Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

Journal of Business Ethics (2010) 96:425–434 Ó Springer 2010

DOI 10.1007/s10551-010-0475-4

Beyond Good and Evil: The Adiaphoric


Company Tommy Jensen

ABSTRACT. In this article, six demoralising processes in In relation to this, companies are, on the one
the context of the company are identified. These pro- hand, targeted as key-agents and one of the main
cesses promote a realm of ‘being-with’, in which out- drivers of change towards sustainable development
comes of human interaction are evaluated on rational (broadly defined as including green as well as social
grounds, and on whether or not a particular action issues). Companies are in this ‘pro-business’ camp
accorded with stipulated ethical rules. Thereby the realm
primarily considered as valuable assets for the quest
of ‘being-for’, in which individuals are supported to take
increased responsibility, is marginalized. The conclusion
of combating and finding solutions to environmental
made is that not only do the demoralizing processes sys- and social problems due to their entrepreneurial
tematically produce moral distance between humans, capacity and responsible stakeholder management
which weakens individual spontaneous outbursts of (Freeman, 2005; Prahalad, 2004). When companies
sympathy to take increased moral responsibility, they also are targeted as a problem in relation to sustainable
promise to release individuals from their moral ambiva- development, this is mainly framed as a governance
lence by declaring organised action morally indifferent. problem (current deficits in global governance and
Organisational action is, in other words, declared as adi- corporate governance). On the other hand, com-
aphoric – beyond good and evil. panies are depicted as one of the key-agents resisting
change. Companies are in this ‘business-sucks’ camp
KEY WORDS: adiaphorisation, business ethics, primarily considered as profit maximizers refusing
demoralising processes, morality
to abandon prevailing business objectives and ways
of creating economic value (Stieb, 2009; Walsh,
2005).
Introduction Although the description above is way too sim-
plified to do justice to the many complex discussions
Contemporary environmental and social planetary on companies’ role and capability as drivers for or
problems (global warming, species extinction, deg- against change found in the business ethics literature,
radation and depletion of natural resources, corrup- it is sufficient enough for making the point that both
tion, famine, poverty and inequality etcetera) have camps share common ground; collectives of artificial
casted their shadow over business. The discussion on bodies (companies as assemblies of humans, gover-
business ethics with regard to companies’ role and nance structures, rules, guidelines and policies) and
capability to take responsibility has in the era of human collectives are considered capable of having
globalisation gained momentum. The background to moral responsibility. Collectives of artificial bodies as
this momentum is basically that since companies ‘act well as human collectives are indeed vehicles,
within a set of structures that materially connect and importantly powerful sources, to avoid harm
them to one another and to factory workers’, their from being done (negative responsibility) as well as
families, governments, natural resources and eco- preventing or solving ethical dilemmas (positive
logical systems etcetera all over the world, ‘they have responsibility), but it is an ontological mistake to
responsibilities to concern themselves with the stretch moral responsibility beyond the individual
wellbeing’ of those effected (Young, 2004, p. 382; (Bevan and Corvellec, 2007; McMahon, 1995).
see also Held and McGrew, 2007; Heymann, 2006). Consequently, the position taken in this article is
426 Tommy Jensen

that moral responsibility belongs exclusively to bility as such is exclusively individual. In stark
individual human beings. contrast to other human domains (political, social,
However, taking this position does not imply that economical and legal), individuals cannot refrain
moral responsibility ‘is something within each of us from the moral domain as it is synonymous with
– our essential humanity – which resonates to the having to give up interaction, talk and action within
presence of this same thing in other human beings’ the human community (Benhabib, 1992). Moral
(Rorty, 1989, p. 189). It does not either imply that responsibility is in this sense thus something essential
there is a universal moral self, for example, that we to human beings.
are naturally good or bad; ‘humans are morally Taking moral responsibility, then, is challenging
ambivalent’ (Bauman, 1993, p. 10). In other words, because responsible action may require individuals to
even though moral responsibility is considered to act against established social norms, laws and rules in
belong exclusively to individual human beings, it is which the individual is embedded (Bauman, 1989,
crucial to stay sensitive to contexts. The moral 1993, 1995; Levinas, 1969; Løgstrup, 1997). Indi-
position taken here insists on contingencies, thus the vidual moral responsibility, as it is outlined here, is
notion that societies, and the individuals embedded essentially about exercising ‘one’s freedom of
in there, have no predestined path (either towards authorship and/or actorship as a choice between
human/inhuman, good/evil, altruistic/opportunis- good and evil’ (Bauman, 1995, p. 1; cf. Rorty,
tic). What is counted as moral and immoral, and 1989). The current situation, or the degree of free-
the way in which individuals perceive morality/ dom, under which the choice between good and
immorality, are socially historic and institutionally evil has to take place, might provide an explanation
dependent (Hume, 1739/1978; Rorty, 1989; to why an individual does not take moral responsi-
Willmott, 1998). bility, but it does not release the individual from
From the starting point that the social context of moral guilt (Bauman, 1989).
companies always allows for certain amounts of indi- Essentially, moral responsibility implies ‘not to
vidual moral responsibility (ten Bos, 1997), this article consider the Other any more as a specimen of a
has as purpose, first, to outline a moral philosophical species or a category, but as unique’, with its own
framework that illustrates the fragility of individual unique history, capabilities, needs and limitations
moral character and, second, to identify demoralizing (Bauman, 1995, p. 60; see also Benhabib, 1992). In
processes in companies to illustrate how these wield other words, moral responsibility is distinctively
forceful pressure on individuals to refrain from taking about ‘safeguarding and defending the uniqueness of
increased moral responsibility. Illuminating the fragil- the Other’ (Bauman, 1995, pp. 51–52). To take
ity of individual moral character and the identification increased moral responsibility requires that individ-
of demoralizing processes is important so as to pave uals transcend the realm of ‘being-with’ (Bauman,
way for critical conceptual discussions within business 1993, 1995). The realm of being-with is a social
ethics and stimulate researchers within the field to context where ‘individuals [live] alongside but
conduct critical field studies. independently of one another’ and where individuals
In the next section, a framework for individual primarily are indifferent to each others fate (Tönnies,
moral responsibility is outlined. In the subsequent 1887/2001, pp. 18–19). Although such a social
section, the demoralizing processes and implications context might be just, individuals are ‘essentially
on individual moral responsibility are identified. In detached’ and ‘remain separate in spite of everything
the last section, consequences of these demoralizing that unites them’, whilst in the realm of ‘being-for’
processes on individual moral responsibility are individuals ‘stay together in spite of everything that
discussed. separates them’ (Tönnies, 1887/2001, p. 52).
In stark contrast to the realm of being-with,
entering the realm of being-for implies entering a
Outlining moral responsibility context in which no corresponding deterministic or
probabilistic cause and effect exists (Bauman, 1993,
How to take responsible action can be negotiated 1995). Essentially, moral responsibility is permeated
and decided upon collectively, but moral responsi- by ambivalence since:
Beyond Good and Evil: The Adiaphoric Company 427

[T]he course of action is not-yet-determined. The tion, and on whether or not a particular action
dividing line between good and evil is not-yet-drawn. accords with stipulated rules (Bauman, 1993, 1995;
It is only the subsequent actions of the actors that will Jonas, 1984). Rather it is a type of reflective rea-
make the distinction, set apart good from evil, deter- soning that directs us towards increased sensibility –
mine the goodness and the evil of what will have been a meaning of the word that according to Rawls
done. There is no scenario written in advance, and the
(1971) comes close to the mundane meaning of
actors write the plot as they proceed, each being his or
her own director; and construe the language of writing
‘common sense’, which he argued needed to be
in the course of writing it. (Bauman, 1995, p. 64) upgraded within moral philosophy – so as to thereby
include more humans (distant in space and time) to
The leap from the realm of being-with to being- our realm of moral responsibility. Despite their dif-
for is not, and can never be, preceded by consider- ferent philosophical positions, this plea can be found
ation; it is an emotional spontaneous impulse that in the writings of Bauman (1993, 2008), Benhabib
lacks rational purposes and considerations of future (1992), Jonas (1984), Rorty (1989), Sen (2006) and
risks (Bauman, 1993, 1995; Hume, 1739/1978; Singer (2002).
Jonas, 1984). In the moral philosopher Hans Jonas’s Having outlined the foundation of individual
words ‘the revulsion of feeling [- - -] acts ahead of moral responsibility, the demoralising processes are
knowledge’ (1984, p. 27; or in Levinas terminology, turned to next.
1969, morality comes before being, before ontol-
ogy). An individual entering the realm of being-for
is ‘enclosed in the frame of sympathy, of the will- Demoralising processes in companies
ingness to serve, to do good, to self-sacrifice for the
sake of the Other’ (Bauman, 1995, p. 60). To Discontinuous reinvention of companies
rephrase an already made point, this implies a
readiness, which often has to manifest itself as This first demoralising process arises from the
disobedience to social norms, laws and rules widespread organisational movement (see, for
(Bauman, 1989, pp. 243–244). instance, Peters, 2003) that has as its aim to tear
Establishing that emotional spontaneous impulses down routines and to reinvent companies ‘decisively
are the starting point for moral responsibility does and irrevocably, so that the present becomes dis-
not rule out reason from the moral equation, nor continuous from the past’ (Sennett, 1999, p. 48).
does it render reason inferior to emotions.1 When Constant discontinuous reinvention makes organi-
the leap from being-with to being-for is done, sational life episodic (Bauman, 1998) by putting
emotions need guidance by reason; moral dilemmas upfront the demand on organisational members to
that individuals confront are eased up, but not produce now, instantly. Organisational members
resolved, through spontaneous, yet erratic, emo- become embedded in the notion that every day is a
tional actions. For Bauman (2002, pp. 215–216), this new beginning (Bauman, 2002).
erratic state of being needs to be supported by ethical As a consequence of this, organisational members,
reflection if individuals are to address the root as an individual or as part of a work group, have to
problems of our time; that our actions ‘here’ and prove his/her (most often: cost-benefit) value to the
‘now’ have remote effects ‘there’ and ‘then’ (e.g. company (Kotter, 1996; Sennett, 2006); otherwise
purchasing a product has remote effects on working they risk dismissal or transfer to new ‘opportunities’
conditions and workers salary thousands of kilome- within the company (Kallinikos, 2001; Sennett,
tres away and, in turn, the future possibilities for 1999). Furthermore, different members and groups
children to attend school since they have to help of the company are arranged so that they are in
parents with their work, looking after siblings and autonomous and competitive position towards each
doing household keeping). other (Hamel, 2007; Peters, 2003). In this type of
However, reason is not defined in its normal context, organisational members need to recognise
meaning, which is close to the term rationality; that that alliances are only profitable as long as they prove
is to say that action occurs under the condition that useful in promoting their career, and that they have
expectancy of returns follows from human interac- to exclude colleagues before they are themselves
428 Tommy Jensen

excluded. Consequently, the skill to disintegrate structure of [companies]. All these elements of
with parts of the social network that are not useful responsiveness make for an acceptance of decisive,
becomes essential for individual success (Bauman, disruptive change. (also see Alvesson, 1990)
2002, p. 65; Castells, 2000; Jensen and Sandström,
A key aspect enabling the organisation to imple-
2009).
ment flexible specialisation of production is infor-
In this organisational context, individuals face ‘the
mation technology (Castells, 2000), which makes it
task of weaving the mode of their togetherness from
possible to identify and make sense of stakeholder
scratch and with no promise of durability’ and it is to
demands on a global scale with little lagging in time
them ‘demonstrated again and again how whimsical
(probably most developed within consumer behav-
and unpredictable’ the organisational world is
iour, Peters, 2003). Information technology also
(Bauman, 2002, p. 62), which acts according to
enables dramatic reduction in time for production
‘rules of the game’ that workers fail to identify,
planning and production (reprogramming and con-
monitor and manipulate (regarding how and when
figuration of machines on a daily basis) (Sennett,
economic efficiency, labour productivity, company
1999, p. 52). Moreover, flexible specialisation of
profitability, etc., are defined and used). Decisions
production requires fast decision making and prob-
about who is next to fall victim to the process of
lem solving, which have caused a dramatic shift from
discontinuous reinvention of companies fall outside
the formal organisation to the temporary network
the reach of individuals to comprehend (Sennett,
(the project) (Castells, 2000; Ekstedt, et al., 1999;
1999, 2006). Numerous are the cases in which parts of
Pettigrew et al., 2003).
companies, or whole companies, have been shut
Flexible specialisation of production paves way for
down and where the workers, by themselves or
a ‘damaging measure of talent’ since the new version
voiced through union representatives, are chocked
of talent breaks with craftsmanship, broad skills and
and fail to understand on what grounds they and their
durability, and looks for individuals who have the
work groups have been considered to underperform.
capability to constantly learn new skills (Sennett,
According to recent research in social identity
2006, p. 115). More and more workers find them-
theory, this type of organising leads to individual
selves in the situation of signing until further
stress, decreased motivation, suspicion of fellow co-
notice employment contracts (temporary contracts)
workers (are you my colleague or ‘collegial com-
(Kallinikos, 2001; Sennett, 1999, 2006). It also
petitor’) and self-interest (Hogg and Terry, 2001).
becomes the responsibility of the worker to contin-
uously upgrade his/her skills and capabilities to avoid
becoming a victim to the process of downsizing and
Flexible specialisation of production
productivity changes aiming at doing more with less
(Bauman, 2002; Kallinikos, 2001; Sennett, 1999,
The second demoralizing process also helps to explain
2006).
the continuous search ‘for a change of a decisive,
This organisational context has profound effects
irreversible sort, disorganised or unproductive as it
on work ethics. When instability is considered
may be’ (Sennett, 1999, p. 51). Primarily, flexible
normal, work ethics has shifted from long-term
specialisation of production responds to changing
collective commitment to short-term individual
demands from external stakeholders (such as inves-
gains (Bauman, 1998; Hogg and Terry, 2001); as a
tors, consumers, business-to-business partners, lobby-
consequence ‘bonds of trust and commitment’ are
groups, non-governmental organisations etcetera).
loosened, and ‘will’ is divorced from ‘behaviour’
To speak through Pierre Bourdieu, external stake-
(Sennett, 1999, p. 31).
holders become a deputy to strategic management.
When companies seek to respond to outside-in
movements, Sennett (1999, p. 52) states that:
Concentration without centralisation of power
The most strongly flavored ingredient in this new
productive process is the willingness to let the shifting The third demoralizing process is a ‘way of con-
demands of the outside world determine the inside veying the operation of command in a structure
Beyond Good and Evil: The Adiaphoric Company 429

which no longer has the clarity of a pyramid – the of nobody (Arendt, 1969; Bauman, 1989, 1995,
[company] structure has become more convoluted, p. 99), making it hard to identify who is accountable
not simpler’. The word ‘debureaucratization’ is (an outstanding account of how it is to work in such
therefore misleading, top-down domination ‘is both a fluid social context is Franz Kafka’s novels ‘The
strong and shapeless’ (Sennett, 1999, pp. 56–57). In Trial’ and ‘The Castle’). It is, thus, difficult to
companies that succeed in practicing concentration prosecute any individuals, or individual elites, at the
without centralisation: centre of companies, whilst individuals and work
groups located in the periphery are exposed to
[p]ower becomes concentrated at the center; the constant threats of facing penalties (according to
institution’s central processing unit sets the tasks, jud-
Arendt, 1969, this is the worst form of tyranny).
ges results, expands and shrinks the firm. New analytic
Individuals working in this context cautiously avoid
technologies have enabled firms to engage in what
Michel Foucault has called ‘panoptic surveillance’; action that exposes them to the risk of being marked
these technologies put real-time maps of resources and out and isolated, thereby being distinguished from
performance on screen. (Sennett, 2006, p. 51) others, as wrong-doers. ‘Responsible action’ thus
equals behaving and acting in accordance to informal
Power has, at least partly, broken free from the as well as formal company rules and demands.
pyramid structures. Companies must therefore also
be conceived of as flat structures in which organi-
sational nodes are geared towards becoming auton- Differentiation through mediation of action
omous and loosely coupled with the centre of
domination (for example, Gary Hamel’s radical de- The fourth demoralizing process stands out as one of
centralisation, 2007, or Charles Handy’s federalist the most salient and seminal features of organisations
decentralisation, 1993). In practice, this means that (Arendt, 1963/1994; Bauman, 1989; Milgram,
nodes manage themselves but are lead from the 1974/2005). The major effect is ‘social production
centre. When concentration without centralisation of distance’ (Bauman, 1989, p. 199) and functional
of power is performed, the centre leads by dispersing division of labour and specialisation are essential for
mistakes, failures and certain responsibilities to the this type of distancing to occur. Performing tasks
periphery (Sennett, 1999, 2006). within a company that is organised through func-
Of course, power still runs through traditional tional division and specialisation, which all compa-
hierarchies, but the exercise of power comes in nies to different degrees are, implies that individual
many disguises and is ‘put to circulation by many action ‘here’, in this part of the organisation, and
different regimes’ (Kallinikos, 1996, p. 66; cf. Clegg effects ‘there’, in that part of the organisation, are
et al., 2006). This dynamic capacity stems from the distanced. More precisely, ‘intentions and practical
fact that bureaucratic coordinating mechanisms in accomplishments’ are distanced because ‘the space
companies no longer are dependent on disciplining between the two’ is mediated through a number
through physical presence; they also discipline digi- of actors, minute acts and events (Bauman, 1989,
tally (Kallinikos, 1996, 2001). Digital surveillance pp. 24–25).
and monitoring thus make it possible for bureau- The social distance is also constructed because of
cracy to reach out beyond traditional borders, even ‘the lack of similarity between the task at hand and
through loosely coupled networks (Jensen, 2008), the task of the [company] as a whole [- - -], which
suggesting that bureaucracy is also ‘at work’ in distances the contributor from the job performed by
so-called post-bureaucratic companies. Bureaucracy the [company] of which he is a part’ (Bauman, 1989,
has proved to have a remarkable capability to adjust pp. 99–100). The social production of distance is,
to disorder and turbulence (Courpasson and Reed, however, not only an internal organisational affair.
2004; Du Gay, 2000; Jensen, 2008; Jensen and Outcomes of individual actions stretch well beyond
Nylén, 2006; Kallinikos, 2004). the boundaries of the company, and, arguably,
The main effect of concentration without cen- the current globalisation process, which could be
tralisation of power is that companies becomes framed as a process compressing time and space
characterised by floating responsibility and the rule (global markets and global trade, instant and dense
430 Tommy Jensen

communication and coordination, Urry, 2003), legitimate authority (the researcher), the subjects
accelerates the social production of distance. Com- initial promise to take on the very experimental task,
panies take part in global processes in which they are and the task itself, gradually became more important.
materially connected to distant others; from the Although academic references to Milgram’s
company that places an order of, say clothes, to the experiments most often focus on the influence of
thousands and thousands of remote workers that authority, another crucial observation Milgram
produce these clothes in their homes. As for indi- makes, however, is that a majority of those partici-
viduals, companies also act within a set of structures pating in the experiments found themselves
that have no isolatable perpetrator; structural injus- becoming ‘so absorbed in the narrow technical
tice is mediated through a multitude of mediated aspects of the task that he loses sight of its broader
actors, minute acts and events that take place along consequences’ (1974/2005, p. 9). This process seems
global value-chains (Young, 2004). also to be self-enforcing; as Weber wrote (1964,
Individuals working in this ‘dual’ context, char- p. 117), ‘the more unconditionally the actor devotes
acterised by differentiation through mediation of himself to this value for its own sake, [- - -] the less is
action, are guided by coordinating principles that he influenced by considerations of the consequences
have as their purpose to physically and psychologi- of his action’ (see also Bauman, 1989; Jonas, 1984;
cally distance individual action ‘here’ from intra- and Milgram, 1974/2005).
inter-organisational consequences ‘there’. Conse- An individual that gradually becomes absorbed by
quently, lack of direct psychological and physical technological aspects of the task at hand, how this
experience has as consequence that individuals loose task could best be technically solved and carried out,
sight of the outcomes of his/her actions, causing pay lesser and lesser attention to dimensions and
moral distancing. Confronted with claims for in- consequences other than those belonging to the
creased moral responsibility, individuals’ fend-off technological realm of action. In a company in
such claims as ‘absurd’ and argue that ‘[w]e are not which substitution of technical for moral responsi-
the cause of the injustice [- - -], and we do not bility is established ‘[t]he options open to the actor in
control those who are’ (Young, 2004, p. 367; cf. his relation to the other’ shrinks and are reduced to
Bonnedahl et al., 2007). being evaluated from whether or not the option is
‘effective and ineffective, efficient and inefficient –
indeed, rational and irrational’ (Bauman, 1989,
Substitution of technical for moral responsibility p. 180).

The fifth demoralising process also ‘conceals the


moral significance of action’ (Bauman, 1989, Reduction to traits
p. 199). Technological responsibility is, however,
not a concept dealing with ‘technological’ problems, The increase of techniques that seek to make ‘human
such as seeking solutions to engineering or energy behaviour’ and everyday life ‘visible, inspectable and
problems; rather it is a term that is applicable to all manageable’ in organisations are an essential part of
kinds of human action. We thus can have a more or ‘the grand and ever-expanding project of the Wes-
less technological orientation towards decisions tern world’ (Kallinikos, 1996, p. 65). Consequently,
made in all areas of life, raising children, dealing with contemporary companies, and their organisational
personal problems etcetera. members, are ‘highly dependent on the kind of
Milgram’s (1974/2005) experiments, in which information that is codifiable and effectively trans-
students participated in an experiment under the mittable across time and space’ (Kallinikos, 1996,
fabricated condition that they were to deliver pun- p. 114; see also Callon, 1998; Callon and Muniesa,
ishment (electroshocks) to another person in order 2005; Jensen, 2004, 2006).
to see how the learning capacity was affected, The sixth demoralising process implies that per-
revealed that individuals’ moral responsibility is sons at which this kind of technical operation is
fragile. Despite the obvious agony that the victim aimed can be and are dissembled into a set of specific
expressed (a hired actor), obedience to a present traits (Bauman, 1989, p. 102; ten Bos, 1997,
Beyond Good and Evil: The Adiaphoric Company 431

p. 1004). We can say that out of these techniques another, or that the existence of one demoralizing
‘is born an accountable and predictable version of process might require that another one is put into
man which is essential to the instrumental experi- place.
ence’ (Kallinikos, 1996, p. 65; cf. Jensen et al., What is without doubt is that companies system-
2009). atically organise along the dimensions as described
Reduced to a set of traits, most notably through within each demoralizing process. Consequently,
quantitative measurements such as cost–benefit demoralizing processes are so to speak normal features
analysis, individuals are represented in terms that of contemporary companies and contemporary
‘‘are abstracted from ‘total persons’’’ (ten Bos, 1997, organising (Bauman, 1989; Jensen et al., 2009; Sen-
p. 1005). Reduced to kilograms, centimetres, litres, nett, 1999, 2006). Of course, common and contem-
purchasing power, annual income, work hours, porary practice of organising is normally not
salary, productivity, needs and wants, etc., individuals associated with negative outcomes on an individual
loose their distinctiveness and become an ‘entity, level. On the contrary, practice of organising is nor-
devoid of quality’ (Bauman, 1989, p. 103; Bonnedahl, mally associated with individual progression and
et al., 2007; Callon, 1998; ten Bos, 1997). Conse- betterment; individuals are empowered, their inner
quently, techniques for dissembling persons into creativity liberated, their motivation elevated, and,
specific traits wash away the possibility of those even, that they become more responsible.
divided up to have a just cause, to have interests and And, of course, there might be positive effects on
claims to subjectivity (Bauman, 1989, p. 104; ten Bos, power, creativity and motivation, but I strongly re-
1997). Human individuals become objectified. sist the idea that individuals are becoming more
Furthermore, the ‘standardized and abstract con- responsible. The moral perspective developed here
stitution’ (Kallinikos, 1996, p. 114) of techniques suggests that current ways and attempts of organising
that dissemble persons into a set of specific traits, come at a price; the corrosion of individual moral
creates a moral distance between decision makers character (Sennett, 1999). When an individual’s
and objectified persons. The language of quantifi- character corrodes, the capability of spontaneous
cation in particular, but in general any technique that outbursts of sympathy weakens (Bauman, 1989,
dissembles persons into traits, ‘is unfit for normative- 1993, 1995; Hume, 1739/1978; Sennett, 1999,
moral statements’ and therefore acts as a safeguard for 2006). In fact, in order to become successful, com-
decision makers (those who construct and/or use panies need to, at least partly, construct organisa-
such techniques) from normative-moral dimensions tional contexts that increase moral distance and
concerning individual persons (Bauman, 1989, weakens individuals capability of spontaneous out-
pp. 103, 116; Milgram, 1974/2005). bursts of sympathy (cf. Bevan and Corvellec, 2007;
Jackall, 1988; ten Bos, 1997). This context makes it
hard for individuals to take an increased moral
Conclusion: the adiaphoric company responsibility, or framed according to the earlier
developed moral perspective; to transcend the realm
The account of individual moral responsibility and of being-with to the realm of being-for.
the identification and description of demoralizing This article has been an attempt to critically assess
processes make it conceptually possible to compre- how organisational contexts hinder individuals from
hend how individual moral responsibility is nega- taking increased moral responsibility in companies.
tively affected by organisational contexts. However, Based on this assessment, the main conclusion is that
to what extent different companies coordinate we can expect only few individuals to succeed in
organisational action through these demoralizing making the leap from being-with to being-for. Hope
processes and to what extent individuals thereby for extended individual responsibility seems futile as
refrain from taking increased moral responsibility long as current organisational practice remains
is an empirical question – it is still up for scrutiny. uncontested.
It has also to be empirically investigated how However, more is at stake. Taken together, as a
demoralizing processes influence and condition each unity, the demoralizing processes also threatens to
other; how one might reinforce, or even cancel out, make another distinct negative imprint on individuals;
432 Tommy Jensen

they together carry with them a promise of releas- here, is that it is not possible to order and manage
ing individuals from their moral ambivalence, even morality. From this, Bauman argues that our times call
guilt, by declaring organised action morally indiffer- for morality without ethics at the same time as we live
ent. That is to say that organised action can no longer in a time of ‘ethically unfounded morality’ (1995,
be morally ambivalent since questions about human/ p. 18). However, ten Bos and Willmott (2001) misread
Bauman (notably they quote mainly Bauman’s 1993
inhuman, altruistic/opportunistic, empathy/indiffer-
book on postmodern ethics) as claiming that ethics and
ence, caring/exploitation are made into non-ques- morality are disengaged and that the former is irrelevant
tions. Organisational action is declared as exempt vis-à-vis the latter (moral scholasticism). Thus, the con-
from moral judgement and moral significance and clusion that Bauman ends up making emotions superior
is, in other words, declared as morally adiaphoric2; to rationality. In the subsequent book, Life as Fragments
‘neither good nor evil’ (Bauman, 1993, p. 125). (Essays in Postmodern Morality), Bauman argues that
Consequently, not only do companies that sys- ethics and morality, which in Bauman terminology cor-
tematically produce moral distance between humans, respond to reason and emotions as well as ethical
weakening individual spontaneous outbursts of authority from above (rules and laws) and autonomous
sympathy, run the risk of hindering individuals from moral subjects with their unfinished life projects, ‘grow
taking increased moral responsibility; they are also of the same soil: moral selves do not ‘discover’ their
risking annulling the question of moral responsibility ethical foundations, but [- - -] build them up whilst
they build up themselves’ (Bauman, 1995, p. 20). Bau-
as such! Refraining from taking individual moral
man’s moral position thus renders ethics insufficient to
responsibility in such an adiaphoric context would current praxis, but without taking away its capacity to
be considered as ‘a rational step to take, a legitimate influence everyday life. Bauman’s postmodern ethics, or
conclusion from a sober, ‘rational’ evaluation of the liquid ethics to use a more up to date term, as I see it,
possible and the feasible’ (Bauman, 2002, p. 216; rebalances the relation between reason and emotions.
Jensen, 2007). 2
‘The term adiaphoron belongs to the language of
Companies’ role and capability in the battlement ecclesia; it meant originally a belief or a custom de-
of contemporary environmental and social planetary clared by the Church indifferent – neither merit nor sin
problems are essential. If there is an upsurge of – and hence requiring no stand, no official endorsement
genuine adiaphoric companies, annulling the ques- or prohibition’. (Bauman, 1993, p. 125)
tion of moral responsibility for organised action,
then managers and employees in such companies
will most probably fail taking the kind of responsi-
bility that the social and environmental challenges References
demand from them. At worst, then, adiaphoric
companies take a leading role as a protector of the Alvesson, M.: 1990, ‘Organization: From Substance to
contemporary unsustainable society. Image?’, Organization Studies 11(3), 373–394.
Arendt, H.: 1963/1994, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report
on the Banality of Evil (Penguin books, New York).
Notes Arendt, H.: 1969, On Violence (Harcourt, Brace and
World, New York).
1
Within the context of business ethics, this moral Bauman, Z.: 1989, Modernity and the Holocaust (Polity
position has been criticised for not breaking the dualis- Press, Cambridge).
tic, antagonistic, relationship between reason and emo- Bauman, Z.: 1993, Postmodern Ethics (Blackwell Publish-
tion. ten Bos and Willmott (2001) use Bauman as a case ing, Malden, MA).
for making their point and argue that what Bauman Bauman, Z.: 1995, Life in Fragments. Essays in Postmodern
actually ends up in is an inversion of the hierarchical Morality (Basil Blackwell, Cambridge, MA).
relationship between reason and emotions; making Bauman, Z.: 1998, Work, Consumerism and the New Poor
emotions superior to reason. To me this type of critique (Open University Press, Celtic Court).
is misplaced. I will therefore discuss ten Bos and Bauman, Z.: 2002, Society Under Siege (Polity Press,
Willmott’s (2001) critique of Bauman since it has rele- Cambridge).
vance to the moral position taken in this text. A starting Bauman, Z.: 2008, Does Ethics Have a Chance in a World of
point for Bauman, and for the moral position developed Consumers? (Harvard University Press, London).
Beyond Good and Evil: The Adiaphoric Company 433

Benhabib, S.: 1992, Situating the Self: Gender, Community, Obligations, Benevolence, Editorial with an Analytical
and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics (Routledge, Index by L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2nd Edition with text
London). revised and variant readings by P. H. Nidditch (Clar-
Bevan, D. and H. Corvellec: 2007, ‘The Impossibility of endon Press, Oxford).
Corporate Ethics: For a Levinasian Approach to Jackall, R.: 1988, Moral Mazes: The World of Corporate
Managerial Ethics’, Business Ethics – A European Review Managers (Oxford University Press, Oxford).
16(3), 208–219. Jensen, T.: 2004, Översättningar av konkurrens i eko-
Bonnedahl, K. J., T. Jensen and J. Sandström: 2007, nomiska laboratorier: Om ekonomiska teoriers fören-
Ekonomi och Moral: Vägar mot Ökat Ansvarstagande kling, komplexitet och fördunkling i hälso- och
(Economy and Morality: Routes to Increased sjukvården (Translations of Competition in Economic
Responsibility) (Liber, Malmö). Laboratories: How Economic Theories are Simplified,
Callon, M.: 1998, ‘The Embeddedness of Economic Complex and Blurred Within Health Care). Doctoral
Markets in Economics’, in M. Callon (ed.), The Laws of Dissertation, Umeå University, Sweden.
the Markets (Blackwell Publishers, Oxford), pp. 1–57. Jensen, T.: 2006, ‘Fördunklad Organisering i en Het-
Callon, M. and F. Muniesa: 2005, ‘Economic Markets as erogent Materiell Värld’ (Blurred Organizing in a
Calculative Collective Devices’, Organization Studies Material Heterogeneous World), in D. Ericsson (ed.),
26(8), 1229–1250. Den Oavsedda Organisationen (The Unexpected Orga-
Castells, M.: 2000, ‘Materials for an Exploratory Theory nisation) (Academia Adacta, Lund), pp. 46–66.
of the Network Society’, British Journal of Sociology Jensen, T.: 2007, ‘Moral Responsibility and the Business
51(1), 5–24. and Sustainable Development Assemblage: A Jonasian
Clegg, S. R., D. Courpasson and N. Phillips: 2006, Power Ethics for the Technological Age’, International Journal
and Organizations (Sage, London). of Innovation and Sustainable Development 2(1), 116–129.
Courpasson, D. and M. Reed: 2004, ‘Introduction: Jensen, T.: 2008, ‘Voluntary Ghettos and Mobile
Bureaucracy in the Age of Enterprise’, Organization Bureaucracy. Civic Activity and Acts of Citizenship
11(1), 5–12. Under Threat’, in D. Hislop (ed.), Mobility and Tech-
du Gay, P.: 2000, In Praise of Bureaucracy. Weber, Organi- nology in the Workplace (Routledge, London), pp. 43–53.
zation, Ethics (Sage, London). Jensen, T. and U. Nylén: 2006, ‘Striving for Spontaneity:
Ekstedt, E., R. A. Lundin, A. Söderholm and H. Wir- Bureaucracy Strikes Back’, International Research Journal
denius: 1999, Neo-Industrial Organising, Renewal by Problems and Perspectives in Management 4(2), 144–158.
Action and Knowledge Formation in a Project-Intensive Jensen, T. and J. Sandström: 2009, ‘Global Trafficking
Economy (Routledge, London). Networks and Business Studies’, Tamara: Journal for
Freeman, R. E.: 2005, ‘Stakeholder Theory’, in P. H. Critical Organization Inquiry 7(3–4), 147–159.
Werhane and R. E. Freeman (eds.), The Blackwell Jensen, T., J. Sandström and S. Helin: 2009, ‘Corporate
Encyclopaedia of Management: Business Ethics (Blackwells, Codes of Ethics and the Bending of Moral Space’,
Oxford), pp. 496–500. Organization 16(4), 529–545.
Hamel, G. (with B. Breen): 2007, The Future of Manage- Jonas, H.: 1984, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of
ment (Harvard Business School Press, Harvard). an Ethics for the Technological Age (The University of
Handy, C.: 1993, ‘Balancing Corporate Power: A New Chicago Press, Chicago).
Federalist Paper’, McKinsey Quarterly (3), 159–182. Kallinikos, J.: 1996, Technology and Society. Interdisciplinary
Held, D. and A. McGrew: 2007, ‘Introduction: Global- Studies in Formal Organisations (Accedo Verlagsgesells-
ization at Risk?’, in D. Held and A. McGrew (eds.), chaft mbH., Munich).
Globalization Theory: Approaches and Controversies (Pol- Kallinikos, J.: 2001, The Age of Flexibility, Managing
ity Press, Cambridge), pp. 1–11. Organizations and Technology (Academia Adacta, Lund).
Heymann, J.: 2006, Forgotten Families: Ending the Growing Kallinikos, J.: 2004, ‘The Social Foundations of the
Crisis Confronting Children and Working Parents in the Bureaucratic Order’, Organization 11(1), 13–36.
Global Economy (Oxford University Press, Oxford). Kotter, J. P.: 1996, Leading Change (Harvard Business
Hogg, M. A. and J. T. Terry: 2001, Social Identity Processes School Press, Harvard).
in Organizational Contexts (Psychology Press, Phila- Levinas, E.: 1969, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exte-
delphia). riority (Duquesne University Press, Pittsburgh, PA).
Hume, D.: 1739/1978, A Treatise of Human Nature: Løgstrup, K. E.: 1997, The Ethical Demand (University of
Being an Attempt to Introduce the Experimental Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, Indiana).
Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects, book 3: McMahon, C.: 1995, ‘The Ontological and Moral Status of
‘‘Of Morals’’ – A Treatment of Moral Ideas, Justice, Organizations’, Business Ethics Quarterly 5(3), 541–554.
434 Tommy Jensen

Milgram, S.: 1974/2005, Obedience to Authority: An ten Bos, R. and H. Willmott: 2001, ‘Towards a Post-
Experimental View (Pinter and Martin Ltd., London). dualistic Business Ethics: Interweaving Reason and
Peters, T.: 2003, Re-Imagine. Business Excellence in a Dis- Emotion in Working Life’, Journal of Management
ruptive Age (Dorling Kindersley, London). Studies 38(6), 769–793.
Pettigrew, A. M., R. Whittington, L. Melin, C. Sánchez- Tönnies, F.: 1887/2001, Community and Civil Society
Runde, F. A. J. Van Den Bosch, W. Ruigrok and (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge).
T. Numagami: 2003, Innovative Forms of Organizing Urry, J.: 2003, Global Complexity (Polity Press, Cam-
(Sage, London). bridge).
Prahalad, C. K.: 2004, The Fortune at the Bottom of the Walsh, J. P.: 2005, ‘Book Review Essay: Taking Stock of
Pyramid: Eradicating Poverty Through Profits (Prentice Stakeholder Management’, Academy of Management
Hall, London). Review 30(2), 426–438.
Rawls, J.: 1971, A Theory of Justice (Harvard University Weber, M.: 1964, The Theory of Social and Economic
Press, Massachusetts). Organization. Edited with an introduction by Talcott
Rorty, R.: 1989, Contingency, Irony and Solidarity (Cam- Parsons (The Free Press, New York).
bridge University Press, Cambridge). Willmott, H.: 1998, ‘Towards a New Ethics? The Con-
Sen, A.: 2006, Identity and Violence. The Illusion of Destiny tributions of Poststructuralism and Posthumanism’,
(W.W. Norton and Company, New York). in M. Parker (ed.), Ethics and Organizations (Sage,
Sennett, R.: 1999, The Corrosion of Character. The Personal London), pp. 76–121.
Consequences of Work in the New Capitalism (W.W. Young, I. M.: 2004, ‘Responsibility and Global Labor
Norton & Company Ltd, London). Justice’, The Journal of Political Philosophy 12(4),
Sennett, R.: 2006, The Culture of the New Capitalism (Yale 365–388.
University Press, New Haven).
Singer, P.: 2002, One World: The Ethics of Globalization Umeå School of Business,
(Yale University Press, New Haven). Umeå, Sweden
Stieb, J. A.: 2009, ‘Assessing Freeman’s Stakeholder E-mail: tommy.jensen@usbe.umu.se
Theory’, Journal of Business Ethics 87(3), 401–414.
ten Bos, R.: 1997, ‘Essay: Business Ethics and Bauman
Ethics’, Organization Studies 18(6), 997–1014.

You might also like