Psiquiatría y Filosofía

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 18

The Pathogenesis

of Auditory Verbal
Hallucinations in
Schizophrenia:
A Clinical–
Phenomenological
Account Mads Gram Henriksen,
Andrea Raballo and
Josef Parnas

A
Abstract: Although hallucinations are among the uditory verbal hallucinations
most studied psychiatric symptoms, their pathogenesis (AVHs) form an essential criterial feature
remains largely unknown and their experiential com- in the schizophrenia definition in the Diag-
plexities are rarely accounted for. In schizophrenia, nostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders
auditory verbal hallucinations are by far the most
(DSM)-IV (American Psychiatric Association
frequently reported type of hallucination. In this study,
we explore verbal hallucinations in schizophrenia 1994) and International Classification of Diseases
and we argue that these are best understood not as (ICD)-10 (World Health Organization 1992). In
abnormal perceptions, but as cognitive phenomena both classificatory systems, the presence of a hal-
arising from a partial dissolution of certain structures lucinatory voice that continuously comments the
of self-consciousness. Consistent with recent empirical patient’s behavior or thoughts, or the presence of
and conceptual studies in phenomenological psychia- several voices that discuss the patient with each
try, we claim that specific alterations of self-awareness
other, is a sufficient criterion to diagnose schizo-
tend to precede the emergence of verbal hallucinations
in schizophrenia. We illustrate these altered states of phrenia (if the duration criterion is fulfilled and
self-awareness in three detailed case vignettes of hallu- the exclusion criteria are not). The DSM-IV defines
cinating schizophrenia spectrum patients. We propose a a hallucination as “a sensory perception that has
clinical–phenomenological account of the pathogenesis the compelling sense of reality of a true percep-
of verbal hallucinations in schizophrenia, suggesting tion but that occurs without external stimulation
that pathological changes in the experience of space of the relevant sensory organ” (American Psychi-
and morbid objectification of inner speech may lead to
atric Association 1994). This definition is largely
crystalized verbal hallucinations.
consistent with the traditional definition of hallu-
Keywords: auditory verbal hallucinations, pathogen- cinations as perceptions without external stimuli,
esis, schizophrenia, self-disorders, phenomenology which basically has remained unchanged in the

© 2016 by The Johns Hopkins University Press


166  ■  PPP / Vol. 22, No. 3 / September 2015

history of psychiatry since Esquirol introduced the sensory–perceptual but rather cognitive phenom-
term hallucination in 1817 (Berrios 1996, 37f.). ena arising from a partial dissolution of certain
Despite the definition’s long endurance, it has been structures of self-consciousness (Ey 1973; Sass
widely criticized (Behrendt 1998; Leudar et al. and Parnas 2003). The reason for voicing these
1997; Liester 1998; Lothane 1982; Stanghellini concerns is not merely a definitional matter (i.e.,
and Cutting 2003)—not least because it presup- of having a more appropriate nosological descrip-
poses, as Esquirol explicitly did (1838, 200f.), that tion), but relates to the fact that research into the
all hallucinatory experiences, independent of the pathogenesis of AVH in schizophrenia is likely to
sense modality involved, are somehow uniform be misleading, even flawed, as long as these are
and conceivable in the light of one specific type of defined as abnormal perceptions, which implicitly
hallucination, namely that occurring in the visual facilitates a search for causes in terms of errors in
modality. Although hallucinations may occur in the processing of external sensory stimuli (Larøi
all sense modalities in schizophrenia, patients most et al. 2010; Stanghellini and Cutting 2003).
frequently report auditory hallucinations and only During the last decades, attempts have been
to a lesser extent visual and tactile hallucinations made to redefine AVHs as disorders of self-con-
(Baethge et al. 2005). Besides the debatable views sciousness, and more specifically to explain their
of uniformity and of the primacy of vision, there pathogenesis by referring to the occurrence of cer-
are other problems with the definition. First, it is tain altered states of self-awareness that frequently
simply not correct that hallucinations necessarily precede the emergence of AVHs in schizophrenia
occur without stimuli—often they have certain (Ey 1973; Naudin 1997; Naudin and Azorin 1997;
experiential precursors (as we will show in this Sass 1992, 231-235; Tatossian 2007). Our article
article) and they may also be triggered by stimuli complements phenomenological studies (Larøi et
from sense modalities not involved in the actual al. 2010; Raballo and Larøi 2011; Sass and Parnas
hallucination (the so-called reflex hallucinations). 2003; Stanghellini and Cutting 2003), which so
Second, obviously there are similarities between far have been quite theoretical, dense, and limited
perceptions and hallucinations, but there are also with regard to clinical descriptions. Although these
important differences. For example, perceptions studies have provided seemingly different explana-
are usually experienced actively in the sense that tions to the explanandum (AVHs), for example,
they are controlled by a goal-directed or willed ‘hyperreflexivity’ (Sass 1992), ‘ipseity disturbance’
attention and they occur in the public domain. (Sass and Parnas 2003), and ‘morbid objectifica-
Moreover, they involve the integration of multiple tion of inner dialogue’ (Stanghellini and Cutting
sense modalities and they are closely dependent on 2003), these explanations are not really competing
a sensory motor reciprocity within the physical or incompatible, but merely highlighting different
space (e.g., the intensity of a sound is affected by aspects of the same underlying experiential trans-
moving toward or away from its source or by the formation. The aim of our article is to further elu-
interposition of barriers). In contrast, hallucina- cidate the pathogenesis of AVHs in schizophrenia
tions are typically experienced more passively (i.e., by providing detailed clinical descriptions of the
the patient does not control them), they usually altered states of self-awareness and their cohe-
involve only a single sense modality, and they are sion, which will enable us to qualify, refine, and
often experienced as intrinsically private. In other clinically ground the existing phenomenological
words, hallucinations do usually not conform accounts of AVHs. More generally, our intention is
to the physical constraints of the peri-personal, to familiarize the clinician with these altered states
sensorial space, but are rather ‘superimposed’ on of self-awareness that often precede the formation
it (e.g., hallucinatory voices are ubiquitous and of AVHs and other psychotic symptoms in schizo-
unrestrained by physical barriers that would at- phrenia, thereby enriching the psychopathological
tenuate sounds; Merleau-Ponty 2002, 395; Larøi resources to recognize impending psychotic states
et al. 2010). From a phenomenological perspec- before their full-blown manifestation.
tive, AVHs in schizophrenia are not primarily
Henriksen, Raballo, and Parnas / Pathogenesis of Hallucinations  ■ 167

The Phenomenological voices appeared, I had a tinnitus-like whistling


like a beeping sound from a television. Then I
Architecture of AVHs in got the impression of hearing somebody talking
Schizophrenia about me. Now, the voices are like a murmur
When referring to verbal hallucinations in in the background.” Similarly, one of Bleuler’s
schizophrenia, there is an implicit tendency to patients described the indistinct auditory quality
understand them as univocal and quite well- of his ‘voices’ in the following way: “The voices
defined phenomena. From a phenomenological are unlike spoken voices but are as if thought”
or clinical perspective, hallucinatory voices are (Bleuler 1950, 114). In our view, hallucinatory
not just ‘voices.’ Rather, they form a wide and voices seem to be given to patients in a sort of
heterogeneous group of phenomena marked by direct inner intuition (Anschauung) rather than in
multiplicity of manifestations, for example, with a sensory perception (Sinneswahrnehmung)—or,
regard to their clarity (ranging from murmur to quoting Sass, “as if heard with the mind rather
voices), volume (from whispering to shouting), than the ear” (1992, 233).
linguistics (they can be only words, sentences, or Additionally, it is important to note that pa-
full dialogues), content (which often is demeaning, tients rarely seem to mistake their hallucinatory
humiliating, or threatening), and form of address voices for real voices in the external world. For
(where running commentary or arguing voices are example, Zucker (1928) found that hallucinating
particularly important in schizophrenia). In addi- patients that were presented with a real analogue
tion, they may vary with respect to their location of their hallucinatory experience (created by the
(i.e., they can be experienced as located within experimenters) were able to distinguish the hal-
the patient’s interior psychic space or as located lucinatory experience from the real perception
externally) and degree of insight (patients may and identify which one was real. Comparably,
recognize the hallucinations as abnormal)—these Aggernæs (1972) examined seven pairs of ‘real-
two aspects in particular have influenced the clini- ity qualities’ (sensation vs. ideation, behavioral
cally and theoretically dubious distinction between relevance vs. irrelevance, publicness vs. private-
hallucinations and pseudohallucinations (Berrios ness, objectivity vs. subjectivity, existence vs. non-
1996, 49-59; Berrios and Dening 1996), where the existence, involuntary vs. voluntary, independence
latter often is taken to mean either hallucinations vs. dependence) in 45 hallucinations (41 auditory
with insight or vivid internal imaginary (Taylor [39 verbal], 3 visual, and 1 tactile) in 41 chronic
1981). For example, when a chronic schizophre- schizophrenia patients. Although he found that
nia patient from time to time becomes aware of most hallucinations resembled normal percep-
the fact that she is hallucinating, this insight into tions with regard to 6 of the 7 reality qualities,
illness does not necessarily alter the phenomenal the crucial quality of publicness was negative in
quality of her AVHs in any significant way. Besides 30 of 45 hallucinations (Aggernæs 1972). These
varying along these lines, a closer exploration of studies seem to suggest that the majority of verbal
what patients refer to as ‘hearing voices’ further hallucinations are experienced as private and inac-
blurs the picture, for example, patients will often cessible to others, that is, that patients with schizo-
say that the hallucinatory voices do not neces- phrenia rarely mistake their hallucinatory voices
sarily have a clear acoustic or auditory quality, for voices that are ‘real’ in the sense of existing in
and they hardly ever say that they hear the voices the intersubjective space. Consequently, we find
through their ears. In contrast, when asked to the predominant cognitivist conception of AVHs
further describe their hallucinatory voices, some as errors of source or reality monitoring debatable
of our patients said: “often, I cannot tell if I have a (Bentall and Slade 1985; Garrett and Silva 2003;
thought, if it’s the voice, or if it’s a feeling I have,” Morrison and Haddock 1997), because it seems
“the voice seems partly real, but at the same time to presuppose that patients believe that their hal-
distorted. It can also appear as a face or a text. I lucinatory voices are real. In other words, we are
cannot really describe the sound,” or “before the skeptical about some of the underlying presump-
168  ■  PPP / Vol. 22, No. 3 / September 2015

tions, for example, that a propositional belief tations is the presence of a pervasive experiential
about the reality status of the hallucination neces- distance or dissociation between the sense of
sarily is involved in the experience, that ‘voices’ self (ipseity) and the flow of consciousness. This
constitute a quite univocal phenomenon, and that experiential distance tears apart or disunites the
mistaking ‘voices’ for real is at all essential to the normally unbreakable unity of the experiencing
hallucinatory experience. The French phenom- self and its thinking and brings along disturbing
enologist, Merleau-Ponty, argued against related forms of defamiliarization and self-alienation,
positions in his seminal book Phenomenology of which potentially affect all modalities of con-
Perception: “But in fact the insane do not believe sciousness and threatens to fragment the self from
they see, or, when questioned, they correct their within. What seems to be essential to auditory
statements on this point. A hallucination is not a hallucinatory experiences are, in our view, not
judgment or a rash belief, for the same reasons really their acoustic or auditory properties, but
which prevent it from being a sensory content: the rather that the experiential distance in this case
judgment or the belief could consist only in posit- has brought about pathological changes in the
ing the hallucination as true, and this is precisely experience of space and an incipient morbid au-
what the patients do not do” (2002, 390; author’s tomation and objectification of inner speech. Both
italics). In our view, Merleau-Ponty’s account is aspects are examined carefully and illustrated with
too radical, because some patients report that quotes and vignettes from schizophrenia spectrum
they at some point in the course of illness were patients describing non-psychotic alterations of
confused about the ‘voice’s’ status of reality (e.g., self-awareness and cognition.
patients sometimes say that when the ‘voice’ first The basic idea that certain deformations of self-
appeared, they turned around to see if someone awareness are core features of schizophrenia was a
was standing there or that they once asked their view shared by many classical psychopathologists
intimates if they could hear someone talking (Berze 1914; Berze and Gruhle 1929; Blankenburg
about them). Other cognitivist accounts of AVHs 1971; Bleuler 1911/1950; Conrad 1959; Kraepe-
are more consistent with the phenomenological lin 1913; Minkowski 1927; Schneider 1950; Ey
conception of these phenomena as involving a 1973). For example, Ey wrote: “depersonalization
disturbance of intentionality (Hoffman 1986) is the negative primary disorder [le trouble négatif
and being preceded by certain deformations of primordial] of the whole hallucinatory experi-
self-awareness (Frith 1979). ence. And in this sense it corresponds to the first
manifestation of the destructuration of the field of
Experiential Precursors to consciousness” (1973, 298; our translation). What
AVHs is meant here with “destructuration” of the field
of consciousness is a decomposition of the normal
In this section, we present a different account structures of experiencing, which primordially af-
of AVHs in schizophrenia, one that focuses on fects the phenomenal character of the experience
experiential precursors to fully formed AVHs, itself, that is, the evidentness of lived experience
namely, schizophrenia-specific alterations of self- in the very actuality of its manifestation to the
awareness and disorders of cognition, rather than experiencing subject (Parnas and Sass 2010).
beliefs and failures of reality testing. We suggest During the last 25 years, the search for schizo-
that, although the preceding pathological process phrenia specific alterations of self-awareness has
may vary, certain deformations of self-awareness been systematically incorporated into clinical
and cognition are constitutive for the restructuring research programs aiming at identifying and de-
of self-consciousness in the prodromal phase of tecting non-psychotic alterations of self-conscious-
schizophrenia and for the subsequent formation ness in schizophrenia—the most distinguished
of AVHs. We present detailed clinical material of psychometric assessment instruments to detect
these alterations shortly, but in advance just note these alterations are the BSABS (Bonn Scale for
that what seems to underlie their various manifes- the Assessment of Basic Symptoms; Gross et al.
Henriksen, Raballo, and Parnas / Pathogenesis of Hallucinations  ■ 169

1987), EASE (Examination of Anomalous Self- or attentional disturbances) and evokes certain
Experience; Parnas et al. 2005a), and SPI (Schizo- compensatory responses (e.g., introspective scru-
phrenia Proneness Instrument; Schultze-Lutter et tinizing to reassert a feeling of control). These
al. 2007). Empirical studies founded on the BSABS consequential and responsive outcomes of the
have documented transitional sequences from non- ipseity disturbances can, as indicated in the follow-
psychotic disorders of cognition and stream of ing vignettes, contribute to the ways in which the
consciousness (the so-called ‘basic symptoms’) to diachronic pathogenetic pathways are played out
florid Schneiderian first-rank symptoms, and they in schizophrenia, for example, by increasing the
found that of particular importance were thought sense of self-alienation, the feeling of disembodi-
pressure, thought interference, and obsessive- ment, and the fragmentation of meaning.
like perseveration (Klosterkötter 1988, 1992;
Klosterkötter et al. 2001). The majority of schizo- Case Vignettes
phrenia spectrum patients, who later develop
hallucinatory voices, report these self-perceived, In this section, we present vignettes of clusters
non-psychotic changes in the prodromal phase. of anomalies of self-experience reported by three
It seems, therefore, reasonable to have a closer schizophrenia spectrum patients. The vignettes
look at how patients experience these phenomena, were retrieved from first-admitted patients hos-
which are often accompanied by a panoply of pitalized at the Psychiatric Center Hvidovre dur-
other disturbances involving other domains such ing the clinical field test of a novel psychometric
as self-presence, bodily experiences, and demarca- instrument for the examination of anomalous
tion problems. We are aware of the risk that the self-experience, namely, the EASE scale (Parnas
following clinical descriptions of certain anoma- et al. 2005a). All patients were recruited upon
lous self-experiences (or ‘self-disorders’) might informed consent. The patients portrayed in the
be interpreted as either strictly necessary for the vignettes exemplify typical cases of referrals to
subsequent formation of verbal hallucinations or public mental health setting. In this sense, they
as reified, independent symptoms merely occurring do not display any extraordinary or unusual
together. Initially, we therefore warn against such psychopathology, but exemplify the combination
interpretations. Our aim is not to overly emphasize of behavioral and experiential phenomena that
certain self-disorders or infuse the selected ones subtend some prototypical presentations of clinical
with strong pathogenetic value at the expense schizophrenia spectrum conditions.
of others that might be virtually as relevant, but
to portray a self-constellation or, we could say,
Case 1
a structure of self-consciousness vulnerable to Hanna, 29, describes persistent thought pres-
schizophrenia and the emergence of AVHs. Despite sure disabling her from having any peace of
the fact that these anomalous self-experiences tend mind—“it feels as if my head is exploding, like a
to persist, the self-constellation is to some extent pressure boiler with the lid blowing off.” Thoughts
dynamic in the sense that, even though there seems may come so rapidly that she does not have time
to be a baseline of trait-like self-disorders, these to “think them through,” and the content of these
may, as in any other psychiatric symptomatology, thoughts is often totally disconnected from the
fluctuate in terms of intensity, while other anoma- context of her main line of thoughts. Although she
lies may appear or disappear dependent on, for clearly recognizes these thoughts as her own, she
example, situational stressors and life events. We still conceives them as “strange and impersonal,”
agree with Parnas and Sass (2008, 268f.), when primarily because she lacks control of them. She
they claim that these anomalous self-experiences reports that her thoughts, besides being spoken
reflect a primary ipseity disturbance that not only aloud internally by her own voice, also occur in
prefigures the positive and negative symptoms that moving images—“like an inner movie.” She de-
may emerge but also elicits some rather automatic scribes that this inner movie always runs and that
consequences (e.g., non-volitional hyperreflection her main line of thoughts and the imaged thoughts
170  ■  PPP / Vol. 22, No. 3 / September 2015

expressed in the inner movie not necessarily cor- has been living inside this bubble and regularly it
respond, and that she therefore may have two dif- gets, as he puts it, “so foggy that I lose contact
ferent lines of thoughts occurring simultaneously. with the outside world.” In these situations, he
When she closes her eyes, the images in the inner is unable to communicate with others, but more
movie often become macabre, for example, she generally he also finds that his native language is
often sees children screaming. Despite its pictorial not sufficiently precise to express his experiences.
content, this pseudo-obsession occurs with only Therefore, he considers learning Latin, because he
minimal resistance and it does not really provoke at one point was told that it is the most precise
anxiety. Rather, she describes that the macabre language in the world. Moreover, he is able to
images are somehow intertwined with a feeling spatially locate his thoughts inside the bubble and
that she is supposed to help someone and this co- he is “almost able to see” his thoughts, which he
incides with her general attitude—“I feel that I am reports appear like on a filmstrip. He describes
brought into this world to help others.” Moreover, a peculiar distance to his own thoughts—“they
she frequently experiences that she cannot express are my thoughts but not me,” which he further
her thoughts, that is, that her expressions do not explains with an analogy: “it’s like when I put
correspond with what she wanted to express—“it’s on my jacket. It’s my jacket, but it’s not me.” He
as if my brain and mouth are disconnected.” She experiences thought blockage, which he describes
claims that the alterations of cognition described as “a kind of paralysis or feeling of emptiness” or
are the source of her long-lasting concentration “a shrieking emptiness or silence,” and intrusive
difficulties and that since her teens she regularly forms of derealization.
has inflicted pain on herself (cutting) to dampen In addition, the patient reports self-disorders in
her thoughts and gain a moment of inner peace. the remaining EASE domains, most pronounced
Moreover, the patient reports multiple self- are passivity phenomena, Weltuntergangsstim-
disorders in the domain of self-awareness and that mung, transitivistic experiences, primary self-refer-
of existential reorientation, scoring 20 EASE items ence, and solipsistic grandiosity. In total, he scored
in total. She has negative symptoms, vague delu- 27 EASE items dispersed over all five domains. In
sions, and a hallucinatory voice that constantly addition, he has hallucinatory voices commenting
comments her thoughts and actions—fulfilling the on his behavior, and bizarre, religious, and perse-
criteria for paranoid schizophrenia. With regard cutory delusions. He was diagnosed with paranoid
to the male voice she hears, she may sometimes schizophrenia.
argue with it aloud or try to provoke it, and she is
sometimes able to spatially locate this voice to the Case 3
right side of her head, whereas her own thoughts John, 30, fears that his “brain might burn out”
are located to the left. and that he regularly feels a “sort of pressure on
the brain”—“I experience a murmur inside the
Case 2 head. It’s as if I am standing in a field in stormy
David, 29, reports that he already from child- weather listening to the wind. It feels as if wind
hood felt different from others, “robot-like” as is blowing directly on my brain.” This experience
he puts it, and he often doubted “if others have a is usually accompanied by a complete empti-
soul or any feelings.” He does not know who he ness of thoughts, and in such situations, he can
is, and he can feel that his identity is dissolving. transiently experience a disruption of normally
He describes a worsening at the time of puberty. It automatic movements. For example, he may find
started, he explains, when he began to analyze all it difficult to walk because, as he puts it, “when I
kinds of words, which caused not only the mean- expect to move the left foot, the body moves the
ing of these words, but “every meaning to float right foot.” When he hears the murmur or wind
until nothing made sense.” He felt apathetic and blowing on his brain, it captivates his attention
distanced from the world and others—“as if I was and everything else recedes into the background.
living inside a glass case or bubble.” For years, he He describes it as a vacuum-like state in which
Henriksen, Raballo, and Parnas / Pathogenesis of Hallucinations  ■ 171

all his thoughts and feelings are subdued and he AVHs in schizophrenia emerge from a partial
experiences a distinct lack of resonance and spon- dissolution of the structures of self-consciousness,
taneous engagement with the world to the extent which, as shown in the vignettes, entails a panoply
that “it feels unreal” and he feels “like a specta- of different disturbances of cognition and self-
tor” watching the world from afar. In addition, he awareness that are not to be conceived as inde-
experiences silent thought echo (i.e., his thoughts pendent symptoms, but rather as interdependent
are automatically repeated), perceptualization of and mutually implicative aspects of the same psy-
thoughts (i.e., some thoughts occur in the form of chopathological Gestalt. For this reason, it seems
images), and pictorial pseudo-obsessions with a dubious to account for the pathogenesis of AVHs
content that is directly violent or sexually perverse. by systematically listing these disturbances and
He reports that these pseudo-obsessions, which he forming assumptions about their possible causal
feels compelled to live through, tend to start from relations. Still, this does not imply that all efforts
contextually disconnected thoughts that interfere to understand the transition from these early, non-
with his main line of thoughts, and owing to their psychotic anomalies of self-experience to florid
bizarre content, he feels that he does not really psychosis are in vain. A famous phenomenological
produce them, but rather witnesses them. Com- study aiming at establishing such an understand-
parably, he has the impression as if he is divided ing is found within the so-called basic symptom
into two parts, a good and a bad part, where he approach. A brief recollection of this study and
lacks control of the latter. This contributes to his its main results seems appropriate.
pervasive lack of identity, which involves dissocia- In a study of 121 patients with paranoid schizo-
tive depersonalization (sometimes he feels as if he phrenia, Klosterkötter (1992) examined by means
is observing himself from outside) and identity of the BSABS the transitional sequences from basic
confusion. With regard to mirror phenomena, to first-rank symptoms. At the onset of 48 symp-
he reports that he used to stare intensely into the tom sequences ending in AVHs, cognitive deficits
mirror until his face changed and he was unable to such as thought pressure, thought inference,
recognize it. Recently, however, he was involved in thought blockage, obsessive-like perseveration,
an accident in which he got facial scars, and since and decreased abilities to discriminate between
then he rarely looks into the mirror. Instead, he thought and perception were found to be signifi-
has a photo of himself from before the accident, cant. He explained the transition in the three steps
which he then scrutinizes. (Klosterkötter 1992, 618-621): First, the presence
In total, he scored 30 EASE items shared among of these cognitive deficits and the inherent loss of
all five domains. He has poor rapport with oth- cognitive control caused incessant thought infer-
ers and isolation, pseudo-obsessions, perceptual ence and blockage. The combination of increasing
disturbances, and micro-psychoses (fleeting AVHs thought pressure and a decreasing ability to dis-
and vague persecutory delusions)—fulfilling the criminate thoughts from internal auditory images
criteria for schizotypal personality disorder. led the patients to the experience of not really
knowing if they, so to say, thought their thoughts
Transition from or listened to them inside their own head. Second,
Non-Psychotic Anomalies patients began hearing their pressing thoughts
spoken aloud with their own voice internally,
of Experience to Florid and these thoughts included self-instructions,
Hallucinations self-commands, and self-conversations. It became
The three case vignettes describe a multiplic- increasingly difficult to discriminate between inner
ity of alterations of cognition and self-awareness auditory images and outer acoustic perceptions,
that illuminate core features of a self-constellation and the louder the thoughts became, the more it
prone to schizophrenia. All patients reported first- seemed as if they were spoken by external voices.
rank verbal hallucinations, although of varying Third, the leap into frank first-rank verbal hallu-
intensity and duration. From our perspective, cinations was marked by a loss of feeling that the
172  ■  PPP / Vol. 22, No. 3 / September 2015

heard thoughts belonged to the listening subject. in nature and that mathematical spaces (Euclidian
The former inner self-instructions turned into as well as non-Euclidean) only are possible on the
external alien commands, the self-comments into basis of the “life-world” (Husserl 1970) or “lived
external alien remarks on behavior or thoughts, space” (Ströker 1987), that is, the spatiality that
and the self-conversations into a dialogue between is given and pre-reflectively experienced in our
external alien voices. daily, pre-scientific life. We do not provide an ex-
This model is plausible clinically and the ini- haustive account of the phenomenology of space,
tial cognitive disturbances identified in his study but only highlight three key points crucial to our
are also well-reflected in the patient vignettes we subsequent analysis of the pathological changes
have presented. Nonetheless, the main focus on in the experience of space in schizophrenia. First,
subjective disorders of cognition in the transitional phenomenological analyses of perception stress
sequences might result in a too restrictive outlook that all spatial objects appear in a perspectival
at the premorbid and prodromal experiential way, that is, they never appear in their totality,
changes. In our view, subjective disorders of cogni- but always in a certain profile, that is, from a
tion are just one (although perhaps one of the most specific angle and distance (e.g., we cannot see
recurrent in clinical settings) of the possible expres- the rear of a tree, but if we move around it, we
sions of the manifold alteration of self-awareness can see another front). This perspectival incom-
that occur in schizophrenia spectrum conditions pleteness is characteristic of spatial objects and it
and which may contribute to the development of implies that all appearances involve not only an
AVHs. In this sense, the transitional sequences appearing object but also a subject for whom the
from cognitive-perceptual basic symptoms detailed object appears. Second, the experiencing subject
by Klosterkötter might be reconceived in a broader is not conceived as a world-less entity (existing
phenomenological framework. initially by itself only later to relate to the world),
As already noted, we propose that pathological but as world-constituting (Husserl 1983, 109-12;
changes in the experience of space and an incipient Merleau-Ponty 2002, 499f.). Thus, the subject is
morbid objectification of inner speech are essential not merely “in” space like the match is “inside”
to the formation of AVHs. To substantiate this the matchbox. Rather, the idea is that the subject’s
claim, we first clarify exactly what we mean with spatiality enables perceptual objects to appear in
“space” and then account for the pathological their spatiality. For example, Heidegger argued
changes occurring in latent schizophrenia. On this that spatial objects appear in a specific profile,
basis, we elucidate the morbid objectification and because the subject already has a certain direction
automation of inner speech. These two features (Ausrichtung) or orientating in the world (the
(i.e., the pathological changes in the experience window is to my left, but if I turn around, it is to
of space and the morbid objectification of inner my right), thereby bringing relevant objects into its
speech) are mutually interdependent and result own proximity (the man struggling to remain on
from a disturbance of what we call ‘primordial his feet in stormy weather is closer to me than the
presence.’ window through which I perceive him or the floor
on which I stand; 2007, 135-48). He suggested
Pathological Changes in the that the subject’s spatiality (Raumlichkeit) consists
Experience of Space in “giving space” (Raum-geben) and “making
room” (Einräumen) by which he emphasized
When trying to articulate what we normally that our primordial experience of space and spa-
mean with “space,” one may be tempted to use the tial objects quintessentially is determined by our
metaphor of an infinite container. Such an under- involvements and orientation in the shared world
standing of space seems largely comparable with (Heidegger 2007, 146). Third, although Heidegger
the three-dimensional Euclidian space known from argued for the primacy of what we might call the
geometry. However, phenomenologists argue that space of action over that of plain sensory percep-
our primordial relation to space is not geometrical tion, other phenomenologists have, in our view,
Henriksen, Raballo, and Parnas / Pathogenesis of Hallucinations  ■ 173

rightfully criticized him for leaving out of account consequently there is no distance between me and
the most basal relation to space, namely, that my thoughts, feelings, and corporeality. Moreover,
constituted by corporeality (e.g., Merleau-Ponty primordial presence as this form of minimal,
2002, 192). Already Husserl argued that cor- pre-reflective self-identity encompasses a normal
poreality makes perceptual experiences possible sense of vitality and agency, a continual unity in
(1989, 61), that is, perceptions presuppose and the ever-changing stream of consciousness, and
co-occur with a form of bodily self-awareness, a definite feeling that one’s own conscious life is
which he also referred to as “kinaesthetic sen- private and clearly demarcated from the world
sations” (Husserl 1997). This idea of the lived and others. Some of the earliest and most alarming
body (Leib) is closely related to his notion of subjective experiences of beginning schizophre-
“operative intentionality” (i.e., a non-objectifying, nia involve disturbances of primordial presence,
non-propositional, and ante-predicative form of which hinder patients from being spontaneously
intentionality encompassing, e.g., desires, affects, immersed in the world. Some patients specifically
and passive syntheses), which is distinguishable complain about a compromised phenomenality
from “act intentionality” (articulating that the of experience when describing that they don’t feel
majority of conscious experiences are directed fully present—“I feel a sort of emptiness in my
toward an intentional object, e.g., the book in head as if I am not awake. I feel detached or airy
front of me). Operative intentionality functions as if I am not present. It’s like having a cold, as if
as a tacit, pre-reflective background organization my head is stuffed with cotton.” David described
of the field of consciousness. Following Husserl persistent experiences of diminished presence and
(1973), Merleau-Ponty argued that act intentional- the associated distance to the shared world, when
ity is grounded in operative intentionality and that stating that he for years has been “living inside a
the latter constitutes our primary relation to the glass bubble,” which regularly gets “so foggy”
world (2002, 498), which he described as a pri- that he loses “contact with the outside world.”
mordial “inalienable presence” (2002, vii). Ströker Comparably, John described a “vacuum-like
suggested something similar when proposing that state” in which all his thoughts and feelings were
“attuned space” forms our basic, pre-reflective subdued and he experienced a distinct lack of
orientation in the world, that is, “an immediate resonance with the world, which he then felt as
affinity with the world” (1987, 20). In our view, “unreal” and himself “like a spectator” watching
the pathological changes in the experience of space the world. It was in the midst of this emptiness
in schizophrenia result from disturbances or insta- that the hallucinatory voice surfaced, initially as a
bilities in the most fundamental relation to space, murmur inside his head as if he was “standing in
namely, the primordial presence in the world. In a field in stormy weather listening to the wind.”
schizophrenia spectrum disorders, this primordial Others patients who experience disturbances
presence is not as “inalienable” as Merleau-Ponty of primordial presence report that the normally
seemed to suggest. implicit sense of being a self no longer saturates
The concept of primordial presence signifies their experiences—“I feel caught off guard. As
that our pre-reflective immersion in the world and if the thoughts aren’t really coming from me. If
pre-reflective sense of self are, in fact, inseparable: they were my thoughts, I would be able to control
“At the heart of the subject himself we discov- them and I would not think them.” These experi-
ered, then, the presence of the world” (Merleau- ences often involve a disturbing feeling of being
Ponty 2002, 498). Primordial presence may be radically different from others—“robot-like” (as
described as a basic, pre-reflective self-awareness David put it) or, as some of our other patients put
(ipseity) that renders everything I experience as it, “I feel like I don’t belong here,” “I feel like an
my experiences, that is, it makes me implicitly alien,” and “I cannot find myself” (cf. Parnas and
aware that I am the one who perceives, thinks, Henriksen 2014, 253).
imagines, and so on. All experiences are given to Additionally, diminished presence is associated
me from within my first-person perspective, and frequently with abnormalities in the normal sense
174  ■  PPP / Vol. 22, No. 3 / September 2015

of embodiment (e.g., “the body feels awkward as sociated pathological changes in the experience of
if it doesn’t really fit,” “it feels like the body isn’t space emerges an experiential distance between the
really me, as if it is rather a machine controlled self and its thoughts. David provided an example
by my brain, as if the body is a mere appendage,” of this subtle loss of thought ipseity (Gedanke-
and “the body feels alien as if it doesn’t belong nenteignung), when describing the estrangement
to me. There’s no connection between my mind he experienced toward his own thoughts—“they
and my body. I might as well have been a dog”). are my thoughts but not me.” The experiential
Fuchs (2005) has described the “disembodiment distance enables a self-alienation to grow from
of the self” that frequently occurs in schizophrenia within the disturbed subjectivity, by which one’s
conditions and has argued that in such cases the thoughts, feelings, or parts of the body eventually
patients no longer inhabit their body in the normal may be experienced as strange or alien.
sense, but that they due to the psycho-psychical Furthermore, schizophrenia spectrum patients
split, which results from the loss of basic self- frequently complain about “living in the head”
awareness (ipseity), may come to experience their and being unable to be absorbed in daily, practical
body as a sort of machine potentially steered by activities. This typical complaint is, in our view,
external forces. Similarly, Stanghellini spoke of neither trivial nor should we understand it merely
“deanimated bodies” in schizophrenia, that is, metaphorically. Normally, we never experience
a kind of mechanization or objectification of the our own interiority as a space or experience our
lived body, stemming from a lack of presence and thoughts with spatial qualities, but schizophre-
sensory self-consciousness (2004, 127ff., 153ff.). nia patients often do so. For example, a patient
A core aspect of the disturbances of primordial reported that when he listens to music, he is not
presence is, we argue, pathological changes in the really listening to the sound, but rather observing
experience of space. More specifically, the distur- himself listening—that is, his gaze is somehow
bance or discontinuation of primordial presence turned inward instead of outward. Stanghellini
enables a construction of a sort of persistent, inner (2004) sought to articulate this separation of the
space that continuously articulates itself, thereby self from the mediating processes it normally in-
allowing schizophrenia patients to experience their habits with the term “disembodied spirits.”
own interiority as a space and their thoughts and
feelings with spatial qualities. David, for example, Morbid Objectification of
can locate his thoughts spatially inside the glass Inner Speech
bubble and almost see his thoughts, and Hanna
sees some of her thoughts in an on-going inner To characterize the morbid objectification
movie. Other patients can locate their thoughts of inner speech, we must first describe the pre-
spatially to one side of the brain or describe how morbid inner speech. Normally, a substantial part
certain thoughts move from the neck to the fore- of our thinking occurs in the form of a so-called
head, and so on. Often, the hallucinatory voice has inner speech, which has a verbal and dialogical
a different location than the thoughts they consider structure (Sass 1992, 193-7; Vygotsky 1986).
their own. John described that he does not feel like In other words, I am engaged with myself in an
he produces the pictorial pseudo-obsessions with inner dialogue in the sense that one part of me
bizarre content, but that he rather witnesses them. asks questions and gets replies from another part
Furthermore, Hanna and David heard their own of me. Although I experience these two parts as
thoughts spoken aloud internally. Normally, we somehow distinct, I experience them at the same
do not listen to our thoughts, witness them, or see time as deeply integrated, and the underlying feel-
them to know what we are thinking—they have ing of unity in this duality remains perfectly intact
no spatial qualities or sound and there is, so to (Stanghellini and Cutting 2003, 126). In schizo-
say, no temporal delay between my thoughts and phrenia spectrum conditions, this unity disunites
myself. I simply inhabit my thoughts. From the as we have described, and an experiential distance
disturbances of primordial presence and the as- emerges between the self and its thoughts. In our
Henriksen, Raballo, and Parnas / Pathogenesis of Hallucinations  ■ 175

view, this dissociation between the sense of self and split (Ich-Spaltung). John gave an example hereof,
the inner speech is essential to understanding the when describing that he felt as if he was divided
pathogenesis of AVHs. It reflects a fundamental into two separate parts. Another patient reports
weakening of the implicit sense of being in touch that she for a long time has heard two different
with oneself and introduces an unbridgeable gap voices spoken aloud inside her head. She recogniz-
between the normally unified dialoguing parts es both voices as her own, and she describes how
of inner speech. Frequently, patients report that these voices constantly discuss even the slightest
certain thoughts, usually interfering or pressing matter. For example, if one voice says, “Now that’s
thoughts, feel, as Hanna put it, “strange and im- funny,” then the other will instantly reply, “No,
personal.” Partly because they are not controlled, it’s not.” She distinguishes between the thoughts
they may be experienced as if they were not really she thinks (and also hears aloud internally), which
generated by the patient. This was also the case she spatially locates to her neck, and the discuss-
with John’s pseudo-obsessions. The experiential ing thoughts, which she locates to her mouth.
distance transforms the inner speech and enables This continuous inner discussion captivates her
the patient to introspect his thoughts. The inner attention and makes it nearly impossible for her
speech that normally functions as an implicit or to concentrate, initiate new lines of thoughts, and
silent medium for self-presentation becomes now remember things for more than a few minutes.
the object of explicit awareness and in this objec- Like John, she also has the impression of being
tifying process, thoughts get reified and acquire divided into two separate parts (corresponding
properties not completely unlike those of physical with the two discussing voices) and she identi-
objects. This kind of alienating self-consciousness fies more with the one part than with the other.
has been described by Sass (1992) under the head- We may consider such experiences of I-split as a
ing “hyperreflexivity.” It involves a distortion of manifestation of the dissociation between the self
the structures of awareness (such as foreground– and its inner speech, and in that sense the I-split
background, explicit–implicit, focal–tacit) in the reflects a vulnerability to verbal hallucinations.
sense that something normally tacit becomes In our view, AVHs in schizophrenia arise from
focal, enabling aspects of oneself or one’s inner inner speech dialogues between thoughts that have
life to be experienced with qualities similar to acquired quasi-acoustic qualities and become in-
those of external objects (Sass and Parnas 2003). creasingly loud, and that, owing to the increasing
As noted, some patients, like Hanna, are able to experiential distance (which involves both patho-
locate specific thoughts spatially, whereas other logical changes in the experience of space and a
patients, like John, experience their thoughts au- morbid objectification of inner speech), eventually
tomatically being repeated or doubled in the form seem to be so unfamiliar and alien that the patient
of silent echoes (l’écho de pensée). Moreover, the is unable to recognize them as her own thoughts.
inner speech often acquires an acoustic quality, Deprived all sense of mineness, the unity of the
that enables the patient to listen to her thoughts dialoguing parts of inner speech “shatters into a
(Gedankenlautwerden, la pensée parlée) as in the mere dichotomy” (Stanghellini and Cutting 2003,
case of Hanna. Another typical form of this per- 126), enabling patients to experience or hear their
ceptualization and spatialization of inner speech own “loud” or unfamiliar thoughts as alien voices.
is described in the patient vignettes, when they
report that they are able to see their own thoughts Discussion
inside their head. However, the morbidly objecti-
fied inner speech may not only appear as sharply Our account of the pathogenesis of AVHs
delimited objects locatable in space, but also as complements a range of empirical or phenom-
objects instantaneously given as a whole, appear- enological studies of the formation of verbal
ing, so to say, in a glance. hallucinations in schizophrenia, in particular the
Another non-psychotic, anomalous self-experi- works of Ey (1973), Klosterkötter (1988, 1992),
ence, which some patients report, is the so-called I- Sass (1992), Stanghellini and Cutting (2003), Sass
176  ■  PPP / Vol. 22, No. 3 / September 2015

and Parnas (2003), Larøi et al. (2010), Raballo distance and the intrinsic feelings of losing con-
and Larøi (2011), and Parnas and Sass (2011). We trol or lack of control of, say, one’s thoughts and
have proposed that verbal hallucinations in schizo- bodily movements, precede prodromal feelings as
phrenia tend to arise from preceding alterations if being controlled as well as crystallized delusions
of self-awareness that involve both pathological of control and other first-rank symptoms such as
changes in the experience of space and a morbid commenting or arguing voices, thought insertion,
objectification of inner speech. We recognize that thought broadcasting, and thought withdrawal.
our account of the pathogenesis of AVHs in schizo- We have used the term self-alienation to des-
phrenia comes with certain limitations. First, the ignate broadly the variety of forms of estrange-
reduction of this heterogeneous group of mental ment and self-estrangement experienced and
phenomena to specific structures of experience encountered in schizophrenia spectrum conditions.
inevitably involves some generalizations, which Hence, self-alienation encompasses the notion of
may prove too crude. Second, clinicians familiar experiential distance, which articulates a crucial
with the psychopathology of schizophrenia know aspect of the altered structures of self-awareness,
that verbal hallucinations sometimes occur quite but self-alienation may also refer to disturbances
suddenly or acutely, and in those cases our account involved in more reflected facets of personhood
does not really contribute to the understanding such as social withdrawal, isolation, idiosyncra-
of their formation. This limitation touches on the sies, suicidal ideation, and so on. Although alien-
inherent unpredictability of the schizophrenic ation (alienatio) traditionally has been equated
disorder and the associated incomprehensibility. with insanity (alienatio mentis), its etymology is
Although the formation of verbal hallucinations also linked to distancing (Entfremdung, Verfrem-
in such cases is not reconstructable in the manner dung) and externalizing (Veräusserung). From a
described, we maintain that AVHs tend to arise clinical–phenomenological perspective, we have
from manifold alterations of self-awareness—the argued that both distancing (in the sense of the
majority of which were exemplified in the case increasing experiential gap between the sense of
vignettes and the subsequent analysis. Klosterköt- self and the experiential stream, i.e., the loss of
ter (1992) identified some of these alterations, mineness of experience) and externalizing tenden-
namely, the subjective disorders of cognition, but cies (in the sense of spatialization of experience
as we have tried to show, cognitive disorders are and morbid objectification of inner speech) are es-
just one of the possible expressions of the deforma- sential to the formation of AVHs in schizophrenia,
tions of self-awareness in schizophrenia spectrum and more generally that they are at the very root
conditions that precede the formation of AVHs. of the schizophrenia spectrum disorders. We chose
To articulate the pervasive self-alienation imma- the term self-alienation over alienation because
nent in the manifold alterations of self-awareness, the former indicates that the alienation in schizo-
we used the term experiential distance. This phrenia seems to grow from within the disturbed
term illuminates a core aspect of a phenomenon, subjectivity. Obviously, we do not dispute that
which has been thematized under headings such some of the earliest as well as prime manifesta-
as ‘hyperreflexivity’ (Sass 1992), “disturbances tions of schizophrenic vulnerability occur in the
of presence” (Parnas and Handest 2003, 124), intersubjective sphere, for example, interpersonal
“diminished self-affection” (Parnas and Sass 2003, difficulties (including social withdrawal and isola-
429), and “instability of minimal self” (Parnas and tion), perplexity (Störring 1939), and lack of com-
Sass 2011, 533). Addressing this phenomenon is mon sense (Blankenburg 1971, 2001), but we do
hardly a new idea; the specificity of the first-rank claim that schizophrenia spectrum conditions seem
symptoms consists in structural alterations of self- to begin as a fragmentation from within, which
awareness in which the unifying abnormality is gradually leaves the patient trapped in a prison of
the decreased sense of mineness (Meinhaftigkeit) his or her own deserted interiority.
of experience and the associated loss of ego-
boundaries (Schneider 1950). The experiential
Henriksen, Raballo, and Parnas / Pathogenesis of Hallucinations  ■ 177

Empirical Studies on controls and patients from other diagnostic


groups), indicating that the disturbances of self-
Self-Disorders consciousness in schizophrenia are different from
An increasing amount of empirical studies disturbances found in other mental disorders. For
supports the hypothesis that anomalous self- example, in cases of senile dementia, the mineness
experiences (i.e., self-disorders) are pivotal to the of experience, which is unstable or even shattered
psychopathology of schizophrenia. For example, in schizophrenia, remains perfectly intact. As
Huber, Klosterkötter, and their collaborates found Kimura puts it, “an Alzheimer’s patient, who no
many non-psychotic “basic symptoms” to be longer knows with whom she is speaking or what
specific to schizophrenia (Huber 1983; Huber et her own name is, will hardly ever say that she is not
al. 1979; Klosterkötter 1988, 1992). Danish and herself, or that she is someone else” (2001, 332).
Norwegian studies showed elevated levels of self- In contrast with Alzheimer’s disease and other
disorders in the initial prodrome of schizophrenia memory disorders where the disturbances of self-
(Møller and Husby 2000; Parnas et al. 1998). hood affect the so-called narrative or extended self,
Self-disorders have been found to aggregate selec- we agree with Cermolacce et al., when they argue
tively in schizophrenia and schizotypal personality that the disturbances of self-awareness in schizo-
disorder (Nordgaard and Parnas 2014; Parnas phrenia primarily affect “the sense of minimal
et al. 2005b; Raballo et al. 2011; Raballo and self” or “ipseity” (2007, 712). Consequently, we
Parnas 2012) but not in bipolar disorders (Par- also embrace the so-called “ipseity disturbance”
nas et al. 2003; Haug et al. 2012a). In the study model proposed by Sass and Parnas (2003), which
by Haug et al. (2012a), the mean EASE score of suggests that schizophrenia can be understood
the schizophrenia group (n = 57) was 25.3 (SD = as a self-disturbance with two complementary
9.6), whereas the mean EASE score of the bipolar distortion of self-awareness, namely, diminished
psychosis group (n = 21) was 6.3 (SD = 4.8). In self-affection and hyperreflexivity.
the study by Raballo and Parnas (2012), the mean
EASE score of the schizophrenia group (n = 19) Anomalous Self-Experiences
was 21.4 (SD = 9.6), and the mean EASE score of
Outside the Spectrum
the schizophrenia group (n = 46) was 19.63 (SD
= 8.39) in the study by Nordgaard and Parnas Finally, we briefly address a pertinent question
(2014). Furthermore, self-disorders have been that seems to challenge our account. Individuals in
found to occur in genetically high-risk individu- different diagnostic groups may describe anoma-
als (Raballo and Parnas 2011), to be predictive of lous self-experiences quite similar to those por-
incident cases of schizophrenia spectrum disorders trayed in the case vignettes. If these deformations
in a 5-year follow-up study of 155 first-admitted of self-awareness are constitutive for the formation
patients (Parnas et al. 2011), and to predict the of verbal hallucinations, then why don’t these pa-
transition to psychosis in an ultra–high-risk sample tients develop verbal hallucinations regularly? It is
(Nelson et al. 2012). Finally, self-disorders have perfectly correct that, for example, patients with
been correlated with other variables, including major depressive disorders or depersonalization
positive and negative symptoms, formal thought disorders sometimes report self-experiences fairly
disorders, and perceptual disturbances (Nor- similar to those portrayed in the vignettes (e.g., a
dgaard and Parnas 2014), suicidality (Haug et fragile sense of identity, diminished presence, and
al. 2012b; Skodlar and Parnas 2010), and social decreased vitality). Moreover, victims of torture
dysfunction (Haug et al. 2014)—see Parnas and often describe subtle experiences of derealiza-
Henriksen (2014) for a review of empirical studies tion, a lack of basic trust, and a global crisis of
on self-disorders. meaning (see, e.g., Brison 2003, ix; Delbo 1995,
The available empirical studies suggest that 260ff.; Ortiz and Davis 2002, 51, 138ff.), which
self-disorders discriminate schizophrenia spectrum also resemble some of the core self-experiences
patients from non-spectrum individuals (healthy described in the vignettes. Obviously, we do not
178  ■  PPP / Vol. 22, No. 3 / September 2015

dispute that these individuals as well as others can pathogenesis of AVHs in schizophrenia is different
have experiences quite similar to those described from that of AVHs found in populations outside
in the vignettes, but we do argue that such ex- the spectrum—recall that the mean EASE score of
periences only are similar with regard to certain patients with schizophrenia ranges from 19.63 to
aspects. When empirical studies suggest that self- 25.3 (Haug et al 2012a; Nordgaard and Parnas
disorders are specific to schizophrenia, this does 2014; Raballo and Parnas 2012). In comparison,
not mean that such anomalous self-experiences the mean EASE score of a healthy control group
are exclusive to and cannot be found outside the (n = 52) was 2.37 (SD = 2.45; Nelson et al. 2012).
schizophrenia spectrum, but simply that the differ- Bearing in mind the heterogeneity of AVHs, it
ence in the number of anomalous self-experiences seems, in our view, highly questionable if the phe-
is statistically highly significant between spectrum nomena actually are of the same form and quality
and non-spectrum individuals. In other words, in schizophrenia and normal populations. The
when schizophrenia patients describe experiences mere fact that most voice-hearers in the so-called
of inner void, unreality, and lack of presence, these normal population rarely, if ever, seek help for
experiences are not isolated to specific situations, their abnormal experiences seems to indicate that
but embedded in a globally changed experiential these voices are qualitatively different from those
framework, which reflect the comprehensive that typically torment schizophrenia patients.
structural alteration of subjective experience in In an interesting study, Stanghellini et al. (2012)
schizophrenia (Henriksen and Parnas 2012; 2014; compared hallucinatory experiences in a clinical
Henriksen and Nordgaard 2014; in press; Parnas sample of schizophrenia patients (n = 23) with
and Bovet 1991; Parnas et al. 2002). It is, more hallucinatory-like experiences in a non-clinical
specifically, the psychopathological Gestalt that is sample (n = 60) and found that the phenomenal
schizophrenia specific, not any anomalous experi- quality of these experiences was “remarkably dif-
ences per se, and it is this Gestalt that is constitu- ferent” in the two samples. In the schizophrenia
tive for the formation of AVHs in schizophrenia. sample, the hallucinatory experiences were closely
Non-spectrum individuals can therefore have related to the patients’ identity, which was marked
anomalous self-experiences that in some respects by persistent anomalies in their sense of self and
resemble those found within the spectrum, but by metamorphosis of the self–world relationship,
without the same underlying psychopathological whereas the hallucinatory-like experiences in the
Gestalt these individuals rarely develop the same non-clinical sample were related to circumstantial
form and quality of verbal hallucinations as those events or reported as a single experience (Stang-
frequently found in schizophrenia—in particular hellini et al. 2012). Further research that explores
running commentary or arguing voices. the heterogeneity of hallucinatory voices might
However, some empirical studies attest that provide the details needed to establish a genuine
verbal hallucinations also occur in normal popu- and sound differentiation of these complex mental
lations (Barrett and Etheridge 1992; Posey and phenomena.
Losch 1983; Tien 1991). If we maintain that
the psychopathological Gestalt of schizophrenia Conclusion
is constitutive for the formation of AVHs, how
can we then account for the presence of AVHs in We have put forth a phenomenological account
non-spectrum individuals? Does the presence of of the pathogenesis of AVHs in schizophrenia that
hallucinatory voices in non-clinical populations complements, elucidates, and clinically grounds
not somehow indicate that the pathogenetic causes contemporary phenomenological accounts of
must be sought elsewhere and that we have got AVHs in schizophrenia. More specifically, we
it all wrong? Again, we argue that the empirical have proposed that verbal hallucinations tend to
studies described suggest that deformations of arise from preceding alterations of self-awareness,
self-awareness are highly characteristic of schizo- which involve both pathological changes in the
phrenia spectrum conditions, indicating that the experience of space and a morbid objectification
Henriksen, Raballo, and Parnas / Pathogenesis of Hallucinations  ■ 179

of inner speech, and we have provided clinical Berrios, G. E., and T. R. Dening. 1996. Pseudohallucina-
descriptions of these pervasive alterations. In tions: A conceptual history. Psychological Medicine
addition, we have suggested that “experiential 26:753–63.
Berze, J. 1914. Die primäre Insuffizienz der psychischen
distance,” which arises from disturbances of
Aktivität. Ihr Wesen, ihre Erscheinungen und ihre
primordial presence, is at the very core of the Bedeutung als Grundstörungen der Dementia
deformations of self-awareness in schizophrenia Praecox und der Hypophrenen überhaupt. Leipzig:
spectrum disorders and that it may function as a Frank Deuticke.
precursor to florid first-rank symptoms, such as Berze, J., and H. W. Gruhle. 1929. Psychologie der
verbal hallucinations and delusions. Furthermore, Schizophrenie. Berlin: Springer.
we dispute that AVHs in schizophrenia should Blankenburg, W. 1971. Der Verlust der natürlichen Selb-
stverständlichkeit. Ein Beitrag zur Psychopathologie
be conceived in terms of abnormal perception,
symptomarmer Schizophrenien. Stuttgart: Enke.
but rather as cognitive phenomena arising from ———. 2001. First steps toward a psychopathology of
a partial dissolution or reorganization of certain ‘common sense’. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychol-
structures of self-consciousness. Finally, we sug- ogy 8, no. 4:303–15.
gest that clinically grounded phenomenological Bleuler, E. 1911. Dementia Praecox oder Gruppe der
models of the pathogenesis of AVHs may guide Schizophrenien. Leipzig & Wien: Deuticke, trans.
the empirical search for the neurobiological basis J. Zinkin. 1950. Demetia Praecox or the group of
of these complex phenomena. schizophrenias. New York: International Universi-
ties Press.
Brison, S. 2003. Aftermath: Violence and the remaking
Funding of a self. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Cermolacce, M., J. Naudin, and J. Parnas. 2007. The
M.G.H. is funded by the Carlsberg Foundation
‘minimal self’ in psychopathology: Re-examining
(#2012010195). the self-disorders in the schizophrenia spectrum.
Consciousness and Cognition 16:703–14.
References Conrad, K. 1959. Die beginnende Schizophrenie.
Aggernæs, A. 1972. The experienced reality of hallu- Versuch einer Gestaltanalyse des Wahns. Stuttgart:
cinations and other psychological phenomena. An Thieme.
empirical analysis. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica Delbo, C. 1995. Auschwitz and after. New Haven, CT:
48:220–38. Yale University Press.
American Psychiatric Association (APA). 1994. Diag- Esquirol, E. 1838. Des maladies mentales considérées
nostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: sous les rapports médicaux, hygieniques et médico-
DSM-IV, 4th ed. Washington, DC: American Psy- légaux. Paris: Baillière.
chiatric Association. Ey, E. 1973. Traité des hallucinations. Paris: Masson.
Baethge, C., R. J. Baldessarini, K. Freudenthal, A. Frith, C. D. 1979. Consciousness, information process-
Streeruwitz, M. Bauer, and T. Bschor. 2005. Hal- ing and schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry
lucinations in bipolar disorder: Characteristics and 134:225–35.
comparison to unipolar depression and schizophre- Fuchs, T. 2005. Corporealized and disembodied minds.
nia. Bipolar Disorders 7:136–45. A phenomenological view of the body in melancholia
Barrett, T. R., and E. Etheridge. 1992. Verbal hallucina- and schizophrenia. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psy-
tions in normals, I: People who hear ‘voices’. Applied chology 12, no. 2:95–107.
Cognitive Psychology 6:379–87. Garrett, M., and R. Silva. 2003. Auditory hallucina-
Behrendt, R.-P. 1998. Underconstrained perception: A tions, source monitoring, and the belief that ‘voices’
theoretical approach to the nature and function of are real. Schizophrenia Bulletin 29:445–57.
verbal hallucinations. Comprehensive Psychiatry Gross, G., G. Huber, J. Klosterkötter, and M. Linz.
39:236–48. 1987. Bonner Skala für die Beurteilung von Basis-
Bentall, R. P, and P. D. Slade. 1985. Reality testing and symptomen. Heidelberg: Springer.
auditory hallucinations: A signal detection analysis. Haug, E., L. Lien, A. Raballo, L. Bratlien, M. Oie, O.
British Journal of Clinical Psychology 24:159–69. A. Andreasen, I. Melle, and P. Møller. 2012a. Selec-
Berrios, G. E. 1996. The history of mental symptoms. tive aggregation of self-disorders in first-treatment
Descriptive psychopathology since the nineteenth DSM-IV schizophrenia spectrum disorders. Journal
century. New York: Cambridge University Press. of Nervous and Mental Disease 200:632–36.
180  ■  PPP / Vol. 22, No. 3 / September 2015

Haug, E., I. Melle, O. A. Andreassen, A. Raballo, U. Klosterkötter, J. 1988. Basissymptome und Endphän-
Bratlien, M. Øie, L. Lien, and P. Møller. 2012b. omeneder Schizophrenie. Eine empirische Untersu-
The association between anomalous self-experience chung der psychopathologischen Übergangsreihen
and suicidality in first-episode schizophrenia seems zwischen defizitären und produktiven Schizophre-
mediated by depression. Comprehensive Psychiatry niesymptomen. Berlin: Springer.
53:456–60. ———. 1992. The meaning of basic symptoms for
Haug, E., M. Øie, M, O. A. Andreassen, U. Bratlien, the genesis of the schizophrenic nuclear syndrome.
A. Raballo, B. Nelson, P. Møller, and I. Melle. Japanese Journal of Psychiatry and Neurology
2014. Anomalous self-experiences contribute inde- 46:609–30.
pendently to social dysfunction in the early phases Klosterkötter, J., M. Hellmich, E. M. Steinmeyer, and
of schizophrenia and psychotic bipolar disorder. F. Schultze-Lutter. 2001. Diagnosing schizophrenia
Comprehensive Psychiatry 55:475–82. in the initial prodromal phase. Archives of General
Heidegger, M. 2007. Being and time. Oxford: Blackwell. Psychiatry 58:158–64.
Henriksen, M. G., and J. Nordgaard. 2014. Schizophre- Kraepelin, E. 1913. Psychiatrie. Ein Lehrbuch für Stud-
nia as a disorder of the self. Journal of Psychopathol- ierende und Ärzte. Leipzig: Johann Ambrosius Barth.
ogy 20:435–41. Larøi, F., S. de Haan, S. Jones, and A. Raballo. 2010.
———. In press. Self-disorders in schizophrenia. In Auditory verbal hallucinations: Dialoguing between
An experiential approach to psychopathology – the cognitive sciences and phenomenology. Phenom-
phenomenology of psychotic experiences, ed. G. enology and the Cognitive Sciences 9:225–40.
Stanghellini, and M. Aragona. New York: Springer. Leudar, I., P. Thomas, D. McNally, and A. Glinski. 1997.
Henriksen, M. G., and J. Parnas. 2012. Clinical What voices do with words: Pragmatics of verbal
manifestations of self-disorders and the Gestalt of hallucinations. Psychological Medicine 27:885–98.
schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin 38:657–60. Liester, M. B. 1998. Toward a new definition of hal-
———. 2014. Self-disorders and schizophrenia: A lucination. American Journal of Orthopsychiatry
phenomenological reappraisal of poor insight and 68:305–12.
noncompliance. Schizophrenia Bulletin 40:542–47. Lothane, Z. 1982. The psychopathology of hallucina-
Hoffman, R. 1986. Verbal hallucinations and language tions – A methodological analysis. British Journal
production processes in schizophrenia. Behavioural of Medical Psychology 55:335–48.
and Brain Sciences 9:513–48. Merleau-Ponty, M. 2002. The phenomenology of per-
Huber, G. 1983. Das Konzept substratnaher Basissymp- ception. London: Routledge.
tome und seine Bedeutung für Theorie und Therapie Minkowski, E. 1927. La schizophrénie. Psychopatholo-
schizophrener Erkrankungen. Nervenarzt 54:23–32. gie des schizoïdes et des schizophrénes. Paris: Payot.
Huber, G., G. Gross, R. Schüttler. 1979. Schizophrenie. Morrison, A. P., and G. Haddock. 1997. Cognitive
Eine Verlaufs- und sozialpsychiatrische Langzeit- factors in source monitoring and auditory hallucina-
studie. Berlin: Springer. tions. Psychological Medicine 27:669–79.
Husserl, E. 1970. The crisis of European sciences Møller, P., and R. Husby. 2000. The initial prodrome
and transcendental phenomenology. Evanston, IL: in schizophrenia: Searching for naturalistic core di-
Northwestern University Press. mensions of experience and behavior. Schizophrenia
———. 1973. Experience and judgment. Evanston, IL: Bulletin 26:217–32.
Northwestern University Press. Naudin, J. 1997. Phénoménologie et Psychiatrie. Les
———. 1983. Collected works, vol. II: Ideas pertaining voix et la chose. Toulouse: PUM.
to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenologi- Naudin, J., and J. M. Azorin. 1997. The hallucinatory
cal philosophy - first book: general introduction to a epoche. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology
pure phenomenology. The Hauge: Martinus Nijhoff. 26:65–83.
———. 1989. Collected works, vol. III: Ideas pertain- Nelson, B., A. Thompson, and A. R. Yung. 2012. Basic
ing to a pure phenomenology and to a phenom- self-disturbance predicts psychosis onset in the ultra
enological philosophy - second book: studies in the high risk for psychosis “prodromal” population.
phenomenology of constitution. Dordrecht: Kluwer Schizophrenia Bulletin 38:1277–87.
Academic Publishers. Nordgaard, J., and J. Parnas. 2014. Self-disorders and
———. 1997. Thing and space: lectures of 1907. Dor- schizophrenia-spectrum: A study of 100 first hospital
drecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. admissions. Schizophrenia Bulletin 40:1300–7.
Kimura, B. 2001. Cogito and I: A bio-logical ap- Ortiz, D., and P. Davis. 2002. The blindfold’s eye: My
proach. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 8, journey from torture to truth. Orbis: New York.
no. 4:331–6. Parnas, J., and P. Bovet. 1991. Autism in schizophrenia
revisited. Comprehensive Psychiatry 32:7–21.
Henriksen, Raballo, and Parnas / Pathogenesis of Hallucinations  ■ 181

Parnas, J., P. Bovet, and D. Zahavi. 2002. Schizophrenic Raballo, A., and J. Parnas. 2011. The silent side of
autism: Clinical phenomenology and pathogenetic the spectrum: Schizotypy and the schizotaxic self.
implications. World Psychiatry 1:131–6. Schizophrenia Bulletin 37:1017–26.
Parnas, J., and P. Handest. 2003. Phenomenology of Raballo, A., and J. Parnas. 2012. Examination of anom-
anomalous self-experience in early schizophrenia. alous self-experience: Initial study of the structure of
Comprehensive Psychiatry 44:121–34. self-disorders in schizophrenia spectrum. Journal of
Parnas, J., P. Handest, L. Jansson, and D. Saebye. Nervous and Mental Disease 200:577–83.
2005b. Anomalous subjective experience among Sass, L. A. 1992. Madness and modernism. Insanity
first-admitted schizophrenia spectrum patients: em- in the light of modern art, literature, and thought.
pirical investigation. Psychopathology 38:259–67. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Parnas, J., P. Handest, D. Saebye, and L. Jansson. 2003. Sass, L. A., and J. Parnas. 2003. Schizophrenia, con-
Anomalies of subjective experience in schizophrenia sciousness, and the self. Schizophrenia Bulletin
and psychotic bipolar illness. Acta Psychiatrica 29:427–44.
Scandinavica 108:126–33. Schneider, K. 1950. Klinische Psychopathologie. Stutt-
Parnas, J., and M. G. Henriksen. 2014. Disordered gart: Thieme.
self in the schizophrenia spectrum: A clinical and Schultze-Lutter, F., J. Addington, S. Ruhrmann, and J.
research perspective. Harvard Review of Psychiatry Klosterkötter. 2007. Schizophrenia Proneness Instru-
22:251–65. ment, Adult version, SPI-A. Roma: Fioriti.
Parnas, J., L. Jansson, L. A. Sass, and P. Handest. 1998. Skodlar, B., and J. Parnas. 2010. Self-disorder and
Self-experience in the prodromal phases of schizo- subjective dimensions of suicidality in schizophrenia.
phrenia: A pilot study of first admissions. Neurology, Comprehensive Psychiatry 51:363–6.
Psychiatry, and Brain Research 6:97–106. Stanghellini, G. 2004. Disembodied spirits and de-
Parnas, J., P. Møller, T. Kircher, J. Thalbitzer, L. Jans- animated bodies. The psychopathology of common
son, and P. Handest, and D. Zahavi. 2005a. EASE: sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Examination of anomalous self-experience. Psycho- Stanghellini, G., and J. Cutting. 2003. Auditory verbal
pathology 38:236–58. hallucinations – Breaking the silence of inner dia-
Parnas, J., A. Raballo, P. Handest, L. Jansson, A. logue. Psychopathology 36:120–8.
Vollmer-Larsen, and D. Saebye. 2011. Self-experi- Stanghellini, G., Langer, Á. I., Ambrosini, A., and A. J.
ence in the early phases of schizophrenia: 5-year Cangas. 2012. Quality of hallucinatory experiences:
follow-up of the Copenhagen Prodromal Study. Differences between a clinical and a non-clinical
World Psychiatry 10:200–4. sample. World Psychiatry 11:110–3.
Parnas, J., and L. A. Sass. 2008. Varieties of “phe- Störring, G. E. 1939. Wesen und Bedeutung des Symp-
nomenology.” On description, understanding, and toms der Ratlosigkeit bei psychischen Erkrankungen.
explanation in psychiatry. In Philosophical issues Leipzig: Thieme.
in psychiatry. Explanation, phenomenology, and Ströker, E. 1987. Investigations in philosophy of space.
nosology, ed. K. S. Kendler, and J. Parnas, 239–85. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press.
Baltimore. MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Tatossian, A. 2007. La phénoménologie des psychoses.
Parnas, J., and L. A. Sass. 2010. The Spectrum of Le Cercle Herméneutique, Collection Phéno. Paris:
Schizophrenia. In The embodied self: Dimensions, Vrin.
coherence and disorders, ed. T. Fuchs, H. C. Sattel, Taylor, F. K. 1981. On pseudo-hallucinations. Psycho-
and P. Henningsen, 227–44. Stuttgart: Schattauer. logical Medicine 11:265–71.
Parnas, J., and L. A. Sass. 2011. The structure of self- Tien, A. Y. 1991. Distributions of hallucinations in
consciousness in schizophrenia. In The Oxford the population. Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric
handbook of the self, ed. S. Gallagher, 521–46. New Epidemiology 26:287–92.
York: Oxford University Press. Vygotsky, L. 1986. Thought and language. Cambridge,
Posey, T. B., and M. E. Losch. 1983. Auditory hallu- MA.: MIT Press.
cinations of hearing voices in 375 normal subjects. World Health Organization (WHO). 1992. The ICD-
Imagination, Cognition, and Personality 3:99–113. 10 classification of mental and behavioral disorders:
Raballo, A., and F. Larøi. 2011. Murmurs of thought: clinical description and diagnostic guidelines. Ge-
Phenomenology of hallucinatory consciousness in neva: WHO.
impending psychosis. Psychosis 3:163–6. Zucker, K. 1928. Experimentelles über Sinnestäuschun-
Raballo, A., D. Sæbye, and J. Parnas. 2011. Looking gen. Archiv für Psychiatrie und Nervenkrankheiten
at the schizophrenia spectrum through the prism of 83:706–54.
self-disorders: An empirical study. Schizophrenia
Bulletin 37:344–51.

You might also like