Nicomachean Ethics Is The Name of A Series of

You might also like

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 8

A.

VIRTUE ETHICS There are two central components of virtue


Nicomachean Ethics is the name of a series of ethics: the concept of virtue, and the concept of
books that Aristotle wrote about ethics. In these character.
writings, he uses logic to determine a definition A good person is a virtuous person, one with a
and the potential impacts of ethics. He starts his certain sort of character.
presentation of ethics with a simple assumption: Moral virtues are those qualities of a
humans think and behave in a way to achieve personality that are valuable for everyone to
happiness, which Aristotle defined as the have, whether they are offensive tackles, cyclist,
constant consideration of truth and behavior or anyone else. Possessing and acting on the
consistent with that truth. virtues amounts living a morally worthwhile and
Aristotle defines virtue as the average, or flourishing life for human being.
'mean,' between excess and deficiency.
Partial list of typical moral virtues: loyalty,
Meaning of VIRTUE ETHICS by Aristotle honesty, fairness, kindness, courage,
 Aristotle's perspective on ethics was considerateness, civility, compassion,
based on the virtue of being human; friendliness, patience, self-reliance, generosity,
 There are two important distinctions and dependability.
between Aristotle's approach to ethics According to Aristotle, many virtues are the
and the other predominant perspectives midpoint, or “golden mean” between related
at the time. vices of deficiency or excess. Virtue is a sort of
 First, Aristotle did not consider ethics just Goldilocks zone. Here are some examples.
a theoretical or philosophical topic to
study. To understand ethics, Aristotle Too little Just right Too much
argued, you actually have to observe how Stingy Generous Wasteful
people behave. Cowardly Courageous Reckless
 That led to the second distinction. Ethics Cranky Friendly Sucking
weren't about ''what if'' situations for up/brown-
Aristotle; instead, he took a very practical nosing
approach and much of his ideas on ethics False Honesty about Bragging
were based on what someone did and modesty oneself
how their virtues impacted their actions. Anorexia Moderate Gluttony
consumption
VIRTUE ETHICS sloth ambition Workaholic
The final ethical theory on deck is also the most
ancient, endorsed by religion such as Islam and What is character?
with a pedigree going back to Aristotle’s Virtue theory, the virtues are not specific
discussion in nichomachean ethics. It is the idea behaviors or actions so much as they are habits
that morality isn’t about outcomes (like of character. No single action demonstration
utilitarians think), or rule following (like kant much, if anything, about one’s character. rather,
and Christians think), but about being a certain character is a tendency is a tendency to act in
type of person. Instead of obsessing about good certain sorts of ways.
actions, we ought to focus on what it is to be a
good person. Character is the sort of thing that comes in
This is the idea of virtue ethics. Virtue is an degrees.
appealing way to understand morality. Instead of  So someone with a strong character is
a daunting calculus that must take every actual dependable, steady, unflinching,
and future person into account, or some rigid unwavering, steadfast, and reliable.
and abstract moral law, virtue is within the grasp
 Someone with a weak character is fickle,
of everyone.
weak, faithless, irresolute, erratic,
capricious, and incontinent.
ethics is the notion of character, the idea that
Objections to virtues ethics each person has tendency to act in certain sorts
Objection 1: Virtue is compatible with evil the of way given the appropriate situation.
first objection to virtue theory is that it seems
entirely possible to cultivate and endorse the B. ARISTOTLE CONCEPT OF HAPPINESS
classic moral virtues and still participate in Aristotle's first contention in this regard is that
considerable wickedness. When Salvatore Lo subjective conceptions of happiness fall down
Piccolo, the capo the Sicilian Mafia was arrested
miserably on this score. Sometimes our desires
in 2017, the police found a written code of
behavior for the mob. Here’s the Mafia’s “ten are satisfied, but instead of feeling pleasure or
commandments” satisfaction, we in fact become perplexed with
1. No one can present himself directly to another ourselves, even to the point of self-alienation. A
of our friends. There must be a third person to man who desires a yellow sports car more than
do it. anything, who sacrifices mightily to obtain it,
2. Never look at the wives of friend. may wonder, when he has it in his possession
3. Never be seen with cops.
why exactly he had wanted it so very badly.
4. Don’t go to pubs and clubs.
5. Always available for Cosa Nostra is a duty- Further, even if we do feel satisfied when our
even if your wife is about to give birth desires are realized we may in truth do so
6. Appointments must absolutely be respected, despite the fact of our having develop desires
7. Wives must be treated with respect that are not worthy of us.
8. When asked for any information, the answer
must be the truth. Happiness and the human function
9. Money cannot be appropriated if it belongs to
It may come as a surprise that human beings
others or to other family
10. People who can’t be part of Cosa Nostra: have a function. Computers and can-openers
anyone who has a close relative in the police, have functions, to compute and to open cans. We
anyone with two-timing relative in the family, know that these sorts of artefacts have functions,
anyone who behaves and doesn’t hold to moral and we have no trouble identifying what they
values. are, for the simple that we gave them the
Lo Piccolo’s list emphasizes honesty, respect,
functions they have. We designed them with
duty, and moral values. Traditional Mafia
morality also includes absolute loyalty to the specific purposes in mind. Matters are not so
family, the omertá code of silence, and the clear with the functions of human beings. To
prohibition on harming a made man. begin, Aristotle denies that human beings are
Objection 2: Clashing virtues virtue ethics designed by the activity of any form of
advises that the good life consists in cultivating intentional agent. Yet he does not suppose that
all the virtues. It is a good thing to be honest, but this precludes our manifesting functions. Final
it is even better if you are a kind person too.
causes occur in nature, he contends in the
Option 1. It is a much kinder and considerate
response absence of intentional design. If that is so, then it
Option 2. More honest should be possible to identify a human function,
Objection 3 relativism about virtues the third which in turn will provide a basis of a functional
objection is that what qualities of character that account of human goodness. That is, just as we
count as virtues and which count of vices seems may easily that a good can-opener is a can-
heavily dependent on the culture which you are opener which opens cans well, we should
raised.
likewise be able to say that a good human being
Objection 4. There is no such thing as character
the final objection of virtue ethics comes from a human being who performs the human
experimental psychology and perhaps the most function well. The key then, is to specify the
powerful complaint. The essential of virtue human function.
Aristotle's identification of the human good , according to Aristotle, sensibly say that we
progresses in the form of his function argument were happy between lunch and dinner, but not
(FA): during either.
1 The function of any given kind F is determined Aristotelian happiness (eudaimonia), to
by isolating the unique and characteristic activity underscore our first two features, is neither
of Fs. fleeting nor a feeling; still less is it, then, any sort
2. The unique and characteristic activity of of fleeting feeling.
human beings is reasoning. Once he has identified the human
3 Hence, the function of human beings is (or function in these terms, it is a
centrally involves) reasoning short step for Aristotle to characterize the
4 Exercising a function is an activity (where, in human good in his canonical expression (EN
living beings, this will be the actualization of 1098a161-17):
some capacity of the soul). • Happiness (eudaimonia) = df an activity of the
5 Hence, exercising the human function is an soul expressing reason in a virtuous manner.
activity of the soul in accordance with reason.
The function argument has proven controversial. In conclusion
Many regard it as wholly unpersuasive. Even so, Happiness is the ultimate purpose of human
some - though not all – of the difficulties critics existence
locate in the argument result from Happiness is living well
misunderstandings. Happiness is the final end or Goal that
encompasses the totality of life
Thus, Aristotle concludes, the human good Happiness is not subjective
consists in leading a fully and characteristically Happiness is not a pleasure
human sort of life. This conclusion high lights Happiness depends on the cultivation of virtue
three distinctive features of Aristotle's account of
human happiness: (i) happiness is an activity; “He is happy who lives in accordance with
(ii) happiness is objectively rather than complete virtue and is sufficiently equipped with
subjectively determined; and (iii) happiness is external good, not for some chance period but
forever rather than fleeting. throughout a complete life” (Nichomachean
First, then, human happiness is a kind of living Ethics, 1101a10)
and is thus an activity rather than a passive state As Aristotle says “for as it is not one swallow or
or affective experience: happiness is a doing one fine day that makes a spring, so it is not one
rather than a being. That is, the best form of life day or short time that makes a man blessed and
is active rather than passive. This is yet another happy”
reason why a human being would not, upon “the function of man is to live a certain kind of
rational reflection a pink pleasure pill when life, and this activity implies a rational principle,
offered: feeling pleasure is an affective state, and the function of a good man is the good and
whereas the best form of human life involves the noble performance of these, and if an action is
execution of plans ad projects. well performed it is performed in accord with
He cites with approval a famous dictum of appropriate excellence: if this is the case, then
Solon's: 'Look to the end' (EN 1100a10-11), by happiness turns out to be an activity of the soul
which he means that we cannot stably judge in accordance with virtue. (Nichomachean Ethics
whether someone is happy before the end of 1098a13)”
their life.
C.TELOS OR THE ULTIMATE END The telos of living things:

Aristotle, the ancient Greek father of western The purposes of the natural features of living
philosophy, thought so, and he called that things; example are wings for flying, ears for
purpose, telos (pronounced ‘TELL-os’ or ‘TAY- hearing.
los’). The word telos means purpose, intent, end,
D. MORAL VIRTUE AS GOOD HABIT
or goal.

Aristotle has this special meaning of “the state in


Nicomachean Ethics: Books I to IV
Scholars do not agree on where the name for
which something’s nature is fulfilled”, or where
the Nicomachean Ethics comes from. Both
something is fully “in act”. Aristotle’s father and his son were named
Nicomachus, so it is possible that the book is
Also, In Aristotle, Physics II.9, where his theory
of telos is most fully worked out, is said to be dedicated to either one. Other scholars suggest
talking “Teleologically because he asserts that that Aristotle’s son may have edited the book
everything that moves, is moved in part by a type after Aristotle died, so that the title
of cause called the telos, i.e. that towards “Nicomachean” may refer to this particular
which the thing moves. In this sense telos is where edition of Aristotle’s ethical works.
something is supposed to be.
Summary
Teleological ethics (teleological from Happiness is the highest good and the end at
Greek telos, “end”; logos, “science”) theory which all our activities ultimately aim. All our
of morality that derives duty or moral obligation activities aim at some end, though most of these
from what is good or desirable as an end to be ends are means toward other ends. For example,
achieved. we go grocery shopping to buy food, but buying
food is itself a means toward the end of eating
Also known as consequentialist ethics, it is well and thriftily. Eating well and thriftily is also
opposed to deontological ethics (from the not an end in itself but a means to other ends.
Greek deon, “duty”), which holds that the basic Only happiness is an end in itself, so it is the
standards for an action’s being morally right are ultimate end at which all our activities aim. As
independent of the good or evil generated) such, it is the supreme good. The difficulty is that
people don’t agree on what makes for a happy or
In the book of Solomon & Greene Morality and the good life, so the purpose of the Ethicsis to find an
Good Life, one of the most important Aristotle’s answer to this question. By its nature, the
theory, that of a thing telos or end, is developed in a investigation is imprecise because there are so
similar way from his many studies of the natural
many variables involved when considering a
world, Aristotle concluded that nature is
person’s life as a whole.
purposive, that “she does nothing in vain”. That is
Aristotle defines the supreme good as an activity
everything (almost) has a particular purpose for
which it is the best suited, and that purpose or goal of the rational soul in accordance with virtue.
is what Aristotle calls it Telos. Virtue for the Greeks is equivalent to excellence.
A man has virtue as a flautist, for instance, if he
Included in this account are not only natural plays the flute well, since playing the flute is the
objects such as plants and animals, but man made distinctive activity of a flautist. A virtuous person
artifacts as well. is someone who performs the distinctive activity
of being human well. Rationality is our
The telos of human artifacts distinctive activity, that is, the activity that
distinguishes us from plants and animals. All
The purposes of human-created artifacts; living things have a nutritive soul, which governs
example are books for reading, chairs for growth and nutrition. Humans and animals are
sitting. distinct from plants in having a sensitive soul,
which governs locomotion and instinct. Humans
are distinct above all for having also a rational and don’ts but rather in the same kind of striving
soul, which governs thought. Since our after excellence that might make an athlete train
rationality is our distinctive activity, its exercise hard. The Greek word ethos, from which we
is the supreme good. derive the word ethics, literally means
Aristotle defines moral virtue as a disposition to “character,” and Aristotle’s goal is to describe
behave in the right manner and as a mean what qualities constitute an excellent character.
between extremes of deficiency and excess, The important lesson to draw from Aristotle’s
which are vices. We learn moral virtue primarily Doctrine of the Mean is that virtue consists of
through habit and practice rather than through finding an appropriate middle ground between
reasoning and instruction. Virtue is a matter of
two extremes. As such, each virtue has not one
having the appropriate attitude toward pain and
pleasure. For example, a coward will suffer opposite but two. The opposite of courage is
undue fear in the face of danger, whereas a rash both cowardice and rashness, for example. This
person will not suffer sufficient fear. Aristotle idea that there are two opposites for every virtue
lists the principle virtues along with their goes against much of the received wisdom of
corresponding vices, as represented in the Aristotle’s time, including Plato’s writings on
following table. A virtuous person exhibits all of virtue. It also emphasizes the importance of
the virtues: they do not properly exist as distinct Sphere of
qualities but rather as different aspects of a action or
virtuous life. feeling Excess (vice) Mean (virtue) Deficiency (vice)
Fear and
confidence Rashness Courage Cowardice
Pleasure and
We can only be held responsible for actions we pain Licentiousness Temperance Insensibility
Getting and
perform voluntarily and not for cases involving spending
physical compulsion or unavoidable ignorance. (minor) Prodigality Liberality Illiberality
The best measure of moral judgment is choice, Getting and
spending
since choices are always made voluntarily by (major) Vulgarity Magnificence Pettiness
means of rational deliberation. We always Honor and
choose to aim at the good, but people are often dishonor
(major) Vanity Magnanimity Pusillanimity
ignorant of what is good and so aim at some Honor and
apparent good instead, which is in fact a vice. dishonor Proper
(minor) Ambition ambition Unambitiousness
Anger Irascibility Patience Lack of spirit
Analysis
The Nicomachean Ethics advances an Self-expression Boastfulness Truthfulness Understatement
understanding of ethics known as virtue Conversation Buffoonery Wittiness Boorishness
ethicsbecause of its heavy reliance on the
Obsequiousness
concept of virtue. The word we translate Social conduct or flattery Friendliness Cantankerousness
as virtue is aretê, and it could equally be Shame Shyness Modesty Shamelessness
translated as “excellence.” Something has aretê if Righteous Malicious
it performs its function well. A good horseman, Indignation Envy indignation enjoyment
for example, has the aretê of being good at moderation: we achieve virtue by finding a
handling horses, and a good knife has middle ground, not by aiming for an extreme.
the aretê of sharpness. For the Greeks, moral Where exactly this middle ground lies, however,
virtue is not essentially different from these
is less obvious. Aristotle repeats a number of
other kinds of excellence. The Greeks do not
have a distinctive concept of morality like we do, times that his table presents only a rough
which carries associations of sanctity or duty. approximation and that virtues lie closer to one
Moral virtue is simply a matter of performing vice than another to different extents for
well in the function of being human. For the different people. The Table of Virtues just
Greeks, the motivation for being good is not presented is not intended as a set of exact rules.
based in a divine legislator or a set of moral dos
On the contrary, Aristotle argues that a truly happiness unless we exercise those virtues.
virtuous person will naturally be inclined to Courageous people who never test their courage
behave appropriately and will have no need of by facing down fear have virtue, but they are not
rules. happy. Aristotle illustrates this distinction
Aristotle is clear that we arrive at moral virtue between happiness and virtue by saying that the
primarily through practice and that the value of best athletes only win at the Olympic Games if
studying ethical texts such as the one he has they compete. A virtuous person who does not
written is limited. This view makes sense when exercise virtue is like an athlete who sits on the
we consider that moral virtue is not essentially sideline and watches. Aristotle has a proactive
different from other forms of excellence as far as conception of the good life: happiness waits only
the Greeks are concerned. If we want to achieve for those who go out and seize it.
excellence in rock climbing, for instance, it helps
Ethical Virtue as Disposition
to study texts that show us how to improve our
technique, but we can’t make any significant Aristotle describes ethical virtue as a “hexis”
improvements except by getting on a rock wall (“state” “condition” “disposition”)—a tendency
or disposition, induced by our habits, to have
and practicing. Analogously, it helps to read texts
appropriate feelings (1105b25–6). Defective
like the Nicomachean Ethics to get a clearer states of character are hexeis (plural of hexis) as
understanding of moral virtue, but the only way well, but they are tendencies to have
to become more virtuous is through practice. We inappropriate feelings. The significance of
can only become more courageous by making a Aristotle's characterization of these states
point of facing down our fears, and we can only as hexeis is his decisive rejection of the thesis,
found throughout Plato's early dialogues, that
become more patient by making a habit of
virtue is nothing but a kind of knowledge and
controlling our anger. Since practice, not study, is vice nothing but a lack of knowledge. Although
the key to becoming virtuous, Aristotle takes a Aristotle frequently draws analogies between
strong interest in the education of the young. He the crafts and the virtues (and similarly between
perceives that there is only so much we can do to physical health and eudaimonia), he insists that
improve a nasty adult, and we can more easily the virtues differ from the crafts and all branches
mold virtuous youths by instilling the proper of knowledge in that the former involve
appropriate emotional responses and are not
habits in them from a young age.
purely intellectual conditions.
Aristotle calls happiness an “activity,” which
distinguishes his conception of happiness both Furthermore, every ethical virtue is a condition
from our modern conception of happiness and intermediate (a “golden mean” as it is popularly
known) between two other states, one involving
from virtue, which Aristotle calls a “disposition.”
excess, and the other deficiency (1106a26–b28).
We tend to think of happiness as an emotional In this respect, Aristotle says, the virtues are no
state and hence as something we are, rather than different from technical skills: every skilled
as something we do. The Greek word generally worker knows how to avoid excess and
translated as “happiness” is eudaimonia, and it deficiency, and is in a condition intermediate
can equally be rendered as “success” or between two extremes. The courageous person,
for example, judges that some dangers are worth
“flourishing.” People who are eudaimon are not
facing and others not, and experiences fear to a
in a particular emotional state so much as they degree that is appropriate to his circumstances.
are living successfully. While happiness is the He lies between the coward, who flees every
activity of living well, virtue represents the danger and experiences excessive fear, and the
potential to live well. Excelling in all the moral rash person, who judges every danger worth
virtues is fine and good, but it doesn’t ensure our facing and experiences little or no fear. Aristotle
holds that this same topography applies to every objectionable. A critic might concede that in
ethical virtue: all are located on a map that some cases virtuous acts can be described in
places the virtues between states of excess and Aristotle's terms. If, for example, one is trying to
deficiency. He is careful to add, however, that the decide how much to spend on a wedding
mean is to be determined in a way that takes into present, one is looking for an amount that is
account the particular circumstances of the neither excessive nor deficient. But surely many
individual (1106a36–b7). The arithmetic mean other problems that confront a virtuous agent
between 10 and 2 is 6, and this is so invariably, are not susceptible to this quantitative analysis.
whatever is being counted. But the intermediate If one must decide whether to attend a wedding
point that is chosen by an expert in any of the or respect a competing obligation instead, it
crafts will vary from one situation to another. would not be illuminating to describe this as a
There is no universal rule, for example, about search for a mean between extremes—unless
how much food an athlete should eat, and it “aiming at the mean” simply becomes another
would be absurd to infer from the fact that 10 phrase for trying to make the right decision. The
lbs. is too much and 2 lbs. too little for me that I objection, then, is that Aristotle's doctrine of the
should eat 6 lbs. Finding the mean in any given mean, taken as a doctrine about what the ethical
situation is not a mechanical or thoughtless agent does when he deliberates, is in many cases
procedure, but requires a full and detailed inapplicable or unilluminating.
acquaintance with the circumstances.
A defense of Aristotle would have to say that the
It should be evident that Aristotle's treatment of virtuous person does after all aim at a mean, if
virtues as mean states endorses the idea that we we allow for a broad enough notion of what sort
should sometimes have strong feelings—when of aiming is involved. For example, consider a
such feelings are called for by our situation. juror who must determine whether a defendant
Sometimes only a small degree of anger is is guilty as charged. He does not have before his
appropriate; but at other times, circumstances mind a quantitative question; he is trying to
call for great anger. The right amount is not some decide whether the accused committed the
quantity between zero and the highest possible crime, and is not looking for some quantity of
level, but rather the amount, whatever it action intermediate between extremes.
happens to be, that is proportionate to the Nonetheless, an excellent juror can be described
seriousness of the situation. Of course, Aristotle as someone who, in trying to arrive at the correct
is committed to saying that anger should never decision, seeks to express the right degree of
reach the point at which it undermines reason; concern for all relevant considerations. He
and this means that our passion should always searches for the verdict that results from a
fall short of the extreme point at which we would deliberative process that is neither overly
lose control. But it is possible to be very angry credulous nor unduly skeptical. Similarly, in
without going to this extreme, and Aristotle does facing situations that arouse anger, a virtuous
not intend to deny this. agent must determine what action (if any) to
take in response to an insult, and although this is
The theory of the mean is open to several
not itself a quantitative question, his attempt to
objections, but before considering them, we
answer it properly requires him to have the right
should recognize that in fact there are two
degree of concern for his standing as a member
distinct theses each of which might be called a
of the community. He aims at a mean in the sense
doctrine of the mean. First, there is the thesis
that he looks for a response that avoids too much
that every virtue is a state that lies between two
or too little attention to factors that must be
vices, one of excess and the other of deficiency.
taken into account in making a wise decision.
Second, there is the idea that whenever a
virtuous person chooses to perform a virtuous Perhaps a greater difficulty can be raised if we
act, he can be described as aiming at an act that ask how Aristotle determines which emotions
is in some way or other intermediate between are governed by the doctrine of the mean.
alternatives that he rejects. It is this second Consider someone who loves to wrestle, for
thesis that is most likely to be found example. Is this passion something that must be
felt by every human being at appropriate times shameful and ugly. Determining what is kalon is
and to the right degree? Surely someone who difficult (1106b28–33, 1109a24–30), and the
never felt this emotion to any degree could still normal human aversion to embracing difficulties
live a perfectly happy life. Why then should we helps account for the scarcity of virtue
not say the same about at least some of the (1104b10–11).
emotions that Aristotle builds into his analysis of
the ethically virtuous agent? Why should we
experience anger at all, or fear, or the degree of
concern for wealth and honor that Aristotle
commends? These are precisely the questions
that were asked in antiquity by the Stoics, and
they came to the conclusion that such common
emotions as anger and fear are always
inappropriate. Aristotle assumes, on the
contrary, not simply that these common passions
are sometimes appropriate, but that it is
essential that every human being learn how to
master them and experience them in the right
way at the right times. A defense of his position
would have to show that the emotions that figure
in his account of the virtues are valuable
components of any well-lived human life, when
they are experienced properly. Perhaps such a
project could be carried out, but Aristotle himself
does not attempt to do so.
He often says, in the course of his discussion, that
when the good person chooses to act virtuously,
he does so for the sake of the “kalon”—a word
that can mean “beautiful”, “noble”, or “fine” (see
for example 1120a23–4). This term indicates
that Aristotle sees in ethical activity an attraction
that is comparable to the beauty of well-crafted
artifacts, including such artifacts as poetry,
music, and drama. He draws this analogy in his
discussion of the mean, when he says that every
craft tries to produce a work from which nothing
should be taken away and to which nothing
further should be added (1106b5–14). A craft
product, when well designed and produced by a
good craftsman, is not merely useful, but also has
such elements as balance, proportion and
harmony—for these are properties that help
make it useful. Similarly, Aristotle holds that a
well-executed project that expresses the ethical
virtues will not merely be advantageous
but kalon as well—for the balance it strikes is
part of what makes it advantageous. The young
person learning to acquire the virtues must
develop a love of doing what is kalon and a
strong aversion to its opposite—the aischron, the

You might also like