is atomic. Note that the only atom in 2 is the unit element. We have
(b) stated (iii) with slightly more generality than needed here for purposes of
(c) =st nIl
E
=
sf
nEI I later generalization.

(d) s(
sf
n I)
EI
d( n I)
sf E I
To conclude our discussion of TPI let us note:

THEOREM 20. TN is isomorphic to Tp 1 •


(e) s( nI !)vd( nI I)
sf E sf E
Proof sketch. The function f from P (= TN) into H2/P* (= Tp 1 ) which
sends each pEP to f p , defined in Definition 36, is easily seen to be an iso-
(f) = 1\ s(I) V 1\ d(I) morphism fromP onto H2/P*.
sf E I sf E I

The interpretation of the lines down to (d) is obvious. Line (d) merely says Defining TP n , all n
that every student sing is interpreted as the value of the sing homomorphism
Note that we want the PI (kiss (John and Bil!) to be interpreted as the same
at the denotation of every student; and similarly for every student dance.
element of TP 1 as «kiss John) and (kissBil!). This will guarantee for example
And (e) says the truth value of (43) is expressed by the join of these two
that our representations for (44a) and (44b) will be logically equivalent:
truth values. The equality of (e) with (f) follows from the fact that sand d
are both homomorphisms and thus preserve meets. And it is obvious that line (44) a. Mary kissed both John and Bill.
(f) here need not be the same truth value as that in line (f) of (42). For (f) b. Mary kissed John and kissed Bill.
in (43) to be I it must be the case that at least one of the truth values we take
the join of is 1. That is, either every student is singing is true or every student Of course by the pointwise definition of meet in individuals in Tp l' (44b)
above will be logically equivalent to (44c) below:
is dancing is true. But line (f) in (42) can be 1 if some students are singing
but not dancing and the others are dancing but not singing, since it only (44) c. Mary kissed John and Mary kissed Bill.
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 101 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 103

So this semantics will correctly predict that (44a) and (44c) are logically (i) TCo = TC and
equivalent. But to say that the PI'S in (44a, b) are the same elements of Tpl (li) TC n+l = HTcnIP*, regarded as a complete and atomic algebra
is just to say that the interpretation of the P2 kiss preserves meets. Similarly where the operations are defined pointwise on the individuals.
(to) kiss either John or Bill should be interpreted the same as (to) kiss John
or kiss Bill whence it will follow that Mary kissed either John or Bill will be Thus the type for Nl (= N/N) is defined as the set of complete homomor-
represented as logically equivalent to Mary kissed John or Mary kissed Bill, phisms from Til = p* into TN 0 (= TN), since TN is a complete and atomic
which is correct. So the kiss-function should preserve joins. Similarly (to) kiss algebra. The adequacy and interest of this definition will be discussed in the
no student should mean the same as (to) not (kiss a student), so kiss preserves extensions to L proposed shortly. For the nonce we may note that NI is
complements. Thus elements of Tp 2 should be homomorphisms from TN = an empty category of L, as are Ps , P4 , etc. Once we add a lambda operator
p* into Tp 1 . to L however it will follow that whenever a category C is interpreted by a
Moreover boolean combinations of P2 's are clearly interpreted pointwise ca-algebra then for all n, Cn is non-empty.
on individuals. Thus (to) both hug and kiss John means the same as (to) hug This completes the definition of the types for L. For convenience to the
John and (to) kiss John, etc. Thus we want TP 2 to be the set of complete reader we present these definitions in toto below:
homomorphisms from p* into TP I , regarded as a boolean algebra where
the operations are defined pointwise on the individuals. Since Tpl is a ca- Summary Definition of the Types
algebra the IT says that we may define elements of HTP1/P* just by stating
their values on the individuals. We immediately generalize this approach for DEFINITION 39. An ontology, or set of semantic primitives, for L is a pair
(P, 2) where P is a complete and atomic boolean algebra and 2 is the minimal
n-place predicates as follows:
boolean algebra
DEFINITION 38. For all n ~ 0, Tp n is defined inductively as follows:
DEFINITION 40. Relative to an ontology (P, 2) we define for each category
(i) Tpo = 2. C, Tc, or the type for C, as follows:
(ii) TP n +l = HTPn/P*' regarded as a complete and atomic boolean
TN=P,
algebra where the operations are defined pointwise on the indi-
TN =P*, regarded as a power set boolean algebra,
viduals. That is, On+l (I) = On, all individuals I; analogously for
TN pro p = {I: lis an individual on P}, where lis an individual on
I n +l' And (/lI n +l g) (I) =/(I) lin g(I), all individuals I. Analo-
P iff I is a subset of P such that
gously for V n+l and 'n+l-
(i) for all pEP, P E liff pi tf. I and
THEOREM 21. For all n ~ 0, TPn as above is a complete and atomic boolean (ii) for all K ~ p, 1\ K E I iff K ~ I.
algebra.
Proo/sketch: by induction on n. Remark: individuals so defined provably satisfy the Joins
Condition. We denote the set of individuals on P by Ip.
(i) for n = 0 we have that Tpo = 2 is a ca-aIgebra.
(ii) Assume the theorem for n, show it for n + 1. Then Tpn is a ca- TNIN = {f E Fp* IP: f is conservative}, regarded as a complete
algebra by the induction hypothesis, hence On+l, and In+l are and atomic boolean algebra where the operations are defined
well defined elements of HTp /p* by the IT, as are if I\n+ 1 g), pointwise on P.
, n
if Vn+l g) and / n+l when / and g are in TP n +l- The proof Tp (= Tpo) = 2 _ _
that the boolean axioms are satisfied follows the paradigm For C any of N, P, N, or N/Nwe use Co to abbreviate C and Cn+l
illustrated for TP I . The atoms of TPn +l map a single individual to abbreviate Cn/N and define inductively:
102 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 104 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

onto some atom of Tpn and all other individuals onto On. And (i) TCo = TC and
the glb for a subset K of TPn+l maps each individual onto the (ii) TC n +l = HTcn/P*, the set of complete homomorphism fromP*
glb for {kef): k E K} in Tpn' Analogously for lub's. into Tc n , regarded as a complete and atomic boolean algebra
where the operations are defined pointwise on Ip.
We have then defined TP n for all (finite) n. We note as well the following
two theorems (whose induction proofs are omitted): For all categories C not mentioned above, Tc = 0.
THEOREM 22. (Generalized Justification Theorem: CJT). For all n > 0, Defining Interpretations for L
if f is a function from (Ip)n into 2 then there is a unique complete homo-
morphism hf E TPn such that for all individuals 1 1'/2, ... ,In ( ... «hf(Id) An interpretation for L will be a function m from L = Uc E Cat C into
(12 ) ) " ' ) (In) =f(I 1 ,/2, . . . ,In). U c E Cat TC which assigns to each expression e of L of category C some
element of TC in accordance with certain constraints on lexical expressions
For example, the CJT says that we may define an element of Tp 2 merely by and constraints on derived expressions. Since the interpretation of a derived
giving a function from pairs of individuals into 2. E.g. we may define be as expression is uniquely determined once the interpretations of those it is
that element of TP2 such that for all individuals II, 12 be (Id (1 2) = 1 if derived from is given it will turn out that an interpretation m is uniquely
II =12 ; otherwise be (Id(I2) = O. determined by an interpretation M of the primitive expressions of L. Ac-
Finally, let us note that in the same way that Tp I is isomorphic to the cordingly we shall first define a lexical interpreting function M and then
power set of Ip, the set of individuals on P (= TN), so Tpn is isomorphic to extend M to a complete interpretation m. The domain of M will be the basic
the power set of (Ip)n. For let K be an element of that power set. Then K vocabulary V less the syncategorematic symbols and, or, and not. For con-
is a set of n-tuples of individuals. Define by the CJT the element fK in TP n venience let us define:
by « ... (fK (II)) ... ) (In) = 1 iff(Jl, 12 , . . . ,In) EK. The functionf
from «(Ip )n)* into Tpn which sends each K in «Ip )n)* to fK is the desired DEFINITION 41. Lex, or the lexicon of L, = V - {e E PEv: e is syncategore-
isomorphism. Thus: matic}, where e in PE V is syncategorematic iff e 'f- C for any category C.

DEFINITION 42. A model J.l of L is a triple <P, 2, M>, where <P, 2> is an
THEOREM 23. For all n ;;;:. 0, TP n is isomorphic to the power set of (Ip)n.
Theorem 23 says in effect that n-place predicates in L are semantically just ontology for Land M is a function from lex into Uc E Cat TC which satis-
sets of n-tuples of individuals, as they are in standard FOL. fies the following conditions:
(i) For all e E Lex and all categories C, if e E C thenM(e) ETc,
Defining Types for Predicative Hierarchies in General (ii) conditions on logical constants
The method of constructing types for the Pn generalizes immediately to any (a) M(individual) =M(existent) = ITN
predicative hierarchy (though in each case of course we must check that the (b) M(exist) = 1TPl
definition is descriptively adequate, i.e. the right elements are in fact judged (c) M(be) = be, that element of TP 2 such that for all individuals
to behave as homomorphisms and operations on them are pretheoretically 1 1 ,12 (be(Id)(I2)
judged to behave pointwise on the individuals). ={Ol if Ii =12
More specifically, let C be any category such that TC is a complete and if Ii fI2
atomic algebra. Then the predicative hierarchy generated by C is defined (d) M(every) = M(all) = M(each) = every, that element of TN/N
inductively as follows: Co =C and Cn+l = Cn/N. Types for the Cn are defined which sends each p E TN to 0 I, where I ranges over individuals
pEl
inductively as follows: on P ;
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 105 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 107

M(a) = M(some) = a, that element of THIN which maps each For example, in the same way that (John sang) and (Mary worked or Peter
p E TN onto
,
U I
pEl
slept) is logically equivalent to «John sang and Mary worked) or (John
M(no ) =a sang and Peter slept) in standard FOL so here e.g. John and (Mary or Peter)
M(the) is that element of TN/N which sends each p E TN to ~ if is logically equivalent to (John and Mary) or (John and Peter).
p is not an atom and to I p , the individual generated by p, if pis
an atom; DEFINITION 47. For all categories C and all e E C, e is logically 1 iff
(/J <e.
(iii) conditions on non-logical constants
M(bachelor) ~ M(man) It follows that for e E C, e is logically 1 iff for all interpretations m,
«M(kill) (IdHI z ) ~ (M(die))(II), all individuals 11,12. m(e) = 1Te- If e is logically 1 and e E Po we say that e is logically true.

We may now extend M to an interpretation of L as follows: DEFINITION 48. An expression e is logically 0 iff (not e) is logically 1.
DEFINITION 43. For all models <P, 2, M), m is an interpretation of L relative
It follows that for e E C, e is logically 0 iff for all m, m(e) =0TC' When e is
to (P, 2, M) iff m is a function from L into U{Tc: C E Cat} which satisfies
logically 0 and e EPo we say that e is logically false.
the following conditions: The reader may verify that in L, existent, exist, and every student be a
(i) for all e E Lex, m(e) = M(e) student are all logically 1. Their negations are all logically O.
(ii) for all X, Yin eATn, if el E XjY and e2 E Yi, 1 ~ i ~ n, then
m({el> e2}) =meed (m(ez)) DEFINITION 49. An expression e is logically trivial iff e is logically I or e
(iii) for all categories C, if el E C and e2 E C then is logically O. e is synthetic iff e is not logically trivial.
m({el, and, ez}) =meed /I m(ez) and
m({el' or, e2}) = meed v m(ez) and DEFINITION 50. For K ~ C and e E C, e is independent of K iff K f. e.
m({not, el}) = (m(ed)'. K is independent iff for all k E K, k is independent of K - {k}.

DEFINITION 44. m is an interpretation of L iff for some model (P, 2, M>,


m is an interpretation of L relative to <P, 2,M>. Advantages of the Generalized Entailment Relation

In terms of interpretations we may now define the fundamental semantic It is perhaps reasonable to query here just what the advantage of generalizing
relation, ~, called extensional inclusion, (= extensionally more informative the classical entailment relation is. Our purpose is only to show that in the
than) of which the classical entailment relation is but a special case. same way that the meanings of and, or, and not are not specific to sentence
meanings so entailment is not specific to sentence meanings. It is in essence
DEFINITION 45. For all categories C, all K <;;; C, and all e E C, K ~ e iff for just the boolean inclusion relation. Thus we have a direct way of expressing
all interpretations m of L, I\k E K m(k) ~ m(e). the intuitively felt relation between e.g. walk slowly and walk, sing and dance
and sing, etc. We feel however that the generalizations we have offered will
Notational remarks on Definition 45
have further utility. We suggest below a few possibilities for further thought,
(i) if K ~ e as per the above we say that K is (extensionally) included though none will be explored here in any detail.
ine. First, it is often taken as a truism of sorts that extensional inclusion is
(li) if K is a unit set {el }, we write el ~ e rather than {el} ~ e. the converse of intensional inclusion. Loosely, we may say that el is inten-
(iii) if C in Definition 45 is the category Po and K ~ e we say that sionally included in e2 if the meaning of el is 'part of' the meaning of e2 ,
K entails e and write K 1= e. i.e. if we know what e2 means then necessarily we know what el means. But
106 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 108 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Discussion of Definition 45 Note first that our definition of inclusion does the claim that the two inclusion relations are converses can easily be shown
in fact coincide with entailment when applied to sentences, i.e. elements of to be false, though many simple cases appear to support it. For example
Po. Thus if S is a sentence and K a set of sentences our definition says that walk is intensionally included in walk slowly, and indeed walk slowly is
K entails S iff A {m(k): k E K} 0:;;;; m(S), for all interpretations m of L. extensionally included in walk. Similarly sing is intensionally included in sing
Thus, given an arbitrary interpretation m, if all the sentences kinK are true and dance while sing and dance is extensionally included in sing. But it is
in m, that is, m(k) = I for all k E K, then Ak E K m(k) = I and thus m(S) also true that sing is intensionally included in sing or dance but not true that
must be 1. Thus to say that K entails S is just to say that S is true when- sing or dance is extensionally included in sing. Similarly, anticipating the
ever all the sentences in K are true. Of course if K is a unit set, say {T}, then addition of adjectives to L, it will turn out that a tall student is extensionally
Ak E K m(k) = A {meT)} = meT). Thus T entails S iff for all interpretations included in a student and intuitively a student is intensionally included in a
m, if meT) = 1 then m(S) = 1. tall student. But by parity of reasoning every student is intensionally included
But our definition of course is much more general than the classical one. in every tall student, but the converse does not obtain as regards extensional
It says that entailment among sentences is just the special case of boolean inclusion. In fact, every student is extensionally included in every tall student
inclusion. So the definition applies equally well to any expressions inter- (the set of properties which all students have in common is a subset of those
preted as elements of a given boolean algebra. For example it follows on our which the tall students have in common).
semantics that (sing and dance) 0:;;;; sing, kiss John and Mary 0:;;;; kiss John, some Second, and potentially much farther reaching, it seems to us likely that
but not all 0:;;;; some, sing 0:;;;; sing or dance, John 0:;;;; John or Mary, etc. and in the use of the boolean :s;;;; relation in all categories will be useful in formulating
the various extensions of L that we propose walk slowly 0:;;;; walk, tall student properly natural deductive systems - that is, systems which formalize logical
0:;;;; student, etc. reasoning in ordinary language. Consider for example the following crudely
As an exercise in our semantics we invite the reader to verify that the sets stated fIrst approximations to rules of inference on ordinary language (we use
of sentences in the a-examples below entail the corresponding b-sentence: d, d t , d 2 , etc. as variables ranging over P t and n, nt, n2, etc. as variables
ranging over N):
(45) a. John (kiss (no student))
Mary (be (a student))
b. John (not (kiss Mary))
(46) a. John «hug and kiss)) «some student) and (every teacher))),
Thus from Both John and Mary are linguists we may infer Mary is a linguist
Mary (be (a teacher))
since John and Mary :s;;;; Mary; and from no student sang we may infer no
b. John (hug Mary)
tall student sang since (see Section B) no student :s;;;; no tall student. Note
(47) a. (John or (every student)) spoke
that (49) is a sound rule since d is interpreted by a homomorphism and
Mary (be (a student))
for any homomorphism h we have hex) :s;;;; h(y) if x :s;;;; y. So in fact for
b. (John or Mary) spoke
dE Pk, any k > 1, we have that for all interpretations m, m(dnd = m(d)
(48) a. «not every) student) spoke
(m(nd) :s;;;; m(d) (m(n2)) = m(dn2) when mend :s;;;; m(n2)' But (49) only
b. (some student) (not spoke)
licenses inferring one sentence from another by replacing n I by n2, n I :s;;;; n2,
In standard logic a certain number of other semantic properties of expres- when n I is the subject of the sentence. (We may define n I to be the subject
sions are defined in terms of entailment. These are of course definable in our of of S E Po iff S = (nl d) for some d E PI)' If non-subjects are replaced
system and, like extensional inclusion, apply to all categories, not just Po. the inference in L is not generally valid. Thus (50a) below does not entail
Some examples follow: (SOb):

DEFINITION 46. For all categories e, all el , e2 E e, (50) a. No student kissed both John and Mary
el is logically equivalent (=) to e2 iff el 0:;;;; e2 and ez 0:;;;; el. b. 17'= No student kissed John
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 109 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 111

Of course, kiss (John and Mary) ..;; kiss John, but whether (n! (kiss (John Proofs of the Theorems
and Mary))) (nl kiss John) or not depends on whether nl is logically increas-
Here we sketch out those proofs which were not given explicitly in the
ing, decreasing, or neither. Formally,
text.
Our first proof is that of:
DEFINITION 51. For nl Eo N, nl is (logically) increasing iff for all inter-
pretations m, m(ndis illcreasing; n! is (logically) decreasing iff for all m,
m (n 1 ) IS decreasing.
By Temporary Definition 10, if x Eq, thenq Elx. Thus, q E nUx: x Eq}.
We may then posit, as first approximations, (51) and (52) as rules of inference: Again by Temporary Definition 10, if x 'f. q, then q 'f. Ix, whence q E (IS Thus,
q E n{(Ix)': x 'f. q}. We conclude that q E nUx: x E q} n n{(Ix)': x 'f. q},
(51) FromaPo (nddinfer(nd 2 )ifd!";;d2 andn is increasing. which is to say that {q} ~ nux: x E q} n n{(Ix)': x 'f. q}.
(52) From a Po (nd l ) infer (nd 2 ) if d 2 ..;; d l and n is decreasing. To prove the reverse inclusion, let r be an arbitrary member of u* such
that r is an element of n{Ix: x E q} n n{(Ix )': x 'f. q}. Thus, r E n{Ix:
Thus by (51) we may infer every student is either singing or dancing from xEq}andalsorEn{(Ix)':x'f.q}.
every student is singing, since sing";; sing or dance. And by (52) we may Now, let Ix 1 be an arbitrary individual (as defined in Temporary Defini-
infer no student is singing from no student is either singing or dancing. tion 10). Either Xl E q or else Xl 'f. q (but not both).
Space will not permit deeper consideration of the suggested rules of If Xl E q, then q Elxl' whence r EIxl . If Xl 'f. q, then r E (Ixl)" whence
inference above. We should only note that much more needs to be said r 'f. Ix 1 • In other words, the individuals which contain r as a member are
concerning the formulation of the proof language in expressions which precisely those which contain q as a member. By Temporary Definition 10,
are shown to bear the ..;; relation to each other. Nonetheless the examples the individual Ix 1 contains r as a member iff Xl E r. Thus, we conclude that
are suggestive enough, we think, to justify a certain optimism concerning the elements of r are precisely the elements of q; that is, r = q. Since r was an
the general use of ..;; in representing everyday reasoning in natural language. arbitrary member of nUx: x E q} n n{(Ix)': x 'f. q}, this proves this set is
included in {q}.

A Concluding Remark on Comparative Ontologies


Next, we have the following theorem about the ~ relation in any boolean
algebra:
It appears that an ontology for L, a pair <P, 2), is somewhat more complex
than the corresponding ontology (U, 2) for standard first order logic in that
THEOREM 2. For all x, y, z E H, H the domain of a boolean algebra,
both our primitives are required to be boolean algebras whereas in the standard
case only 2 is required to possess a boolean structure, U being an arbitrary (a) O~xandx~l
non-empty set. In fact, however, this judgment of relative complexity is (b) x ~x (Reflexivity)
somewhat spurious. We claim for example that the standard ontology is (c) ifx~yandy~xthenx=y (Antisymmetry)
actually more complex than ours, as it requires the existence of two rather (d) if x ~y and y ~ z then x ..;; z (Transitivity)
different primitives, one a boolean algebra, the other not; whereas our (e) (xl\y)~xand(xl\y)~y
approach is simpler since it requires the existence of two rather similar (f) x~(xvy)andy~(xvy)
primitives, complete and atomic boolean algebras in both cases. (g) if x ~ y and x ~ z then x ~ (y 1\ z)
To see that our claim is something more than a quibble over words, (h) ifx ~ z and y ~ z then (x v y) ~ z
consider that we may easily omit 2 as a primitive, limiting our primitives (i) x ~y iff (x 1\ y') = 0
thus to P = TN. To do this we simply define Tpo to be the set whose elements G) x~yiff(yvx)=y
110 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 112 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

are just the zero and unit of P, the boolean operations just being those of P (a) o!\X =(X 1\ X') 1\ X (Complement Law)
restricted to {Op, ip}. There will be no change in the arguments represented = (x 1\ x) 1\ x' (Commutative and Associative Law)
I
as valid or the sentences represented as logically true since the 'new' Tpo is =XI\X (Idempotent Law)
isomorphic to the old one. And now our ontology seems clearly simpler than =0 (Complement Law)
that of standard FOL since we have only one primitive and FOL has two,
neither of which can be reduced to the other. Note: this proof makes use of two laws which are not part of Defmition 9,
Whether we want in fact to simplify our ontology in this way however namely:
raises a host of non-trivial questions concerning the nature of 'truth values'
and their relation to common noun denotations. Notice that we did not Associative Law: for all x, y, z E B, B the domain of a boolean algebra,
justify 2 as the type for Po in the informal way in which we justified the
other types; we simply carried it over from standard FOL without change. X 1\(y 1\ z) =(x 1\ y) 1\ Z and
Can we in fact justify 2 as the type for Po? More specifically, what properties x v (y v z) = (x v y) v z
of Tpo have we used in our semantics, and are they sufficient to justify that
Tpo should be the minimal algebra 2? Idempotent Law: for all x E B, B the domain of a boolean algebra,
We have used the fact that Tpo is a boolean algebra in order to correctly
interpret conjunctions, disjunctions, and negations of sentences. Moreover (xl\x)=x and
we have used the fact that Tpo is complete and atomic in defining the types (xvx)=x
for the other Pn's, in particular the PI'S. If Tpo were not both complete
and atomic the Justification Theorem would not apply and we could not These can be proved from the axioms in Definition 9. We omit the proofs
define PI interpretations merely by giving their values on the individuals, here, but the interested reader can find them in Mendelson (1970), pp.
so the logic would not be a first order extensional one. 52-58.
But can we justify that Tpo should specifically be the algebra 2 rather than The fact that x ,.;;; 1 follows directly from Definition 12 and the Law of
an arbitrary complete and atomic algebra? The answer is no. No further the unit (Definition 9(e)).
properties of Tpo have been assumed in our treatment. Hence we should take
Tpo to merely be an arbitrary ca-algebra. And relaxing our requirement that (b) This follows directly from Definition 12 and the Idempotent
Tpo be specifically the algebra 2 no changes in which arguments are deter- Law.
mined to be valid ensues. So the weaker ontology is as adequate as the one (c) x ,.;;; y implies x 1\ y = x, and y ,.;;; x implies y 1\ x =y.
we took; by Occam's Razor, it should be chosen.
It is worth noting however that being a ca-algebra does impose cardinality By the Commutative Law, y !\ X =x !\ y. Thusy =y !\ x =x !\ Y = x.
constraints on the choice of Tpo' Such algebras as we have seen are isomorphic We omit the proofs of the remaining parts, which are equally mechanical
to, and hence of the same cardinality as, power set algebras, whence they (if somewhat longer, in a few cases). However, the follOwing additional
must have 2k elements for some cardinal k. So we cannot use a three valued, lemma should be noted, since it comes in handy in many situations:
or a five valued logic, or even an a valued logic, as they are not cardinality
2k for any cardinal k. Complement Flip Law: For all x, y EB, B the domain of a boolean algebra,
It is also worth noting that standard approaches to intensional logic take if x ";;;y theny' ";;;X'.
'[Po as F2/W, the set of functions from an arbitrary non-empty set W of
'possible worlds' into 2. As this set is isomorphic to W* and W is arbitrary For, if x ";;;y, we have x 1\ y = x (Definition 12), whence x' = x'v y' (De-
this amounts to taking Tpo as an arbitrary complete and atomic algebra, Morgan Law), so y' ,.;;; x' by part U) of Theorem 2. Here we have made
by Theorem 6. use of:
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 113 THE SEMANTICS FOR L 115

DeMorgan Laws: For all x, y E B, B the domain of a boolean algebra, y = 0 or y = x. Since z = iCY), this means that z = 0 or z = i(x). Thus, i(x)
is an atom.
(x II y)' = x'v y' and If x E is arbitrary and i(x) is an atom, then, by what we have just proved,
(xv y)' =x' II y'. x =i-I (i(x)) is an atom.
(d) Let us use the notation i(K) = {i(k): k E K}. If I\K exists, then by
Again, these can be proved directly from the axioms in Definition 9. part (b) i( I\K) is a lower bound for i(K). If z ED is a lower bound for i(K),
then, again by part (b), i-I (z) is a lower bound for K, whence i-I (z) <
THEOREM 3. For x, y elements of an arbitrary algebra B, (x II y) is the glb I\K. But this means that z =i(i-l (z)) < i( I\K). Thus, i( I\K) is the glb of
for {x, y} and (x v y) is the lub for {x, y}. i(K). Similarly i(VK) is the lub of i(K).

By Theorem 2(e), (x II y) is a lower bound for {x, y}. If z is a lower bound We need not prove Theorem 8, since that theorem is just a special case
for {x, y}, then z .;;;; x 1\ y by Theorem 2(g). Thus, (x 1\ y) is the glb for of Theorem 6.
{x, y}. The proof that (x v y) is the lub for {x, y} is similar. Half of Theorem 9 is proved in the text. Here we give the other half.
Namely, we prove that if b E TN is an atom, then lb satisfies the Meets,
THEOREM 4. Let B be an arbitrary algebra and b be an atom in B. Then Joins, and Complement Conditions.
Given K ~ TN. If K ~ lb, then b is a lower bound for K, whence b < I\K,
(a) ForallxEB,either(bllx)=Oor(bl\x)=b. that is, I\K E lb. Conversely, if I\K E lb, then b < I\K, whence b is a lower
(b) For all x EB, either b';;;;x or b ';;;;x' but not both. bound for K, so that K ~ lb. Thus, lb satisfies the Meets Condition.
(c) For all c EB, if c is an atom of Band c f b then (b 1\ c) = o. If K () lb =!= f/J, then there is at least one k E K such that b < k. Thus,
b < VK, whence VK E lb. Conversely, if VK E lb, that is if b < VK, then
(a) Since b II x .;;;; b (by Theorem 2(e», this follows directly from Defini- b = b 1\ (VK) = V k E K (b 1\ k); since b =!= 0 and b 1\ k =b or 0, we must have
tion 16(a). b 1\ k = b for at least one k E K. This k is an element of K () lb. Thus,lb
(b) If b';;;; x and b .;;;; x', then b .;;;; x 1\ x' (Theorem 2(g», whence b .;;;; 0 satisfies the Joins Condition.
(Complement Law), and hence (since 0 .;;;; b by Theorem 2(a» b = 0, con- Finally, p E lb iff b < p iff b 1. p' iff p' €f:. lb, so lb satisfies the Com-
tradicting Defmition 16(a). If b 4,x, then b 1\ x f b, whence b 1\ x = 0 by (a). plements Condition.
But then b ';;;;x' by Theorem 2(i) (since x" = x).
(c) If band c are both atoms and b II C f 0, then b II c = b (by (a» and also Theorems 10 and 11 are proved in the text. Theorem 12 is straightforward
b 1\ C =c (by (a», so b =c. and left to the reader to check. The reader should see Keenan and Stavi
(1981) for Theorems 13, 14, and 15.
The proof of Theorem 5 is sketched in the text, as is the proof of Theo- The reader can easily check that the proof given above for Theorem 7(a)
rem 6. However, we give here the details of the proof that any complete and the first part of the proof given for Theorem 7(b) constitute proofs of
atomic algebra B is isomorphic to the power set (AB)*, where AB is the set the two parts of Theorem 16.
of atoms of B. Recall that a function r- B -+ (AB)* is defined by setting Theorem 17 is proved in the text.
f(x) = {b E AB: b .;;;; x} for each x E B. We show thatfis an isomorphism. We have next:
First, f is one-to-one. For let x, y E B with x f y. By Theorem 2(c), we
°
cannot have both x .;;;; y and y .;;;; x. Say x 4, y. Then x 1\ y' f (by Theorem
2(i». If b is an atom such that b';;;;x 1\ y', then b';;;;x (whence b Ef(x» and
THEOREM 18. Fp = H2/P*
Fp and H2/P* are both subsets of F2!P*. We prove the theorem by proving
b ';;;;y', so that (Theorem 4(b» b 4,y (whence b ~f(Y». Thusf(x) f f(Y). the two inclusions Fp r:::: H2!P* and H2/P* r:::: Fp.
Next,! is onto. For, let K E (AB)* be arbitrary. Define x = UK; we show To prove the first inclusion, we need only prove that an arbitrary fp is a
that f(x) = K. homomorphism.
114 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 116 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

If b EK, then b ~ UK = x, so b E[(x). Thus, K ~f(x). To show that t p preserves meets, let {QaJ be a (possibly infinite) set
If b Ef(x), then b ~ x = UK. Now, we must have b EK; for otherwise,
°
b = b 1\ X = b 1\ (UK) = Ub o E K {b 1\ b o} = by Theorem 4(c), contra-
dicting the fact that b is an atom. Thus,f(x) ~ K, whence [(x) =K.
of subsets of P. Then tp(n", Q",) = 1 iff pEn", Q", iff 'V'" p E Q", iff
'V'" tp(QoJ = 1 iff A", tp(Q",) = 1. ThustpCn", Q",,) = /\01. tpCQ",,). The proofs
that tp preserves joins and complements are equally straightforward.
We have shown that fis a one-to-one mapping of B onto (AB)*. We now To prove the second inclusion, given any h E H2/P*, we must show that
show that [preserves meets, joins, and complements. h =[Ph for some Ph EP. Define Ph by the condition that Ph EJ iff h(!) =1,
For x, y E B, we have b E f(x 1\ y) iff b ~ x 1\ y iff b ~ x and b ~ Y for any individual J; by Corollary 2 to Theorem 11, this is a proper definition
(Theorem lee) and leg»~ iff b Ef(x) nf(y). Thus,fpreserves meets. The of a unique element of P. Now, h = tp h; for, by the first part of the proof,
proof that f preserves joins is similar. Finally, b E f(x') iff b ~ x I iff b 1:. x tPh is a homomorphism, and by the defmition of Ph, h and[Ph take the same
(Theorem 4(b» iff b tf. f(x) iff b E (f(x»' , so f preserves complements. This values on the individuals (tp h (I) = 1 iff Ph E I iff h (1) = 1), so the Justifi-
shows thatfis an isomorphism. cation Theorem can be applied.

THEOREM 7. Let i be an isomorphism from B onto D. Then, Sketches for the proofs of Theorems 19, 20, 21, and 23 are given in the
text; we leave it to the reader to fill in the details. We omit the proof of
Theorem 22, which is a straightforward induction.
(a) i(OB) = 0D and i(1B) = lD.
(b) x ~ y iffi(x) ~D iCy).
(c) x is an atom of B iffi(x) is an atom of D. NOTES
(d) i preserves unbounded meets and joins, i.e. for K ~ B, i(I\K) = ! Treating PP's this way leads to many cases of multiple analysis. Thus, the English
I\{i(k): k E K} and i(VK) = V{i(k): k E K} where these equa- sentence John found Mary in the garden can be analyzed either as (i):
tions are interpreted to mean that if the meet GOin) on the left (i) John «find Mary) (in the garden))
exists, (i.e. if K has a glb (lub) in B), then the meet Goin) on the
right exists and the equation holds. in which in the garden functions as a member of category pdp!, or as (ii):
(e) the function i- 1 fromD into B defined by i- 1 (d) = b iffi(b) =d (li) John «find (in the garden)) (Mary))
is an isomorphism from D onto B.
in which in the garden functions as a P2/P2' In general, we will claim that these multiple
possibilities are welcome; see Section I.B3.
(a) Given any x E B, since 0B = x /\ x', we have i(OB) = i(x /\ x') = 2 For example, we might define PEV = Uo .;; n .;; w Vn , where Vn are defined induc-
i(x) /\ i(X') = i(x) /\ (i(x»' = 0D. The proof that i(lB) = ID is similar. tively for all natural numbers n as follows:
Next we skip to
(i) Vo =df Vand (li) Vn+l =df Vn U (Vn)*.
(e) Since i: B -+ D is one-to·one and onto, i-I is a well-defined function
from D into B which is also one-to-one and onto. Now, i-I preserves meets, 3 But recall that there is no linear order among constituents of expressions in L, whereas
for, given w, z ED, there exist unique x, y EB such that i(x) = wand iCy) =z. such order does exist for constituents of English phrases. Thus, order is one respect in
which the L-representation of an English expression is not isomorphic to that expression_
Then i-I (w /\ z) = i-I (i(x) /\ iCy»~ = i-I (i(x /\y» = x /\ Y = i-I (w) /\ i-I (z).
4 It is easy to show that any boolean algebra whose domain has exactly two elements
Similarly, i-I preserves joins and complements. must be isomorphic to 2 (see below, Definition 18, for a discussion of the notion of
Now back to: isomorphism). Briefly, by condition (a) of Defmition 18, if B has exactly two elements,
(b) If x ~B y, then x /\ y = x, whence i(x) /\ iCy) = i(x /\ y) = i(x), so these elements must be the zero and the unit. It is then relatively straightforward to
that i(x) ~D iCy). If i(x) ~D iCy), then by what we have just proved, prove, on the basis of the remaining conditions, that the meet, join, and complement
operations applied to various combinations of these two elements must agree with the
i-I (i(x» ~B i-I (i(y», that is, x ~B y. corresponding truth functions.
(c) Let x be an atom of B. Then i(x) =F 0D, for otherwise i-I (i(x» = 5 The intersection of the sets X and Y is the set of all those elements which are mem-
x = 0B. Moreover, if z ~ i(x), then lety = i-I (z). By part (b),y ~x, whence bers of both X and Y. The union of the sets X and Y is the set of all those elements each
THE SEMANTICS FOR L 117 MODIFIERS 119

of which is a member either of X or of Y (or both). If X is a subset of S, the complement language L whose expressions are intended to represent attributive adjectives
of X relative to S is the set of all those elements of S which are not elements of X. in English, as well as certain complex expressions, such as relative clauses,
In general, we assume that the reader is familiar with these set-theoretic operations
which function as attributive-adjective-like modifiers. The lexical members
and with their properties.
6 This development is not usually followed in standard presentations of FOL, which
of this category will ultimately consist of the full range of English adjectives
only allow and, or, and not to combine with formulas. However, the boolean character which can be used attributively, such as tall, female, skillful, good, fake,
of U* does allow the direct interpretation of boolean combinations of PI'S even in FOL, alleged, etc., although we shall see that rather many of these are properly
and so we thought to mention it here, anticipating the general approach we will be intensional, and hence will not be able to be dealt with by means of the
following in defining the semantic system for L.
constructions to be presented in this section.
7 Suppose that m E' B is a least element with respect to the ordering <:;;. Then m <:;; O.
But, by Theorem 2a,0 .;; m, whence m = 0, by Theorem 2c. The proof that 1 is the only Syntactically, APs combine with Ns (common noun phrases) to form
maximal element is done analogously. expressions which themselves are Ns. Thus, for example, the lexical AP tall
8 Note that an atom b in an algebra is .;; join of elements iff it is .;; one of the elements can be combined with the N student to form the expression tall student.
over which the join is taken. Formally , for b an atom in B, K ~ B, b .;; VK iff for some Semantically, it is reasonable that the (extensional) denotation of this expres-
kE'K,b';;k. sion should be a property, just as the denotation of student is. Syntactically,
tall student should be combinable with determiners to form noun phrases
such as every tall student, a tall student, no tall student, or the tall student.
We therefore regard the expression tall student as a N, and take tall to be of
category N/N.
Since AP (= N/N) is a slash category, the denotation of an AP will be
some function from T.1If into TN, that is, from Pinto P. The type TAP of
the category AP will therefore be some subset of the set Fp/p of all such
functions. In order to determine which subset of Fp/p should be taken to
be TAP, we must examine the adjectives more closely. Traditionally, as well
as in the recent logical literature, a variety of subclasses of adjectives are
distinguished on intuitive semantic grounds. We shall begin by discussing
several such classes informally to see what properties we want the functions
which interpret them to have. We will then define a number of subcategories
for the major category AP of our logical language which will correspond to
certain of the subclasses of English adjectives we will have discussed. Each
of these subcategories will have its own subset of Fp/p as it type; the type
for the major category AP will then be the union of the types for all the
subcategories.
Let us first consider the scalar adjectives. Very roughly and intuitively,
the semantics of such adjectives involves the notion that an individual which
has the property denoted by an N which is composed of such an adjective
and another N is at the extreme of some imagined scale of values. Examples
of scalar adjectives are adjectives denoting size, such as large, tall, short, wide;
many value-judgment adjectives, such as good, bad, smart, beautiful; and
manner adjectives, such as rapid, slow, clumsy, skillful; the manner adjectives
perhaps all have a value judgment component.
120 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Scalar adjectives can compare: taller than, smarter than, more beautiful
PART 1: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC than; there are also equality comparison forms which these adjectives enter
B. Extending the Core Language into, such as as tall as, as well as negative comparative forms like less tall
than. Scalar adjectives also have intensive forms: very tall, very good, etc.
An important logical property of scalar adjectives which we will have
occasion to refer to in a number of different contexts is the property of
In this section we present a variety of ways in which the syntax of L can be being restrictive. This means that an individual which, for example, has the
enriched so as to represent a significantly larger fragment of English. Broadly property denoted by tall student, necessarily has the property denoted by
speaking L is enriched in two sorts of ways: We add new lexical items in student. We can give a general definition of the notion of being restrictive
heretofore empty categories, and we add new operators forming derived by considering the function r p ...,. P which would interpret a restrictive
expressions in new ways. adjective. To say that f is restrictive simply means that, for any property
Among the lexical additions we enrich L to include new Modifiers and p, if an arbitrary individual has the property f(p), then that individual must
new Predicatives. Among the Modifiers we now have expressions like tall, have the property p. Examining the statement of Theorem 11 of Section
female, etc. of category N/N or Adjective Phrase; and secondly we add a A, we see that the notion of restrictiveness can be defined very simply as
variety of Predicate Modifiers (of category Pn/Pn , for each n ~ 1) such as follows:
here, in the garden, etc. Among the Predicatives we add a variety of expres-
sions which combine with full NP's to form expressions in already existing DEFINITION 1. Let f E Fp/p be arbitrary. Then f is restricting iff for each
(non-empty) categories. These include 'transitive' common nouns like friend pEP,f(p)<p.
(of), colleague (of), etc., 'transitive' adjective phrases like fond (of), jealous
(of), etc., ditransitive verb phrases such as give, show, etc., and Prepusitions Theorem 11 then guarantees us that for f restricting, any individual with
such as in, on, etc. f(p) is of necessity an individual with p.
Of the new ways of forming derived expressions from simpler ones we It will be noticed that the simplicity of Definition 1 is made possible by
add: (1) the's which forms Determiners from full NP's; (2) some valency the fact that P is a boolean algebra, and hence has a relation < defined
affecting operators such as Passive which forms Pn's from Pn+l 's; and (3) on it. It will be useful later to have a more general notion of restricting
several variable binding operators, ones which form relative clauses and function. As modifiers are always interpreted as functions from a boolean
reflexives in addition a generalized lambda operator. algebra into itself, we may define the notion of restrictiveness for any such
function exactly as we did for functions from Pinto P, as follows:
1. MODIFIERS
DEFINITION 2. Let B be a boolean algebra, and let f E FB/B be arbitrary.
In general an expression will be called a modifier if its category is C/C for Then f is restricting iff for each x E B, f( x) < x.
some category C, and the category C/C itself will be called a modifier cate-
gory. So modifiers form C's from C's, for various choices of C. There are no Since scalar adjectives are restricting, it is clear that if a scalar adjective is
modifiers in the core language L, but in the extensions of L proposed below to be interpreted by a function from Pinto P, then that function must be
we add expressions to the category N/N or Adjective Phrase and we add a restricting function, in the sense of Definition 1. But can scalar adjectives
expressions to the category Pn/Pn or Predicate Modifiers. be interpreted by functions from Pinto P? In many cases, and perhaps in
most cases, the answer is no. To see this, suppose that the adjective severe
were to be interpreted as a function from Pinto P. Then, in any model in
Adjective Phrases
which, say, parent and teacher happened to be interpreted as the same
The category N/N of Adjective Phrases (APs) is a new category in our logical (extensional) property (which means that, in that model, the parents and

118
MODIFIERS 121 MODIFIERS 123

the teachers were the same individuals), the expressions severe parent The sense in which an intersecting adjective determines a property can
and severe teacher would be interpreted as the same property. But this be described as follows. If Dana is a female student and if Dana is also an
is cleary false. If, for example, the individual John is the only parent and athlete, then Dana is a female athlete. More generally, what female attributes
also the only teacher, we certainly want to allow for the possibility that to Dana in the formula Dana is a female e is independent of the choice of the
John might be a severe parent but a lax teacher. Thus, even though parent common noun e. This is in striking contrast to the scalar adjectives: if Dana
and teacher are interpreted as the same property, severe parent and severe is both a jockey and a basketball player and if Dana is a tall jockey, it is not
teacher should not have to be. We conclude that the interpretation of severe necessarily the case that Dana is a tall basketball player.
cannot be a function from Pinto P. Analogous arguments can be constructed Another way of describing the intersecting character of an adjective like
for most scalar adjectives. female is to note that, for example, to be a female student means exactly
Let us say that an adjective is transparent if it can be represented as a the same as to be a female existent (individual) and also a student. Thus, the
function from Pinto P. What we have just said can then be rephrased by set of individuals who are female students is the intersection of the set of
saying that most scalar adjectives are not transparent. This means that such individuals who are students with the set of individuals who are female
adjectives cannot be represented in our logical system as it has been devel- existents, hence the term intersecting adjective. Alternatively, we can say
oped so far. In fact, the non transparency of most scalar adjectives is one that the property which interprets female student is the meet (in P) of the
serious motivation for extending our logic to an intensional one. When we property which interprets student with the property which interprets female
do so, we will see that scalar adjectives can be represented, and that the existent. Viewed this way, it is easy to give a characterization of the kind of
functions which interpret them are restricting, but in the more general sense function which is needed to interpret an intersecting adjective:
of Definition 2.
It may be the case that the best analysis would have all scalar adjectives DEFINITION 4. Let f E Fp/p be arbitrary. Then f is intersecting iff for
nontransparent. However, it seems to us that adjectives of physical size like eachp EP, f(p) = p II f(l).
tall, short, wide, narrow, etc. are actually transparent scalar adjectives. For
example, in a model in which the doctors and the teachers are the same (Of course, the symbol] refers to the unit element in P; recall that existent
individuals, if John is a tall doctor, it seems necessarily the case that John is a logical constant which is always interpreted as 1.)
is a tall teacher, and vice versa. This is clear if we think of the process of As in the case of the notion restricting, the above definition for the notion
determining whether a given individual I has the tall doctor property as one intersection can be generalized to the case of a function from any boolean
of comparing the height of I with the heights of all the individuals which algebra B into itself. We give the general definition, which will be applicable
have the doctor property and seeing if the height of I is in some sense sub- to other modifiers.
stantially greater than the average height of these individuals. If such a
DEFINITION 5. Let B be a boolean algebra and let fE FBIB be arbitrary.
process is followed, then whether an individual has the tall doctor property
Thenfis intersecting iff for each x EB, f(x) = x II f(1).
or not depends on a physical property of the set of individuals which have
the doctor property. Thus, if doctor and teacher happened to be interpreted (Here, ] is the unit element in B.)
as the same extensional property, then this process of checking an individual The following theorem is immediate:
for the tall doctor property would necessarily lead to the same answer as
checking that individual for the tall teacher property. But this means that THEOREM 1. For B a boolean algebra andfEFB/B, iffis intersecting then
the interpretation of tall depends only on the extensional denotation of the f is restricting.
N with which it is combined; that is, tall can be interpreted as a function Proof. Let f as above be intersecting. We must show that for all b E B,
from Pinto P. In other words, tall is transparent. f(b) .;;; b. Since f is intersecting we know that f(b) = b f\ f(l). By Theorem
On the other hand, objections have been cited to this argument. For 2e, Section A we have that (b f\ x) .;;; b, x any element of the algebra. Thus
example, it might be argued that in a model in which the jockeys and the f( b) .;;; b, so f is restricting.
122 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 124 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

basketball players were the same individuals, a given individual could be a We may now add intersecting APs to our language as follows: The feature i
short basketball player but not a short jockey. While our judgments here are (for intersection) is added to SFL and expressions like male, female, Albanian,
not certain, our feeling is that there is a confusion here between the idea etc. are added to the basic vocabulary and assigned by lexical rule to the
of being a tall jockey and of being tall for a jockey. In a model in which there subcategory AP. We specify that the type for this subcategory be the set of
I
are neither jockeys nor basketball players (so the sets of individuals which all intersecting functions from Pinto P:
have the properties which interpret jockey and basketball player are trivially
the same), an individual could surely be tall for a jockey but not tall for a DEFINITION 6. TAP = {jEFp/p: fis intersecting}.
i
basketball player. It also seems reasonable that we would want to say of an
individual in some world that he was a tall jockey but not tall for a jockey We will have more to say about the scalar and the intersecting adjectives, but
(that is, he is well within the height limits we expect jockeys to have, but first we want to briefly consider two other classes of adjectives.
he is still taller than most jockeys, and hence a tall jockey). Thus, being a In Montague (1973) it was pointed out that there exist adjectives which
tall jockey and being tall for a jockey are perhaps independent properties. are not restricting. Among these is the class of negative adjectives, which
If this is so, it seems reasonable to regard tall as transparent, that is, as having includes fake, bogus, phony, and perhaps ungrammatical, false. That these
an extensionally definable interpretation. adjectives are not restricting is seen by noting that, for example, a fake gun
Another argument that tall is transparent, as opposed to most scalar need not be a gun. That these adjectives are negative is seen by noting that
adjectives like, say smart, is provided by the transparency of the APs created a fake gun cannot be a gun, or at least, it cannot be a real gun. Similarly,
by their comparative forms. Namely, if John is a taller doctor than Bill, and an ungrammatical sentence is, possibly, not a sentence, nor is a false theorem
if John and Bill are both lawyers as well as doctors, then John is a taller a theorem.
lawyer than Bill. However, if John is a smarter doctor than Bill, and if John We are tempted to say that a negative adjective should be interpreted by
and Bill are both lawyers as well as doctors, we cannot necessarily conclude a function f which is required to satisfy the condition that f(p) .;;;; p' for all
that John is a smarter lawyer than Bill. properties p. This would guarantee that, say, an individual which had the
For these reasons, we tentatively propose that the category AP in our property which interprets fake doctor would also have the complement of
extensional language does contain lexical items like tall, wide, etc. Since the property which interprets doctor, so that that individual would not have
these are all restricting adjectives, we enrich SFL, the subcategorization the doctor property.
features for L, to include the feature r (for restricting); then, the above However, closer examination shows that the functions which interpret
lexical items are all in the subcategory AP. Moreover, let us specify that negative adjectives cannot be transparent; that is, a negative adjective cannot
r
the type for this subcategory be the set of all restricting functions from P be interpreted by a function from Pinto P. For example, suppose that in
into P: some model gun and diamond are both interpreted as 0 (that is, no individual
has the gun property and no individual has the diamond property). If fake
DEFINITION 3: TAP = {fEFp/p: fis restricting} were interpreted by a transparent function, then, since gun and diamond
r
have the same (extensional) interpretation, it would be the case that fake gun
The next subclass of adjectives we want to discuss are the intersecting adjec- and fake diamond would be interpreted by the same property. But this is
tives. Roughly, these are the adjectives which by themselves determine a clearly counter to what we want. There might be, for example, no fake guns
property independent of the N with which they are combined. Among the but many fake diamonds in the model under consideration, even if there
adjectives usually regarded as intersecting are male and female; nationality are no real guns and no real diamonds. Whether an individual has the fake
adjectives, such as Albanian, Ugandan, etc.; color adjectives, such as blue, gun property or not simply has nothing to do with whether there are any
aquamarine, etc.; shape adjectives, such as square, rectangular, etc.; and individuals with the (real) gun property or not. For this reason,fake (and the
certain social class adjectives like RepUblican, Communist, etc. In addition, all other negative adjectives) will be interpreted by a properly intensional, that
relative clauses fall into this subclass; but we will discuss these much later. is, non-transparent, function.
MODIFIERS 125 MODIFIERS 127

There is another class of nonrestricting adjectives, which we term con- The reverse entailment, of course, is false. The reader may easily construct
jectural adjectives. These are adjectives whose semantic effect is to indicate a model in which John (kiss (a student» is true but John (kiss (a (tall stu-
that the individual is merely considered, hypothesized, or conjectured, etc. dent») is false (for example, take a model in which there are exactly two
to have the property denoted by the N with which it is combined. Examples students, say, Betty and Sally, with only Betty being a tall student, and with
of such adjectives are ostensible, alleged, apparent, possible, likely. These John kissing Sally but not Betty). The statements in (2) and (3) below can
adjectives are not restricting, since, for example, an alleged thief is not also be shown to hold based on what we have done so far; the reader is
necessarily a thief. However, they are also not negative, since an alleged thief invited to prove these statements as an exercise.
is not necessarily a non-thief. (2) John (kiss (every student)) entails John (kiss (every (tall stu-
Like the negative adjectives, the conjectural adjectives are not transparent.
dent))),
Thus, in a model in which thief and murderer are interpreted as the same
(extensional) property, so that the thieves and the murderers are the same but the reverse entailment does not hold.
individuals, it still does not follow that the alleged thieves and the alleged (3) (Mary (be (an (Albanian doctor»)) and (Mary (be (a lawyer))
murderers are the same individuals. entails Mary (be (an (Albanian lawyer»).
It seems clear, however, that there is a semantic connection between any
given conjectural adjective and some 'sentence operator'. Thus, a possible If the only adjective phrases we needed to deal with consisted of single
millionnaire is a person for whom it is the case that it is possible that he/she lexical adjectives which occurred only in combination with Ns to form Ns,
is a millionnaire; an alleged thief is a person who has been alleged to be a this would complete our study of them, at least as far as the extensional
thief. language is concerned. However, if our language is to have anything like the
When we come to discuss our intensional language, negative adjectives and richness of real English, we have to consider complex APs, as well as APs
conjectural adjectives will be members of subcategories AP and AP, respec- occurring in situations other than combined with Ns. We proceed to consider
n c several extensions along these two lines now.
tively, with appropriately defined types. For now, we do not discuss these
adjectives any further. We begin by noting that adjectives can combine with the syncategorematic
Returning to the extensional language, we see that we have added a new expressions and, or, and not to form complex APs. This is particularly clear in
major category AP, with two subcategories, namely 1).P and A'p. Actually, the case of scalar adjectives: a tall and heavy student, a tall or heavy student,
I a tall but not heavy student. In the case of intersecting adjectives, conjunc-
since all transparent adjectives appear to be restricting, we do not need to
tions are typically odd: ?a male and Communist student, while disjunctions
define a subcategory AP for the extensional language; we can simply regard
r are often acceptable: a Communist or Socialist student. Moreover, not can
the non-intersecting adjectives as members of AP, and define the type of AP
often combine with an intersecting adjective in the special form non-: a
as being the set of all restricting functions from Pinto P. Of course, in the non-Communist student. We also· note that combinations of a scalar with
intensional language, there will be many members of AP that are not restrict- an intersecting adjective tend to be odd: ?a tall and Communist student, ?a
ing, as we have seen, so that APwill be a proper subcategory. tall or Communist student. However, it is important to keep in mind that
r
We have also given the type for our two subcategories. With what we all of the odd combinations involving adjectives and the syncategorematic
have done so far, we can show, for example, that John kissed a tall student expressions are nevertheless easily interpretable. Our approach here will be to
entails that John kissed a student. To do so, we first calculate the inter- allow all such combinations to be formed and interpreted. We will then have
pretation of John kissed a tall student in our system, as follows: something to say concerning the oddness of some of the combinations.
To allow for the construction of these combinations, we need only declare
that AP is a boolean category. (Non-restricting adjectives strongly resist
r
combining with and, or, and not; we will discuss this later.) To provide for
interpretations of boolean combinations of adjectives, we have to define
126 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 128 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

(1) John kissed a tall student operations on the set TAP which will turn that set into a boolean algebra.
(a) John (kiss (a (tall student))) The proper way to do thls will become clear by considering the meanings
of Ns which contain boolean combinations of adjectives.
(b)
(c) kLa~~, It is clear, for example, that an individual which has the property which
interprets tall and heavy student must have the property which interprets
tall student and also the property which interprets heavy student. Moreover,
(d) a(t(s))
the converse holds also: if an individual has the properties which interpret
(e) = U
t(s) E I
I tall student and heavy student respectively. then we certainly would want
that individual to have the property which interprets tall and heavy student.
(f) k(t(S)~ I I) By virtue of this, we would like to make the following definition:
(g) (k(t(S)~ II))(Ij) DEFINITION 7. Let f, g E TAP be arbitrary. Then f /\ g is defined by setting
r
(h) = (t(S)VE I k(/)) (Ij) (j /\ g) (P) =f(P) /\ g(p) for eachp EP.

(i) = t(S)VE I (k(I)) (Ij). It is clear that by this definition f /\ g is a function from Pinto P. However,
in order to be a member of TAP, it is also necessary that f /\ g be restricting,
r
We leave it to the reader to provide the justification of each step. A similar that is, that (j /\ g) (P) , ;;;;, p for all p. But (j /\ g) (P) = f(P) /\ g(p) ";;;;'f(P)·
analysis of John kissed a student, which we represent in our language by the Since f(p) , ;;;;, p (since f is restricting), we conclude that (f II g) (p) , ;;;;, p,
formula John (kiss (a student)), shows that this is interpreted as whence the function (f II g) is restricting.
V (k(/))(Ij). We leave it to the reader to formulate the arguments which motivate
sEI the following definition for the operation v in TAP:
r
To show that John (kiss (a (tall student))) entails John (kiss (a student)),
we have to show that in any model in which DEFINITION 8. Let f, g E TAP be arbitrary. Thenfv g is defined by setting
r
(jv g) (P) = f(P) V g(p) for eachp EP.
t(S)VE I (k(f)) (Ij) = 1,
The argument that f V g is restricting is slightly different. Since f(P) , ;;;;, p and
it is necessarily the case that
g(p) , ;;;;, p (since f and g are restricting), we have that f(P) V g(p) , ;;;;, p, by
s ~ I (k(I))(Ij) = 1. Theorem (2h) of Section A, and hence (jv g) (P) , ;;;;, p.
We have yet to define an operation I in TAP. On the basis of the two
Suppose, then, that the first of these two equations is true in some model. r
definitions above, it might seem that the appropriate definition would be that
Then it is the case that there exists an individual I which contains the prop- f' is defined by the equation f' (p) = (f(p))' . However, f' defined this way
erty t(s) such that (k(/)) (Ij) = 1. Now, since tall is a member of the category would not be restricting. This is most easily seen by assuming that P is a
AP, t is a restricting function, so we conclude that t(s) :s;;; s. Since I is an power set algebra, so that 'properties' are sets and";;;;' is the subset relation.
r
individual, we can apply Theorem 13(ii) of Section A to conclude that s E I. Then, if f(p) is a proper subset of p, (f(p))' would contain all the elements
Thus, we have shown that there is an individual I containing the property s of p', together with those elements of p which are not in f(p); this is clearly
such that (k(/)) (Ij) = 1. But this is just the condition necessary and sufficient not a subset of p. More generally, for any algebra P, if f(P) , ;;;;, p, then
for the second equation above to hold. That is, whenever the first equation p' , ;;;;, (j(P))', by Theorem (2k) of Section A. Thus, we cannot have (f(P))''';;;;'p
holds for some model, the second one must hold also, which proves the in general, since this would mean that p' , ;;;;, p, that is, that P'li p = p', whence
entailment. p'=O,orp=l.
MODIFIERS 129 MODIFIERS 131

The way out is easily seen by examining the meaning of a phrase like (not Among other things, this theorem tells us that an intersecting adjective
tall) student (say, as in a heavy but not tall student). An individual has the determines a property; in fact, the intersecting adjective function [ deter-
property denoted by this N if and only if that individual has the student mines the property [(1). Thus, for example, the adjective Albanian determines
property, but does not have the tall student property. The correct definition the property associated with the common noun phrase Albanian existent.
is therefore the following: The fact that an intersecting adjective determines a property correlates
with the fact that intersecting adjectives appear to be more common-noun-like
DEFINITION 9. Let f E TAP be arbitrary. Then / is defined by setting than scalar adjectives. Thus, intersecting adjectives can often be used as
/(P) = p 1\ (f(P))' for eachp EP. common nouns: two males, an Albanian, every Communist, no square, etc.
Similarly, intersection adjectives, like common nouns, are negatable by non-:
It is clear by Theorem 2e of Section A that f' defined this way is restricting.
non-Albanian (cf. non-student).
Now, it happens that under the operations II, v, and' defined above,
As in the case of our earlier definitions and theorems, Theorem 4 can be
TAP is a boolean algebra. While not completely obvious, this fact is easy to
r generalized to a statement that any boolean algebra B is isomorphic to IB / B ;
prove. We leave the proof to the reader, noting here only the following. The the formal statement and proof will be found in the section at the end of
zero element of TAP is the function which maps every property onto the this chapter.
r
zero property; we may write this as O(p) = 0 for every pEP, if we understand We pointed out earlier that intersecting adjectives sound odd when con-
the first 0 to refer to the zero element of the type for restricting adjectives, joined with and although they combine acceptably with or and with not
and the second 0 to refer to the zero property. And, the unit element of TAP (usually in the form non-). The following theorem sheds some light on this:
r
is the function which maps each property into itself; that is, 1(p) = p. Readers
not wishing to bother proving that TAP is a boolean algebra may note that THEOREM 5. Let f, g E TAP be arbitrary. The, for eachp EP, ([II g)(p) =
r
this fact follows from the more general theorem to be discussed momentarily. [(g(p)) =g(f(p)). i

We saw earlier that the notion of a restricting function could be defined


whenever we were dealing with functions from any boolean algebra into itself. This theorem tells us that, for example, the common noun phrase (male
The definitions we have just given for operations in TAP can also be given and Communist) student has the same interpretation as the phrase male
r (Communist student). The oddity of the phrase male and Communist student
in the general case. The following theorem summarizes the situation:
can be perhaps explained by saying that this phrase is always passed over in
THEOREM 2. Let RBIB = {fEFBIB: fis restricting}, where B is an arbitrary favor of the equivalent phrase male Communist student, which is at least
boolean algebra. Then RBIB is a boolean algebra under the operations II, v, shorter, and possibly easier to process. Since boolean combinations of inter-
and' defined as follows: section adjectives involving or and not cannot be paraphrased this way,
they, unlike combinations involving and, are used in real English, and do not
(a) For f, g E RBIB arbitrary, f II g is defined by setting (f II g) (b) sound odd.
= feb) 1\ g(b) for each bE B.
Unfortunately, an approach such as this cannot be used to explain the
(b) For f, g E RBIB arbitrary, f v g is defined by setting (tv g) (b) = oddity of combining an intersecting and a (nonintersecting) restricting
feb) v g(b) for each b EB. adjective with and, as in the phrase tall and Communist student. In particular,
(c) For t E RBIB arbitrary,!' is defined by settingf'(b) = b II (t(b ))' (tall and Communist) student and tall (Communist student) are not neces-
for each b EB. sarily equivalent. For, an individual which has the property which interprets
Moreover, if B is a complete algebra, then RBIB is complete, and if B is tall (Communist student) need only be tall relative to the Communist stu-
atomic, then RBIB is atomic. dents in the relevant model; he/she need not be tall with respect to all the
See the end of this section for proofs of theorems not given in the body students. However, as we have seen, an individual which has the property
of the texts. which interprets (tall and Communist) student does have the property which
130 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 132 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

DEFINITION 10. If B is a boolean algebra, then the algebra RB/B is called interprets tall student, so such an individual has to be tall with respect to all
the restricting algebra on B. students in the model, not just the Communist ones. Since an individual
could easily be tall with respect to the Communist students in a model but
Thus, we can summarize what we have done so far by saying that the type for not with respect to all students (if, say, all the Communist students were
restricting (transparent) adjective phrases shall be the restricting algebra on P. rather short), the tall (Communist student) property could hold of individuals
Turning now to the intersecting adjectives, we note that by Theorem 1
for which the (tall and Communist) student does not hold.
TAP is a subset of TAP. However, we can say more. Suppose that f and g are
i r However, the situation may not be hopeless. For, it appears that in real
two intersecting functions from Pinto P. Since f and g are restricting functions English there is a phrase whose logical interpretation is in fact representable
from Pinto P, we can apply Definition 7 and form the restricting function as (tall and Communist) student in our logical language, namely the phrase
f /\ g. An easy argument shows that f /\ g is itself intersecting. (Namely, tall, Communist student (not to be confused with the phrase tall Communist
if /\ g) (P) = f(P) /\ g(p) = (p /\ f(1)) /\ (p /\ g(1)) = P /\ [(1) /\ g(l)) = p /\ student, which appears to be representable as tall (Communist student)).
if /\ g) (1)). In other words, starting inside the (proper) subset TAP of TAP, Thus, there is actually nothing odd at all about the logical phrase (tall and
i r
we stay inside this subset whenever we operate with fl. This is described by Communist) student; it is simply a fact about real English that comma
saying that T A.P is closed under the operation fl. The importance of this is intonation is the method that is used to conjoin adjectives rather than the
1
that the operation /\, which we have defined on the larger set TAP, can be word and. Unfortunately, the oddness of tall or Communist student remains
viewed as an operation on the smaller set T Af as well. r unexplained. (The phrase tall but not Communist student sounds a bit less
1
It turns out that TA.P is closed under the operations V and' as well. Since odd to us.)
1 Let us turn now to some other considerations concerning adjectives. We
the operations /\, V, and', satisfy the axioms of boolean algebra (since TAP is
r noted earlier that scalar adjectives like tall can compare (a taller man than
a boolean algebra), we can conclude immediately that TA.P is a boolean Bill) and have intensive forms (a very tall man). However, the situation is
1
algebra under these operations which it 'inherits' by being a subset of TAP. different for intersecting adjectives; phrases like a more Albanian student
This situation is described by saying that TAP is a subalgebra of TAP. r than Bill or a very Albanian student seem uninterpretable unless we read into
i r
Again, what we have here is a special case of a more general situation: Albanian a content richer than the usual meaning of Albanian as simply an
indication of nationality-membership. We can gain some understanding of
THEOREM 3. Let IB/B = {IE RB/B: fis intersecting}, where B is an arbi- this from what we have developed so far. First, let us note the following
trary boolean algebra. Then IB/B is a subalgebra of RB/B. Moreover, if B is theorem, which follows almost immediately from Theorem 5:
complete, then IB/B is complete, and if B is atomic, then IB/B is atomic.
THEOREM 6. Let fE TAP be arbitrary. Then, for eachp EP,f(f(p)) = f(p).
DEFINITION 11. If B is a boolean algebra, then the algebra IB/S is called i
the intersecting algebra on B. In fact, if we make the following definition:
If we examine the definition of the notion of intersecting function, it is clear r
DEFINITION 12. Let X be an arbitrary set, and let X -+ X be an arbitrary
that such a functionfis completely defined once we specify the value of f(1). function. Then, for each nonnegative integer n, define fn: X -+ X as follows:
This means that it is possible to define a mapping of Pinto T AJ' by associat-
. 1 (a) fO(x)=x,foreachxEX;
ing to the property p that intersecting functionfsuch that[(l) = p. We then
(b) tn+ 1(x) = f(tn(x)) for each x EX,
have the following important theorem:
then, by a simple inductive argument, we can show the following:
THEOREM 4. Let the function u: P -+ TAJ' be defined as follows: given
1
pEP, u(P) is that function from Pinto P such that for each q E P, (u(P)) THEOREM 7. Let f E TAP be arbitrary. Then, for any positive integer n,
(q) = q /\ p. Then u is an isomorphism of P onto TAP' fn =f. i
i
MODIFIERS 133 MODIFIERS 135

But if I is any restricting (not necessarily intersecting) adjective function, not want the converse to hold. For example, John and Bill might both be
then the best we can say is the following: short students, making them both tall students to degree zero, and yet one
of them might be taller than the other. In general, two individuals might have
THEOREM 8. Let I E TAP be arbitrary. Then, if nand m are nonnegative the tall student property to the same degree and still differ in height.
r
integers with n > m, then r
~ 1m . A more promising approach emerges if we recall that the atoms of P
represent the properties of being particular individuals. Thus, if a is an atom
(Note that, since TAP is a boolean algebra, the relation ~ is defined between of P, there is a unique individual Ia such that a is a member of the set Ia but
r of no other individual (see Section A, Theorem 9), so that a can be regarded
members of it. The fact that r is a restricting adjective function if I is follows
as the property of being Ia. If a and b are distinct atoms, then Ia and Ib are
directly from the definitions.)
distinct individuals.
If the restricting adjective function f is not intersecting, it may be the
Now, consider the property a v b. Since a';;; a vb, Ia must contain the
case that r+ 1 < r for every nonnegative integer n. A simple example of
property a v b; and similarly, Ib contains the property a v b. However,
this is the following. Let P be the power set of the positive integers, so that
no other individual contains a vb. For, suppose that the individual I contains
an element of P is a set of positive integers. Let I be defined as follows: if a v b. We know that I = Ie for some atom c. Thus, c';;;a v b, which we may
pEP is any nonempty set of positive integers, then f(p) is the set obtained
rewrite c = c 1\ (a v b) = (c 1\ a) v (c 1\ b). If a, b, and c are three distinct
by removing from p the smallest integer. We also set I(f/J) = f/J. It is obvious atoms, then by Theorem 4c of Section A c f\ a = c f\ b = 0, whence c = 0,
that f is a restricting function. Moreover, applying I successively to the unit a contradiction to the fact that c is an atom. We conclude that 1a and Ib
element 1 of P (where, of course, 1 is actually the set {I, 2, 3, ... }), we are exactly those individuals which contain the property a vb.
find that r(1) = {n + 1, n + 2, ... }. In particular, for every nonnegative
Suppose now that f is the restricting adjective function interpreting a
integer n, r+l(1) is a proper subset of r(1). Thus r+1 :j= In for each n,
scalar adjective such as tall. We can apply f to the property a v b; since f
whencefn+ 1 <r foreachn. is restricting, there are four possible results:
Now, suppose that the restricting adjective function I interprets tall is
some model. If p is the property which interprets student, then tall student (5) (1) f(avb)=avb
is, of course, interpreted as I(p). Now, pep) = f(f(p)) is thus the inter- (2) f(a vb) = a
pretation of tall (tall student); so an individual has the property pep) iff (3) f(avb)=b
that individual is tall with respect to the tall students. Let us tentatively (4) f(avb)=O.
propose that this is just what is meant by the phrase very tall student. For-
mally, very will be a member of the category API AP. Moreover, it will be a
r r To interpret these possibilities, recall that if p is the property of being, say,
logical constant: in any model, very will be interpreted as the function very: a student, then f(p) is the property of being a tall student, that is, of being
TAP ~ TAP defined by setting very(f) = 12. Let us consider some facets of substantially taller than the average height for the set of individuals with
r r
this proposal. the student property. Following the same line of thought, we can say that
First of all, very is a member of the category API AP, which is a category f(a Vb) represents the property of being taller than the average height for the
r r
of modifiers, being of the form X/X; we might call this category the category set of individuals with the property a v b, that is, for the set {Ia, Ib}' But,
of ad-adjectives. Thus, the English phrase very tall student is represented in our if f(a vb) = a, only Ia has this property; that is, Ia is the unique individual
logical language as (very tall) student, where very tall is an adjective phrase. which is taller than the average height of Ia and lb. Clearly, we may identify
Next, we anticipate a later discussion and note that modifiers are typically this situation as the case of Ia being taller than lb. Similarly,t(a vb) = b
restricting. In the case of the adjectives, we have seen that the two largest may be identified with the situation thatIb is taller thanIa .
groups of adjectives, namely, the scalar adjectives and the intersecting adjec- There remain the other two possibilities. It seems reasonable to view
tives, are restricting, whereas the nonrestricting adjectives fall into a number f(a vb) = 0 as representing the situation in which Ia and I b are sufficiently
134 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 136 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

of rather small groups each definable by a highly particular semantic charac- similar in height so that neither can be said to be substantially taller than
terization. Accepting the idea that modifiers are typically restricting, we their average. On the other hand, the case in which f(a vb) = a V b seems
would prefer that very be restricting. But, with the suggested proposal, this uninterpretable; to be consistent with the discussion so far, we would have
is indeed the case, as follows directly from Theorem 8. to say that f(a vb) = a V b means that both Ia and Ib are substantially taller
Finally, under this proposal, we would have that, for any intersecting than their average, a situation which ought to be impossible. One way to
adjective function f, very (n = [, by Theorem 7. What this means is that in deal with this is simply to require that any function f which interprets a
our logical language, very Albanian will be a well-formed AP, but that it will lexical scalar adjective shall be strictly restricting in the following sense:
be interpreted the same as Albanian in all models. We can then explain the
necessary reinterpretation of Albanian in the English phrase very Albanian DEFINITION 13. f E Fp /p is strictly restricting iff f is restricting and for all
as follows. Since very is logically redundant if Albanian is given its usually t-
pEP, ifp 0 thenf(p) p. t-
interpretation as an intersecting adjective, the presence of very constitutes
a pragmatic invitation to reinterpret Albanian in such a way that very is no Thinking of such an f as the interpretation of tall, and defining an individual
longer redundant, that is, as a nonintersecting, scalar adjective. This is in Ia to be taller than an individual I b iff f(a vb) =a, Definition 13 guarantees
fact just what happens: Albanian is reinterpreted as denoting not mere that of any two individuals either one is taller than the other or they have
nationality-membership, but rather the scalar quality of possessing the approximately the same height (the case where f(a vb) =0). It also guarantees
characteristics associated with that membership. As a general principle we that no individual is taller than himself, since if Ia were taller than Ia then
may say that logically redundant elements when present in an expression f(a v a) would be a, which is impossible since (a v a) =a by idempotency
constitute a pragmatic invitation to reinterpret the expression that element is and f(a) = 0 since f is strictly restricting.
combined with. We will see other examples of this from time to time. However the constraint on the interpretation of scalar APs given in Defini-
tion 13 is not adequate to guarantee an empirically correct definition of e.g.
taller than since it does not imply that that relation on individuals is transitive.
Comparative Adjectives
For example, a strictly restricting function f might behave as follows on
Turning next to the matter of comparative expressions, we note that the distinct atoms a, b, and c: f(a vb) =a (Ia is taller than I b );/(b v c) = b (Ibis
semantics of such expressions clearly involves the idea of comparing degrees taller than Ie); and f(a v c) = C (Ie is taller than fa)' So let us further require
of possession of some quality along a scale. We defer a precise statement of that functions which can interpret scalar APs be transitive:
the syntax and semantics of comparatives; here we make some preliminary
investigations into the matter of scalarity. DEFINITION 14. f E Fp/p is transitive iff for all atoms a, b, c EP, if f(a v b)
Theorem 8 provides us with a way of defining a discrete scale for restrict- =a andf(b v c) = b thenf(a v c) =a.
ing adjectives. Namely, it follows from that theorem that if lis an individual,
p is a property, and f is a restricting adjective function, then either there is Now our informal definition of taller than above does determine a transitive
a unique largest integer n such that I has the property m(p) but not the relation on the individuals (or atoms). But still more is needed. We want to
m m
property + 1(p), or else I has the property (p) for all positive integers define more than a binary relation is taller than on the set of all individuals;
n. In the former case, we may say that I has the property f(p) to degree n; we want to define the sorts of relations expressed by is a taller student than.
in the latter case, we would say that I has the property f to countable degree Informally, then, let us define for any property p, Ia is a taller p than Ib iff
(or, to degree aleph-null). Now, it is clear that if the individual which inter- a";; p and b ..;; p andf(a vb) = a, where finterprets tall. Thus John is a taller
prets John has the tall student property to a degree strictly greater than the student than Bill holds just in case both John and Bill are students and John
individual which interprets Bill, then, in that model, we would want John is taller than Bill. Note that John is taller than Bill is now logically equivalent
is a taller student than Bill to be interpreted as true. Unfortunately, this to John is a taller individual than Bill. Note further that this approach has
procedure cannot be made defmitional for the comparative, since we would treated taller . .. than as a discontinuous operator, syntactically speaking.
MODIFIERS 137 MODIFIERS 139

We may informally define a non-discontinuous operator taller than as surgeon (or a good driver or a famous jockey) even if he is the only one,
follows: fa is a p taller than fb iff a ~ p and [(a vb) =a, where [interprets whence the interpretations of skillful, good and famous need not be strictly
tall. Thus John is a taller student than Bill does not imply that Bill is a restrictive. And second, if John and Bill are both doctors and both drivers
student. and John is a more skillful doctor than Bill it clearly does not follow that he
A final problem remains: taller . .. than is a transitive relation on individ- is a more skillful driver than Bill, whence order consistency would appear
uals, given that tall is interpreted by a transitive strictly restricting function to fail for skillful.
from Pinto P, but we have not guaranteed that this relation is respected by
the interpretation of tall. We must guarantee for example that John is a tall
Predicate Adjectives
student whenever John is taller than Bill, John is a student, and Bill is a tall
student. This we do by requiring that the functions which may interpret Given the semantics for (non-comparative) APs above and the semantics
scalar APs are order consistent: for one place predicates (PI'S) of Section A, we consider now the semantics
of PI'S formed from AP's, such as be happy, seem bored, look disgusting, feel
DEFINITION 15. A strictly restricting function [E Fp/p is order consistent sticky, taste lousy, sound horrible, etc. Each of these involves a lexical item
iff for allp EP and all atoms a, b satisfying a ~p and b ~p, which can be combined with an AP to yield a PI' Of the various lexical
items appearing in these examples, only be 'can be treated in an extensional
(i) if [(a v b) =a and b ~[(p) then a ~f(p) and system. For example, even if happy and healthy are 'interpreted as the same
(ii) if f(a vb) =0 then a ~f(p) iff b ~[(p). function from Pinto P, it will not follow that seem happy and seem healthy
should be interpreted as the same PI function. An individual can seem
Requiring that scalar APs like tall be interpreted by strictly restricting, (look, appear) happy without seeming healthy, regardless of whether in fact
transitive, order consistent functions and interpreting comparatives and all the happy e's are exactly the healthy e's, for each common noun phrase e.
superlatives as suggested above yields, we believe, a semantic analysis of To treat be as it occurs in an expression like be happy, we first recall that
these constructions which enables us to represent many of their entailment in the core language L there is already an expression be of category P 2 =
properties. It is however open to at least two objections. The first, and least Pt/N. This earlier be is a logical constant; its interpretation is given in Defini-
serious to our minds, is that the constraints on the interpretations of tall tion 42 of Section A. Clearly, the be of be happy should likewise be a logical
are motivated by the desire to make the semantics of comparative forms constant, but this be is of category PI / AP. In our earlier treatment (Keenan
empirically correct rather than by direct consideration of arguments involving and Faltz, 1978), these two be's were treated as distinct, and, in fact, un-
the non-comparative form. related lexical items (denoted bel and be2), but, given the general system
This objection is simply not correct. For example, the conjunction of the of category names defined in Section A, we are not forced to do this here.
sentences in (Sa) below entails On our semantics (Sb) and the proof (left Rather, we can (and do) propose that there is a lexical item be of category
as an exercise for the reader) crucially requires that tall be interpreted by an <PI, PI) I <ii, AP). This simply means that be can be grammatically combined
order consistent function. either with an expression of category R or else with an expression of category
AP; in either case, the resulting expression is of category PI.
(S) a. John is a tall student, Bill is student but not a tall one, Next, to define the interpretation of be, we note the general principle for
John is a jockey, Bill is a tall jockey interpreting an expression of category (XI, X 2 ) I (Y 1 , Y 2 ). Namely, if e
b. John is a tall jockey is an expression of this category, then M(e) is a function from TYI U TY 2
into Tx 1 U Txz which has the property that, when M(e) is applied to an
As none of the sentences in (5) use anything other than the bare adjective element of Ty l' the result is an element of Tx l' and when M(e) is applied
tall we may conclude that our semantics for such APs would be inadequate to an element of Ty 2' the result is an element of Tx 2' Iff is such a function,
if we omitted the order consistency requirement. then f is equivalent to a pair (fl, f2), where fl,' Ty 1 --)0 Tx 1 and f2,' Ty 2 --)0
138 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 140 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Similarly the transitivity condition on tall is needed to guarantee entail- TX 2' For, given [, we can define [1 by setting [I (z) = fez) if z E Ty I; and
ments between sentences none of which mention the comparative form. For similarly, we can set [2(Z) = fez) if z E TY2' Conversely, if we have two
example, the conjunction of the sentences in (6a) below entails (6b) in functions [I: Ty 1 -+ Tx 1 and [2: Ty 2 -+ Tx 2' where Ty 1 and Ty 2 are
virtue of the transitivity condition on tall. disjoint, then the function [defined by setting fez) = [1 (z) if z E Ty 1 and
fez) = fz(z) if z E TY2 is a function from TYt U Tyz into TXt U TX2
(6) a. John and Bill are the only students, John is a tall student and with the property given above.
Bill isn't, Bill and Sam are the only socialists, Bill is a tall socialist In the matter of the interpretation of the logical constant be, we must
and Sam isn't, John and Sam are the only vegetarians, therefore define the function (M(be))I: P* -+ TP 1 (which interprets be when
b. John is a tall vegetarian and Sam isn't. it is combined with a noun phrase) and the function (M(be))2: TAP -+ TP 1
(which interprets be when it is combined with an adjective phrase). Now,
Finally, the strict restricting condition guarantees the validity of sentences for {M{be))I' we just take the function already defined earlier, when be was
like those in (7). (The judgments are admittedly less compelling than in (5) introduced as a logical constant of category P2 in the core language (Defini-
and (6) above but still we feel more right than wrong.) tion 42 of Section A). For {M{be)2' we make the following definition:

(7) a. Not all students are tall students. DEFINITION 16. For any [ E TAP, (M(be))2(f) is that complete homo-
b. If John is a tall student then there is a student different from morphism from P* into 2 such that, for any individual I, «M(be))z (f») (I) =
John who is not a tall student. 1 iff V [(P) E I.
pEP

A second objection to our approach is that the three conditions we have


We may rephrase this definition by saying that (M(be»2(f) is the verb phrase
imposed on the interpretations of scalar APs would all follow automatically
homomorphism which is associated with the property Vp E P rep), in the
on an approach in which the semantics of these APs was primitively taken
sense of Definition 36 and Theorem 18 of Section A.
to involve comparison of individuals on a scale. That amounts to taking the
To see what this definition means, note first that by the joins condition
interpretation of taller than as basic, as in Bartsch (1976), and defining the
for individuals, an individual I has the property Vp E P rep) iff I has the
semantics for tall in terms of it. Whatever its elegance when worked out in
property rep), for some property p. Suppose, then, that [interprets tall,
detail, however, we object to this approach on the grounds that it violates
so that (M{be» (f) is the interpretation of the verb phrase be tall. By this
the Compositionality condition. Namely, in English and in all languages
definition an individual I has the property associated with be tall just in
with which we are familiar, the comparative forms of APs are given as a
case, for some property p, I is tall for the set of individuals which have the
function of the non-comparative one - they contain it as a discernable part,
property p. In particular, it does not necessarily follow from the truth of
whence the interpretation of tall-er than should be given in terms of the
John (be talT) that John is a tall existent (in contrast to, say, the system of
interpretation of tall, as we have done, and not conversely.
Montague, 1970, where this does follow). This accords with our pre theoretical
A second objection to defining non-comparative in terms of comparative
intuitions, according to which, for example, we would want John is tiny to
forms, one which we find suggestive even though it is not worked out in
be true in a model in which John is a tiny elephant is true, even if John is a
enough detail to be convincing, is the following. The semantics for com-
tiny existent is not true.
paratives of non-transparent APs suggests that only (at most) the transitivity
Let us examine the consequences of our definition a bit closer. In the
requirement should hold, but that strict restrictiveness and order consistency
case of intersecting AP's, the following theorem shows that our definition
should not be required. If this is so then the three conditions are in fact
leads to a reasonable result:
(partially) independent since some APs satisfy all of them while others only
satisfy transitivity.
THEOREM 9.1f [EFp/p is intersecting then V rep) = [(1).
Examples supporting these claims are, first, that John can be a skillful PEP
MODIFIERS 141 MODIFIERS 143

What this says for example is that the property associated with the PI be Now, since (f 1\ (g v h» (b) = ((f 1\ g) V (f 1\ h») (b) for every bin B, we
male is the same as the property determined by the intersecting AP male conclude that f 1\ (g v h) = (f 1\ g) V (f 1\ h).
(see Theorem 4 above and the discussion following it). Thus for intersecting The remaining axioms involve the distinguished elements 0 and 1. We
AP's like male (Albanian, etc.) John is male is logically equivalent to John define 0 as that element of RBIB such that O(b) = 0 for each element b of
is a male existent, clearly a desired result. B (where, of course, the second 0 refers to the zero element of B). Note that,
The case of scalar adjectives does not work out quite as well. In real since 0 .:;;; b for every b E B by Theorem 2 of Section A, the function 0 thus
English, a sentence like John is tall is interpreted to mean, approximately, defined is indeed restricting (that is, it is a member of RBIB).
John is a tall e, where e denotes some N which defines a set of individuals We can now show that the first complement axiom in the definition of a
whose tallness provides a standard with respect to which John's tallness is boolean algebra is satisfied by RBIB. Let f be an arbitrary member of RBIB,
measured. Since John is typically the name of a man, and since tallness is a and let b be an arbitrary element of B. Then:
property which is often saliently predicated of men, John is tall is reasonably
likely to be interpreted to mean John is a tall man, in the absence of other (f 1\ /') (b) =f(b) 1\ / ' (b) (definition of 1\ inRBIB)
contextual factors. However, if it is known that John is a jockey, and if the =f(b) 1\ (b 1\ (f(b»)') (definition of' in RBIB)
context of the utterance makes this fact salient, then John is tall would = b 1\ (f(b) 1\ (f(b »)') (commutative and associative laws in B)
probably be interpreted to mean that John is a tall jockey. In any case, the =b 1\ OB (complement axiom in B)
context supplies a specific set of individuals (of which John is a member) =OB (Theorem 2a, c of Section A applied to B)
whose tallness is the standard of measurement. = O(b) (definition of 0 inRBIB)'
However, we have not at this time provided for a method by means of
which such a contextually defined distinguished set of individuals (or, equi· Since (f 1\ /') (b) = O(b) for each b E B, we conclude that f 1\ / ' = O.
valently, a contextually defined property) can be represented in our system. Next, we define 1 as that element of RBIB such that l(b) = b for each
It is for this reason that we have settled on the definition given above, accord· element of b of B. That 1 thus defined is in fact restricting (that is, an ele-
ing to which John is tall is true just in case for some property p John is tall ment of RBIB) follows from the fact that b':;;; b (Theorem 2b of Section A).
for the set of individuals which have the property p. But if we assume that With this definition, we prove that the second complement axiom of the
the scalarity of tall is reasonably represented in some manner (for example, definition of a boolean algebra is satisfied by RBIB by letting f E RBIB and
by imposing the conditions of strict restrictiveness, transitivity, and order· b EB be arbitrary elements and noting that:
consistency discussed earlier on the function which interprets tall) our
definition leads to the unpleasant conclusion that John is tall is true just in (fV/')(b) =f(b)v/,(b) (definitionofvinRB/B)
case there is an individual who is shorter than John. (For, if there is such =f(b) v (b 1\ (f(b »') (definition of' in RB/B)
an individual, say, Bill, then John is tall relative to the set consisting just of =(f(b) vb) 1\ (f(b) v (f(b »)') (distributivity in B)
the individuals John and Bill. The converse is obvious.) For now we leaVE = (f(b) vb) 1\ 1B (complement axiom in B)
things as they are, contenting ourselves with the remark that the represen· =f(b) v b (axiomeinB)
tation of contextually determined elements seems to be necessary for any =b if is restricting, that is, f( b) .:;;; b)
fully adequate treatment of predicate adjective phrases. =l(b)
With this we end our discussion of adjective phrases in our extensional
system. In the next section we will see how much of what we have donE Since (f v /') (b) = 1(b) for each b E B, we conclude that f v/'= 1.
here can be extended immediately to the case of other modifiers. The proofs of the remaining axioms are similar, and are left to the reader.
Now, let us suppose that B is a complete algebra. To show that RBIB is
complete, we must show that every subset K of RBIB has a glb and a lub.
In order to do this, it is convenient to have the following lemma, which
142 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 144 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Proofs of Theorems from This Section allows us to operate easily with the relation < in RBIB, where B is any
boolean algebra.
The first theorem we have to prove is the following:
LEMMA. Let B be a boolean algebra, and lett, gERBIB be arbitrary. Then,
THEOREM 2. Let RB/B = {jEFB/B: fis restricting}, where B is an arbitrary f < g ifffor each b E B,!(b) < g(b).
boolean algebra. Then RB/B is a boolean algebra under the operations II, v,
and' defined as follows: For, suppose first that f < g. This means that f 1\ g = f, so that, for each
b E B, feb) = (f 1\ g) (b) = feb) 1\ g(b) (the last equality by the definition
(a) For f, g ERB/B arbitrary,! II gis defined by setting (f II g) (b) = of 1\ in RBIB), so thatf(b) <g(b) for each b EB.
feb) II g(b) for each b EB. Conversely, if for each b E B we have f(b) < g(b), this means that, for
(b) For f, g E RB/B arbitrary, fv g is defined by setting (fv g) (b) = each bE B, feb) = feb) /I g(b) = (f 1\ g) (b), whence f = f 1\ g, that is,f<g.
feb) v g(b) for each b EB. This proves the lemma.
(c) For fERB/B arbitrary,!' is defined by setting/,(b) = b II (f(b))' Now, assume that B is complete, and let K ~ RBIB be an arbitrary subset.
for each b EB. For each b E B, define feb) = I\{k(b): k E K}. Then feb) is well defined
(because B is complete), and is a function from B into B. Moreover, since
Moreover, if B is a complete algebra, then RB/B is complete, and if B is k(b) < b for each k in K, it follows that f(b) < b. Thus,! is a restricting
atomic, then RB/B is atomic. function, that is, a member of RBIB' We show thatfis the glb of K.
Let k E K be arbitrary. For each bE B, feb) = I\{k(b): k E K} < k(b),
We note that since TAP = Rp/p, it follows from this theorem that TAP
r r so by the lemma, f < k. Since this holds for each element k of K, we conclude
is a complete atomic boolean algebra. thatfis a lower bound for K.
We first have to show that f IIg,!v g, and/' as defined above are actually Next, suppose that y is a lower bound for K. Let b E B be arbitrary. Since
members of RB/B. However, the proofs of these statements are essentially y < k for every k E K, we have y(b) < k(b) for every k EK, by the lemma.
identical to the corresponding proofs for TAP, which were given explicitly in
r
But, by the definition of f, we conclude that we must have y(b) < feb).
the text. We leave it to the reader to verify that this is indeed the case. Since this holds for arbitrary b, we have, again by the lemma, that y < f,
To prove that RB/B is a boolean algebra, we have to verify that the axioms that is, f is the greatest lower bound.
of a boolean algebra are satisfied (see Definition 9 of Section A). As in the The definition and proofs for least upper bounds are dual to the ones
case of previous proofs of this sort, we will only prove some of these axioms for greatest lower bounds; we leave it to the reader to formulate them.
explicitly, leaving the others for the reader. Finally, agsume that B is atomic. We will show that RBIB is atomic.
The commutativity axioms follow obviously from the fact that the opera- First, what are the atoms of RBIB? For each b E B where b 1- OB and
tions in B satisfy these axioms. The distributivity axioms likewise follow each atom a < b, let us define the function fab as follows: for each e E B,
in a straightforward way from the definitions. For example, to prove that fab(e) = OB if e 1- b, and fab(b) =a. Then, since fab(e) =OB < e (for the case
the first distributivity axiom holds in RB/B, let f, g, and h be arbitrary that e 1- b), and fab(b) = a < b, fab is a restricting function from B into B,
members of RB/B, and let b be an arbitrary element of B. Then, that is, an element of RBIB. Moreover, fab is an atom. First, fab 1- 0 since
fab(b) 1- 0B· Second if g <fab, then (by the lemma) gee) < fab(e) = OB if
.(f II (g v h)) (b) =feb) II (g v h) (b) (definition of II inRB/B) e 1- b, whence gee) = OB if c 1- b. Also, g(b) <fab(b) = a, whence, since a
=feb) II (g(b) v h(b)) (definition ofv inRB/B) is an atom, g(b) = OB or g(b) = a. In the first case, g =0, and in the second,
=(f(b) II g(b)) v (f(b) II h(b)) (distributive axiom in B) g = fab. Thus, fab satisfies the definition of an atom. We leave it to the reader
= (f II g) (b) v (f II h) (b) (definition of II inRB/B) to show that any atom of RBIB must be of the form fab, a fact we do not
= «f II g) v (f II h)) (b) (definition ofv inRB/B) need in the current proof.
MODIFIERS 145 MODIFIERS 147

To show that RB/B is atomic, let f E RB/B be arbitrary, with f 7'= O. We then, for arbitrary b E B, fa(b) = b /I a. Alternatively, the reader may supply
show that there exists an atom a of B and an element b of B, with a ~ b, such the entirely straightforward direct proof that the functions fa so defined
thatfab ~f. are indeed atoms in IB/B, and that for any f EIB/B, f1 0, there exists some
Since f 7'= 0, there must exist at least one element of B, say, b, such that fa such that fa ..;; f. This completes the proof and discussion of Theorem 3.
f(b) 7'= 0B. Since f is restricting, we have f(b) ~ b, whence we also have that
b 7'= 0B. Since B is atomic, there must exist at least one atom, say, a, such that Rather than proving Theorem 4 of the text, we prove the following slightly
a ~ feb). Then, we also have that a ~ b, so that fab is well defined for the more general theorem:
elements a and b we have just chosen. Now, it is the case that fab ~ f.
For, if c 7'= b, then fab(e) = OB ~f(c), no matter what fCc) actually is. And, THEOREM 4'. Let B be a boolean algebra, and let the function u: B ..... FB/B
fab(b) = a ~ feb), by the way a was chosen. Thus, by the lemma, fab ~f, be defined as follows: given b E B, u(b) is that function from B into B such
whence RB /B is atomic. This completes the proof of the theorem. that for each c E B, (u(b)) (c) = c " b. Then u is an isomorphism of B onto
IB/B.
Our next theorem is the following:
First of all, note that (u(b» (1) = 1 "b =b, so that (u(b» (c) =c" (u(b» (1),
THEOREM 3. Let 1B/B = if E RB/B: f is intersecting}, where B is an arbi- whence u(b) is intersecting. Thus, we may regard u as a function from B into
trary boolean algebra. Then 1BIB is a sub algebra of RB/B. Moreover, if B is IB/B'
complete, then I BIB is complete, and if B is atomic, then I BIB is atomic. Next, suppose that b l 1 b 2 • Then, (u(bd) (1) = b l f b 2 = (u(b 2 » (1), so
that u(bd and u(b 2 ) are distinct functions from B into B; that is u(bd f
The fact that 1BIB is a subalgebra of RB/B will follow if we can show that u(b 2 ). This proves that u is one-to-one.
1BIB is closed under the operations 1\, v, and I defined in RBIB, and if IBIB Suppose next that f is an arbitrary element of I B / B. Since f(1) is an
contains the elements 0 and I of RBIB; for then the axioms of a boolean
algebra must be fulfilled in I B/B, since they are fulfilled in RB/B.
».
element of B, it makes sense to consider u(f(1 But (u(f(l» (c) =c" f(l) =
f( c) (since f is intersecting), whence u(f(l» = f. Since f was arbitrary, this
Suppose that f and g are elements of IBIB. Then, for b E B arbitrary we shows that u is onto.
have: We have shown that u, regarded as a function from B into IB/B, is one-to-
one and onto. The proof will be complete if we can show that u is a homo-
(f 1\ g)(b) = f(b) 1\ g(b) (definition of 1\ in RB/B)
morphism. We show that u preserves meets and complements.
= (b 1\ f(1)) 1\ (b 1\ g(1)) (f and g are intersecting)
Let b l and b 2 be arbitrary elements of B. For any c EB, we have:
=(b 1\ b) 1\ (t(1) 1\ gel)) (commutative and associative laws
inRB/B)
(u(b l " b 2 » (c) =C" (b l " b2 ) (definition ofu)
= b 1\ (f(l) 1\ g(1)) (idempotent law in RBIB) (idempotent law in B)
=(c "c)" (b l " b 2 )
= b 1\ (f 1\ g)(I) (definition of 1\ inRBIB)
=(c" bd" (c" b 2 ) (commutative and associative
laws in B)
which shows that f 1\ g is intersectirg. We also have:
=(u(bt}) (c)" (u(b 2 » (c) (definition of u)
(tv g)(b) =feb) v g(b) (definition of v inRB/B ) =(u(bd " u(b 2 » (c) (definition of" inIB/B)
=(b 1\ f(I)) v (b 1\ gel)) if and g are intersecting)
= b 1\ (f(1) V g(1)) (distributive law inRB/B) Since this holds for arbitrary c E B, we conclude that u(b l /I b 2 )
= b 1\ (fvg)(l) u(b l )" u(b 2 ), that is, u preserves meets.
(definition of v in RB/B)
Finally, let b be an arbitrary element of B. For any c E B, we have:
which shows that fv g is also intersecting.
146 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 148 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

To show that IBIB is closed under', letfbe an element of IBIB. Then, (u(b ')) (C) = c 1\ b' (definition of u)
for b EB arbitrary, we have: = (C 1\ b ') V (c 1\ C' ) (since c 1\ C ' = 0)
=C 1\ (b ' ve') (distributive law in B)
f'(b) = b /I (f(b))' (definition of' inRB/B) =c 1\ (b 1\ C)' (De morgan law in B)
= b /I (b /I f(l))' (f is intersecting) = C 1\ «u(b)) (C))' (definition of u)
=b 1\ (b'v ([(1))') (DeMorgan law in RBIB) = (u(b))' (C) (definition of I inIB/B)
= (b /I b')v (b /I (f(1))') (distributive law inRB/B)
= b /I (t(1))' (since b /I b' = 0) Since this holds for arbitrary c E B, we conclude that u(b') = (u(b))', that is,
= b /I (1/\ (f(I))') (since (f(1))' = 1/\ (t(1))' u preserves complements. Thus, u is a homomorphism, and, since it is a one-
= b /I 1'(1) (definition of: in RBIB) to-one mapping of B onto IB/B, it is an isomorphism of B onto IB/B. This
completes the proof.
showing that I' is intersecting.
Finally, for any b E B, O(b) = OB = b /I OB = b /I 0(1), and l(b) Let us note that in the part of the above proof in which we showed that u is
= b = b /I 1 = b /I 1(1), so that 0 and 1 are intersecting. This completes onto, we proved the equation u(f(1)) = f, which, together with the fact that
the proof that IB/B is a subalgebra of RB/B. u is one-to-one, shows explicitly that the intersecting adjective function f
If B is complete or atomic, it will follow directly from Theorem 4', proven determines the property f(1).
below, that IBIB is complete or atomic, since IBIB is, in fact, isomorphic to Again, rather than proving Theorem 5 of the text, we prove the slightly
B. The reader may easily verify that nothing in the proof of Theorem 4' more general:
makes use of the fact that!BIB is complete or atomic if B is.
However, before proceeding to that proof, it is instructive to examine THEOREM 5'. Let B be a boolean algebra and let f, gElB / B be arbitrary.
directly what is going on in IBIB. As far as completeness is concerned, Then, for each b E B, (f 1\ g) (b) = f(g(b)) = g(f(b )).
we can verify directly that if K ~ IB IB, then I\K and VK, which are well
defined elements of RBIB (since RBIB is complete), are elements of IB/B. For, we have
To show this, let b be an arbitrary element of B. Then, first of all, we have
that (I\K) (b) = 1\/ E K feb) = 1\/ E K (b 1\ f(1» = b 1\ [1\/ E K f(1)] =
(f 1\ g)(b) =feb) 1\ g(b) (definition of 1\ in IB/B)
b 1\ (I\K) (1), where we have used the definition of I\K as given in the
proof of Theorem 2, together with the fact that the elements of K are inter-
=(b 1\ f(l)) 1\ (b 1\ g(1)) (f and g are intersecting)
secting. Of course, the equation (I\K) (b) = b 1\ (I\K) (1) shows that K is
=(b 1\ f(1)) 1\ g(1) (commutative, idempotent, and
associative laws in B)
intersecting.
Similarly, we have (VK) (b) = V/ E K feb) = Vf E K (b 1\ f(I» =
And we also have
b [VfE K f(1)] = b 1\ (VK) (1), so that (VK) is intersecting.
The matter of atomicity is more interesting. By Theorem 2 above if B
is atomic, so is RBIB. However, it is easy to show that none of the functions g(f(b)) = f(b) 1\ g(l) (g is intersecting)
fab, which were defined in the proof of Theorem 2 and shown there to be =(b 1\ f(1)) 1\ g(1) (f is intersecting)
the atoms of RBIB, are elements of IB/B- Thus, the atoms of IBIB must
be certain elements which are not atoms when viewed as elements of RBIB. Thus, (f 1\ g) (b) is equiu to g(f( b)), since they are both equal to (b 1\ f(1))
1\ g(1). The proof that f(g(b)) is also equal to (b 1\ f(l)) 1\ g(1) is similar,
From the statement of Theorem 4' below, it follows that the atoms of IB/B
must be exactly those functions fa defined as follows: if a is an atom of B, and left to the reader.
MODIFIERS 149 PREDICATE MODIFIERS 151

We now prove a slightly generalized version of Theorem 7, from which or of other adverb-formers, even though most of our examples will involve
Theorem 6 follows immediately as a special case. such elements, since we need to know what TpM is in order to study functions
which have TpM as their range. As it turns out, however, in addition to the
THEOREM 7'. Let B be a boolean algebra and letfEIBIB be arbitrary. Then, more common complex PMs, there will be a small number of lexical PMs,
for any positive integer n, r
=f. such as the logical constants somewhere and everywhere, as well as certain
other lexical expressions such as here, there, etc.
The proof is by induction on n. Clearly, the statement r =f is true for the As in the case of the APs, PMs can be subdivided into a number of distinct
case that n =1. Assume, then, that it is true for n =k. groups. We now consider some of these groups.
Letting b E B be arbitrary, we have that Recall that many common scalar adjectives, such as skillful, as well as
nonrestricting adjectives, such as fake or alleged, are properly intensional;
fk+l (b) =f(fk (b)) (part (b) of Definition 12)
that is, they cannot be interpreted as functions from N extensions into N
=f(f(b)) (inductive assumption)
extensions. We called those APs which can be so interpreted transparent.
= f(b) " f(1) (fis intersecting)
Similarly, let us say that a PM is transparent if it can be defmed as a function
= (b i\ f( 1)) i\ f(1 ) (f is intersecting)
on the set of possible extensional interpretations of the predicate with which
=b "f(1) (associative and idempotent laws in B)
it is combined.
=feb) (f is intersecting)
Now, in the case of PMs, it appears that a striking majority of them are
which proves the theorem. nontransparent. Let us examine a few representative cases.
Manner adverbs such as skillfully or slowly are nontransparent. For,
We similarly generalize Theorem 8 as: suppose that in a given model those individuals who are singing are exactly
those individuals who are dancing. Then, sing and dance will be interpreted as
THEOREM 8'. Let B be a boolean algebra and let f E RBIB be arbitrary. the same (extensional) PI homomorphism, in that model. Now, we certainly
Then, if nand m are nonnegative integers with n > m, then fn <.,fm. would not want to conclude that those individuals who are singing slowly
are exactly the same as those individuals who are dancing slowly. However,
We prove this by induction on the set of integers greater than m; we will
if slowly were interpreted transparently, this unfortunate conclusion would
make continual use of the lemma of Theorem 2 above.
follow, since the function which interprets slowly would be applied to the
For the case n =m + 1, we have, for each bE B,
same argument in order to produce the interpretations of sing slowly and of
f m +1 = f(fm(b)) (part (b) of Definition 12) dance slowly.
<.,fm(b) (fis restricting) Similarly, comitative phrases such as with Fred are nontransparent. If,
for example, the individuals who are working are exactly those individuals
whencefm +1 <.,fm, by the lemma. who are talking, then work and talk would be interpreted as the same PI
Next, we assume that the statement of the theorem is true for n = m + k. homomorphism. But we would not want to conclude that those individuals
For n = m + k + 1, we have, for each b EB, who are working with Fred are exactly the same as those individuals who are
talking with Fred; obviously, one could be working with Fred but only
fm+k+l(b) =f(fm+k (b)) (part (b) of Definition 12) talking with John, who is sitting on the sidelines. Thus, with Fred had better
<.,fm+k(b) (f is restric ting) not be interpreted as a function which takes as argument the extensional
<.,fm(b) (inductive assumption). interpretation of work or of talk, for if it were, work with Fred and talk with
Fred would have the same interpretation.
Whence fm +k+ 1 <., f m , by the lemma. This proves the theorem. Benefactive phrases are not transparent. If those who are buying a present
are exactly those who are whistling a tune, it will not follow that those
150 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 152 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

The final theorem of this section shows that the property associated with a who are buying a present for Mary are those who are whistling a tune for
predicate intersecting adjective is just the property determined by that Mary.
adjective, in the sense of Theorem 4. Again, we give a slightly more general Directional phrases are not transparent. If those who are driving a taxi
theorem than the one stated in the text: are exactly those who are spitting, it will not follow that those who are
driving a taxi through the store window are exactly those who are spitting
THEOREM 9'. Let B be a complete boolean algebra and let f E 18/8 be through the store window.
arbitrary. Then V feb) =f(1). Instrumental phrases are not transparent. If those who are eating a pickle
b EB
are exactly those who are killing a snake, it will not follow that those who
We have that are eating a pickle with a fork are exactly those who are killing a snake with
a fork.
= bEB
V (b 1\ f(1) (f is intersecting) Subject·matter phrases are not transparent. If those who are lecturing are
=( V b) I\f(1) (infinite distributive law in B) exactly those who are thinking, it will not follow that those who are lecturing
b EB
=ll\f(1) (since 1 = lub (B)) about the Common Market are exactly those who are thinking about the
Common Market.
=f(l) (since f(1) = 1)
Finally, source and goal expressions are not transparent. If those who
This concludes the proofs for this section. are talking are exactly those who are waving, it will not follow that those
who are talking to Bill are exactly those who are waving to Bill. Similarly,
if those who are running are exactly those who are stealing an apple, it does
2. PREDICATE MODIFIERS
not follow that those who are running from the police are exactly those
We come next to the category of predicate modifiers, which we shall ab- who are stealing an apple from the police. (But see the discussion below on
breviate as PM. Much of the work carried out in the previous section for the argument-oriented PMs.)
APs will carry over to the case of the PMs, as well as to other modifiers. There is, however, an important class of predicate modifiers which do
Bya predicate modifier we mean, to begin with, any expression of category seem to be transparent. These are the stative locatives, such as in the park,
Pn/Pn , for some nonnegative integer n. For the first part of our discussion, under a table, etc. If, say, in some model, the individuals who are singing
the reader may wish to think of predicate modifiers as simply being of the are exactly those who are dancing, we can conclude that those who are
category PdP 1 although the more general approach will ultimately be taken. singing in the park are exactly those who are dancing in the park.
Thus, predicate modifiers include all expressions normally thought of in any As a matter of fact, in the case of these stative locatives, we can say
sense as adverbial. something more precise. Namely, the sentence John is singing in the park is
Now, relatively few such are lexical expressions. In the discussions to true if and only if John is singing and John exists (= is) in the park are both
follow, we will be most concerned with prepositional phrases, such as in a simultaneously true. Suppose that sing is interpreted as the P l homomorphism
garden, with John, etc., and with adverbs derived from adjectives, such as t, and that in the park is interpreted as the function g. Then sing in the park
skillfully, allegedly, etc. Prepositional phrases are formed by combining an will be interpreted as the P l homomorphism g (t), while exist in the park is
expression of category fl with a (mostly lexical) expression of a new category interpreted asg (1) (since the logical constant exist is interpreted as 1 in every
which we call, of course, prepositions (abbreviated Prep); and adverbs like model). But by what we have just said, this means that g (f) = tAg (I).
skillfully are formed by combining an adjective with the logical constant ly. If we examine Definition 5 of the previous section, we see that g is just
Following our general program, since, clearly, Prep = PM/fl, we will want an intersecting function, that is, a member of ITPl/TPl. At this point,
to interpret a preposition as a function from Tfi into TpM; and, similarly, therefore, we might be tempted to say· that for the extensional language
the interpretation of ly will be some function from TAP into TpM. Thus we the category PM consists just of stative locatives, that PM = PdP l , and that
find it necessary to discuss PMs before taking up the discussion of prepositions TpM = 1TPl/TPl. While we will see shortly that such an approach is not
PREDICATE MODIFIERS 153 PREDICATE MODIFIERS 155

sufficient for our purposes, it is instructive to see how much can be done just boolean combinations of stative locatives. Suppose, for example, that in
with this, based on what we have developed so far. the garden and in the park are two such expressions, interpreted by gl and
First, by Theorem 1 of the previous section, we can conclude that stative gz respectively. Then, as we have seen, in the garden and in the park is
locatives are restricting. However, we can easily verify that all of the adverbial interpreted by gl /I. g2' Now, it follows directly from the defmition of inter-
phrases we have been discussing are restricting. Thus, for example, from the secting that gl /\ g2 f 0 if and only if (gl /\ g2) (1) = gl(l) /\ gl(l) f O.
truth of John is working skillfully we can surely conclude that John is working But this is true if and only if there exists at least one individual for which
must be true. Similarly, if Fred is spitting into the tub is true, it must be true gl(1) and g2(1) both take the value 1. In other words, gl /\ g2 f 0 if and
that Fred is spitting. In fact, predicate modifiers which are not restricting are only if in the garden and in the park share at least one atomic location;
rare. We will see examples of such occasionally (including the transparent intuitively, this would mean that the spaces referred to by in the garden
formula-modifier false, discussed later in this section). In general, however, and by in the park overlap. Moreover, a formula like John (sing «in the
PMs support the notion suggested in the previous section on the basis of the garden) and (in the park») would be true just in case that (a) John sing is
APs that modifiers generally are typically restricting. true, and (b) John's location is to be found in the overlap of these spaces. If
Next, since Tp 1 is a complete atomic boolean algebra (by, essentially, the spaces do not overlap at all, then gl /\ g2 = 0, whence (gl /\ g2) if) = 0
Theorem 19 of Section A), we conclude by Theorem 3 of the previous for any PI homomorphism /; in this case, such a formula would automatically
section that IrplITPl is a complete atomic boolean algebra. Let us see what be false.
relevance this has to our system. Now, if we recall that our formulas are intended to be tenseless, then this
The fact that ITPIITPI is a boolean algebra allows us to regard the stative is intuitively correct. In real English, if in the garden and in the park refer
locatives as a boolean category, something we certainly want to do, inasmuch to totally disjoint (i.e. nonoverlapping) areas, then a sentence like John is
as they can be combined with and, or, and not in ordinary English: John is singing in the garden and in the park is understood to refer to at least two
singing in the garden and/or in the park, John is Singing in the garden but not occasions of singing, one in the garden and one in the park, which take place
in the park. The boolean operations on IrP I ITPI' calculated as in Definition
at different times.
Following this train of thought, it seems not unreasonable to define
37 of the previous section, allow such combinations to be interpreted if the
the interpretation of the logical constant everywhere as meaning something
interpretations of the constituent parts are known. For example, if the PI
like 'at every atomic location', which we can formally define as the meet
homomorphism f interprets sing, and if the functions gl and g2 interpret in
of all the atoms in ITP1/TP 1 ' However, except for the case of the boolean
the garden and in the park respectively, then it follows from that definition
that, say, sing in the garden and in the park is interpreted by (gl/\ g2) (f) = algebra with exactly one atom, this meet is always O. Thus, as far as our
gl (f) /\ g2 (f), which is the interpretation of the PI sing in the garden and extensional system is concerned, everywhere is always interpreted as O.
sing in the park. A similar statement can be made for the combination with While this does not seem particularly insightful, it does at least capture the
or. Finally, it follows from that definition that sing not (in the garden) is fact that, for example, in order for a sentence such as John sang everywhere
interpreted as gil (f) =f /\ (gl (f))', that is, as sing and not (sing in the garden). to be true, it is necessary that more than one occasion of singing has to be
These interpretations accord with our intuitions. involved (assuming that the world in which this sentence is supposed to apply
But here too what we have just said about stative locatives holds for all offers more than one possible location). It also has the merit of indicating
(restricting) adverbials. For example, we would certainly want the PI sing rather clearly the direction we will have to go in in order to represent the
({with Mary) and (about peace») to have the same interpretation as (sing with meaning of everywhere in a fully adequate way: we will have to provide for
Mary) and (sing about peace) (and similarly with or replacing and). We will the representation of different occasions of an event-type (such as sing).
still be able to achieve this if we assume that the intensional type of PI is Similarly, if we imagine that the logical constant somewhere means some-
some boolean algebra B; for then the interpretations of the adverbials will be thing like 'at an atomic location', then we would define its interpretation in
in RB IB, which is a boolean algebra, by Theorem 2 of the previous section. any model as being the join of all the atoms in ITP1/TP 1 ; but this join is
Of course, B cannot be the set Tp, that we have defined for our (extensional) always 1. Thus in our system, somewhere is logically redundant; e.g. John
154 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 156 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

core language; we will have to wait until we consider enlarging our system sing and John sing somewhere are logically equivalent. Again, some funda-
to an intensional one before we learn what B should be. mentally non-trivial extension of our system would be needed in order to
Returning to the stative locatives, we note next that ITP1/TP 1 is complete. adequately represent the meaning of somewhere.
The usefulness of this will be easier to appreciate after we discuss the pre· Finally, we would want to define nowhere as always being interpreted to
positions. However, we can anticipate a bit and note that a phrase such as be equivalent to 'at no atomic location', Thus, in any model, nowhere is
in a park will be interpreted as the join of functions each of which could be interpreted as the intersection of the complements of all the atoms· in
thought of as the interpretation of a phrase like in e, where e is an N whose IrPl/TP I (or equivalently, as the complement of the join of all the atoms in
interpretation ranges over all the parks. The completeness of 1TPl/TPl allows Irpi/Tp) However, since the join of all the atoms in an atomic algebra is
this procedure to be well defined even in the case that there is an infinite 1, this means that nowhere is interpreted always as O. Thus, John sings
number of parks. Similar considerations hold for other quantifiers. nowhere is logically false in our system, since, essentially, if this sentence
Again, it appears that completeness is relevant to the analysis of all were true, then it would have to be true that John exists nowhere; but John
(restricting) adverbials, not just to the stative locatives. Thus, for example, exists at the atomic location which he himself defines. This is different
the interpretation of a phrase such as about a number (as in, say, John argued from the usual interpretation of a PI like sings nowhere in real English,
about a number) will be the join of functions each of which can be thought which is, rather, equivalent to not (sing somewhere). In this interpretation,
of as the interpretation of a phrase like about e, where e is an N whose since sing somewhere and sing are logically equivalent, John sings nowhere
interpretation ranges over all the numbers. If the interpretations of these would be eqUivalent to John doesn't sing. We could, of course, define the
adverbials lie in a complete algebra, then this join will be well-defined. This interpretation of the logical constant nowhere in our system in such a way
will be the case if the the intensional type of PI is a complete algebra B; for that when applied to the interpretation of a PI e, the resultant PI would be
then the adverbial interpretations will lie in RB IB, which, by Theorem 2 of equivalent to not (e somewhere), but such an interpretation would not be
the previous section, is complete. a member of ITPI/TP I '
Turning to the matter of atomicity, and again restricting our attention While we are on the subject of atoms, we might point out that the lexical
just to the stative locatives, we recall from the proof and the discussion of stative locative expressions here and there seem to refer to atomic locations,
Theorem 3 of the previous section that Irp I ITp I is atomic because it i5 though, of course, which ones depend on context. In our system, therefore,
in fact isomorphic to Tp l , by Theorem 4' of the previous section. By it seems reasonable to require simply that these expressions be interpreted
the construction used in the proof of this latter theorem it is clear that as atoms. Thus, in a sense, here and there are locational proper nouns. A more
g E ITP1ITP 1 is an atom if and only if g (1) is an atom in Tp 1 . But an atom adequate treatment would require a theory of context.
of Tp) is simply a homomorphism which takes the value I on exactly OnE The notion of atom is potentially available in the more general context
individual, as shown in the proof of Theorem 19, Section A. Thus, th< of adverbials. By Theorem 2 of the previous section, if the algebra B which
stative-Iocative interpretation function g is an atom just in case the PI homo· is the (intensional) type for PI is atomic, then RB/B is atomic. Thus, if
morphism g (1) takes the value 1 on exactly one individual. But, as we saw the type for adverbials turns out to be all of RB/B, then the atoms of this
earlier, g (1) is the interpretation of the PI formed by combining the stative algebra could appear as the interpretations of certain adverbial expressions.
locative which g interprets together with exist. Thus, we may say that atomic However, inasmuch as the definition of these atoms depend on the atoms
locations are those defined by individuals, in the sense that a particulal of the as yet undefined algebra B, we will not attempt a discussion of them
individual is at that location but no other individual is. Thus, a typical atomic here.
location could be described as being 'where John is'. Our system therefor< Let us return now to the general question of classifying the subtypes of
has a rather Leibnitzian, or, perhaps, Einsteinian flavor: space does not exist adverbial expressions. In the case of the restrictive APs, we found that there
absolutely, independent of the individuals which populate it. Rather, spac< were essentially two subtypes of interest: intersecting APs, and scalar APs.
is defined by, or arises from, those individuals. However, the situation for adverbial expressions is much more complicated.
This being the case, it is interesting to reexamine the interpretations 01 In particular, not all nonintersecting restricting adverbials are scalar.
PREDICATE MODIFIERS 157 PREDICATE MODIFIERS 159

To be sure, there are scalar adverbials, the clearest examples of which are Now, we would like our system to be able to represent this sort of fact.
the manner adverbs, such as skillfully, slowly, etc. Note that such adverbs Letting g represent the function which interprets in the park and letting I
compare; we can say John drives more skillfully than Bill. We can also combine be the PI homomorphism which interprets hit Mary, it cannot be the case
such adverbs with very: Fred works very slowly. An adequate representation that g is an intersecting function with I in its domain, for, if it were, then
of these adverbs should account for their scalarity. In principle, the discussion hit Mary in the park would be interpreted (by g(f)) as logically equivalent
of scalarity of APs in the previous section is applicable here too. However, to hit Mary and exist in the park, as we have seen. We therefore have to
since that discussion centered around the notion of a relation defined on the abandon either the notion that g is an intersecting function, or the notion
atoms of the algebra which interprets the modified expression, and since that the interpretation of John hit Mary in the park involved g taking I as an
the scalar adverbs are nontransparent, we cannot reasonably discuss their argument. If we were to take the former course and retain the idea that hit
scalarity until we can define the notion of an intensional atom of a PI, that Mary in the park is interpreted as g (f), then we are faced with the following
is, until we define the atomic algebra B which will be the intensional type problem. Suppose in some model the individuals who hit Mary are exactly
for the category PI. those individuals who sing. Then sing and hit Mary have the same interpreta-
However, we can make one generalization here. Recall that in the previous tion f. But this would mean that sing in the park and hit Mary in the park
section, very was put into the category APjAP, and interpreted as a logical would have the same interpretation, whence, again, hit Mary in the park
r r
constant: in any model, very is interpreted as the function very, defined by would be equivalent to hit Mary and exist in the park in this model (since
very (f) = f2, for each f in its domain. But we surely want to be able to hit Mary is equivalent to sing in this model, and sing in the park is equivalent
combine very with adverbs as well, as we saw above. We can achieve this as to sing and exist in the park). Thus, we are forced to abandon the idea that
follows. We will enter very into the category (AP, PM}/(AP, PM); and we will hit Mary in the park is interpreted as g(f). But this means that we must
r r
interpret it again as the function very defined by means of the same equation abandon the idea that, in this case, in the park combines with the PI hit
as above, but now with a larger domain: f can be either the interpretation of Mary.
an AP or the interpretation of a PM. To deal with this situation, we will do the following. We retain the idea
r
As in the case of intersecting APs, very is logically redundant when that in the park can be a PI modifier, and, as such, is interpreted by an
combined with any expression whose interpretation f satisfies the equation intersecting function. However, we also allow in the park to be a P2 modifier.
f2 = f. For convenience, let us call such expressions idempotent. Formally: This means that it can combine with hit to create the expression hit in the
park; and, moreover, this latter expression is itself a Pz . To form the repre-
DEFINITION 17. Let e be a modifier (that is, an expression of category sentation in our language of the English sentence John hit Mary in the park,
X/X, for some X). Then e is idempotent iff, for any model, the function f this P2 is combined first with the N Mary and then with the N John. We thus
which interprets it satisfies f2 = f. wind up with the expression; John «hit (in the park» Mary).
In the case of APs, we saw that intersecting expressions were necessarily What we have done, of course, is allow in the park to be a member of
idempotent; this is the content of Theorem 6 of the previous section. In the the category (PI, P 2 )/(P I , P 2 ). As such, it will be interpreted by a function
case of adverbials, the same theorem shows that stative locatives are neces- g: Tpi U Tp z -+ Tpi U Tpz such that if IE Tpi then g (f) E TpI' and if
sarily idempotent. However, they may not be the only ones. For example, h E Tpz then g (h) E TP2' In order to insure that the logical properties
assuming that, say, «sing (about peace» (about peace») is a well·formed described earlier for PIS like sing in the park are correctly represented, the
Pi> we would certainly want it to be logically equivalent to sing (about peace). restriction of g to Tpi must be required to be an intersecting function.
Similar statements can be made for the other types of adverbials mentioned However, to insure that the logical properties of hit Mary in the park are
above, with the exception of the manner adverbials, which are, as we have properly represented, a further condition must be imposed on g. Clearly,
seen, clearly scalar, and hence nonidempotent. Thus adverbials provide ex- if Ij and 1m are the individuals which interpret John and Mary respectively,
amples of nontransparent idempotent modifiers. Theorem 7' of the previous and if h is the P2 homomorphism which interprets hit, then we want the
section is not immediately applicable to these. At this point we leave open equation
158 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 160 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

the question of whether the idempotency of these expressions should auto· (8)
matically follow as a consequence of other properties they must be required
to have, or whether they should be specifically subcategorized as being to hold. Note that on the right hand side of this equation, '1' refers to the
idempotent (by means of a feature). unit element of the PI (not the P2 ) algebra, that is, to the interpretation of
We now wish to consider a classification of PMs along a rather different exist. Thus, this equation says exactly that John hit Mary in the park has
line. In so doing, we will have to abandon the idea that PMs should be reo the same truth value as John hit Mary and Mary exist in the park.
garded syntactically as PI modifiers. We begin our discussion again with the We have just seen that there is motivation for regarding stative locatives
case of stative locatives, whose properties can be represented within the as P2 modifiers as well as PI modifiers. We will see shortly that similar
framework of an extensional system. motivation exists in the case of a substantial number of other PM types.
We noted earlier that a stative locative such as in the park appears to We therefore propose to generalize the definition of the category PM along
behave as an intersecting PI modifier. Our example was the formula John the lines suggested above for stative locatives. However, rather than setting
(sing (in the park)), which is true in a model just in case John sing and John PM = (PI, P2 >/(P I , P2 >, we will make use of the fact that we have a category
(exist (in the park)) are both true. In this case, the PM in the park is combined Pn of n-place predicates defmed for any nonnegative n, and say that a PM
with a lexical PI sing. However, when a stative locative is combined with a is an expression which can be a Pn modifier for any n ;;;;, 1. Thus, we have:
PI consisting of a transitive verb together with an object fl, the logical facts
are often different. DEFINITION 18. PM = (PI"" ,Pn ,·· ->/(PI , ... ,Pn , .. .>.
Consider, for example, the real English sentence John hit Mary in the park.
If this is true, then certainly we can conclude that John hit Mary is true. For convenience, we will abbreviate this as PM =(Pn/Pn ).
Moreover, if by 'hit' the speaker's intention is to refer to, say, an act of In the case of the stative locatives, we saw that an interpreting function
slapping or punching, in which a part of John's body comes into violent must be intersecting when restricted to Tp I ' and that such a function must
contact with a part of Mary's body, then we can conclude that John was in also satisfy Equation (8). We will be interested in imposing similar conditions
the park is true. So far, then, this sentence seems to be working the same as on other classes ofPMs. We therefore make the following definitions.
a sentence like John sang in the park.
However, we can note immediately that there is something else which DEFINITION 19. Let S be a set of categories. Then F(S)/(S) is the set of
can be concluded from John hit Mary in the park, namely the truth of Us
those functions f from eE Te into itself such that, for each c E S, if x E Te,
Mary was in the park. This suggests the possibility that John hit Mary in thenf(x)ETe·
the park might be logically equivalent to the three sentences: John hit Mary,
John was in the park, Mary was in the park. Thus, F(S)/(S) is the set of all functions which are possible candidates for
But this is not true. The reason is that hit might not refer to an event in membership in T(S)/(S).
which a part of John's body comes into violent contact with a part of Mary's
body. The sentence John hit Mary could be used to indicate that a rock DEFINITION 20. The function g E F(Pn/P n ), is argument-oriented of degree
thrown by John came into violent contact with a part of Mary's body, or n iff, for each f E Tpn and for each set of n individuals II, ... , In the fol-
that a bullet shot from a gun by John came into violent contact with a part lowing equation holds:
of Mary's body. Now, if John hit Mary in the park is uttered with such
an event in mind, then, while it is true that Mary was in the park can be
concluded, we cannot conclude the truth of John was in the park. Taking
the various senses of 'hit' into consideration, then, it seems to us that the where, on the right hand side, '1' refers to the unit element of Tpl'
sentence John hit Mary in the park is logically equivalent to the two sentences
John hit Mary and Mary was in the park. The reader will note that it follows directly from the definitions that g is
argument-oriented of degree 1 iff the restriction of g to Tp I is intersecting.
PREDICATE MODIFIERS 161 PREDICATE MODIFIERS 163

DEFINITION 21. The function g E T(Pn/P n ) is argument-oriented iff it is locative can be combined with a P 2 and two Ns in two ways. Either the
argument-oriented of degree n for every n ;;:. 1. stative locative combines first with P2 to create a compound P 2 which is
then combined with the Ns, as in:
We can now say that, by our earlier discussion, the function which interprets
a stative locative must be required to be argument-oriented. (9) John «call (in Boston)) Bill)
Now, we noted earlier that, when viewed merely as P 1 modifiers, stative
locatives formed a boolean category whose type was a complete atomic or else the P2 combines with its object N to create a PI which is then com-
boolean algebra. Moreover, we pointed out that the category of PMs in bined with the stative locative, as in:
general should be regarded as boolean, and that there was motivation for
(10) John «call Bill) (in Boston)).
hoping that TpM might be at least complete. Having defined the category
PM not as that of P1 modifiers, but rather as in Definition 21, we must In general, we want to have both possibilities at our disposal. However,
reexamine the matter of a boolean structure for TpM. It is clear that TpM while certain English sentences appear to be genuinely ambiguous, such as
must be a subset of F(Pn/P n >. However, the definitions and theorems of the John called Bill in Boston (which may be interpreted either as in (9) or
last section do not apply directly, since the elements of F(PnIP n > are not as in (10)), many English sentences seem to allow only one of the possible
functions from a single boolean algebra into itself. Nevertheless, the essentials interpretations. Thus, we have already seen that John hit Mary in the garden
can be carried over, as will be seen in the proofs of the theorems we are requires that Mary be in the garden; similar facts hold for John saw/shot/
about to give. As before, we present this material in a slightly more general washed/heard Mary in the garden. On the other hand, if the transitive verb
form than is needed just for the PMs. We begin with two definitions which is properly intensional, the locative phrase apparently never applies to the
supersede Definition 19 above. object. Thus, John criticized Mary in the garden definitely requires that
John be in the garden, but puts no demands on Mary. In addition, certain
DEFINITION 22. Let S be a set of sets. A function f: Us Us is a proper
--i> verbs denoting the creation of their objects require that the locative apply
function iff, for each XES, if x E X, then f (x) EX. to the subject: if John sang a song in the garden is true, then surely John was
in the garden.
DEFINITION 23. Let S be a set of sets. Then PFs/s == if: f E F US/US
We will not attempt to represent facts such as these formally in our
and f is a proper function}.
system. One way to do so, of course, would be to restrict the syntax of our
DEFINITION 24. Let A be a set of boolean algebras and let f E PFA/A. Then language (say, by appropriate features) so that, for example, an expression
f is restricting iff f (x) ~ x for each x in the domain off. like John «criticize (in the garden)) Mary) could not be constructed. How-
ever, such a method of sub categorization of transitive verbs would become
Note that by Definition 22, f (x) and x in this definition are members of the rather complex, for a reason we shall see shortly. Another possible line of
same boolean algebra, so that it makes sense to ask whether or not f (x) ~ x attack might be to change the interpretation of stative locative expressions
is satisfied. in such a way as to become sensitive to the transitive verb with which it is
combined. For now, we prefer to leave the matter open.
DEFINITION 25. Let A be a set of boolean algebras. Then PRAIA This almost completes our discussion of the extensional members of the
{f: f E PFA /A and f is restricting}. category <Pn/Pn >. However, before proceeding to other categories, let us
consider the notion of argument-orientation as it may apply to other PMs.
We can now state the following theorem:
Facts similar to the ones we have seen in connection with stative locatives
THEOREM 10. Let A be a non-empty set of disjoint boolean algebras. Then will provide further justification for taking the category PM to be <Pn/Pn>.
PRA/A is a boolean algebra under the operations 1\ , V , and I defined as
Consider source PMs, which we identify here as prepositional phrases
follows: containing the preposition from. A phrase like from the bus denotes the
162 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 164 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

(a) Let gl, g2 E PRA IA . Then, for each x E UA, beginning point of a trajectory of motion executed by some entity, or else
(gl/\ g2)(X) = gl (x) /\ g2 (x). the beginning point of a trajectory describing the progress or effect of the
(b) Letg l ,g2 EPRAIA. Then, for each x E UA, action of some entity. The entity in question may be the one denoted by the
(gl v g2) (x) =gl (x) V g2 (x). subject or the object ii, and, in some cases, there is ambiguity.
(c) Let g E PRAIA. Then, for each x E UA, An example of an ambiguous case is the sentence John grabbed the child
g'(x) =(g(x))'/\ x. from the bus. On one reading, perhaps the more common one, John is, say,
on the platform outside the bus, and the child is initially on the bus. John
Moreover, if each algebra in A is complete, then PRAIA is complete, and if then grabs the child, causing it to move through a trajectory whose initial
each algebra inA is atomic, then PRAIA is atomic. point is on/at the bus and whose final point is, presumably, near John. On
the other reading, John is on the bus, the child is, say, on the platform, and
Since, even in the intensional system, almost all PMs are restricting, we will John grabs the child and brings it into the bus with him. In this reading, the
restrict our attention to the algebra PRA IA. If A = {TP n : n ~ I}, then phrase from the bus denotes the initial point of the trajectory of action
we will use the obvious notation PR(PnIPn > for the algebra of restricting performed by John.
functions in F(PnIP n ). The following theorem is easy but important: An ambiguity of this sort can be handled if we assume that the phrase from
the bus is a member of the category <Pn/Pn>(rather than, say, just PI/PI), and
THEOREM 11. If g E F(PnIP n > is argument-oriented, then g is restricting. if we further assume that this phrase is, in some sense, argument oriented.
The following two sentences can then be constructed in our language:
Let us denote the set of argument-oriented functions in F(P n IP n > by
AO(PnIPn >' Then, Theorem 11 says that AO(PnIPn ) ~ PR(PnIPn >' However, (11) John «grab (from the bus)) (the child))
we can say more: (12) John «grab (the child)) (from the bus))

THEOREM 12. AO(Pn/Pn) is a complete subalgebra ofPR(Pn/Pn>' Moreover,


AO(PnIPn > is atomic. In (11), from the bus is construed as a P2 modifier. Since the phrase is
argument-oriented, its denotation will involve the denotation of the argument
In fact, it is still the case that an atomic argument-oriented function is defined of the phrase which it forms, namely, the argument of grab (from the bus).
by a single individual. Thus, our earlier discussion concerning somewhere, But the argument of this phrase is the child. Thus, in (11), the source phrase
everywhere, nowhere, here, and there, as well as the interpretation of boolean denotes the initial point of the trajectory performed by the child. This,
combinations of stative locatives, carries over essentially unchanged. Precisely, then, corresponds to the first of the two readings of the English sentence
we can say the following: John grabbed the child from the bus.
In (12), from the bus is construed as a PI modifier. Again, since the
THEOREM 13. Let h: Tp l ...,. AO(PnIP n ) be defined as follows: for each phrase is argument-oriented, its denotation will involve the denotation of the
g E Tp l , and for eachfE TP n , (h(g)) (f) is that element of TP n such that, argument of the phrase which it forms, but this time, it forms the PI (grab
for individuals II, ... , In, «h(g)) (f)) (In)··· (Id = f(In) ... (II) f\g(In)· (the child)) (from the bus). Since the argument of this PI is John, the source
Then h is an isomorphism of Tp l onto AO(Pn/P n >' phrase denotes the initial point of the trajectory performed by John. This
corresponds to the second of the two readings of John grabbed the child
Let us explicitly take note of the fact that by regarding stative locatives as from the bus.
members of the category (Pn/Pn> rather than PdP l , we are automatically As in the case of the stative locatives, the facts depend on the transitive
allowing more than one way to combine a given stative locative with an verb involved. For example, if the verb is one of perception, a source phrase
n-place predicate (if n ~ 1) and various noun phrases. For example, a stative refers unambiguously to the subject. Thus, in the sentences
PREDICATE MODIFIERS 165 PREDICATE MODIFIERS 167

saw some way of representing the meaning of from the garden so that, in this
watched case,John (exist (in the garden» is at least entailed.
spied on But the situation is worse in other cases. Consider, say, John «throw
(13) John Mary from the garden
studied (from the roof) Mary). By our definitions earlier, this would be equivalent
observed to (John (throw Mary» and (Mary (exist (from the roof). Here it is not
touched even clear that we want to say that Mary (exist (from the roof) entails Mary
(exist (on the roof), although the latter sentence must surely have been
John is in the garden, and the source phrase refers to the conceived trajectory true at a moment just prior to the instant at which John threw Mary off the
of John's perception. On the other hand, in the sentences roof.
What we want, of course, is for a sentence such as Mary (exist (from
(14) John { knOcked} Mary from the roof the roof) to represent, in our language, the situation of the roof being
t h rew
the initial point of a trajectory executed by Mary (either by virtue of her
the source phrase seems to refer unambiguously to the trajectory of motion actually moving along that trajectory, or at least by her performing some
executed by the denotation of the object, that is, by Mary. Sentences like action which follows that trajectory, in some sense). It seems to us not
unreasonable that a single interpretation such as this might be adequate
( 15) John {shot } Mary from the roof both for John «throw (from the roof) Mary) and for Mary «see Sally)
pelted
(from the garden», say. If so, then it is perfectly reasonable to include
seem to us ambiguous, with either John on the roof shooting or pelting Mary, source phrases in our extensional system as argument-oriented members of
or with Mary initially on the roof and falling off as a result of being shot or (PnIPn). But even if there are difficulties with the idea of source phrases
pelted. being extensional, the facts we have been looking at here suggest strongly
Incidentally, if we compare these facts with the facts concerning stative that they should definitely be regarded as argument-oriented modifiers
locatives, we note a difficulty in handling the matter by means of subcate- capable of being combined with P2 s as well as with PI s.
gorization of the transitive verbs. Namely, particular transitive verbs do not Certain other classes of PMs besides the stative locatives and the source
behave the same with respect to stative locatives as they do with respect phrases exhibit facts which suggest that they should be viewed as argument-
to source phrases. In particular, stative locatives with transitive verbs of oriented modifiers which can be combined with P 2 s as well as with PIS. For
perception (like see, observe) apply to the object, whereas, as we have just example, in the sentence John saw Bill with Mary, the most usual interpreta-
seen, source phrases with the same verbs apply to the subject. Thus, we tion involves the idea that Bill is with Mary. However, in the sentence John
cannot simply subcategorize these verbs either to insure that a PM combines saw the show with Mary, the interpretation is that John is with Mary. These
with them before they are combined with an object, or to insure conversely facts can be accounted for by regarding with Mary as an argument-oriented
that they combine with an object before a PM is combined with them. Of PM. Then, the representation of John saw Bill with Mary in our system will
course, if the PMs themselves are subcategorized, then such a subcategorization be John «see (with Mary» Bill) which will be logically equivalent to (John
of transitive verbs becomes possible, with the same verb being subcategorized (see Bill) and (Bill (exist (with Mary»). On the other hand, John saw the
to respond differently to PMs of different SUbtypes. show with Mary will be represented as John «see (the show)) (with Mary»,
Having accepted the idea that source phrases are argument-oriented which is logically equivalent to (John (see (the show» and (John (exist (with
members of category (Pn/Pn>, let us reexamine the issue of their exten- Mary»). However, we will not pursue the analysis of these PMs here. Nor will
sionality or proper intensionality. We must be careful, in examining this we further examine other classes ofPMs.
issue, not to confuse the use of a particular source phrase as a PI modifier Before leaving the PMs, let us reexamine our analysis of the source phrases
with the use of the same phrase as a P z modifier. With this taken into con- from a somewhat different point of view. We recall that source phrases were
sideration, it seems to us that source phrases are extensional. seen to refer to the initial point of a trajectory executed either by the subject
166 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 168 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Suppose, for example, that those individuals who see Mary at a particular or by the object. However, those instances in which the source phrase involves
instant are exactly those individuals who spy on Karg at that instant. Then, the object seem typically to be sentences containing a causative verb of
surely, the individuals who see Mary from the control tower are exactly motion. Now, it is not out of the question that such verbs should be analyzed
those who spy on Karg from the control tower. For, those who see Mary as consisting, in some sense, of a verb cause combined with an (intransitive)
from the control tower are just those individuals who see Mary and who verb of motion; thus, for example, John threw Mary from the roof might be
are in the control tower; and similarly, those who spy on Karg from the represented as John «cause (by throwing)) (Mary (from the roof))), roughly.
control tower are just those who spy on Karg and who are in the control Note that in this structure from the roof involves the subject of the sentence
tower. Thus, since the Mary-seers and the Karg-spiers are the same individuals of which it is most immediately a member.
in this world, the same set of individuals is obtained when either of these This being the case, let us suppose, for the moment, that source phrases
sets is intersected with the set of those individuals in the control tower. always refer to the initial point of the trajectory executed by the subject,
Note that a source phrase when used with the transitive verbs see and spy but never by any other argument of an n·place predicate. Then our analysis
on refers to the subject in both cases. suggested above is incorrect: source phrases are not argument-oriented
Next, suppose that at a certain instant the verbs throw and kick have the members of the category (PnIPn ). A simple way to handle them would be
same interpretation. This means that if individual II is throwing individual just to regard source phrases as intersecting members of PdP I . Then, source
12 at that instant, then II is also kicking 12 at that instant, and conversely. phrases would be restricted to combine only with PI s (so that a transitive
It seems that, given this, if II is throwing 12 from the roof, then II must verb would have to combine with its object first before the source phrase
(since he is kicking 12) also be kicking 12 from the roof, and conversely. In could apply to it ), and they would necessarily involve the subject.
both cases, from the roof denotes the initial point of the trajectory through However, suppose that reasons are found for wanting source phrases to
which 12 moves. Note that a source phrase when used with the transitive be able to combine with P2 s as well as with PIS. If so, a different approach
verbs throw and kick refers to the object to both cases. would be required. To see how this could be handled, let us make the fol-
This being the case, we can include source phrases in our system at the lowing definitions:
extensional level. They will be categorized as argument-oriented members
of the category (Pn/Pn>, just as the stative locatives were. They will differ DEFINITION 26. The function g E F<PnIP n > is subject-oriented of degree n
from the stative locatives in that the transitive verbs with which they can iff, for eachf E TP n and for each set of n individuals II, .. .,In, the following
function as P2 modifiers will not be the same as the transitive verbs with equation holds:
which the stative locatives can.
However, this approach leads to a difficulty of a different sort, which we
can see by examining Definitions 20 and 21. If we interpret from the garden
where, on the right hand side, '1' refers to the unit element of Tp l .
as an extensional, argument-oriented PM, then John «see Mary) (from the
garden)) turns out to be equivalent to (John (see Mary)) and (John (exist Note that g is subject-oriented of degree 1 iff the restriction of g to Tp I
(from the garden))). The difficulty resides, of course, in the second conjunct is intersecting.
John (exist (from the garden)). On the one hand, it is not clear that we would
want to allow such a sentence to be constructed. On the other hand, if we do DEFINITION 27. The function g E F<PnIP n > is subject-oriented iff it is
allow its construction, it is not particularly clear that it is a viable representa- subject-oriented of degree n for every n > 1.
. tion of the semantics involved. One approach we could take would be to
require (say, by a meaning postulate) that from the garden and in the garden Theorems similar to the ones given earlier for argument-oriented functions
be logically equivalent; surely, John saw Mary from the garden is at least can also be given for subject-oriented functions. Thus, we have:
logically equivalent to John saw Mary and John was in the garden, even if
these two are not completely synonymous. Alternatively, there might be THEOREM 14. If g E F(P n IP n > is subject-oriented, then g is restricting.
PREDICATE MODIFIERS 169 PREDICATE MODIFIERS 171

If we let SO(P n /P n ) denote the set of subject-oriented functions in F(Pn/P n ), (20) fdO) = 0,/tC1) = 1
then we have: (21) f[(O) = 1,/[(1)=0

It seems reasonable to include the lexical expressions true and false in our
THEOREM 15. SO(Pn/P n ) is a complete subalgebra ofPR<Pn/Pn)' Moreover, extensional language as members of the category Po/Po. These will be logical
SO(Pn/P n ) is atomic. constants: we require that in any model, true be interpreted as the function
ft defined in (20), and false be interpreted as f[ defined in (21). Thus, if e
And, more precisely:
is any formula in our language, then true e (which can be thought of as
THEOREM 16. Let h: TpI -+ S0<Pn/P n ) be defined as follows: for each representing the English sentence it is true that e) will be a formula whose
truth value in any model is the same as the truth value of e. Similary,/alse e
gE Tpl' and for each f E TP n , (h(g)) if) is that element of Tpn such that,
(representing it is false that e) will be a formula whose truth value in any
for individuals II, ... ,In, «h(g)) if)) (In)··· (II) = f(In) ... (IJ) I\g(Id· model is the opposite of the truth value of e.
Then h is an isomorphism of TpI onto SO(Pn/P n )'

Now, even if we permit source phrases to be members of the category (Pn/Pn), Proofs of Theorems from This Section
so that they can modify n-place predicates for all n ;;;. 1, they will still involve
Our first theorem is:
the subject if we require that their interpretations be subject-oriented func-
tions. Thus, suppose we form the sentence
THEOREM 10. Let A be a non-empty set of disjoint boolean algebras. Then
(I 6) John «see (from the garden)) Mary) PRAIA is a boolean algebra under the operations A , V , and' defined as
follows:
By the equation in Definition 26, this sentence will be logically equivalent to
(I 7) (John (see Mary)) and (John (exist (from the garden))) (a) Letg 1 ,g2 EPRAIA. Then, for each x E UA,
(gl A g2)(X) = gl (x) /\ g2(X).
which is what we want. Of course, (16) will also be equivalent to (b) Letg 1 ,g2 EPRAIA. Then, for each x E UA,
(I 8) John «see Mary) (from the garden)) (gl V g2) (x) =gl(X) V g2(X).
(c) Let g E PRAIA. Then, for each x E UA,
The duplication illustrated by (16) and (18) is an undesirable feature of this g'(x) = (g (x», A x.
approach, unless reasons can be found for wanting to distinguish between
these two structures. Except for this point, it is an adequate analysis of Moreover, if each algebra in A is complete, then PRAIA is complete, and if
source phrases to assign them to the category (Pn/Pn > and to require that each algebra in A is atomic, then PRA IA is atomic.
they be interpreted by subject-oriented functions, provided, as we said earlier,
that causative verbs of motion are broken down into a cause component and This theorem is an extension of Theorem 2 of the previous section on APs.
a separate intransitive motion verb component (or are optionally broken To prove it, our general method is to consider the restrictions of functions
down in this way, as in the case of verbs like grab, shoot, pelt, etc.; see (11) in PRAIA to the algebras which comprise the collection A and to apply that
and ( 15) above). earlier theorem.
It is reasonable here to wonder whether we have any reason for wanting We first show that gl /\ g2 as defined in (a) is a member of PRA IA. Clearly,
exclusively subject oriented source phrases to ever combine with P2 s to gl /\ g2 is a function from UA into UA; we have to show that it is a proper
form complex P2 s. One such reason is given by the interaction of such function, and that it is restricting.
P 2 s with Passive. We refer the reader here to the later section on Valency To show that it is a proper function, choose x E UA arbitrary. Then, for
Affecting Operators noting only the broad outlines of our analysis here. If one algebra B E A, x E B. Since gl and g2 are proper functions, gl (x) and
170 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 172 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

P is a P 2 interpretation then its passive, pass (P), is a P 1 denotation which g2(X) are members of B, whence so is g\(x) 1\ g2(X), since B is a boolean
holds of an individual x iff for some individual y, (P (x)) (y) holds. Now if algebra. Thus, if x E B, then (g \ II g2)(X) E B, so gill g 2 is a proper function.
the predicate of Mary was seen from the garden is analyzed as the passive To show that this function is restricting, let B be an arbitrary member
of the complex P 2 see from the garden, it will hold of Mary just in case (see of A. Since gland g 2 are restricting functions, their restrictions to Bare
from the garden) (Mary) holds of some individual y. And this will, correctly, restricting functions from B into itself; that is, the restrictions of gl and
entail that y, the individual who saw Mary, was in the garden. But if from gz are members of RB/B· By Theorem 2, the restriction of gl 1\ gz to B is
the garden could only be analyzed as a modifier of the P 1 was seen (= {pass, a member of RBIB; thus, for any x E B, (gl II gz) (x) <x in B. Since any x
see}) then Mary was seen from the garden would, incorrectly, entail that in the domain of gj II g2 is an element of one B, this proves that gl II g2 is
Mary was in the garden. restricting as a function from UA into UA.
Even if the analysis of source phrases as subject-oriented does not turn out The proofs that g I V g 2 as defined in (b) and g' as defined in (c) are
to be the best approach we shall still need the concept of subject-orientation members of PRA IA are similar and will be omitted.
to represent the semantics of agentive by-phrases in passives. Specifically by The fact that the axioms of a boolean algebra are satisfied by the opera-
Mary in John was kissed by Mary is subject oriented in that semantically it tions in PRA IA follow from the fact that these axioms are satisfied by
predicates something of the subject argument of the P 2 kiss: it says that the restrictions of the functions in PRAIA to individual algebras in A. For
that argument is identical to Mary. A formal semantics for agentive by is example, to prove that gl II (g2 v g3) = (gj II g2) V (gill g3) for arbitrary gil
given in our later section on Passives. g2, and g3 E PRAIA, we have to show that (gl II (g2 v g3)) (x) = «gill g2) v
This completes our presentation of the predicate modifiers in the exten- (gi II g3)) (x) for each x E UA. However, for one boolean algebra B EA,
sional system. Before closing this section, we make two additional comments. x E B, whence this equation holds, since the restrictions of gl g2, and g3
I

First, at least some PMs should probably be viewed as members of the to B are members of RBIB, and, by Theorem 2, RBIB is a boolean algebra.
category <N, Pn>j(N, Pn> (or even of (Nm, Pn>j<Nm, Pn> (see the later section By this approach, we see immediately that the zero element in PRAIA is
on transitive common noun phrases)), in order to be able to form expressions the function 0: UA -* UA such that 0 (x) = OB for each x E UA, where B
like man in the garden. Such an expression would be an N, interpreted by is the boolean algebra in the collection A which contains x. Similarly, the unit
the property which is contained in exactly those individuals each of which element of PRAIA is the function 1: UA -* UA such that 1 (x) = x for each
both contains the property which interprets man and is mapped onto 1 by x EA. It is clear that, for a given B E A, the restrictions of 0 and 1 to Bare
the interpretation of exist in the garden. (Loosely, an individual has the just the zero and unit elements of RBIB, so that the axioms which involve
property which interprets man in the garden iff that individual is a man and o and 1 must be satisfied in PRA lA, since these axioms are satisfied in each
is in the garden.) We omit a formal statement of this here. RB IB, by an argument parallel to the one given above for the distributive
Secondly, we note that our account above does not provide for the possi- axiom.
bility of expressions of the category Po/Po. Clearly, there are such expres- Let us next note that the proof of the lemma of Theorem 2 carries over
sions, which we are going to want in our system, such as possible, necessary, unchanged to PRAIA' We can conclude from this that if gi, gz E PRAIA,
etc. However, the vast majority of them are propertly intensional, and so we then gl ..:;; gz iff this relation holds for the restrictions of gl and g2 to B,
defer detailed discussion until we develop our intensional system. At the foreachBEA.
extensional level, we note here that since Tpo has only two elements, namely Suppose now that every B in A is a complete algebra. Let K c;:: PRA IA
o and 1, there are only four functions which are available as extensional be an arbitrary subset. For each x E UA, define g (x) = 1\ {k (x) : k E K}.
interpretations of expressions of category Po/Po. These functions are fo, Comparing this with the definition in the comparable part of the proof of
f1' ft, and ff' defined by: Theorem 2, we see. that the restriction of g to B (for each B EA) is just the
glb of the restrictions of the elements of K to B, viewed as members of RBIB.
(18) fo (0) =fo (1) = 0 In particular, g is well defined. It is obvious that g is a proper function; and
(19) f1 (0) =f1 (1) = 1 the proof that g is restricting is exactly the same as in that previous theorem.
PREDICATE MODIFIERS 173 PREDICATE MODIFIERS 175

Thus, g E PRA IA . Moreover, since the lemma of the section applies to PRA IA , PR(PnIP n ), since g/(l) = (g(l»)' f\ 1 = (g(l)'. But the last equality shows
the proof that g = glb K here is exactly the same as the proof in the earlier that g' is argument-oriented of degree n. Therefore, if g is argument-oriented
theorem. Thus, arbitrary subsets of PRA IA have greatest lower bounds, and, of all positive degrees, so is g / .
dually, least upper bounds, so that PRAIA is complete. This shows that AO(PnIPn ) is closed under II , V , and '. Let us now check
Finally, suppose that each B in A is atomic. For each BJ E A, for each that 0 and 1 are members of AO(Pn/Pn)' First, we have, on the one hand,
atom a E B J , and for each bE BJ such that a < b, define gab; UA -+ UA o (f) (In) ... (II) = 0 (In) .,. (II) = 0, and on the other hand,f(In) ...
as follows. Let x E UA. If x E B 2 , where B z fBI, then gab (x) = 0B2' If (Id II 0 (1) (In) = [(In) ... (Id II 0 (In) = [(In} ... (Id II 0 = O. (We leave
x E B I , then, if x f b, gab (x) = OBI; and gab (b) = a. It is obvious that gab it to the reader to supply the justifications for the equalities.) Thus, 0 (f)
is a proper and restricting function, that is, a member of PRAIA. Moreover, (In) ... (II) = [(In) ... (Id II 0 (l)(In), so 0 is argument-oriented of degree
the restriction of gab to any other algebra in the collection A is the zero of n. Since n is arbitrary, 0 is argument-oriented.
its restricting algebra. Again, since the lemma is valid for PRA lA, the proof Secondly, 1 (f) (In) ... (II) = [(In) ... (Id. On the other hand'/(In) ...
that fab is an atom, given in the proof of Theorem 2, carries over intact to (II) II 1 (1) (In) =[(In) ... (Id 111 (In) =[(In)· .. (Id 111 = [(In) . .. (Id.
yield that ga b is an atom in PRA IA. Similarly, we can prove that PRA IA is Thus, 1 (I) (In) ... (Id =[(In) ... (Id II 1 (1) (In), so 1 is argument-or-
atomic: let g E PRAIA, with g f O. Then for some x E UA, g (x) fOB, where iented of degree n. Since n is arbitrary, 1 is argument-oriented.
B is the algebra containing x. Since g is restricting, g (x) < x, whence x f OB, Thus, AO(PnIPn ) is a subalgebra ofPR(PnIPn ), The fact that it is complete
and since B is atomic, there is an atom a E B such that a ,;;;;; x. Thus, gax is and atomic will follow from Theorem 13, to be proved below, since TP I is
well defined for the elements a and x we have just chosen. But, gax < g, a complete and atomic algebra. Alternatively, these facts can be verified
exactly as in the proof of the earlier theorem. This completes the proof. directly for AO(PnIPn ), For example, if K <: AO(PnIPn ) is an arbitrary subset,
Our next theorem concerns the argument-oriented elements of PR(PnIPn )' then, since K is a subset of PR(PnIP n ), and since the latter is complete, by
Theorem 10 above, I\K and VK are well defined. It is a straightforward
THEOREM 12. AO(PnIPn ) is a complete subalgebra ofPR(PnIPn )' Moreover, matter to show directly that these are argument-oriented; we leave this to the
AO(PnIPn ) is atomic. reader.
As to atomicity, the situation here is similar to what we saw in the last
The fact that A0<PnIPn) is a sub algebra of PR(PnIPn ), will follow if we can
section concerning IBIB for the case that B is atomic. Just as the atoms
show that it is closed under the operations 1\, v, and , and that AO(PnIPn )
of RBIB are not elements of IBIB, yet IBIB contains elements which are
contains the elements 0 and 1 ofPR(PnIPn ),
atoms in it but not in RBIB, so the atoms of PR(PnIPn ) are not elements of
Suppose that gl and g2 are argument-oriented of degree n. Let f E Tpn
AO(PnIPn ), yet this subalgebra contains elements which are atoms in it but
be arbitrary, and let!1 , .. . ,In be n arbitrary individuals. Then we have:
not in PR(PnIPn ), It is clear from the construction in Theorem 13, to be
«gl 1\ g2) (I) (In) ... (II) =(gl (I) 1\ g2 (I) (In) ... (II) proved shortly, that the atoms of AO(PnIPn ) are just those argument-oriented
=(gl (I) (In) 1\ g2 (I) (In» (In-I) ... (II) functions g such that g (1 Tp I) is true for exactly one individual only. In-
where the first equality follows from the definition of 1\ in PR(PnIP n ), and cidentally, it is almost obvious from the definition of argument-orientation,
and essentially proved as part of Theorem 13 (where it is shown that h
the second equality follows from the definition of 1\ in TP n . Iterating the
is one-to-one and onto), that an argument-oriented function is completely
procedure which gave us this second equality, we get finally:
determined by its value on ITP I ' Without further delay, let us proceed to:
«gll\ g2)(I)(In ) ... (It> =
= (gl (I» (In) ... (II) 1\ (g2 (I) (In) ... (II) THEOREM 13. Let h: Tp i -+ AO(PnIPn ) be defined as follows: for each
= [f(In) ... (II) 1\ gl (1) (In)] 1\ [f(In) ... (II) 1\ g2 (1) (In)] g E TP I , and for each [E TP n , (h (g» (f) is that element of TP n such that,
=f(In) ... (II) 1\ [gl (1) (In) 1\ g2 (l)(In)] for individuals II, ... , In, «h (g» (f» (In) ... (Id =[(In) . .. (Id II g (In).
=f(In) ... (II) 1\ (gl 1\ g2)(1 )(In). Then h is an isomorphism of Tp j onto AO(PnIPn ),
174 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 176 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Using the fact that gl and g2 are argument-oriented of degree n in the second Let g be an arbitrary member of Tpl. We show first that h (g) is indeed an
equality, the commutative, associative and idempotent laws in the third argument-oriented function. (That it is a proper function from U n
Tp into
n
equality, and the definition of II in PR(Pn/P n ) in the fourth equality. But itself is obvious.) Applying h (g) to the unit element of Tpi and letting
the fourth equality shows that gl II g2 is argument-oriented of degree n. If I be an arbitrary individual, we have, using the definition of h, as well as the
gl and g2 are argument-oriented of all positive degrees, then so is gl A g2. properties of the unit of Tp I ' that «h (g» (1) (I) = 1 (I) 1\ g (I) = 1 1\ g (I)
The proof that gl v g2 is argument-oriented of degree n if gl and g2 are =g (I). Since this is true for an arbitrary individual I, we have shown that
is exactly parallel as regards the equation: (h (g» (1) = g. Substituting this in the equation which defines h, we get
«h (g» (f) (In) ... (Id = [(In) ... (Id 1\ (h (g» (1) (In), which shows
«gi v g2)(f) (In)·· . (II) = that h (g) is argument-oriented of degree n. Since n was arbitrary, h (g) is
= [f(In) ... (II) II gi (l)(In)] V [f(In) ... (Id II g2 (l)(In)]· argument-oriented.
Next, we show that h is a homomorphism by showing that it preserves
The next step is to use the distributive law, and then the definition of v in meets and complements.
PR(Pn/P n ) to get: To show that h preserves meets, let gl and g2 be arbitrary elements of
TPI. If [E Tpn and II, .. .,In are arbitrary individuals, then we have:
«gl v g2)(f) (In)··· (II) =f(In)· .. (Id II [gi (l)(In) V g2 (1) (In)]
= f(In)··· (II) II (gi v g2)(I)(In) h (gl 1\ g2) (f) (In) ... (Id = [(In) ... (Id 1\ (gl 1\ g2) (In)

which shows that gi v g2 is argument-oriented of degree n. Again, if gi and =[(In) ... (Id 1\ gl (In) 1\ g2(In)
g2 are argument-oriented of all positive degrees, then so is g 1 V g2. = [[(In) ... (Id 1\ gl (In)] 1\[[(In) ... (Id 1\ g2 (In)]
Finally, suppose that g is argument-oriented of degree n. We have first = h (gd (f) (In) ... (Id 1\ h (g2)(f) (In) ... (Id
that
where the first equality follows from the definition of h, the second by
(g' (f) (In) ... (II) = «g (f» , A f) (In) ... (II) the definition of 1\ in Tp I ' the third by the commutative, associative, and
= [«g (f)) (In» , A f(In)] (In-l) ... (II) idempotent laws, and the fourth by the definition of h. But the fourth
equality shows that h preserves meets.
where the first equality follows from the definition of' in PR(Pn/Pn ), and the To show that h preserves complements, let g be an arbitrary element
second equality follows from the definitions of II and of ' in Tpn. Iterating of TP I . Again, if [E TP n and II, ... , In are arbitrary individuals, we have:
the procedure which gave us the second equality, we get eventually:
h (g') (f) (In) ... (II) =[(In) ... (II) 1\ g' (In)
(g' (f) (In) ... (II) = «g (f))(In) ... (Id) , II f (In) ... (II) = [(In) ... (II) 1\ (g (In» ,
= (f(In)··· (IdA g(I) (In»)' IIf(In)··· (Id = [[(In) ... (Id 1\ ([(In) ... (Id) ']
= [(f(In)··· (Id)' v (g(1) (In))'] A f(In)··· (II) V[f(In) ... (Id 1\ (g(In» ']
=0 v [f(In) .. . (II) A (g(1) (In))'] = [(In) ... (II)1\ [([(In) . .. (II» , V (g (In» ']
=f(In)··· (II) II (g(l)' (In) =[(In)··· (Id 1\ [[(In) ... (Id I\g(In)] ,
=f(In) ... (II) A g' (1) (In) =[(In) ... (Id 1\ [h (g)(f) (In) ... (Id] ,
=(h (g»' (f) (In).·· (II)
where the second equality follows from the fact that g is argument-oriented
of degre~ n, the third follows from the deMorgan laws, the fourth from where the first equality follows from the definition of h, the second from
the distributive law (together with x A x' = 0), the fifth from the definition the definition of ' in Tp I' the third from x 1\ x' = 0 and 0 V x = x, the fourth
of ' in Tp 1 (together with 0 v x = x), and the sixth from the definition of' in from the distributive law, the fifth from DeMorgan's law, the sixth from the
PREDICATIVES 177 PREDICA TIVES 179

definition of h, and the seventh from the definition of I in AO<Pn/Pn ). But a plausible tree structure for John handed the book to Bill would be:
the seventh equality shows that h preserves complements. Since h preserves
meets and complements, h is a homomorphism. (22)
To show that h is an isomorphism, we must show that h is one-to-one,
and that h is onto.
To show that h is one-to-one, suppose that gl, g2 E TP 1, and that gl nom

nofJ~ ~N
=f: g2· Then, since a PI homomorphism is determined by its values on the
individuals, there must be some individual, say I, such that gl (I) =f: g2 (I).
Then, letting 1 be the unit of Tp j , we have, from the definitions, that h (gl)
(1)(1) = 1 (I) /\ gl (I) = 1/\ gl (I) =gl (I), and similarly h (g2)(1)(1) =g2 (I). / --------- R
Thus, h (gd (1) (I) =f: h (g2) (1) (I), whence h (gd (1) =f:h (g2) (1), whence P3 /\
nom[to ace ~
h (gd =f:h (gz), so that h is indeed one-to-one.
To show that h is onto, let k be an arbitrary member of AO<Pn/Pn ). Set the book
John hand Bill
g = k (lTP1). Then g E Tpl' and we have, for arbitrary [E Tpn and individ- nom to ace
ualsI l , . . . ,In:
Note that the tree structure in (22) uniquely determines that Bill will be
(h (g» (f) (In) ... (II) = [(In) ... (II) /\ g (In)
case marked to, since Bill is the argument of the P 2 hand the book which
=[(In) ... (Id /\ k (1) (In) is marked as imposing to on its argument.
=(k (f) (In) ... (II) To simplify the case marking notation (in the few cases where we shall use
it at all) we shall adopt the following conventions: (1) the argument of a PI
where the first equality follows from the definition of h, the second from will be understood as nominative unless marked otherwise; (2) argument of
the definition of g (here, '1' means the unit of Tp 1 , of course), and the third any n-place Pred other than PI will be understood as accusative unless marked
from the fact that k is argument-oriented. But the third equality shows that otherwise; (3) when informally representing expressions in our language by
h (g) = k. This shows that h is onto, and completes the proof of Theorem 13. strings of words, overtly indicated case markers will be given in parentheses
The remaining theorems of this section are 14, 15, and 16. It will be next to the N they are imposed on. Thus our linear informal represen ta tion of
noticed that these theorems are exactly parallel to Theorems 10, 12 and 13, (22) above is simply John hand the book (to) Bill. The finite set CM of case
markers for English will include a variety of abstract elements such as nom,
with the notion of subject-orientation replacing that of argument-orientation.
We leave it to the reader to convince himself that the proofs given above for ace, to, of, and (homophones of) most lexically simple prepositions.
Theorems 10, 12, and 13 are transformed into proofs for Theorems 14-16 What about the types for the new subcategories of n-place Pred we have
introduced above? Given that Pn is a subcategory of Pn we know
simply by replacing the appropriate occurrences of the symbol In by II. (c,' ... , en)
that its type must be a subset of Tpw If the case marking is semantically
irrelevant we could take TPn = TPn as previously defined. But by
3. PREDICATIVES (c" . . . , cn)
the remarks on the Overview if case marking is semantically irrelevant we
Syntactically we use the cover term predicative (Pred for short) to refer to have no motivation for including that notation in our logical structures at all.
categories of expressions which combine withNs to form derived expressions. There appear to be, however, several sorts of semantic motivation for
In the Intensional Logic in Part II the category N is generalized to that of including case marking at a level of logical form. For one thing, there appear
Argument Category and Preds are expressions which combine with Argu- to be n-place Preds which are semantically distinct but which differ formally
ments. New Argument categories will include S (= sentence complements), only with respect to the case marker they impose on their argument. Consider
PI (= infinitival nominals). for example the semantic differences between call (= call) and call for
nom ace
The new Preds we treat here are: 'transitive' common nouns (friend of, (= call), or ask and ask for. The items taking their arguments with for
nom for
178 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 180 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

etc.), 'transitive' adjective phrases (fond of, etc.), ditransitive verb phrases, are non-transparent on their argument, whereas the accusative ones appear to
and prepositions. The construction of the types for these new categories be transparent. Thus in a situation in which the only doctor is the President of
follows the pattern established for the Preds considered in Section A (the the bank, John asked a doctor to attend to the sick must have the same truth
n ;;" 0 place predicates): in each case the new category is of the form C/N, value as John asked the President of the bank to attend to the sick. But John
where Te is a complete and atomic boolean algebra. The type for the category asked for a doctor to attend to the sick can be true in such a situation even
then may be represented as the set of complete homomorphisms from TN though John asked for the President of the bank to attend to the sick is false.
into Te, exactly as was done for the type for Pn+l (= Pn/N). The empirical Moreover, calling all case markers other than non and ace obliques (ob!),
adequacy of defining the new types in this way is justified in the appropriate it seems likely, following Anderson (1971), that there will exist regularities
subsections below. Here we merely underline that a nice advantage of our in the interpretations of Pz's which differ only with regard to whether their
system is that the types for (first order) predicatives in general are an im- argument is ace or obI. Thus the difference between shoot and shoot at is,
mediate generalization of the basic cases of Preds considered in Section A. very roughly, that the object of shoot at is less wholly affected by the action
The generalization is significant in that the new categories seem syntactically than when it is the object of shoot. Similarly with plow vs. plow in, etc.
fairly diverse. We turn now to a detailed consideration of the new categories. We might be inclined to represent these regularities by imposing a general
constraint on the lexical interpreting function M such that M ( e )
(nom acc)

Preliminary Remarks on Case Marking .;;;; M C( e b ). This would guarantee for example that if John plowed the
nom 0 I)
field then he plowed in the field. While this generalization is doubtless too
We have so far ignored the fact that the n-place Preds of L impose case on gross, it seems right enough as a first approximation to support the claim
their arguments. E.g. PI s normally take their argument in the nominative that items which differ regularly in case marking differ regularly in semantic
(nom), Pzs in the accusative (ace), etc. As such case marking is largely only interpretation, and hence we want case marking represented at a level of
overt on pronominal forms, items we do not explicitly consider here, our semantic interpretation. Moreover E. Moravscik (1978) has shown that such
logical structures have so far not differed appreciably from surface forms in semantic differences extend to a rather wide range of languages (see also
these respects. But many of the new Predswe add to L take less trivial case Keenan, 1979, for further discussion) and in those which are more heavily
marking, and while we shall by and large ignore it in our representations case marked than English in a traditional sense these differences show up in
we do want to indicate how we might incorporate a case marking notation the choice of case marker.
into our system and what the semantic motivation for this might be. Another sort of motivation for including case marking in our logical
In keeping with the generalizations of Keenan (1979) we note that com- structures concerns dependencies between case marking and selectional
monly across languages, expressions interpreted as functions on N denotations restrictions. For example consider that intransitive run implies that its sub-
impose case on their (N) arguments (and moreover may show agreement with ject, if an individual, moves more or less autonomously. We might build in
these arguments). We shall then treat the case markers that a particular Pred this restriction by requiring that for all individuals x, M (run) (x) ';;;;M (move)
imposes on its arguments as part of the representation of that Pred. Thus, (x). Then, given that locative PP's such as through the woods, across the
technically, our representation for the English verb sleep would be sleep, mountain, etc. are restricting, we infer that John ran across the mountain
_ nom
assigned by lexical rule to the category PI (= Po/N), itself a subcategory of entails John ran, which entails John moved. However, the telephone lines run
nom nom
PI (by a subcategory rule). Similarly kiss would be an element of Pz across the mountain does not entail the telephone lines run or the telephone
_ nom acc (nom aee) lines move. So we clearly want telephone lines to be among the possible
(= PliN), a subcategory of Pz. And more generally, for a dny n- tuple
nom ~cc arguments of the interpretation of run across the mountains but not of that
of case markers and c a case marker, Pn+ 1 (= Pn/N) is a subcategory of Pn+ 1 , of run. One prima facie way to capture these facts is to say that in addition
(d, c) d c
and its elements are represented as e . Note then that using this notation, to the PI run we have a P 2 , run which is a member of P2 • We are
(d, c) nom across
a given n-place Pred subcategorized by Cl, . . . ,cn imposes the case marker C n then free to state its selectional restrictions as we like. Furthermore, since
on its argument to yield an n-! place Pred subcategorized for Cl, . . . , Cn - I. across is (at least homophonously) both a case marker and a preposition, we
For example, treating the indirect object to as a case marker (as we will)
PREDICA TIVES 181 PREDICATIVES 183

.ave two logical forms for John ran across Mary according as run across is combined with the No friend of every senator, as in (25). Arguably each
P2 taking Mary as its argument, or run is aP 1 combined with the Predicate structure expresses one way of understanding an expression like (a) non-
10difier across Mary. The latter case would get the interpretation in which friend of every senator so the (admittedly somewhat forced) ambiguity of
cross Mary specifies the path of John's movement (imagine John a dwarf this expression is represented in our system.
nd Marya giant). The former interpretation could be constrained so that
ransitive run across plus human object means something like meet. In any

\!
(24) (non-friend) of every senator
vent we have two logical forms for John ran across Mary and may thus in
Irinciple represent the (admittedly somewhat forced) ambiguity in the
lnglish sentence.
However, as indicated at the beginning of this section, we are not con· f'
~\n[
:erned in this monograph to represent the semantic properties of case marking _____ ~I
illd in consequence shall not generally employ the case marking notation
ntroduced above. It will however be (we think) perspicuous to use that (f')( n I)
sEI
IOtation for certain of the Preds we discuss below which impose oblique
:ase markers, and it is important to realize that the notation we use there can since f' is a homomorphism
Ie given as a quite general extension of the notation used in the core language
; and that its semantic motivation extends beyond the few examples in = 'for every senator, (a) non-friend of his'
vhich we use it. We turn now to the specific extensions of L represented by
he new classes of predicatives mentioned in the introduction to this section.

Transitive Common Noun Phrases


r{e want to enrich L so as to generate structures for R's such as a friend
)f every senator, the father of John or Bill, no friend or colleague of the
?hairman of the department, etc. We may do this very simply by adding
'fiend (of), father (of), etc. to the basic vocabulary V and assigning them
he category N/iI! (more exactly, N/iI!, but we shall usually omit the case
of
narker of). Then the rules of functional application plus the lexical rules we
tlready have will generate expressions like that in (23a) below with the
;tructure given in (23b).
=( A . f(I))' sincefis a homomorphism
SEI
(23) a. a friend of every senator =(V (f(I))') de Morgan laws
8EI
b. N =(8 ~ r (f') (I)) pointwise definition of'
R/N------ _________ N
= 'for some senator, (a) non-friend of his'
N/iI!-------- - - - R
I R/N-------------r
Note that while the ambiguity in the scope of non- may seem somewhat
artificial, there is a similar scope ambiguity with regard to nominal modifiers
a friend of Jery senator which we can capture in a similar way.
182 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 184 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Using the Predicative Hierarchy notation developed earlier we may abbreviate Modifiers ofn-place Common Nouns
the category of friend (of), etc. as N l . More explicitly, PHN or the predicative
Hierarchy generated by N, is the set of categories N n , where No 'abbreviates' We have been treating the adjective phrases as the category No/No. But given
N, and Nn+l abbreviates Nn/N. (The Predicative Hierarchy generated by P now the nominal hierarchy of N n we have defined it is easy to extend the
recall is the set of categories Pn , where Po = P and Pn +l = PnIN). domain of APs to be modifiers of Nn's in general. On this analysis then the
The types we associate with these new (non-empty) categories is given lexical APs would be entered into the category <NnINn>(= <No, N 1 , .• .> I
inductively by: TN 0 =TN, a primitive of the model, and TNn+l =HTNn/Tii, <No, N l , .. .>. And the type for that category would be the set of proper
the set of complete homomorphisms from TN into TN n' regarded as a com- functions from TN n into TN n (so if p is in TN n then f(P) is in TN n ) which
plete and atomic boolean algebra where the operations are defined pointwise are restricting (for all n and all p in TN n,f (P) "" p). The set of such!,s is
on the individuals. So elements of TN 1 are c-homomorphisms from full NP a restricting algebra as per Theorem 10.
denotations into common noun denotations. This choice of type of course While this extension of TAP is algebraically both easy and natural, is there
makes a variety of predictions concerning semantic equivalence of English any motivation from the valid arguments of English for such an extension?
expressions. It means for example that the friend of John or Bill property It appears that there is. Thus consider the classically noted ambiguity in
is the same as the friend of John or friend of Bill property. Thus Harry is a expressions like an old friend of John, a good friend of John, etc. On the
friend of John or Bill iff he is a friend of John or a friend of Bill, a correct one hand the first expression might denote properties which an individual
prediction. Similarly since friend of preserves arbitrary meets we have that has iff he is a long-time friend of John; and on the other hand the expression
the friend of every senator property is the same as the meet of the friend might denote properties of individuals who are friends of John and old
of x property taken over all individuals x with the senator property. Whence (either absolutely or perhaps just relative to friends of John). In any case
it follows that Mary is a friend of every senator iff for every senator, Mary the ambiguity seems naturally representable as a function of the scope of
is a friend of his, again a correct prediction. And finally, since friend of old, good, etc. And on the proposed extension such expressions have two
preserves complements it follows that friend of no senator expresses the logical structures which differ injust this way:
same property as non- [friend of a senator] , whence Mary is a friend of no
senator iff she fails to have the friend of a senator property. (26) No

<Nn/Nn>~ ~
Notice that a different set of correct predictions follows from taking
TN 1 as an algebra defined pointwise on the individuals. This means, recall,
No
that where f and g are elements of TN 1 and x is an individual, (f A g) ex) =
/~­
I
f (x) A g (x), and (f v g) (x) = f(x) v g ex), and (f') (x) = (f(x)) '. Thus
for x an individual, it follows that John has the friend or colleague of Bill
property iff he has the friend of Bill property or the colleague of Bill pro-
perty, which is correct. Of course these equalities fail in general if x is a set
fl/
old friend (of) John
of properties which is not an individual. Thus the property expressed by
friend or colleague of every senator is the property an individual has iff (27)
for every senator he is a friend of x or a colleague of x. But the property
expressed by friend of every senator or colleague of every senator is one an
individual has iff either he is a friend of every senator or a colleague of
every senator. Similarly consider the two non-equivalent logical structures
presented below. They differ with respect to the scope of non-, according
as it has combined directly with the Nl friend to form a derived Nl (the
complement of friend in the Nl algebra) as in (24), or according as it has
PREDICATIVES 185 PREDICATIVES 187

Moreover, in the absence of further restrictions on TNn/N n , these two condition obtains iff h(!) = 1. Thus Ig(h) and h assign the same values to the
structures are not logically equivalent. The first one is any property g which individuals, and by the Justification Theorem they assign the same values to
~ friend of John. In the second what we know is that old friend is a Nl every set of properties Q. Thuslg(h) = h.
semantically ~ friend, whence (old friend) (of) John is ~ friend of John. (3) This last fact basically tells us that g, restricted to Tp I ' is an isomor-
But since old friend can be any element of TN 1 less than or equal to friend, phism from Tpi onto TN o ' For recall from Theorem 20, Section A, that
its value on John need not be g above, that is, it need not be the same as the the function I from TN 0 into Tp I which sends each property ponto Ip, is
value of old on the friend of John property. So this analysis says that if an an isomorphism. Hence its inverse I-I is an isomorphism from Tp I into
individual has either of the properties denoted by (26) and (27) then he TN 0; in fact g = I-I. From the definition of inverse we have for all h in
has the friend of John property, which seems correct. On the other hand, TPI I-I (h) = p iff 1(P) = h. In particular r l (h) = g (h) iff I(g (h)) = h,

an individual can have either of the properties (26) and (27) without having and I (g (h)) is simply Ig(h)' So the latter equation holds by the end of
the other, which also seems correct. remark 2. Since h was arbitrary, we have that I-I = g, so g restricted to
This analysis also yields some interesting predictions concerning the scope Tp I is an isomorphism onto TN 0 .
of old relative to quantified NPs. Thus if John is an (old friend) (of) every (4) The semantic relations expressed by g and I above seem so simple
senator, then for every individual x with the senator property, John is a and natural that we might reasonably expect a natural language to have
long-time friend of his. On the other hand, if John has the old (friend (of) ways of expressing these relations. Specifically for g, it appears (by and
every senator) property then John is merely a friend of every senator and is large) that the nominalizer -er transforms many PI'S into No's in such a
old (either relative to individuals generally or if old in this usage is 'merely' way that p in PI holds of an individual iff that individual has the property
restricting, relative to the friends of every senator). And while these inter- expressed by p+er. E.g. John swims iff John has the property expressed by
pretations are slightly forced, they seem more right than wrong, and thus swimmer (= swim+er).
support the correctness of the extended analysis of APs. What about I? Given a common noun phrase such as doctor, English
and indeed all languages have a regular way to assert that an individual, say
John, has that property. English does it with the 'is a' construction. That
Some Relations Between Nominals and Predicates
is, on the semantics we have given be and a it follows that (be (a doctor)
We have defined then two Predicative hierarchies, that generated by Tpo and holds of John iff the property which interprets doctor is a member of the
that generated by TN o. These hierarchies are not independent. In fact we individual which interprets John. Since be and a are both logical constants,
have already shown that Tp 1 is isomorphic to TN 0' and it should not be we may conclude that English has a regular way of converting common
surprising (we prove this below) that for every n ;;;;. 0, TPn+l is isomorphic nouns into PI'S. Many languages of course would perform this conversion
to TN n' This isomorphism has considerable linguistic interest. For one thing more directly. At a decent guess only half the world's languages would use an
it tells us as a special case that TN l ' the type for the 'transitive' common overt copula (be) to express John is a doctor, and still fewer would use an
noun phrases, is isomorphic to Tp2' the transitive verb phrases, thereby indefinite article.
justifying formally our pre theoretical intuition that father (of), friend (of), (5) Consider now clause (b) of the definition of g. The simplest and
etc. should be called transitive even though they only take one argument. most relevant case is for n = 1. Then h is a member of Tp2' a transitive
More interestingly, however, accepting that there is a general correspon- verb phrase denotation, and g (h) is a member of TN I ' a transitive common
dence between surface form and logical form, we can now (once we prove noun denotation. Further, for any individual x, h (x) is a member of TPI'
the theorem) justify that we should expect the internal structure of Nt's to a one place predicate denotation, and (g (h)) (x) is a property in TN o' The
be similar to that for P2 's, since semantically the types for these two sets definition says that that property is just the one which h ex) asserts of its
are highly similar, in fact isomorphic. And much recent work in linguistics, argument. So for example taking h as the interpretation of employ and
beginning perhaps with Chomsky (1973), has pointed out several such syn- interpreting er now as the isomorphism g, we have that employ+er is that
tactic similarities between the internal structures of 'noun phrases' and NI which maps an individual, say Bill, onto the property (emp!oy+er (on
186 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 188 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

that of 'verb phrases', e.g. destroy the city/destruction (of) the city, etc. BilT) which the PI employ Bill asserts of its argument. Thus it follows that
While we do not represent abstract nominals like destruction in our exten- John employs Bill is true iff John has the 'employer of Bill' property, that
sional language, we can extend the core language by some nominalizing is, iff John is an employer of Bill. This result is particularly nice and provides
functions which derive n-place nominals from n+ 1 place predicates. In fact, serious justification for our treatment of NI's and P2 's, since the naive
the agent nominalizer er (swim .... swim+er) will be interpreted as the natural semantics for employer, treating it as a property in TN 0 which an individual
isomorphism (defmed below) from TPn+l into TN n , for each n;;;;' O. From has iff he employs someone, is not sufficient to guarantee that he is an
this fact alone then the logical equivalences of the a-/b- sentences below employer of Bill iff he employs Bill. Something further on that approach
follow: would have to be said about how 'PP's' like of Bill combine with No's to
form further No's. But on our treatment nothing else of that sort need be
(28) a. John swims said. It is sufficient to defme the types for the relevant n-place Preds as we
b. John is a swim+er have done, and interpret er as g in Theorem 17, namely as the generalized
(29) a. John employs Bill isomorphism from TP n+l into TN n all n;;;;: O.
b. John is an employ+er (of) Bill
(30) a. John contributes money (to) the church Proof of Theorem 17.
b. John is a contribute+er (of) money (to) the church By induction on n; the case for n = 0 has already been proven in Remark
3 above, so for arbitrary n, assume the theorem holds for all m < n. We show
Let us first prove the existence of the natural isomorphism referred to above it holds for n. By the induction hypothesis we have that for all m < n, g is an
and then show how the equivalences follow. isomorphism from TP m +l into TN m' We must show g to be an isomorphism
from TP n +l into TN n .
THEOREM 17. The function g defined below is, for all n;;;;' 0, an isomorphism (i) g is a homomorphism
from TPn+l onto TN n : (a) g preserves complements.
We must show that for all h in TP n +l g (h') = (g (h)) I, that is, that these two
g is a function from n ~ 0 TP n +l into n ~ 0 TN n defined re- homomorphisms have the same value at every individual x. (Note that for all
cursively as follows: Pn +l homomorphisms k, g (k) is a homomorphism in TN n by clause (b) since
a. for n = 0 and all hE TP n +l' g (h) is that element of TN 0 such the Justification Theorem tells us that we can define homomorphisms in TN n
that for all individuals I, g (h) E I iff h (J) = 1; by stating their values on the individuals in any way we like). So in particular
b. for n > 0 and h E TP n +l' g (h) is that element of TN n such that g (h') is in TN n . Now,
for all individuals I, (g (h)) (J) = g (h (J)).
(g (h')) (x) =g(h'(x)) by definition of g,
Remarks on Theorem 17: = g«h (x)') defmition of' in TP n + 1
(1) In clause (a) we define a property, g (h), by stating what individuals = (g (h (x))) , h (x) is in TP n so g is an isomorphism by
it is in. By corollary a to Theorem 11, Section A this does defme a property. the induction hypothesis
(2) We call g in clause (a) natural because it picks out, for each one place = (g (h))(x))' definition of g
predicate h, the property which h asserts of its argument. Recall from Sec- =(g(h))' (x) definition of' in TN n
tion A that each such h is an i p for some property p, where i p is that Pi (b) g preserves meets; that is g (h 1\ f) = g (h) 1\ g (f), all h, fin TP n +l .
homomorphism mapping a set of properties Q onto 1 iff p E Q (and onto 0 The proof parallels that in (a) and is left as an exercise for the reader.
otherwise). To say that g (h) is the property h asserts of its argument is just to (ii) g is one-to-one.
say that ig(h) = h. By Definition 36 (Section A) of ig(h) we have that ig(h)(J) Let h, fin TP n +l such that h 'f f. Then for some individual x, h (x) 'f f (x)
= I iff g(h) E I, I any individual, and by the definition of g, this latter (otherwise by the Justification Theorem h = f). So g (h (x)) 'fg(f(x)) since
PREDICATIVES 189 PREDICATIVES 191

hex) and f(x) are in TPn and by the induction hypothesis g is an isomor- verbs and which impose other case markers on their arguments. Examples
phism on Tpw But by the definition ofg, g(h(x)) =(g(h)) (x), andg(f(x)) = would be infatuated with, bored with, fed up with, even in love with, as well
(g(f)) (x). So (g(h) (x) j (g(f)) (x), so g(h) j g(f). as interested in, visible from, addicted to, etc. We shall treat such items here
(iii) g is onto. as lexically primitive as we have no conviction that they can be verbally
For k arbitrary in TN n define h in Tp n + 1 such that for all individuals x, derived in a regular way, that is, in such a way that their interpretation
h (x) = g-I (k (x)). By the Justification Theorem this is a well definition, can be given as a function of that of the verb they are derived from. (And
given that k (x) is in TN n -1 and g is an isomorphism from Tp n into TN n -1 ' note that in many cases, such as fed up with, bored with, there is in fact no
so g-J is an isomorphism from TNn_l onto TP n . Then g (h) = k, since: for obvious verbal source).
x an arbitrary individual, As very little is known either syntactically or semantically about such
transitive adjectives, we shall only attempt a preliminary analysis here, one
(g (h))(x) = g (h (x)) definition of g that can serve as a basis for a more detailed analysis.
=g (g _I (k (x)) definition of h As regards their syntax, let us defme Ao as an abbreviation for No/No,
=k (x) definition of inverse. the adjective phrases already studied. Then, as before, An+l will be the
category An/N. Extend L then by adding fond of etc. to the basic vocabulary
Formally then we may extend L as follows. Add er to the basic vocabulary V, and by lexical rule put them in the category Al (= Ao/N= (No/No) IN).
V, and by lexical rule assign er to the category N n /Pn +l, which abbreviates This then defines another Predicative hierarchy. As with the N1's there
(No, N J , •• .> / (PI, P 2 , •• .>. The type for that category can (for the nonce) appear to be no lexical members of An for n > 1, but again when the variable
be taken as the entire set of proper functions whose domain is the union of binding rules are introduced all such categories will have members.
the types for Pn+l and whose range is included in the union of the types for Semantically we may define the type for An+l in the expected way. That
N n , n ;;a. O. Finally, constrain the lexical interpreting function M such that is, since TA 0 itself is a complete and atomic boolean algebra, we may define,
M (er) is the natural isomorphism g defined in Theorem 17. for all n > 0, TAn+l to be the predicative algebra from TN into TAn. This
claims then that the A 1 's are homomorphisms. This predicts that teacher
fond of John or Mary == teacher fond of John or fond ofMary == teacher fond
Subcategories of N n of John or teacher fond of Mary. And since a join of properties is in an
individual iff at least one of the properties over which we take the join is
Finally, to conclude our discussion of the n-place nominals, we should in it, we have that Bill is a teacher fond of John or Mary iff Bill is a teacher
consider whether these categories present any natural subcategories. They fond of John or Bill is a teacher fond of Mary, which seems basically correct.
will in fact present many such, but few that we can represent within the Similarly if Bill is a teacher fond of no student then Bill must be a teacher
confines of our system. such that for each individual x with the student property, Bill is not (fond
First let us consider one subcategory we can represent. The NJ's we of x). And this seems correct.
have considered are all semantically arbitrary binary relations on the set of Moreover having taken An as boolean, for each n ;;;. 0, we can form expres-
individuals (isomorphic to P z ). However certain of them, such as (biological) sions such as both fond of and jealous of, either bored with or interested in,
father (of), and mother (of) should be constrained to be interpreted by etc. The pointwise defmition of meets, joins, and complements in TA n
relations which are (set theoretically speaking) functional. That is, at most predicts, correctly, that Mary is a teacher either bored with or interested in
one individual can have the property expressed by father of John (on the John iff Mary is a teacher bored with John or interested in John.
literal, biological sense of father). On the other hand we probably do not Notice finally that on the definitions of TAn as given, interpretations
want to require that father (of) be a total function. Even for human indi- of fond of John etc. are merely required to be restricting functions from
viduals it does not seem a logical truth that every man has a father. Hence we properties to properties, not necessarily intersecting ones. Consequently
shall require that expressions like father (of) take their denotations in a
190 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 192 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

proper subset of TN J ; those functions which are such that for every individual we expect that they should accept modification by very, which is correct
x, f (x) is either the 0 element of TN o of f (x) is an atom in TN o ' That as Mary is a teacher very fond of John, very proud of every student, etc.
is, either no individual has the property f (x) or exactly one does. And are sensible. But notice that this analysis predicts that Mary could be a
syntactically we may add the feature pf (for partial function) to SFL and teacher fond of John without being an individual fond of John. It is sufficient
take the type of NJ to be those functions TN J as previously defined which that relative to teachers she is fond of John. If very many people other than
· . pf. b
meet the candItlons gIven a ave. teachers are much fonder of John than she is then she might fail to be an
On the other hand, a great many apparent NJ 's in English do not determine individual fond of John. And while this is slightly forced, it seems more
properties of individuals at all but rather are objects of some more abstract right than wrong.
sort. Some examples would be: (the) edge of the plate, comer of the table, Moreover this analysis together with the natural extension of the domain
sex of the President, temperature of the patient, acceleration of the vehicle, of very makes some interesting predictions concerning scope ambiguities
height of the teacher, etc. None of these expressions naturally occur in or analogous to those discussed earlier for non-. First, extend very as follows:
make sense in contexts like 'John is a ' which is, as we have seen, the very is now assigned the category <An/An> (= <Ao, AI, .. ,) / <A o• AI, . . ,»).
normal way in English to assert that an individual has a certain property. So F or all f in TA 0' the value of M (very) is given as before. And for all fin TA n '
such expressions seem not to denote properties of individuals. Moreover if any n > 0, we merely constraint M (very) so that M (very) (f) ~ f. This
they did, we would be forced to say that e.g. the sex of the President, the guarantees then that (very fond) of John ~ fond of John, as is very (fond of
temperature of the room, etc. could denote individuals, and thus perhaps John); but the two Ao's need not be interpreted as the same element of TA o'
even be things like John, or you, or me, etc. This seems ontologically dubious And this difference seems (delicately) to show up when the argument of fond
at best. Most likely then the ontology of our model would have to be enriched of is not an individual denoting expression. Thus to say that Mary is (very
before proper denotations of such expressions could be provided. So we skirt fond) of every student is to say that for each individual x with the student
this problem by not adding such expressions to L. property, Mary is very fond of x. But to say that Mary is very (fond of
Notice further than many 'abstract' NJ's in English will determine not every student) merely says that she has the fond of every student property
properties of individuals but properties of the social roles or statuses they to a great extent. That guarantees that she is fond of each student, but not
occupy and hence not be transparent (extensional). For example, if the necessarily that she is very fond of each student. Thus she might be fond of
President and the Commander of the Army are the same individual it will every student to a great extent even if there was say one of the 100 students
not follow that the duties of the President and the duties of the Commander in question that she was merely fond of but not very fond of.
of the Army are the same objects (whatever they are). It will follow however
that the sex of the President and the sex of the Commander are the same ob-
Ditransitive Verb Phrases (P 3 's)
ject, so transparency is a logical feature which cross classifies with 'abstract'.
We shall be primarily concerned in this section to enrich L by including
lexical predicates like give, show, and hand which combine with three Ns
Transitive Adjective Phrases
to form a sentence. It might appear that there is little to say here since
There are a variety of lexically simple items in English which appear to we may simply assign them the category P 3 (= P 2 /fIl) by lexical rule and
combine with full NPs to form adjective phrases. Many such items, like the interpret them freely in Tp3 which is already defined as the set of complete
most common lexical Nl 's, impose the case marker of on their NP arguments. homomorphisms from Tjij into Tp 2 . However using the case marking notation
Examples would be fond of, jealous of, envious of, weary of, afraid of, developed earlier there are at least two plausible subcategories of P 3 to which
proud of, etc. as they occur in expressions like a teacher fond of every such predicates might be assigned: P3 and P3 . These assign-
nom to acc nom ace to
student, a soldier weary of the battle, etc. In addition there are many items ments yield different structural analysis of John handed the book (to) Bill,
of a syntactically similar sort which give the appearance of being derived from as follows:
PREDICATIVES 193 PREDICATIVES 195

(31) (34) John hand (to) every student

N P~p, I
j
I
h
~~
fi n
nom
x
no~2to ----------- ~ sEx

~~_

John
P
nnm]'' '
hand
6 N

the book Bill


h( n x)
SEX

(h( n
SEX
x))(
bEy
U y)
(32) Po

fii------~ PI
nom
«h (S Q x)) (b ~y y)) (j)
X

~~- =(bEy
V (h ( n x)) (y)) (j) h (n x)is a homomorphism
P2 ~ N sEx SEx
nom ace
= (V (1\ «h (x)) (y)) (j))) h is a homomorphism
~~- bEy sEX
P~ N
nom a3cc to I = 1 iff for some individual y with the book property it is the
case that for every individual x with the student property,
John gave y to x
John Jnd Bill the book
We add then give, show, hand, etc. to the category P3 and hence-
nom to ace
On the analysis in (31), henceforth the Patient analysis, the 'Patient' NP forth drop the case marking notation.
forms a logical constituent with the P 3 , and the Recipient is the argument Since the type for P 3 consists of homomorphisms we then correctly
of the derived P2 hand the book. On the analysis in (32), henceforth the predict that e.g. John handed a book and a pen to Mary is logically equivalent
Recipient analysis, it is the 'Recipient' which forms a constituent with to John handed a book and handed a pen to Mary, which is correct. And
the P 3 and the Patient NP is the argument of the derived P2 hand (to) Bill. 'since the elements of Tp3 are defined pointwise on individuals we correctly
Of these two analyses we prefer the Patient analysis in (31) since the predict that the sentences in (35) below are all logically equivalent.
two analyses make different predictions concerning the relative scope of
the Patient and Recipient NP's and it is the Patient analysis which makes (35) a. John showed and gave the book to Mary.
the correct predictions. b. John showed the book and gave the book to Mary.
On the Patient analysis the Recipient N will have wide scope over the c. John showed the book to Mary and gave the book to Mary.
Patient N, whereas just the opposite scope assignment will prevail on the d. John showed the book to Mary and John gave the book to Mary.
194 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 196 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Recipient Analysis. (33) below is the semantic tree of John handed a book Finally, with only some abuse we may enrich the subcategories of P 3 to
to every student on the Patient analysis. (x and y range over individuals include, for each c E {in, on, under, next to, ...} the subcategory P3
nom c ace
of course): The types for such categories will be P 3 homomorphisms h which meet the
additional subcategory condition that for all individuals x, y, z h(x)(y)(z)
.;:;; be(c(y))(x). So assigning put to the subcategory P3 we guarantee

\)
(33) Jolm hand a book (to) every student
nom on ace

I
1 ~l
that John puts the book on the table entails the book is on the table. This
seems reasonable given that we have not in our semantics associated activity
j
predicates with time intervals. A more adequate semantics with such an

\;~yy
association would have to guarantee that a certain time relation held between
nx
SEx
the time of putting and the time of being on the table.

Prepositions and Predicate Modifier Hierarchies


h( U y)
bEy
In this section we provide a syntactic and semantic analysis of English
prepositions such as in, at, by, with, from, next to, near, etc. which is com·
patible with our earlier treatment of Predicate Modifiers (PM's). We show

h( U
bEy
y)( n x)
sEx
in particular that the two types of PM's discussed earlier, subject oriented
and argument oriented, are the generators of two Predicative Hierarchies,
PM n : n )0 0 and PMn : n )0 O. The two classes o[PM's discussed earlier are
q ~ -
the PMo's in their hierarchy, and prepositions are PM1's, combining with N's

(h (
bEy
n x))(j)
U y)(sEx
to form PMo's. In the concluding portion of this section we generalize the
treatment of prepositions to allow them to combine directly with Pn's to
formP n +l's.
We assume in what follows, though it plays little direct role in our analysis,
=« SEX
1\ hCbU y))(x))(j)
Ey
h( U
bEy
y) is a homomorphism that English prepositions occur in a variety of homophones. Thus in a richer
treatment than we propose here we should need to distinguish three with's, a
=(1\
SEX
V (h (y))(x)) (j)
bEy
h is a homomorphism withcom to represent the comitative use in John left with Mary, a withinst
to represent the instrumental use in John dug a hole with a spoon, and a
=sEX
1\ V
bEy
«h (y)) (x)) (j)) pointwise definition of !\ and V with man to represent the manner use in John greeted Mary with joy. It is
only the instrumental use of with that we intend to represent here (and that
= 1 iff for every individual x with the student property there only in the intensional logic). Similarly it is only the agentive use of by, as
is an individual y with the book property such that j in the University forbids cheating by students, John was kissed by Mary, etc.
(= Jolm) gave x to y that we intend to represent here. A fuller treatment would include as well
a by/oc as in John sat down by the window, etc. Further, since the only
Clearly then on this analysis every student has wide scope over a book, structures using agentive by in a natural way which we represent in our
the preferred reading of the sentence. On the other hand, on the Recipient system are passives we defer its semantics to the following section on passives.
analysis illustrated below we find that a book was wide scope over every
student, which is not correct. Prepositions as Formers of Predicate Modifiers
Syntactically we treat prepositions as expressions which combine with ii's
PREDICATIVES 197 PREDICA TIVES 199

such as the garden to form PM's such as in the garden. Recall from our earlier =(x3Vb (n /\ i') (x» (s) (j) (n /\ i') in Tprep is a homomorphism
q
treatment that PM was formally the category (Pn/Pn), itself an abbreviation
for (PI, P2 , •• .> / (PI, P2 , ••• ). Moreover we distinguished two subcategories =(x3Vb (n /\ i') (x) (s» (j) pointwise definition of V in TpM
q
of PM's according as they were subject oriented or argument oriented. For-
mally we add the features subj and arg to the logical subcategorization features = Vb «n /\ i') (x) (s) 0) pointwise definition ofv in TPI
X3
of L thereby determining two subcategories of PM, which we will usually
abbreviate PM and PM. These features also determine two subcategories of
subj arg
=
X3
Vb (n (x) /\ (i (x» ') (x) 0) ptwise definition of /\ and' in TPrep
q
preposition: PM/AT and PM/AT, which we commonly abbreviate simply as Prep
sub) arg sub) =X3Vb (n (x) (s) /\ (i (x» , (s» (j) ptwise definition of /\ in TpM
and Prep respectively. We now enrich L to include by (and in the intensional q
arg
logic of Part II with) in the former category and the locative prepositions in, =x Vb «n (x) (s) /\ (s /\ (i (x) (s» '» (j) definition' in TpM
3 arg
at, next to, under, etc. in the latter category. On this syntactic analysis (36a)
below is generated with the structure shown in (36b) (in which we have not, =x3Vb (n (x) (s) (j) /\ s (j) /\ (i (x) (s) (j»') ptwise definition of /\ and'
.
somewhat exceptionally, used all the abbreviations noted above). mTpl
=X3 Vb (n (x) (s) (j) /\ s (j) /\ (s (j) /\ i (x) (1) (j»') definition TpM
q
(36) a. John sing in the garden
b.
=
X3
Vb (n (x) (s) (j) /\ s (j) /\ «s (j» , \I (i (x) (1) (j» '» de Morgan laws

= V b (n (x) (s) (j) /\ s (j) /\ (i (x) (1) (j»' distributivity and laws for
N x3 ~~m~
= V s (j) /\ n (x)(l) (j) /\ s (j) /\ (i)(x) (1) (j» I definition TpM
x3b arg
(Pn/Pn)
I = V
R I x 3 b
n (x) (1) (j) /\ (i (x) (1) (j» , /\ s (j) idempotency, commutativity
d ...
prop (Pn/Pn ) an assocIatIvIty
arg
= 1 iff for some individual x with the bar property, John exist near x and
-~-
it is not the case that John exist in x and John sing
N
(Pn/Pn)/N A Let us now properly generalize the treatment of prepositions so far given.
arg ~
First we have, for ex E {subj, arg}; that Prep is just the second element of the
CI<

John sing il the garden Predicative Hierarchy defined by PM. Explicitly, from the general definition
of Predicative Hierarchy in Section A, we have that PM o = PM as previously
Semantically, argument oriented Preps will be interpreted by functions
defined, and PMn+l = PMnlN. Choosing ex =arg for illustrative purposes, the
from R denotations into argument oriented PM denotations; analogously
types for the elements of the argument oriented Predicative Hierarchy are
for subject oriented Preps. Moreover Prep interpretations are not just random
given in Definition 28:
functions in these sets, they behave homomorphically on their R arguments.
Thus we want the PM in (New York or Chicago) to be interpreted by the same
DEFINITION 28.
function as in New York or in Chicago in order to guarantee for example
that (37a, b) below are logically equivalent. (a) TPMo = AOiPn/Pn) (as per Definition 20)
arg
(37) a. John is singing in (New York or Chicago) (b) TPMn+l = HTPMn/TN, regarded as a complete atomic algebra,
b. John is singing (in New York or in Chicago) arg arg
the operations being defined pointwise on the individuals.
198 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 200 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

This amounts to saying that the interpretation of in must preserve joins. The corresponding subject oriented Predicative Hierarchy is defined as in
Similarly, replacing or by and in the above example we infer that we want Definition 28 replacing arg everywhere by subj.
the interpretation of in to preserve meets. Finally the equivalence of (38a,c) Note then that for a E {subj, arg} the category we have been referring
below is shown if the interpretation of in preserves complements: to as Pr&p is just P~l' Moreover the linguistic intuition that prepositions
are 'transitive' is justified as it is straightforward to prove that the type for
(38) a. John is singing in (New York and not Chicago)
Prep, a: E {subj, arg}, is isomorphic to the type for P2 • Formally,
b. John is singing (in New York and in (not Chicago)) ex
c. John is singing (in New York and not (in Chicago)) THEOREM 18. ForaE {subj, arg}; TPMn is isomorphic to Tp n +1'
a
Note that the types for subject and argument oriented PM's, given earlier Proof sketch. To show that Tp2 is isomorphic to TPMI (= TPrep) define a
as SO(Pn/P n > and AO(Pn/Pn > in Definitions 26 and 20 respectively are subj subj
both complete and atomic boolean algebras isomorphic to the type for PI function k from TP2 into TPrep (= T<Pn/Pn)/N) as follows: For all p E Tp2'
subj subj
(Theorems 13 and 16). It thus makes sense to represent subject and argument k(P) is that homomorphism in TPrep such that for all individuals I, (k(P)) (I)
subj
oriented Preps as homomorphisms whose values are determined by their
= h(P(I)), where h is the isomorphism from TPI into TpMo (= SO<p /P »)
values on the individuals as per the Justification Theorem of Section A. subj n n
And of course we want Prep denotations to lie in a boolean algebra in order defined in Theorem 16. Prove that k is an isomorphism.
to directly interpret booleanly complex elements of Prep, as either in or To conclude this subsection let us note that we have so far been motivated
near, near but not in, etc. as they occur in sentences like John is singing near to define four Predicative Hierarchies, those associated with n-place predicates,
but not in Chicago. Formally then we define: n-place common nouns, n-place common noun modifiers, and n-place pred-
icate modifiers. This corresponds rather well to the linguistic intuition in
DEFINITION 27. TPrep = HTPM/TR regarded as a complete and atomic current generative grammar that nominal, predicate, adjective, and preposition
suli] subj
boolean algebra where the operations are defined pointwise on the individuals. are the fundamental grammatical categories. Of note however is that the
elementary expressions in PM o will not be bare prepositions combining with
Replacing subj by arg in the above definition we obtain that for TPrep. Using
arg Pn's to form Pn's, but rather will be expressions like here and there (and
Definition 27 (and our previous definitions) we can show in (39) below that perhaps expressions like Eastwards, leftwards, bogwards, etc. if lexically
John is singing near bu t not in some bar will be interpreted to mean for some simple). We may note that bare Preps do sometimes seem to combine with
bar, John is near it and John is not in it and John is singing. (x and y range Pn's to formPn 's as illustrated in (40) below:
over individuals of course.)
(40) a. John sleeps in on Saturdays
(39) John sing

j
I Is «n'(l~t('\J)) b. The project fell through
c. John talked on (and on).

The meaning of the 'prepositions' in these constructions seems however only


idiosyncratically related to their use as PM) 's, so we prefer to treat such
n 1\ i' Ub X derived PI'S as sleep in (= sleep late), etc. as independent basic expressions
~X3
related idiosyncratically by constraints on the lexical interpreting function
(n 1\ i')( Ub x) M to the PI'S they are apparently derived from.
L_------X3

(nl\i')( Ubx)(s)
x3

(n 1\ i')(
X 3
Ub x)(s) (j)
PREDICA TIVES 201 VALENCY AFFECTING OPERATIONS 203

Prepositions as Verbal Extensors independently existing Predicate Modifiers in which a non-subject noun
phrase semantically binds the subject argument. To our knowledge this
The analysis of prepositions given above can be extended in several directions. treatment of agent phrases is novel and is the only one in the literature
One which is of some interest is a usage common in many languages such as which explicitly treats agent phrases as 'semantic subjects' but not 'syntactic
Latin and Kinyarwanda (and other Bantu languages) in which prepositions subjects'. Finally, we conclude with some curiosities regarding the logical
appear to combine with Pn's to form Pn+l 'so Thus for a Latin P z such as nature of Passives and their relation to actually occurring passives in natural
ferre 'to carry' we may form P3 's such as trans+ferre 'to carry across', in+ferre languages. This includes a generalization of the Passive operator to all the
'to carry into' , ex+ferre (= efferre) 'to carry from', etc. Predicative Hierarchies we have discussed so far.
Extending the syntax and semantics of Preps to accommodate this usage
is quite easy in our system. First, for a E {subj, arg}, Prep would be the
- ~ A Generalized Passive Operator
category <Pn/Pn , Pn+l) / <N. Pn ). Functions in the corresponding type would
~

be ones which, restricted to TN behaved as the appropriate sort of PM! 's as In Keenan (I 981), an extensive cross language study of passives, it is sup-
already defined. The value of such a function f at a Pn denotation is given ported that the most widespread type of passive structure is that illustrated
in (41) below, where f is assumed to be argument oriented for simplicity of in (44b) below:
presentation:
(44) a. John kissed Mary
(41) f (P) is that element of TPn+l such that for all individuals 1[, b. Mary was kissed
I z , ... , I n+l, (f(P)) (Id ... (In+d = (f(Id (P»)(I 2 ) . . . (In+l)' c. Some individual kissed Mary

This definition guarantees for example that (42a, b) below are logically
equivalent: The meaning of (44b), at least up to logical eqUivalence, is given in (44c).
Clearly the main predicate of (44b) is a P 1 and, it would appear, equally
(42) a. John (slept (in the bed» clearly that that P 1 is a syntactic/morphological function of the P 2 kiss.
b. John ((slept in) (the bed» We shall refer to the P1 was kissed in (44b) as a passive predicate. Keenan
(op. cit.) shows that the general form of such predicates across languages is
In (42b) the Prep in has combined with the P! slept to form a P z slept in. given by (45) below:
Admittedly the motivation in English for assigning a structure like (42b)
to John slept in the bed is not massive. But, as is well known (see Keenan (45) {(AUX),f(P2)}:
and Faltz, 1978 for further discussion) some motivation does exist. Namely,
while P 2 's in English have passive forms, e.g. was kissed formed as the passive
of the P z kiss (see the next section for an extensive discussion of passives), Here P2 is an expression of category P 2 and! is a strictly morphological
Pj's do not form passives in English, e.g. *was slept from sleep. But (43) function. That is, !(P2) differs from P2 in strictly morphological ways -
below appears to instantiate a passive form corresponding to the Pz in affixing or internal vowel change. Thus a passive P 1 may consist optionally,
(42b). Thus in order to generate (43) we are motivated to assign sleep in the depending on the language, of an auxiliary verb together with a strict mor-
category P z . phological function of a P2 • Let us refer to passives of the form in (45) as
canonical passives. We shall first extend L to include canonical passives and
(43) The bed was slept in. then further extend L to include various non-canonical passives, specifically
ones in which the predicate passivized is not aP2 and ones in which an agent
This completes our analysis of prepositions. Unless noted otherwise we only phrase is present.
202 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 204 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

assume the PM analysis in the subsequent sections. We turn now to the DEFINITION 29. Canonical Passives
treatment of Valency Affecting Operations, most specifically Passives.
a. Syntax: add the single symbol pass to the basic vocabulary V
and assign it by lexical rule to the category P liP 2
4. VALENCY AFFECTING OPERATIONS
b. Semantics: M (pass) is that function from Tp 2 into TP I such that
Languages present quite a variety of operations which derive predicates from for all p E TP 2 and all individuals x, M (pass) (P) (x) = (p (x))
predicates by modifying in some way their valency, that is, the number and (V y), where y ranges over all individuals
arrangement of their arguments. In the last section for example we saw that
some languages derive Pn +l'S from Pn's by adjoining a 'preposition' to the Thus (44b) is represented in L as (46a) below, and its logical equivalence to
Pn . Another, even more common valency increasing operation is causative (44c) is shown in (46b).
formation: many languages can form a P2 translatable as cause to cry by
affixing the PI which translates cry. (46) a. (Mary (pass kiss))
Equally languages may derive predicates from predicates by rearranging b. (Mary (pass kiss))
in various ways the argument structure of the predicate without increasing I
m M (pass) k
I I
or decreasing the number of arguments. Arguably many Bantu languages
for example can derive a P 3 which we might represent as give-to from a P 3
represented as give. The roughly stated semantic relation between the two
predicates is given by: (give-to) (x) (y) (z) = (give) (y) (x) (z). Some linguists
~;;;;(k)
in fact would argue that the relation between give Mary the book and give M (pass) (k) (m)
the book (to) Mary instantiates such an operation, although neither of the
P 3 's appears to be derived from the other in any morphological way. = (k (m)) (Vy) Definition 29b
Finally, languages present many valency decreasing operations. For ex- = V (k (m)) (y) k (m) in Tp l is a homomorphism
y
ample many languages (e.g. Uto-Aztecan) would derive the intransitive = 1 iff for some individual y, (k (m)) (y) = 1, that is some
form of sew as in John is sewing from a transitive form, as in John is sewing individual kiss Mary is true.
a shirt. Again English shows no derivational morphology verb form in these
Note further that where j is the individual which interprets John we have
cases. Another example: many languages derive reflexive and reciprocal
immediately that (k (m)) (j)';;;; V (k (m)) (y) since (k (m)) (j) is one of the
PI'S (in the simplest cases) from P 2 's by affixing theP 2 's. E.g. we may form
elements over which the join <in the right is taken; more specifically, that
selfhit or each other hit from the P 2 hit.
join is an upper bound for a certain set, of which (k (m)) (j) is an element,
It is a matter of considerable linguistic interest to characterize the
and each element of the set is thus';;;; to that upper bound. Thus we have
possible valency affecting operations which natural languages may present.
(for later reference):
In this section we shall be principally concerned with one of these operations,
Passive. THEOREM 19. (John (kiss Mary)) entails (Mary (pass kiss))

Thus our representations for (44a) correctly entails that for (44b).
Passives
Before generalizing Definition 29 to a more adequate view of Passive
Our account of Passive is presented in three major parts. First, we present we shall point out a few of its non-obvious features, ones which contrast
a generalized syntax and semantics for a Passive operator which derives favorably our treatment with certain other treatments in the linguistic lit-
Pn's from Pn +1 's. Second, we present a syntax and semantics for agent erature. We consider specifically sentence level views of Passive and other
phrases (e.g. by Mary in John was kissed by Mary). These are generated as predicate level views, referring the reader to Keenan (1980) for a more
V ALENCY AFFECTING OPERATIONS 205 VALENCY AFFECTING OPERATIONS 207

extended discussion of the contrast, especially as regards syntactic properties favored reading of (52c). It is not ambiguous. We exhibit its interpretation
of passives. in (53).

Sentence Level Views (52) a. Some individual kissed every student


b. For some individual x every student y is such that x kissed y
Many modern linguistic approaches to Passive have attempted to treat it as
c. Every student y is such that for some individual x, x kissed y
a relation between sentences (or clauses), not one between predicates as on
d. Every student was kissed
our approach. For English, Passive would be the relation which held between
(47a) and (47b) below, the latter being in various ways depending on the
(53) (every student) (pass kiss)

\) \}
theory derived from the former:
(47) a. NPl VNP 2
b. NP2 be V+en
We shall not examine these views in any detail, but do wish to point out y n
pass (k)
that no sentence level derivational view of Passive can be made to satisfy y~~
the Fregean condition that the interpretation of the derived structure is
given as a function of that from which it is derived. The reason is simple
pass (k)(
y
n y)
3 S
enough: basically there is no regular semantic relation between sentences
of the form (47a, b). In particular sentences of form (47a) do not in general
=y 1\ s ~
(pass (k) (y)) pass (k) in TP 1 is a homomorphism
entail the corresponding sentence of form (47b). For example (48a) below
not only fails to entail (48b), it is actually logically equivalent to its negation,
= 1\ (k (y)) ( Ux) Definition 29 (Ip is the set of all
y~s XElp
individuals, recall)
as illustrated in (49).
= 1\ V k (y)(x)
y ~ S x Elp
(48) a. No individual kissed Mary
b. Mary was kissed 1 iff for every individual y with the student property there
is an individual x such that x kiss y .
(49) (no individual) (kiss Mary)

a
I, 1
\ I
k m
I These examples show clearly that for given choices of NP 1 and NP 2 there
is no regular entailment relation between (47a), NPI V NP 2 , and its passive
~
(a') (1)
V
k (m)
(47b), NP2 be V+en. Whether such an entailment relation obtains depends
in part, as we have shown, on how the NP's are interpreted.
~ In short, if we derive passive sentences from active ones we cannot give
k (m)(a')(l))
the interpretation of the derived structure as a function of the interpretation
=k (m)(a (1))') pointwise definition of' in TDet of the one it is derived from. This condition is of course satisfied if we derive
= (k (m) (a (1))) , k (m) in Tp2 is a homomorphism passive predicates from active ones, as we have done in Definition 29. It
appears then that the only regular semantic relation between actives and
=(k (m)(y3 U 1 y))' Definition of M (a)
passives is the relation between their predicates. Given that relation, and the
=(pass (k) (m)) , Definition 29 noting that all individ- independently motivated semantics for quantified N's, the correct entailment
uaIsy have 1 relations between active and passive sentences are predicted.
= 1 iff (Mary (pass kiss)) is false In addition to satisfying the Fregean condition, predicate level views
206 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 208 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Note that in the above example we have represented the interpretation of of Passive have other more specifically semantic advantages. Here we present
logical constants c by the symbol c itself rather than M (c), a practice we just one. Namely, since pass is a function on P 2 denotations we may, in a
shall continue. more refined treatment than given in Definition 29, make its value depend
Further since each of the sentences in (50) below can be true if (48a) is ort the semantic nature of the P 2 denotation it applies to. For example, in
it follows that none of them entail the passive (48b). the intensional logic of Part II, Pn denotations are distinguished according
as they are transparent on their arguments, and this semantic difference is
(50) No student preserved under Passive. That is, pass (P) must lie in the transparent PI
At most two students denotations if p is a transparent P2 denotation; but pass (P) is not so con-
Neither John nor Fred kissed Mary strained if p is not a transparent P 2 denotation. See Part II for the definition
Fewer than three students of transparency.
No student's father Similarly we would like to distinguish among P 2 denotations ones which
express an activity which affects their argument and ones which do not have
Clearly then active sentences do not in general entail their agentless passives, that property. Call the former activity P2 denotations. If p is an activity
though of course some do as illustrated in Theorem 19. Furthermore the P2 denotation then pass (P) is given as in Defmition 29. But if p is not an
entailment failure cannot be localized to the decreasing character of the activity P 2 denotation, it appears that we should require stronger truth
subject N of the active. For example the sentences in (51a) below, with a conditions for pass (P) (x). Thinking of p as a denotation of, say, respect,
proper noun subject, fail to entail their corresponding passives in (51 b). or admire, or even hate, for John was respected to be true we want to require
something like 'Most individuals who know John respect him', and not
(51) a. exactly two students merely that some individual respected him. Though we don't know how
between five and ten students to state precisely these truth conditions, nor do we attempt to represent in
John kissed at most two students L the difference between activity and non-activity predicates, the point
no student that the Passive operator behaves differently according to the semantic
Mary but not Sue properties of its argument seems valid.
b. Exactly two students
Between five and ten students Predicate Level Views
At most two students were/was kissed
No student Several recent treatments of Passive, notably Bach (1980), Bresnan (1978),
Mary but not Sue Dowty (1978) and Thomason (1976) broadly agree with the treatment
of canonical passives in Definition 29 though they differ in formalism.
Nor would matters improve for the sentence level view of Passive if agent- (Our treatment differs in more serious ways from theirs with regard to the
less passives were to be derived from corresponding actives whose subject treatment of agent phrases and the generalization of Passive to Pn's as well
was some individual. In the first place, if we replace John by some individual as to norninals.) Some of these treatments however (Dowty's and Bresnan's)
in (51 a) the resulting active still does not in general entail the corresponding would syntactically limit the P2 's which could form passives to lexical ones
agentless passive in (51 b). And in the second place, such actives would differ (elements of the basic vocabulary V in our notation).
semantically from their passives with regard to judgments of relative scope This limitation cannot be motivated semantically, whatever its syntactic
as between the subject some individual and a quantified noun phrase object. merits. We cannot tell by looking at an element of TP n whether it is the
Thus consider that (52a) below is most naturally interpreted as a paraphrase interpretation of a lexical or a syntactically complex expression. Obviously
of (5 2b), though at least for some speakers it also has a less favored reading in some state of affairs it is possible that x is hugging y iff x is both hugging
expressed in (52 c). However the agendess passive in (52d) has only the less
VALENCY AFFECTING OPERA nONS 209 VALENCY AFFECTING OPERATIONS 211

and kissing y, so in that state hug and hug and kiss would be interpreted as Assuming we could distinguish perception elements of TPn from others
the same element of TP 2 . More generally it seems that we want to constraint we could then constrain M such that M (from) lay in TPrep and satisfied
the lexical interpreting function so that certain complex Pn's are always (61) below: sub)
interpreted as (approximately) the same as certain lexical ones, e.g. hop and
jump up and down on one foot, brew and make beer, rewrite and write again, (61) Forallindividualsx,YI,···,Yn andallpE TP n
decapitate and remove the head of, etc. + perception
Furthermore there are many cases where we want pass to apply to com- M(from) (x) (P) (YI) ',' . (yn) = P (Yd ( ... (yn) /\
plex P2 's since otherwise we obtain incorrect semantic interpretations. M (at) (x) (1) (yn)
Consider for example P2 's consisting of a P2 and a subject oriented PM
This would guarantee then that John saw Mary from the house entailed that
(Predicate Modifier). The clearest example which we can represent in L is that
John was at the house. Then the passive in (62a) below can be generated as
of agentive by phrases which we treat in the next subsection. Another clear
in (62b), correctly entailing that some individual who saw Mary was at the
case which can be treated in the intensional logic is that of instrumental
house, as per (62c)
PM's, italicized in (54) below.
(62) a. Mary was seen from the house
(54) a. John opened the can with a stick
b. (Mary (pass (see from the house)))
b. John tickled Bobby with afeather
c. John whittled with a knife Po

The sentences in (54) entail, and are perhaps logically equivalent to, the ii~PI
corresponding ones in (55).
P2
(55) a. John used a stick to open the can
b. John used a feather to tickle Bobby P~
2Pn/Pn

(Pn~N
c. John used a knife to whittle

To guarantee these entailment we want to constrain the interpretation


of instrumental with and use. One approach would only put instrumental
Mary pass see
I
from
A
the house
PM's in the category PdP I , so with would be of category (PdPd/N. Then
we could (informally) constrain the lexical interpreting function M as c. M «Mary (pass (see from the house») = 1 iff
follows: for some individualy, M«see from the house) (Mary» (y) = 1
iff for some y, M (see Mary) (y) /\ M «at (the house») (exist» (y)
(56) For all individuals x and y and all p E Tp l , =1
M (with) (x) (P) (y)";;'M (use) (x) (to p) (y)
Once again then allowing complex P 2 's such as see from the house be under
the scope of pass permits us to represent a correct entailment. Conversely,
(see Part II for the interpretation of to p as the individual generated by p.)
if source locatives could only apply to PI'S then (62a) would have to be
This approach however leads to wrong predictions concerning passives.
generated as (63a) below, which would incorrectly entail (63b).
Thus the passive in (57a) would have to be analyzed as in (57b), wrongly
predicting the entailment (57c). (63) a. (Mary «pass see) (from the house»
b. Mary was seen and Mary was at the house
210 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 212 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

(57) a. The can was opened with a stick In fairness we should note that the prima facie motivation for treating
b. Po Passive as purely lexical is that the distinctive passive morphology in English
only shows up on the verb, not elsewhere in complex P 2 's. (Such morphology
N~p! does appear to show up elsewhere in both Turkish and Malagasy passives
however. See Keenan (1980) for examples.) Moreover our syntactic analysis
P~ PdP!
1
of passives as (pass e), for e E P2, does not explicitly assign any morphology
to e. For us then, that morphology assignment rule would have to be stated

~ ~-
L
so as to apply to syntactically complex e's. This in fact is unproblematic.

\ \Z (PIT!) IN
We give an appropriate definition below, assuming that past participle forms
oflexical P2'S are simply listed.

the can pass open with a stick DEFINITION 30. (pass e) = be + en (e), where en (e) =
c. The can used a stick to be opened (a) the past participle of e if e is in V (Le. lexical)
(b) (en(ed,c, en (e2)) ife=(el' c, e2)forc E {and, or}
A correct approach here is achieved if we let with combine with N's to (c) (en(el),g)ife=(el,g)forg EPMU {not}
form subject oriented PM's and constrain its interpretation as follows:
Thus en (see from the house) = (en (see), (from the house)) by clause (c)
above, which equals (seen, from the house) by clause (a). Essentially then
(58) For all individualsx,y!, .. .,Yn and allp E TP n ,
the past participle forms of complex P2 's is given recursively as a function
M (with) (x) (P) (Yl) ... (yn) ..;; M (use) (x) (to p) (Yl) ... (yn)
of what they are formed from; that for lexical P2'S is given ad hocly.
Since with a stick may now combine with Pz's to form P 2 's we may represent
Generalizing Passive
(57a) in L by (59a) below in which the complex P z open with a stick is under
the scope of pass. From Definition 29 then (59a) will be equivalent to our Definition 29 is insufficiently general in several respects. For example in
representation for (59b) which essentially by (58) above will entail (59c). many languages, such as Latin, Turkish, Shona, etc. we may derive Po's
(sentences) from PI'S using the same verbal morphology as used to derive
(59) a. (the can) (pass (open with a stick)) passive PI'S from P 2's. Thus from the P2 amat 'love (3rd person singular)'
b. For some individualy, (open with a stick) (the can) (y) =1 we form amatur '(3sg) is loved' in the same way as from the PI currit '(3sg)
c. For some individualy, Y use a stick to open the can runs' we form thePo curritur 'running is being done'. The obvious generaliza-
tion here is that pass should be allowed to combine withPn+l'S to formPn's
Thus a correct interpretation of the can was opened with a stick is obtained for all values of n. Thus:
if we allow pass to operate on syntactically complex P 2 's such as open with
DEFINITION 31. Generalized Passive
a stick.
A similar argument can be given for source locatives. Recall from our a. Syntax: pass is assigned by lexical rule to the category <Pn/Pn +l)'
first treatment of PM's that source locatives predicate of the subject argument the category of expressions which combine with Pn +l'S to form
of perception Pn's. Thus each of (60a, b) below entails (60c). Pn's, all n;;:;' 0;
b. Semantics: M (pass) is that function from Un ;;. 0 TP n +l into
(60) a. John gazed from the mountain top Un;;. 0 TP n such that for all n;;:;'O. allpETp n +l,andallindi-
b. John watched Mary from the mountain top vidualsxI, X2," .,xn,
c. John was on the mountain top. M (pass) (P) (xd ... (xn) = P (Xn)(XI) ... (x n -)) (U y E Ip y).
V ALENCY AFFECTING OPERA nONS 213 V ALENCY AFFECTING OPERATIONS 215

From Definition 31 we may generate Latin curritur as in (64a) with the Passives on P 3 's in many languages (and perhaps even English) provide
semantics indicated in (64b). additional motivation for generalizing Passive as we have done. In languages
like Malagasy and Kinyarwanda either non-subject argument of a P 3 may
(64) a. Po be the subject of a corresponding passive, using the same verbal morphology

~l'
in both cases. Thus we can say, as we can in English in a restricted class of
cases, either Mary was given the book or The book was given (to) Mary.
pass currit Using English structures these two passives could be generated as in (67b, c),
where (67a) gives the active for comparison.
(pass currit)
I
pass c
I (67) a.

~
pass (c)
R Pl
nom

= c (U

= V
YElp

YElp
y)
c (y) c is a homomorphism p,~N nom to
= 1 iff for some individual y, c (y) = 1,

p~R
6
that is, iffy is running.
The existence of subjectless passives like (63a), traditionally called imper-
sonal, provides further evidence for not restricting pass to lexical Pn's. It is
completely natural for example to combine currit 'runs' with a PM such as
nom't'"'
in the garden and (impersonally) passivize the resulting complex PI yielding John gave the book Mary
a Po meaning roughly running in the garden is being done.
A more interesting case for our purposes concerns impersonal passives b. Po
formed from P 2 's in combination with a N. Such complex PI 's are naturally
formed in Latin in cases where the P 2 (somewhat) exceptionally takes its
R
argument in the dative rather than the accusative case. Compare: PI
nom
(65) a. Po

N PI P2

---------------
nom to

P3~R
N- P2
I nOT dat
L
nom to ace
Marcus mihi invidet
Marcus to me envies I
'Marcus envies me' Mary pass give the book
214 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 216 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

b. c.

PI N
nom

N~P2 N
I nOT dat
P2
nom to

pass mihi invidet


(= mihi invidetur) P3
nom to ace
'to me (it) is envied'

We have used here the case marking notation developed earlier. Note that the book pass
I
give Mary
the structure of (65b) is essentially that of (64a), cumtur, except that the
PI passivized is syntactically complex. Note that in (67b) it is the P 2 give the book which is passivized and thus
Of further interest is that dative object taking P 2 's in Latin such as envy, has no argument. In (67c) it is the P 3 give which is passivized and thus has
persuade, obey, etc. also allow, in literary Latin (Horace) personal passives. no argument; the P 2 (pass give) does have an argument, marked with to.
Thus we may form (66a) below (where the subject pronoun would normally
be omitted), generated in our grammar straightforwardly as in (66b).
Agent Phrases
(66) a. (Ego) invideor By agent phrases we mean expressions like by Mary in (68).
1sg am envied (lsg)
nom (68) John was was kissed by Mary
'I am envied'
b. Traditionally we say of such sentences that John is the syntactic subject
but not the semantic subject, whereas Mary is the semantic subject but not
N the syntactic subject. It is this intuition that we embody explicitly in our
treatment of agent phrases.
First, just what sort of a non-subject is Mary in (68)? Clearly it forms a
P2 constituent with by which independently exists as a preposition in English
nom dat (He sent it by air mail, sat down by the window, etc.). Superficially then

ego pass
I
invidet
by Mary appears to be a 'prepositional phrase', that is, a Predicate Modifier
in our terminology. Moreover this similarity is quite general. As Keenan
(1980) supports, commonly across languages agent phrases are presented
Note that both sentence level and (lexical) predicate level treatments of like independently existing adverbials or oblique case noun phrases. Most
Passive have difficulty generating both of (65a) and (66a) since it would commonly they resemble instrumentals, locatives, or genitives. Formally
appear that we need to derive two structures from a single one. On our then we shall treat agent phrases as PM's.
approach however both passive~ are naturally generated and uniformly Additional support for this treatment is that agent phrase are sometimes
interpreted. construed overtly as adverbials rather than as Prep + R combinations. Thus
VALENCY AFFECTING OPERATIONS 217 VALENCY AFFECTING OPERATIONS 219

(69a, b) are paraphrases showing that universally is understood synonymously Thus John was kissed by Mary and Mary kissed John are logically equivalent,
with by everyone. as desired. As further support for the empirical adequacy of our treatment
we invite the reader to show that the sentences in (74) below are all logically
(69) a. The proposal was rejected by everyone equivalent.
b. The proposal was universally rejected

Semantically, how can we say that by Mary determines the 'semantic (74) a. Some individual kissed John
subject' in (68)1 Note first that it is the 'semantic subject' of kiss, not of b. John was kissed
was kissed. Since by Mary predicates something (identity with Mary) of the c. John was kissed by some individual
subject argument of the denotation of kiss it appears that we want to treat
by Mary semantically as a subject oriented PM, and by as a subject oriented Similarly the passives of PI'S with agent phrases in Latin yields essen-
preposition (PMd. Thus we want M (by), the interpretation of by, to satisfy tially correct results on our analysis. That is, (75 a, b) are provably logically
(70) below, as per Definition 26: equivalent.

(70) For all individualsx,Yl, .. .,yn and allp E TP n ,


(75) a. (pass (run (by John»)
M(by) (x) (P) (Yl)' .. (yn) =P (yd· .. (yn) /\
b. (John run)
M (by) (x) (1) (yn)
To defineM (by) the following is sufficient: Returning now to the curious excess of N's in (72), notice that we can
generate sentences with 'too many' N's precisely because we introduce a
DEFINITION 32. M (by) is that element of Tprep such that for all individuals semantic argument of a Pn as part of a predicate modifier and thus the
x, M (by)(x)(lP 1 ) = M (be)(x). subj
resultant structure may still take a syntactic argument. Were we to derive
I t follows then that M (by) (x) (1 PI) holds of an individual y iff Y = x, and agented passive sentences from active ones by (roughly) interchanging noun
we shall normally write y = x instead of M (by) (x) (1) (y). In informal phrases and adding a by as part of the transformation this possibility would
terms, Definition 32 guarantees that (71 a, b) are logically equivalent, as not arise. But this option is both syntactically and semantically misguided.
are (na,b). Syntactically, it would fail to account for the general fact that agent
phrases are in surface presented as PM's, as previously discussed. It would also
(71) a. (John (run by Bill) fail to account for the fact that agent phrases may occur in non-passive struc-
b. (John run) and (John=Bill) tures. For example, in the various nominalizations of PI'S below we clearly
have agent phrases, i.e. semantic but not syntactic subjects of the nominalized
(n) a. (John «kiss (by Bill» Susan»
predicates, but those phrases cannot have been introduced by a passive rule
b. (John kiss Susan) and (John=Bill)
since PI'S don't passivize in English.
Since (nb) obviously entails (Bill (kiss Susan» our semantics for agent
phrases correctly tells us that the agent N is interpreted as the subject argument (76) a. Talking by students during examinations is forbidden
of the interpretation of kiss. Moreover it clearly is not the subject argument b. The strike by the farm workers was successful
syntactically of kiss, since it occurs as part of a Predicate Modifier of kiss.
Of course (na) and (71a) seem bizarre considered as expressions of On our approach, though we do not provide a semantics for nominalized
English since they present too many N's. There are only two participants Pn's, such nominals as (76a) could be represented by a nominalizer ing
in the action expressed in (na) but there are three independently referring deriving nominals from PI'S. It could of course, like pass, take complex PI'S
R's. But this just says that some expressions in L are not representations as arguments. Thus the subject phrase of (76a) could be analyzed as ing (talk
by students during examinations).
218 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 220 PART 1: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

for any expression in English, something which we actually want in general And semantically, deriving agented passive sentences from active ones
(since for example we want to provide semantic representations for say still fails the Fregean condition, there being no regular entailment relation
relative clauses in English which violate syntactic constraints in English like between actives and the corresponding agented passives. For example (77a)
the Complex NP Constraint, etc.). We return to this matter shortly, but first below does not entail (77b).
we want to show that we do correctly represent English passives with agent
phrases. Given our analysis of by we may now represent English (73a) below (77) a. No politician kissed every baby
by (73b) with the semantic analysis in (73c). b. Every baby was kissed by no politician

(73) a. John was kissed by Mary Replacing no above by other determiners like fewer than three, at most
three, etc. preserves the lack of entailment. Thus actives do not in general
b. Po entail their agented passives. The converse holds as well, since (78a) fails
N~Pl to entail (78b).

(78) a. Fewer than three babies were kissed by every politician


P2 b. Every politician kissed fewer than three babies

P2~/Pn> Thus, from the examples above we see that we don't want to derive
agented passives from actives and we do want to generate agent phrases
~-
<Pn/Pn> IN N independently of passive constructions.
I I Further there might be some additional motivation for independently
John pass kiss by Mary generating agent phrases in non-passive structures as follows: observe that
the L sentences in (79) below are logically equivalent.
c. (John (pass (kiss (by Mary))))
I \ \ I \ (79) a. (John (walk (by John)))

p\
j

v.~
b. (John walk) and (John (be John))
c. (John walk)

~~))(k) We might want to consider that (79a) is our representation in L for John
walks by himself (see the section on Variable Binding Operators for an
pass (by (m)) (k) exact statement of reflexives in L). This would mean that John walks by
himself and John walks would be logically equivalent on our representations.
pass (by (m)) (k) (j)
On the one hand that may seem incorrect since the former sentence seems
to imply something like John walks without help whereas John walks at
= (by (m)) (k) (j) 01 y) Definition of M (pass)
least does not so clearly imply that. Our judgments of entailment here are
= V
y
(by (m)) (k) (j) (v) (by (m)) (k) (j) in Tpl is a
a little fuzzy however and we might want to impute the inference not to
homomorphism
logical entailment but rather to some more pragmatically based interpreta-
=V(k(j)(v)f\m=y Definition of M (by)
y tion of the sentence. The basis of the pragmatic inference would be that
= V (k (j) (m) Substitute:: for = sentences which are logically redundant, as (79a) is since (see (79b)) part of
y
= k (j)(m) vacuous quantification its truth conditions involve the logically true statement that John is John, get
= 1 iff (Mary (kiss John)) is true
V ALENCY AFFECTING OPERATIONS 221 VALENCY AFFECTING OPERATIONS 223

interpreted in a more emphatic way than non-redundant ones. Perhaps In general however it seems that English does not present the means
then it is the 'logical' focussing of attention on John in (79a) which is re- to construct from an e E Pn an expression d E Pn +1 such that (pass d) and
sponsible for the inference that John performs the action unaided. Thus, if e are interpreted identically. Moreover, L as so far developed also seems
our pragmatic analysis could be made explicit we might after all find a use for to be expressively deficient in this way (though the reader may check that
L sentences with two N's referring to the subject argument of the predicate. for e E P 1, (pass (e by)) and e and interpreted identically; note our assumed
Finally, let us observe that by phrases in English are perhaps not the use of by as a verbal extensor here). Once the lambda operator, A, is added to
only sorts of non-subject expressions which function to specify the subject L (see the section on Variable Binding Operators) this deficiency is remedied
argument of a predicate. For example, (80a, b) below are approximately however. Thus the reader may check in that section that kiss is interpreted
paraphrases. the same as (pass AY x z «x (kiss y)) and (x (be z))).
To continue our generalization of Passive to nominals, recall from Theorem
(80) a. They worship Gandhi in India 17 that TP n +l is isomorphic to TN n , all n ~O, and that that isomorphism is
b. Inhabitants of India worship Gandhi at least partially expressible in English by -er. Thus, mixing levels, swimmer
is the isomorphic image of swim, employer of employ, etc. For reference
It seems that the PM in India in (80a) in effect determines the semantic let us give an explicit definition of the interpretation of er:
argument of worship Ghandi. Somewhat similarly note that (81 a, b) are
paraphrases: DEFINITION 33. M(er) is thatfunctionfrom Un;;. 0 TPn+1 into Un;;. 0 TNn
such that for all individuals Xl, ... ,X n , and J, and all hE TPn+ l'
(81) a. That Fred left was strange
b. It was strange that Fred left M (er)(h)(Xl)' .. (Xn) EJ iff h (xd ... (xn)(J) =1
So for example employer is interpreted as that element of TN 1 such that
It appears here that the non-subject expression that Fred left in (80b) specifies for all individuals x and J, (employer (of) x) is a property J has iff (employ
the semantic subject of that sentence, its syntactic subject being it. x) holds of!.
Now, to define pass on TN n consider the following diagram which in
Extending Passive to Nominals and Other Predicative Hierarchies effect defines a passive relation between elements of TN n and TN n -1 (n ~ 1).
er
(82) TPn+l ----~~----
Nominals
Chomsky (1970) suggests that we might want to extend the domain of pass
Passive in order to represent the relation between the enemy's dest1Uction
of the city and the city's dest1Uction by the enemy. We do not represent er
in L non-count nominals like dest1Uction but we have represented nom-
inalizations such as swimmer, employer, etc. and there is a natural algebraic Thus to find the passive of an element of TN n first find the element of
generalization of pass nominalizations of the latter sort, one which, perhaps TP n +l it is the isomorphic image of, take its passive, and then find the
surprisingly, has a natural, if somewhat limited, linguistic expression in isomorphic image of that in TN n . Formally,
English. To illustrate the generalization let us note some further (somewhat
curious) facts regarding passives. DEFINITION 34. For n ~ 1, d E TN n , pass (d) = er (pass (er- l (d)))

THEOREM 20. For all p E TPn' n ;;;" 0, there is agE Tpn+l such that To consider a special case, suppose that h E TP2' Then er (h) E TN l ' and
pass (g) =p. by Definition 34 we have that pass (er (h)) = er (pass (er- l (er (h)))) which
222 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 224 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Proof Let n, p arbitrary as above and define gp in TPn + 1 by: gp (x d ... is just er (pass (h» by the definition of an inverse (er- 1 ) of an isomorphism.
(xn + 1) = P (X2) ... (xn ) (xd, all individuals XI . . . xn + 1. Then, Thus we have that pass (employer) is er (pass (employ», which from Defini-
pass (gp)(Z 1) ... (Zn) =gp (Zn)(Z I) ... (Zn- d (V y) by Definition 31, tion 33 will denote the property an individual I has iff pass (employ) (I) = 1 ;
that is, just in case I is employed. But this property is just the one denoted
= V gp (Zn)(Zl) ... (zn- d (y) gp (ZI) ... (zn- d is a homo-
in English by employee. Thus we may think of employee as the passive
Y morphism
of employer, advisee of advisor, etc. Note that the active/passive -er/-ee
= Vp (zd .. . (zn) Definition ofgp
Y morphology can be used productively in English: It was the killee not the
=p (zd ... (zn) vacuous quantification killer who broke the vase, the kissee and not the kisser who had bad breath,
whence by the Justification Theorem pass (gp) = p. etc. Though these examples are somewhat strained they are good enough we
feel to show that items like employee are not simply independent lexical
Thus we may infer that pass restricted to Tp n + 1 is a function onto TP n . items idiosyncratically related to ·er forms. We might note as well that the
Theorem 20 is somewhat curious from the point of view of ordinary passive nature of -ee forms is in accordance with the etymology of -ee.
English. It says that, semantically, any element of TPn is the passive of an The ending is borrowed from French where it functions as the distinctive
element of Tpn+l. morphology on passives: Marie est employee = Mary is employed.
Can we, for example, find a P 2 whose passive is, in effect, the PI exist? We have been arguing that in a certain reasonable sense employee is
Here the answer is yes: be is such. Using be and exist to represent their the passive of employer. But would we really want to enter -ee in L in the
interpretations, we note: category {Nn/Nn+l> and interpret it as pass restricted to the Predicative
Hierarchy generated by No (= N)? The answer is no. Morphologically -ee
THEOREM 21. For all interpretation m of L, m (pass, be) = m (exist) and actually combines with P2 's to form Ns (Le. No's). The interpretation of
m (pass, exist) = 1 (true) -ee is given by:
Proof.
DEFINITION 35. M (-ee) is that function from TPn+l into TNn_l such that
(a) for all individuals x,
pass (be)(x) = (be (x» (U y) Definition 31
»,
M (-ee) (P) = er (pass (p all p E TPn+l .
y E:. Ip
=Y E:.l
V (be (x») (y) be (x) is a homomorphism The active/passive distinction in nominals then is derivative. Whenever we
p have an expression d E P 2 for example which forms an Nl with the -er suffix
= (be (x» (x) \I (other terms) x is one of the individuals and an No with the -ee suffix the resulting forms will bear the active/passive
over which the join is taken relation. But, at least for the class of nominals considered in L, we do not
=1 Defmition of M (be) appear to have a way of directly passivizing Nl 's to form No's. Thus lexically
= (exist) (x) Definition of M (exist) simple N1's such as friend (of), colleague (of) etc. do not form passive No's.
So pass (be) and exist hold of the same individuals These facts should not however detract from the fact that diagram (82) did
and thus are the same elements of Tp] . lead us to notice an active/passive distinction among nominals, albeit a
derived one. We may further query whether other of the isomorphisms
(b) pass (exist) = exist (U y) Definition 31 among the Predicative Hierarchies we have defined also determine such a
Y E:.lp
= V exist (y) exist is a homomorphism
distinction.
Y E:. Ip
=1 Definition M(exist) andlp f (/J
Passive Adjectives?

So truth is the passive of to exist (and false the passive of not exist). Curious. Recall that intersecting AP's denoted functions f from TN into TN such that
VALENCY AFFECTING OPERATIONS 225 EXTENDING THE CLASS OF DETS 227

for all p E TN, f(P) = P fI f(1), where 1 here is the unit element in TN, the the world would the passive of say under mean? Simplifying slightly we
denotation of existent (or individual). We saw (Theorem 4) that TN was may compute its passive as follows: the P2 it corresponds to under the
isomorphic to TA.P, whence TA.P is isomorphic to Tpt' (The function h from isomorphism is roughly be under. Its passive then holds of x iff for some
1 1
Tp t into TA.P such that for all gin Tpl' h(g) is that element of TA.P such y, y is under x. The corresponding PM o - call it undered for the nonce -
1 1
that h(g) (1) is an element of an individual I iff g(I) = I is easily shown to be would send a PI h to a PI undered (h) which held of x iff h (x) was true
and for some y, y was under x. Thus John sang undered would mean John
an isomorphism.) Moreover setting APo equal to AP and APn+l to APn/Nwe
I i i i sang and some individual was under John.
have that the function h above generalizes to an isomorphism from TPn+l Unfortunately there seems no regular, or even irregular, way of forming
onto TArn by setting h(g)(xt) ... (xn)(l) E I iff g(xd ... (xn)(I) = 1. We the passive of under. Perhaps the best idiosyncratic case we can think of
1
may therefore extend pass to combine with APn's yielding APn-l'S and define (and it's pretty bad) is with converse prepositions such as in front of and
I I
its interpretation as that function which makes the diagram below commute: behind. (x is in front of y iff Y is behind x.) Now let us suppose (this is
the dubious part) that John sat in front (behind) means that John sat and
h
(83) TP n +1 -----'-"------ T APn John was in front of (behind) someone. So in front and behind would be
I i
I PMo's, and in front of and behind would be PM I 'so Then in front would be
pass I
I
pass the passive of behind (considered as a PM I) since John sat in front = John
j sat and John was in front of someone =John sat and someone was behind
h TAPn-l John. Perhaps as well we might consider Eastwards a lexical passive of the
i
PM I to the West of However these examples are not fully accurate, but
But is there any way in English (or L) to form the passive of say a one place perhaps they suggest that the existence of passives of prepositions is not
AP? Recall that among the API'S (we drop the sub categorization feature i wholly implausible.
since we are only considering intersecting AP's here) we have expressions
like proud (of), envious (of), jealous (of), respectful (of), etc. Note that
these expressions do seem naturally interpreted by intersecting API's. This S. EXTENDING AND SUBCATEGORIZING THE CLASS
will say for example that an individual has the student proud of Billy property OF DETERMINERS
iff he has the student property and the individual proud of Billy property, In our earlier treatment of Determiners (= NIN, abbreviated Det) we claimed
which seems basically correct. (Theorem 14, Part A) that TDet was just the set of conservative functions
Formally we define: from P (= TN) into P* (= TN), where f E Fp* Ip is conservative iff for all
p, q E P, p Ef (q) iff (p A q) E f (q). But so far we have provided only four
DEFINITION 36. For d E TAPn, pass (d) = h (pass (h- I (d») logically distinct elements of Det: every, a, the, and no. One of our tasks
i
in this section is to significantly increase the set of expressions of category
To find the passive of proud of we note first (mixing levels of notation) Det. Our additions will include first a variety of 'numerical' Dets such as
that h- I (proud of) = is proud of. The passive of that is that PI which holds at least six, more than six, at most six, fewer than six, between six and ten,
of an individual x iff for some y, y is proud of x. So we are looking for an exactly six, infinitely many, half (of) the, the six, and all but six. These
AP o whose value at the existent property is an element of an individual I 'expressions, like those currently in Det, will be logical constants in the
iff someone is proud of I. Once we introduce relative clauses into L (see the sense of satisfying (84) below:
section on Variable Binding Operators) we can easily concoct such an APo.
It is simply who someone is proud of. But there does not appear to exist (84) For e an expression of category C, if e is a logical constant then
in English any unitary syntactic operation on API'S which yields AP 0 's for all ontologies (P, 2) and all interpretations m 1, m2 of L,
interpreted as their passives. ml (e) = m2 (e)
226 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 228 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

The situation is so far reminiscent of the absence of direct passives relating Among these logical constants we semantically distinguish a subset which
NI's to No's. So we might wonder whether there is here an analogue of -ee are cardinality dependent. That is, we define a property of functions from
and -er where -ee (d) was interpreted as the passive of -er (d), for d a Pz . A Pinto p* and show that denotations of at least six, exactly six, etc. have
near analogue of -ee would appear to be the past participle function -en. This that property while the denotations of every, all but six, etc. do not.
function would derive beaten from beat, kissed from kiss, and it very roughly Somewhat more deeply, we add elements to Det such as John's, no
appears that a woman kissed is a woman and an individual who someone student's, etc. as they occur in John's house, etc. These expressions are
kissed. So we might plausibly regard beaten, kissed, etc. as passive APo's. But not logical constants - they fail (84). Moreover, we find a property of
we find no plausible API'S of which they are the passives. That is, we appear functions from Pinto P* which defines the set of possible denotations of
to lack the analogue of -er which would send us from P z to AP I . logical constants among Det. That is, we have found a semantic property
One possible, if forced, candidate here is -ing. It does at least approximate of Dets which distinguishes 'logical' ones from 'non-logical' ones. This allows
to the isomorphism from PI'S to APo's. That is, a laughing child is a child us to provide a novel analysis of certain 'vague' yet 'logical' Dets such as
and an individual who is laughing. We might consider that it also applies several and a few. It also provides the basis of some further language universals
to P2 's, so that kissing would be a derived API, combining with an unmarked concerning Det interpretations. Namely, we can show that there is a sense
N to form an APo such as kissing Bill as it occurs in the woman kissing Bill in which Dets, compared to expressions of other categories, are not freely
is drunk. But it doesn't seem correct to regard kissed as the passive of kissing. interpreted despite the existence of non-logical elements such as John's
Using -ing for h in Definition 36 for example we have that pass (ing (kiss)) = among the Dets. Moreover we can also, at least in part, account for why
ing (pass (ing- I (ing (kiss)))) which is just ing (pass (kiss)), which in turn there are so many logical constants among Dets compared to other categories.
is expressed in English by being kissed. So if we accept kissing as an AP I We close this section by extending the class of Det's considered in two
we do have a natural passive, being kissed, but this hardly seems interesting. ways. First, we extend the analysis of possessor Dets (e.g. John's) in several
F or now we have only two operators, ing which takes us from Pn+ 1' s to ways. And second, we extend Det to include two place Dets such as more . ..
APn's and pass which takes us from Pn+l'S to Pn's. But we have no English than ... as it occurs e.g. in more students than teachers, treating it as an
operator expressing pass which takes us from APn's to APn -1 's, nor do expression which combines with two Ns (student, teacher) to form an R.
we even have the partial operator analogous to -ee which takes us from The definition of conservativity is shown to naturally extend to functions
Pn+l'S to APn-l 's. fromP X P intoP*.
Rejecting kissing as the active AP I form of kissed then we appear to have
no regular active/passive alternation within AP's even of a derived sort. There
appear only to be a handful of idiosyncratic cases where we can derive an Numerical Determiners
API from a P2 in such a way that the ·er form of the P2 behaves like its
passive. For example, arguably from the P2 envy we can derive the API To enter expressions like at least six, more than six, etc. into L let us assume
envious of and its passive APo envied. Perhaps respectful of and respected that we have defined the set K of finite cardinal numerals. That is, K is the
from respect is another case. set {zero, one, two, ... }(So we ignore whatever rules English has which
forms say two hundred forty six from two, four, and six.) We may then
Passive Prepositions?? enrich L as follow:

The case here seems hopeless and is at most only interesting as a way of (85) For all k, kl' and k2' in K, the following expressions are added
illustrating some expressive limitations of English. Recalling from Theorem to the basic vocabulary V and assigned by lexical rule to Det: at
18 that Tp +1 is isomorphic to TPMn we may construct diagrams analogous least k, k or more, more than k, at most k, fewer than k, exactly
n &g
to (82) and (83) and extend pass to derive PM n -1'S from PMn's interpreting k, between kl and k2' the k, all but k, infinitely many, just
that operator as the one which makes the diagram commute. But what in finitely many, at least half (a!) the.
EXTENDING THE CLASS OF DETS 229 EXTENDING THE CLASS OF DETS 231

Adding these expressions to L as syntactically unanalyzable is merely a are conservative follows from the fact that they are defined to be boolean
simplifying strategy. A more refined approach would treat K as a new prim- functions of conservative functions and the fact that TDet is closed under
itive category whose type would be the natural numbers. Then expressions these boolean operations by definition and Theorem 14, Part A, which
like at least, at most, etc. would be of category Det/K and thus interpreted proves TDet to be just the set of conservative functions from Pinto P*.
by functions from natural numbers into TDet. As we have done it however As for the functions in Definition 40, the fact that M (the k) is conserva-
we may interpret the above expressions, which are all intuitively logical tive follows directly from the fact that M (every) is. Observe further that
constants, by appropriately constraining the lexical interpreting function
M.
M (every) (q), by definition n 13 q
I, is just {s: q .;;; s}, that is, the filter
generated by q (denoted Fq). Observe second that in any boolean algebra
We consider first expressions of the form at least k. In general the prop- (x 1\ y) .;;; z iff (x 1\ y) .;;; (z 1\ x). Then,
erties which at least k students possess are those properties p which are
elements of at least k distinct individuals each having the student property. THEOREM 23. M (all but k) is conservative.
As a somewhat special case we may note that any property p is possessed Proof. For p, q E P, p EM (all but k) (q) iff
by at least zero students. The following definition is then intuitive (it could For some s .;;; q, lsi = k, p EM (every) (q 1\ s') Definition 40b
have been given more elegantly to avoid the special case, but the definition iff for some s .;;; q, lSI =< k, (q 1\ s') .;;; p observation above
would be less perspicuous): iff for some s .;;; q, lsi =k, (q 1\ s') .;;; (p 1\ q) observation above
iff (p 1\ q) EM (all but k) (q) Definition 40b
DEFINITION 37. For all k in K, all q EP,
And to prove that M (at least half the) is conservative, observe that (p 1\ q) =
(a) M (at least k) (q) = IDet if k =zero; otherwise, «p 1\ q) 1\ q) and (p' 1\ q) = «p
1\ q)' 1\ q), whence we may infer that similar
(b) M (at least k) (q) = UUI n 12 n ... n h : Ii'!' Ij for j =/=i and Dets such as more than half the, less than half the, etc. are conservative as
q Ell nI2 n ... nId well.
Let us point out now a few properties of the new Dets. Syntactically
Two remarks are in order here. First, recall that since TDet is defined as a several of the new Dets enter into boolean combinations, which gives us
subalgebra of the pointwise algebra from Pinto P* the unit element 1Det significantly more motivation than did our original class of Dets for wanting
of TDet is that function sending each q E P to P itself, the set of all the TDet to have a boolean structure. Thus complex Dets such as either fewer
properties. Second, we are assuming with our use of subscripts in part (b) than ten or (else) more than a hundred, at least two and at most eight, either
of the definition that we know what number k refers to. We are in fact exactly two or exactly three, etc. are reasonably natural English.
assuming natural number arithmetic. This assumption is harmless for our Semantically, we may observe that some of the old Dets are logically
purposes, though we indicate shortly how to define Det denotations without equivalent to some of the new ones. In particular M (a) = M (at least one)
that assumption, thereby providing in fact another type of model for natural and M (the) = M (the one). Further, it is reasonable to extend the Dets
number arithmetic. formed from the along the following lines: Add the k or more and the more
than k to Det and interpret them as in Definition 40a, replacing Iql = k by
DEFINITION 38. For all k E K and all q E P, M (more than k) (q) = Iql ;;;. k and lql > k respectively. Add thepl to Det and set M (thepZ) = M
UUI n 12 n ... n h+l: Id Ij for j=f i and q E II n 12 n ... n h+d. (the two or more). This will give us distinct representations for the student
and the students, namely (the student) and (thepl student).
Definition 38 is self explanatory, noting only that in our use of subscripts More interestingly, let us consider some of the semantic distinctions we
k+ 1 we assume the ordinary definition of addition of natural numbers. can make among the elements of Det. First, it is natural to distinguish Det
Relative to Definition 37 and 38 definitions for many of the other Dets in denotations according as they are increasing, decreasing, or neither. (RecalI
(85) is straightforward: from Definition 29, Part A, that a subset S of an algebra B is increasing iff
230 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 232 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

DEFINITION 39. For all k, kJ, k2 EK and all q EP, whenever xES and x < y then yES; S is decreasing iff whenever xES and
y < x then yES; a function from S into S* is increasing (decreasing) iff its
(a) M (k or more) =M (at least k) value at every argument is increasing (decreasing).)
(b) M (fewer than k) = (M (at least k)) I We invite the reader to verify that, of the syntactically unanalyzed elements
(c) M (at most k) = (M (more than k)) I of Det, every, a, the, at least k, more than k, infinitely many, the k, the k or
(d) M (exactly k) =M (at least k) 1\ M (at most k) more, the more than k, and at least half the are interpreted by increasing
(e) M (between kl and k 2 ) = M (at least kJ) 1\ M (at most k 2 ) functions; at most k, fewer than k and less than half the are interpreted by
(t) M (strictly between kl and k 2 ) = M (more than kd 1\ M (fewer decreasing functions; and exactly k, between kJ and k2' just finitely many,
than k 2 ) and all but k are interpreted by functions which are not in general either
(g) M (infinitely many) = 1\ M (at least k) increasing or decreasing.
kEK
A less obvious distinction among Det denotations is that between those
(h) M (just finitely many) = V M (exactly k) which crucially refer to cardinalities and those which don't. To specify
kEK
this property more precisely let us first give an alternate characterization
To simplify the definitions of the other Dets in (85) let us use the following of conservativity.
notation (which is not necessary, only convenient): if X is a set, IXI will
denote the cardinality of X, as is standard. By extension, for pEP, Ipl will DEFINITION 41. fEFp*/p is meet dependent ifffor all p, q, rEP,
denote I{o:: 0: is an atom in P and 0: ..;; P}I.
if (p 1\ r) =(q 1\ r) then p Ef(r) iff q Ef(r)
DEFINITION 40. For all k EK and all q EP, THEOREM 24. For f E Fp*/p, f is conservative iff f is meet dependent.
(a) M (the k) (q) ={M (every! (q) if Iqj =k Proof. Assume first thatfis conservative. Let (p 1\ r) =(q 1\ r).
~ otherwIse
Then,p Ef(r) iff(P 1\ r) Ef(r) f is conservative
(b) M(allbutk)(q)= V M(every)(q1\ S') iff (q 1\ r) Ef(r) assumption
s.;;q
iff q Ef(r) f is conservative
lsi = k
Thus f is meet dependent.
(c) M(at least halfthe)(q) = {p: 1(P 1\ q)1 ~ 1(P' I\q)l}
Assume second thatfis meet dependent. Then
The functions defined in Definitions 37-40 are all easily shown to be if(P 1\ q) = «(P 1\ q) 1\ q) thenp Ef(q) iff(P 1\ q) Ef(q).
conservative. For example, But (P 1\ q) = «(P 1\ q 1\ q), whencefis conservative.

The intuition behind the concept of meet dependence is the following: an


THEOREM 22. M (at least k) is conservative. element f in TDet cannot distinguish between properties p, q which have the
Proof. For p, q E P, (P 1\ q) EM (at least k) (q) iff there exist k distinct same meet with its argument r. Either it puts both of them inf (r) or it puts
individuals such that: neither in.
Consider now the stronger notion of cardinality dependence. The intuition
«(Pl\q)l\q)E/l n/2 n .. ,nh Definition 37
here is that the function f cannot distinguish among properties p, q at an
iff(P 1\ q)E/J n/2 n ... nh idempotency
argument r if (P 1\ r) and (q 1\ r) have the same cardinality. Thus,
iff p EM (atleast k)(q) Definition 37.
DEFINITION 42. f E Fp*/p is cardinality dependent iff for all p, q, rEP,
The proof that M (more than k) is conservative is identical to that in Theorem
22 above, replacing k by k+ 1. That the functions defined in Definition 39 if 1(P 1\ r)1 = I(q 1\ r)1 then p E fer) iff q E fer)
EXTENOING THE CLASS OF OETS 233 EXTENDING THE CLASS OF DETS 235

Theorem 25 below follows immediately from Definition 42 and Theorem 24: where 1Det plays the role of 0 (the empty set) and + corresponds to the
set theoretical successor function. We may now interpret the cardinality
THEOREM 25. For allfEFp*/p, if fis cardinality dependent then dependent Dets above in Cardp. M (at least zero) is IDet. M (at least one)
is M (at least zero» +, M (at least two) is (M (at least one» + , etc. Ultimately
fis meet dependent, whence fE To et . of course the 'etc.' in this last clause would have to be replaced by an explicit
statement of how complex numerical expressions in English take their deno-
We have defined cardinality dependence for elements of TOet. By extension tations as a function of their parts, but this we still forego. Of course M
we shall say that d E Det is cardinality dependent iff for all ontologies <P, 2) (more than k) is now just (M (k» +. And the other cardinal Dets are defined
and all interpretations m relative to (p, 2), m(d) is cardinality dependent. as before in terms of at least k and more than k.
And in general when a property of elements of To et has been defined we
shall assume its extension to elements of Det as has been done above. Non-Logical Determiners
As expressions like John's car, every student's house, etc. are clearly full
THEOREM 26. For k, kJ, k2 in K, the set of finite cardinal numerals, at least
noun phrases in English and car, house, etc. are clearly common nouns, it
k, more than k, fewer than k, at most k, exactly k, between kJ and k 2 ,
is reasonable to treat expressions like John's, every student's, etc. as being
infinitely many, just finitely many, and the k are cardinality dependent.
determiners. We may then enrich L as follows:
Proof hint: To see that at least k is cardinality dependent assume that
!(p A r)1 = I(q A r)l. Then p EM (at least k) (r) iff there are k distinct indi- (86) Enter's in the basic vocabulary V and assign it by lexical rule
viduals such that (p A r) is in each of them. But by assumption (p A r) and to the category DetlN (= (N/N) IN).
(q A r) dominate the same number of atoms and thus are elements of the
same number of individuals. Whence there must be k distinct individuals It follows immediately that John's, every student's, etc. are elements of Det.
which (q A r) is in, so q EM (at least k) (r). The proof for more than k is How shall we interpret these Dets? Intuitively we want (87a) and (87b)
similar. Most of the other cases follow from their definitions and Theorem below to have the same interpretation:
27 below.
(87) a. John's car
b. The car which John has
THEOREM 27. The set of cardinality dependent elements of To et is a
complete and atomic sub algebra of To et . Thus the interpretation of John's, and so ultimately of's, will not be in-
dependent of the non-logical P 2 have. We hereby enter have in the basic
Proof. We must show that (a) OOet and lOet are cardinality dependent vocabulary and assign it the category P 2 .
(CD), (b) if f is CD then!, is CD, and ( c) if K is a set of CD functions then Now we need a way of referring to the property denoted by car which
I\K and VK are CD. Let p, q, rEP such that l(p A r)1 = I(q A r)1. Then trivially John has. Once relative clauses are entered into L in the section on Variable
OOet is CD since for all r, OOet (r) = (/J, so P E OOet (r) iff q E OOet (r). Binding Operators we will be able to form such expressions directly in L.
Similarly lOet is CD trivially 'since lOet (r) = P, all r. But even without relative clauses L already has enough expressive power
Now assume fis CD. Thenf' is CD since: to express car which John has. It will basically be (p 1\ q), where p is the
p E ([')(r) iff p E (f(r)) , Pointwise definition of' in To et car property and q is the property an individual I has iff John has I is true.
iff p rF f (r) Definition' in p* Now the P j (pass (have (by John») is the one which holds of an individual iff
iffqrFf(r) fisCD John has it. Recall that er expresses the natural isomorphism from Tp 1 into
iff q E (f') (r) P (= TN)' That is, for h E TP1' er (h) is that element of P which is in an
Finally, let K a set of CD functions. Then I\K is CD since: individual I iff h (I) = 1. Thus the property q mentioned above is essentially
p E (I\K) (r) iff pEn k (r) Pointwise definition A in To et expressed by (er (pass (have (by John»». So at least we can say that we
kEK
234 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 236 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

iff for all k E K, p E k (r) Definition n want the value of the lexical interpreting function M at's to satisfy (88)
iff for all k EK, q Ek (r) each k is CD below:
iff q E (I\K) (r)
There are however several elements of Det as so far defined which are not CD. (88) F or all individuals I and all pEP,
Thus: (M ('s)) (I) (P) =M (the) (p /\ er (pass «by I) (M (have))))).

THEOREM 28. every, all but k, and more than half the are not CD. Note that as before we use er, pass, and by to represent their own inter-
Proof sketch: Choose P with denumerably many atoms. Choose r to be pretations.
the join of all the atoms, so r = Ip. Choose p = Ip and q = b' for some atom But of course the domain of M ('s) is all of P*, not just the individuals.
b. Then 1(P /\ r)1 = I(q /\ r)1 =~o· But p EM (every) (r) = FI but q rt. FI since So how does M ('s) behave on non-individuals in P*? Surprisingly perhaps
I 1. (b' /\ 1) = b'. it by and large behaves homomorphically. For example, takingM('s), which
Proofs for the other cases are essentially similar though more tedious. we henceforth represent simply as's, as a complete homomorphism we have
that (89a) is true under the conditions expressed in (89b). This is represented
Note that every only fails to be CD in cases where we have an infinite number explicitly in (90) below.
of individuals. If P is finite then for some (finite) k, M (every) = M (at least
k) which was proven above to be CD. (The k in question is the one which (89) a. Some teacher's car exploded
denotes the number of individuals = the number of atoms of P). Note that b. There is a teacher x such that x's car exploded
from standard logic we are used to thinking of every and a (= at least one)
as being interdefinable. Yet a has a semantic property which every fails to (90) (( (some teacher) 's) car) exploded
have, namely it is CD.
I
We would like now to turn to non-logical Dets. First however let us
make good on a promissory note tendered earlier. Namely, we claimed that
in specifying the value of M at Dets like at least k etc. it was not necessary
~UI
U I
b
h

to assume the ordinary development of arithmetic. Here we sketch how this 13t
can be done, and thereby provide a new model for arithmetic. We begin by
defining an analogue of the successor function in arithmetic.

DEFINITION 43: + is that function from Fp* IP into Fp* IP such that for
all!EFp*/p, and allp EP,
r+(P) = {(q V 0:): q E !(P) and 0: an atom, 0: :r;;;; p and 0: -;, q}.
h (' s (U I) (P))
Then we may define the finite cardinal numbers over P, Cardp as follows: 13t

DEFINITION 44. Cardp is the least set of functions from Pinto p* such that
=h «13t
V ('s (I))) (P)) 's is a homomorphism

= h (V's (I) (P)) pointwise definition V in TDet


(i) IDet E Cardp and 13t
(ii) Cardp is closed under +. =13V t h ('S (I) (P)) hE Tp j is a homomorphism

We note without proof that if P is infinite then Cardp is isomorphic to = I iff for some individual I with the teacher property, he s (I) (P))
W, the standard set theoretical representation for the natural numbers, = 1. That is, iff for some such /, I's car exploded.
EXTENDING THE CLASS OF DETS 237 EXTENDING THE CLASS OF DETS 239

Similarly we want (the interpretation of) 's to preserve complements. If so, b E B if there is an isomorphism i: B -7 D such that i (b) = d. (Note that if
then (91a) will, correctly, be logically equivalent to (9lb) as shown in (92). there is such an isomorphism then there is also an isomorphism from D to B
which sends d to b, namely i-I, so we may think of two elements p, q of
(91) a. No teacher's car exploded P as having the same boolean structure iff for some isomorphism i: P -7 P
b. It is not the case that a teacher's car exploded we have that i (P) = q. An isomorphism from an algebra onto itself is called

1'0
an automorphism.)
(92) «(no teacher) 's) car) exploded
Now, how may we say that an element[E TDet treats booleanly identical
I elements in the same way? The idea here is that if q differs from p by an
~t P h
1 isomorphism i, that is q = i (P), then the elements of [(q) are just those
which differ from those of [(P) by the isomorphism i, that is [(q) = {i (s):
a'(t) / / s E[(P)}. Formally then we define:

's(a'~ DEFINITION 46. For all [ E Fp* /P, [ is automorphism invariant (AI) iff
('s (a' (t))) (P) for all p, q E P and all automorphisms i on P, if q = i(P) then [(q) =
{i (s): s E [(P)}.
h «'s (a' (t))) (P))
(The definition is a bit long-winded. The function i above extends naturally
to a function fromP* ontoP* as follows: for allK ~P, i (K) = {i (k): kEK}.
=h «('s «a (t))')) (P)) pointwise definition' in TDet
So the last line in Definition 46 may be written: if q = i (P), then [(q) = i
=h «('s (a (t))) , (P)) 's is a homomorphism
», ».
(f (P and that in turn simply says: [(i (P» = i ([ (P We may note as
=h «'s (a (t)) (P)) ') pointwise definition' in TDet
well that the extended function i restricted to p* is an automorphism on P*.)
=(h ('S (a (t)) (P))) , hE TP 1 is a homomorphism
= I iff h ('S (a (t)) (P) is false; that is, iff a teacher's car exploded
THEOREM 29. All elements of Det introduced before the section called
is false.
Non-logical Dets are interpreted by automorphism invariant elements of
So we want's to preserve complements, whence both complements and joins, TDet·
whence it is a should be a complete homomorphism from TN into TDet.
Let us show for example that M (every) is AI. We use in the proof the fact
Accordingly we may constrainM as follows:
that M (every) (P) is provably just Fp , the filter generated by p, that is,
(93) M ('s) is a complete homomorphism from TN into TDet which {q: p .;;;; q}. We also use standard observation that if i is an isomorphism from
satisfies (88) above. B to D, then x .;;;; y iff i (x)';;;; i (y). Then, M (every) (i (P» = i (M (every) (P»
as follows: For s EP,
Recall from the Justification Theorem of Part A that homomorphisms on TN
are not only defined by stating their values on the individuals, but those values s EM (every)(i (P» iff i (P).;;;; S
may be. freely stated, that is, in any way we like. Note further that once M iffi- l (i (P» =p .;;;; i-I (s)
(have) is given, the values of M ('s) on the individuals is uniquely determined. iffi- l (s) EM (every) (P)
Finally, it is easily shown that for all individuals I, M ('s) (I) is conservative, }ffi(i-l (s»=s Ei(M(every) (P»
whence for any set of properties Q, M ('s) (Q) is conservative since it is a
boolean function of elements of the form M (' s) (I) and by Theorem 14, Part Similarly let us sketch the proof that M (a) is AI. Recall first that an
A, the conservative functions are closed under the boolean operations. individual I is the filter generated by some atom. Moreover, by Theorem 7c
238 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 240 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

Now it is clear that possessor Dets (ones of the form N's such as John's) of Part lA, the value of an isomorphism at an atom must itself be an atom.
are not logical constants in the sense of (84). For a given ontology (P, 2) Then,
different interpretations may assign John's to different elements of TDet
depending upon which individual John is interpreted as, and depending upon s EM (a) (i (P)) iff for some individual I, i (P) E I and s E I
which element of TP2 have is interpreted as. iff for some atom 0:, 0:':;;;; i (P) and 0: .:;;;; s
Further there appear other plausible candidates for non-logical Dets in ifffor some atom 0(, i-l (O()':;;;; i-I (i (P)) =p and
English besides the simple possessives. One class of cases is given by extending i-l (0:)':;;;; i-I (s)
ways of forming complex Dets from simpler ones which we have, in effect, iff for some atom {3, {3 .:;;;; p and (3 .:;;;; i-I (s)
already seen. Thus plausibly John's three is a Det as it occurs in John's three iff for some individual I, pEl and i-I (s) E I
cars were stolen. In general the interpretation of John's k will follow that ifU-1 (s) EM (a) (P)
of the k and will not be given explicitly here. iffi(i- I (s))=sEi(M(a)(p).
A different sort of example is given by comparatives of the sort more male
than female, fewer French than Spanish as they occur in more male than To facilitate proofs for other cases we note the following theorem:
female students failed the exam. Let us define:
THEOREM 30. {f E TDe( f is AI}is a complete and atomic subalgebra of
DEFINITION 45. MT is that function from (TAP)2 into TDet such that for TDet
all h, g E TAP and all pEP,
The proof that meets, joins, and complements of AI functions are themselves
MT (h, g) (P) = {q: Iq!\ h (P)I > Iq!\ g (P)I}.
AI is merely a tedious exercise and will be omitted.
We may conclude then that the Dets we have been calling logical constants
It is easily checked that MT (h, g) as above is conservative (given that hand
are automorphism invariant. Moreover, as expected, the Dets such as John's
g are restricting!). We may then interpret more male than female as MT
which we have called non-logical are not automorphism invariant. That is,
(M (male), M (female)). And clearly such Dets are not logical constants since
we can find interpretations m of L such that m (John's) is not AI. It will
their interpretation varies with that of the AP's they are formed from.
be instructive to exhibit a case where John's fails to be AI. First let us note
that any two atoms of P have the same boolean structure, i.e. they can be
Characterizing 'Logical' Determiners
identified by an automorphism. More generally consider Theorem 31 and
At this point an interesting question arises: we have been (partially at least) its corollaries below, where Atp denotes the set of atoms of P and f is a
characterizing logical constants in terms of uniqueness of interpretation permutation of Atp ifffis a one-to-one function from Atp onto Atp.
given a choice of P. But aside from giving examples we have said nothing
about what elements of TDet may be denoted by logical constants. Can in THEOREM 31. For every permutation f of Atp the function if from P to
fact just any element of TDet be a denotation for a logical constant, or rather P defined by setting if (P) = V {f (0:): 0: an atom and 0:':;;;; P } extends f and
does being a logical constant impose some constraint on which elements of is an automorphism. Moreover the set of automorphisms on P is just {it f
TDet are possible denotations? The latter option turns out to be correct. a permutation of Atp}
Intuitively we would expect that interpretations of 'logical' Dets would
treat properties 'with the same boolean structure' in the same way. We may COROLLARY 1. For all atoms 0:, {3 there is an automorphism i such that
represent the notion of having the same boolean structure as follows. By i (0:) ={3 and i ((3) =0:.
definition an isomorphism from an algebra B to an algebra D is a function
which preserves all of the boolean structure of B, so an element of d ED COROLLARY 2. For all p, q E P, there is an automorphism i onP such that
may reasonably be said to have the same boolean structure as an element i (P) = q iff Ipl = Iql and Ip'l = Iq'l.
EXTENDING THE CLASS OF DETS 241 EXTENDING THE CLASS OF DETS 243

Again the proofs are straightforward algebraic exercises and will be omitted. satisfy additional constraints. Arguably for example they are cardinality
We may now show: dependent. For example, if the number of Democrats who are vegetarians
is the same as the number of Democrats who are alcoholics then it seems that
THEOREM 32: John's is not automorphism invariant. several Democrats are vegetarians and several Democrats are alcoholics
Proof. Choose P with at least two atoms 0:, (3. Interpret have such that should have the same truth value. We can of course require that M (several)
for all individuals x, y m(have)(x) (y) = 1 iff x = 10" the individual generated etc. be CD in the same way that we required that they be AI above. Note
by 0:, andy = M (John). Then m (John's) (0:) = 101. and m (John's) ((3) = 0. Now that these two properties are completely independent:
let i be that automorphism on P such that i(o:) = (3 and i((3) = 0: and for all
other atoms 'Y, i(')') = 'Y. Then i((3) = a: but i((m (John's) ((3» = i(O) = 0 f m THEOREM 33.
(John's) U((3» = m (John's) (0:) = 101.. Thus m (John's) is not AI.
(a) There existfE TDet such thatfis AI and not CD
To illustrate the intuitive interpretation of the proof above imagine an inter- (b) There existfE TDet such thatfis CD and not AI.
pretation in which there are at least three individuals, one being John, one
being the only individual with the boat property, and the third being the only Proof sketch.
individual with the car property. Suppose that John has the boat and nothing
else. Then John's boat is that individual with the boat property, and John's (a) M (every) has already been shown to be AI and not CD.
car is the empty set. But since both boat and car are interpreted by atoms we (b) Choose P with at least two atoms a, ~. Define fOi. from Pinto
can find an automorphism in which the boat atom is the isomorphic image P*by:
of the car atom. But John's boat, an individual, is not the set of isomorphic
fOi.(q)= {Pifex~~
image of elements of John's car, which is empty. ~ otherwIse.
Loosely then, John's is not automorphism invariant, that is, it is not fa as defined is easily seen to be conservative and (trivially) CD.
'logical', because it can tell the difference between atoms, sending some It is not AI since it sends distinct atoms ex and ~ to elements of
to individuals and others to the empty set, elements of p* which do not p* (P and ~ respectively) which are not isomorphic images of each
have the same boolean structure (that is, which cannot be identified by any other.
automorphism on p* since only the zero element of p* (the empty set)
can be identified with the zero element). Finally, it seems reasonable, though judgments are somewhat less clear for
We have then distinguished among elements of TDet according as they several than for a few, that M (several), etc. be interpreted by increasing
may interpret 'logical' Dets or not. We might then add the subcategorization elements of TDet. Clearly if a few Democrats are vegetarians and all vege-
feature logical to SF (L) and define: tarians are alcoholics, then a few Democrats are alcoholics. If we accept the
comparable judgements for several then we might posit a second universal
(94) TDet = {fE TDet: fis automorphism invariant} as follows:
logical
But is there any motivation for adding this feature to L? After all, we don't (97) Universal II
need to explicitly constrain the interpretations of at least k, every, etc. to lie All syntactically simple Dets in a language which are extensional
in TDet. since we give their denotations explicitly and it is a theorem that are increasing.
logIcal
they lie in that set. Similarly, all the non-logical Dets we have discussed
are syntactically complex, whence their interpretations are given as a function (97) is more problematic than the first universal. At the very least it requires
of that of their constituents, and it is a theorem (see Theorem 32 above) that no and neither, which are clearly decreasing and not increasing, be
that they need not lie in the set of AI elements of TDet. Nevertheless some analyzed as syntactically complex. It is historically correct that they consist
242 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 244 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

motivation for adding the feature logical to L may come from the analysis of a base and a negative morpheme ne, and plausibly we might consider
of 'vague' Dets, to which we now turn. them to be synchronically bimorphemic, based on alternations like one/none,
either/neither, ever/never, ary/nary, etc. But other plausible counter-examples
exist. Bare numerals like two in two students came early are not increasing
Vague Determiners
if they are interpreted in the sense of exactly two (but they are increasing
Dets such as several, a few, many, few, a large number of, etc. seem vague if interpreted to mean at least two). Finally, few appears to be decreasing
in a way in which the Dets so far considered are not. It is unclear for example and not increasing, though it is argued in Keenan and Stavi (1981) that few
just how many, or what proportion, of the Democrats must be vegetarians in (like many) cannot be analyzed as a function from Pinto p* at all.
order for the sentence several Democrats are vegetarians to be true. Limiting
ourselves to several and a few, one approach to the problem of vagueness Determiners Compared to Other Categories
would be to simply enter these items as syntactically unanalyzed elements
of Det and not constraint their interpretation. So more than one element Despite the existence of non-logical constants among the Dets, Det as a
of To et would be a possible denotation for these items. They would be category seems distinct from the other categories we have considered in
vague then in the sense that since their interpretations are not a function of that, in some sense, a heavy proportion of elements of Det are either logical
the interpretations of their parts (they don't have any) we have no way of constants or at least interpreted by AI elements of TDet. For other categories
knowing which elements of To et they do denote. we find the odd logical constant among their syntactically simple members,
However this approach (so far) overshoots the mark in the sense that e.g. exist, be, individual, etc. but generally the lexical elements of N, AP,
several and a few are surely not freely interpretable in To et . Intuitively and the Pn's are not logical constants. Is this just an accident, or can we
for example they are more 'quantitative' or 'logical' than John's. Thus, provide some reason to expect this distribution?
assuming a P with only finitely many individuals for simplicity of illustration, In fact the distribution of logical constants is not wholly unexpected. It
if the number of Democrats is the same as the number of Republicans, and correlates with certain semantic properties of the relevant categories. To see
the number of Democrats who are vegetarians is the same as the number this in broad outline (see Keenan and Stavi, op. cit., for all details and proofs)
of Republicans who are alcoholics, we want (95a, b) below to have the same let us first note that it makes sense to speak of automorphism invariant
truth value. elements in any type, not just TDet. Specifically:

(95) a. Several Democrats are vegetarians (98) An automorphism i on P extends to an automorphism on all the
b. Several Republicans are alcoholics types as follows:
(a) We extend i to Tpo by setting i (1) = 1 and i (0) = O.
This will be guaranteed (see Keenan and Stavi, 1981, for details) if we require (b) if i has been extended to an automorphism on a set X then i
that several and a few are interpreted by automorphism invariant elements extends to X* by setting i (K) = {i (k): k E K}, all subsets K of X.
of To et . We may than enter these expressions into the Det . subcategory (c) if i has been extended to sets X and Y, then i extends to F y! X as
logical
of Det, whence by (94) their interpretations are AI. This analysis moreover follows: for all x E F y! x, i (f) is that element of F y! X such that
suggests the following language universal: for all x EX, i (f)(x) = i (f(i- I (x))).

(96) Universal I Given (98), slightly elaborated to cover types for categories like (PI, P 2 , •• .> /
All syntactically simple Dets in a language which are extensional (PI, P2 , •• .>, we may define an element TETe, C any category, to be
are automorphism invariant automorphism invariant iff i (T) = T, all automorphisms i on Te which extend
ones on P. The reader may check that this yields the same results as earlier
Of course we probably want the interpretations of several and a few to for AI elements of TDet. We may then show:
EXTENDING THE CLASS OF DETS 245 EXTENDING THE CLASS OF DETS 247

THEOREM 34. whose natural interpretations are easily shown to be conservative are fewer . ..
than . .. , exactly as many . .. as . .. , twice as many . .. as . .. , etc.
(a) Tiv has no elements which are automorphism invariant. There are at least two properties of interest concerning such two place
prop Dets. First, we cannot treat them as one place functions from Pinto TDet.
(b) Each of TN, TAP, and TP 1 have exactly two AI elements. If we did, the appropriate definition would be:
i
(c) Tp z has at most four AI elements.
(I 00) For each q E P, (more than q) is that function f from Pinto p*
We note that Theorem 34 holds regardless of the size of P and hence of the such that for allp EP,f(P) = {s: I(s /\p)l> I(s /\ q)l}.
. number of individuals of the model. Thus Theorem 34 (a) says that there
can be no logically constant proper nouns. Part (b) says for example that But clearly the function f above is not conservative (so more than q does
there can be at most two logically distinct logical constants among the PI'S not lie in TDet) since if it were it would follow that for all properties s, p
(their simplest expressions are exist and not exist). Part (c) says that there I(s /\ p)1 > I(s /\ q)1 iff I«s /\ p) /\ p)1 > I«s /\ p) /\ q)1 which is obviously
are at most four logically distinct logical constants among the Pz's. (The false.
only one which is lexically expressible is be; the others are not be and the The second point of interest is that two place Dets give us a way to
zero and unit elements of Tp z .) It is then no accident that we do not find represent a certain ambiguity, or variation in interpretation of noun phrases
more logical constants among the proper nouns, common nouns, intersecting consisting (apparently) of an ordinary Det and a conjunction or disjunction
adjectives, and one and two place predicates. of common noun phrases. The subject noun phrase of (lOla) below is perhaps
Matters are quite otherwise for TDet however. There are 'typically' a most naturally interpreted as synonymous with that in (I 01 b), whereas that
rather large number of AI elements in TDet. Moreover the number increases in (102a) is more naturally thought of as synonymous with that in (1 02b).
with the number of individuals and thus does not have a fixed upper bound
An informal way to exemplify this is to note that for a finite P with k indi- (101) a. A man and woman came to see me today
viduals, all the Dets of the form at least kl' more than kl' etc. for kl > k b. A man and a woman came to see me today
denote the same element of TDet. namely the zero element. But choosing
a P with more than k individuals some of these Dets will no longer denote (102) a. A professor and civil rights activist will speak this afternoon
the zero element. As all these Dets are AI then we infer that the number of b. An individual who is both a professor and a civil rights activist
AI elements of TDet increases with the size of P. will speak this afternoon.
These facts are perhaps not sufficient to explain why in fact so many of
the AI elements of TDet are naturally expressible in English, but they do at If we analyze such constructions as consisting of a Det and a conjunction
least say that it is possible to have many logical constants among the Dets. of N's, the only interpretation we represent is that in (102). To represent
We might note that TN has even more AI elements than TDet since for every the interpretation in (101) we can extend the class of two place Dets by
AI element I of TDet. I (1) and I (0) are AI elements of TN. Taking (as we treating a . .. and ... as a two place Det and interpreting a p and q as
have) individual and non-individual to denote the unit and zero respectively a (P) n a (q). More generally:
in TN such AI elements of TN are expressible whenever the AI element lin
TDet is. For example, every individual, at least three individuals, etc. denote DEFINITION 48. ForfEFp*/p'
AI elements of TN. These elements however are not commonly expressed
by syntactically simple elements of N, though indefinite pronouns such as (a) (f and) is that function from p2 into p* such that for all p. q E P,
everyone, no one, and someone are near exceptions (if we take them as (f and) (p, q) =f(P) nf(q)
syntactically simple). (b) (f or) is that function from p2 into p* such that for allp, q EP,
Universal I suggests another related way in which Det semantically differs (f or) (p, q) =f(P) U f(q).
246 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 248 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

from other boolean categories. Namely, it imposes a severe constraint on how THEOREM 36. If f E Fp*/p is conservative then so are (f and) and (f or).
the lexical elements of the category may be interpreted in TDet. In general, Proof. Let sand t have the same meet with p and the same meet with
most elements of TDet are not possible denotations of lexical Dets. By q. Then,
contrast, for an arbitrary P, an arbitrary element of TP I is denotable. Simply
choose a lexical interpreting function M which interprets say sleep as that s E (f and) (p, q) iff s Ef(P) nf(q) Definition of (f and)
element. Let us say that a category C is expressively free if there is an expres- iff s Ef(P) and s Ef(q) Definition of n
sion e E C such that for any ontology (P, 2) and any element 1 E Tc there iff t Ef(P) and t Ef(q) fis conservative
is an interpretation m such that m(e) = 7. Then PI is expressively free. ifft E(fand) (p, q)
Is Det expressively free? The answer is not obvious, for while lexical Dets
The proof that (f or) is conservative is completely analogous. Moreover both
are not freely interpreted, more complex Dets such as John's, etc. introduce
proofs generalize easily to the case where f is a function from pn into P*.
greater degrees of freedom, not being constrained to denote AI elements
of TDet. Nonetheless, under quite generous assumptions concerning what
Extending Possessive Determiners
non-logical expressions Dets may be formed from, it is shown in Keenan
and Stavi (op. cit.) that: We have been treating IS as having the category DetlN (= (N/N) IN). Here
we shall extend its category in a variety of ways which are of syntactic
THEOREM 35. There is no element e of Det such that for any finite P and and semantic interest. First, we argued in Keenan and Faltz (1978) that IS
any element f of T Det there is an interpretation m such that m ( e) = f. should be able to combine directly with N's to form expressions of category
N/f\!. On this view, John's house would be analyzed as (John ('s house)).
Semantically, IS would send a property p to that complete homomorphism
Generalizing Determiners
from Til into Til such that for all individuals I, IS (P) (I) = ('s (I)) (P) as
As suggested at the beginning of this section, it is not unreasonable to analyze previously given. We shall not pursue that analysis here, but only want to note
expressions such as more . .. than . .. as it occurs in more students than that both analyses of IS may be incorporated into our system by assigning IS
teachers as ones which combine with two N's to form an N. Semantically to the category «N/N), (N/IV» I (N/N>.
then such expressions would be interpreted by functions from P X Pinto P*. A more important extension concerns the use of IS in expressions such
For example, the obvious definition of more ... than . .. is given by: as John's friend, every country's president, etc. Since friend, president,
etc. are of category NI (= N/N) it appears that we should allow Dets like
(99) For all p, q EP, nwre p than q = {s EP: Is /\ pi > Is /\ q I} John's to combine directly with N I 's as well as No's (that is, N's) to form
N's. For simplicity of presentation let us think of John's for the nonce as
If we adopt such an analysis it is natural to wonder whether the notion of have only the category N/N I and let us take the type for that category as
conservativity generalizes to such functions. In fact it does, the characteriza- simply the entire set offunctions from TN I into TN, regarded as a (complete
tion in Theorem 24 forming the basis of the generalization: and atomic) algebra where the operations are defmed pointwise. Then IS
would be of category (N/N I ) IN and would be interpreted as follows:
DEFINITION 47. For all n > 0, all functionsffrom pn intoP*,fis conserva-
tive iffforallp,q EP and all n-tuples (rl, r2,"" rn}Epn, if(p/\ ri) = (q /\ ri), (103) M ('s) is that complete homomorphism from Til into FTil/TNI
all ri in the n-tuple, then p E f(r1> r2, ... , rn) iff q E f(r1, r2, ... ,rn). such that for all individuals I and all f E TN l' M ('s) (I) (f) =
M (the) (f(/)).
This obviously coincides with our earlier defmition for the case where n = 1.
Further, the reader may easily check that more . .. than ... as defined in We may then extend the previous analyses of s to accommodate this usage
f

(99) is a two place conservative function. Other expressions of this sort by assigning IS the category in (104).
EXTENDING THE CLASS OF DETS 249 VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS 251

(l04) (WIN> / (N I , No), NIN) I WIN> is a P 2. Our syntax for self will tell us that (self x save from x) is also a P2 ;
it combines then with the N Mary to form a P!, and the result combines
Note that on this analysis John's friend and the friend of John will be with the N John to form a Po .
logically equivalent, that is, always interpreted by the same element of TN. Finally the A operator is used to represent ambiguities of quantifier scope
But this will fail for every student's friend and the friend of every student. as well as variable binding which cannot be expressed by the syntactically
To see the difference, imagine a state of affairs in which each student has more restricted operators such that and self. Thus the classical scope ambi-
exactly one friend. Then every student's friend will be the intersection of guity in (I lOa) below can be represented in our extended language. (110b)
those individuals. But the friend of every student will denote the unique represents the 'natura1' reading of (1 lOa) in which every student has wide
individual who has the property that for every student he is a friend of his. scope over some book. (110c) represents the reading in which some book
If there is no such individual then it will denote the empty set. Arguably has wide scope over every student.
in fact the English expression the friend of every student is ambiguous,
having either of the interpretations noted above (though every student's (110) a. Every student read some book
friend is not ambiguous, having only the interpretation given). The second b. (every student) (read (some book»
reading, on which it is a paraphrase of every student's friend, cannot be c. (some book) (Ax «every student) (read x»).
represented in L at the moment, but it can be once variable binding operators
are introduced in the next section. There the wide scope reading may be In (1lOc) the expression (every student read x) is of category Po; the result
represented by (every student) (Ax the friend (of) x). of combining it with A and x is a PI, which combines then with some book
Finally, a somewhat more subtle use of's concerns the ambiguity in to form aPo .
(lOSa) below: We note that our treatment of A is general enough to represent similar
scope ambiguities within N's. Thus the two readings of (lIla) are represented
(105) a. Every student's bike was stolen as in (111 b, c) below:
b. For each student, his bike was stolen
(111) a. some friend of every senator
c. Every bike of the student variety was stolen
b.(some (friend (every senator»)
of
Only the reading in (1 OSb) is currently represented in L. To represent the c. (every senator) (Ax (some (friend x»)
(lOSc) reading we shall extend's to allow it to combine with N's (student) of
to form something which combines with an N (bike) to yield an N (student's In (I 11 c) the expression (some friend x) is an N and (A x some friend x) is
of of
bike). The (lOSc) reading then will be represented as (every «student's) an (N)! , that is, an N/N, so the whole expression in ( 111 c) is an N.
bike)). We will think of student's bike as merely specifying a subtype of As an example of variable binding expressible with A but not with the
bike, so in effect student's will be interpreted by a restricting function from other operators consider (lI2a) below which has a reading expressed in
Pinto P, that is, an element of TAP. Thus on this view, M ('s) will send a (I 12b) in which informally his is bound by every child.
property p to an arbitrary element of TAP since we have no substantive
way of saying what we mean by 'bike of the student variety'. nor have we (112) a. Every child and his father
investigated whether M ('s) in this use should have any particular properties b. «every child) (A x (x and x's father»)
other than yielding a restricting function from Pinto P. This analysis can
be made compatible with our previous analyses by assigning's the category Since x is a N we have that (x and x's father) is an N, so the result above
in (l06). of combining it with A and x is a N/N, which combines with the N every
child to yield an N.
(106) «N, N) I (N, N), (N, f.i> I (N, NI »I <N, f.i> Another use of the lambda operator, whose formal statement must await
250 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 252 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

6. VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS the intensional logic of Part II, is the creation of transparent or de re
structures. Thus in Part II the transparent reading of (113a), in which we
We shall now extend L to include variables and variable binding operators understand that there is a unicorn and John sought it, may be represented
(VBO's). The VBO's are 'A, self, and suchthat. The variables are XI, X2, ... ; as in (113b). The more natural reading, in which the existence of a unicorn
they will have category N. Arbitrary variables will often be denoted simply is not implied, will be represented directly, that is, without the use of a
x andy. lambda operator, as in (1l3c).
OUf motivation for extending L in this way is twofold. First, we shall
be able to represent English expressions such as relative clauses and reflexives (113) a. John sought a unicorn
not currently representable in L (or its previous extensions). And second, b. (John «'A x (seek x)) (a unicorn))
we can represent alternate readings (ambiguities) of English expressions c. (John) (seek (a unicorn)
in cases where only one reading is currently representable in L. Below we
informally illustrate some typical cases of these extensions and then turn to We turn now to the formal statement of the syntax and semantics of
their formal statement. VBOs.
The such that operator is used to represent English relative clauses. Thus First, variables are added to L as follows. Put var in the set of subcatego-
(l07a) below will be represented as in (l07b). rization features for L, whence for all CE CAT, Cvar is a subcategory ofC.
Potentially, therefore, we allow variables of every category; in practice
(107) a. every doctor (who(m)) Mary saw we shall limit our variables to Nvar . Thus, for every positive integer n we
b.(every (doctor (x suchthat (Mary (saw x»)))). add the symbol Xn to the basic vocabulary V. (we may think of Xn as an
abbreviation for ('x', n) if we like.) By lexical rule we set {xn: n a positive
In (107b), x is of the category N so (Mary saw x) is of category Po. Our interger}= Nvar .
syntax for suchthat will tell us that (x such that (Mary saw x» is an inter- Semantically we expect that the type for Nvar will be a subset of the type
secting AP. It thus forms an N when combined with theN doctor. And since for f.!. In fact we limit our variables to range over individuals. Thus.
every is a Det (NIN), the entire expression in (1 07b) is an N.
The self operator forms reflexives, as illustrated in: DEFINITION 49. Titvar = Ip.

(l08) a. No doctor shot himself Recall that Ip is the set of individuals over P (= TN). The type for the variables
b. (no doctor) (self x (shoot x). then is not closed with respect to the boolean operations on Tit and we do
not enter Nvar into our list of boolean categories, just as we did not enter
Since shoot is a P2 and x an N, shoot x in (l 08b) is a PI' Our syntax for self Nprop into that list.
will tell us that (self x (shoot x)) is also a PI , whence the entire expression Note that L as so far extended provides expressions like (x3 sleep). Our
in (108b) is aP o . principle interest in such expressions, as in standard logic, is the role they
Our syntax for self is general enough that it can 'bind' positions other play in defining the interpretation of expressions containing a VBO in which
than the two argument positions of P 2 's. We may for example represent ex
they occur such as (x 3 such that 3 sleep)). Such expressions however have
object controlled reflexives as in (109): some independent interest which we shall note but not pursue. Namely,
there is a sense in which they correspond to English expressions like he is
(109) a. John saved Mary from herself sleeping in which the denotation of he is understood to be provided in some
b. (John «self x (save from x» Mary) way by the context of utterance. Such expressions contrast with ones like
John is sleeping in which, in an ordinary discourse, social conventions of some
In (1 09b) from x is a Predicate Modifier and save a P 2, whence save from x sort determine the denotation of John and typically different occurrences
VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS 253 VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS 255

of John are interpreted as the same individual. Different occurrences of he (114) For each expression e in a boolean category C, and each variable
however may be interpreted more easily as different individuals, especially x, (AX e) is an expression of category CjN.
if accompanied by overt acts of ostension, as in he is drunk and he is merely
exhausted. Thus, where X and yare variables (elements of Nvar ) we have that (x (kiss y»
It would be linguistically interesting to pursue the difference in context is a Po, whence (A x (x (kiss y ») is of category Po/N, that is, PI, and (A y
dependency between definite pronouns like he, she, it, and proper nouns (A x (x (kiss y»))) is of category PIN (= P z ). Similarly, since (some (friend x»)
- -- ~
like John by formally distinguishing how they are interpreted. For example is a Nwe have that (AX (some friend x» is of category NiN.
of
we might represent a context (minimally at least) by functions which assign Semantically an expression of the form (A x e) will be interpreted by an
appropriate values to variables and then interpret expressions in L relative element of TC/N' where e is of category C and C is boolean. Thus Tc is a
to such assignments; that is, we would interpret expressions not directly as complete and atomic algebra and TC;N is the set of complete homomorphisms
elements of the appropriate type but rather as functions from assignments from TN = P* into Tc. By the Justification Theorem we can define such
into the appropriate type. In this way the interpretation of (x 3 sleep) would homomorphisms by stating their values on the individuals. This we do as
vary with the context. follows:
Later in this section we shall sketch this approach in somewhat more
detail as it overcomes a technical awkwardness in our formal definition of DEFINITION 52. For (P, 2, M) a model, x E Nvar and e E C, C boolean,
the interpretations of VBOs. A full treatment however would lead us to m (A x e) is that complete homomorphism from TN into Tc such that for
the study of the context dependency of English expressions in general, all individuals I, m(A x e) (I) = m'(e), where m' is that x-variant of m such
something we shall eschew for purely practical reasons: it would be a long that m'(x) =1.
study, requiring for example a serious treatment of tense in English, and
the novelty and interest of our work here does not in any specific way So for example m (AXI (every boy kiss xd) is that complete homomorphism
concern such context dependencies. which assigns to an individual I the truth value of (every boy kiss xd where
Let us turn now to the treatment of the VBOs themselves. To present their Xl has now been interpreted as I. (We refer the reader to the end of this
semantics it will be helpful to recall first the way in which a full interpretation section for further technical comments on Definition 52.)
of L is defined. We now go through several examples to illustrate how expressions involving
We have defined a model to be a triple (P, 2, M, where 2 is the boolean A are actually interpreted with this definition (writing (A x e) indifferently
algebra of truth values, P is an arbitrary complete atomic boolean algebra, as (x A e), which we may do since derived expressions are sets). First, starting
and M is a lexical assignment function. Let us denote by V+ the subset with the formula John (kiss x) we may form the expression (x A(John (kiss
of the set of vocabulary items V consisting of interpretable expressions. x)) of category Po/N = PI. Combining this with an N, say Mary, we form
The expressions of V which are not themselves interpreted are the boolean a new formula (Po). Since Mary is a proper noun, its interpretation in any
combiners and, or, and not, and, now that we are adding them, the VBOs model, say, the model (P, 2, M), will be an individual, say 1m. Thus we have
such that, self, and A. Thus, we simply have V+ = V - {and, or, not, suchthat, m (Mary) =M(Mary) =Im.
self, A} We can now say that V+ is the domain of M, and if e E V+ and e is Now, by the way interpretations are constrained on functional expres-
of category C, thenM (e) is an element of Te. sions, we have that m«Mary) (x A John (kiss x») = (m (x A John (kiss x»)
Now, given the triple (P, 2,M, there is a unique function m defined whose (m(Mary» = (m (x A John (kiss x») (Im). But by the definition above, this
domain is the set of all expressions of the language L. If e is an expression is simply equal to m' (John (kiss x», where m' is the x-variant of m such that
of L, then we just have m (e) = M (e) if e E V+ . If e is a complex expression, m' (x) =1m. Since m' is an x-variant ofm, we have that m' (John) = m (John)
then m (e) is calculated according to the principles we have been using all = Ij (say), and m'(kiss) = m(kiss) = k (say). Thus, since m'(x) = 1m , we have
along. Thus, if e is a boolean combination of expressions then m (e) is the that m'(kiss x) = k (Im), and therefore m'(John (kiss x» = (k (Im» CIj).
appropriate boolean function of the interpretations of the constituents of e. We have thus shown that the interpretation in the model (p, 2, M) of
254 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 256 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

And if e is composed of an expression of a functional category and an (Mary) (x A John (kiss x» is (k(1m» (4), where k, Im, and 4 are the inter-
expression of its argument category, then m (e) is calculated by applying the pretations in this model of kiss, Mary, and John respectively. The reader
interpreting function to the interpreting argument. Now that we are adding can easily check that this is also the interpretation in this model of the
the VBOs to our language, of course, we must define how m (e) is calculated formula John (kiss Mary). Thus, (Mary) (x A John (kiss x» and John (kiss
in the case that e is constructed using a VBO. We will do this in a moment. Mary) are logically equivalent (since the model (P, 2, M) was arbitrary).
But here, let us note that, with P fixed, the functions m are in one-to-one Examining these two expressions we can see the sense in which the A effects
correspondence with the lexical assignment functions M. For, distinct Ms a substitution of the N Mary for the variable x.
lead to distinct ms (since, for MJ and M2 to be distinct, we must have MJ (e) As a somewhat less trivial example, let us start with the formula (every
of M 2 (e) for some e E V+; but then, since miCe) = Mi(e) (i = 1 or 2), we boy) (kiss x) and form the expression (x A (every boy) (kiss x», which is
have m J(e) of m2 (e) for this expression e). On the other hand, given M, there again a member of category PolN = PI. Let us calculate the interpretation
is a unique m defined, as we have already indicated. Finally, we note that of the formula which results when this PI is combined with the N a girl.
if m is an interpretation function, then the restriction of m to V+ is the Letting <P, 2,111) be the model we are working in, we have, say, m(kiss) =
lexical assignment function M which gave rise to it. M(kiss) = k, m(boy) = M(boy) = b, and m(girl) = M(girl) = g. Next, we
In order to give the definitions of the interpretations of the VBOs we will have that mea girl) = a(g) = Ug E I I. We therefore have that m«a girl) (x A
need the notions defined as follows: (every boy) (kiss x») = (m (x A (every boy) (kiss x») (m (a girl)) = (m (x A
(every boy) (kiss x») (U g E I£)= Vg EI (m (x A(every boy) (kiss x») (£),
DEFINITION 50. Let MJ and M2 be two lexical assignment functions relative
where the last equation follows because m(x A (every boy) (kiss x» is a
to a given ontology (P, 2), and let x E Nvar . Then MJ is an x-variant of M2
homomorphism and so preserves joins.
iff for every y E V+ such thaty of x, MJ (y) = M2(y)'
Now, by Definition 52 above, m (x A (every boy) (kiss x» (£) =m' «every
Thus, M J is an x-variant of M2 iff M J interprets every lexical item the same boy) (kiss x», where m' is the x-variant of m such that m' (x) = I. Since m'
as M2 , with the possible exception of the variable x. Note, therefore, that is an x-variant of m, we have m'(boy) = m(boy) = band m'(kiss) = m(kiss)
if M2 is given, and if we specify that MJ is an x-variant of M2 , then MJ is =k. Thus,
completely and uniquely determined by assigning a value to MJ (x).

DEFINITION 51. Let m J and m2 be two functions which interpret the


m'«every boy) (kiss x» n
= (k (1» (bEl J) (from the definition of
m(every»
language L; assume that mi restricted to V+ is the lexical assignment function = /\ (k (1» (J) (since k (I) is a homo-
Mi (i = 1 or 2), again with the same P chosen for both. Then m J is an x-variant bEl morp hi sm.
)
of m2 iff M J is an x-variant of M2 .
(J ranges over individuals of course). Substituting this in the expression
By the fact that the interpretation functions of the language are in one-to-one obtained above for m«a girl) (x A (every boy) (kiss x))), we arrive at the
correspondence with the lexical assignment functions, we conclude that if conclusion that this is equal to Vg E I [/\b E 1 (k (J)) (J)] . This expression
m2 is an interpretation function and if mJ is specified as an x-variant of m2, is true iff there is some. individual who is a girl which is such that every
then mJ is completely defined by giving a value for mJ(x). individual who is a boy kisses her. In other words, the interpretation of
We are now in a position to give the syntax and semantics of the VBOs. (a girl) (x A (every boy) (kiss x» differs from the interpretation of (every
boy) (kiss (a girl)) precisely in that, in the latter formula, the quantifier
combined with boy has wide scope, whereas in the former formula, the
The Lambda Operator
quantifier combined with girl has wide scope. Thus, the effect of the A to
Syntactically we enrich L by adding (114) below to the formation rules for render the object argument position of kiss accessible after kiss x is combined
complex expressions in L : with a subject N also includes the effect of giving that now-accessible object
VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS 257 V ARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS 259

N wide scope over the subject N. The A therefore enables us to represent in is a PI, so then is (Xl self (cut Xl». And if (save (from x» is aP 2 then so
our logical language the possible but less-common scope relationship of the is (x self (save (from x»). Semantically we define:
English sentence every boy kissed a girl in which only one girl is involved.
Note that the more common reading of every boy kissed a girl is the one DEFINITION 53. For (x self e) as in (117), m(x self e) is that complete
with the simplest representation in our system, namely (every boy) (kiss (a homomorphism from TN into TC such that for all individuals I, m (x self e) (I)
girl», whereas the less common reading is the one which requires the use =m'(e) (I), where m' is that x-variant of m such that m'(x) =I.
of the A: (a girl) (x A (every boy) (kiss x». It is surely not an accident that From the above definition it follows that for m an interpretation of Land
the more common reading is represented in the simpler way. Rather, it is 1 an individual, m(x self (cut x» (I) = m(cut) (I) (I). In more detail:
evidence that our system, more than being merely logically adequate, reflects
something of the way real English is interpreted. Of course, the correlation (118) m(x self (cut x»)(I)
= m'(cut x) (I), where m'(x) = 1 Definition 53
between simplicity of representation and priority of reading would have to be
verified in a wide variety of cases, something we do not do here. Nevertheless, = m'(cut) (m'(x» (I) m' is an interpretation
it seems promising to us that such a correlation may exist, based on several and (cut x) is generated
particular cases such as the one we have just seen. by the rules of functional
The examples of the use of A that we have looked at all involved combining applications
= m' (cut) (I) (I) m' (x) =1
it with a formula. However, the definitions given for the syntax and semantics
of this VBO are quite general. For example, if e is an expression of category =m(cut) (I) (I) m' is an x-variant of m
Pn or N n , then (x A e) is a well-formed and interpretable expression of and so differs from m on
category Pn +l or Nn+l respectively. For example, (x A (kiss x» is a Pz. lexical expressions only
By Definition 52, the interpretation of this expression as applied to an atx.
individual I, that is, (m(x A (kiss x)) (1), is m'(kiss x), where m' is the We may then calculate the interpretation of our representation for every
x-variant of m such that m'(x) = I. However, we have m'(kiss x) = student cut himself in (119) below as follows, where we take m (student) to
(m'(kiss» (m'(x» = (m(kiss» (1), since m'(kiss) = m(kiss). Since the equation be the property sand 1 ranges over individuals:
(m(x A (kiss x») (1) = (m(kiss» (1) holds for an arbitrary individual I, we
can conclude that m(x A (kiss x» = m(kiss), and since kiss was an arbitrarily (119) m(every student) (x self (cut x»)
chosen P z , subject only to the condition that m'(kiss) = m(kiss), we can con- =m(x self (cut x») m(every student)
clude further that if e is a P 2 which does not contain any free occurrence =m(x self (cut x» ( n
['9 S
I)
of x, then the interpretation of the P2 (x A (e x» is always the same as the =['91\ S m(x self(cutx»)(/) m(x selfcutx) is a homomorphism
interpretation of e; that is, e and (x A (e x» are logically equivalent. In
particular, this holds if e is a lexical P 2 . The reader may easily show that =[!is m(cut)(/)(I) by(118 above).
the logical equivalence of e and (x A (e x» remains true if e is any expression
(in a boolean category of the form C/fJ) not containing a free occurrence of Note that the corresponding representation for every student cut every
x. This suggests that our definitions may be too general. student would be as in (120) below, where 1 and J range over individuals:
However, in addition to those cases in which e does contain a free oc- (120) [1\ [ 1\ m (cut) (J) (I)]
'9s J3S
currence of x so that e and (x A (e x» are logically distinct, let us point out
here that in the intensional system it will turn out that e and (x A (e x») Thus the effect of the VBO self is not to mechanically substitute the
are not in general logically equivalent, even if e does not contain a free argument expression for the variable x, a procedure which would incorrectly
occurrence of x. In particular, if e is, say, a P z such as seek which is properly lead to the conclusion that every student cut every student is logically
intensional on its object, then the interpretation of e as combined with an equivalent to (every student) (x self (cut x».
258 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 260 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

object N will always represent the de dictu interpretation, whereas the Note that the analysis in (118) remains essentially unchanged if cut x is
interpretation of the P 2 (x A (e x)) as combined with an object N will re- replaced by any expression (with a free occurrence of x) in any category of
present the de re interpretation. Thus, it appears that the generality of our the form CjN. Thus if expressions such as safe from x or tell about x are
definitions is indeed necessary in order for the significant distinction between analyzed as complex P 2 s we may compute that m (x self (save (from x))) is
de dietu and de re readings to be representable in our logic. that homomorphism whose value at an individual lis m(from (I) m(save) (I).
Note finally the case of expressions (X x e) where e is not in a category Thus (x self (save (from x))) is an appropriate representation in L for the
of the form CjN; for example, e may be a Po. In such a case the reader English to save from oneself. Similarly, making use a few more times of the
may prove that m (A x e) is that complete homomorphism whose value at definition of an interpretation at expressions generated by the rules of
each I is just m(e). So meA x e) is constant on the individuals. Surprisingly functional applications, we may compute the value of m(x self (love (x's
perhaps such expressions with 'vacuous' variable binding may be of some mother))) at an individualIto be m (love) [('s) (J) (m (mother)) (J)], whence
utility in representing English expressions. For example, while (l1Sb, c) that P 1 is an appropriate representation for to love one's own mother. (we
are logically equivalent, we may want to choose (I lSb) as a representation note that many languages, such as Hindi and Japanese, present reflexive
for (lISa) on grounds of better correspondence between surface form and possessives, somewhat imperfectly realized in English as one's own).
logical form. This essentially completes our analysis of reflexives. The following reflec-
tions on that analysis suggest ways we might want to extend or restrict that
(115) a. As for John, everybody loves him analysis.
b. (John (Ax (everybody (love x)))) First, some languages appear not to permit object controlled reflexives of
c. (everybody (love John)). the save Mary from herself, tell Mary about herself sort. One might suggest
that the semantic representations for those languages would present a more
Now, while the variable binding in (llSb) is not vacuous since (everybody restricted self operator in which in (x self e) e was required to be a Pl' But if
love x) contains a free occurrence of the variable introduced with the lambda the logic for those languages has an unrestricted lambda operator of the
operator, we may concoct other examples, somewhat less natural admittedly, sort we have presented, the restriction on (x self e) will not in fact guarantee
in which the binding is vacuous. Imagine for example a discussion of a new that 'inherently' non-subject noun phrases cannot control reflexives. Thus in
university complex in which someone says "The classrooms are barely toler- (121) below the object argument y of tell about x controls the reference of x:
able, and as for the auditorium, you can't even hear the speaker from the
podium". It is not unreasonable here to represent the second conjunct above (121)
by (the auditorium (A x e)), where e represents you can't even hear the
speaker from the podium.

Po
The Reflexive Operator
-~
The VBO self will serve to bind a variable which occurs in an expression N P1
that takes an N argument in such a way that that variable has the same ~-
interpretation as that argument when it is an individual. We thus enrich L P2 N
as follows:
(117) For C a boolean category, e an expression of category CjN, and
1~PM
for x E Nvar , (x self e) is an expression of category CjN. ~-
PrepN
Note that e and (x self e) above have the same category. Thus since (cut xd
x self y John tell
I
about
I
x y
VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS 261 VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS 263

Second, note that (x self e) is logically equivalent to (A x (e x)). So the DEFINITION 54. For e, x as in (124), and for any model <P, 2, M>,
reflexive operator self does not contribute anything to the expressive power m (x such that e) is that intersecting function from Pinto P such that for each
of L as extended. But it does give us structures which correspond better to individual I, m(x suchthat e) (1) E I iff m'(e) = 1, where m' is the x-variant
natural English. Thus in the lambda representation for reflexives John cut of m such that m' (x) =I.
himself would be represented as (John (A x (x (cut x)))). This expression
contains an embedded Po, (x (cut x)) and aN, the subject of (x (cut x)), not To exemplify this definition let us assume an arbitrary model (P, 2, M>
present in any way in the English expression. The representation with self and calculate the interpretation of(125) below:
localizes the complexity of reflexives in the PI and does not present the
additional N expression. It thus provides a better correspondence with the (125) student (x suchthat (Dorothy (hug x»).
English expression whose logical properties it represents. It also provides
more natural representations (present in the intensional logic) for reflexive This phrase is formed by combining the N student with the AP (x such that
Pn's in which no subject is present in English, as in to shave oneself in the (Dorothy (hug x») and so is itself of category N. Its interpretation is therefore
dark is difficult. an element of P. For convenience, let us set m(x such that (Dorothy (hug x»)
Third, our semantics for reflexives crucially (it appears) uses the fact = f. Then the interpretation of the phrase (125) is res), where s =m(student).
that e in (x self e) is interpreted by a function taking elements of TN as Our task is to determine just what property [(s) actually is. We will do
arguments. Thus e cannot be a PM (in x's garden) or an AP (proud of x) since this by indicating for each arbitrary individual I whether or not I contains
these expressions are interpreted by functions taking properties and n > 0 res).
place predicate denotations as arguments respectively. Equally e cannot be First, since [is intersecting, we have that [(s) = s A [(1). By the Meets
an N (friend of x) since Ns are not interpreted by functions at all. Yet e can Condition on individuals (part A), the individual I contains [ (s) if and only
be a PI and the types for PM (whether subject or argument oriented), AP , and if I contains both sand [(1).
N are isomorphic to the type for Pl' Thus it is a straightforward matter to Next, we apply Definition 54 above. Set m(Dorothy) = Id and m(hug)
extend the domain of the reflexive operator to apply to expressions in these = h. If m' is the x-variant of m such that m'(x) = I (where I is an arbitrary
categories. The mechanism for the extension is given informally by the individual), then m'(Dorothy (hug x» = (m'(hug x» (m'(Dorothy» =
diagram in (122) below, where C is any category whose type is isomorphic (h (I)) (fd) (since m'(hug) = m(hug) and m'(Dorothy) = m(Dorothy». Thus,
to that for PI and h is such an isomorphism. Then for eEOC, (x self e) is the individuall contains [(1) if and only if (h (f» (fd) = l.
interpreted as that element of Tc which makes the diagram commute as Combining this result with the previous paragraph, we conclude that
indicated by the dotted line: the property [(s) is the one which is contained in the individual I just in case
I contains sand h (1) (Id) = 1. Informally, (125) denotes the property an
h individual has iff that individual is a student and Dorothy hugs that individual.
(122) Tc - - - - - - -.... Tp j Thus (125) appears to be an adequate representation of the somewhat stilted
I English (126) below, as well as of the more natural expressions in (127).
I self
self I
I (126) student such that Dorothy hugged him
Tc h
who (m) 1 Dorothy hugged
For example, taking critic as an NI (= NIN) and thus (critic (of) x) as an N,
we have that the isomorphic image of m (critic of x) is m (criticize x). That
(127) student 1~hat

is, m (critic of x) is the property an individual I has iff m (criticize x) (I)


is true, whence from (122) we infer in effect that m (x self (critic of x}) is Obviously (125) exhibits a better correspondence with (126) than with
the property an individual I has iff m (x self (criticize x)) (I) is true, that is,
262 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 264 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

the individual I criticizes himself. Thus (x self (critic of x)) is a natural (127) since (126) presents an overt pronoun, him, in the position correspond-
representation of critic of oneself. ing to the bound occurrence of x in (125). We shall not consider the problem
Similarly the intersecting AP (x self (proud of x)) is a reasonable repre- of systematically relating structures like (127) to their L-representations,
sentation of proud of oneself as it is interpreted by that function from P noting only that in many languages, e.g. Persian, Fijian, Margi, Arabic, etc.
into P whose value at the unit property (the denotation of individual) is a the natural expression of (125) would present an overt 'resumptive' pronoun
member of an individual I iff m (x self (be (proud of x))) holds of I. That in surface. (128) below from Hebrew is illustrative.
is, the individual I is proud of himself.
Finally, a reflexive PM such as (x self (in x's garden)) will denote that (128) talmid se- Dorit xibka oto
element of TpM whose value at the unit element in Tp j (the denotation student that- Dorothy hugged him
arg
of exist) is the denotation of (x self (exist (in x's garden))). Thus (x self 'student who Dorothy hugged'
(in x's garden») is a reasonable representation for in one's own garden.
We might note that extending the domain of self in this way allows us to We may note as well that the superficial similarity in structure between
represent a sort of binding which is known to be difficult to represent in a (126) and (127) is perhaps misleading, suggesting that such that in English
way which preserves some reasonable correspondence between logical form is a relativizer with the same status as whom(m), that, etc. In more complex
and surface form. (l23a) below illustrates the type of problem (matching relatives however such that tends to force a wide scope reading of the head
subscripts indicating binding), and (123b) is our representation for it: N compared with who(m), that, etc. Contrast for example (l29a, b):

(123) a. a mani with a scar on hisi face (129) a. the language that everyone here speaks best (is an Indo-European
b.(a (man (x self (with a scar onx's face»). language)
b. the language such that everyone here speaks it best ...
(Note that we have assumed here that the domain of PMs has been extended
to include N. This assumption is unproblematic since TN is isomorphic to (129b) rather forces the interpretation that everyone here speaks the same
Tp j which is already included in the domain ofPMs.) language best, whereas (129a) seems to allow that different people here
may speak different languages best; it is true as long as in each case that
language is an Indo-European one.
The Relative Clause Operator Moreover the such that construction, analyzed as an AP in L, functions
naturally as an AP in predicate position, illustrated in (130a) below and
Adding (124) below to the formation rules of L allows us to generate relative represented in L by (130b). The wh-relatives function less naturally in pred-
clauses straightforwardly: icate position, as indicated in (131).

(124) if e is an expression of category Po and x a variable then (x (130) a. No one is such that everyone likes him
suchthat e) is a phrase of category AP. b. (no individual (be (x such that (every individual like x))))
i

To interpret such expressions recall first that a property (an element of (131) *No one is who(m) everyone likes
P = TN) is defined by stating just what individuals it is an element of (see
the earlier discussion in Part A). And secondly, recall that TAP is the set of Notice also that the such that construction in English, especially when
intersecting functions from Pinto P and that any such fun~tion is defined functioning predicatively, does not always force the sentence it combines
by stating its value at the unit property. We may then straightforwardly with to contain a bound N position, as in the acoustics of the auditorium
interpret expressions of the form (x such that e) as follows: were such that no one could hear the speaker from the podium.
V ARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS 265 NON-HOMOMORPHIC PREDICATES? 267

Observe further that the VBO such that allows us to construct relatives This concludes our treatment of VBOs in L. It also essentially concludes
in L which correspond to ungrammatical wh-relatives in English due to our treatment of the extensional additions to L. Below we consider (but
the violation of island constraints. Thus (132) below corresponds to the reject) a final addition to L which has doubtless occurred to many, namely,
ungrammatical (133) in English as well as to the grammatical but stilted the addition of predicates which do not behave homomorphically on their
(134) in English and the grammatical though slightly cumbersome (135) arguments.
in Hebrew:
7. NON-HOMOMORPHIC PREDICATES?
(132) student (x suchthat (Dan (know (a girl (y suchthat (y hug x))))))
(133) *student who Dan knows a girl who hugged There are a variety of English predicates which appear to behave non-homo-
morphically on their arguments. Several such are surveyed below. The natural
(134) student such that Dan knows a girl who hugged him suggestion for incorporating such predicates into L would be to introduce
a sub categorization feature for Pns into L, say +hom, and define the type
(135) talmid se- Dan makir brumra se- xibka oto
for Pn to be Tpn as previously defined. Then predicates not in this
student that- Dan knows girl that· hugged him +hom
subcategory would not be required to be interpreted by homomorphisms.
The expressions (134) and (135) are sufficient to show that we want logical On closer examination however the apparent non-homomorphic predicates
representations for natural language expressions to contain structures which do not appear to be adequately treated in this way. Rather, to the extent
violate island constraints. Thus the motivation for such constraints in English that we understand their (pre-theoretical) semantics it seems that the domain
does not arise from any difficulty with their logical semantics and must then of these predicates is not properly taken to be sets of properties of individuals
be otherwise motivated. but rather something at least as complicated as sets of properties of sets of
Finally, we note that since an expression like (x such that e) is a member individuals. Once the domain of these predicates is properly defined, some-
of the boolean categories .N> and AP, it is possible to construct and interpret thing we do not do rigorously here, it appears that, in fact, the predicates
expressions like (136) and b37) in our logical language: do behave homomorphically.
Let us consider first some apparent non-homomorphic predicates. For
(136) (Albanian and (x suchthat Dorothy (hug x))) student a more thorough discussion we refer the reader to Gil (1982) and Busby
(137) (tall and (x suchthat Dorothy (hug x))) student. (1983) and references cited there. We shall draw examples freely from those
works below; moreover, our classification of non-homomorphic predicates
In English, there are no expressions like *Albanian and who (m) Dorothy is intended as mnemonic only. The classes are not exhaustive or mutually
hugged a student, *student Albanian and who(m) Dorothy hugged, *tall exclusive.
and who(m) Dorothy hugged a student, etc. However, as in the case of the
island constraints, we do not want to claim that the difficulty with such
Numerical Predicates
expressions resides in their logical semantics since the normal interpretations
of English phrases like Albanian student that Dorothy hugged and tall student Predicates such as be two teachers, be the two students John knows best,
that Dorothy hugged are just (136) and (137) respectively. be the only survivors, etc. appear non-homomorphic since (138a, b) below
This essentially completes our treatment of VBOs in L. Let us however are not logically equivalent, whence such predicates appear not to preserve
indicate how a (standard) awkwardness in our basic definitions may be meets.
corrected. In defining the value of an interpretation m at for example (X x e)
we refer to the values of all x-variants m' of m at e. But strictly speaking the (138) a. John and Bill are the two students I know best
. ,
only x-variant of m we are allowed to refer to is m itself, the others having b. John is the two students I know best and Bill is the two students
not yet been defined. I know best
266 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC 268 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

There are a variety of ways this difficulty can be overcome. One which, Collective Predicates
as indicated earlier, will prove useful in a more detailed treatment of context
dependency of English expressions will be sketched here. Predicates such as be a bore, be a happy couple, constitute a quorum, etc.
First, let us use for the nonce A to denote the set of functions from Nvar also appear to fail to preserve meets, as illustrated in (139a, b) below which
into Ip, the set of individuals of the model. Elements of A will be called are not logically equivalent.
assignments (of values to the variables). If a is an assignment and x is a
variable and! an individual then ax. 1 will be that x-variant of a which sends (139) a. John and Mary are a happy couple
x to I. Now given an ontology (P, 2) we define a model to be a triple (P, 2, M) b. John is a happy couple and Mary is a happy couple
as before, except that the variables do not lie in the domain of M. We shall Predicates such as solve the problem together and read ten plays between
then interpret expressions of L in general not directly as elements of the them probably also fall into this category. In any event (140a) below does
appropriate types, but rather as functions from A into the types. So the not mean anything like (140b).
interpretation of an expression will depend on what assignment is being
considered. It will turn out that expressions containing no free occurrences (140) a. John and Mary read ten plays between them
of variables will be constant functions, that is, they will not in fact depend on b. John read ten plays (between him) and Mary read ten plays
how the variables are interpreted. Typically however, expressions containing (between her)
free occurrences of variables will depend on the assignment, that is, they will
send different assignments to different elements of the appropriate type. Reciprocal Predicates
Somewhat more formally, given a model (P, 2, M) we defme m to be an
Obviously PI s such as love each other cannot be represented as homomor-
interpretation of L iff m is a fUnction from L into the set of functions from
phisms from P* into 2 since (ISOa, b) are not paraphrases:
A into the union of the types such that the following conditions are satisfied
for all a EA and all individuals!:
(ISO) a. John and Mary love each other
b. John loves each other and Mary loves each other
(i) for e in the domain of M, m (e) (a) =M (e).
(ii) for e a variable, m (e) (a) = a (e).
Into this category as well we might include a large variety of nominal and
(iii) for e), e2 in any boolean category C, m (el and e2) (a) = m (el) (a)
adjectival predicates which, in one way or another, involve a reciprocal
1\ m (e2) (a), and analogously for other boolean combinations.
meaning even though no overt use is made of the reciprocal pronoun each
(iv) forel inXjYande2 in Y, m(el e2)(a)=(m(ed(a»)(m(e2)(a»
other. Thus (ISla, b) are not paraphrases:
(v) for e in any boolean catefory C, m (A x e) is that complete
homomorphism from Tjij into Tc such that m (A x e) (a) (1) =
(151) a. John and Bill are partners/friends/enemies
m (e) (ax. I)' b. John is a partner/friend/enemy and Bill is a partner/friend/enemy
(vi) for e in a boolean category of the form CjM m (x self e) (a) (I) =
m (e)(a x 1)(1) Similar predicates crucially involving adjectives would be live in neighboring
(vii) for e of ~ategory Po, m (x such that e) (a) (1) E I iff
villages, work on parallel streets, attend the same school, work for different
m (e) (ax, I) = 1.
employers, etc. So called symmetric predicates such as (intransitive) meet, be
parallel, etc. also fall into this category.
Note that this approach does overcome the awkwardness alluded to since,
for example, the value of m at (A x e) does not refer to the values of other
Intensional Predicates
interpretations m' at e but only to the value of m at e; analogously for the
interpretations of the other VBOs. Non-extensional predicates such as seek, look for, need, etc. appear not to
NON-HOMOMORPHIC PREDICATES? 269 NON-HOMOMORPHIC PREDICATES? 271

preserve joins since I'm looking for the owner or the manager is not (at least We shall not however pursue this approach here since it seems clear that
on one reading) logically equivalent to I'm looking for the owner or I'm we cannot adequately represent reciprocal predicates (or the other non-
looking for the manager. Similarly the complex non-extensional PI in (152) extensional ones discussed above) merely by extending the types for the
below also fails (on one reading) to preserve joins: predicates to include non-homomorphisms. Rather we must seriously extend
the domains of the predicates in our system in such a way as to introduce
(152) a. The President or the Vice-President is required to be a citizen the full apparatus of higher order logic. And while this is a much needed
b. The President is required to be a citizen or the Vice-President enterprise, it would surely encompass another monograph. Instead we turn
is required to be a citizen now to the revisions of L necessary to accommodate properly non-extensional
expressions of English.
((IS2a) is true if the constitution stipulates that 'Either the President or the
Vice-President must be a citizen', whereas that condition is not sufficient
to guarantee the truth of either disjunct of (1S2b) and thus it does not
guarantee the truth of the disjunction.)
Of the predicates considered above the intensional ones are treated in Part
II of this monograph and are in fact interpreted there by non-homomorphic
elements of the appropriate type. The other predicates however are exten-
sional and it is tempting to want to add them to L but not require that they
be interpreted by homomorphisms. It appears to us however that no such
approach is likely to succeed. To support this claim let us consider the case
of overt reciprocal predicates such as love each other.
If love each other were interpreted by some sort of function, not nec-
essarily a homomorphism, from P* into 2 this would necessitate a very
thorough going redefinition of the interpretations of Ns. For example,
conjunctions of Ns would no longer be both commutative and associative
since the natural reading of (lS3a) below is a paraphrase of (1S3b) and not
of (lS3c). Yet by the commutativity and associativity of meets, (lS3a, c) are
logically equivalent since their subject Ns are interpreted as the same element
ofP*.
(153) a. Both John and Mary and also Bill and Sue love each other
b. John and Mary love each other and Bill and Sue love each other
c. Both John and Bill and also Mary and Sue love each other

Further, determiner denotations would have to be redefined. Consider for


example a model with at least three individuals, John, Bill, and Harry, in
which Bill and Harry are the only students. Then every student is interpreted
as the same element of P* as Bill and Harry, whence (lS4a) should have the
same truth value in that model as (lS4b). But this is incorrect. (154a) is a
paraphrase of (1S4c) and does not, as judged pre-theoretically, entail (1S4d).
(154b) does however entail (1S4d).
270 PART I: THE EXTENSIONAL LOGIC

(I 54) a. John and every student love each other


b. John and (Bill and Harry) love each other
c. John and Bill love each other and John and Harry love each other PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC
d. Bill and Harry love each other

Now we can fmd no way of reinterpreting and and every in such a way
that the fis they form take their denotations in P* and the entailments we
1. INTRODUCTION TO THE INTENSIONAL SYSTEM
have previously modelled correctly by L are still correctly represented.
Additional reasons for not taking love each other as a function on p*
We now wish to address ourselves to the task of constructing a logical system
could be adduced but it seems needless to belabor the point since in fact
which can represent facts of the sort referred to as properly intensional,
our initial pre-theoretical intuitions concerning a correct approach to the
facts which cannot be handled by the extensional system developed earlier.
semantics of reciprocals are clear: love each other does not express a property
We begin with some basic discussion which will set the stage for the more
of individuals, but rather of (at least) sets of individuals. Roughly the set
detailed developments to come.
{John, Mary} has the love-each-other property iff John loves Mary and Mary
Our motivation in wanting to construct an intensional system should be
loves John. Minimally then we want the domain of the love-each-other
clear at this point. Even while developing the extensional system, we often
function to include sets of individuals, or pursuing the general approach taken came across phrases or constructions for which an extensional interpretation
here, sets of properties of sets of individuals. Once the domain of reciprocal was in principle unable to represent the logical facts adequately. For example,
predicates is correctly defined it appears, contra our initial intuitions, that an adjective like skillful cannot be correctly interpreted in a purely exten-
reciprocal predicates do behave homomorphically on their arguments. For sional manner. For if it were, then its interpretation would be a function
example, (I55a, b) below are logically equivalent, whence love each other which would take as its argument the extensional interpretation of the N
preserves joins. with which it is combined. Now, this would mean that in a world in which
(155) a. Either John and Mary or Bill and Sue love each other the individuals who are lawyers are exactly the same as the individuals who
b. Either John and Mary love each other or Bill and Sue love each are doctors, so that lawyer and doctor have the same extensional interpre-
other tation, the interpretation of skillful lawyer and of skillful doctor would
automatically be the same, since the function which interprets skillful would
Similarly the equivalence of (I56a, b) shows that reciprocal predicates have been applied to the same argument. But this is unsatisfactory: even if
preserve meets and complements: the lawyers and the doctors in some state of affairs are the same individuals,
the skillful lawyers and the skillful doctors clearly need not be so. Similar
(156) a. John and Mary but not Bill and Sue love each other situations exist in the case of other modifier categories. Thus, we noted
b. John and Mary love each other and it is not the case that Bill and earlier that PMs like manner adverbs (skillfully) or comitative phrases (With
Sue love each other Mary) cannot be adequately represented extensionally.
Pursuing this approach would probably require that we distinguish two and's The difficulty is not restricted to modifiers, of course. A classic example
in English, the lower order and we have been using which forms intersections of a transitive verb which cannot be handled extensionally is look-for. Exten-
and a higher order one which (roughly) forms sets. Using and for the lower sionally, this verb would be interpreted by a homomorphism whose argument
order one and & for the higher order one, we might represent (I 57a) below is the extensional interpretation of its object f.i. This means that, in a world
as (I 57b). in which, say, Mary and the queen refer to the same individual (so that their
extensional interpretations are the same), look for Mary and look for the
(157) a. Both John and Mary and also Bill and Sue love each other queen would automatically have the same interpretation, since the interpre-
b. ((John & Mary) and (Bill & Sue)) (love each other) tation of either would be obtained by applying the look-for homomorphism

272
INTRODUCTION TO THE INTENSIONAL SYSTEM 273 INTRODUCTION TO THE INTENSIONAL SYSTEM 275

to the common interpretation of the two noun phrases. But, again, this is defined on the basis of <P, 2, n, the reader may have guessed another possible
incorrect: John could be looking for Mary without looking for the queen (he relationship between Tc and Tt, namely that Tc =FTtlJ, that is, that the
might not know that Mary is in fact the queen). elements of TC are just all the functions with domain J and with range the
In order to handle examples such as these (and many others as well), we extensional type Tt. This by now standard notion of intension captures the
will enrich the semantic system of our language. But before we set about idea that to know the meaning of an expression is equivalent to knowing its
to do this, let us note that syntactically, we will not change our language extension in any possible world. This is in fact how the intensional types of
in any way, except to enlarge the membership of certain categories and to categories are defined in classical Montague grammar.
refine the sub categorizations. Thus, the slash, bar, and bracket notations In the system we shall propose, we shall indeed take TC to be equal
of the extensional language are defined and used exactly the same for the to FT !:IJ, but only for certain categories C, rather than for all of them,
intensional system, categories such as Pn and N m have the same definition, as is done in Montague grammar. In the core language, for example, the types
etc., and a complex expression is still an unordered set of other expressions. for the categories Po, N, and N will be so defined. However, functional
The sort of enlargement that will be involved can be illustrated by the categories will be handled differently. Suppose, say, that C = B/A. Then,
verb look-for. This verb cannot be a member of P z in the extensional lan- rather than taking Tc = FT!:IJ, we will in general take Tc to be some subset
guage, for the reason indicated above. In the intensional language, however, of FTBITA. Thus, if I is a possible (intensional) denotion of an expression
P z will contain this verb, along with others whose interpretations may be of category C, then I is indeed a function, but its argument, rather than being
properly intensional (such as criticize). Moreover, such verbs will be sub- the index of a possible world, is just the intension of the expression with
categorized in such a way that they are part of a different subcategory of which the original expression was combined. It will turn out that a relation-
P z from verbs like kiss or hit. The interpretations of expressions of category ship between FTBITA and FTt/J can often be established; how this is done
P z will then be arranged so that expressions of the latter subcategory will will become clear later on.
never be interpreted in a properly intensional manner. Suppose that C is one of those categories for which we have TC =FT!:IJ.
In addition, there are categories which are definable but which have no If I is a possible intensional denotation of an expression of category C (which
members in the extensional language. The intensional system will allow we abbreviate by calling I a C-intension), then, given j E J, l(j) is a well-
us to treat expressions which are members of certain of these. Thus, for defined member of Tt. We will call1(j) the extension 011 in the world j.
example, the categories Po, Po/Po, and Pt/Po are definable but uninhabited Next, suppose that C is a category for which it is not the case that TC =
in the extensional language. In the intensional language, these categories will FTt/J, and let I be a C-intension. Now, of course, if j E J, the expression
contain expressions such as that Bill kiss Mary, that, and believe, respectively. t(j) is undefined. However, in certain cases, it will be possible to associate
The method of presentation here will be the same as for the extensional with I a set {/j: j E J}, where each fi is a member of Tf:. This association
system. That is, we will discuss the system category by category, beginning will be biunique; this is, given I, a unique fi E Tf: will be defined for each
with a core language consisting of (at least) the categoriesN, ii, ii/N, andPn j E J, and, conversely, given the set {/j: j E J}, where each fj E Tf:, there
(for all nonnegative integers n). In the remainder of this section we lay the will be a unique lETC associated with it. In such cases, we will call fj the
groundwork for our intensional semantics. extension 01 I in the world j. (Again, we ask the reader's patience: how a
It will be recalled that, in our extensional system, for each category C, C-intension I can be associated with a set {/j: j E J} will become clear later
a set Te, the type for C, was defined. Moreover, the definition of each Te on.)
depended on the pair (P, 2), where 2 is the boolean algebra of two elements, Now, let I be a C-intension, where C is any category. Then we will say
representing the set of possible truth values of a formula, and P was an that I is extensional iff, for each j E J, I has an extension in the world j.
arbitrary complete atomic boolean algebra, representing the set of (exten- In general, we will use the notation fj to denote this extension. Thus, by
sional) properties, that is, the set of possible denotations of a common what we have said above, if I is a C-intension for a category C such that
noun. In our intensional system, we again will define a type for each category Tc = FT!:IJ, then I is necessarily extensional, and fi =l(j). For other cate-
C, which we again denote Te. However, rather than depending on the pair gories, a particular intension I mayor may not be extensional depending on
274 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 276 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

<P, 2), the definition of the intensional types will depend on the triplet <P, 2, whether the association of f with a set {/j: j E J} discussed in the previous
J>, where, as before, 2 is the boolean algebra of two elements and P is an paragraph can be defined. Thus, for these categories, we can expect that the
arbitrary complete atomic boolean algebra, but now J is an arbitrary set. The extensional intensions will form a proper subset of TC. Let us denote the
set J is to be understood as a set which indexes the possible worlds which subset of TC which consists of all the extensional intensions by Tce. Then,
are involved in a particular intensional interpretation. we have TCe = Tc if Tc =Fr{;lJ, and in general TCe ~ Tc.
Having chosen the triplet <P, 2, J> on which to base our defmitions of the We pointed out above that in the case that a C-intension f is extensional,
types, we could, of course, construct the extensional types which our earlier we want the association of f with the set {/j: j E J} to be biunique. Let us
system associated with the categories on the basis of just 2 and P (that is, formulate this as a definition:
ignoring the set J). The sets so constructed will be henceforth denoted T~.
We are thus promulgating a change of notation: sets which previously were DEFINITION 1. Given the category C, TCe is total iff for every set
denoted Te are now going to be denoted Ti;, whereas the symbol Te will {xi-' j E J} ~ Ti:, there exists a unique f E TCe such that fi = Xj'
be used for the intensional type of C. In general, we will be free to use the
superscript e to create a symbol which will denote an object defined in our Note that, a priori, a set TCe might not be total. That is, it might be possible
extensional system. to define fi E Ti: for each j E J, given a C-intension f, in such a way that
Our general task will be to create a system of model-theoretic interpre- distinct C-intensions have the same extensions in all the worlds. Or again,
tation for our logical language which will preserve the advantages and insights it might be the case that not every set {xj.' j E J} of j-indexed elements of
revealed by our extensional system while allowing properly intensional facts Tt is the set of extensions of some C-intension. These possibilities are ruled
to be represented. Loosely speaking, we want the extensional system that out when TCe is total.
we have already developed to be embedded, in some sense, inside the inten- For all the cases of interest to us, Tee will turn out to be total. Of course,
sional system we are constructing. Exactly how we propose to do this will this will have to be proved for each category or class of categories as we
become clear in the course of the presentation. However, we would like to study it. However, we can say at least the following right now:
point out that there is no a priori reason to assume that there is only one
(1) If the category C is such that Tc = Fr{;lJ, then TCe (= Tc) is
viable way to extend our extensional system to an intensional one. The
total.
system we will present here seems to us to be a natural one; and it certainly is
capable of representing a substantial range of properly intensional phenomena. The reader will recall that at several places in the development of the
Nevertheless, it may be that a different system could be constructed which extensional system, we used the term transparent to denote an expression
would be superior in some respects, but would still incorporate the exten- whose denotation could be defined as a function which takes an extensional
sional system given earlier. denotation as an argument. Transparent expressions were in contrast to
A question we could raise immediately is the following: given the category properly intensional ones. In our intensional system, transparent expressions
C, what is the relationship between Te and Ti;? A conceivable answer is that and properly intensional ones of the same category will be interpreted by
Ti; is a subset of Te. Thus, for example, if C = P2 , we can imagine that the intensions of the same general sort. In order to represent the different logical
interpretation function will be restricted so that, while verbs like look-for behavior of these two sorts of expressions, we will want to require that the
and criticize could take their (intensional) denotations anywhere in the set intension of a transparent expression be dependent extensionally on its
Tp2' verbs like kiss or hit would have to take their denotations inside the argument, in some sense. We are able to give a precise formulation of what
subset T: 2 • As it turns out, it will be the case for no category that T[; is a this means, using what we have already developed in this section, as follows:
subset of Te, although for some categories (P2 included) properly extensional
expressions will be restricted to take their denotations in a proper subset DEFINITION 2. Let C1 and C2 be arbitrary categories, and let f" TC1e -+
ofTe· TCze be an arbitrary function. Then f is transparent iff for eachj EJ, if x, Y
Since we have already mentioned that the intensional types are to be E TCleare such that Xj =Yj, then (f(x))j = (f(Y))j-
INTRODUCTION TO THE INTENSIONAL SYSTEM 277 INTRODUCTION TO THE INTENSIONAL SYSTEM 279

Thus, for the function f (which maps intensions onto intensions) to be (b) Iff, g E TCe, fv g is that element of TCe such that for eachj E
transparent, it must be the case that the extension of the value of f in any J, (jv g)j =fi v gj.
world depend only on the extension of the argument of f in that world. (c) If f E TCe, f' is that element of TCe such that for each j E J,
As an example, consider the transitive verbs kiss and look-for as applied (f')j =(fi)' .
to the Ns Mary and the queen. In our intensional system, all four expressions
will be interpreted by intensions. In general, Mary and the queen will be Moreover, if Tt is complete, then TCe is complete, and if Tt is atomic,
interpreted by different intensions, say, X and Y respectively; but in some then TCe is atomic.
particular world, say j, Mary and the queen might be the same individual,
that is, Xj = Yj. Now, although the intensions of kiss Mary and kiss the queen The operations on TCe defined in the lifting theorem may be described as
can be expected to be different, in general, we would want the extension operating 'pointwise on the worlds'; that is, the extension in some world
of kiss Mary in j to be the same as the extension of kiss the queen inj, since, of the boolean combination of intensions is just the (extensional) boolean
in j, Mary and the queen are the same person. But if the function f which combination of their extensions in that world. In this sense, the boolean
interprets kiss is transparent, then this is exactly what happens; since Xj =Yj, structure of TE; is 'lifted' up to TCe.
the definition insures that (f(x))j (the extension in j of kiss Mary) equals We note that in the case that C is a boolean category such that TC =FTE;IJ,
(f(y))j (the extension in j of kiss the queen). On the other hand, if g in- the lifting theorem automatically assigns boolean structure to Tc (= TCe). In
terprets look-for, we would not, in general, want this to be the case: even the case that TCe is a proper subset of Tc, the lifting theorem does not assign
though Xj = Yj, the extensions of look for Mary and look for the queen structure to the whole of Tc, but only to TCe. The question of whether it
might be different in world j. Thus, if the function which interprets an is possible to make all of T C a boolean algebra, or even whether it is desirable
ordinary extensional transitive verb like kiss is required to be transparent, to do so, is somewhat difficult, and will be taken up in connection with
while the function which interprets a properly intensional transitive verb certain specific categories.
like look-for is not so required, these basic facts will automatically be Having laid this much of a foundation, we are ready to proceed to the
represented. construction of the intensional system for the core language.
Definition 2 is formulated only to apply to a function whose domain and
range are sets T Ce. It is convenient to use the term transparent for a function Proofs of the Theorems
with any domain and range to mean that the restriction of that function to
the subset of extensional arguments is transparent in the sense of Definition Statement (1) in the text is an obvious consequence of the definitions. Here
2. An important special case is: we shall prove the general extensionality theorem and the lifting theorem.

DEFINITION 3. Let l TCI -'r TC2 be an arbitrary function (where Cl , C 2 THEOREM 1. General Extensionality Theorem. Let C l and C2 be categories
are arbitrary categories) such that whenever x E TCle, then f(x) E TC 2 e. such that TCle and TC 2 e are total. Lett- TC I -+ TC 2 be such that whenever
Then f is transparent iff its restriction to T C leis transparent. x E TCle. f(x) E TC 2 e. If fis transparent, then, for eachj EJ, the equation
fi(Xj) = (f(x»j Vx E TCle uniquely defines an element fi of FTE; ITt.
We can now give the following important theorem, which, in essence, Conversely, if for each j E J a function fi E FT~ IT~l is given, the~ theie
relates the notions of transparency and extensionality: is a unique transparentf' TCle -7 TC2e such that U(x»j = fi(Xj).

THEOREM 1. General Extensionality Theorem. Let Cl and C2 be categories Suppose first that C l • C z , and f satisfy the assumptions of the first part of
such that T C 1 e and T C 2 e are total. Let f· T C 1 -'r T C 2 be such that whenever the theorem. Let ~ be an arbitrary element of TE;. For a fixed j E J, there
x E TCle, f(x) E TC 2 e. If fis transparent, then, for eachj EJ, the equation must be an x E TCle such that Xj = t since TCleis total. We define fi(~)
!j(Xj) = (f(x))j 't/x E TCle uniquely defmes an element!j of FTf:/Tf:1. by setting it equal to (f(x»j. Note that (f(x»j is indeed an element of TE;2'
278 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 280 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

Conversely, if for each j E] a function Ii EFrt,/rt1 is given, then there is Moreover, if some Y :f x were chosen from TC 1 e such that Yj = t then (f(y »j
a unique transparent!· TC1e-+ TCze such that (f(x))j = Ii(Xj). would be equal to (f(x »j, since Yj = Xj and f is transparent. Thus, fj (~) is
well defined. Since Xj = t the equation fj(Xj) = (f(x»j holds. This proves
There are two points of detail that the reader should keep in mind about the the first part of the theorem.
general extensionality theorem. The first is that the theorem does not assert Next assume that functions fj E FTt2/TtJ have been given. For an
that there is a unique function l Tel ~ TC2 defined when extensions /j arbitrary x E Tc 1 e, fi(Xj) E Tl; 2. Thus the set 1Ji(Xj): j E J} (for this fixed
are given. What is unique is the restriction of such a function/to TCle; but
x) is a subset of Tt 2' and so, since TC 2 e is total, there is a unique element
if T C 1 e is a proper subset of TC l ' then the values of f for nonextensional
Z E TC2e such that Zj = fj(Xj), Vj E J. Set f(x) = z. Then, the equation
arguments are not in any way constrained, a priori. Thus, there could be
(f(x»j = !;(Xj) holds, by the way f was defined. Moreover, f is transparent,
distinct functions f1 and f2' which took different values on nonextensional
as follows directly from this equation: if, for some j, Yj = Xj, then (f(y»j =
arguments, but whose restrictions to T C 1 e were the same; these functions
fj(yj) = fj(Xj) = (f(x»j. Finally, the equation (f(x»j = fj(Xj) determines f
would have the same extensions in all the worlds (if they were transparent,
uniquely. For, if there was a function g such that (g(x»j = !;(Xj), then,
of course). However, in the special case that TC1eis all of TC 1 (a situation
for each x, f(x) and g(x) would have exactly the same ex tension in all worlds.
which happens often enough to be of interest to us), we can conclude that a
r
unique transparent function TC1 ~ T C2 is defined by giving its extensions
Since TC 2 e is total, this would mean that f(x) = g(x); and since x is arbitrary,
we would havef= g.
in all the worlds.
The second point is that the function r TC1e -+ TCze whose existence
THEOREM 2. Lifting Theorem. Let C be a category for which T Ce is total.
and uniqueness is guaranteed if extensions Ii are given cannot be assumed
If Te is a boolean algebra, then TCe is a boolean algebra under the operations
to be a member of TC2/Cle. The reason is that, in addition to being a
II, v, and' defined as follows:
function from TC 1 e into TC2e, a member of TC Z /Cl e might have to satisfy
other restrictions, such as being a homomorphism, being restricting or inter-
(a) Iff, g E TCe, f 1\ g is that element of Tce such that for eachj EJ,
secting, etc. Even if each extension of such a function lies in Tt 2 /C 1 and
(f 1\ g)j =!; 1\ gj.
hence satisfies the appropriate restrictions it is not automatically guaranteed
(b) If f, g E TCe, f v g is that element of TCe such that for each
that the intensional function will also do so. In particular cases, it will happen
j EJ, (fv g)j =fj v gj.
that an extensional intension inherits properties of its extensions, and hence
(c) If f E TCe, I is that element of TCe such that for each j E J,
will be a member of Tc z/C 1 e; but this will have to be proven in addition to
(f')j =(fj)'.
appealing to the general extensionality theorem.
In developing the extensional system, we argued that the types for many
Moreover, if Te is complete then Tce is complete, and if Tc is atomic, then
categories should have the structure of boolean algebras. The same arguments
show that the intensional types for many categories should be boolean
TCe is atomic.
algebras. The following theorem will prove useful in many cases for defming
We note first that the totality of TCe guarantees that the operations are in
boolean structure:
fact well defined by the statements in (a), (b), and (c).
Next, the fact that the boolean axioms are satisfied in T Ce follows almost
THEOREM 2. Lifting Theorem. Let C be a category for which TCe is total.
trivially from the fact that they are satisfied in Te. For example, suppose
If Tt is a boolean algebra, then Tce is a boolean algebra under the operations
we want to prove the distributive law for TCe. Lettingf, g, and h be arbitrary
II, Y, and' defmed as follows:
elements of T Ce, we have:
(a) Iff, gE TCe,f IIgis that element ofTCe such that for eachj E],
(fl\(gvh)j =!;I\(gvh)j (by (a»
(f II g)j = Ii II gj.
=!; 1\ (gj v hj) (by (b))
INTRODUCTION TO THE INTENSIONAL SYSTEM 281 INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 283

=(I; 1\ gj) v (I; 1\ hi) (by the distributive law in Tt:) (M(e) 1\ M(e')) 0) = M(e) 0) 1\ M(e') 0). This says that the truth value of
= (fl\g)j v (fl\ h); (by (a)) e and e' in; is just the ordinary boolean meet (that is, truth table combina-
= «(f II g) v (fll h))j (by (b)) tion) of the truth values of e and of e' in;.
Let us briefly examine the atoms of Tpo. By the discussion in the proof
for an arbitrary j E J. Since Tce is total, we conclude that f II (g v h) =(f 1\ g) of the lifting theorem, these are exactly those formula intensions which are
V (f II h). true in exactly one world. In other words, if the formula intension I is an
The other boolean axioms may be proved in exactly the same way. We atom, then there is exactly one world, saY;f, such that l(jf) = 1; for all
leave it to the reader to supply the details. Here, we simply point out that worlds; t= jf, l(j) = O.
the zero element of TCe is that element 0 such that OJ =OTt: for each j E J; The atoms of Tpo will not playa significant role in the sequel. However,
similarly, the unit element of TCe is that element 1 such that 1; = ITt: for one can imagine ways in which these atoms may become relevant. Suppose,
each j E J. Thus, the zero is that intension whose extension in any world is for example, that the set J is conceived of as indexing moments of time.
zero, and the unit is that intension whose extension in an world is the unit. An atomic formula would then be one true at an individual moment. Thus,
Similarly, by a proof similar to the proof of the distributive law above, it we would be able to distinguish formulas like John died or the door opened,
follows from the definitions that, for arbitrary f, gETCe, f';;;; g iff I; .;;;; gj which are understood as occurring at individual moments, from formulas
for each j E J. That is, for one extensional intension to bear the relation .;;;; like John worked, or even John wrote the letter, which appear to be true
to another, it is necessary and sufficient that all its extensions bear this during intervals consisting of many moments, if they are true at all. Momen-
relation to the extensions of the other intension, in all the worlds. tary formulas would somehow have their interpretations restricted in such
Now, suppose that T'I; is complete. Let K <::::: TCe be an arbitrary subset. a way that they would always be atoms, whereas the interpretations of non-
We define AK by setting (AK)j = A[ E K I; for each j E J. The right hand momentary formulas would not be atoms. Since we do not impose any
side of this equation is well defined, since T'I; is complete. Since TC e is total, structure or special interpretation on the set J in this study, we will not
this equation defines the element AK. We claim that AK so defined is in pursue this approach here.
fact the glb of K. Let us now move on to the categories Nand N. As in the case of formulas,
First, let fo E K be arbitrary. Then we have (AK)j = A[ E K I; ';;;;fo; we define the intensional type of N to be the set of functions from J into
for each j E J, since A[ E K I; is the glb of the set {I;: f E K}, and fOj is a the extensional type:
member of this set. But then AK .;;;; fo, since j was arbitrary. Since fo was
an arbitrary member of K, this shows that AK as defined above is a lower DEFINITION 2. TN =FTfr/J (= Fp/J),
bound for the set K.
Secondly, suppose that g .;;;; f holds for every f E K. Then, for arbitrary where P is an arbitrary complete atomic boolean algebra, representing as
j E J, gj .;;;; I; for every f E K, whence gj is a lower bound for the set before the set of (extensional) properties. Thus, the intension of an N like
{jj: fEK}. But this means thatgj ';;;;A[E K I; = (AK)j, since, again, A [EK I; student will associate an element of P to each world j. Again, all N intensions
is the glb. Since this is true for arbitrary j E J, we have g .;;;; AK, showing are extensional, and, by the lifting theorem, TN is a complete atomic boolean
that AK is the glb. algebra. By the definitions of the operations in TN, boolean combinations of
The proof that any subset of Tee has a lub is of course just the dual of Ns are interpreted on a world-by-world basis using the operations in P.
this one. The intensional type for Ns will be defined in the same way:
Finally, suppose that Tt: is atomic. Given an atom a E Tt: and a world
index j E J, let us define an element faj E TCe as follows. For each j' E J DEFINITION 3. Til = FTit/J (= Fp */J).
such that j' =f j, set (faj)j' = OTt; and set (faj)j =a. Then, since Tce is total,
fa; is a well defined element of TCe. Moreover,faj is an atom; for,ifg';;;;faj An N intension associates an element of p* to each worldj. AlI.IV intensions
then, for each j' =f j, gj' .;;;; (faj)j' = 0 so that gj' = 0 if j' =f j. And, gj .;;;; (faj)j = are extensional, and, by the lifting theorem, Til is a complete atomic boolean
282 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 284 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

a, so gj is either 0 or a, since a is an atom. If gj = 0, then g = 0, since all algebra, with boolean operations on N intensions calculated on a world-by-
of its extensions are zero. If gj = a, then g = faj, since g and faj then have world basis using the operations in P *.
the same extensions in all the worlds. Thus, faj is an atom. The reader may However, let us note at this point that an alternate definition for TN might
show easily that any atom of Tce is of the form faj, for some atom a of suggest itself. Namely, since TN = Fp/J is the set which represents (inten-
T{; and some j E J. sional) properties, and since we argued, in our development of the extensional
Now, if g E TCe and g f 0, we can show that TCe contains some atom system, that an N is reasonably interpreted as the set of all properties which
less than or equal to g. For, since g f 0, there must be at least one j E J hold of its referent, we might wish to have the denotation of an N be a subset
such that gj f O. Since T{; is atomic, we can find an atom a such that a ~gj. of Fp/J. This would mean that, instead of Fp*/J, TN would be taken to be
The element faj of TCe is an atom, as we just showed above, and moreover equal to (Fp/J)*. In preliminary support of this idea, we note that since Fp/J
faj ~ g, since, as the reader can easily verify, (faj)j' ~ gj' for every j' E J. is a complete atomic boolean algebra, the entire algebraic development which
Thus, TCe is atomic. we constructed earlier for p* carries over unchanged to (Fp/J)*' In_particular,
It is worth remembering that an extensional intension is an atom iff its (Fp/J)* has individuals, the justification theorem allows a unique homomor-
extensions are zero in all worlds but one, and in that exceptional world its phism from (Fp/J)* into an arbitrary boolean algebra to be specified by
extension is an atom. arbitrarily assigning values to these individuals, etc. (Thinking ahead, we will
need some such theorem in order to handle PI intensions properly.)
2. THE INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE
Nevertheless, problems arise as soon as we attempt to consider the exten·
sions which such R intensions would have. Presumably, the extension in
We begin by defining the intensional type for the category Po of formulas: world j of a set of (intensional) properties is the set of extensions of these
properties inj. Formally:

DEFINITION 4. Let Q EO (Fp/J)* be an arbitrary element, and let j EO J be


Thus, a formula intension is a function which assigns a truth value for each an arbitrary world index. Then Qj = {p(j): p EO Q}.
world. By the developments of the previous section, formula intensions are
always extensional, that is, TPoe = Tpo. Moreover, since 2 is a complete Note that Qj EO TN (= P*).
atomic boolean algebra, the lifting theorem enables us to conclude that With this definition, all elements of (Fp/J)* are extensional. However,
Tp o is also a complete atomic boolean algebra. the set of extensional elements of (Fp/J)* is not total. To see this, suppose
The effect of the pointwise definition in the lifting theorem is to allow that Q EO (Fp/J)* is such that, for some particular j, Qj =0. By the definition
the calculation of the interpretation of boolean combinations of formulas above, this can only happen if Q = 0. But then Qj = 0 for all j. What this
on a 'world-by-world' basis. For example, suppose that e and e' are formulas. means is that there could be no R intension whose extension in some worlds
Then, their interpretations M(e) and M(e') in some model will each be is 0 and whose extensions in other worlds is not 0. Thus, it would be possible
a formula intension, that is, a function from J into 2. If j is a particular to give a set of extensions {Qj} such that these are the extensions for no
world, then the truth value of the formula e in j is just the value of the intension. But this does not seem reasonable. Surely, we want to allow for
function M(e) applied to the argument j, that is, M(e) (j). Similarly, the the possibility that a particular R is interpreted as 0 in some worlds but
truth value of e' in j is the value of M(e') (j). Now, if we form the boolean not in others. (The reader may also check that, in general, it is possible for
combination e and e', then this too is a formula, and so its interpretation distinct intensions to have the same extensions in all worlds, using Definition
M(e and e') must also be a function from J into 2. Thus, the truth value of 4.) Because of this nontotality, it does not seem that (Fp/J)* is the appro-
e and e' inj is M(e and e') (j). But, since boolean combinations of expressions priate candidate for TN.
are interpreted as boolean combinations of interpretations, M(e and e') = Having fixed on Definition 3 as the proper definition for TN, let us con-
M(e) f\ M(e'), Now, by (a) of the lifting theorem, we have M(e and e') (j) = sider what the interpretation of a proper noun should be. Extensionally,
INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 285 INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 287

a proper noun is interpreted as an individual in P*, so we will naturally want denotation of its subject. This is in contrast to PIS like kiss Mary; we cer-
the intension I of a proper noun to be such that l(j) is an individual for every tainly do want to claim that
world j. Moreover, since individuals are conceived of as being defined by
the properties which hold of them, and since the property set P is chosen a (3) The president kissed Mary
priori and is independent of the set J, it seems not unreasonable to require
that the extension of a proper name be the same individual in every world. and
Let us define the notion intensional individual thus:
(4) Franklin Pierce kissed Mary
DEFINITION 5. The function f E Fp*/J is an intensional individual iff there
exists an individual I E P * such that Vj E J, fO) =I. necessarily have the same truth value in any world in which the president
and Franklin Pierce have the same extension.
We now define the type for proper nouns to be the set of intensional in- The way in which this can be handled was indicated in the previous section.
dividuals: The type for PI in general will be a certain set of functions from Til into
Tpo. A PI like kiss Mary will always be interpreted as a transparent such
DEFINITION 6. TN prop = {f E TN: fis an intensional individual}. function. By the definition of transparency, the value returned by such a
function in a particular world depends only on the extension of its argument
Algebraically, intensional individuals are somewhat different from ordinary in that world. Properly intensional PI s will in general not be interpreted as
individuals. Recall that the individuals of p* are in one-to· one correspon- transparent functions. Thus, if f interprets be required to be over 35 years
dence with the atoms of P; in fact, each individual contains exactly one old, f might return distinct truth values in world j when applied to distinct
atom as a member, and distinct individuals contain distinct atoms. However, arguments, even if those arguments happen to have the same extension
intensional individuals are, first of all, not sets of extensional or intensional inj.
properties, so they cannot be said to contain atoms of any algebra. Moreover, We will say that PI s like kiss Mary belong to the subcategory of trans-
they are not in one-to-one correspondence with the atoms of TN. From parent PIS; we denote this category Pl. Similarly, properly intensional PIS
t
the proof of the lifting theorem, we know that the atoms of TN are those will be said to belong to the subcategory of nontransparent PIS; this category
functions faj which map the particular world j into the atom a of P, and will be denotedPl. To insure that expressions of these categories are properly
which map all other worlds into the zero property. Recalling that an atom of interpreted, ther~tare two things we must do.
P may be thought of as the property of being a particular individual, we can Firstly, lexical members of the category PI must be specified as being
think of faj as being the (intensional) property of existing only in world j either transparent or nontransparent. The interpreting function will then be
and being a particular individual in that world. If P has n atoms, say, then the restricted so that lexical members of PI will be interpreted only by trans-
number of atoms in TN is therefore n IJI. But there are only n intensional parent members of TPI . As it turns <iut, all of the lexical members of PI
individuals, corresponding to the n individuals in p* (and to the n atoms of that we are accounting for in our language are transparent. In fact, we do
P, of course). not know of a clear example of an English intransitive verb, semantically a
We can say that the intensional individuals are in one-to-one correspon- one-place predicate, which is properly intensional on its subject.
dence with the functions fa E TN, where, for each atom a of P, fa is defined Secondly, the interpretation of nonlexical PIS must be calculated in
by la(j) = a for every j in J. In fact, if fis an intensional individual, then for such a way that the correct transparency always results. For example, the
exactly one atom a of P, fa 0) E fO) for each j in J. But, of course, fa is not (intensional) function which interprets kiss in any model must be such that,
an atom in TN; in fact, for eachj in J, we havefaj ~fa. when applied to an N intension, the resulting PI intension is automatically
Having defined TN and TN as in Definitions 2 and 3, let us consider the transparent. Each construction which results in a PI will have to be dealt
definition of TDet. Restricting our attention to the few simple determiners with separately.
286 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 288 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

in the core language, we can use the second part of the general extensionality Let us restrict our attention now to transparent PIS. In our development
theorem to define intensional interpretations for these logical constants. of the extensional system, we showed that the denotation of a P I should be
For example, let us take the determiner every. We would like the intension a homomorphism. Clearly, the evidence cited there is just as relevant here:
of this determiner to have the extension everye in each world, where everye is we would like the intensional denotation of a transparent PI to be a homo-
as defined in Definition 25 of Part IA (note the superscript 'e' to indicate an morphism. Note that such a denotation is a function, in fact, a transparent
object defined within our extensional system). By the general extensionality function, from TN (= TNe) into Tpo (= TPoe), which are both boolean
theorem, there is a unique transparent function every, mapping TN into Tfi, algebras, as we have seen, so it makes sense to require that it be a homomor-
such that, for every j E J, (every(x))j = everye(Xj), for each x E TN. We will phism. However, by our earlier development, it would appear rather that
now restrict any (intensional) model of our language in such a way that the what we want is for the extensions of such a function in all the worlds to
logical constant every is always interpreted as every. be homomorphisms. We might ask if there is any connection between an
The other logical constant determiners in the core language are handled intension being a homomorphism and its extensions being homomorphisms.
in exactly the same way. Note that the intensions which interpret these The answer to this is provided by the following theorem:
determiners are all transparent, which is what we want, since the interpre-
tation of an N formed by combining such a determiner with an N, in a given THEOREM 1. Homomorphic Inheritance Theorem. Let C I and C2 be cate-
world, depends only on the extension of the N in that world. In general, gories such that TC I e and TC 2 e are total and Te I and Te 2 are boolean
of course, properly intensional determiners do exist. Thus, when properly r
algebras. Then, a transparent function TC I e -+ TC2e is a homomorphism
defined, TDet cannot consist entirely of transparent functions from TN into iff Vj EJ, fj: Tel -+ Te 2 is a homomorphism.
Tfi. However, the question of a general definition of TDet will not be further
considered here. (Note that the lifting theorem guarantees that TC I e and TC 2 e are boolean
We are now ready to turn to the category Pn of n-place predicates. As algebras.) The content of this theorem can be paraphrased by saying that
earlier, we begin by considering the category PI, and then examining how our a transparent function inherits the property of being a homomorphism from
considerations can be extended to the general case. its extensions; and conversely, the extensions inherit the property of being
Let us note at the outset that the category PI will have to be subdivided homomorphisms from their intension.
into two subcategories, namely, those expressions which are 'extensional' in In the case of transparent PI'S, the effect of this theorem, together with
their arguments (that is, in their subject Ns), and those which are properly the general extensionality theorem, is to insure that a transparent homomor-
intensional. All the examples of PI s we have dealt with up until now have phism [from Til into Tpo is determined by a set of homomorphismsfj from
been examples of the former type; but properly intensionalPls exist as well. Tit into Tpo' one for each world j. That is, any transparent homomorphism
For example, consider the PI is required to be over 35 years old. We surely [ determines such a set {fj}, and conversely, if an arbitrary set of such
do not want the two sentences homomorphism {fj} is given, there is a unique transparent homomorphism
r Til -+ Tpo which has those fjs as extensions. All this being so, it is clear
(I) The president is required to be over 35 years old that we want to define the type for transparent PI s as follows:

and DEFINITION 7. Tpi :::: {fEFTp /Til: [is a transparent homomorphism}.


t 0

(2) Franklin Pierce is required to be over 35 years old And, as we just saw, by the homomorphic inheritance theorem and the
general extensionality theorem, TPI = TPI e is total. But note now that Tj, is
t t l
to have the same truth value in any world in which the president and Franklin a boolean algebra (in fact, a complete atomic one). Thus the lifting theorem
Pierce happen to have the same extension. But this means that this P I cannot can be applied to conclude that Tp I e is a complete atomic boolean algebra
t
be interpreted by a function which takes as its argument the extensional under the operations defined pointwise on the worlds.
INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 289 INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 291

At this point, it may be instructive to illustrate how our intensional either lexical PIS or else boolean combinations of transparent PIS, these
system is used to calculate truth values for formulas of the sort which our considerations show that, so far, a transparent PI will always be interpreted
extensional system was able to handle. Let us take the formula every student by a transparent homomorphism, as desired.
laughs or cries. The calculation here should be compared with the discussion Let us now turn our attention to the nontransparentPls. So far, the only
of (42) in Part IA. We have: thing we have said concerning their interpretation is that a nontransparent
PI intension is a function from TN into Tpo which is not required to be
(5) every student laughs or cries transparent. Let us examine the question of whether such an intension
should be a homomorphism.
(a) (every student) (laugh or cry)
Comparing the sentences

(b)
I
every S
I
)~c (12) The president and the vice-president are required to be over 35
~ years old.
(c) every (S)~ I V c
and
(d) (I v c) (every (s))
(13) The president is required to be over 35 years old and the vice-
president is required to be over 35 years old.
Line (a) gives the representation of the given English sentence in our logical
language. In line (b), the lexical expressions are replaced by their interpre- it certainly seems that the truth of one of these in some world necessarily
tations; but note that these are now intensional denotations. Lines (c) and entails the truth of the other. The logical equivalence of these sentences
(d) just involve combining these in the usual way. Line Cd), therefore, is the suggests that the intension which interprets the PI should preserve meets.
intensional denotation of the entire formula. However, when we examine the situation with regard to joins, the matter
Now, suppose that, given a world j E J, we wish to know the truth value is not so simple. Consider the following two sentences:
of the formula in j. Clearly, all we need to do is to apply the formula inten-
sion to j, giving us (14) The president or the vice-president is required to be over 35
years old.
(6) «(I v c) (every (s))) (j). (15) The president is required to be over 35 years old or the vice-
president is required to be over 35 years old.
By using the theorems and definitions we have developed, we can express
the truth value (6) in terms of the extensions of s, t, and C in j. To do this, Sentence (14) is ambiguous. In the reading which appears to us to be the
we first note that since 1 v c is transparent (see below), we have the equation: most natural one, the sentence asserts that there is a requirement to the
effect that, of the two individuals who are serving as president and as vice-
(7) «(1 v c) (every (s))) (j) = (I v c)j (every (s))j- president, at least one be over 35 years old. The less natural reading of (14)
Next, we recall that the lifting theorem defines the boolean operations in TPl is logically equivalent to (15); in this reading, what is asserted is that there
pointwise on the worlds. This means that we have: t is either a requirement for the president to be over 35 years old, or else there
is a requirement for the vice-president to be over 35 years old. Clearly, these
(8) (lvc)j=tjVCj. two readings are not logically equivalent, and, in fact, neither entails the
other. The second reading is the one which results if the PI is required to be
Also, the function every was defined earlier by means of the following over 35 years old is assumed to preserve joins.
equation: Similar facts obtain in the case of a subject N quantified by a determiner
290 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 292 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

(9) (every (s»j =everye (Sj) = n


SjE I
I, of the sort that we are representing in our language by a. In the case of the
sentence
where we have added on the equation which defines everye in the extensional
(16) An elected official is required to be over 35 years old.
system. Substituting (8) and (9) into (7), we get:

(10) ((I v c)(every (s») (j) = (lj v Cj)(


SjE I
n J). it is virtually impossible not to interpret the subject generically. However,
the following are ambiguous the way that (14) above is:

Note that (10) expresses the truth value of the formula in j in terms of the (17) { Asoml e } elected official is required to be over 35 years old.
extensions of student, laugh, and cry in j. The remainder of the calculation t east one
proceeds exactly as in the extensional system. We have:
On one reading, (17) asserts a requirement that among all the individuals who
are elected officials, at least one be over 35 years old; on the other reading,
(11) «(l v c) (every (s») (j)= (lj v Cj) (s.Q II)
I (17) asserts that of all the elected offices, at least one has on it the require-
= Sj A [(lj v Cj) (1)] ment that the person who fills that office must be over 35 years old. It is
EI this second reading which corresponds to the preservation of joins by the
interpretation of the PI' Again, this reading neither implies nor is implied
by the first reading.
The chief embarrassment to our system provided by these sentences is
where the second equality follows since Ij V Cj is a homomorphism, and the their ambiguity; but perhaps it is made worse by the fact that the more
third equality follows from the definition of V in TJ.
I · The right hand side common reading is the one which does not preserve joins. The ambiguity
of the third equality in (11) should be compared with (42f) of Part IA. means that these sentences will ultimately have to have two representations
The reader may find it instructive to calculate the truth value of «every in our logical language_ However, it would be preferable if the simpler repre-
student) laugh) or «every student) cry), and to show that in any world in sentation corresponded to the more common reading. Here, however, it is
which this formula is true, the formula (every student) (laugh or cry) must clear that the simpler representation of, say, (14), will just be something like
be true, but not conversely.
In our illustrative example above, we made use of the fact that I v C was (18) «the president) or (the vice-president)) (be required ... ).
transparent (in fact, a transparent homomorphism). Let us briefly review the
justification for this conclusion. It will surely be easier to impose join-preservation on the PI (which corres-
First, I and C are transparent homomorphisms, since they are the interpre- ponds to the second, less-likely reading) than to somehow guarantee that
tations of the lexical PIS laugh and cry. Recall that lexical PIS are always the PI interpretation in (18) can reference the internal structure of the
transparent, and hence their interpretations are required to be in the set TP l interpretation of its subject N, which is what would be needed in order to
defined in Definition 7. t represent the first, more common, reading. Nevertheless, as a first approxima-
Secondly, TP l is a boolean algebra, by the lifting theorem. Therefore, tion, it does not seem too unreasonable to assume that even nontransparent
t
boolean combinations of transparent homomorphisms from TN into Tpo are PI s preserve joins, and to hope that the other reading of (14) can be re-
always themselves transparent homomorphisms from TN into Tp o' But this presented by a structure in which the highly derived character of the PI
means that the interpretation of a boolean combination of transparent PI sis (involving as it does passive, as well as an embedded PI) will form the basis
automatically an appropriate denotation for a transparent P l , which is what for the way the more common interpretation is calculated.
we want. In particular, I v C is a well-defined transparent homomorphism. The fact that nontransparent PI s preserve complements seems relatively
Since the only transparent Pi s we can handle so far in a formal way are unproblematic, for surely (19) and (20) are logically equivalent:
INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 293 INTENSION AL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 295

(19) The president but not the vice-president is required to be over 35 (23) Every elected official is required to be over 35 years old or is
years old. required to be an American citizen.
(20) The president is required to be over 35 years old but it is not the
case that the vice-president is required to be over 35 years old. With the pointwise approach, this sentence would be logically equivalent
to (24), whereas with the individual approach, it would presumably be
We therefore might propose that nontransparent PI s be interpreted by equivalent to (25):
homomorphisms, just as transparent PIS are. If so, we can define the inten-
sional type for PI s as follows: (24) Every elected official is required to be over 35 years old or
every elected official is required to be an American citizen.
DEFINITION 8. Tpi
(t)
= {fEHTp 0 /Tft <[is transparent>} (25) For each elected official, there is a requirement on that official
where the angle bracket notation indicates, as usual, that the presence of the to the effect that he/she must either be over 35 years old or else
subcategorization feature t correlates with the presence of the condition that be an American citizen.
[be transparent.
Note that if f' TN ~ Tpo is not transparent, there is no natural way to It is unclear to us which of these is or ought to be the interpretation of (23).1
define extensions of [ in the various worlds. On the other hand, we saw A similarly difficult sentence is:
earlier that TPle = TP1' and that TP1e is total. We conclude that the exten-
t t t (26) At least one elected official is required to be over 35 years old
sional members of Tp 1 are just the transparent members_ That is, Tp 1 e =
and is required to be an American citizen.
TP 1 ; and, of course, TPle is total, since TPle is. Note moreover that TPle
t t
is a proper subset of Tp 1 . The category PI is the first category we have en- With the pointwise approach, this sentence would be equivalent to (27),
countered (with the exception of Det, whose full intensional type we whereas with the individual approach, it would be equivalent to (28):
have not actually defined yet) where this is the case.
There remains to be considered the matter of the category PI and its (27) At least one elected official is required to be over 35 years old
subcategories being boolean. In the case of {I, we have seen that the lifting and at least one elected official is required to be an American
theorem provides a boolean structure for Tp l . We now consider the following citizen.
t
two questions: (i) should the subcategory of nontransparent PI s be a boolean (28) For at least one elected official, that official is required to be over
category, and, if so, how should boolean structure be defined for its type?; 35 years old and is also required to be an American citizen.
and (ii) should the category of all PIS be boolean, and, if so, how should
boolean structure be defined for its type? Again, our judgments are unclear.
To take up the first of these questions, we first take note of sentences However, if we examine the mathematics involved, it appears that we

!~~~siS 1
such as: can make a decision. To see what the situation is, let us recall the way the
individual approach was developed in the extensional system.
(21) The president is required to be over 35 years old The justification theorem says that homomorphisms from TNinto an
but isn't arbitrary boolean algebra are uniquely determined by giving arbitrary values
required to be an American citizen. on the individuals. But this requires that TN contain individuals in the first
place. If the definitions are examined, it is seen that the individuals of TN
While stylistically a bit awkward, these sentences seem both grammatical exist by virtue of the fact that TN is a power set p* of a set P which itself
and perfectly interpretable. We conclude that we would like the category is a boolean algebra. There are two things to note about this.
of nontransparent PI s to be boolean. The first is that the definition of which elements of p* are individuals
294 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 296 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

To define boolean structure on the type for nontransparent PI s, there makes use of the algebraic structure of P. Thus, if B is an abstractly defined
are two sorts of considerations to bring to bear: the interpretation of English boolean algebra which happens by accident to be isomorphic to some P*,
sentences involving boolean combinations of nontransparent P 1 s, and the there is no way to define individuals in B making use only of its own algebraic
mathematical possibilities and consequences of various defmitions of boolean structure. In general, if B is isomorphic to some P*, then there is more than
structure. Let us first look at the interpretation of English sentences. one isomorphism of p* onto B, and distinct isomorphisms will associate
The first thing we can say is that the sentences in (21) above are clearly distinct sets of elements of B with the individuals of P*.
logically equivalent to: The second is that it is possible for a boolean algebra B to not be isomor-
phic to any p* at all. In the finite case, this is very easy to see by a counting
argument. Since P is an arbitrary boolean algebra, if Pis fmite, then P has 2 n
(22) The president is required to be over 35 years old I ~~d elements, and so p* has 22n elements. Now, an arbitrary finite boolean
1and it is not algebra B has 2k elements, for some integer k. But, if k f 2 n for some n,

j
then B cannot be isomorphic to any P *. For such a B there is no way that the
the president is required to be an American citizen. definitions which were set up to apply to p* can be made to apply.
the case that Actually, we can say even more. Suppose that B is a boolean algebra for
which the justification theorem holds. Then, the development of Part IA
If g and h are the intensions of the two P 1 S in (21) and if f is the intension of can be applied to conclude that the set of all homomorphisms from B into
the president, this shows that we must have (g 1\ h) (f) =g(f) 1\ h(f) in this an arbitrary algebra X itself forms an algebra. Now, let us take X = {O, 1}.
case, where, of course, g 1\ h is the intension of the PI formed by conjoining If B is a finite boolean algebra of 2 k elements, it can be easily shown that
the two PIS of (21) with and; and similar equations hol~ for g v h and for g'. the number of distinct homomorphisms from B into X is just k. 2 Since the
This being so, there are two conceivable approaches we might take towards number of elements of a finite boolean algebra is always a power of 2, if k is
the definition of boolean structure on the type for nontransparent PI s. One not a power of 2, there is no way that the set of homomorphisms from B
would be to define g 1\ h by simply setting (g !I h) (f) = g(f) !I h (f) for every into X can be made into a boolean algebra. Thus, if k is not a power of 2,
fi intension f; and similarly for the other operations; call this the pointwise the justification theorem does not apply to an algebra with 2k elements.
approach. This would certainly define g fI h as a function from TN into Tpo' Returning to the matter of defining boolean structure on the type for
However, let us recall that this is not the way that the boolean combinations nontransparent PI s, what all this means is simply that, since Til is not the
of P 1 interpretations were defined when we were developing the extensional power set of an algebra, there is no way to define individuals in Til (indi-
system. In fact, with such a definition, g !I h is not in general a homomor- viduals in the sense of Definitions 10 and 21 of Part IA), and, in addition, the
phism. What was actually done there is to define g fI h by setting (g !I h) (f) = justification theorem may not apply to Til at all. In fact, if J is finite with,
g(f) !I h (n just in case f was an individual, and then use the justification say, m members, and if P has 2 n members, then Til has 2 m2n members.
theorem to show that this in effect defined a unique homomorphism g!l h Thus, if m is not a power of 2, then, by the argument above, the justification
from Th into Tfto; call this the individual approach. In the case of the non- theorem cannot apply to Til.
transparent PIS, however, it is not a priori obvious which of these two ap- It appears, therefore, that there is good mathematical reason for rejecting
proaches is the correct one. the individual apporach to defining boolean structure on the type for non-
We can try to clear up the matter by examining sentences in which non- transparent PIS. This may seem unfortunate: there is a sense in which an
transparent PIS that are boolean combinations of PIS are combined with Nlike the president should be interpreted as an individual, and that an AT like
fis that are themselves boolean combinations of fis, and seeing how the every elected official should be interpreted as the intersection of individuals,
resulting sentences are interpreted. Unfortunately, such sentences tend to each one of which is the intension of some particular elected official. Of
be unwieldy, and it is difficult to judge what interpretation is the most course, it may still be possible to do this, provided that we do not insist that
natural. Consider, for example, the sentence: these 'individuals' have all the properties of individuals as defined in Part IA.
INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 297 INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 299

The notion of intensional individual defined above for the purpose of provid- (29) The president is required to be over 35 years old and is kissing
ing interpretations for proper nouns is surely too strong. We might propose Mary.
that an N like the president have an intension whose extension in any par-
ticular world is either an (extensional) individual or else ~, with distinct The awkwardness of such a combination is evident. If (29) can be interpreted
individuals permitted as extensions of the same intension in different worlds. at all, it seems that the properly intensional PI is given its de re rather than
de dictu reading (see Note 1). We will see later that in our system the de re
This seems satisfactory as a first approximation, but we caution that an
reading of what in English is normally a properly intensional expression will
arbitrary function which gives values for such intensions in a boolean algebra
cannot be presumed to define a unique homomorphism from all of TN into be represented in our system by means of a A operator which will create a
that algebra. The individual approach could perhaps be salvaged by changing transparent expression. Thus, in our language, the representation of (29)
the definition of TN, but we will not pursue that here. will not actually involve the combination of a nontransparent PI with a
The pointwise approach is mathematically unproblematical. Of course, transparent PI, but rather the combination of two transparent PI s. If we
assume that combinations such as (29) in general require a de re reading for
with this approach, we must admit nonhomomorphisms as possible PI
intensions, so that Definition 8 must be rejected. One possibility would be the properly intensional constituent, then, in our system, we need never have
to take all of FTPo/TJIl as the type for nontransparent PI s. Note that this to deal with a transparent and a nontransparent PI being combined. Thus,
set is indeed a boolean algebra with the operations defined pointwise; in fact, the category PI will not be a boolean category, and we are not faced with
this follows essentially from the lifting theorem, with TN here playing the the task of defining a boolean structure on all of TPI .
role of the set J in that theorem. However, it might be claimed that any Let us summarize what we have done regarding the intensional type for
nontransparent PI intension either is a homomorphism or else is a boolean the category PI and its subcategories. We take Tp 1 to be the set of transparent
t
combination of homomorphisms. This suggests that we restrict the type of homomorphisms from TN into Tpo. This set is a boolean algebra by the
nontransparent PI s to the subalgebra of FTPo/TN generated by the homo- lifting theorem; the boolean operations are carried out on a world-by-world
morphisms. (Another way of saying the same thing is that we would take the basis on the extensions of its members. For the nontransparent PI s, we define
type of nontransparent PI s to be the smallest subalgebra of FTp 0 /TN that boolean structure on the set of all functions from TN into Tpo by pointwise
,
contains HTpo/TN') Using the symbol HTpo/TN to denote this subalgebra, operations. We then take T~} to be the subalgebra of this generated by
we could therefore make the following definition: the homomorphisms. The sets Tp I and Tp I are defined to be disjoint.· Tp I is
t nt
DEFINITION 9. TPI == HTp /Tfl/' simply the union of these sets. No boolean structure is defined on Tp 1.
nt 0 There remains one relatively minor difficulty. If we ask which elements
In general, HTp /TR is a proper subset of FTp /TR,3 so that this definition of Tp I are extensional, we find that not only are all the members of Tp I
t
does narrow do~n the class of possible denotftions of nontransparent PI s extensional, but, by the general extensionality theorem, so are those elements
when compared with the idea of taking the type of PI to be simply FTp /TR' of T~} which are transparent functions. This means that the set of all exten-
nt 0
If we do this, however, a new problem arises. The difficulty is that sional elements of TPI is not total. In particular, if {fj} is a set of elements
since the set of homomorphisms from TN into Tp 0 is contained in Tp I , then of Tp I' one for each world j E J, then there are two intensions in Tpi which
nt have these extensions, one in Tp I and one in Tp I. In the sequel, we can avoid
in particular, the set of all transparent homomorphisms, that is, Tp ,is con- t nt
ti
tained in Tp l ' There is nothing wrong with this in itself; we surely want any difficulty which might arise from this simply by defining Tp I e to be
nt the set TPI. This set is total, as indicated earlier, and moreover, it is the set
to allow the possibility that in some model a nontransparent PI happens t
to get interpreted transparently. However, while Tp I is a subset of Tp I ' of possible intensions for those PI s which are necessarily extensional, as
opposed to those PI s which might be interpreted extensionally in some
it is not the case that Tp I is a subalgebra of Tp l ' In tparticular, the bool;in
t nt particular model. Still, the fact that there is a problem of this sort suggests
operations in TPI are defined differently from the boolean operations in that further study is needed here.
t
Tp I . What this means is that if f and g are transparent homomorphisms from Let us turn now to the consideration of the intensional type for P2 s. Since
nt
298 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 300 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

TR into Tpo' then, for example, there are two distinct definitions for f V g, P2 = Pdfll, TP 2 will consist of functions from TN into TP I . As usual, our
depending on whether f and g are regarded as members of TPI or of TPI' task is to determine which such functions are appropriate interpretations
t n::
This in turn means that the interpretation of a boolean combination of of P 2 s.
PIS cannot be defined on the basis of the intensions of the constituent PIS Let us first examine the PI s which are created by combining a P 2 with its
alone: it is also necessary to know whether the PIS are transparent or non- argument fIl. Since there are two subclasses of PI s, namely, the transparent
transparent. That is, the semantics of the constituent PI s are not sufficient to ones and the nontransparent ones, we can automatically divide the P2 s into
determine the interpretation of the combination, since reference has to be two classes, namely: those P2 s which always yield a transparent PI when
made to the syntactic category membership of the constituents, a situation combined with any fIl, and those which can yield a nontransparent PI when
we would hope to avoid. so combined. However, when we examine lexical transitive verbs in English
We can avoid this problem in the following, somewhat mechanical, way. or boolean combinations of these, it appears that there are no cases of the
We define two distinct and disjoint copies of FTpo/TR, indexed, say, by latter. That is, it is always the case that when any P2 (even one which itself
is properly intensional on its own argument, like look-for) is combined with
the features t and nt. Let us denote these copies by Fho/TR and F!}~o/TR its argument fIl, the PI which results is transparent. This being so, we can
respectively. We then require that transparent PIS take their intensions in already narrow down the class of functions which could possibly make up
Fho/TR' and that nontransparent PI s take their intensions in F!}~o/TR' TP2; namely, Tp 2 can only consist of functions from Tit into TpI which
We define T~I as the subset of F}Po/TR consisting of exactly the transparent actually take values in Tp 1 .
t
homomorphisms, with a boolean structure as defined earlier. We define TPI Now, since Tp I e = Tp I ' and Tit e = TN, all the functions which are poten-
nt t
as the subset fiTpo/TR of the distinct set F!}~o/TR' as defined above. If we tially members of Tp 2 can be viewed as functions from Tite into TPle'
do this, then even if the intension f of a nontransparent PI happens to be Definition 2 of Part ILl can be applied to divide these functions into two
a transparent homomorphism, f will be a member of F!}~o/TR and not of subclasses: those that are transparent and those that are not. As in the case
of the PIS, we make use of this distinction in setting up the interpretations
F~Po/TR: Boolean operations applied to such an intension f will therefore of two subclasses of Pzs. Namely, those P 2 s which depend extensionally on
automatically follow the definitions as in Tp I rather than as in Tp I ' their argument will be called transparent, whereas those which are properly
nt t
To conclude, we can say that the category of nontransparent PI s should intensional on their argument will be called nontransparent. The interpre-
be taken to be boolean. With the individual approach to the definition of tation of a transparent P2 will always be a transparent function, whereas
boolean structure on the type for nontransparent PI s, there are mathe- the interpretation of a nontransparent P2 will not be so restricted.
matical problems, at least if the definition of TR is the one given earlier. To insure that each P z is correctly interpreted, we must, first of all, mark
With the pointwise definition, a mathematically coherent system can be set all lexical P2 s as being either transparent or nontransparent. Unlike the case
up, but we now run into the problem that syntactic information has to be with the PIS, there are nontransparent lexical P2 s, such as look-for, need,
accessed in order for the interpretation of boolean combinations of PI s to or criticize. The correct interpretation of complex P 2 s will result if the
be carried out. This problem can be mechanically solved by interpreting principles for calculating them are properly set up.
transparent and nontransparent PI s in disjoint copies of FTPo/TR' Here we Let us restrict our attention for the moment to the transparent P2 s. These
shall opt for this latter solution, but the question deserves further study. will be interpreted as transparent functions from TN into Tp I e, as we have
Let us turn our attention now to the question of whether the category seen. By the general extensionality theorem, any such function has extensions
of all the PIS should be regarded as boolean, and, if so, how boolean com- in all the worlds; in fact, a transparent function r TNe -+ TPle is in one-to-
binations are to be interpreted. Given two PI s, if both are transparent, or one correspondence with a set {ij} of functions each mapping TN Tp
into I '
if both are nontransparent, then the matter of the interpretation of a boolean Moreover, by the homomorphic inheritance theorem, since Tite and TPle
combination of which they are the constituents has already been discussed. are total and TN and Tf, 1 are boolean algebras, f: Tit e -+ Tp I e is a homo-
There remains the question of what happens if a transparent and a nontrans- morphism iff each ij: Tit -+ Tf, I is a homomorphism. Now, we surely want
parent PI are combined. An example of such a situation might be:
INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 301 INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 303

the interpretation of a transparent P 2 to be a homomorphism, for the reasons its three arguments, this would be clear counterevidence to our claim. We
given earlier in our development of the extensional system. Thus, we con- know of no unimpeachable example of such a verb. However, a case to be
clude that, if TP? consists exactly of the transparent homomorphisms from considered might be the verb criticize, as used in a construction like John
TRe into TP1e, then the elements of TP? are in one-to-one correspondence criticized the queen for supporting the tax plan. Here it might be claimed
with sets Vi} of homomorphisms from Tit into Tf, l ' that is, with sets of that the direct object and the for phrase constitute two arguments in both
of which the verb is properly intensional. Again, we suggest that the for
elements of Tpe . This already shows that Tp2 is total. But now, since Tpe
2 t 2 phrase is not in fact an N, so that criticize in this construction is not a P3'
is a complete atomic boolean algebra, we can apply the lifting theorem to
Moreover, the fact that the subject of the verb in the for phrase is understood
conclude that TP? is a complete atomic boolean algebra, with the boolean to be coreferent with the direct object of criticize shows that the two argu-
operations in TP2 defined on a world-by-world basis. ments in question are not independent of each other, suggesting further that
t
Before we consider the question of the type for nontransparent P 2 s, let we ate not dealing with a P 3 here. The relevance of this example to our claim
us note that our treatment of the type for transparent P z s can be generalized, seems to us sufficiently doubtful that we are content to proceed with the
by induction, to transparent n-place predicates. To see this, we first note general definition for the type for n-place predicates on the assumption that
that the type for n-place predicates, or for any subcategory thereof, is a set an n-place predicate intension does indeed map TN into TPn-l.
t
of functions from TN into TP n _1' where we can assume by induction that Now, by the inductive assumption, TPn-l is a total set of extensional
Tpn -1 has already been defined. However, we claim further that an n-place t
homomorphisms; moreover, it is a boolean algebra. Clearly, TPn should be
predicate intension actually maps TR into TP n -1' that is, into the type for t
transparent n - 1 place predicates. t the set of all transparent homomorphisms from TN into TPn-l. By the
t
The evidence supporting this claim is conclusive to a greater or lesser general extensionality theorem and the homomorphic inheritance theorem,
degree depending on the way we analyze certain constructions involving each such function f has extensions fi in every world which are themselves
predicates that take three or more arguments. What we want to show, of homomorphisms, and conversely, given a set {fi} of homomorphisms from
course, is that there do not exist any expressions of category Pn which are Tin' one for each world j E J, there is a unique transparent homomorphism
properly intensional in more than one argument; and, moreover, if such an f from TN into TPn-l which has that set as its extensions. Thus, the set
expression is properly intensional in one argument, then that argument is t
of all these transparent homomorphisms is total, and so the lifting theorem
its 'first' argument, that is, the argument with which it is directly combined
can be applied to define a boolean structure for this set using the boolean
to create an expression of category Pn -1.
structure of Tin to calculate boolean combinations of n-place predicate
Restricting our attention to three place predicates, we note that the verbs
intensions on a world-by-world basis. Thus, TP n is defined as a boolean
discussed in Part IB in connection with our representation of ditransitive
algebra for any positive integer n. t
verbs in the extensional system are indeed extensional in all arguments. Thus,
Let us now restrict our attention to the P 2 s again, and let us consider
for example, in a world in which the novels are exactly the same individuals
the type for nontransparent P 2 s. Our earlier discussion concerning the non-
as the books, the sentence John gave a novel to Mary must have the same
transparent PIS carries over to the P 2 s. We briefly go through the important
truth value as John gave a book to Mary. Similarly, if Mary and the queen
points, with some examples.
refer to the same individual in some world, then John gave a book to Mary
First, is a nontransparent P 2 intension a homomorphism? As in the case of
has the same truth value as John gave a book to the queen.
the PI s, the evidence that a nontransparent P 2 preserves meets and comple-
Ditransitive verbs which are extensional in all arguments support our
ments seems unproblematic. Thus, the sentences (30) are logically equivalent
claim, but they do so in a weak way. It would be more revealing to find
to the sentences (31) respectively:
ditransitive verbs which are properly intensional in (at least) one argument.
Verbs such as give, hand, send, which refer to acts of physical transfer, as
well as sell, lend, etc. which involve change of (permanent or temporary)
(30) John is looking for a unicorn {~~~ not}a leprechaun.
ownership, will not exhibit any proper intensionality.
302 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 304 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

A candidate for a ditransitive verb with a properly intensional argument . I00 king f or a umcorn
. {and
(31) J oh n IS b t'is looking
tIki }"lor a Ieprec h aun.
is tell. We do not mean the verb tell with an ordinary N object. Such com- u IS no 00 ng
binations appear to be extensional; thus, if in some world the stories and the
jokes are exactly the same, then John told Marya story and John told Mary However, preservation of joins is less clear. Sentence (32) is ambiguous:
a joke surely have the same truth value (and, the extensionality of tell in its
(32) John is looking for a unicorn or a leprechaun.
other two arguments is obvious). However, if tell is combined with a that
clause, as in John told Mary that Bill kissed Sally, it seems reasonable to One reading has (32) logically equivalent to:
consider tell to be properly intensional in the that clause.
In order to make use of this as a piece of evidence which bears on our (33) John is looking for a unicorn or is looking for a leprechaun.
hypothesis, we first must show that tell in this construction is indeed a
member of P3. If tell is a member of P3 , then a formula is constructed by With this reading, look-for preserves joins. On the other hand, (32) has an-
combining tell successively with three Ns. But is a that clause an N? Note other reading which appears to us to be much more natural. Namely, (32)
that, so far, we have not discussed Ns whose structure appears anything like can mean that John is engaging in a search which will be satisfied if John
that of a that clause. In fact, we will suggest later that a that clause is not an either finds a unicorn or a leprechaun. Unlike the parallel situation with
N, but rather a member of the category Po. If this analysis is accepted, then the PIS discussed earlier, we cannot here hope to represent this ambiguity
tell in this construction is not a P3 at all, and hence provides no evidence for by making use of any internal structure of the P2 , since look-for is, in our
our hypothesis. system, an unanalyzable lexical item. On the other hand, it is clearly inade-
However, let us suppose for the sake of argument that the that clause is quate not to represent the more common reading of (32), and it is clear that
an N. Then our hypothesis is supported if the that clause is combined directly this will require that the English expression look for will have to be indicated
with tell as its first argument, to create a complex P2 , to which the remaining as being equivalent to something like search 'with an aim towards finding
two arguments are added; otherwise, our hypothesis is argued against, for, at some level of the description. One way this could be done would be
say, the P 2 created by combining tell with one of its extensional arguments to assume that the English P2 look for has two translations in our logical
would then be properly intensional in its own argument, namely, in the that language. One would be the single lexical item look-for, whose intension
clause. Now, if we analyze tell as being analogous to give, and if the Patient would be a homomorphism; this would enable us to represent the less com-
analysis, chosen for verbs like give in Part IB, is adopted for tell, then indeed mon reading of (32). The other translation would be a complex P2 , perhaps
the that clause (which is clearly analogous to the patient) is the direct argu- something like try to find, whose interpretation would be set up in such a
ment of tell, confirming our hypothesis. This is further strengthened by way that the more common reading of (32) would be represented.
examining the scope relations in sentences like John told every professor But such an approach has drawbacks. First of all, it represents a retreat
that a student failed or John told a professor that every student failed. The from the idea of having the constituent structure in our logical language
Patient analysis predicts that the quantifier associated with the recipient be parallel to the constituent structure in English. If the English P 2 is a
(professor in these two sentences) has wide scope over the quantifier asso- (relatively) simple expression, or at least an expression without the internal
ciated with the patient (the that clause in these sentences). This is indeed syntactic structure of an embedding or an infinitive, then we want its trans-
the case, provided we assume that the quantifier in the subject of the that lation in our logical language to be equally simple.
clause somehow can be viewed as quantifying the that clause itself, not an More seriously, this approach would leave unrepresented and unexplained
unreasonable assumption, since the quantifier of a subject fj does quantify the fact that the ambiguity of (32) is due to the semantics of the expression
the sentence of which it is the subject (since the p) it combines with is inter- look for. That is, it is because the expression look for has a meaning involving
preted as a homomorphism). It would seem, therefore, that, to the extent the fulfillment of a desire that (32) can be ambiguous. Note that other verbs
that verbs like tell are at all relevant for our claim, our claim is supported. involving desire, including want, are similarly ambiguous. Thus, (34) can
If we could find a ditransitive verb which is properly intensional in two of mean either (35), or, more commonly, (36):
INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 305 INTENSIONAL SYSTEM FOR THE CORE LANGUAGE 307

(34) John wants a unicorn or a leprechaun. Recall that we have already defined the type for the transparent n-place
(35) John wants a unicorn or wants a leprechaun. predicates as the set of transparent homomorphisms from TN into TPn-l.
t
(36) John has a desire which will be fulfilled if he can get either a For the nontransparent n-place predicates, we start with a copy of the set of
unicorn or a leprechaun. all functions from TN into TPn-l which is disjoint from TPn, and we impose
t t
Idealy, therefore, look for (like want and all verbs of this sort) should be boolean structure by means of the pointwise definition of the operations.
represented by a single lexical item in our language whose semantic inter- Some sub algebra of the resulting algebra will then be taken to be Tpn , perhaps
nt
pretation would have properties leading to the ambiguity of (32). If we the subalgebra generated by the homomorphisms from TN into TPn-l. The
t
insisted that our logical language be unambiguous, it would still be better if type for all n-place predicates will then be the disjoint union of TPn and TPn
the interpretation of the simplest translation of (32) were the more common t nt
interpretation, which would mean that the intension of look-for would not be with no boolean structure defined. Thus, Pn as a whole is not a boolean
a homomorphism, since it would not preserve joins. category.
We will not present a solution to this issue here, noting only that we
Proof of the Theorems
should allow for the possibility that a nontransparent P 2 intension might not
be a homomorphism. Thinking ahead, and recalling our discussion of the In this section we have only the following theorem:
nontransparent PIS, we note that the interpretation of boolean combinations
of nontransparent P 2 s may also be nonhomomorphisms in general, so that THEOREM 1. Homomorphic Inheritance Theorem. Let CI and Cz be cate-
we will need to allow for this anyway. gories such that TC I e and TC 2 e are total and Tt I and Tt 2 are boolean
In fact, turning our attention to the matter of boolean combinations of algebras. Then, a transparent function rTCle ""* TCze is a homomorphism
nontransparent P 2 s, we see that we are faced with exactly the same issue as iff Vj EJ, fj: Ttl ""* Tt2 is a homomorphism.
we were when we considered boolean combinations of nontransparent PIS,
namely, whether the interpretations of such combinations should be defined Let f be a transparent function from Tc I e into TC 2 e , let j E J be arbitrary,
by means of the pointwise approach or the individual approach. In the case and let x and Y be arbitrary elements of Tc Ie. Note that Xj and Yj are well
of the P 2 s, the evidence from the interpretations of real English sentences defined elements of Ttl' and that (x A Y)j = Xj A Yj by the lifting theorem
seems to favor the pointwise approach somewhat more clearly than in the applied to TCle.
case of the PI s. Thus, (37) seems to mean (38) rather than (39), which, it Now, since f is transparent, we have (f(x A Y»j =fj((x 1\ Y)j) =fj(Xj A Yj).
seems to us, is rather difficult, if not impossible, to interpret de dictu: Suppose that f preserves meets. Then we have:

(f(x A Y»j = (f(x) 1\ f(y»j


(37) John needs or is looking for every unicorn.
(38) John needs every unicorn or is looking for every unicorn.
=(f(X»j A f(y»j (by the lifting theorem in Tc 2 e)
= fj(Xj) A fj(yj) (since f is transparent)
(39) For each unicorn, John needs that unicorn or is looking for that
unicorn. Substituting this into the equation (f(x A Y»j = fj(Xj 1\ Yj), we getfj(xj A Yj)
= fj(Xj) 1\ fj(yj). That is,fj preserves meets.
The mathematical arguments, of course, are exactly the same in the case We have just proved that if fpreserves meets, then so doesfj, for arbitrary
of the P 2 s as in the case of the PI s, since we are again dealing with functions j E J. Exactly parallel proofs show that if f preserves joins or complements,
whose domain is Tf.j, an algebra for which the justification theorem does then fj preserves joins or complements respectively, for arbitrary j E J. Thus,
not in general apply. We conclude that the type for the nontransparent P 2 s if fis a homomorphism, then eachfj is a homomorphism.
should be a subalgebra of the algebra of fun9tions from Tf.j into TP'l where Conversely, choosing f, j, x, and Y as before, and having (f(x 1\ Y»j =
the operations are defined pointwise; that is, giving g and h such functions fj (Xj A Yj) as before, suppose that fj preserves meets. Then we have:
306 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 308 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

and any f E Tfj, (g !\ h) (J) = g(f) !\ h(J), and similarly for V and '. We (f(x II Y»j = fj(Xj) II fj(Yj)
could perhaps further specify that Tpz should be HTP]/Tfj, the subalgebra = (f(x»j II (f(Y»j (since f is transparent)
nt t
of FTP,/Tfl generated by the homomorphisms. However, given the uncer- =(f(x) II f(Y»j (lifting theorem applied to TCze)'
t
tainly surrounding the correct interpretation of lexical Pz s like look-for, this
Since this last equation is true for all j, we conclude, since TCze is total,
might be premature. that f(x II y) = f(x) II f(Y), that is, that f preserves meets. Corresponding
Again, since the interpretation of nontransparent P2S might in some model
proofs show that if each fj preserves joins or complements, then f preserves
be transparent homomorphisms, whereas the boolean combinations of these joins or complements, respectively. Thus, if each fj is a homomorphism, then
interpretations are defined differently for nontransparent P2 intensions fis a homomorphism. This completes the proof of the theorem.
from the way they are defined for transparent P 2 intensions, we postulate
that TP2 and Tpz be regarded as disjoint sets.
t nt
NOTES FOR II.2
As far as the category P z as a whole is concerned, we take its type Tpz
to be simply the disjoint union of TP2 and Tpz' with no boolean structure. I The judgments concerning the interpretation of (23) are complicated by the fact that
t nt
sentences with a nontransparent PI exhibit a de dictu/de re ambiguity. With a de re
Thus, P z is not a boolean category in our intensional language. We are thus
reading the individual interpretation is clearly right, but we are trying for the de dictu
claiming that boolean combinations of two P2 s, one transparent and one reading here; similarly for (26).
nontransparent, do not occur. Actually, it seems possible in real English 2 S has k atoms a I, ... , ak. If h: S -+ 2 is a homomorphism, then h (aj) = 1 for at least
to get sentences like one atom, for otherwise h (IS) = h (a 1 v ... v ak) = h (a I) v .•• v h (ak) = 0, a contra-
diction to h (IS) = 1 (since h is a homomorphism). However, h cannot map two distinct
(40) John looked for and found a unicorn. atoms onto 1. For, if, say,h(ai) = I, then ifjfi, we haveaj <ai, whence h (aj) <h(at)=
(h(aD)' = l' = O. For each i, the equations h(ai) = 1, h(aj) = 0 (j f i), can be easily seen
where the first verb is understood de dietu. The meaning of (40) is apparently to define a unique homomorphism h: S -+ 2.
the same as that of 3 By a simple induction argument, if [ is a boolean combination of homomorphisms
from TH into Tpo (boolean operations defined pointwise), then either [ClTH) = 1Tpo
(41) John looked for a unicorn and found a unicorn. or [(1TH) = OTpo' This might not be true for an arbitrary function from THinto Tpo'

(with looked for a unicorn understood de dietu). We could represent this


in our system if all P 2 intensions (transparent and nontransparent) were 3. THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs
elements of the same copy of FTPdTfj, and if boolean operations were As in the extensional system, the category AP is defined by
t
defined pointwise in this set. However, this would lead us back to the same
difficulty we discussed earlier in connection with the interpretation of DEFINITION 1. AP =N/N.
nontransparent P 1 s whose intensions happened to be transparent homomor-
phisms; namely, boolean operations would have to make reference to the The justification for this is exactly the same as it was in our earlier develop-
syntactic category of the expressions that were being interpreted in order to ment. Syntactically, the only difference between the category AP as we shall
calculate combinations of transparent homomorphisms, since the definition discuss it here and the category AP as discussed previously is that we now
of these operations would be different depending on whether these homo- permit AP to contain properly intensional expressions. In particular, lexical
morphisms were intensions of transparent or of nontransparent P2 s. For expressions such as skillful, severe, fake, alleged, etc. which were pointed out
the present, we simply will not form sentences such as (40) in our logical earlier as being impossible to represent within the structure of an extensional
language. logic are now assumed to be legitimate members of AP.
This construction of the type for nontransparent P2 s (and for the entire In the discussion of the extensional logic for AP, we examined several
category of P 2 s) can be easily generalized to the case of n-place predicates. distinct subcategories of this major category. We will do the same here. Of
INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs 309 INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs 311

course, since we are now permitting properly intensional expressions to that the considerations above do not require in any way that fbe transparent.
be part of our system, there will be more such subcategories, and there will Suppose, for example, that the N intensions P and q have the same extensions
be more things to say about the relationships among the types for these in world j, that is, that Pj = qj- If f is a restricting AP intension, we can
subcategories. conclude that (f(p ))j .,;; Pj = qj and that (f(q ))j";; qj =Pj. However, it might
Since AP is a slash category, we know that TAP will consist offunctions. still be the case that (f(p))j f (f(q))j. In other words, even though in some
In particular, TAP will be some subset of the set FTNITN (= FFp/JIFP/J; see world the lawyers and the doctors are exactly the same individuals, and even
Definition 2, Part II.2). In fact, different subcategories of AP will have types though, in that world, a skillful lawyer is a lawyer (and a doctor), and a
which are different subsets of this set. Our principal task is to determine skillful doctor is a doctor (and a lawyer), a skillful lawyer need not be a
which subsets these types ought to be. Most of the mathematical develop- skillful doctor, and vice versa.
ments needed to do this have already been done. It will be recalled, for Let us turn next to those APs which can be handled in the extensional
example, that in Part IB we gave definitions for a number of subsets of FBIB, system. By the general extensionality theorem, the functions which interpret
where B is an arbitrary boolean algebra, and we proved some theorems about these APs should be required to be transparent. We assume a feature t,
these subsets. Now, TN is a boolean algebra, and so these definitions and therefore, and we regard these APs as members of the subcategory AP.
t
theorems can be applied directly. Lexical members of AP will be required to be interpreted by transparent
t
Recall further that TN = TNe, and that, in fact, TN is a boolean algebra functions from TN into TN.
by virtue of the lifting theorem. In order to formulate statements of greater Conceptually, the features rand t are independent of each other. We
generality than just for the category AP, it will be handy to have the follow- thus have, at this point, a four-way classification of APs, namely: restricting,
ing definition: transparent APs, restricting APs which are not transparent, transparent
APs which are not restricting, and APs which are neither restricting nor
DEFINITION 2. The boolean algebra B is J-Ufted iff there exists a boolean transparent. However, it appears to us that there may be no members of the
algebra Be such that B is isomorphic to FBelJ. third sort. We could therefore, if we wished, include the notion of restricting-
ness as part of the notion of transparency for APs. But it does not seem
Note that although we are not viewing FBelJ as the type for any particular advisable to do so; not only would such a procedure be entirely ad hoc,
category in this definition, it nevertheless makes sense to view FBelJ as but it would also add confusion to the notion of transparency. After all,
a set of objects each of which has an extension in each world indexed by
transparency is relevant to many categories, some of which lack the notion
J. In this sense, FBelJ satisfies Definition 1 of Part 11.1 for totality, and
of restrictingness (e.g. the categories Pn). It seems better, therefore, to
hence the lifting theorem can be applied to conclude thatFBelJis a boolean
allow rand t to remain independent, and to leave unexplained the fact that
algebra. Thus, it is reasonable to require that B be isomorphic to this algebra,
there are no transparent nonrestricting APs.
as we do in the definition above.
Given this, we would want to make the following definition:
As in our extensional discussion earlier, it is useful to consider various
subcategories of APs one at a time. The first such subcategory we will discuss
DEFINITION 4. TAP = {fEFTN/TN: (fis restricting)!}
is the subcategory of restricting APs.
By a restricting AP we mean here exactly the same as in our earlier discus-
m; <f is transparent)2
sion. Adjectives like Albanian, tall, and skillful are restricting, since, for
There is one potential source of difficulty. We would certainly want our
example, an individual who can be truthfully described as an Albanian
definition here to reduce to the definitions given earlier in the case of trans-
doctor, a tall doctor, or a skillful doctor, in some world, is necessarily a parent APs. However, restrictingness for an AP intension was defined without
doctor in that world. In our extensional system, the category of APs was any reference to the properties, let alone existence, of its extensions in the
limited to restricting expressions, since, as far as we can tell, all APs which worlds. Specifically, if f is a transparent restricting AP intension, can we be
are not properly intensional are restricting. Here, we do not want to do this, sure that its extensions are restricting (as AP extensions in the sense of the
310 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 312 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

since there are a number of properly intensional nonrestricting APs, such as extensional system)? As it turns out, there is no problem at all, as shown by
alleged and fake, as we have seen. However, there is a sense in which the the following theorem:
prototypical function of a modifying expression is to be restricting; and,
statistically, nonrestricting adjectives certainly appear to be a small minority, THEOREM 2. Restrictingness Inheritance Theorem. Let B be a i-lifted
limited to a few particular classes of expressions. Therefore, it does not boolean algebra and let [ E FB/B be transparent. Then [ is restricting iff
seem incorrect to regard the set of restricting APs as being 'almost' the whole 'fIj E j, fj is restricting.
set of APs.
Let us assume that there is a feature r, and that the restricting APs are The restrictingness inheritance theorem was given in a slightly more general
all members of the subcategory AP. Lexical members of AP will be marked statement than is needed just for the APs. Note that since B is i-lifted, the
r r
definition of transparency applies directly to the elements of FB/B, and, by
with the feature r. As in the cases of subcategorization we have already seen,
the general extensionality theorem, the extensions fj of [ are elements of
we will require that lexical restricting APs have intensions which lead to the
FBe/B e . In the present case, of course, TN plays the role of B. We conclude
correct entailment. Complex APs will have to be interpreted as a combination
that an AP intension is restricting and transparent just in case it has restricting
of the interpretations of their constituent expressions in such a way that a
extensions (in the sense of the extensional system) in every world.
complex restricting AP will automatically have an appropriate intension.
In our extensional system, we defined a particular subclass of the exten-
Which elements of FTNITN are appropriate interpretations of restricting
sional (here: transparent and restricting) APs called the intersecting APs.
APs? The answer is easily given, using Definition 2 in Part IB: a restricting AP
Loosely speaking, an intersecting AP is one which determines a property
should be interpreted by means of a restricting member of FTNITN (since
independent of a particular N. Thus, in a particular world, an Albanian
TN is a boolean algebra, Definition 2 can be applied.) In other words, using
athlete is an individual who is simultaneously an athlete and an Albanian.
the notation introduced in Theorem 2 of Part IB, we can define:
We clearly want to distinguish these APs in our intensional system as well,
so we posit a feature i, and we take intersecting APs to be members of the
DEFINITION 3. TAP =RTNITN
r subcategory AP of AP.
I

To see that this corresponds to the desired notion of restrictingness, we To determine which elements of FTNITN are the appropriate interpreta-
reason as follows. First, we note that if p and q are elements of TN, then tions of intersecting APs, we turn to Definition 5 in Part IB. Letting TN play
p ~ q ifffor eachi EJ, Pj ~ qj. Slightly more generally, we have: the role of B in that definition, we can say that an intersecting AP should
be interpreted by means of an intersecting member of FTN/TN' Noting
THEOREM 1. Let B be a J-lifted boolean algebra and let p, q E B be arbitrary. that the meet operation in that definition here corresponds to and as con-
Then p ~ q iff Vi E J, Pj ~ qj (in Be). joining N intensions and that 1 in that definition here corresponds to the
intension of being an entity, we see that, if, say, [is the intension of Albanian
Theorem 1 is an almost trivial consequence of the lifting theorem. and x is the intension of athlete, then the equation [(x) = X II [(1) translates
Now, to say thatfEFTNITN is restricting means just to say thatf(p) ~p directly to the requirement that the intension of Albanian athlete must be
for any p E TN. By Theorem 1 above, this is equivalent to saying that for the same as the intension of athlete conjoined with the intension of Albanian
each world i, (f(p))j ~ Pj. But this is just what we want. If, say,p is the entity. Using the notation introduced in Theorem 3, Part IB, we can alter-
intension of doctor and f is the intension of skillful, then this would mean natively define:
that for each world i, if an individual is a skillful doctor in that world, then
DEFINITION 5. TAl =ITN/TN'
that individual is a doctor in that world. I
We will see in a moment that intensions which interpret APs that can
be represented in the extensional system will be required to be transparent Can anything be said about the relationship between intersecting APs and,
(in the sense of Definition 2, Part ILl). However, it is important to notice on the one hand, restricting APs, and, on the other hand, transparent APs?
INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs 313 INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs 315

Theorem 1, Part IB can be applied directly, with TN playing the role of B, The interpretation of alleged can therefore not be restricted to lie in any of
to conclude that an intersecting AP intension is automatically restricting. the special subsets of FTNITN that we have defined above.
We thus have: Because of this, it is perhaps simplest if we assume that conjectural APs
just do not carry any of the four subcategorization features that we have
(1 ) defined for APs. If so, then a complete definition of the types for the cate-
gory AP and its subcategories can be given as follows:
However, we can show more. Suppose that f is an intersecting AP intension,
that x is an N intension, and that j is the index of some world. We have that <f is restricting>! }
(f(x»j = (x A f(I»j = Xj A (f(I»j, where the first equality follows by the <f is transparent>2
definition of intersectingness and the second equality follows from the fact <f is intersecting>3
that, since TN = TNe is total, meets in TN are calculated on a world by world <fis negative>4
basis. Now, suppose that x and yare N intensions with the same extension
in j, that is, that Xj = Yj. Then (f(x»j = Xj A (f(1»j =Yj A (f(l»j = (f(y»j- As pointed out following the previous version of this definition, namely
But this just means that f satisfies the definition of transparency. We have Definition 6, there are relationships among the subsets defined above. Here
thus shown that an intersecting AP intension is necessarily transparent. In we need only add that TAP and TAP are almost disjoint by their very defini-
r n
other words, we have: tion: there is only one function which is a member of both these sets, namely,
the function which maps every N intension into the zero N intension.
(2) At this point we are in a position to illustrate how the interpretation of
sentences with APs can be carried out. Let us calculate the interpretation of
Thus, there are no new expressions of category AI> when we pass from the John kissed a skillful doctor:
extensional to the intensional system. In additidn, we have the following
theorem: (4) John kissed a skillful doctor
(a) John (kiss (a (skillful doctor)))
THEOREM 3. Intersectingness Inheritance Theorem. Let B be a I-lifted
boolean algebra and let f E FBIB be transparent. Then f is intersecting iff
(b) x
I k
I
a
I s
\ I
d
vj E I, fj is intersecting.

As in the case of the restrictingness inheritance theorem, the definition of


transparency applies to FBIB since B is I-lifted, and the extensions fj of f
are elements of FBe IBe. In the case ofthe intersecting APs, TN plays the role
of B in this theorem.
(c)

(d)
~v"¥ a(s(d))

Summarizing what we have so far, we can extend Definition 4 above to (e) k(a(s(d))
read as follows:
(f) k(a(s(d))) (x)
DEFINITION 6. TAP = {fEFTNITN: <fis restricting>!}
~ill Line (a) gives the representation of the given English sentence in our logical
w; <f is transparent>2
<f is intersecting>3 language. In line (b), the lexical expressions are replaced by their interpre-
tations, which are, of course, intensions. In particular, x is an N intension
Moreover, the sets TAP, TAP, TAP, and TAP are related as in the diagram: whose extension in every world is some individual, say I!. The remaining lines
r -1 i
314 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 316 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

(3) involve combining the intensions in the usual function-argument manner.


Line (f) is therefore the intension of the whole sentence.
In a particular worldj, the following calculation can be made:

(5) (k(o(s(d))) (x))j =(k(o(s(d))))j (II) (Xj = II; k(o(s(d))) is


transparent)
= kj(o(s(d)))j (11) (k is transparent)
with the shading in TAP- TAP indicating that these intensions are apparently
t r =kj(oj(s(d))j) (Jd (0 is transparent)
not the intensions of any actual APs. Finally, for transparent AP intensions,
the properties of being restricting or intersecting are equivalent to having = k·( U I) (I )
J (s(d})j E l l
(definition of 0)
restricting or intersecting extensions in all the worlds.
Let us turn next to the small class of negative APs, which includes adjec- =«S(d))j ~ I kj(I)) (II) (kj is a homomorphism)

tives like fake. It is convenient to make the following definition: = (S(d))jEI


V k·(I)
J
(I )
1
(definition of V in Til)

DEFINITION 7. Let B be a boolean algebra. The functionfEFB/B isnega-


(This should be compared with the calculation in (1) in Part IB.) Now, since
tive iff '1x EB, f(x) ";;x'.
skillful is a lexical member of the category AP, its intension s is required to
r
If we now require that negative APs are members of the subcategory AP, we be restricting. Thus, sed) .;:;; d, whence, by Theorem 1, (s(d))j .;:;; dj. But
n
can insure that the correct entailments result by taking the type for AP to (s(d))j and dj and N extensions, that is, elements of P. Since anN extension
n
be the set of negative functions from TN into TN. Note that if f is such a is a member of an individual iff the atom associated with that individual
negative function and x is an N intension, then, by Theorem 1, we have is contained in that N extension, we conclude that:
that, for each world j, (f(x))j ..;; (x')j = (Xj)' (the last equality following by
the lifting theorem applied to TN). Thus, iff interprets fake and x interprets (6)
gun, then, in any world, if an individual is a fake gun, that individual is not
a gun. Since the right hand side of (6) is the extension in j of John (kiss (a doctor)),
Finally, there is the class of APs, including the adjectives alleged, putative, as the reader can easily verify, we conclude that John (kiss (a (skillful doc-
etc., which are neither negative nor restricting. The logical characteristic of tor))) implies John (kiss (a doctor)) in any world. Note that in our discussion
these APs, which we call conjectural APs, is a negative one: none of the we never made use of any assumption of transparency for s; indeed, since
entailments which can be made on the basis of an AP being restricting, skillful is not a member of AP, we must allow the possibility that s is not
transparent, intersecting, or negative, can be made for these APs. Therefore, t
transparent, and therefore that there are no such things as extensions of s
we define the type for this group of APs as being the entire set FTN/TN.
in the worlds.
Note that we do not want to forbid the intension of a conjectural AP to be
transparent, restricting, etc. It might happen that in a particular interpre- Of course, if we replace skillful in (4) with tall, which is a member of AP,
t
tation, some conjectural AP could in fact exhibit one or another of these then, assuming that t is the intension of tall, the extension of John (kiss
special properties. For example, it might happen that in some interpretation (0 (tall doctor))) in j is equal to
an alleged thief always (or never) turned out to be a thief. For such an
(7) V k·(I) (II) = V k·(I) (I )
interpretation, the interpretation of alleged would be restricting (or negative). (t(d))jEI J tj(dj)EI J I
However, this would be an accidental fact about that interpretation; in gen-
eral, an alleged thief is neither necessarily a thief nor necessarily a non-thief. since t is transparent. The right hand side of (7) should be compared to (Ii)
INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs 317 319
INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs

in Part IB; the situation reduces to precisely what we had in the extensional finds any entity which has the property of being a doctor in the world in
system. question. Now, we cannot conclude that John is looking for a doctor in this
If we replace skillful in (4) with fake, then, assuming that f is the intension sense if we know that it is the case that John is looking for a skillful doctor.
of fake, the extension of John (kiss (a (fake doctor))) in j is equal to The reason is simply that finding an entity which has the property of being
a doctor is not enough to satisfy John's desire. The entity which will satisfy
this desire must in fact be a member of the presumably smaller set of skillful
doctors. If we saw John engaging in a search, finding a number of doctors,
Since fake is a member of the subcategory AP, we must have fed) ,,;;; d', but rejecting them and continuing his search, we would surely say that it
n
whence (f(d))j ,,;;; Cd')j =(dj)'. From this we can conclude that any individual is not the case that John is looking for a doctor is true in the sense just
I which contains (f(d»)j cannot contain dj (since the atom associated with indicated.
I would have to be contained in (f(d))j, and hence in (dj)', and so that atom On the other hand, it appears that the English sentence John is looking
could not be contained in dj). Since (8) implies that John kisses an individual for a doctor is sometimes open to the following looser interpretation: John
with the property (f(d»j in world j, we see that John (kiss (a (fake doctor») is engaged in a search, the search will be satisfied if John finds any entity
implies that John kisses at least one individual who is not a doctor. No con- satisfying a certain property, and any such entity is a doctor. Note that this
clusion can be drawn concerning whether John kisses any doctors in world means that the set of entities anyone of which will satisfy John's search is
j or not, of course. a subset of the set of doctors, but is not necessarily the whole set of doctors.
Finally, if we replace skillful in (4) with putative, then, assuming that p In other words, this looser interpretation of John is looking for a doctor is
is the intension of putative, the extension of John (kiss (a (putative doctor») equivalent to the tighter interpretation (as defined above) of a sentence like
in j is equal to John is looking for a doctor satisfying some (perhaps contextually defined)
additional property. It is this looser sense that we are using when we conclude
('obviously') that John is looking for a doctor on the basis of knowing that
John is looking for a skillful doctor.
However, this suggests that the looser interpretation actually involves
Since putative does not carry any of the features r, t, i, or n, no particular
ellipsis. It is certainly the case that the tighter interpretation is the preferred
relationship can be assumed to hold between (p(d»j and dj. Thus, not only
(or possibly only) interpretation of John is looking for a doctor if this sen-
can we conclude neither the truth nor the falsity of John (kiss (a doctor»
tence is used out of context. Presumably, the problem of ellipsis is one which
from the truth of John (kiss (a (putative doctor»), but, assuming this latter
is appropriately handled by the component of grammar which mediates
sentence to be true in a world, we cannot conclude that any of the individuals
between English sentences and sentences in our logical language. If so, then
kissed by John either is or is not a doctor. we do not want John (look-for (a (skillful doctor))) to imply John (look-for
It is interesting to consider the question of what interpretation results
(a doctor)), since these logical sentences will correspond unambiguously
if kiss in (4) is replaced by a nontransparent Pz , say, by look-for. If the to the tighter interpretation. But this means that we do not want it to be
intension of look-for is I, then, parallel to (4f), we obtain l(a(s(d») (x) as automatically the case that (l(a(s(d))) .;;;; l(a(d)). This is not only further
the intension of John (look-for (a (skillful doctor»). Since this latter is the evidence that we had better not require nontransparent Pn intensions to
translation, in our logical language, of the English sentence John is looking be homomorphisms, it is evidence that we had better not require nontrans-
for a skillful doctor, let us examine the implications of this sentence and see parent Pn intensions even to preserve the .;;;; relation. This matter clearly
if they match of predictions made by our system. deserves further investigation. For now, however, we do not pursue it any
As a preliminary fact, let us note that since skillful is restricting, we have,
further.
for an arbitrary j E J, that (s(d»j ,,;;; dj- Since a is an increasing determiner,
Let us return now to the types for the various subcategories of the cate-
we can conclude that aj (s(d»j ,,;;; aj (d;) for each j E J. Finally, since a is
gory AP. In Definition 8, we indicated what these types are insofar as being
318 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 320 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

transparent, we have that (a(s(d)))j .,;; (a(d))j for each j E J, whence by sets of intensions. However, there remains the task of deciding which of these
Theorem 1,a(s(d))";;a(d). types ought to carry boolean structure and what that structure ought to be.
Having obtained this, what can we conclude about the relationship, if The case of restricting APs is easily handled. We clearly want boolean
any, between I(a(s(d))) and l(a(d))? Clearly, this depends on what we combinations of these to be constructed and interpreted, in order to handle
assume about l. In Part 11.2, we discussed the question of whether or not a English fis such as a skillful and (but)/or/but not severe teacher. If we define
nontransparent P2 intension ought to be a homomorphism, tentatively AP to be a boolean category, then the way to define boolean structure is
r
concluding that, since we wanted to use pointwise defined boolean operations indicated in Theorem 2 of Part IB. In fact, since TAP = RTN/TN (in the
on the nontransparent P 2 intensions, we could not restrict these intensions to r
notation of that theorem), we can conclude directly that TAP is a boolean
being homomorphisms. However, it was suggested that, perhaps, the algebra r
of the nontransparent P2 intensions is generated by the homomorphisms. algebra (in fact, a complete atomic one) with operations as defined in that
Specifically, we discussed the logic of some sentences involving the lexical theorem. We leave it to the reader to verify that those operations correspond
P 2 look-for, deciding that there was some doubt whether the intension of correctly to the interpretations of English fis such as the ones just mentioned.
this expression could be restricted to be a homomorphism. In the present Since the types for transparent and intersecting APs are each subsets of
circumstance, we note that if I is a homomorphism, we could conclude that the type for restricting APs, we may ask whether or not they are subalgebras
I(a(s(d))) .,;; I(a(d)). However, if I is not a homomorphism, it still might of TAP. The case of the intersecting APs follows directly from Theorem 3
r
be the case that, whenever x .,;; y, it would be the case that I(x)";; l(y). In of Part IB; note that TA.P = ITN/TN in the notation of that theorem. The
!
Keenan and Faltz (1978), it was proposed that P2 s like look-for carry a issue of transparency (in the technical sense) was not discussed in Part IB,
feature +additive, and that the intensions of such P 2 s be required at least so we need an additional theorem. First, we define:
to preserve the < relation, even though they could not be required to be
homomorphisms. If we take this approach, then we can indeed claim that DEFINITION 9. Let B be a i-lifted boolean algebra. Then
l(a(s(d))) .,;; l(a(d)). If this is so, then, since two transparent P l intensions
are being compared, we can conclude directly (since transparent PI intensions TB/B = {jEFB/B: fis transparent}.
are uncontroversially homomorphisms) that l(a(s(d))) (x) .,;; I(a(d)) (x).
Since the latter is the interpretation of John (look-for (a doctor)), this would We now have the following theorem:
mean that John (look-for (a (skillful doctor))) implies that John (look-for
(a doctor)). Is this correct? THEOREM 4. Let B be a i-lifted boolean algebra. Then TB/B n RB/B is
At first blush, this seems to be exactly what we want. Surely, if John a subalgebra of RB/B. Moreover, if B is complete, then TB/B n RB/B is
is looking for a skillful doctor, we can conclude that John is looking for a complete.
doctor. However, if we examine carefully the way look for sentences are
actually used in English, we can detect an ambiguity which calls this 'obvious' In Part IB we discussed the fact that boolean combinations of APs of different
claim into question. subcategories are sometimes odd. Similar facts obtain when nontransparent
The ambiguity we mean is not the de dictu-de re ambiguity; this we shall restricting APs are combined with APs of other categories. Combinations of
discuss in a later chapter, where we shall see that the direct interpretation such APs with transparent nonintersecting APs seem mostly to be all right:

l
of look-for sentences as we have set things up always corresponds to a de
dictu reading, and that de re readings always involve a A operator in the and (but))
translation of the English sentence into our logical language. What we have (10) a skillful ?or fat geisha (or: a skillful, fat geisha).
in mind here is rather the following. In one sense, the sentence John is but not
looking for a doctor means that John is engaging in activity based on the
desire to find some entity, and that this desire of his will be satisfied if he Combining a nontransparent restricting AP with an intersecting one is worse:
INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs 321 INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs 323

SkillfUll~; ~~d
These expressions, though odd sounding, are perfectly interpretable. More-
(11) a IAlbanian dancer (but ok: a skillful, Albanian over, our intuition is that, although the expressions not fake diamond and
? but not not phony doctor are not used by themselves as Ns in English, they ought
dancer). to be interpreted as meaning something like real diamond and real doctor
respectively. In particular, this would mean that the negation of a negative
Our earlier remarks appear to apply to the same degree here that they did AP is a restricting AP. How should this negation be interpreted?
in Part IB. Note, incidentally, that since intersecting APs are transparent, Suppose that f is the intension of a negative AP and that p is the intension
Theorem 5 in that discussion holds on a world by world basis, and hence, of an N that it is combined with. If we apply Definition 9 of Part IB to
also, of intersecting intensions. determine f', we would have that f'(p) = p f\ (f(p»)'. But, since f is the
We come now to the question of whether boolean combinations of other interpretation of a negative AP, f(p) < p', whence p = p" < (f(p»)'. But
subclasses of APs ought to be formed, and, if so, what the interpretations of this means that f' (p) = p. That is, to be a not phony doctor (or a non-phony
such combinations ought to be. doctor) would be equivalent to being a doctor.
Consider first the negative APs. Some lexical expressions of category AP If we think of not phony doctor as equivalent to real doctor, this is not
n
are, perhaps, false, fake, phony, artificial. Combinations involving these and unreasonable. Surely, in any world, the set of real doctors is precisely the
restricting APs combined with and sound odd: same as the set of doctors. The function of the adjective real seems to be
solely discoursal, calling the hearer's attention to the fact that a certain
(12) ? an artificial and heavy diamond
entity is indeed a member of the set of doctors, perhaps contrary to some
? a fake and Albanian gun
presupposition or expectation, rather than narrowing down the set of doctors
although these seem to become all right if comma intonation is substituted to a properly smaller set.
for and: Accepting this, we see that if Definitions 7, 8, and 9 of Part IB are ex-
tended to negative AP intensions, then the resulting interpretations appear
(13) an artificial, heavy diamond to be reasonable. However, if we do this, the boolean axioms are not satisfied.
a fake, Albanian gun In particular, if f is a negative AP intension, it is not necessarily the case
that (f')' is equal to f. For, according to what we showed above,[' (p) = p,
However, if we try to think what the expressions in (13) might mean, we whence (f')'(p) = p f\ (f'(p»' = p f\ p' = O. But, while we do require that
may detect an odd sense of contradiction in them. We can get some insight f(p) < p', we certainly cannot assume that f(p) = 0, as would have to be the
into this if we try to construct a formal interpretation for these expressions. case if f(p) = (f')' (p), by what we have just seen. We are now faced with
To interpret the conjunction of APs in (12), it seems reasonable to try three choices:
to use Definition 7 of Part IB. Supposing f and g to be the intensions of (i) Abandon the requirement that boolean-like operations always satisfy
artificial and heavy respectively and x to be the intension of diamond, the the classical axioms. That is, with this choice, we would admit certain types
intension of (artificial and heavy) diamond would be (f 1\ g) (x) = f(x) as being sets with boolean-like operations but not being boolean algebras.
1\ g(x). Now, since artificial is negative, we have f(x) ~ x', whence (since We would certainly want to investigate what deviations from boolean-algebra-
f(x) 1\ g(x) ~ f(x)) (f 1\ g) (x)~x'. However,gis restricting, so thatg(x) ~ hood were permitted.
x, whence (since f(x) 1\ g(x) ~ g(x)) (f 1\ g)(x) ~x. Thus, (f 1\ g)(x) ~x' (ii) Change the definitions of the operations as they apply to negative AP
1\ x = O. What we have just proved shows that, according to our interpretation, intensions in such a way that the boolean axioms are indeed satisfied.
there are no entities which have the property which interprets (artificial and (iii) Abandon the idea of extending the boolean operations to negative
heavy) diamond in any world. While our intuitions are a bit vague as to the AP intensions altogether.
meaning of the expressions in (13), this seems to have a reasonable chance Each of these choices has its appeal as well as its drawbacks. For now,
of being correct. we simply leave this issue open.
322 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 324 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

The argument above would not hold, of course, if Definition 7 Part IB Given the fact that we have not resolved the matter of boolean operations
were used with the intensions of two negative APs. If the corresponding for negative AP intensions, it is perhaps academic to consider the question of
expressions are actually formed, we still have the sense of oddness when whether a single set of boolean operations can or should be defined on the
and is used: entire type TAP' However, let us note a few points relevant to this issue.
Defining a boolean structure on all of TAP would allow the interpretation
(14) ? a fake and phony diamond of combinations of APs at least one of which was a conjectural AP. However,
the English expressions corresponding to conjunctions of this sort sound
If a comma is used instead, the expression exudes a feeling of redundancy, quite bad, whether the conjunction is expressed by the word and, as in:

I~~~~l I
due to the similarity in the meanings of the two APs:

(15) a fake, phony diamond. (20) an alleged and doctor


Albanian
However, our intuition is that the contradiction hovering within the meaning
of the expressions in (13) is absent from (15). It appears, therefore, that or by a comma (as seems to be the way such conjunction is normally handled
Definition 7 Part IE may reasonably be extended to apply to the intensions in English for pre nominal adjectives), as in:

I~~~~~l I
of restricting and of negative APs.
Disjunctions of negative APs with other APs tend to sound odd, especially
when the second AP is intersecting: (21) an alleged, doctor
Albanian
(16) ? an artificial or heavy diamond
(17) ?? a fake or Albanian gun There are two points we should note about these.
First of all, the expressions in (21) should not be confused with expressions
However, such expressions do seem interpretable. If a disjunction is formed such as the following in which there is no comma:
with two negative APs, the or seems to be rhetorical rather than logical.
That is, in an expression like

(18) a fake or phony diamond


(22) an alleged I~~~l~~l I
Albanian
doctor

there is a sense that or indicates the speaker's hesitation concerning which which are acceptable and interpretable. These are, of course, interpreted
word, fake or phony best applies, rather than indicating that the speaker not as boolean combinations of adjectives, but rather as applications of
is interested in referring to an entity which either satisfies the fake diamond the alleged function to the combinations phony doctor (or skillful doctor).
property or else the phony diamond property. This, too, is due to the simi- In other words, the translation of the expressions in (22) into our logical
larity in the meanings of the two negative APs. In any case, if disjunctions language will be a (alleged (phony doctor» (and, similarly, a (alleged (skil(ful
involving negative APs are allowed, the reader can see easily that Definition doctor», etc.). Such expressions are already taken care of by what we have
8 of Part IE provides acceptable interpretations of such combinations. set up in our system, and need no further comment.
Turning finally to the matter of negations of negative APs, we first examine Secondly, there appears to be an inherent contradiction in the expressions
expressions like in (21), a contradiction of a sort not expressible in our logic. A speaker who
refers to an entity by means of the N
(19) a green but not fake diamond
an Albanian but not phony doctor. (23) an alleged, skillful doctor
INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs 325 INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs 327

seems to be committed to the idea that that entity could be referred to is not necessarily a problem; the procedure of Part IB will impose a scalarity
simultaneously by means of the N on individuals-per-world, allowing the (probably desirable) possibility of
comparing individuals in different worlds with respect to some scale. If
(24) an alleged doctor worlds correspond to points in time, this would allow us to make sense of
a sentence like John is smarter than he was last year.
and by theN However, in the case of a properly intensional AP like skillful, the prop-
erty of order-consistency will not work correctly. To see this, let f be the
(25) a skillful doctor intension which interprets skillful, let a and b be two atoms of P, let j and k
be two worlds, and let q E TN be such that q(j) = a, q(k) = b, and q(i) = 0
Now, since skillful is restricting, the use of (25) commits the speaker to for every world i where i f j and i f k. Suppose that f( q) is the N intension
the belief that the entity he wishes to refer to is indeed a doctor. However, which maps every world except k into 0 and which maps k into b. Intuitively,
the proper use of (24) involves the idea that the speaker is precisely not then, this should correspond to the idea that the only skillful 'q' is to be
committing himself to the doctorhood of the intended referent. This is found in world k, and that the only individual in world k who is a skillful
different from saying that the extensional referent of (24) is not required 'q' is the individual corresponding to the atom b.
to be a doctor (but is not required to be a non-doctor, either). In terms of Now, suppose that the individual corresponding to a is a doctor in worldj,
the relationship between the Ns (24) and (25) and their extensions, there is and that the individual corresponding to b is a doctor in world k. Suppose
no inherent contradiction; if both are proper Ns to use to refer to the same further that a is a skillful doctor in world j. By the property of order con-
entity, then it simply must be that that entity, which/who might be a doctor sistency as defined in Definition 15 of Part IB, it would necessarily be the
(by (24», genuinely is a doctor (by (25)). However, there is a contradiction case that b is a skillful doctor in world k. Clearly, we do not want to be
between the required presence of a speaker-commitment with (25) and the able to come to such a conclusion.
required absence of a speaker-commitment with (24). In other words, the The difficulty, of course, is that there is no particular connection between
locus of the contradiction inherent in the N (23) is the matter of speaker being a 'q' and being a doctor. Thus, a properly intensional AP like skillful
commitment, an area totally distinct from the concerns which our logical must be expected to behave randomly different when modifying distinct N
system addresses. Since this is the case (and since, as the reader may easily intensions. Note that if we replace skillful with tall in the above paragraph,
check by forming expressions himself, disjunctions and negations involving the problem disappears. We could, perhaps, then retain the earlier analysis,
conjectural APs sound equally peculiar), we feel it is reasonable, at least but restrict it to transparent scalar APs only. But this still would leave the
provisionally, not to suggest a general definition for boolean structure on problem of the scalarity of nontransparent APs like skillful to be dealt with;
TAP· note that the chief motivation which led us to want to formalize scalarity,
This completes our discussion of TAP and the subsets of this set relevant namely, the existence of comparatives, applies to these nontransparent cases
to the intensional interpretation of various classes of APs. However, before as well. This too is a question which we leave unresolved for now.
moving on to the next major topic to be discussed, let us briefly look at a Finally, let us briefly consider a situation in which APs enter into a struc-
few special issues that relate to APs. ture as arguments. What we have in mind are expressions such as seem happy,
We would like our system to be able to handle expressions which serve look Albanian, appear rested and content in which an expression like seem,
to modify APs. Such expressions would include lexical items like very and look, appear, sound, etc. is combined with an AP to produce a complex
somewhat, as well as, ultimately, complex expressions like to a certain extent. Pl. By the way we have been setting up our syntax, we see that, as a first
We will not make a serious proposal here concerning the syntax of such approximation, seem, look, etc. are members of category P1/AP. However,
expressions. However, we can easily say something about their interpretation. we can tighten this up somewhat.
Note first that these modifiers can probably be safely restricted to combin- First of all, not every AP can be an argument of such a verb. In particular,
ing only with restricting APs: conjectural APs cannot be used this way:
I I
326 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 328 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

*very alleged (27) * The thief seemed/looked/sounded alleged/putative.


(26) a ?very phony doctor
very skillful However, negative APs, as well as all subclasses of restricting APs, can be
This means that they are of category API AP, and therefore their interpreta- freely combined with these verbs:
r r
tions are functions from TAP into TAP.
r r
Next, these modifiers are probably all restricting. Thus, a somewhat phony 1
skillful doctor is, perhaps, a skillful doctor. If so, then the type for such
modifiers can be taken to be the set of restricting functions from TAP into
(28) The thief { seemed}
looked 1 skillful
tall
r Albanian
itself. Note that since TAP is a boolean algebra, the notion of restrictingness
r
is defined for such functions. (If there turn out to be clear examples of We can therefore say more specifically that seem, etc. are members of the
nonrestricting AP modifiers, we simply can enlarge the type to include other category PI/(AP U AP).
r n
functions.) Secondly, the PI that is created when such a combination is made is
Finally, we can perhaps define the interpretation of one such modifier, always transparent. Thus, in a world in which the thief and John are the same
regarding it as a logical constant. The modifier we have in mind is very, and individual, the truth values of the sentences in (28) are necessarily the same
the interpretation we can give is the same one we suggested earlier in our as the truth values of:
discussion of extensional APs. Namely, we can require that in any model
very be interpreted as very, where very (f) = f2 for any fE TAP. The reader
r
can check easily that Theorems 7 and 8 of Part IB are still true even if we are (29)
phony 1
dealing with AP intensions rather than AP extensions. We conclude that this
John {Seemed}
looked 1tall
skillful

definition interprets very as a restricting AP modifier. Moreover, iff is inter- Albanian


secting, then very (f) =f, so that the discussion in Part IB of the awkwardness
and reinterpretation of intersecting APs combined with very still goes through. Note that, as in the case of be (see our discussion in Part IB), we feel com-
Incidentally, there is nothing particularly problematic about combining very pelled to neglect the role of context in the interpretation of such sentences.
with a nontransparent AP like skillful. If the intension of skillful is f, then For example, if we compare (30) and (31):
the intension of very skillful will be just J2 , itself a nontransparent restricting
function, in general. (30) The doctor seems skillful
Returning to the APs themselves, recall that in Part IB we discussed the (31) The lawyer seems skillful
extensional interpretations of scalar adjectives. One approach suggested there
was that the extensions of scalar adjectives be required to satisfy three con- we have the sense that, in its most expected context, sentence (30) would
ditions, called coherence, transitivity, and order-consistency. Since an AP be used to indicate that the individual referred to by the R the doctor seems
intension is a restricting function from a complete atomic boolean algebra skillful as a doctor, whereas sentence (31) would be used to indicate that the
(namely TN) into itself, the same definitions can be mechanically adopted individual referred to by the R the lawyer seems skillful as a lawyer. In a
for AP intensions. However, it is not clear that the correct notion of scalarity world in which there is precisely one doctor and precisely one lawyer and
emerges from this procedure. in which the one doctor and the one lawyer are the same individual, it might
To see the problem, note first that the atoms of TN do not correspond appear, therefore, that although the extensions of the subjects of (30) and
to individuals or entities, but rather to individuals·per·world. That is, an (31) are the same, the truth values of these sentences needn't be the same,
atom of TN is determined uniquely not by an atom a of P, but by a pair and hence that seem skillful is not transparent. However, if we factor out
(a, j), where a is an atom of P and j E J is an arbitrary world. This by itself the effect of context, this problem does not arise. Specifically, we imagine
INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs 329 INTENSIONAL LOGIC FOR APs 331

the meaning of seem skillful as applied to an individual to be that that indi- Extensionality Theorem and the Homomorphic Inheritance Theorem, this
vidual exhibits an appearance from which one may deduce that he is skillful uniquely defines an element of Tpz.
t
at some (contextually determined) activity. Since this activity is contextually When combined with an AP, be is interpreted as bez, where bez is that
determined, we are not in a position to take it into consideration in our element of FTpITAPsuchthatgivenfETApandiEJ,(be2(/))/'isthat
representation of the semantics; for our purposes, we have to imagine that t1
homomorphism from P* into 2 such that, for any individual I, «be2 (/))j (1)
seem skillful means exhibit an appearance of skill at some activity. If so,
then (30) and (31) do necessarily have the same truth value in the world we
= 1 iff VP E TN (f(p ))j E I. The reader may check easily that this definition
reduces to the one given in the extensional system on a world by world basis
sketched out. Note, in support of this, that, say, (31) could be perfectly
in case f is transparent. However,f need not be transparent for this definition
well uttered to indicate that the individual described as being the lawyer
to be applied. If f is the interpretation of skillful, then, with this definition,
seems skillful as he gives medical attention to someone, Le., as he acts in
be skillful is still true of an individual in a particular world iff, roughly, be
the capacity of being a doctor, even though he is being referred to as the
a skillful e is true of that individual, for some actual or potential N e.
lawyer.
This being the case, we can further state that the category of seem, etc.
Proofs of the Theorems
is Ptl/(AP U AP). From this, we can deduce that the type of this class of
r n
words is some subset of FTp /(T AP U TAP). The question now arises THEOREM 1. Let B be a J-lifted boolean algebra and let P, q E B be arbitrary.
tl r n
Then p <: q iff Vi E J, Pj <: qj (in Be).
as to which subset of this set is the appropriate type for the category
Ptl/(AP U AP).
r n We have P <: q iff P A q = P (definition of <:)
We have seen that when an expression of type ~2 is combined with an
iff (p A q)j =Pj, Vi EJ (B is J-lifted)
argument to create a transparent PI, the interpretation of that P2 depends iff Pj A qj = Pi, Vi E J (lifting theorem)
homomorphically on the interpretation of its argument. We might therefore iff Pi <: qi' Vi EJ (definition of <:)
expect that when a verb like seem is combined with an AP argument, its
interpretation depends homomorphically on the interpretation of the AP. THEOREM 2. Restrictingness Inheritance Theorem. Let B be a J-lifted
As it happens, this is not so. boolean algebra and let f E FBIB be transparent. Then f is restricting iff
First of all, if the argument AP is negative, we have the problem that the Vi E J, fj is restricting.
boolean operations have not been defined for negative APs. Thus, TAP U TAP
r n
is simply not a boolean algebra, as things now stand, and so no function We have that f is restricting iff f( b) <: b Vb E B (definition of
which has this set as its domain can be described as being a homomorphism. restricting)
However, it still might be the case that the restriction of the interpretation' iff (f(b ))j <: bi Vb E B, Vi E J (Theorem 1)
of seem to TAP is a homomorphism (recall that TAP is a boolean algebra; ifffj(bj)<:bj Vb EB, ViEJ
r r
in fact, it is the restricting algebra RTN/TN). This would mean that the (a) (f is transparent; B is J-lifted;
and (b) sentences in the following pairs would necessarily have the same truth general extensionality theorem)
value in any world: ifffj(x)<:x VxEBe, ViEJ (B isJ-lifted)
iff fj is restricting ViE J (definition of
(32) (a) John seems happy and successful
restricting)
(b) John seems happy and seems successful
(33) (a) John seems happy or successful THEOREM 3. Intersectingness Inheritance Theorem. Let B be a J-lifted
(b) John seems happy or seems successful
boolean algebra and let f E FBIB be transparent. Then f is intersecting iff
(34) (a) John seems successful but not happy Vi EJ, fj is intersecting.
(b) John seems successful but doesn't seem happy
330 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 332 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

While it might seem at a causal glance that the (a) and (b) sentences in each We have that f is intersecting
of these pairs are indeed synonymous, a closer examination reveals that this iff feb) =b 1\ f(1) Vb EB (definition of intersecting)
is probably not so. Consider for example (33a) and (33b). Sentence (33a) iff (f(b))j =(b I\f(1»j 'Vb EB, 'VjEJ (B is J-lifted)
appears to state that John exhibits a certain appearance, and that that appear- iff (f(b »j = bj 1\ (f(1 »j Vb E B, Vj E J (lifting theorem)
ance suggests that either happiness or success can be truthfully predicated iff fi (bj) = bj I\fi(l) VbEB, VjEJ (f is transparent; B is J-
of John. Sentence (33b) on the other hand states that John exhibits one of lifted; general extension-
two appearances, one of which suggests happiness, the other of which sug- ality theorem)
gests success. While our judgments here are not secure, it seems possible that iff fi(X) = x 1\ fi(1) Vx EBe, Vj EJ (B is J-lifted)
(33b) might be true in a world in whlch (33a) is false. (The reverse situation iff fi is intersecting Vj E J (definition of intersecting).
seems less likely.)
The nonequivalence of (34a) and (34b) is perhaps clearer. From sentence THEOREM 4. Let B be a J-lifted boolean algebra. Then TB/B () RB/B is
(34a) we definitely derive the sense that John's appearance suggests actual a subalgebra of RB/B' Moreover, if B is complete, than TB/B () RB/B is
unhappiness, whereas (34b) merely states that John lacks the appearance of complete.
happiness. Thus, (34b) could easily be true in a world in whlch (34a) is false.
The case of the pair of sentences in (32) is less clear. Possibly, (32a) Let f, g E TB/B () RB/B' We can show that the latter set is a subalgebra of
predicates a single appearance while (32b) predicates two appearances. RB/B if we show thatf 1\ g,fv g, andf' are transparent, using the operations
In any case, we prefer not to assume any algebraic properties to hold of as defined in RB/B' .
the intensions of words like seem. Provisionally, then, we take the type Let x, Y E B be such that Xj =Yj for some particular j E J. Then
of category Ptl/(AP U AP) to be the full set of functions from TAP U TAP
r n r n
into TP I •
t
we have that «f 1\ g) (x»j =(f(x) 1\ g(x»j (definition of 1\ inRB/B)
Incidentally, the situation here is clearly reminiscent of the situation =(f(x))j 1\ (g(x»j (lifting theorem)
involving nontransparent P2 s as they are applied to their object fils. Here =(f(Y))j 1\ (g(Y)j (f and g are transparent)
too we have a nontransparent intension (transparency being here defined = «fl\g) (y»j (definition of 1\ inRB/B)
according to the more general Definition 3 of Part ILl rather than Definition
2): in a world in which the happy individuals are precisely the successful This shows that f 1\ g is transparent. The proof that f V g is transparent is
individuals, it need not be the case that the individuals who seem happy completely parallel. Finally we have
are exactly the individuals who seem successful. The algebraic properties
of such intensions are unclear; they may depend on meaning postulates (f'(x))j = (x 1\ (f(x))')j (definition of' in RB/B)
which relate these intensions to the interpretations of complex expressions. =Xj 1\ «(f(X))')j (lifting theorem)
In the case of seem, we will return to this question briefly later, when = Xj 1\ «f(x)j)' (lifting theorem)
we consider the interpretation of sentences like John seems to be happy =Yj 1\ «(f(y))j)' (f is transparent)
and it seems that John is happy. =Yj 1\ «f(Y))')j (lifting theorem)
However, in the one case of the logical constant be, we can easily give an = (y 1\ (f(y))')j (lifting theorem)
interpretation. What we do is simply to take the definitions already worked =(f'(Y))j (definition of' in RB/B)
out in the extensional system and embed them into our intensional logic.
As before, be is viewed as a member of category <PI, PI) / <ii, AP). When If B is complete then R B / B is complete (Theorem 2 of Part IB). If the set
combined with an ii, be is interpreted as bel, where bel is that element of K ~ RB/B contains only transparent functions, proofs parallel to the ones
TJ;2 such that, for every i E J, (bel)j is the element of Tf,2 defined to be above show that AK and VK are transparent, and hence TB/B () RB/B is
complete.
the extension of be in our earlier discussion; recall that, by the General
PREDICATE MODIFIERS AND PREPOSITIONS 333 PREDICATE MODIFIERS AND PREPOSITIONS 335

This completes the proof of the theorem. Incidentally, the reader may proof for this here in the case of complementation; the proofs for the other
check that if B is atomic, so that RB/B is atomic, the atoms of RB/B are not operations are similar (and, if anything, slightly simpler), and are left to the
in general transparent .... reader.
Let f, p, and g have the meanings they have in Definition 1 above. We have
4. PREDICATE MODIFIERS AND PREPOSITIONS IN THE then:
INTENSIONAL SYSTEM
(4) f'(p(g)) =peg) 1\ ([(p(g)))' (definition of ' in PRA /A)
In extending the intensional system, we find it convenient at this stage to = peg) 1\ «f(p))' (g)) (extensions of g are individuals)
discuss the predicate modifiers (PMs) and prepositions together. = (p /\ (f(p))') (g) (extensions of g are individuals)
Syntactically, the category PM is defined to be <Pn ) j <Pn ), just as in the = (!'(p))(g) (definition of ' in PRA / A)
extensional system. Prepositions are then members of the category PMjN.
As in the extensional system, we are interested in distinguishing various Thus,!' is a consistent function. Note that since we require that p and f(p)
subcategories of these categories. However, we will not consider further the be transparent n-place predicate intensions, boolean operations involving
matter of argument-orientation and subject-orientation, which we feel we them can be performed on a world by world basis. Thus, if the extension of
treated in the earlier chapter as deeply as we wish to do so at this time. g in any world is an individual, it is permissible to unpack boolean combi-
Here we are interested in discussing the question of transparency as it applies nations of n-place predicate intensions pointwise, as we did in the second and
to these categories. third steps of (4) above.
But first, let us consider the intensional type for the category PM as a Let us turn now to the prepositions. Since TpM and TN are boolean
whole. By our general procedure, we want the type of PM to be some subset algebras and since prepositions are predicatives, we expect to define Tprep to
of the set of functions from the union of the sets TPn into itself. In fact, be the set of homomorphisms from TN into TpM. Generally speaking, this
based on the development found in Definitions 22 through 25 in Part lB, approach gives reasonable answers. For example, if the interpretation of with
we might wish to define TpM to be PRA /A, where A = {Tpw' n ;;;. I}; that preserves meets, then the phrases with the hammer and the chisel is logically
is, TpM would be the set of proper restricting functions from the union of equivalent to with the hammer and with the chisel, a reasonable thing to
the TPn into itself. However, given our discussion of the nature of TPn in suppose; surely if John sculpts this statue with the hammer and the chisel,
the intensional system, we are not in a position to do this, simply because then he sculpts it with the hammer and with the chisel, and conversely.
we are not assuming that the types TP n are boolean algebras. Similarly, if, in a particular world, the only tools are the hammer and the
The way around this problem which we shall adopt here is to restrict chisel, if John sculpts this statue with a tool, it must be that he sculpts it
the PMs so that they may only combine with transparent n-place predicates. with the hammer or with the chisel, and conversely.
In other words, the category PM is now defined to be <fn) j <fn). If we take However, defining Tprep as HTPM/TN leads to difficulties as soon as we
A to be the collection of sets TP n , we can apply the development of Part IE turn to the matter of transparency. By the definitions of ILl, in order for
t
to define TpM as being PRA /A, since each TP n is a boolean algebra. In terms a preposition intension to be transparent, it would be necessary for it to
t
of the ability of our system to represent English sentences, this will not ac- map every N intension into a transparent PM intension. Thus, a transparent
tually constitute a serious restriction. A sentence like John is looking for a preposition would be one which creates a transparent prepositional phrase.
unicorn with a magnifying glass will simply have only the translation in (1): Recalling our discussion in Part IB of extensional versus properly intensional
PMs, this would mean that locative prepositions, and, possibly, source prep-
(1) John (look-for (a unicorn» (with (a magnifying glass» ositions, would be the only transparent prepositions.
The problem with leaving things this way is that there are differences in
as opposed to the two translations of John sees a unicorn with a magnifying the logical behavior of other prepositions which seem to have to do with
glass in (2): transparency but which are not captured with this approach. To see this,
334 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 336 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

(2) (a) John (see (a unicorn)) (with (a magnifying-glass)) let us compare the prepositions with (in its instrumental sense) and about
(b) John (see (with (a magnifying-glass))) (a unicorn) (in the sense of 'concerning'). Surely, in a world in which the hammers and
the metal tools are precisely the same entities, the phrase with a hammer
Still, this difference in behavior could be claimed to lack any correlation should have the same extension as with a metal tool. However, in a world
with linguistic facts. If this is the case, we would have to regard the difference in which Mary is the queen, we certainly do not want the phrase about Mary
between (1) and (2) as a defect in our system, albeit a minor one. to be interpreted the same as about the queen; surely John could be talking
Since we are not considering argument or subject orientation here, we are about the queen without saying a word about Mary (he might not even know
faced with a small issue which we should resolve before proceeding. Namely, that Mary is the queen).
we certainly want the following two P 1 s to be logically equivalent: To see how this may be handled, let us examine more closely the trans-
parency of instrumental with. If w is the function which interprets with, we
(3) (a) (kiss Mary) skillfully have just seen that in a world j in which the N intensions f and g have the
(b) (kiss skillfully) Mary same extension, that is, in a world j such that fj = gj, the PMs w(!) and w(g)
are, in some sense, the same. But what does it mean for these to be the same
If skillfully is interpreted as an arbitrary proper restricting function, this in j? If these PMs had extensions inj, the meaning is simple: we would simply
need not be the case. This is very easily taken care of, however. We make be requiring that (w(f)j = (w(g»j; this is just our ordinary definition of
the following definition: transparency. But by the General Extensionality Theorem, this would require
that w(!) and w(g) be transparent PMs. However, we have already seen that
DEFINITION 1. The function f E PRUTp /UTp is consistent iff for each
with phrases modify n-place predicates in a properly intensional way. There-
tn tn
p E TPn and for each g E TN whose extension in any world is an individual fore, it cannot be the case that with phrases have extensions at all.
t
we have [(peg)) = (f(p)) (g). However, we can still give meaning to the idea that w (!) and w (g) are the
same in world j. Namely, if p is an arbitrary transparent n-place predicate
If [ interprets skillfully, p interprets kiss, and g interprets Mary, then the
intension, then the extensions «w(!) (p»j and «w(g» (p»j are well
equation in Definition 1 says precisely that (3a) and (3b) are logically equi-
defined. Clearly, to say that w(i) and w(g) are the same in world j means
valent. Note, incidentally, that, in the left hand side of this equation, fis
(at least) that these two extensions are equal. As an example: in a world in
applied to an element of TPn _ l' whereas on the right hand side, it is applied
t which the hammers and the metal tools are precisely the same entities, while
to an element of TPn' The equation thus constrains the behavior of [ as it the phrases with a hammer and with a metal tool would not themselves have
t
applies to predicates of different valences, which is just what we want. extensions, PI s like fix the door with a hammer and fix the door with a metal
Incidentally, the reader may easily check that argument-oriented and subject- tool would necessarily have the same extension.
oriented PMs (in the sense of Part IB) are necessarily consistent. Formally, we can make the following definition:
Letting A be a set of total boolean algebras, we use the notation CPRAIA
to represent the set of all consistent proper restricting functions from the DEFINITION 3. Let X and Y be sets of extensional intensions, and let Z
union of the algebras in A into itself. It now seems reasonable to define. be a subset of Fy /y. A function f from X into Z is modifyingly transparent
(or m-transparent) iff, whenever for some XI, X2 EX andj EJwe have Xlj =
DEFINITION 2. TpM =CPRAIA, where A is the set of algebras Tp n .
t
X2j' then for each y E Y it is the case that «(f(XI» (Y»j = «f(X2» (Y»j.

It is not immediately obvious that TpM defined this way is itself a boolean Using this definition, we can describe the intensional interpretation of dif-
algebra. However, this is indeed the case. To show that it is, we need only ferent classes of prepositions as follows. All prepositions take their inter-
show that the boolean operations already defined in PRAIA yield consistent pretations in the set HTPM/Tfl" Some prepositions, such as the locatives
functions when they are applied to consistent functions. We indicate the like in, are subcategorized as transparent; their interpretations are required
PREDICA TE MODIFIERS AND PREPOSITIONS 337 PREDICA TE MODIFIERS AND PREPOSITIONS 339

to be transparent (in the usual sense). Another group of prepositions (includ- Assuming that that saw is an individual, we can suppose that the verbal
ing instrumental with) are subcategorized as being m-transparent; these are extensor analysis predicts that work with that saw entails work. Thus, (8)
required to take m-transparent intensions as their interpretations. Finally, is predicted to entail work by both analyses, and hence we cannot as yet
prepositions like about would carry neither sub categorization feature, their distinguish between them.
interpretations would be unconstrained, allowing Pi s like talk about Mary To avoid this problem, we clearly have to get rid of the noncomplemented
and talk about the queen to have different extensions even in a world in part of the object of the preposition in (8). If we do this, the result is not
which Mary and the queen have the same extension. acceptable English:
It may be objected that the definition of m-transparency above is inelegant,
in that reference must be made to the nature of the elements of the set Z, (10) work with not this hammer
rather than merely to abstract properties of that set. In the case of prep-
ositions, we are making crucial use of the fact that when a preposition is That is, we cannot say *John works with not this hammer. In the case of
combined with an N, the resulting expression is an n-place predicate modifier. (10), our two analyses make different predictions; the approach here leads
This can be avoided, but other problems arise. to the claim that (10) entails work, while the verbal extensor approach does
One way of avoiding this difficulty is to regard prepositions not as ex- not lead to that claim. However, since (10) is not an acceptable English PI,
pressions which combine with Ns to create PMs, but rather as expressions we have no intuitions concerning whether or not it ought to entail work.
which combine with n-place predicates to create n-place predicates of valence Normally, it is acceptable in English to negate an N without conjoining
one higher (that is, a preposition would combine with an n-place predicate it to a non-negated N, if the negated N itself contains a quantifier like every
to create an n + I-place predicate). This was essentially the approach taken in or a. However, although not as bad as (10), such combinations sound suffi-
Keenan and Faltz (1978), where prepositions were called 'verbal extensors'. ciently odd as objects of a preposition, that we do not have intuitions as to
Some discussion was provided (pp. 181-191) to convince the reader that whether the PIS:
such an approach was not as bad linguistically as it might seem if only ordi-
nary notions of English phrase structure are considered. In addition to that (11) work with not every hammer
discussion, the reader may check that the kind of inelegance illustrated by (12) work with not a hammer
Definition 3 does not arise if the verbal extensor approach is taken. Neverthe-
less, for English at least, the phrase structure evidence does seem to point entail work or not. If we replace not a hammer with no hammer in (12),
strongly to a notion of prepositional phrase. Thus, the approach outlined we obtain:
here yields a better match between the syntactic structure of our logical
language and the syntactic structure of real English. (13) work with no hammer
As a further point of comparison between the two approaches, we might
ask whether interpreting a preposition as a homomorphism from TN into which seems perfectly acceptable. However, it is still unclear whether John
TpM is algebraically equivalent to the verbal extensor approach. Specifically, works with no hammer entails John works or not. Here, our intuition is
let us attempt to make the following definition: slightly in favor of this entailment. To the extent that this is a valid intuition,
this constitutes slight evidence in favor of the approach taken here over the
(5) Given any f E HTpM/TN' f* is defined as that function from verbal extensor approach.
TP n into TP n + 1 such that, for any p E Tpn and any g E TN, (We note in passing that the fact that, say, John works without a hammer
(f*(p)) (g) =(f(g)) (p). clearly entails that John works does not decide unequivocally in favor of the
approach here. The reason is simply that the relationship between the inter-
It is clear that the equation in (5) definesf*(p) as a function from TN into pretation of without and the interpretation of with, mediated by means of
TP n . However, before we can claim thatf*(p) is really a member of TPn +l' a meaning postulate, say, will not be the same with the two approaches.
338 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 340 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

it is necessary to show that it is a homomorphism. Since f is assumed to be In the verbal extensor approach, the interpretation of without would be
a homomorphism, and since the argument of f is the same as the argument defined not so that without N and with not N are equivalent, but rather so
of f*(p), we might guess that this is indeed the case. We leave it to the reader that without is restricting (as required on that approach; see Keenan and
to show that with f* defined as in (5), f*(p) does preserve meets and joins. Faltz, 1978, p. 223) as well as entailing with - not. In the approach here,
In the case of complements, however, we have the following: we could simply require that without N be equivalent to with not N (which
is equivalent to not (with N), since with is interpreted as a homomorphism.»
(6) (f*(p))(g') = (f(g'))(p) (definition (5)) Summarizing, we can say that the following definition for the type for
= (f(g))' (p) (fis a homomorphism) prepositions is acceptable, providing we can live with a sub categorization
= P fI [(f(g))(p)]' (defmition of' in TpM) feature which is associated with the m-transparency condition given in
=P fI [(f*(p)) (g)]' (definition (5)) Definition 3:

Now, if f*(p) preserved complements, then instead of the result in (6) we


would have:
Before leaving the matter of PMs and prepositions, let us say a brief word
about the relationship between adjectives and adverbs in ly.
For many adjectives in English, there exists an abverb formed by suffixing
Thus, the function f* defined in (5) does not correspond to a verbal extensor -ly whose meaning is related to the meaning of the corresponding adjective
intension, since such an object would be defined as taking its values in TPn+l . in a regular way. The logical content of this relationship can be illustrated
In other words, the approach outlined here is not equivalent, algebraically, by the judgment that (14) is true iff (15) is true:
to the verbal extensor approach.
This being the case, it ought to be possible to decide between the two (14) John is a skillful worker.
approaches by examining data from real English. Since the distinction shows (15) John works skillfully.
up in the case of taking a complement of the fii argument which corresponds
to the object of the preposition, we are led to an example such as the PI: To represent such a fact in our system, we can proceed as follows.
First, let us assume that there is an expression ly of category PM/ AP.
r
(8) work with that saw but not this hammer. Then, ly will combine with restricting adjective phrases to form predicate
modifiers. Of course, this will lead to overgeneration; but that seems to be
The difference between (5) and (7) is that (5) predicts that when a preposi- a relatively harmless defect at this stage, which, hopefully, could be cleared
tion is combined with a complemented fii, it remains the case that the PI up in subsequent investigation.
which the resulting prepositional phrase is modifying must still be entailed; Next, we will want to interpret ly as a logical constant. To see what the
this is not the case with the analysis in (7). Now, in the case of (8), it is interpretation of ly should be, we must first look at the relationship between
certainly true that if John works with that saw but not this hammer, we can the phrases which an AP and its corresponding PM modify.
conclude that John works. However, this does not mean that (5) is definitely In the above example, the ly adverb modifies the PI work, while the
the correct analysis rather than (7). The problem is that the object of the adjective from which it is formed modifies worker, an N related morpho-
preposition in (5) is a conjunction of a complemented fii and one which is logically and logically to work. Morphologically, worker is formed by com-
not complemented. Thus, on the verbal extensor analysis, (8) should be bining the PI work with the suffix -er; and logically, in any particular world,
equivalent to (9): work is true of an individual just in case the property which interprets worker
is a member of that individual.
(9) work with that saw but not work with this hammer. The relationship between work and worker is easy to handle in our system.
PREDICATE MODIFIERS AND PREPOSITIONS 341 VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERA TORS 343

If we wish to include expressions like worker in our logical language, we DEFINITION 3. TN = TN.
var
need only posit an expression er of category N/~I (which, like ly, will over-
generate, but harmlessly). Whether or not we do this, we can still elucidate Let us call Definition 3 the loose definition of variable interpretation. We
the relationship between PIS like work and Ns like worker, which is all note that if this definition is adopted, then variable intensions are still all
we have to do in order to be able to handle the interpretation of ly. The extensional, but the extension of a variable intension in a particular world
key is Theorem 20 of Part lA, which shows that there exists a canonical need not be an individual, and hence this definition does not reduce to the
isomorphism from T~l onto TJv. Let us call this isomorphism l{!e. situation we had previously with our extensional system. In order to evaluate
t the relative merits of the strict and loose definitions of variable interpreta-
Now, since TPI (= TPle) and TN (= TNe) are total, the isomorphism l{!e
t tion, we need to consider the matter of the intensional interpretation of
can be 'lifted' to an isomorphism l{! from TP 1 onto TN. We leave to the reader
variable binding operators, to which we now turn.
the easy demonstration that the equation t
We take over the syntax and general structure of models from the exten-
sional system unchanged. We have three variable binding operators (VBOs),
namely, A, such that , and self. Recall that we use V to denote the set of
defines such an isomorphism (where P is an arbitrary element of Tp,1 and vocabulary items and V+ to denote the set V - {and, or, not, 11., such that,
j is an arbitrary world). Clearly, if p is the intension of work, then l{!(p) is self}. V+ is the domain for lexical assignment functions M which define
the intension of worker. models. That is, a model is now a quadruple (P, 2, J, M), where M is a func-
We can now define the interpretation of the logical constant ly as follows: tion whose domain is V+ and for which, given any x of category C, M(x) is
an element of Te, here the intensional type, of course. As before, M(x) is
DEFINITION 5. In. any interpretation, ly is interpreted as the function ly: an arbitrary element of Te except in the case that x is a logical constant, in
TpM ~ TAP defined by (ly(h)) (P) = l{)-I(h(l{)(P))), where h E TpM and which case M(x) is defined a priori for all models.
t Given the model (P, 2, J, M), we want to extend M uniquely to a function
p E TPI are arbitrary.
t m whose domain is the set of all expressions of the language such that if
(In Definition 5, l{!-1 refers to the inverse isomorphism of l{); that is, l{)-1 e E v+ then m(e) =M(e). If e is a boolean combination of expressions or else
maps TN isomorphically onto TP,l .) Thus, what ly (h) does to a PI intension a function-argument combination of expressions, then m( e) is defined the
p corresponds algebraically with what h does to the corresponding N inten- usual way. Our task here is to define m ( e) in the case that e is a complex
sion l{!(p). expression formed with the aid of a VBO. As before, the functions m andM
Unfortunately, Definition 5 does not settle the matter. While it provides are in one-to-one correspondence. We take over the definitions of x-variance
an acceptable interpretation for ly in the case that the adverb it forms com- (for a given x E R) unchanged (see Part IB, Definitions 50 and 51). We begin
var
bines with a PI, there remains the question of how to interpret such adverbs our detailed discussion of the VBOs with the 11..
when they combine with an n-place predicate, for arbitrary n. However, it As far as the syntax of II. is concerned, we make one change in the defini-
is not difficult to see how the approach given above for PI modification tion given earlier for our extensional system. If x E R , then, in order for (x,
var
can be generalized. The steps are as follows. First, show that there exists A, e) to be a well formed expression, we require that e be not only a member
a canonical isomorphism l{)h from T~n onto TJv n _ 1 (where N n is the category of a boolean category B, but in addition, e must be extensional (that is, the
of n-place common nouns; the category N = No is regarded as the first mem- intensions which could legitimately interpret e must be extensional). In
ber of a predicative hierarchy; see Chapter IB.3). Next, lift this isomorphism practice, this will be fulfilled by e being either a member of a category like
to an isomorphism l{!n from TPn onto TN n-1. And finally, define ly to be Po, all of whose possible intensions are extensional, or else a transparent
t
interpreted as ly, where, for each hE TpM and each p E TPn, (ly(h)) (P) = expression, that is, an expression which must be interpreted by a.transparent
l{)1i 1 (h(l{!n(P))). t (hence extensional) intension. As earlier, (x, 11., e) will be a member of cate-
gory BIN; in fact, it will be a transparent member of this category.
342 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 344 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

5. VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS The intensional semantics of expressions of the form (x, A, e) must now
IN THE INTENSIONAL SYSTEM be defined. To do so, we find it convenient to make the following definition:

As in the extensional system, we assume that variables are expressions of DEFINITION 4. Let a E P be an atom, and let j E J be a world. Then, Daj =
category C, where C is any category and var is a sub categorization feature. {g E TN: gj = Ia }.
var var
We continue to restrict our attention to those variables which are members
In the above definition, Ia refers to the individual (in P) which contains the
of the category No = N , assuming as before that there are variables Xl,
var var atom a. We see that Daj is a set of variable intensions; that is, Daj ~ TN ~ TN.
X2, ... of this category. Again, for convenience, specific such variables may var
In fact, Daj is exactly the set of those variable intensions which have as their
be denoted X, y, etc. extension in the world j the individual associated with atom a.
Our first task is to define the intensional type for these variables. Recallillg
We now define the intensional interpretation of expressions like (x, A, e)
that in the extensional system we have
as follows:
(1) Tfi.=Ip= Tfi. DEFINITION 5. Let e be an expression of the boolean extensional category
N
var
N
proper
B and let x EN. Then the interpretation m(x, A, e) of (x, A, e) in the model
var
the following two definitions suggest themselves: (P, 2, J, M> is the transparent function from TN into TB defined by the fact
DEFINITION 1. TN = TN
that, for each j E J, (m(x, A, e))j is the homomorphism from TJr
into T;
var proper such that, for each atom a E P, (m(x, A, e))j (Ia) = V (mg(e))," Here,
gEDa'
DEFINITION 2. TN =Flp/J Ia denotes the individual containing the atom a, and mg den6tes the x-variant
var of m such that mg(x) = g.
Let us call Definition 1 the intensional individual definition of variable (As in the corresponding extensional definition, there is here, strictly speak-
interpretation, and Definition 2 the strict definition of variable interpretation ing, a circularity which can be eliminated by inductively defining extensions
(this latter term will become clear in a moment). Note that with either of of the function M on expressions of increasing length; we leave it to the
these definitions, a variable illtension is extensional, and its extension in any reader to construct the routine, but rather tedious, correct definition.)
world is an individual, so that, in either case, the situation we had earlier with In this definition, we are of course appealing to the General Extensionality
our extensional definition is recovered if we are working inside one particular Theorem when we define a transparent function from TN into TB by giving
world. its extensions, and to the Justification Theorem when we define a homomor-
In comparing these two definitions, it seems reasonable to reject the phism from TN into T~ by giving its values on the individuals.
intensional individual definition. The reason is this. Although we are not We can see that if the expression e is such that its interpretation depends
specifying ill this work what precisely the ultimate functioning of the distinc- transparently on the interpretation of x, then the definition above reduces
tion between worlds is to be, we surely expect that the extension of a variable to the extensional definition given earlier on a world by world basis. The
should be allowed to vary from one world to the next. Certainly this is the reason is that the union in the definition above is taken over a set of variable
case if distinct worlds are thought of as representing distinct contexts, a intensions whose extensions in world j are all the same. To say that the inter-
common notion often applied to the idea of distinct worlds. pretation of e depends transparently on the interpretation of x just means
This leave us with the strict definition of variable interpretation, appar- that (mg(x))j would be the .same extension for all of the g's. Thus, in this
ently settling the issue. However, ill integrating the intensional illterpretation case, we have a union of identical elements, which is just equal to that ele-
of variables with the intensional interpretation of variable billding operators, ment. Finally, since mg(x) = g, we have (mg(x))j = gj = la, so that the
we will see that there is some evidence in favor of a third definition of the extension (mg(e))j can be identified with the extensional x-variant interpre-
type for variables, namely: tation of e which interprets x as Ia.
V ARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERA TORS 345 VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERA TORS 347

Definition 5 above makes use of the set Daj. Now, the definition of Daj development in (8) is as in the extensional system. Note that, say, the truth of
(Definition 4) is itself relative to Til; that is, depending on whether we choose (7) in world j requires that there exist at least one individual which contains
vax
the strict or the loose definition of variable interpretation (or some other the unicorn property in j, by the last lineof (8). Again, if Mary (interpreted as
definition), we will end up with different definitions for the intensional inter- Imary) is a unicorn, and if John (kiss Mary) is true in j (so that (kj{Imary»
pretation of A. It will be useful to examine here what these interpretations (Ijohn) = 1), then, by the last line in (8) it must be the case that John kisses
involve in a typical case. By what we have said above, if the interpretation of a unicorn in worldj. In other words, the argument:
e depends transparently on the interpretation of x, the interpretation of A
(9) John (kiss Mary»
reduces to what we had earlier in the extensional system no matter what the
Mary (be (a unicorn»
definition of Til is, since, in either case, Daj is a set of f.l intensions whose
vax
extensions in world j are in individual. Thus, to determine the effect of the :. John (kiss (a unicorn»
definition of Til, it will be necessary to examine a case in which e does not
vax is valid.
depend transparently on x. Such a case would be the situation in which the
variable appears as the object of a properly intensional transitive verb. Returning to (5), we see that the development shown in (8) cannot be
Specifically, let us examine the interpretation of carried out here, since f is not (necessarily) transparent, as we have said.
In particular, the intension of the N a unicorn is trapped inside the intension
(2) (a unicorn) (x A (John (look-for x))) of the verb phrase. An immediate consequence of this is that, whereas in
order for (7) to be true in world j it is necessary that at least one individual
which would be a possible translation into our logical language of the English have the property Uj (that is, at least one unicorn has to exist in world j),
sentence: (4) could be true in world j even though no individual has property U j, that
is, even though there are no unicorns in world j. This is the intuitively desired
(3) John is looking for a unicorn.
result.
First of all, it follows from Definition 5 that no matter how the intensional To pursue the matter a little further, the Po John (look-for (Mary» would
interpretation of variables is defined, the intension of the formula in (2) have as its extension in world j
depends transparently on the intension of the expression a unicorn. In
particular, if (2) is true in a certain world, then there must exist at least
one unicorn in that world. In short, it will be the case that (2) represents where h is the intension of Mary. Set hj = I mary , and suppose that Imary
the de re reading of (3). contains property Uj (that is, Mary is in fact a unicorn in world j). Because
Before proceeding with (2), let us stop a moment and see what happens a(u) in (5) and h in (10) are buried inside the P j intension, there is no way
if (3) is interpreted in the more straightforward way shown in (4): to use the fact that Imary contains Uj in order to relate the formulas John
(look-for (a unicorn» and John (look-for (Mary» logically. This strongly
(4) John (look-for (a unicorn)) suggests that the argument in (11) is invalid:
If the intensions of John, unicorn, and look-for are g, u, and f respectively, (11) John (look-for (Mary»
then the intension of the Po in (4) is (f(a(u))) (g), by our general functional Mary (be (a unicorn»
application procedure. (Recall that a is defined a priori as the intension of
a in any model; since a is a logical constant; see II.2.) If j E J is the index :. John (look-for (a unicorn»
of some world, then the truth value of (4) in world j is given by:
To show that the argument is indeed invalid, we need only note that since f
(5) «(f(a(u))) (g))j = (f(a(u)))j (gj) =(f(a(u)))j (Ijohn) (the intension of look-for) is an arbitrary member of TP2' it can be chosen
346 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 348 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

(where Ijohn is the individual which is the extension of g in any world). The such that f(a(u» and f(h) are different members of Tp 1. But then, for some
equation in (5) is valid because of the General Extensionality Theorem. world j, (f(a(u)))j and (f(h»j are distinct, whence t (by the Justification
Recall also that whenever a Pn intension is applied to an N intension, the Theorem) they must differ for some individual.
resulting Pn -1 intension is transparent. Thus, the PI look-for (a unicorn) in Note that, intuitively, we want the argument in (11) to be invalid if
(4) is transparent, so that the General Extensionality Theorem can indeed look-for is given the de dictu interpretation: John may be indeed looking for
be applied. a being named Mary without knowing that Mary is a unicorn. Even if Mary
However, in the case of (5), we can go no further. In particular, the is a unicorn, we would not want to conclude that John is looking for a
General Extensionality Theorem cannot be applied to unpack (f(a(u»)j, unicorn if the property of being a unicorn is not the property which defines
since f is not (necessarily) transparent. This should be compared to the how John's search is satisfied.
situation that arises when we do have a transparent transitive verb, as in the Suppose, however, that we interpret look for in the de re manner, in the
case of the sentence following argument:

(6) John is kissing a unicorn. (12) John is looking for Mary


Mary is a unicorn
which may be translated into our logical language as
:. John is looking for a unicorn.
(7) John (kiss (a unicorn»
The de re interpretation arises if the phrases Mary and a unicorn are the
If the intension of kiss is k, then the intension of formula (7) is (k(a(u») (g). speaker's descriptions (rather than John's descriptions) of the object of
In worldj, we have in this case: John's search. In this case, we would want (12) to be valid. We have already
seen that the argument in (11) is invalid; we cannot, therefore, use the
(8) ((k(a(u») (g»j =(k(a(u»)j (gj) (General Extensionality Pos in (11) to translate the English sentences in (12) (if these are to be
Theorem) interpreted de re). However, if we translate the sentences of (12) by means
=(k(a(u»)j (!john) (!john is the extension of Pos such as the one in (2), then the resulting arument is valid. Specifically,
of g in any world)
=(kj(a(u»j) (Ijohn) (General Extensionality (13) (Mary (x A (John (look-for x))
Theorem) Mary (be (a unicorn»)
=(kj(a e (Uj ») (Ijohn) (General Extensionality
Theorem) :. (a unicorn) (x A (John (look-for x)))
=(kj(u.~ I I) (Ijohn) (Definition of ae)
is valid. In fact, the reader may easily show that (13) is valid no matter which
J
definition we use for TN. Here, let us look carefully at the interpretation of
= (u. ~ I kj (I) (Ijohn) (kj is a homomorphism) var
J (13) as provided by Definition 5.
=u . ~ I (kj(I) (Ijohn) (Definition of V in T: 1 ) First, assume again that John and look-for are interpreted by the inten-
J sions g and f respectively. Let j be a world and let fa be an arbitrary individual
(a EP an atom). By Definition 5,
The third equality in (8) is a valid step since k is a transparent P 2 intension
(Since kiss is subcategorized as being transparent). The fourth equality follows (14) (m(x A (John (look-for x»»j (fa) = V (mh (John (look-
from the (definitional) transparency of a (see 11.2); the remainder of the h EDaj for»)j
VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS 349 VARIABLES AND VARIABLE BINDING OPERATORS 351

That is, John looks for the individual fa in a de re sense if and only if there quantifier over another. However, when both the subject and the object of
is a variable intension h whose extension in j is fa such that, loosely speaking, look for are quantified, the situation is a little different.
John looks for 'h', in the de dietu sense, is true in j. Consider the English sentence:
Let us consider this a bit more carefully. If the individual fa happens to
(23) Every man is looking for a woman.
be named Mary, under what conditions might we want to say that
There are two sources of logical ambiguity in this sentence. On the one hand,
(15) John is looking for Mary. there is the matter of quantifier scope: either every has wide scope or else
a does. On the other hand, there is the de dietulde re ambiguity associated
is true, with the de re reading? Suppose, for example, that in world j, Mary with the verb look for. We can therefore imagine that (23) might be capable
is the queen, and suppose that John is looking for the queen (de dietu). of four logical readings. In fact, however, there seem to be only three, the
Surely, we would want to conclude that (15) holds in the de re sense. forbidden combination being the case where a has wide scope together with
However, in order for this to follow from our analysis, there would have the de dietu reading. The fact that this reading is forbidden follows directly
to be some variable intension h which could equally well interpret the R from the syntax and semantics of Ain our system. On the one hand, in order
the queen. Now, while the extension of the queen in some worlds would for a woman to have wide scope over every man in (23), it is necessary to
surely be an individual, we must allow for the possibility of a world in which use A in order to extract a woman from inside the PI' On the other hand, a
there is no queen. In such a world, the extension of the queen would be the A always creates a transparent expression. Thus, if a woman has wide scope
zero element of TN- This shows that, all other things being equal, variable in (23), it is necessarily the case that the interpretation of (23) as a whole
intensions should not be restricted to having individuals as their only possible be transparent in the interpretation of a woman. But this just means that
extensions. the de re reading results. The three actually occurring readings of sentence
Should variable intensions be allowed to range over all of T]1j? The evidence (23) are represented in our language as follows:
is a little unclear. Suppose, for example, that John is looking (de dietu) for a
unicorn, and that in world j there is exactly one unicorn and that unicorn's (24) (every man) (look-for (a woman)) (de dietu, every
name is Mary. Can we conclude that John is looking (de re) for Mary? The has wide scope)
issue does not seem as clear cut as the case in which John is looking (de dietu) (25) (every man) ((a woman) (x A(look-for x))) (de re, every has
for the queen. Here, we tentatively take the position that this conclusion can wide scope)
be validly drawn. On the basis of such examples, we propose that the loose (26) (a woman) (x A((every man) (look-for x))) (de re, a has wide
interpretation of variables is the correct definition for TN. We emphasize scope)
var
that this is a tentative proposal which should be carefully reexamined. With this, we complete what we shall say here concerning the intensional
We remind the reader that the validity of the argument in (13) above is interpretation of A and of variables. Let us briefly consider the matter of the
independent of our choice for the interpretation of variables. The reader intensional interpretation of self and of suehthat.
may also check that the following arguments are valid, independently of In order to be able to interpret self intensionally, we must restrict its
how we choose to interpret variables: syntax slightly, in the same way we did in the case of A. Specifically, if B
is any boolean category and e is any extensional expression of category BIN,
(16) John is looking for Mary (de dietu) then (x, self, e) is a well formed expression. As in the case of the extensional
:. John is looking for Mary (de re) self, we interpret self intensionally in such a way that (x, self, e) and (x, A,
(17) John is looking for Mary (e, x)) are logically equivalent. Specifically:
(de dietu)
Mary is a unicorn
DEFINITION 6. Let e be an extensional expression of category BIN, where
:. John is looking for a unicorn (de re) EN.
B is a boolean category, and let x
var
Then the interpretation m (x, self, e)
350 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 352 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

Similarly, the following arguments are invalid, independently of how we of (x, self, e) in the model (P, 2, J, M) is the transparent function from TN
choose to interpret variables: into Tn defined by the fact that, for eachj EJ, (m(x, self, e»j is the homo-
morphism from Tit into T; such that, for each atom a E P,we have (m(x,
(18) John is looking for a unicorn (de dietu) self, e»j (fa) =Vg E Daj (mg(e»j (fa)·
Here, fa denotes the individual containing the atom a, and mg denotes
:. John is looking for a unicorn (de re)
the x-variant of m such that mg(x) =g.
(cf. (16), which is valid!) We will not discuss self any further here.
Finally, let us turn to the VBO such that. We do not have to change any-
(19) John is looking for a unicorn (dere)
thing concerning the syntax of this element in order to be able to interpret
:. John is looking for a unicorn (de dietu) it intensionally. The defmition of that interpretation can be given as follows:
(20) John is looking for Mary (de re)
DEFINITION 7. Let e be an expression of category Po and letx EN. Then
var
:. John is looking for Mary (de dietu) the interpretation m(x, suchthat, e) of (x, such that, e) in the model (P, 2,
J, M) is the element of TA.P such that, for eachj EJ, (m(x, suchthat, e»j
e I
These results agree completely with our intuitions. Note that the validity is the element of TAP such that, for each atom a E P, (m (x, such that, e»j
of (16) stems from the fact that the extension of a proper noun is an fa i
(1) E fa iff Vg E Daj (mg(e))j = I. Again, fa is the individual containing the
(in fact, the same fa) in any world. That is, the semantics we have proposed
atom a, and mg is the x-variant of m such that mg(x) =g.
does not allow for the possibility that Mary does not exist in a world. If the
semantics were changed to allow for this possibility (certainly, a conceivable That an element of TAP is actually defined here follows from the Intersect-
i
idea), then (16) would no longer be valid. ingness Inheritance Theorem. The discussion of the definition of the exten-
In the examples we have examined so far, A was used to bind a variable in sional interpretation of such that (Definition 54 of Part IB) should be reviewed
a Po. Definition 5 is more general, however; we have defined an interpretation for the justification that (m(x, suchthat, e»j is properly defined as an
for expressions in which A binds a variable in any boolean extensional expres- element of TAp.
sion. Therefore, it might be thought that an additional reading could be As in the ~ase of A and self, expressions created with such that are neces-
assigned to a sentence like 'John is looking for Mary' by combining A with sarily transparent in their N arguments. In particular, if we relativize out of
the PI look-for x rather than with the Po John (look-for x). This is actually a nontransparent context (such as the object of a non·transparent P 2 like
not the case; the reader should verify the following logical equivalence: look for), the de re reading is automatically produced. Thus, for example,
the de re reading of look for is created in the interpretation of the relative
(21) (Mary (x A (John (look-for x))) =>
clause in (27):
(John) «Mary) (x A (look-for x)))
(27) (a (unicorn (x suchthat (John (look-for x»))) (kiss Mary).
Similarly, no new additional reading is assigned to 'John is looking for a
unicorn', because of the following equivalence: If (27) is the translation into our logical language of the English sentence:

(22) (a unicorn) (x A (John (look-for x))) => (28) A unicorn which John is looking for is kissing Mary.
(John) «a unicorn) (x A (look-for x)))
then this is reasonable: as far as we can tell, only a de re reading can be given
This is to be expected, since the difference between the left and the right to look for in (28). However, if we change the determiner used with unicorn,
sides of the equivalences in (21) and in (22) do not involve crossing one it appears that a de dictu reading becomes possible:
SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 353 SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 355

(29) Every unicorn which John is looking for is kissing Mary. NP (our R). Thus, ignoring many details, a reasonably current structural
(30) The unicorn which John is looking for is kissing Mary. description of(lb) above would be:

Suppose for example that in a certain world it is true that John is looking (3)
(de dictu) for a unicorn which is kissing Mary. It seems that there is a reading
of (30) according to which that sentence is true even if there is no such
unicorn. The de dictu possibility is even clearer in the case of sentences
with a modal, such as;

(31) The unicorn which John is looking for must have a golden horn.

In fact, not only is the de dictu reading possible, but the interpretation everyone believed that the Earth was flat
of look for is linked to the interpretation of must; roughly, the necessity
expressed by must is understood as a requirement to be met by any world It is this latter approach which we shall adopt here. Since it is more compli-
in which John's search is satisfied. At the present time, we are not proposing cated than the standard philosophical approach, we must justify in basically
any way of handling this sort of thing. A more structured conception of the semantic terms why we want to make a category distinction between Sand
notion of world is undoubtedly needed. 8. Such justification, while somewhat subtle, is not hard to come by.
Consider first what sorts of expressions we want to be members of the
category 8. Obviously, we want expressions of the form that+S. But we
6. SENTENTIAL PREDICATES IN THE INTENSIONAL SYSTEM
want much else besides. In particular, given the strongly boolean nature of
The by now classical non-extensional treatments of natural language semantics natural language so far discussed, we would expect boolean combinations in
were initially proposed to handle 'sentence taking' predicates like is necessary, and, or, and not to be included in this category. This is correct, as illustrated
is possible, etc. on the one hand, and predicates expressing propositional in (4) below:
attitudes like believe, think, etc. on the other. Below we extend our inten-
sional logic to include such predicates. The initial treatment we provide is (4) (a) John believes (both) that Fred left and that Mary stayed.
more adequate than 'standard' treatments, e.g. Montague (1974), in several (b) John believes (either) that Fred left or that Mary stayed.
respects. In particular, our boolean approach to semantics generalizes nicely (c) John believes that Fred left but not that Mary stayed.
to such predicates and allows us to represent certain ambiguities not captured (d) John believes neither that Fred left nor that Mary stayed.
on other approaches. It also allows us to capture generalizations concerning
similarities between sentence taking predicates and more 'ordinary' fit taking Thus the direct object of believe in (4a) is a conjunction of two 8's, both
ones. More specifically, we show that there is a semantic unity to the notion of the form that+S. In (4b) it is a disjunction, etc.
argument category which includes ordinary Ns, sentential complements, Thus, the syntax of our extended intensional logic treats the comple-
and certain sorts of infinitival complements. mentizer that as having the category 81S, and treats both Sand 8 as boolean;
On the other hand, our initial treatment of sentence taking predicates in each of those categories boolean combinations may be formed to yield
does preserve one basic inadequacy of 'standard' treatments - one for which complex expressions in those categories. We therefore structurally distinguish
different solutions are proposed in Thomason (1980) and Ben-Chorin (1982). between the result of conjoining two 8's, each of the form that+S, to form
We indicate how our approach may be generalized along the lines in Ben· a complex 8, and the result of conjoining two S's to form a complex Sand
Chorin (op. cit.) without disturbing the advantages we have established combining the result with that to fom an 8. The difference is illustrated in
for it. (5) below:
354 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 356 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

Syntax of Sentence Taking Predicates (5) (a) S

Within the tradition of philosophical logics (specifically, modal logic) the


-~~-
N SIN

(SIN)/S/ ~ S
syntactic arguments of predicates like is necessary have been treated as
ordinary sentences (for which we use the symbol S rather than the typo-
graphically more cumbersome Po in this section). In categorial notation,
then, is necessary would be of category SjS. By extension, believe would be
S/S/ ~
of category (SjfJ)/S; it would combine with an S to yield an ordinary one
place predicate, one taking an ordinary R argument to form an S. Similarly,
S/~S
predicates like surprise, as it occurs in that Fred left surprised John, would ~ ~
be of category (SjS)/R, and one like mean, imply, entail, etc. which take two John believe that Fred left or Mary left
sentential arguments would be of category (SjS)/S.
'John believes that (either) Fred left or Mary left'
By contrast, early work in generative grammar treated the direct objects
of verbs like kiss and believe in (1) as having the same category, NP.
(b)
(l) (a) Mary kissed John
(b) Everyone believed (that) the Earth was flat
N~S~/N
(S/fi)/S/ ~S
S/~S
The motivation for this treatment was strictly syntactic, not semantic as in

'"
the case of the philosophical approach. For example, by treating the objects
of kiss and believe above as having the same category, NP, it was possible to /~ /
formulate the Passive transformation in a reasonably general way: it moved SIS S SIS '" S
NPs around in sentences, and since the objects of kiss and believe were both
NPs the same rule derived (2) from (roughly) their corresponding sources
John believe that
16 Fred left or that
I A Mary left
in (l).
'John believes (either) that Fred left or that Mary left'
(2) (a) John was kissed by Mary
(b) That the Earth was flat was believed by everyone Crucially, the syntactic distinction forced in (5a, b) corresponds to a semantic
distinction: (5a) says that John believes that a certain disjunction holds;
However, on both syntactic and semantic grounds this early linguistic he may have no opinion as to which disjunct it is (as might naturally be the
approach seemed ill advised. Syntactically, for example, the grammar gen- case if the second disjunct were the negation of the first). In (5b), however,
erated such apparent non-sentences as Mary kissed that the Earth was we assert that John does believe one of the disjuncts though we do not
flat. More important for our purposes, such strings seem to be semantic commit ourselves as to which. (5b) is a paraphrase of
nonsense, instantiating some sort of category mistake. We surely do not
want expressions like John and (that) the Earth was flat to be able to denote (6) John believes that Fred left or John believes that Mary left
the same sort of objects. Semantically, then, the philosophical approach
seems preferable. Clearly (5a) can be true in circumstances in which (Sb) is false, whence the
More recent linguistic approaches, however, assign the sentential objects two are not paraphrases.
of believe, etc. to a new category, S, which is distinct both from S and from Thus, we have motivated making a distinction between the categories
SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 3S7 SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 359

Sand S, since by so doing we can provide distinct representations for the Recall that the type for S (= Po) is already given as the set of functions
English sentences in (Sa) and (Sb) and thus can assign them different truth from J, the set of possible worlds of the model, into 2, the set of truth
conditions, ones which for example guarantee that (Sb) entails (6) but that values. We shall refer to this set as Prop, and refer to its elements by lower
(Sa) does not. (In the next section we provide a semantics for Sand S-taking case letters p, q, r, and s. Prop is, recall, a complete and atomic boolean
predicates which does just that.) By contrast, the philosophical approach algebra isomorphic to J*, the power set of J. The boolean operations on
we outlined above does not make a distinction between Sand S and thus Prop are defined pointwise on J, e.g. (p V q) (j) =p (j) V q (j), etc.
would appear inadequate to express the meaning difference between (Sa) What now can we say about the type for S? It seems clear that, as ex-
and (Sb), since it would have to assign them the same logical form. pected, we want it to be a boolean algebra in order to provide interpretations
One might object to our informal analysis above on the grounds that for boolean combinations of S's. Further, where e is of category S, we want
English speakers do not in fact rigidly observe the meaning/form distinction e and {that, e} to have different interpretations for the reasons already given.
we have given for (Sa, b). Might not a speaker utter (Sa), even without the e will be interpreted as an element of Prop, so it remains to find a possible
that, intending the meaning we have attributed to (Sb)? Quite plausibly denotation for {that, e}. We may construct such a denotation by analogy
the answer here is yes. But even for such speakers we feel it is reasonable with the way denotations for proper nouns (in the extensional logic) were
to say that (Sa) is ambiguous, having the distinct meanings we have ascribed constructed, namely as the set of properties which the proposition expressed
to (Sa) and (Sb). On the reading in (Sb), for example, the utterance might bye has. Intuitively this is reasonable. Taking e for example to be Fred left,
be naturally followed in discourse by 'I can't remember which'. In any event, we naturally consider that under a given interpretation e has the property
if (Sa) is regarded as ambiguous, we are obliged in our logical syntax to have that John believes it, that Bill doubts it, that it is surprising, not logically
two structures.,one for each of the two readin!!§.Thus weshalL~ticlcwith_ true, etc. Thus where e is interpreted as a proposition p, we shall interpret
the syntactic course we have charted so far, leaving open the questions con- {that, e} as Ip , the set of properties which p has. More explicitly, a property
cerning how we match up surface forms and logical forms. of propositions is a function from Prop into 2, so Ip is the set of functions
Let us note finally that, for some speakers at least, additional support of from Prop into 2 which assign p value 1. Formally,
a syntactic nature argues in favor of the distinction between boolean com-
binations of S's and the result of combining that with boolean combinations DEFINITION 1. For all p E Prop (= F2/J), Ip = {tEF2/Prop: f(p) = I}
of S's. Specifically, for some speakers, conjunctions of Ss in subject position
may trigger plural agreement in the predicate whereas this is not the case for Recalling that the set of functions from Prop into 2 is isomorphic to Prop *,
that combined with a conjunction of Ss: the power set of Prop, we have that, up to isomorphism, an Ip is a subset of
Prop*, that is, an element of Prop**, the power set of Prop*. Since the IpS
(7) (Both) that Fred passed and (also) that Mary failed were/*was must be among the elements of 'IS it appears sufficient to take that type
strange to be Prop**. We may then naturally interpret the complementizer that, of
(8) That Fred passed and Mary failed was/*?were strange category SIS, as that function from Ts into 'IS which sends each p E Prop
(= TS) to Ip. And finally, since the elements of 'IS are sets (of properties of
Again, the syntactic difference between (7) and (8) corresponds to a semantic propositions) we may naturally interpret boolean combinations of 8's as
difference: (7) says that there were two strange things, Fred's passing and intersections, unions, and complements (relative to the set of all properties
Mary's failing; (8) says that there was only one strange thing, the fact that of propositions) of their conjuncts, disjuncts, etc.
a certain conjunction holds (as would be the case for example if Mary is Note that on this approach p and Ip are always distinct objects, whence
known to be much more knowledgeable than Fred - they might both pass for e a sentence, e and {that, e} are always interpreted as different formal
if the exam was easy, both fail if the exam was hard, but it is surprising to objects. Further, it also turns out that a boolean combination of 8's and the
find an exam which allows Fred to pass and Mary to fail). result of combining that with the corresponding boolean combination of
Overall, we find it more enlightening as regards the semantic system of sentences generally are interpreted differently. For example, suppose that
358 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 360 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

English to elucidate somewhat subtle distinctions than to ride roughshod Fred passed and Mary failed are interpreted by propositions p and q respec-
over them, whence we shall formally incorporate the distinction between tively, and assume further for simplicity of illustration that p and q are
Sand S in our logical syntax. Formally this is done, almost trivially, as completely independent, in the sense that neither is';;; to the other (i.e. there
follows. is a possible world j in which p holds and q fails and another world k in which
First we note that S is already a category and is in our list of boolean q holds and p fails). Then the conjunction of the S's that Fred passed and
categories, so boolean combinations of S's are S's. Moreover S (= Po) is that Mary failed is interpreted as Ip n Iq as illustrated below:
already a category, but to date has no expressions in it. So we add that to
the basic vocabulary and by lexical rule assign it the category SIS. This (10) that Fred pass and that Mary fail
guarantees that expressions of the form {that, e} are of category S, where
e is an expression of category S. Finally we include S in the list of boolean
categories, whence boolean combinations in and, or, and not are also expres-
sions of category S. We shall not add further expressions to the category S,
though a more detailed treatment of this category than we give here would
~Y Ip
~7
Iq
probably do so. For example, the direct objects in (9) should probably be
Ip nIq
assigned this category:
(9) (a) John believes whatever Fred says On the other hand, the result of first conjoining the two S's and then forming
(b) John proved everything that Fred conjectured the S with that is interpreted as follows:
(c) John believes the Axiom of Choice
(11) that [Fred pass and Mary fail]
Thus the expressions in S are just the expressions of the form {that, e} for e

V~Y
of category S, together with all boolean combinations formed recursively
beginning with these expressions.
We then add to the basic vocabulary expressions like is necessary (which
we do not for the nonce analyse into its component parts), believe, surprise, pl\q
mean, etc. and add lexical rules to the grammar assigning these expressions
to the appropriate category; e.g., is necessary is put in the category SIS, Ip ' q
believe in the category (SIfil)/S, etc. We shall also include these categories in
the list of boolean ones enabling us to generate booleanly complex elements Clearly Ip , q and lp n lq are distinct sets of properties. For example, lp , q
in these categories such as (both) hope and believe, as in John both hoped contains the function which assigns p 1\ q value I and all other propositions
and believed that Fred would win; surprise and annoy as in That Fred failed value O. Since p and q are completely independent, p 1\ q is a different
both surprised and annoyed Bill, etc. proposition from p, hence that function is not in Ip and so not in Ip n Iq . So
given that be strange (be necessary, etc.) of category SIS will be interpreted
A Semantics for Sand S- Taking Predicates as a function (about which more in a moment) from 1s into Ts, it can easily
be the case that (7) and (8), repeated below as (12) and (13), are interpreted
Our problem here is to define the types for S and the various categories of as different elements of Prop, since the be strange function is applying to
S-taking predicates. Once that is done, complex expressions formed from different arguments and so may naturally take different values.
these, such as believe that Fred left will be assigned an interpretation accord-
ing to the rule of functional applications already given. We consider first the (12) that Fred passed and that Mary failed were strange
type for S and then that of the relevant predicates. (13) that Fred passed and Mary failed was strange
SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 361 SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 363

This essentially completes our construction of is. Before giving a more homomorphic ally what they say about elements of the types is determined
formal statement let us note the deep and most non-obvious similarity by what they say about the individuals in those types. Let us codify these
between the type for S and the (extensional) type for N. (Note that we have observations with the following definition; note that we have given a general,
not made an extension/intension distinction in the type for S.) The most that is category independent, characterization of the semantic interpretation
crucial similarity is that both types possess distinguished subsets whose of the sub categorization feature proper.
elements we have called individuals. In each case the individuals are gen-
erators for the whole type, in the sense any element of the type is some DEFINITION 3. A complete boolean algebra B is said to be an argument
boolean combination of individuals. So, relative to the boolean operations, algebra iff it has a set of ca-free generators. By extension, a category C is
the elements of the type are, in some sense, determined by the individuals. an argument category iff Tc is an argument algebra.
Moreover, these sets of generators have a very special property - they are
free (for complete and atomic algebras), or ca-free for short. What this means, (18) Constraint on the feature 'proper'
informally, is that anything that can be said about elements of the entire If A is an argument category then TA is a set of ca-free gen-
type is determined by what can be said about the individuals in the type. Prop
erators for TA.
For the extensional type for N, the n-place predicates express what we can
say about the elements of that type; these predicates are just the complete As regards the last constraint it is worth noting perhaps that there may be
homomorphisms on Til, and by the Justification Theorem the complete expressions in S in addition to the ones of the form {that, e}, for e a sen-
homomorphisms from Til into any ca-algebra D are unique functions which tence, which bear some resemblance to proper nouns, in the sense of denoting
extend functions from the individuals in Til into D. So we can define an somewhat arbitrarily a fixed object. Such expressions would include Fermat's
n-place predicate just by stating its values on the individuals, and we can Last Theorem (which is not a theorem), Zorn's Lemma (a specific one of the
state those values freely. In this sense, what we can say about N denota- many he proved), etc.
tions is determined by what we can say about the individuals among those
denotations.
Formal Definitions of the New Types
Similarly in is the lp's are easily shown to be a set of ca-free generators
for Ts. This subset of S may naturally be called the proper'S's in the same Relative to a model <P, 2, J) we define the types for the new categories
way that the subset of N whose possible denotations ca-free generate Til discussed above as follows:
are the proper N's. For later reference let us formally define:
DEFINITION 4. Ts = F2/J as before but now called Prop, regarded as a ca-
DEFINITION 2. S
prop
= {(that, e): e of category S} algebra, the boolean operations being defined pointwise on J.
THEOREM 1. TS is a set of ca-free generators for Ts (= Prop**).
prop DEFINITION 5. TS = Prop** regarded as a power set boolean algebra.
Thus, if predicates on S denotations are judged to behave homomorphically,
as with Til, what can be said of S denotations is determined by what can be DEFINITION 6. TS = {Ip: p EProp}.
said of sentential individuals, the lp's (the proper S denotations). Now, S prop

taking predicates do behave homomorphically on their S arguments. For Recall that, by Theorem I, TS is a set of ca-free generators for TS, whence
prop
example, believe either that S or that T holds of the same individuals as S is an argument category.
does either believe that S or believe that T, and thus believe preserves joins. To give a generalized semantics for n-place predicates regardless of whether
Similarly it is easy to see that it preserves meets and complements, that is, the ith argument category is N or S (or any of the other argument categories
believe is interpreted by a homomorphism. Notice here that we are only to be suggested shortly) we introduce the following systematic abbreviatory
claiming that (14a) and (14b) must be interpreted by the same function: convention:
362 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 364 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

(14) (a) ... believe (either) that S or that T for C, C, .,. , Cn any elements of CAT, Cl, .c.. ,
C n abbreviates
(b) ... (either) believe that S or believe that T Cj , .c..
,Cn_l/Cn · For example, the category to which believe belongs
will be abbreviated fi~' which by the above convention abbreviates Sfils,
We are not claiming that (1Sa) and (ISb) must be interpreted by the same which in turn abbreviates (SIN)/S, the category to which believe belongs.
function:
We may then define:
(15) (a) ... believe that ((either) SorT)
(b) ... (either) believe that S or believe that T DEFINITION 7. For all argument categories AI, ... , An, the type for
Aj , .~ . ,A n is the set of complete homomorphisms from TA n into the type

(14a) and (14b) must be semantically identical since the argument of believe for A I, .. ~ ,A n _ 1 regarded as a boolean algebra where the operations are
in (14a) is a disjunction of S's and must be interpreted then as a join of defined pointwise on TA n .
S denotations, in this case of sentential individuals, Ip's. Since believe is prop
to be interpreted by a homomorphism it must preserve joins and thus be For example, the above definition together with the rule for interpreting
semantically identical to the interpretation of (14b). But in (1Sa) the argu- boolean combinations tells us that m(hope and believe) is that complete
ment of believe is not a join, in fact not even a boolean combination, of S's. homomorphism from TS into TS/fi whose value at any propositional in-
It is merely an expression of the form {that, e} where e has category S. So dividualIp is m(hope) (Ip) 1\ m(be/ieve) (Ip), the meet here being taken in
the argument expression of believe in (1Sa) is interpreted as a generator, an the algebra TS/fi understood to be the algebra of transparent homomorphisms
I p , and the complete homomorphisms take their values freely - in any way from Tfiinto TS'
we like - on the generators. Note that our subcategorization abbreviations have not adequately reflected
Thus the homomorphic nature of S taking predicates is only clear once the transparency distinctions discussed earlier in our intensional logic. It is
the distinction between Sand S is made clear. Similarly it is clear that other unproblematic to enrich our abbreviatory conventions to include them;
S taking predicates behave homomorphically on their S arguments. Thus e.g. we might write the category for believe as fi~' but we shall not make
be strange must preserve meets since (16a) and (16b) below are logically +t
sufficiently elaborate use of the notation to require the detailed spelling out
equivalent:
of these conventions here. We shall assume where relevant that predicative
categories are understood to be transparent unless indicated otherwise.
(16) (a) (Both) that Fred passed and that Mary failed are strange.
(b) That Fred passed is strange and that Mary failed is strange. Lexical Constraints on the Interpreting Function m
The new categories in our system present a variety of expressions which are
Again of course treating be strange as a homomorphism does not commit
in the standard sense logical constants. Thus, as before, the class of inter-
us to the logical equivalence of (17a) and (17b) below, since the argument
preting functions m considered for the language must be restricted so that
of (17a) is not a boolean combination of S's, so the homomorphic nature of
these expressions have fixed denotations relative to the primitives of the
be strange does not commit us in any way as to what proposition it yields
model. In giving examples below we ignore the assignment function a of
when applied to it.
values to variables as these are not relevant to the present discussion.
In addition to the constraints on the acceptable interpreting functions
(17) (a) That ((both) Fred passed and Mary failed) is strange
(b) (Both) that Fred passed and that Mary failed are strange
m already presented we now require that:
(19) m (be true) is that complete homomorphism from TS into Ts
Thus the similarity between f! and S is non-trivial. Their types are both defined by:
ca-free generated algebras, and major classes or predicates on them behave h(Ip) (j) =p(j), all p E Prop, allj EJ.
SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 365 SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 367

Thus, informally, that Fred sings is true holds in a world i iff Fred sings We might note that the predicates for which such sub categorization
holds in i. Note that (19) is a well definition in virtue of the one-to-one features seem to give correct results are 'impersonal' predicates like probable,
correspondence between sentential individuals (Ip's) and propositions. improbable, etc. rather than 'psychological' ones like believe, etc. Thus it is
Thus if I is a sentential individual there is exactly one proposition p such not clear that (26a) below entails (26b).
that I = Ip. Given the individual I then we may unambiguously refer to its
proposition as PI; the equation in (19) could then read: for all sentential (26) (a) John believes that Fred left
individuals I and all possible worlds i, h (I) (j) = PI(j). Having noted this (b) John believes that ((either) Fred left or Mary stayed)
point we shall use the somewhat less correct but easier to read notation
in (19). At least one snag in inferring (26b) from (26a) is that John may never have
considered the proposition expressed by the disjunction in (26b) and thus
(20) m (be false) =(m (be true))' in some sense have no opinion about it, even though if he is rational he
presumably would believe it if he did consider it. And the assumption of
Thus that Fred sings is false holds in i iff the complement of that Fred sings rationality in the latter case actually gives additional reason for doubting the
is true fails in i. entailment. For to say that (26a) entails (26b) is to say that whenever (26a) is
true (26b) is. If this may fail in the case of irrational John then the entailment
(21) m(be necessary) is that complete homomorphism h from Tsinto
fails. We are inclined then not to want to assign psychological predicates to
Ts such that for allp E TS and alli EJ, h(lp) (j) = k ~ JP(k).
upward or downward entailing subcategories of S taking predicates.
On the other hand, another subcategory of S taking predicates which
Thus that Fred sings is necessary holds ini iff Fred sings holds in all worlds k. we feel we can represent in a reasonable if not totally adequate way are
factives (see Kiparsky and Kiparsky, 1970, and Keenan, 1969, for more
(22) m(be possible) is that complete homomorphism h such that for detailed discussion). Thus we judge that each of (27a) and (27b) below
allp, i as above, h(Ip) (j) =k ~ JP(k) entails (27 c).

Thus that Fred sings is possible holds in i iff for some world k Fred sings (27) (a) That Fred left early was strange
holds in k. (b) That Fred left early wasn't strange
Note that on our approach, as in more standard ones, necessity and (c) Fred left early
possibility are treated as properly modal predicates quantifying over possible
worlds, with necessity universal quantification and possibility existential But if strange (ironic, surprising, etc.) is replaced by any of true, false, prob-
quantification. The propositions which interpret the sentences these predi- able, likely, necessary, etc. at least one of the two entailments fails.
cates form are constant (in any given model): they have the same value at We may easily account for the entailment from (27a) to (27c) by assigning
alIi EJ. be strange, etc. to a subcategory of SIS whose type is defined as follows:
fact
We may note as well that there are two place logical predicates with the
same properties - quantifying over worlds and being constant at all worlds DEFINITION 9. TS/S = {h E TS/s: for allp E Prop, h(Jp) ~p}.
fact
in a given model. Thus (23) below is as plausible a semantics for imply as
(21) above is for be necessary. It follows immediately then that if (27a) is true in j then (27c) is; and
conversely if (27c) fails inj then so must (27a).
(23) m(imply) is that complete homomorphism h from Tsinto Ts/s The problem however is to account for the inference from (27b) to (27c).
such that for allp, q EProp and alli EJ, h(Ip)(lq) (j)= 1 ifffor Assuming that the predicate in (27b) is just the negation of that in (27a)
all k EJ, p(k) ~ q(k). and noting that be strange is interpreted by an element of TS/s we have
366 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 368 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

Subcategories of S Taking Predicates that the predicate in (27b) is interpreted by the complement of that in
(27a). And complements in TS/S are defined pointwise on individuals (see
The semantic difference between S and S we have developed allows us to
Definition 7), whence (27b) is true iff (27a) is false. Since (27a) may be false
represent meaning differences between various syntactically similar Staking
if (27c) is, it follows that (27b) does not entail (27c).
predicates in ways we find enlightening. Let us consider again the case of a
The solution we tentatively propose to this problem is as follows. Define
model in which we have completely independent propositions p and q. Then
the type for the factives as in Defmition 9 above but assign it a boolean
I p , I q , Ip A q' and Ip v q are distinct generators of TS; so the' values of homo-
structure as follows: meets and joins are defined pointwise as before, but
morphisms on these generators may be randomly assigned. Thus while we
complements are defined by the equation h'(Ip ) = p fI (h(Ip))'; the unit
have (p /I. q) < p, it does not follow that help A q) < h(Ip), for h a homo-
element sends each Ip to p, and the zero element is as in TS/S, it sends each
morphism on TS. (It does of course follow that help n lq) < h(Ip), but that
Ip to the zero element of Prop, that function which sends each j in J to the
is not the case we are considering.) For example, correctly, that Fred passed
zero element of 2. The reader may verify that the operations so defined
and Mary failed is ironic might be true in a world j even though that Fred
satisfy the axioms of boolean algebra. But now we have a possible ambiguity
passed is ironic is not.
in the interpretation of not be strange. We get one result if we consider be
However it appears that not all S taking predicates are insensitive to the
difference between lp and lp A q' lp and lp v q' etc. For example if the
strange as an element of sis, for thereh' (Ip) is directly (h(Ip))', and another
result if we consider it an element of SIS, where h' (Ip) = p II (h(Jp))'. To
denotation of is probable holds of lp in some world j then it should hold fact
of Ip v q in j_ And if it holds of Ip q in j it ought to hold of lp in j and
A
circumvent this problem we must add a rider to the general rule which inter-
also of lq. That is to say, (24a) below is judged to entail (24b), and (25a) prets boolean combinations. Namely, m(not e) = (m(e))', complements
(25b): taken in the smallest subcategory to which e belongs. Similarly m(el and e2)
= meed II m(eJ, meets taken in the smallest subcategory to which both
(24) (a) That Fred left is probable el and e2 belong. For the nonce this approach seems to us satisfactory since
(b) That (Fred left or Mary fainted) is probable SIS is a subcategory of SIS and in that sense smaller than it. And more
fact
(25) (a) That (Fred left and Mary stayed) is probable generally the smallest subcategory of a category to which an expression e
(b) That Fred left is probable belongs is the one which includes all the subcategorization features which e
is overtly required to satisfy. So for the crucial case of complements we
But if probable above is replaced by doubtful or improbable the entailments
always know in what algebra to evaluate m(not e).
fail to hold; in fact that seem to be reversed. We may then distinguish semantic
Though much more could and should be said concerning subcategories
subcategories of S taking predicates according as entailments such as the
of S taking predicates we turn now to the generalization inherent in our
above hold or fail to hold.
notion of argument category.
These 'and similar facts are naturally accommodated in our system by
adding a sub categorization feature upward entailing (adapted from Ladusaw,
Argument Categories in Addition to Nand S
1979) to our language, assigning be probable to the category SIS by lexical
rule, and defining the type as follows: up We have argued earlier that Nand S should be treated as distinct categories.
They nonetheless have much in common syntactically. As EST theorists
DEFINITION 8. Ts/S = {h E Ts/s: for all p, q E Prop, if p < q then h(Ip) have pointed out (Chomsky, 1970), there are some similarities (and also
<h(Iq)}. up some differences) in internal structure. Externally, both categories are ones
whose expressions may, depending on the language, trigger predicate agree-
The entailments in (24) and (25) then follow automatically. The corres- ment and be marked for case and/or thematic role (e.g. Patient, Stimulus,
ponding feature downward entailing can be added in a similar way with Cause, etc.). They are categories affected (or mentioned) be relation changing
the obvious semantics. rules like Passive and Extraposition (about which more later); they are
SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 369
SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 371
categories whose expressions can be quantified and bound, as by relativiza-
tion operators (everyone who John saw and invited to the party, everything what set is chosen as TQ; TQ is a power set of a power set and so ca-freely
that John believes and tries to prove, etc.) and question operators (What did generated.
It seems to us likely that R, S, and Q (the latter enriched to include the
John see?, What does John believe?, etc.)
Above we adduced a semantic property which Rand S had in common full range of embedded wh-questions) constitute the major, most productive,
and which thus correlates with this similarity in syntactic behavior, namely, categories of English with which predicates combine to form sentences. If
their types are (extensionally, where relevant) ca-freely generated algebras. so, our semantic characterization of argument categories as ones whose types
This property doubtless seems esoteric when stated algebraically, but on have individuals seems reasonably good. However, other categories of expres-
intuitive grounds, as discussed earlier, it means that these types have indi- sion besides those considered may function as arguments of predicates and
viduals, a property which distinguished Rand S from other major categories these would have to be investigated, as their semantics is even less well
which are not generally arguments of predicates. For example, the types for understood than that of the argument categories so far considered. One
possible candidate here are infinitival nominals, as illustrated in the subject
Modifiers, categories of the form CIC, are not ca-freely generated algebras.
phrase in (32).
Similarly, the types for predicates are not ca-freely generated, nor are the
types for Specifiers (= Determiners). Detailed arguments to this effect would
(32) To be very rich is troublesome/pleasant/fun, etc.
require more space than we can devote to them here, but the basic charac-
terization theorem which is used in all such proofs is the following theorem:
It seems reasonable to expect that a minimally adequate semantics for in-
finitival nominals can be obtained along lines fully analogous to that for
THEOREM 2. A complete boolean algebra B has a set of ca-free generators
Sand Q. Semantically, to would map a PI denotation onto the individual
iff B is isomorphic to the power set of a power set.
it determines, i.e. the set of properties which hold of it. The type for these
nominals would have to be booleanly closed to provide denotations for
Note that TS is Prop**, the power set of a power set, and TN is extensionally
boolean combinations of such nominals, as illustrated below:
P*, the power set of TN, itself taken to be a ca-algebra and thus isomorphic
to the power set of its atoms by Theorem 6 of Part lA. We omit the proof
(33) (a) (Both) to be very rich and to be very poor are troublesome
of Theorem 2, which uses completely standard techniques.
(b ) (Either) to leave early or to leave late is forbidden
Are there other categories of English whose types are argument algebras?
( c) To dance but not to sing is dangerous
The natural place to look is at categories which loosely function as arguments
of predicates. To the extent that types for these categories are argument We may take the type for infinitival nominals, call it PI, to be the complete
algebras we may conclude that our semantic characterization of the notion boolean closure of the PI individuals, provably isomorphic to (TP I )**. (PI
'argument of a predicate' in English is a good one. Preliminary investigation here is assumed for simplicity of illustration to be SIN.) This would again
here suggests in fact the answer to our query is affirmative. +t
yield an argument algebra, one which is distinct from TP I itself. This latter
One such category are embedded questions, such as the direct object
point is justified by showing that to, like that and whether, introduces
expressions in (28) below:
alternative scopes involving boolean operators. For example, a disjunction
of infinitives is not equivalent to the infinitive of a disjunction, so that (34a)
(28) John knows/remembers/forgot whether Fred left.
and (34b) are not logically equivalent. Similarly, (35a) and (35b) are not
equivalent.
Tentatively assigning such expressions to the category Q, and limiting our-
selves for expository purposes to embedded yes-no Q's, we may note that
(34) (a) To (either come early or leave late) is forbidden
simple expressions in this category appear to have the form whether+S. We
(b) (Either) to come early or to leave late is forbidden (I can't
want these expressions to have a different category from S, however, since
remember which)
370 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 372 PAR T II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

(29a) and (29b) are not paraphrases, whence their direct objects must denote (35) (a) (Both) to come early and to leave late are forbidden
differently. (b) To (both come early and leave late) is forbidden

(29) (a) John knows whether Fred left. In short, it seems as though the basic facts which motivated our analysis
(b) John knows that Fred left. of S obtain here for PI, and thus PI is properly an argument category in
our semantic sense of the term. However, much more study of the semantic
Clearly if John knows that Fred didn't leave then (29a) is true and (29b) properties of PI taking predicates would have to be done before any certitude
not true. could be attached to that conclusion.
Further, for reasons similar to those given earlier for S, we want Q to be Let us consider now some syntactic and semantic operations which con-
a different category from R. In addition, we want Q to be different from cern argument categories in general and S in particular.
S, for otherwise sentences such as (30a) and (30b) below would be logically
equivalent, which they are not. Extraposition

(30) (a) John knows both whether S and whether T Sentences such as (36a) and (36b) below are logically equivalent, and more-
(b) John knows whether both Sand T over, appear to be syntactically related in a regular way.

(36) (a) That Fred left early is clear


Clearly (30b) says that John knows whether a certain conjunction holds -
(b) It is clear that Fred left early
which he might easily know if T is chosen as the negation of S - But it does
not claim, as does (30a), that he knows whether each conjunct holds or not. Early work in generative grammar derived (roughly) (36b) from (36a) by
Further, (30a) supports the idea that we want Q to form complex members 'extraposing' the S subject of (36a) to the end of the sentence leaving a
in and, and (31) below that we want to form them with or and not, whence 'dummy' it behind (Rosenbaum, 1967). Later work, beginning perhaps
we want Qto be a boolean category having a boolean algebra as its type. with Emonds (1976), preferred to treat (36b) as somewhat more basic and
derived (36a) from it by intraposition.
(31) (a) John knows either whether S or whether T (I can't remember Our concern here is to provide a logical structure for (36b) which cor-
which) responds as closely as possible to its surface form and which is logically
(b) John knows whether S but not whether T equivalent to the one assigned to (36a). Now, (36b) appears to be superficially
in a predicate·argument form, with it as the argument and the rest of the
In the essential respects, then, an adequate type for Q can be constructed sentence as the predicate. This judgment is confirmed by less superficial
along lines completely similar to those for S, with whether playing the analysis. For example, it appears that the argument it 'raises', as do clear
role of that. Let us assume, as it does not enter into our construction, that cases of N arguments. More specifically, (37a) and (37b) below seem to be
the type for Q, the category of yes-no questions, has been defined. (Note syntactically related in the same way as (38a) and (38b).
the obvious one-to-one correspondence between the declarative sentence S
and the yes-no question Is it the case that S?) Then we interpret whether+S (37) (a) John believes that Fred is clever
to be the individual generated by the denotation of the corresponding ques- (b) John believes Fred to be clever
tion denotation, that is, the set of properties (functions from TQ into 2) (38) (a) John believes that it is clear that Fred left early
which hold of that question denotation, and we define the type for Q to be (b) John believes it to be clear that Fred left early
the complete boolean closure of those individuals, an algebra provably
isomorphic to (TQ)**, a power set of a power set and thus by Theorem 2 Accordingly we shall treat (36b) as being of a predicate-argument form with
a ca-freely generated algebra. Note here, as with TS, that it doesn't matter it as argument.
SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 373 SENTENTIAL PREDICATES 375

But to what category should we assign this it? It appears to be a sort of If ej has category X/Y, e2 has category Y, and {ej, e2} has
pronominal place holder for the semantic subject of is clear, expressed by category X, then m({ej, ed) = meed (m(e2)).
that Fred left early. It contributes nothing to the meaning of (36b), which (45) Dummy Rule (Semantics)
is identical to that of (36a) which is it-less. Semantically, then, it is 'dumb', If ej has category S/A (for A an argument category), e2 has
and we shall, adopting a terminology from Relational Grammar (perlmutter category A, and {ej, e2} has category S/DA, then for all x E
and Postal, 1977), treat it as a 'dummy for category S'. Note that it functions TDA (= TA), m({ej, e2}) (x) = meed (m(e2)).
as a dummy for (2, and SIN as well:
Note that we have in a certain sense 'weakened' our semantics, in that we
(39) (a) Whether John left is unknown cannot uniquely determine the denotation of a derived expression if we only
(b) It is unknown whether John left know the types of the expressions from which it is derived. We must now
(40) (a) To leave early would be annoying also know the category of the derived expression. Until now we did not
(b) It would be annoying to leave early have to mention the category of the derived expression in the interpretative
rule since it was uniquely determined given the categories of its immediate
And while it does not function as a dummy for ordinary N's, it does seem constituents. Now that is no longer the case, so the category of the derived
as though there does (as argued in the Relational Grammar framework cited expression must be mentioned in the interpretative rule. So this is a modifi-
above): cation of our system, but not one which is particularly problematic. It merely
allows us to put derived expressions in more than one category.
(41) (a) Unicorns exist It does not, however, allow us to put basic expressions, ones in the basic
(b) There exist unicorns vocabulary, in more than one category (with disjoint types). For here the
interpreting functions m are constrained to interpret basic expressions e of
Thus, perhaps, for every argument category C we want some notion of
category C as elements of the type for C. If a given basic expression e was
'dummy of category C' in our logical syntax. Since we are going to treat
in two categories with diSjoint types there would be no functions m satisfying
such dummies as arguments of predicates we need some way of forming
the condition on basic expressions. This means for example that we cannot
'dummy taking predicates' from the expressions which would 'normally'
assign it to S/Ds and S/DQ by lexical rule. An easy, though not particularly
combine via the rule of functional applications to yield an S. While there
elegant, solution to this problem is to simply add artificially distinct it's to
are doubtless many ways to do this, the option we tentatively propose is
the basic vocabulary and assign say itj by lexical rule to the category S/Ds,
illustrated in (42) below.
it2 to the category S/DQ, etc. It would perhaps be somewhat more natural
(42) to subscript the it's with the category name they are dummies for. We shall

Ds _~~_-------s~. SIDs adopt this latter solution. Thus the basic vocabulary is hereby enriched to
include there, its, itQ, etc. Lexical rules assign there to the category Dj\j, its
to DS, etc. The logical structure we assign to it is clear that Fred left then is:
SIS------- ~s
6
(46)

it be clear
~
that Fred leave early
'It is clear that Fred left early'

Incorporating such structures formally in our logic will be done as follows.


First we add dummy categories to our definition of CAT, the set of category its be clear that Fred leave
374 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC 376 PART II: THE INTENSIONAL LOGIC

names, as per Definition lOa below, and assign them the type indicated in The dummy rule expands the node SIDs; otherwise the only rules that have
Definition lOb: been used are functional applications and lexical rules.
To see that (46) is correctly interpreted as a paraphrase of the logical
DEFINITION 10. representation of (that Fred leave) (be clear) we must technically assign a
type to slDs. This we do generally as follows:
(a) If C is an element of CAT then DC is an element of CAT.
(b) Tnc =Tc DEFINITION 11. For all categories C, TS/DC =FTS/TDC.
With this addition to CAT the direct expansion of Sin (42) is achieved by
To show that (46) is correctly interpreted, let m be an arbitrary interpreta-
the rule of functional applications.
tion of our extended language. m(its) is an arbitrary element in TDs (= Ts),
The main problem now is how to generate {be clear, that Fred leave early}
since its is a lexical element in Ds and it has not been treated as a logical
in the category S/DS. To do this we add another rule to our grammar along-
constant. Since the conditions for the interpretative Dummy rule (45) are
side the rules of subcategorization, functional application, boolean combina-
met, we have that the interpretation of (46) is given by:
tions, and variable binding operators. (43) gives the rule we propose:

(43) Dummy Rule (Syntax) (47) m( {be clear, that Fred leave})(m(its))
For all possible expressions el, e2 and A any argument category, = m(be clear) (m(that Fred leave))
if el E n(S/A) and e2 En(A), then {el, e2} E n(S/DA).
And this latter is just the interpretation of (that Fred leave) (be clear). Our
Note that (43) might appear to 'contradict' the rule of functional appli- semantics then is correct, and dummies have been technically treated as
cations which says that for el, e2 as above the set {el, e2} has category S, arguments and their types are argument algebras. Hence other processes,
not SIDA. A careful reading of our formal syntax however shows that there such as Raising, which are sensitive to arguments, could treat it, there, etc.
is in fact no conflict. We have defmed the naming function n to be the least as they do other arguments.
function from CAT, the set of category names, into (PEV)*, the collection Note, finally, that we have not had to take a position on whether the
of all sets of possible expressions over V, which meets certain conditions. In sentence pairs we are generating are generated by extraposition or by intra-
particular, it must meet the conditions given by both the rules of functional position. We have in fact independently generated each element of the pair.
application and now the dummy rules. Thus, its value at the symbol S must
include {el' e2} as an element, and its value at S/DS must also include
{el' ed as an element. This only means that n(S) and n(SjDs) are not
disjoint sets, which is not in and of itself problematic.
It does mean however that we have derived expressions, such as {be clear,
that Fred left early} in more than one category, so we must be careful in
stating the constraints on the interpreting function m so that we are not
attempting to assign the same (derived) expression to elements in disjoint
types (for the types for Sand SIDs are indeed disjoint). The interpretation
of the Dummy rule in (45) below shows that this is also not problematic,
once we have modified slightly the statement of the interpretation of the
rule of functional applications, as we do now in (44).

(44) Modified Interpretation for Functional Applications


BIBLIOGRAPHY
INDEX

Anderson, S. R.: 1971, 'On the Role of Deep Structure in Semantic Interpretation', IBIB 130, 146ff
2 (algebra of two elements) 5, 6, 43ff,
Foundations of Language 7, 387 -396.
51, 59-65 passim, 87, 94, 99- lifted algebra, of 279, 28lff
Bach, E.: 1980, 'In Defense of Passive', Linguistics and Philosophy 3,297-342.
103 passim, 109 ontological primitive, as 62ff, 73ff
Bartsch, R.: 1976, 'Subcategorization of Adnominal and Adverbial Modifiers', in E. L.
about power set algebra 59ff
Keenan (ed.), Formal Semantics of Natural Language, Cambridge University Press,
see subject-matter phrase PRAIA 162
Cambridge, England.
absolute modifier RB/B 129, 144ff
Barwise, J. and R. Cooper: 1980, 'Generalized Quantifiers and Natural Languages',
see intersecting modifier SO<PnIPn > 169
in Stanford Working Papers in Semantics, Vol. 1, pp. 1-80.
abstract noun 190 stative locatives and 154ff
Ben-Chorin, S.: 1982, 'Sentence Meanings as a Formal Basis for Intensional Logic',
accusative 178ff TP 1 100
in Proc. of the First West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, D. Flickinger, M.
activity predicate 208 TPn 102
Macken, and N. Wiegand (eds.), Dept. of Linguistics, Stanford University, Stanford,
ad-adjective 133 see also atoms, justification theorem
pp.82-93.
additivity (of P2 ) 317ff atoms 56ff, 75ff, 87, 93, 190, 369
Bloom, 1.: 1973, One Word at a Time, Mouton, The Hague, Paris.
Boole, G.: 1854, An Investigation of the Laws of Thought, Cambridge. adjectives of physical size 12lff AO<PnfPn>, in 175
Bresnan, J.: 1978, 'A Realistic Transformational Grammar', in M. Haile, J. Bresnan, and agreement 14, 16, 19, 20, 25, 27, 34, compared individuals, in 135ff, 327
G. Miller (eds.), Linguistic Theory and Psychological Reality, MIT Press, Cambridge, 68, 178,357, 368 Dai' and 344
Mass. ambiguity 20, 22, 26, 163-165, 181- definition 56
Busby, S.: 1983, A Semantics for Plural Noun Phrases and Higher Order Predicative 184, 192, 206, 207, 247-252, definition of the, and 84, 105
Functions, M.A. Diss., Dept. of Linguistics, UCLA. 291, 292, 304, 305, 308, 318, IBIB, in 146
Chomsky, N.: 1966, Cartesian Linguistics, Harper and Row, New York. 351,352,357,368 individuals and 62, 76ff, 239-242
Chomsky, N.: 1970, 'Remarks on Nominalizations', in Roderick A. Jacobs and Peter American Indian languages 26, 66 passim, 316-319 passim, 344
S. Rosenbaum (eds.), Readings in English Transformational Grammar, Ginn and Co., Anderson 180 intensional individuals, and 285
Waltham, Mass. Anglo Saxon 66, 85 lifted algebra, in a 281ff
Chomsky, N.: 1973, 'Conditions on Transformations', in A Festschrift for Morris AO<PnIPn > 162,198,199 pointwise algebra, in a 82
Halle, S. R. Anderson and P. Kiparsky (eds.), Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New Arabic 264 PRAIA, in 173
York. argument algebra 14, 16,363,369,376 preserved under isomorphism 61,
Dowty, D.: 1978, 'Governed Transformations as Lexical Rules in Montague Grammar', argument attraction 24 240-242 passim
Linguistic Inquiry 9, 393-427. argument category 9, 14, 16, 19, 22, property as join of 79
Emonds, J.: 1976, A Transformational Approach to English Syntax, Academic Press, 26, 177, 353, 363ff, 368ff, 374, RBIB, in 144ff,333
New York. 375 stative locatives, and 154ff
Faltz, 1.: 1982, 'On the Non-Bal(l)m(i)er Character of Keenan-Faltz Grammar', in argument-oriented PM 152, 160-167, TN (intensional), in 326
Theoretical Linguistics 9, 221-246. 196-201 passim, 333, 334 TP. (intentional), in 283
Gil, D.: 1982, 'Quantifier Scope, Linguistic Variation, and Natural Language Semantics', arithmetic 63-65, 229, 234 Tpl,in 100
Linguistics and Philosophy 5, 421 ~4 73. aspect TPn , in .101
Gordon, 1.: 1978, 'Raising in Bauan Fijian', ms., Dept. of Linguistics, UCLA. see tense automorphIsm 239ff
Jake, J. and D. Odden: 1978, 'Cross Clausal Movement Rules in Kipsigis', presented assignment to variables 253, 266 automorphism invariance 239ff, 242,
at the 10th Annual African Linguistics Conference. atomic algebra 30,52, 56ff 244
Keenan, E. L.: 1969, A Logical Base for a Transformational Grammar of English, Ph.D. AO<PnIPn > 162
diss., Dept. of Linguistics, Univ. of Pennsylvania. definition 56 Bach 208
Keenan, E. L.: 1979, 'On Surface Form and Logical Form', in B. B. Kachru (ed.), extentionality and 79ff Bantu languages 66, 201, 202

377 379
378 BIBLIOGRAPHY 380 INDEX

Linguistics in the Seventies: Directions and Prospects, Univ. of Illinois, Dept. of bar category 14, 20, 31, 32, 35, 273, preserved by homomorphisms 91
Linguistics, Champaign-Urbana, pp. 163-203. 354ff,368ff preserved by isomorphisms 61
Keenan, E. L.: 1980, 'Passive is Phrasal (not Sentential or Lexical)', in T. Hoekstra et Bartsch 138 properties, of 74 ff
al. Ceds.), Lexical Grammar, Foris Publications, Dordrecht, pp. 343-379. Barwise and Cooper 16,86 RBIB, in 143ff
Keenan, E. L.: 1981, 'Passive in the Languages of the World', to appear in T. Shopen bathwater 51 TP I , in 100
(ed.), Language Typology and Syntactic Description, Cambridge University Press, be 34, 35, 37,102,104,139,140,187, TPn , in 102
Cambridge, England. 222, 245, 328, 330f[ Bresnan 208
Keenan, E. L.: 1982a. 'Parametric Variation in Universal Grammar', in Issues in the believe 13, 14, 25, 273, 353ff Busby 267
Theory of Universal Grammar, R. Dirven and G. Radden (eds.), Gunter Narr Verlag, Ben-Chorin 353 by phrase 170, 196, 197, 203, 208,
Tubingen. benefactive phrase 151,152 209, 216f[
Keenan, E. L., 1982b, 'Eliminating the Universe: A Study in Ontological Perfection', Bloom 66
in Proc. of the First West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, in D. Flickinger, booger 28 ca-algebra (~ complete and atomic
M. Macken, and N. Wiegand (eds.), Dept. of Linguistics, Stanford Univ., pp. 71-82. Boole 46 algebra)
Keenan, E. L. and L. Faltz: 1978, LOgical Types for Natural Language, UCLA Occasional boolean algebra 6, lOff, 44ff see atomic algebra, complete algebra
Papers in Linguistics, No.3, Dept. of Linguistics, UCLA. definition 44 canonical passive 203, 204
Keenan, E. L. and J. Stavi: 1981, 'A Semantic Characterization of Natural Language see also atomic algebra, atoms, cardinalities 11-13, 87, 110, 245,285,
Quantifiers', to appear in Linguistics and Philosophy. boolean relation, complete 296
Kiparsky, P. and C. Kiparsky: 1970, 'Fact', in M. Bierwisch and K. Heidolph (eds.), algebra, justification theorem cardinality dependent determiners 228,
Progress in Linguistics, Mouton, the Hague. boolean category 31, 37, 38, 42, 46 232ff, 243
Ladusaw, W.: 1979, Polarity Sensitivity as Inherent Scope Relations, Ph.D. diss., Univ. AP 127ff, 320ff case marking xii, 14, 19, 20, 178ff,
of Texas at Austin, to be published by Garland Press. PI (intensional) 293ff 180, 190-192, 213, 214, 368
Mendelson, E.: 1970, Boolean Algebra and Switching Circuits (Schaum's Outline Series), Po (intensional) 306 category names of core language 32
McGraw Hill Book Co. Pn (intensional) 307 causative 168,202
Montague, R.: 1970, 'English as a Formal Language', reprinted in Formal Philosophy, PM 161 Chicewa 23
R. Thomason (ed.), 1974, Yale University Press, New Haven. Q 370 child language 18,66,67
Montague, R.: 1973, 'The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English', S 358 Chomsky 18,185,221,368
in J. Hintikka, J. Moravcsik, and P. Suppes (eds.), Approaches to Natural Language, stative locatives 153 cliticization 27
Reidel, Dordrecht. boolean relation 7, 10, 53ff, 99, 107ff, close shave 110
Moravcsik, E.: 1978, 'Ergative and Accusative Patterns', ms., Dept. of Linguistics, Univ. 120,133 closure, complete B- 83
of Wisconsin. definition 53 CM 179
Partee, B.: 1975, 'Montague Grammar and Transformational Grammar', Linguistic F 2 / K , in 58 color adjectives 122ff
Inquiry VI, 203-300. lifted algebra, in a 281 comitative phrase 151, 196, 272
Perlmutter, D. and P. Postal: 1979, 'Towards a Universal Characterization of Passiviza- preserved by homomorphism 91 comma as conjunction 132, 320-324
tion', in Proc. of the Third Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, preserved by isomorphism 61 commitment, speaker
Berkeley, Ca. properties related by 73ff see pragmatics
Rosenbaum, P.: 1967, The Grammar of English Predicate Complement Constructions, R B / B , in 144 commutativity law 44
MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. see also bounds, complete algebra, obeyed by properties 69-70
Thomason, R.: 1976, 'Some Extensions of Montague Grammar', in B. Partee (ed.) entailment, informativeness, comparatives 74, 75, 120, 122, 132,
Montague Grammar, Academic Press. restricting algebra, restricting 134ff, 157, 327
Thomason, R.: 1980, 'A Model Theory for Propositional Attitudes', Linguistics and modifier complement flip law 112
Philosophy 4, 47-71. bounds ((least) upper and (greatest) complements condition 75
Trithart, L.: 1977, Relational Grammar and Chi-cewa Subjectivization Rules, M.A. lower) complete algebra 30, 52, 55[f, 83
Diss., Dept. of Linguistics, UCLA. Also in the Publications of the Indiana University defmition 54 AO<PnIPn> 162
Linguistics Club. IB/B , in 146 definition 55
lifted algebra, in a 281 IBIB 130,146
meet and join as 55 lifted algebra 279, 281
preserved by functions 88ff ontological primitive, as 62ff, 73ff
INDEX 381 INDEX 383

complete algebra (cont'd) 351 intentionality, transparency, non-trans- SO<PnIPn> ~ Tp, 169, 177, 198
power set algebra 59ff directional phrase 152 parency (cont' d) TAP ~ TN (= P) 8, 130, 225, 261
PRAIA 162 distributivity law 44, 46, 47 preserved by passive 208 i
obeyed by properties 69-71 relative clauses 352, 353 TAP ~ Tp 225, 226
RB/B 129,144 In n+,
SO<PnfPn> 169 doubtful 366 scalar adjectives 120-122,138, 139,
TAP ~ TpM 26,341
stative locatives as 154 downward entailing 366, 367 272, 309ff, 315ff
TB/B nRB/B 320,332 Dowty 208 source phrases 165ff ,
Tpt ~ TN (=P) 25, 100, 185, 187,
transitive verbs with PM 163, 333ff 235,261,262,341
Tp, 100 dummy 373ff
Tpn ~ «Ipn~)* 102
TPn 102 dummy rule intensive 120, 132ff, 157
see also very Tp ~ TN 185-189, 223, 224,
see also bounds, justification theorem semantic 375 n+'34l n
complete homomorphism 91, 99-104 syn tactic 374 internal semantic structure 292, 304
interpretation 5ff, 35, 41, 45-49 TpM n ~ TPn +, 200,226
passim -ee 224, 226
complex NP constraint 218 passim, 87-101 passim, 104ff, '"
TQ~ (TQ)** 370
compositionality 24, 25, 51, 63, 138, Einstein 154 197, 223, 227, 233, 238, 240,
246, 253-265 passim, 266, 298, it 372 ff
205, 207, 220, 242 ellipsis 319
conjectural adjective 125, 314 ff embedded question 369-371 315ff, 321,330, 343ff, 351-353, Jake and Odden 23
conservativity 16, 17, 85,86,103,227, Emonds 372 375,376 Japanese 260
230, 231, 237, 238, 243, 246ff entailment 1, 2, 7, 20, 41, 42, 105ff, intersecting algebra 130ff, 145ff J-lifted algebra 309,310,312,313,320,
conservativity, weak 85,86 125, 127 intersecting modifiers 8, 16, 26, 64, 331, 332
consistent PM intension 334 equi 25 122ff, 152ff, 191, 224ff, 262ff, joins condition 75
context -er 186-189, 223-226, 235, 340, .341 312ff JT
see pragmatics everywhere 155, 162 intersectingness inheritance theorem see justification theorem
contraction 27 exist 41, 104, 107, 152, 160, 222, 244 313,331,332,352 justification theorem xi, 12, 13, 92-94,
correspondence between surface forms explanatory adequacy 18 proof 331,332 96, 99-101, 110, 116, 187-189,
and logical forms 9, 14, 17-29, expressively free 246 statement 313 198, 222, 237, 255, 284, 294-
39, 40, 48, 51, 52, 116, 178, extension of an intension 275 intraposition 372,376 296,305,344,348,361
258, 261-264, 304, 337, 357, see also general extensionality island constraint 265 proof 92-94
372 theorem see also complex NP constraint statement 92
CPRA/A 334 extensional in tension 275, 276 isomorphisms
Keenan 24, 27, 29,178, 180,203,204,
criterion of logical adequacy see also general extensionality AO<PnIPn> ~ TP1 162, 175ff, 198 212, 216, 367
see logical adequacy theorem arbitrary isomorphism onto p* 296
Keenan and Faltz xi, 51, 139, 201, 248,
extensionality criterion 78-80 as complete homomorphism 91
318, 337, 340
decreasing function 231, 232 extraposition 368, 372ff B~FEJeIJ(BJ-lifted) 309
Keenan and Stavi 16, 17, 82, 85, 86,
decreasing N 109, 206 boolean properties of 61ff
115,242,244, 246
decreasing subset of a boolean algebra factive 367, 368 Cardp ~ w 234
Kinyarwanda 201, 215
85 false 153, 171,365, 368 definition 60
Kiparsky and Kiparsky 367
de dictu reading 258, 299, 305, 306, Faltz 28 extending self via 261, 262
Kipsigis 23
308,318, 348ff Fijian 23 F2 IX ~ X* 59, 110, 359
in relativized position 351, 352 filter 231,239 IBIB ~B 16,147 Ladusaw 366
validity of arguments involving 345- see also individual I Tp ITp, ~ Tp 154 Lakhota 66
351 first order logic 5, 11-15 passim, 31, isorftorphic coples of 2 59, 64 lambda 20ff, 103, 118, 223, 249-252
degree of having a property 134 39-41, 43-48 passim, 64, 65, p ~ (Ip)* 65,102 passim, 254ff, 299, 318, 343ff
DeMorgan law 112,113 84, 91, 94, 102, 107, 109, 110 power set characterized up to 30, Latin 26, 201, 212
de re reading 252,258, 299, 308, 318, formation rules 20, 33, 34, 36, 37, 40, 59,61,62 Leibnitz 154
345,348ff 118,255,258,262,343,351 power set of power set characterized lexical interpreting function 41, 104,
in relativized position 351,352 free generators 13, 14, 26, 361, 363, up to 13, 295, 369 189, 200, 204, 209, 229, 236,
validity of arguments involving 345- 369-371 passim Prop ~J* 359 246, 253ff, 343
382 INDEX 384 INDEX

Fregean condition increasing N 109 lexical interpreting function (cont'd) constraints on


see compositionality increasing simple determiners 243 constraints on 41, 105, 200, 209- meet dependent determiner 232
from increasing subset of a boolean algebra 212, 217, 224, 229ff, 339, meets condition 75
see source phrase 85,86 340, 364ff Mendelson 55, 112
functional application 35,37,105,119, independent expressions 107 see also logical constant metaphor 28
139, 140, 150, 254, 260, 275, individual lexicon 104 model xi,S, 7, 35,99, 104, 105,120-
345,358,374,375 definitions 48,62, 76, 103 see also vocabulary 134 passim, 152, 253, 255, 256,
function-argument relation 27 preliminary discussion 9ff, 30, 43 lifting theorem 278-283, 285, 288- 263,266,343,352,363
technical discussion 48ff 290, 293, 297, 299, 301, 303, modifier algebra 16
general extensionality theorem 286, see also intensional individual, argu- 307-310,314,331,332 modifer category 118
288, 299, 300, 303, 311, 312, ment algebra proof 280-282 modifyingly transparent function 336ff
331,332,336,344,346 individual approach to boolean com- statement 278,279 moments, as defined by atom formulas
proof 279,280 binations ofin tensions 294ff, 305 likely 368 and worlds 283,327
statement 277, 278 individual constant 5, 29 linking verb 327ff Montague xi, 1, 9, 18, 20, 21, 25, 26,
generalized justification theorem 102 lives on its arguments 86 29, 40, 48, 51, 124, 140, 275,
generator 11, 13, 14, 26, 83~85, 361~ Ineseno Chumash 27 locative 353
363,366 inference, rules of 108ff see stative locative Moravcsik 180
Gil 267 infinitival complement 14, 22, 23, 353, logical adequacy 2, 18, 41, 42
goal expression 152 371,372 logical consequence n-valued logics 11 0
Gordon 23 informativeness 2~4, 6, 42, 105 see entailment name etymologies 66
see also inclusion logical constants 81ff, 104, 123, 133, naming function 35-37,374
HD/B 91 -ing 226 151-157 passim, 187, 227ff, nationality adjectives 122ff
hard core 67 instrumental phrase 152, 196, 209, 210, 238ff, 340, 364 necessary 170, 353, 358, 360, 364, 368
have 235ff 335,337 logical equivalence of expressions 106 negative modifiers 124,314,323
Hebrew 66, 264, 265 intensional individual 285, 297, 342 logical form norninalization 186,187,219,221
here 156, 162,200 intensional individual definition of see correspondence between surface nominative 178ff
Hindi 260 variable interpretation 342 form and logical form non transparency
homomorphic inheritance theorem 288, intensionality, transparency, non-trans- logical implication see intensionality
300,303,307,308,331 parency 272ff see entailment nowhere 156, 162
proof 307,308 abstract nouns 190 logically 0 107 numerals 228
statement 288 accusative versus for 180 logically 1 107
homomorphism 12, 13, 15, 16,26 APs 119,308ff logically false 107 oblique 180
definition 91 conject~ral adjectives 74, 125, 314ff, logically trivial 107 oddness 127, 131, 132, 320-326, 328,
in core extensional semantics 95ff 316 logically true 107 339
see also complete homomorphism, definitions 276, 277 loose definition of variable interpreta- odor 70
homomorphic inheritance determiners 286 tion 342,343,345,348,349 ontological perfection 29, 30
theorem, justification theorem intersecting adjectives 313 -ly 150,340 ontology xi, 1, 5, 6, 29,30,41,43,47,
predicative hierarchy lambda and 257, 258, 343f[ 51,52,62-64,67,103,104,
Horace 214 linking verbs 13 9 m-transparen t function 109, 110, 190, 227, 233, 238,
negative adjectives 124 see modifyingly transparent function 246,273,274
idempotent modifer 157,158 PI 268, 286ff Malagasy 27,66,212, 215 order consistent modifer functions
idiom 28,29 P2 22, 268ff, 272f, 277, 303ff, 317ff, manner phrase 151,157, 196, 272 137ff,327
imply 354, 365 345ff Margi 264 overgeneration 127, 217ff, 265, 340,
improbable 366 Pn 30lff mean 354,358 341
'inclusion 105ff po/po 170 meaning-form correlation principle 27
see also entailment, informativeness PMs 151, 152 meaning postulate Partee 21
increasing function 231, 232, 317 prepositions 335ff see lexical interpretation function,
INDEX 385 INDEX 387

passive 14,26,118,169, 170, 196, 201, predicative hierarchy 33, 34, 40, 87, transparency very 133, 157, 192, 325f[
202f4292,354,368 102-104, 182, 185, 191, 196, see intensionality vocabulary 31, 35-38, 104, 118, 119,
impersonal 212,213 199,200, 203, 224, 341 transparent scalar adjectives 121, 122 122, 124, 150, 151, 181, 184,
morphology 212,215 preferred reading 21,22, 194, 206, 207, Trithart 23 189-191, 195, 204, 208, 212,
past participle 212, 226 251, 252, 257, 291, 292, 304 true 171, 364, 365, 368 228, 235, 252, 253, 287, 343,
patient analysis of ditransitives 193, 302 preserves (arbitrary) joins 88,91 truth values 5, 6, 11-13, 29, 30, 43ff, 358,375
perception, verbs of 164ff preserves (arbitrary) meets 89-91 62, 87-89, 95-98, 110, 253, VOS language 27
Perlmutter and Postal 373 preserves complements 90,91 273, 289, 290, 359 VSO language 27
Persian 264 preserves fmite joins 88, 91 see also 2, ontology
PFSIS 161 preserves fmite meets 89-91 Turkish 26,212 whether 369,370
pointwise algebra 82, 95, 96, 229, 233, probable 366, 368 with
236,237,248 pronoun 252, 253 unbounded intersection and union 49, see comitative phrase, instrumental
see also lifting theorem, J-lifted Prop 359ff 50,61 phrase, manner phrase
algebra proper function 161. 184 universe of discourse x~ 5, 29, 46-48, without 339, 340
pointwide approach to boolean combina- properties 50-52,64,78,109 word order 1, 19-24 passim, 27, 36-
tions of intensions 294ff, 305 boolean character of 63, 67ff upward entailing 366, 367 40 passim, 116
pointwise on the individuals 96-104, cognitively more primitive than Uto-Aztecan 26, 202 world 2, 6, 8, 42, 79, 80, 110, 227,
182, 191, 194, 195, 199, 294, individuals 63ff 274[f, 282ff, 308ff, 326, 335,
364,368 proverb 28 valency 202ff, 334, 337 340, 342, 345-350, 353, 360,
pointwise on the worlds 279,282-284, pussums 31 variable 5, 20-23, 29, 40, 118, 191, 365
288,301,303,335,359 250ff, 342ff see also interpretation, model
possessive 81, 85, 86, 118, 228, 235ff, raising 14,23,25, 372, 376 verb final language 27
248ff,260 razor, Occam's 110 verb initiallanguage 27 x-variant 254ff, 265ff, 343, 344
possible 170,353, 364 read out function 20, 41, 319 verbal extensor 20lff, 223, 33 7ff
possible world Reagan as zero 64
see world recipient analysis of ditransitives 193
power set reciprocal 202, 268-270
as atomic algebra 56 redundancy 220,322
as boolean algebra 47ff see also pragmatics
as complete algebra 55 reflexives 118, 202, 220, 250, 258ff
isomorphic to complete and atomic object controlled 250
algebra 59, 65 see also self
notation 10 reinterpretation
power set of power set 369ff see pragmatics
see also justification theorem relative clause 118, 122, 218, 225, 235,
PRAIA 161,335 250, 262ff, 352, 353, 369
pragmatics restricting algebra 129ff, 142ff
context 141, 156, 252, 253, 266, see also PRAIA
319,328,329 restricting modifiers 7, 8, 16, 26, 74,
redundancy and 13 2, 134, 220, 323, 120ff, 153, 16lff, 168, 184, 191,
326 249, 309ff, 317, 325, 326, 340,
reinterpretation, cause for 8, 134, 341
155 restrictingness inheritance theorem 313
speaker commitment 324,325 proof 331
predicate adjectives 139ff, 327ff statement 312
predicative 14-16, 22, 27, 118, 177ff resumptive pronoun 264
predicative algebra 15, 16, 191 Rosenbaum 372
386 INDEX

's 235ff, 248ff logical 241


scalar modifiers 119ff, 123, 132ff, 157, m-transparency 336, 340
326ff n 125, 314
scalarity as semantically basic 138 nom 178,192
scope 20-22,26,182-185,192-194, nt 297
206, 209ff, 251, 256, 257, 264, obI 180
302,351,371 of 181
self 250, 258ff, 343ff, 351, 352 on 196
semantic primitive pf 190
see ontology proper 32, 363
sentential complement 353ff r 122,310
shape adjectives 122ff subj 196ff
Shona 212 t 287,311
slash category 20, 31-35, 118, 119, to 178, 192ff, 215, 216
273, 275, 309 up 366
S0<Pn/Pn> 169, 198 var 252
social class adjectives 122ff subject matter phrase 152, 336
somewhere 155,162 subject-oriented PM 168-170, 196-
source phrase 152,163-170,210,211, 200, 209, 210, 217, 333, 334
335 suchthat 250, 262ff, 343ff, 352
speaker commitment surface form
see pragmatics see correspondence between surface
specifier 14, 17, 369 form and logical form
specifier algebra 17 surprise 354, 358
state of affairs SVO language 27
see world syncategorematic elements 37, 104,
stative locative 152-163,165,197,198, 127
335, 336 symmetric predicate 268
strange 357, 360, 362, 367, 368 synthetic expression 107
strict definition of variable interpreta- TB/B 320, 332
tion 342 Tee 276
strictly restricting function 136 Ti(: 274ff
subalgebra 16, 83, 86, 130, 162, 169, tell 302
233, 240, 297, 305, 320, 334 tense 12, 19,20,40, 155
subcategorization feature 7, 9, 20, 31, that (complementizer) 273, 302, 355ff
37 there 156, 162,200
ace 178,192 as dummy 373,375,376
across 180 think 353
additive 318 Thomason 208,353
arg 196ff to 371
c 125 total 276
case-marking features 17 8ff tough movement 22
dat 213ff transitive modifier function 136
fact 368 transitive AP 15, 118, 178, 190ff
for 179 transitive common noun 15, 118, 177,
hom 267 18lff
i 124,312

You might also like