Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 14

North American Philosophical Publications

Non-Intentional Actions
Author(s): David K. Chan
Source: American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 32, No. 2 (Apr., 1995), pp. 139-151
Published by: University of Illinois Press on behalf of the North American Philosophical
Publications
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/20009814
Accessed: 08-10-2019 15:30 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

University of Illinois Press, North American Philosophical Publications are collaborating


with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to American Philosophical Quarterly

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Philosophical Quarterly
Volume 32, Number 2, April 1995

NON-INTENTIONAL ACTIONS
David K. Chan

Il here is no doubt that there is such a ality of an action. Two of these make refer?
thing as intentional action, which is the ence to the reasons the agent has for acting.
bringing about of events by agents who have Where they disagree is whether there is a
reasons foi bringing them about, and whose state of intending that is irreducible to rea?
performance of the actions of bringing about sons and their relation to action. The third
those events are explained by those reasons.1 alternative appeals to the notion of responsi?
It is also fairly uncontroversial to claim that, bility.3 This alternative is a non-starter. If
besides intentional actions, there are unin? there is any connection at all between inten?
tentional actions.2 But are these all the ac?
tionally and responsibility, the dependency is
tions there are? Is there not a further
in the wrong direction for our purposes. For
category of actions that are neither inten? we usually try to determine the agent's inten?
tional nor unintentional?
tion in acting before deciding on the question
To make a case for non-intentional action,
of responsibility. Even so, the presence or ab?
I must first explain what is meant by the in sence of intention is not always decisive. We
tentionality of an action. This must be done may hold a person responsible for what he
in such a way that the classification of action
as intentional and unintentional is one which
accidentally brings about, for what he does
that are not actions at all, and even for what
meshes with our intuitions as far as possible someone else does. For instance, a leader is
while being philosophically defensible. I will responsible for his subordinates' actions un?
then have to show that the same grounds der certain unexceptionable circumstances.
used to classify types of action support the
Or a ship-captain who accidentally spills oil
case for classifying some behavior as "non-in?
is responsible even if the occurrence is out?
tentional" action. This can be done by giving side his control.
examples of behavior which does not fit
Now it may be argued that there is more
neatly into a scheme where intentional action
than one sense of responsibility and what we
and unintentional action together exhaust are after is not the sense that is tied to social
the category of behavior that counts as ac?
tion. I will show that we are not entitled to roles. But why make this distinction? Is it be?
treat such behavior as either intentional or cause we want a sense of responsibility that
is conceptually linked with a person's own ac?
unintentional action on the basis of the pre?
tions? If so, we need a definition of action,
viously established criteria, and that we also
and for that, we are likely to fall back on the
have grounds not to treat the behavior as
non-action behavior. In other words, I will ex? concept of intentional action. Then we can no
longer, without circularity, account for inten?
pose a lacuna in the classificatory scheme
tionally in terms of responsibility.
that has been independently defended.
Even if the sense of responsibility we are
I. Action: interested in is not socially-defined, we need
INTENTIONAL AND UNINTENTIONAL to find other ways of classifying action, not in
terms of intentionality, that are more suitable
There are three alternative ways that have for linking up with responsibility. For interest
been proposed to account for the intention in responsibility arises with the need to ap

139

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
140 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

portion blame. Yet there are cases where an agent's reason lead him to act intentionally
agent is not blameworthy for wrong actions without his forming an intention to so act?
he does intentionally. A person may not be To answer these questions, we need to dis?
blamed for intentional actions that he is co? tinguish between a reason causing an action
erced or blackmailed into doing.4 We do not qua cause and a reason causing an action qua
suffer a great conceptual loss in decoupling reason. There are many ways a reason can
intentionality from responsibility. As our ex? cause action where it is not the case that the
amples show, we in fact gain by leaving room action is intentional in the sense defined in
for both intentional action for which the (II). First, a desire can motivate behavior
agent is not morally responsible, and non-ac? without coming to consciousness. Second,
tion for which he is held responsible. one can be conscious that one has a desire
So intentionality should be accounted for that causes one to do something without see?
not in terms of responsibility, but in terms of ing the desire as a reason for doing it. Finally,
one can see a desire that causes one to do
the agent's mental state in acting. The obvi?
ous such mental state to consider is that of something as a reason for doing it but not
make it the reason one does it. In none of
having a reason for acting. If an agent has a
reason for acting and acts for that reason, these cases does the agent do what he does
then he acts intentionally. What does it mean for a reason. To make a reason for doing
to say that he acts for that reason? It is not something the agent's reason for doing it, the
enough that he had the reason and then reason must enter into a process of practical
acted. For he may have acted on impulse or reasoning.10 The outcome of this process is a
for some other reason and not for that rea? commitment to a course of action. Such a
son. So let us add that he reasoned about it, commitment goes beyond just having the rea?
son for acting: it is having an intention to act,
i.e., thought about how to act in the light of a distinctive mental state that leads one to
his reason, and then acted.5 But did he act
act, possibly after further practical reasoning.
because of the reason he had for so acting?
So the state of intending is always causally
Was the performance of the action the out?
relevant when the agent acts for a reason.
come of his reasoning? Well, we can turn the But what I would like to establish is the
reasoning around and explain the action in
terms of the reason. But how do we distin? following claim about intentional action:
guish a case where the reason genuinely ex? (12) If the events brought about in acting are
plains the action from a case where the caused in the appropriate way by the
reason occurred to him but something else agent's intention to so act, the action is
intentional.
motivated him to act? Thus, it seems that the
explanation by reason has to be a causal one That is, I want to say that acting for a reason
for it to work as an explanation.6 So: and acting to satisfy an intention are one and
the same thing, so that the antecedents in (II)
(II) If an action is the bringing about of events
appropriately caused by the agent's reason and (12) are interchangeable. So in addition
for so acting, the action is intentional. to showing that one cannot act for a reason
without forming an intention to so act that
No mention has been made so far of a state
then plays a causal role, I need to show that
of intending that is not reducible to belief, one cannot be acting to satisfy an intention
desire, and their relation to action. We are without having a reason that is one's reason
however neglecting the agent's commitment for doing the action in question.
to action and the roles played by such a com? There are two cases to consider. Why can?
mitment in further practical reasoning. These not I be acting to satisfy an intention without
roles cannot be attributed to beliefs or de? having a reason to do the action? There is a
sires. Thus, we have a case on functionalist trivial and a non-trivial answer to this. The
grounds for a state of intending in its own trivial answer is that an intention to do some?
right.9 Is the state of intending always present thing is also a reason for doing it. The non
when an agent acts for a reason? Or can the trivial answer is that one forms an intention

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
NON-INTENTIONAL ACTIONS / 141

against a background of reasons for acting, ing it about.14 What can be agreed upon here
since an intention is the outcome of previous on the orthodox view is that an agent has to
practical reasoning. The reasoning process be doing something intentionally when he
should lead one to commit to doing an action performs an unintentional action. What he
that one has some reason for doing. If one does unintentionally is not the action intended,
had no reason for doing the action, one is but the unintentional action has to be appro?
unlikely to form an intention to do it. This priately connected to an intentional one:
raises the possibility of a second type of case.
(U) An unintentional action is performed if an
Suppose someone had no reason to do some
intention that an agent acts upon causes an
particular action rather than an alternative.
In what Michael Bratman calls a "Buridan unintended effect and the bringing about of
the latter effect counts as an action.
case," a person may have no reason to prefer
one route over another to get to his destina? Suppose that what I have given here is the
tion.12 He simply plumps for one of the complete account of the intentionality of ac?
routes by forming an intention so that he can tions.15 It would follow that intentional ac?
get on with filling in the details of his plan to tions are always done for a reason. If all
get there. Will he not end up carrying out an actions were either intentional or uninten?
intention to take the chosen route to his des? tional, then there must always be a reason
tination without having any reason to do that that a person acted for if he acted at all. If the
action? But this is not a genuine counterex? action was intentional, he acted for that very
ample. The agent has a reason for taking reason, which explains his action. If it was un?
some route or other to get to his destination intentional, he acted in the course of doing
even though he does not have a reason for something else intentionally, i.e., for a reason,
preferring the chosen route. In taking the but one which is not a reason that explains
chosen route, the agent does act for the for? his unintentional action. But if there are ac?
mer reason, which is part of the background tions that are not done in the course of doing
against which he does his practical reasoning something intentionally, i.e., for some reason,
and forms his intention. This example satis? then such actions are neither intentional nor
fies the antecedents of both (II) and (12), and unintentional. In claiming that there are non
the action is intentional.
intentional actions, I am arguing the case for
We can conclude that acting for or because there being such actions.
of a reason (in the sense explained earlier) is
the same as acting on an intention to perform II. Non-Intentional Action
that action. In both cases, the action is inten?
tional. (II) and (12) define intentional action I shall now give two kinds of examples of
in the same way. non-intentional action.16 The first example
How, on this account of intentional action, concerns what has been called a person's
do we accomodate unintentional actions? "mannerisms:"17
Traditionally, these have been accounted for A public speaker may have acquired the man?
in terms of intention as well.13 For an inten?
nerism of tugging at his ear-lobe once or twice
tion that is acted upon will not only be the as he is giving a speech. And he may do this
cause of the intended effects but also of myr? fully conscious of the quirky action he is per?
iad other effects. The problem is to distin? forming. So, on a particular occasion, he know?
guish the bringing about of effects that count ingly raises his arm in order to tug at his ear.
as actions, albeit unintentional, and those that But afterward, he tells us quite sincerely that
do not count as actions at all. We do not here he was wholly indifferent to whether he
have to resolve this problem, which is part tugged at the ear. It is just something that he
now and then does.
and parcel of the problem of the nature of
action. This is the problem of specifying what My second set of examples is that of cases
more there is to action than the event of acting out of either routine or habit. Even
brought about in acting, an event which can if there were initially reasons for developing
occur without there being an action of bring the routine or habit, i.e., for doing things in

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
142 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

that way, it is quite possible that these reasons concept of action to be a philosopher's inven?
no longer apply. The person just acts in that tion, and we do not want to resolve the ques?
way because that is how he has always acted tion of whether there are non-intentional
in that kind of situation or role. Sometimes, actions simply by fiat. It is rather our intui?
there may even be reasons to halt the routine tions on various aspects of human behavior,
or give up the habit if the agent were to re? including the existence of actions that can be
consider. Yet the continuation of the behav? described as non-intentional, that should be
ior does not show that he is no longer acting, our guide in formulating an account of what
nor that his behavior is no longer under his an action is.
control.18 Typical habitual actions occur So how can I respond to the objection?
when one sprinkles salt on one's food before What difference in kind is there, for instance,
eating, and when one is going through morn? between a person's tugging at his ear-lobe
ing routines in the bathroom. and his tossing around in bed while asleep?
It is possible that our intuitions will not be There may indeed be no difference - if the
in agreement concerning the above examples. mannerism is something the person can
Some may think that neither mannerisms nor never have the appropriate non-observa?
habitual actions count as actions at all. Oth? tional awareness of. What I am alluding to
ers may accept them as actions, but count here is something that we normally experi?
them as intentional actions.19 So in what fol? ence when acting. An agent is usually able to
lows, I shall give arguments to show, first, that tell immediately, without recourse to obser?
the two kinds of examples are of actions vation, that he is acting when he is. And if he
rather than of non-action behavior, and sec? fails to act, he is still able to say if asked what
ond, that they are of actions that should not it was that he was trying to do. Compare, for
count as either intentional or unintentional. instance, a clear case of action, someone's
shrugging his shoulders in response to a ques?
(i) Why non-intentional actions are tion he cannot answer, and a clear case of
actions
non-action behavior that involves bringing
Of my two kinds of examples, the most ob? about the same bodily movement, someone's
vious target of criticism is the first. Manner? shivering as a chilly wind hits him. Given that
isms, it may be objected, are behavior that the shivering is internally caused (although
may be peculiar to individuals but are no dif? triggered by the wind), the person has an im?
ferent from involuntary movements such as mediate awareness that he is shivering when
those a person makes while sleeping. Indeed, he is. But this awareness that he is shivering
if I am to make my case, I should be able to is not the same as the awareness that he has
show some important difference between that he is acting when he performs an action
what I call non-intentional action, and behav? of shrugging his shoulders. In the latter case,
ior that does not count as action at all. One the agent not only knows non-observation
way to do this is to resolve the problem of the ally that he is shrugging his shoulders when
nature of action. If I can give necessary and he is doing it, but has foreknowledge that he
sufficient conditions for something's being an will perform that particular action there and
action, then I can point to the satisfaction or then. This foreknowledge may be momentary,
not of such conditions to justify my class? but its presence can be established if we
ifying a particular example as an action or a imagine that the agent is prevented from act?
non-action. But the problem of the nature of ing. The one who would have shrugged his
action is a large problem, the solution of which shoulders will be able to say what it was that
will be complicated and involve the considera? he was trying to do. Whereas if someone had
tion of every type of behavior before drawing taken an anti-shivering drug, he will not say
general conclusions. Moreover, the question that he was trying unsuccessfully to shiver,
of the existence of non-intentional action is and he cannot tell when it was that he would
methodologically prior to that of the nature have shivered had he not been prevented
of action in general. For we do not want our from doing so.20 Some people may say that

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
NON-INTENTIONAL ACTIONS / 143

they can feel a shiver coming on. By this they a category that includes mannerisms and ha?
mean that they have feelings that, from past bitual actions, and an account of action that
experience, they associate with the onset of denies that either or both count as actions, is
shivering. Such "foreknowledge" however that I have merely described what people
lacks the immediacy of the foreknowledge take to be actions, whereas a philosophical
that I have that I will try to shrug my shoul? account should do some work in conceptual
ders just when I do.21 clarification. As explained earlier, I appeal to
I take it therefore to be a fact of ordinary intuitions because the concept of action
experience that distinctions are made, be? should not be a philosopher's invention. But
tween behavior that is like shrugging and be? I could still make my criterion for counting
havior that is like shivering, on the basis of mannerisms and habitual actions as actions
the kind of awareness a person has when he do some work by dismissing a class of behav?
is behaving. My example of a mannerism was ior that has often been confusedly called "ac?
carefully chosen such that its subject could be tions." In so doing, I further clarify what I
immediately aware that he is performing an take non-intentional actions to be by reject?
action as he is doing it. Thus, the mannerism ing something that does not fit into the class
is similar to the action of shrugging one's of actions that I have in mind.
shoulders, rather than the non-action behav? The class of behavior that has been sug?
ior of shivering in cold weather. Note also gested as examples of non-intentional action,
that we have established the similarity with? but which, on my account, do not count as
out appeal to intentionality, thereby leaving cases of action at all are so-called "spontane?
room for me to argue later that the mannerism, ous actions."22 If it were really the case that
unlike the action of shrugging one's shoulders something were done "spontaneously," then
in reply to a question, is non-intentional. the agent could not have had any non-obser?
It is easier to argue that habitual actions vational forewarning that he was going to do
are actions. For first, we could appeal to the what he did just then. Had the "spontaneous
argument I have just given to show that man? action" not occurred and he were asked to
nerisms are actions. The person who does report what he had been trying to do, he
something out of habit or routine can be im? would surely not have anything at all to re?
mediately aware that he is acting when he is port. For he did what he did without trying.
doing it, in the same way that someone shrug? He was in fact surprised to find himself doing
ging his shoulders can be aware. Secondly, it. Thus, his experience of such behavior is closer
many who reject mannerisms as examples of to his experience of shivering than his expe?
action are less reluctant to accept habitual ac? rience of shrugging. It is quite unlike the ex?
tions. This is because habitual actions are amples I gave earlier of non-intentional action.
often quite complicated and involve many
(ii) Why non-intentional actions are
coordinated steps. Accordingly, many have neither intentional nor unintentional
taken such actions to be intentional. And
they sometimes are. What I am arguing here Let us recall what was argued earlier about
is that they are not intentional when the the nature of intentional action. I put forward
agent no longer performs them for reasons, an account of intentional action as the bring?
even though one must have reasons to form ing about of events for the reason the agent
habits in the first place. So I will be arguing had for acting, or, what I have argued is the
in the next sub-section that there are habitual same thing, the causation in the right way of
actions that are not done in the course of do? those events brought about in acting by the
ing anything for a reason. agent's intention to so act. In acting uninten?
Before that, I want to show that my crite? tionally, an agent must have brought about
rion for counting mannerisms and habitual the unintended events in the course of doing
actions as actions is not overly inclusive. something intentionally. Assuming that this
There is also the possible objection that the account holds without exception, whether an
difference between my claim about actions as agent acts intentionally or unintentionally,

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
144 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

there must be some reason for which he acts, brings us back to the case, made by Bratman,
and he must have an intention that causes the for the irreducibility of intention to other
events he brings about in acting. mental states. Physical entities can in princi?
If someone performs an action of the kind ple be distinguished from one another on the
given in my examples, that I call "non-inten? basis of spatio-temporal criteria. Can we in?
tional," does he not do something that he has dividuate mental types without committing
reason for doing? Here, the hard cases are ourselves to either a type-identity theory of
likely to be habitual actions rather than man? the mind, or introducing mental stuff or sub?
nerisms. As I said before, many who accept stances? Bratman distinguishes intention
habitual actions as actions do so because they from other mental states using a functionalist
think of them as intentional actions. How can approach:23
it be denied that habitual actions are done for
The way to confront skepticism about [a men?
reasons?
tal state] - in particular, future-directed inten?
My opponent may present me with a di? tion - is to show that [the mental state] can be
lemma. Either a habitual action is intentional
embedded in . . .a web of regularities and
or it is not an action at all. But my account of norms_We can also support the claim that
"non-intentional action" requires that habit? our commonsense framework sees [the mental
ual actions be actions. Hence they must in state] as a distinctive attitude ... by showing
fact be intentional. Although the grounds how the nexus of regularities and norms in
that I gave for taking habitual actions to be terms of which we understand [the mental
actions did not directly appeal to reasons or state] differs in systematic and important ways
from those in terms of which we understand
intentions, my opponent asserts that I have in
[other mental states].
fact covertly relied on such an appeal. For I
argued that someone who does something According to Bratman, dispositions and
out of habit could be immediately aware that regularities concerning reasoning are central
he is acting when he is doing it, and aware of to our commonsense understanding of inten?
what it is that he is trying to do if he does not tion. What is distinctive about intentions are
succeed. Moreover, I conceded that habitual the roles they play as inputs into practical
actions are frequently complex and require reasoning. Intentions are the constitutive ele?
coordination. My opponent concludes his ments of plans of action. As limited rational
case by attributing the functions of planning, agents, we formulate partial plans in order to
coordination, control, and awareness to a coordinate our activities intrapersonally and
state of intending that is the cause of the interpersonally, and to increase the amount
events brought about in performing a habit? of time available for deliberation that cannot
ual action. Therefore, habitual actions are in? be left to the last minute. The role of prior
tentional. plans is to serve as a framework for further
What I shall now argue is that those func? reasoning. Prior intentions structure an
tions attributed to intention need not all be agent's practical reasoning in two ways: they
attributed to intention. In fact, there are ad? pose the problem of finding the means for
vantages to distinguishing the roles proper to fulfilling the intentions; and they constrain
intention from those that are fulfilled by the admissibility of options for future action,
some other mental state of the agent. Once I disallowing those that conflict with intended
have made the distinction between roles, I courses of action.24 Thus, a rational agent has
can argue that it is not necessary for the roles to satisfy the demands for "means-end coher?
proper to intention to be fulfilled in order ence" and "strong consistency" between in?
that an action be performed, and that the tentions and beliefs, because by meeting
roles that do have to be fulfilled can be ful? these demands a limited agent increases the
filled by something other than an intention in likelihood of getting what he wants.
the case of non-intentional action. It is clear that desires do not serve the
What do I mean by a role or roles proper same roles as intentions and are not subject
to a mental state such as intention? This to the same rational demands. There is noth

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
NON-INTENTIONAL ACTIONS /145

ing irrational about not finding means to sat? There is no evidence on functionalist
isfy a desire that one sincerely holds, nor is grounds for the presence of intention when a
there anything irrational in holding a set of habitual action is performed.26 On my earlier
desires that cannot all be satisfied in a world account of intentionality, the absence of in?
in which our beliefs are true. Thus, on the tention entails that the action is not inten?
functionalist approach, intention and desire are tional. This may now be challenged on the
mental states that are distinct from each other. grounds that habitual action is an example of
I will now show that there need not be any? intentional action without the agent having
thing that satisfies the roles distinctive of in? an intention to so act, showing hence that my
tention when a habitual action is performed. earlier account lacks generality. First,
Intentions serve as inputs into further practi? Rosalind Hursthouse has argued for there
cal reasoning. That is what makes them inten? being intentional actions that are not done
tions and not mere desires. But is there for any reasons at all. Second, I have still to
practical reasoning prior to habitual action? account for the control and guidance an
A distinction must be made between the rea? agent has over his habitual action. I said ear?
soning done when the habit is first formed lier that these functions need not be included
and the reasoning done when the action is among those distinctive of the state of inten?
performed habitually. I deny only that any tion. But if these functions can be attributed
reasoning goes on when a habitual action is to another mental state, the existence of
performed. The forming of a habit occurs which is sufficient for the action to be inten?
through the intentional performance of the tional, then the absence of intention when a
action. But once the action has become ha? habitual action is performed is not enough to
bitual, it is non-intentional. For the action is prove that the action is not intentional.
now done out of habit, and not for the rea? In what follows, I will first deal with the
sons that originally prompted the action second challenge before turning to a discus?
when it was intentional. The action will con? sion of Hursthouse's "arational actions."
tinue to be performed even when the original Now Bratman seems to have suggested that
reasons are no longer valid, or no longer sup? there is a kind of mental entity other than
port this course of action. In such a case, the intention that may guide action. He argues,
action would not be performed if the agent contrary to my view, that one can act inten?
had reasoned about whether to do it instead tionally without having the intention to so
of doing it out of habit. For example, a person act. When one acts intentionally, what one
in the habit of adding salt to his food will do also does is endeavor to act. But one can en?
so even when the food is tasty enough, and deavor to act and act intentionally without
he would agree that it is if asked about it.25 intending to so act.27 The reason why Brat?
Because the action was intentional when man draws a distinction between intending
the habit was first formed, we have an expla? and endeavoring is that the former is subject
nation of how a complex habitual action is to consistency requirements to which the lat?
possible without reasoning at the time it is ter is not. Bratman has an example in which
performed. The planning needed to develop a person aims to perform each of two actions
a complex action involving sequences of even though he knows that he cannot suc?
means and ends took place when the action ceed in doing both.28 It may be the best strat?
was first performed non-habitually. The abil? egy for success in doing one of the two
ity to perform the same action non-intention actions that one should try to do each. Yet
ally, i.e., as a habitual action, without con? given what the agent knows, he cannot intend
cerning oneself with how one does it, is ac? to do both since such an intention is inconsis?
quired through the practice of doing that ac? tent with his beliefs. Since rational intentions
tion intentionally over a period of time. Once are agglomerative, he cannot then intend to
the ability is acquired, one can (although one do each of the two actions. Yet his behavior
does not have to) perform the action without in each case is guided by his goal in acting.
the intention that formerly preceded it. Bratman has set up his example so that the

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
146 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

two actions are symmetrical. There is no human creature that is not capable of plan?
question of intending to do one of the actions ning may engage in goal-directed behavior,
but not the other. As a solution, Bratman al? and this may even count as action if the fur?
lows that the agent endeavors, without in? ther condition, of its potentially having imme?
tending, to do each of the two actions. Since diate awareness that it is acting, is satisfied.
endeavoring is not subject to the requirement Therefore it is not justified to take the ac?
of consistency with the agent's beliefs, he can tion one endeavors without intending to per?
endeavor to perform each of the actions even form to be intentional. There is, on the one
though he knows that he cannot do both. hand, action that one intends to do that in?
Bratman thinks that endeavoring without volves practical reasoning. There is, on the
intending is, when it produces the event other hand, action that one merely endeavors
aimed at, sufficient for intentional action. For to do that involves only guidance in a tele?
to endeavoring can be attributed the role of ological sense. I see no advantage in taking
guiding one's behavior. But two senses of the actions performed to be intentional in
guidance need to be distinguished. There is a both cases, for doing so not only obscures an
sense of guidance that is associated with important distinction between them, but
would also make it seem somewhat arbitrary
practical reasoning, which is how intention
to deny intentional action to any system ca?
guides behavior. If endeavoring involves this
pable of goal-directed acts, whether it plans
kind of guidance, then it is like intention in
or not. It is theoretically more satisfying to
being subject to the demand for means-end
coherence. But in the case we considered ear? take the actions that involve only guidance in
a teleological sense to belong to a category
lier of a habitual action, we found no mental of its own, that of non-intentional but volun?
state that involves practical reasoning and tary action.
that is subject to the rationality constraints Finally, the immediate awareness that an
distinctive of intention. What Bratman seems
agent has, that he is acting when he is, should
to have in mind instead, when noticing the not be attributed to intention either. The
guiding function involved in endeavoring, is agent does not have such an awareness until
guidance in a teleological sense; i.e., an action he has actually commenced acting, even if he
is directed at some object at which it aims:29 had the intention all along. The awareness is
For me to endeavor [to act] is, in part, for me common to both the actions that one has an
to guide my conduct accordingly. In a normal intention to perform and those that one only
case this means that, other things equal, I will endeavors, without intending, to perform. So
be prepared to make adjustments in what I am the presence of such awareness does not
doing in response to indications of my success show the action to be intentional. Rather, it
or failure in [acting]. I will be prepared to ad? seems to be a mark of action in general.
just [my action] ... in ways believed by me to Let me turn now to the first of the two
promote that goal.
challenges to my claim that absence of inten?
This kind of guidance is independent of the tion when a habitual action is performed en?
roles that are distinctive of intention. I can tails that the action is non-intentional.
grant that it occurs when a habitual action is According to Rosalind Hursthouse, there are
performed. The hand motions that I make "arational actions" that are intentional but
when I brush my teeth may be done from not done for any reason at all. Her examples
habit, but my hand has to respond to the ar? are of actions done in the grip of an emotion,
rangement of the teeth in my mouth, the not in order to express the emotion, but qua
length of my toothbrush, and so on. But given expression of emotion.30 Do habitual actions
that the action is habitual, there is no neces? also belong to this category of actions? Since
sity for practical reasoning to be involved as Hursthouse does not cite them as examples,
it had when the habit was first formed. And we have to answer this question by under?
the fact of there being a goal to be promoted standing why Hursthouse considers emo?
by one's action does not by itself entail there tional actions arational and by examining the
being an intention to be fulfilled. Even a non implications for habitual actions.

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
NON-INTENTIONAL ACTIONS /147

Hursthouse compares two actions done in under the bedclothes could not, since there is
the grip of the emotion of fear.31 If one flees no available reason for doing so. But both
in terror from a lion, a reason can be ascribed actions are equally non-intentional. Habitual
for doing so. But if one burrows under the action is more like the first kind of non-inten?
bedclothes out of fear of ghosts or thunder, it tional action. Although I may habitually
does not make sense to ascribe an analogous sprinkle salt over my food without first tast?
reason because such an ascription would at? ing it, I may now have read about how over
tribute an absurd belief, i.e., that one would consumption of salt causes heart disease. I
be safe under the bedclothes. It is mysterious may still do what I habitually do, but I will in
why there should be a great disanalogy be? this instance reason about it and then form
tween the two cases. It cannot be denied, says an intention to sprinkle salt over my food.
Hursthouse, that actions of the latter kind are There is a disanalogy between this action and
also intentional, "for they are clearly not un? my previous habitual action that is worth not?
intentional, and to say they form a significant ing by classifying one action as intentional
class of actions that are neither intentional and the other as non-intentional.
nor unintentional is to admit that, within the I conclude that there is no basis for class?
standard account, they present a formidable ifying emotional actions as intentional and
problem." therefore arational, in preference to intro?
Hursthouse does not say why she is against ducing a class of action that is neither inten?
introducing a class of actions that are neither tional nor unintentional, namely non
intentional nor unintentional. In fact, it seems intentional action. I do not want to make fur?
to me that the introduction of such a class of ther claims about where emotional actions
actions has the advantage of resolving the belong in my classificatory scheme without
mystery of the "great disanalogy." For we can having examined the different types of such
then distinguish between two kinds of action actions in more detail. What I do claim is that
that one may be performing in fleeing from there is nothing in Hursthouse's argument
a lion. In one case, one reasons about one's for arational actions that makes a persuasive
situation and forms an intention to run. In case for classifying habitual action (and other
another (more typical) case, one does the in? actions not done for any reason) as inten?
stinctive thing and simply runs away. This ac? tional. In fact, the introduction of the concept
tion may be goal-directed but it is not guided of non-intentional action enables me to make
by an intention. Even if in the second case we useful distinctions that are concealed by her
can attribute to the agent the same desire and classificatory scheme. Having rejected the
belief that constitute a reason for running in wider extension that Hursthouse gives to in?
the first case, he did not run for that reason. tentional action, I can amend my earlier more
The action is non-intentional just like the ac? cautionary criteria of intentionality as follows:
tion of hiding under the bedclothes. The mys?
(II') An action is intentional iff it is the bringing
tery of a disanalogy where there should not
about of events appropriately caused by the
be one is created by confusing the two cases agent's reason for so acting.
of running from the lion. There is indeed a
disanalogy between the case where the agent (12') An action is intentional iff the events
forms an intention to run and that of hiding brought about in acting are caused in the
under the bedclothes, an action which the appropriate way by the agent's intention to
so act.
agent has no non-absurd reason to do. There
is however no disanalogy when the case we Now that I have argued the case that ha?
are concerned with is that of running non-in bitual action is non-intentional, it is quite
tentionally from the lion. straightforward to establish the same for
The important point to note here is that mannerisms. As I stated in my example of a
the person who flees from the lion non-inten mannerism, an agent is "wholly indifferent"
tionally could have done the same action in? to whether he performs it. Since he is not
tentionally, whereas the person who hides committed to acting, he is not under any ra

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
148 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

tional constraint to do the kind of practical advantages of distinguishing non-intentional


reasoning that typifies intention. But the ac? actions from the other kinds of action.34
tion nevertheless has to be guided in the tele? One of the important problems in moral
ological sense. For the agent who tugs at his psychology is weakness of will or akrasia.
ear has to direct his hand to the place where Traditionally, the possibility of acting against
his ear-lobe is located. A mannerism is like a one's better judgment has in effect been de?
habitual action in requiring guidance that nied. If a person does not do the thing that is
does not involve practical reasoning. It is best for him to do, then he must have miscal?
therefore also a non-intentional action.
culated his own best interest or he is acting
out of ignorance or under compulsion.35
III. The Importance of More recently, recognition has been given to
Non-Intentional Action the possibility of a form of akrasia that is due
to a self-deceptive failure by an agent to form
I have now set up a classificatory scheme
an intention that corresponds to his "all
that distinguishes between intentional, unin?
things-considered" judgment in favor of a
tentional, and non-intentional action, which
course of action.36 No room is left however
rests on clear criteria derived from the way
the mental antecedents of action are distin? for "last-ditch akrasia," the failure of an
agent to act on an intention correctly formed
guished from one another.32 To sum up, we
at the conclusion of practical reasoning.37
have the following definitions of each kind of
action:33 It is quite likely that the possibility of last
ditch akrasia has been denied because it is
Intentional action: the action of bringing thought that an agent has to be doing some?
about an event for the reason the agent had for
thing intentionally if his bringing about of an
bringing about the event, or, equivalently, the event is to count as an action. So if he has an
appropriate causation of the event brought
intention that he forms as a result of practical
about in acting by the agent's intention to so
act. reasoning, his failure to carry out the inten?
tion is involuntary. If he does something else
Unintentional action: the action of bringing instead, the behavior does not result from an
about an unintended event in the course of intention and hence is not an action. His in?
performing an intentional action.
ability to do that which he intends to do is not
Non-intentional action: the action of bringing a case of acting against his better judgment.
about an unintended event but not in the It is not a case of acting at all.
course of performing an intentional action; i.e., The denial of last-ditch akrasia goes, I
an action in which the agent is not acting for a think, against our intuitions about and our
reason when performing. experience of the phenomenon. So the recog?
It may now be asked whether it matters so nition of the possibility of non-intentional ac?
much which scheme we use to distinguish be? tion enables us to give a more realistic
tween types of action? The answer is that the account of akrasia. If the main obstacle to an
conceptual distinctions suggested above can account of last-ditch akrasia is the refusal to
be useful for addressing important questions accept that one can act without doing any?
in philosophy. So there are costs involved in thing intentionally, then it counts in favor of
neglecting this class of action. What I will do my proposed classificatory scheme that it
in conclusion is to describe briefly one of the leaves room for such action.38

National University of Singapore


Received October 6,1994

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
NON-INTENTIONAL ACTIONS / 149

NOTES

1.1 leave aside for the time being the question of whether there are intentional actions that are not done
for any reason at all, of the kind suggested by Rosalind Hursthouse, "Arational Actions," The Journal of
Philosophy, vol. 88 (1991), pp. 57-68.
2. For a skeptical view, see J.W. Meiland, "Are There Unintentional Actions?" The Philosophical Review,
vol. 72 (1963), pp. 377-81.
3. Michael Bratman, who makes a good case for an irreducible state of intending, nevertheless uses the
notion of responsibility to account for intentionality in action. This is because he rejects what he calls the
Simple View, which takes having an intention to perform an action as a necessary condition for the
intentionality of the action performed. See Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason (Cambridge:Harvard
University Press, 1987), Chapter 8.1 present a solution to the problem Bratman raises for the Simple View
in another paper, "Intention and Belief (unpublished). Here I simplify matters by ignoring Bratman's
objection to the Simple View and concentrating instead on rejecting his alternative account of intention?
ality in terms of responsibility.
4. The fact that the action is not freely chosen is not sufficient for ruling out its intentionality.
5. The distinction here is between having reasons for acting and those reasons being the agent's reasons for
acting. I am suggesting that, for the latter to be the case, the reasons must operate by way of the agent's
practical reasoning.
6. Thus Donald Davidson argued in "Actions, Reasons, and Causes" in Essays on Actions and Events
(Oxford:Clarendon Press, 1980).
7. An anonymous referee has suggested that I "loosen" (II) to read "If an action involves the bringing
about of events appropriately linked to the agent's reason for so acting, the action is intentional." I believe
first that describing an action as the bringing about of events is neutral enough and leaves open the
possibility that the action includes the events brought about. While the point about not unnecessarily
taking a stand on the causal account of reasons explanation is well taken, I have decided to leave the main
text as it is while clarifying here that my case for non-intentional actions can be made without the
particular theoretical commitments implicit in my definition. The reason for my decision is that I am
writing in the context of a tradition in the philosophy of action in which a strong case can be made for
non-intentional actions. But given the referee's point, it should be simple enough to articulate the case for
non-intentional actions in non-Davidsonian traditions by adapting what I say here.
8. Davidson (ibid.) argues that a primary reason for action is constituted of a belief-desire pair with the
appropriate contents.
9. Bratman, Chapters 1-3, argues on such grounds for intention to count as a mental state in its own right,
to be distinguished from belief and desire.
10. There is a normative element to practical reasoning. However, I am not insisting that the agent be
perfectly rational, only that he does some reasoning and forms an intention taking into account his reasons
for acting. His reasoning need not be "right" by some criterion of practical rationality. By the same token,
some agents may do more reasoning in that they take more reasons into account or consider more
alternative courses of action or work out more detailed plans. Again, I do not insist that for the agent to
make a reason his reason for acting, he match up to some ideal of completeness or thoroughness in
practical reasoning. Finally, I do not insist that every stage of the agent's reasoning be consciously carried
out. The agent may have developed short-cuts in reasoning, and some of these steps can become pro?
grammed into his brain and be carried out automatically.
11. There is always the possibility of deviant causality in which an intended event is caused by the intention
but not in a way that will render it appropriate for us to call it intentional, or an action at all. I leave the
specification of "appropriateness" aside since I am interested only in what makes an action intentional,
given that it is intentional.
12. Bratman, p. 11.
13. See for instance, Davidson, "Agency" in Essays, p. 46.

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
150 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

14.1 will have to touch on the problem of the nature of action when I give reasons for taking non-inten?
tional actions to be actions rather than non-action behavior. But I do not have to answer the question
regarding unintentional action that is raised here. For non-intentional actions as I shall define them are not
actions that are done in the course of acting intentionally. So they do not fall into any grey area between
the bringing about of effects that counts as acting unintentionally, and the bringing about of effects that
does not count as acting at all.
15. The challenge that I am postponing discussion of is that posed by Hursthouse's "arational actions,"
supposedly intentional actions that are not done for any reason (p. 59). I will argue in Section II(ii) that it
is theoretically more satisfying to treat the cases that she considers to be examples of such actions as
instead instances of non-intentional action. To do that, I have to first make it clearer what I take
non-intentional actions to be and give some examples, which is what I will proceed to do next.
16.1 do not by any means think that there are no other kinds of examples, but I have selected examples that
I think will appeal to the reader's intuition. The examples I give here have also been noticed by others
writing about action.
17. I borrow this example from George M. Wilson, The Intentionality of Human Action, rev. edn.
(Stanford.Stanford University Press, 1989), p. 192. Similar examples include "twiddling" one's fingers (this
example courtesy of Michael Bratman) and chewing on the end of one's pencil. Wilson, who gives a
teleological account of the intentionality of action, takes his example to be of an intentional action. I will argue
that goal-directedness is a characteristic not just of intentional action but of non-intentional action as well. The
non-intentional mannerisms I have in mind need not be "knowingly" done as in Wilson's example.
18. It is not a necessary condition for a habitual action to be non-intentional that the original reason be no
longer applicable. Examples in which the original reason for developing the habit no longer applies are
meant to bring out the non-intentional nature of the action. An action could be non-intentional even when
the reason still applies, as long as it is done out of habit and the agent does not have an intention that he
acts on when he does it.
19. The kind of examples I give here, especially of habitual actions, have been recognized as cases of action
that is not done for a reason by, e.g., Lawrence H. Davis, Theory of Action (Englewood Cliffs :Prentice
Hall, 1979), pp. 7-8; Myles Brand, The Nature of Human Action (Glenview:Scott, Foresman & Company,
1970), p. 14; and Bernard Gert and Timothy J. Duggan, "Free Will as the Ability to Will," Nous, vol. 13
(1979), p. 208. Brian O'Shaughnessy, The Will, Vol. 2 (Cambridge?Cambridge University Press, 1980)
recognizes bodily mannerisms when he mentions the actions of "idle tongue movings" (p. 15) and
"stroking [one's] chin simplicit?r" (p. 18).
20. Another way of establishing the difference between the two cases is to note how the person who does
not succeed in shrugging is immediately surprised. Someone who fails to shiver may also be surprised, but
only after observing that it is chilly and inferring that such weather normally causes him to shiver.
21.1 do not of course attribute to the agent foreknowledge that he will act. (The world may end before he
succeeds in acting.) Nor do I attribute to the agent infallible authority as to what it is that he is trying to do.
(A devilishly clever neuroscientist may have rewired his nervous system without his knowledge.) The
point though is that it is one thing for a neuroscientist fiddling about in the brain to make a person think
that he is about to act in a certain way (e.g., shrug his shoulders), and quite another thing to make a person
think he is about to be struck with some involuntary behavior (e.g., shivering). The kind of knowledge he
needs to induce is different, and this is why a person can tell immediately that he is acting when he is.
22. Carl Ginet, On Action (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1990), p. 3, cites a spontaneous action
as an example of what he calls an action done "for no particular reason". Michael Bratman, p. 126, gives an
example of "spontaneously" catching a ball unexpectedly thrown at one, which he says could be a
non-intentional action.
23. Bratman, pp. 9-10.
24. Ibid.,pp.31-33.
25. It has been suggested to me that habitual actions are done in the course of doing something intentional
that one does have reason to do. For example, one adds salt to one's food in the course of having a meal.
But adding salt to one's food is not a mere unintended side-effect that accompanies one's having a meal.
Rather, it is a further course of action that has to be initiated separately by the agent. My point is that it is
not initiated by an intention to add salt to one's food nor is it initiated by an intention to have a meal.

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
NON-INTENTIONAL ACTIONS /151

26. For the functionalist, it does not make sense to attribute to a rational agent intentions that do not play
their normal roles in practical reasoning. But a person who acts from habit is not necessarily criticizably
irrational. A referee has asked whether I am conceding that only functionalists are bound to deny the
presence of intention when a habitual action is performed. The answer is affirmative, but this concession is
not damaging to me because it has proved difficult for non-functionalists to make a plausible case for a
distinctive state of intention, even where clearly intentional actions are concerned.
27. Ibid., p. 129. There are in addition the so-called "double-effect" cases, where an expected but unwanted
side-effect is brought about in carrying out one's intention. Bratman argues that the agent neither intends
nor endeavors to bring about this side-effect (p. 142), but the action of bringing it about is intentional in
that the agent may be held responsible for doing it (p. 124). Since I have already argued against defining
intentionality of action in terms of responsibility, I only have to consider cases where intention is absent
but there is endeavoring.
28.This is Bratman's much discussed "video-games example" in ibid.,pp. 113-5.
29. Ibid.,p. 129.
30. Hursthouse, p. 61.
31./Wd., pp. 63-4.
32. Aubrey Townsend suggested the following objection to my classificatory scheme: whereas, following
Davidson, the classification of actions as intentional or unintentional is description-relative, I am suppos?
ing there to be a description-independent class of non-intentional actions, which is characterised only by
the absence of intention. I do not think I am committed to this supposition. Although there is no intention
to specify a description of the goal of a non-intentional action, it remains that one endeavors or tries to
attain a goal under some description. For instance, when I non-intentionally tug at my earlobe, I do not also
non-intentionally raise my hand above the table (assuming Davidson's theory of individuation so that this
is a redescription of the same action). The first is a mannerism of mine which I aim at doing, not the second.
33. Note that since I am not giving a definition of action in general here, there is nothing circular in the
definiens of intentional, unintentional, and non-intentional action, even though reference is made to the
concept of action.
34. Besides my example from moral psychology, I also see applications for my classificatory scheme in
thinking about the motivational psychology of action and the nature of action.
35. Both Plato and Aristotle gave such accounts of akrasia.
36. This is the interpretation that David Pears gives of Davidson's account in "How is Weakness of the Will
Possible?" in Essays, pp. 21-42. For Pears' interpretation, see his "Motivated Irrationality," Proceedings
of the Aristotelian Society, Supplement, vol. 56 (1982), pp. 157-78.
37. The expression "last-ditch akrasia" originated from Pears, ibid.
38. An earlier version of this paper was read at philosophy colloquia at the National University of
Singapore and at Monash University in Australia. I thank all of those who helped me with their comments
on these occasions, not all of whose views I may have accommodated to their satisfaction. I also thank the
anonymous referee who gave me useful suggestions for improving the paper.

This content downloaded from 14.139.69.36 on Tue, 08 Oct 2019 15:30:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like