Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 3

Antonin Scalia: The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules

56 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1175, 1175-81 (1989)

. . Tom Paine . . . said

[L]et a day be solemnly set apart for proclaiming the charter; let it be brought
forth . . . [so] the world may know, that as far as we approve of monarchy, that in
America the law is king. For as in absolute governments the king is law, so in free
countries the law ought to be king; and there ought to be no other.

In his Politics, Aristotle states:

Rightly constituted laws should be the final sovereign; and personal rule, whether
it be exercised by a single person or a body of persons, should be sovereign only
in those matters on which law is unable, owing to the difficulty of framing general
rules for all contingencies, to make an exact pronouncement.It is this dichotomy
between "general rule of law" and "personal discretion to do justice" that I wish to
explore.

[In particular,] I want to explore the dichotomy between general rules and
personal discretion within the narrow context of law that is made by the courts. In a
judicial system such as ours, in which judges are bound, not only by the text of code or
Constitution, but also by the prior decisions of superior courts, and even by the prior
decisions of their own court, courts have the capacity to "make" law. ... [W]hen the
Supreme Court of the federal system, or of one of the state systems, decides a case, not
merely the outcome of that decision, but the [standard of decision] that it applies will
thereafter be followed by the lower courts within that system, and even by that supreme
court itself. And by making the [standard] relatively [broad and definite] or relatively
fact-specific [and judgmental], the courts can either establish general rules or leave ample
discretion for the future.
* * * * * * * * * *

The advantages of the discretion-conferring approach are obvious. All


generalizations (including, I know, the present one) are to some degree invalid, and hence
every rule of law has a few corners that do not quite fit. It follows that perfect justice can
only be achieved if courts are unconstrained by such imperfect generalizations. ...

Of course, in a system in which prior decisions are authoritative, no opinion can leave
total discretion to later judges. It is all a matter of degree. At least the very facts of the
particular case are covered for the future. But sticking close to those facts, not relying
upon overarching generalizations, and thereby leaving considerable room for future
judges is thought to be the genius of the common-law system. The law grows and
develops, the theory goes, not through the pronouncement of general principles, but case-
by-case, deliberately, incrementally, one-step-at-a-time. Today we decide that these nine
facts sustain recovery. Whether only eight of them will do so -- or whether the addition
of a tenth will change the outcome -- are questions for another day.

When I was in law school, I was a great enthusiast for this approach -- an advocate of
both writing and reading the "holding" of a decision narrowly, thereby leaving greater
discretion to future courts. Over the years, however -- and not merely the years since I
have been a judge -- I have found myself drawn more and more to the opposite view.
There are a number of reasons, some theoretical and some very practical indeed.

To begin with, the value of perfection in judicial decisions should not be overrated. To
achieve what is, from the standpoint of the substantive policies involved, the "perfect"
answer is nice -- but it is just one of a number of competing values. And one of the most
substantial of those competing values, which often contradicts the search for perfection,
is the appearance of equal treatment. As a motivating force of the human spirit, that
value cannot be overestimated. Parents know that children will accept quite readily all
sorts of arbitrary substantive dispositions -- no television in the afternoon, or no
television in the evening, or even no television at all. But try to let one brother or sister
watch television when the others do not, and you will feel the fury of the fundamental
sense of justice unleashed. . . . And the trouble with the discretion-conferring approach
to judicial law making is that it does not satisfy this sense of justice very well. When a
case is accorded a different disposition from an earlier one, it is important, if the system
of justice is to be respected, not only that the later case be different, but that it be seen to
be so. When one is dealing, as my Court often is, with issues so heartfelt that they are
believed by one side or the other to be resolved by the Constitution itself, it does not
greatly appeal to one's sense of justice to say: "Well, that earlier case had nine factors,
this one has nine plus one." Much better, even at the expense of the mild substantive
distortion that any generalization introduces, to have a clear, previously enunciated rule
that one can point to in explanation of the decision.

* * * * * * * * * *

[There is] . . . another obvious advantage of establishing as soon as possible a clear,


general principle of decision: predictability. Even in simpler times uncertainty has been
regarded as incompatible with the Rule of Law. Rudimentary justice requires that those
subject to the law must have the means of knowing what it prescribes. It is said that one
of emperor Nero's nasty practices was to post his edicts high on the columns so that they
would be harder to read and easier to transgress. As laws have become more numerous,
and as people have become increasingly ready to punish their adversaries in the courts,
we can less and less afford protracted uncertainty regarding what the law may mean.
Predictability, or as Llewellyn put it, "reckonability," is a needful characteristic of any
law worthy of the name. There are times when even a bad rule is better than no rule at
all.

I had always thought that the common-law approach had at least one thing to be said
for it: it was the course of judicial restraint, "making" as little law as possible in order to
decide the case at hand. I have come to doubt whether that is true. For when, in writing
for the majority of the Court, I adopt a general rule, and say, "This is the basis of our
decision," I not only constrain lower courts, I constrain myself as well. If the next case
should have such different facts that my political or policy preferences regarding the
outcome are quite the opposite, I will be unable to indulge those preferences; I have
committed myself to the governing principle. In the real world of appellate judging, it
displays more judicial restraint to adopt such a course than to announce that, "on
balance," we think the law was violated here -- leaving ourselves free to say in the next
case that, "on balance," it was not. It is a commonplace that the one effective check upon
arbitrary judges is criticism by the bar and the academy. But it is [very difficult] to
demonstrate the inconsistency of two opinions based upon a "totality of the
circumstances" test ... . Only by announcing rules do we hedge ourselves in.

While announcing a firm rule of decision can thus inhibit courts, strangely enough it
can embolden them as well. Judges are sometimes called upon to be courageous, because
they must sometimes stand up to what is generally supreme in a democracy: the popular
will. Their most significant roles, in our system, are to protect the individual criminal
defendant against the occasional excesses of that popular will, and to preserve the checks
and balances within our constitutional system that are precisely designed to inhibit swift
and complete accomplishment of that popular will. Those are tasks which, properly
performed, may earn widespread respect and admiration in the long run, but -- almost by
definition -- never in the particular case. The chances that frail men and women will
stand up to their unpleasant duty are greatly increased if they can stand behind the solid
shield of a firm, clear principle enunciated in earlier cases. It is very difficult to say that a
particular convicted felon who is the object of widespread hatred must go free because,
on balance, we think that excluding the defense attorney from the line-up process in this
case may have prevented a fair trial. It is easier to say that our cases plainly hold that,
absent exigent circumstances, such exclusion is a per se denial of due process.

I stand with Aristotle, then -- which is a pretty good place to stand -- in the view that
"personal rule, whether it be exercised by a single person or a body of persons, should be
sovereign only in those matters on which law is unable, owing to the difficulty of framing
general rules for all contingencies, to make an exact pronouncement."

You might also like