Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 41

The Missing Motivation in Macroeconomics†

By GEORGE A. AKERLOF*

Macroeconomics changed between the early on the cover of Time.2 Even Milton Friedman
1960s and the late 1970s. The macroeconomics was famously—although perhaps misleadingly—
of the early 1960s was avowedly Keynesian. quoted: “We are all Keynesians now.”3 A little
This was manifested in the textbooks of the more than a decade later Robert Lucas and
time, which showed a remarkable unity from Thomas Sargent (1979) had published “After
the introductory through the graduate levels.1 Keynesian Macroeconomics.” The love-fest was
John Maynard Keynes appeared, posthumously, over.
The decline of the old-style Keynesian eco-
nomics was due in part to the simultaneous rise

Presidential Address delivered at the one hundred eigh- in inflation and unemployment in the late 1960s
teenth meeting of the American Economic Association, and early 1970s. That occurrence was impossi-
January 6, 2007, Chicago, IL. ble to reconcile with the simple nonaccelera-
* Department of Economics, University of California at tionist Phillips curves of the time.
Berkeley, 549 Evans Hall, Berkeley, CA 94720 (e-mail:
akerlof@econ.berkeley.edu). This paper is based on a long- But Keynesian economics also declined be-
term research program with Rachel Kranton on the impli- cause of a change in economic methodology.
cations of identity for economic behavior. Our previous The Keynesians had emphasized the depen-
joint papers (Akerlof and Kranton 2000, 2002, 2005) have dence of consumption on disposable income
explored implications outside of macroeconomics of utility
functions dependent on people’s notions of what ought to
and, similarly, of investment on current prof-
be. Some of this paper— especially Section III (“The Miss- its and current cash flow.4 They posited a
ing Motivation: Norms”) and Section IX (“Economic Meth- Phillips curve, where nominal—rather than
odology”)— has been directly taken from our joint real—wage inflation depended upon the un-
manuscript: The Missing Motivation: Economics Made Hu- employment rate, which was used as an indi-
man (Akerlof and Kranton 2006). I am especially grateful to
Professor Kranton for extending to me the invitation to join cation of the looseness of the labor market.
this project, after she had the initial insight in the spring of They based these functions on their own in-
1996 that concerns regarding identity were missing from trospection regarding how the various actors
economic theory. I have also benefited from conversations in the economy would behave. They also
with Robert Shiller, with whom I am coauthoring work on brought some discipline into their judgments
behavioral macroeconomics. In addition, I especially wish
to thank Robert Akerlof and Janet Yellen for invaluable by estimating statistical relations.5
advice. I also want to thank Roland Bénabou, Alan Blinder, But a new school of thought, based on clas-
Louis Christofides, Stephen Cosslett, Ernst Fehr, David
Hirshleifer, Houston McCulloch, John Morgan, George
Perry, Antonio Rangel, Paola Sapienza, Robert Solow, Den-
2
nis Snower, and Luigi Zingales, and seminar participants at Time, December 31, 1965. His appearance on the cover
the IMF, the World Bank, Ohio State University, Vanderbilt was especially remarkable because Time covers are rarely
University, the University of California at Berkeley, the posthumous. Keynes had died in 1946.
3
Munich Behavioral Economics Summer Camp, the 2006 But in a later disclaimer, Friedman said, almost surely
Macroeconomics and Individual Decision Making Confer- correctly, that he had been quoted out of context. See
ence of the NBER and the Federal Reserve Bank of Boston, http://www.libertyhaven.com/thinkers/miltonfriedman/
and at the Social Interactions, Identity, and Well-Being, and miltonexkeynesian.html, which quotes Friedman (1968),
Institutions, Organizations, and Growth groups of the CIAR. I Dollars and Sense, 15.
4
am also grateful to Marina Halac for invaluable research as- The treatment of consumption in The General Theory,
sistance and to the Canadian Institute for Advanced Research as we shall see below, was typical of such thinking. Keynes
and to the National Science Foundation under Research Grant first discusses the dependence of consumption on current
SES 04-17871 for invaluable financial support. income, which he clearly sees as the primary determinant of
1
See, for example, Paul A. Samuelson (1964), Thomas current consumption; but, in addition, he makes a long list
F. Dernburg and Duncan M. McDougall (1967), and Gard- of other factors that will alter the relation between consump-
ner Ackley (1961). The econometric model of Lawrence R. tion and current income.
5
Klein and Arthur S. Goldberger (1955) provides a useful A good example of this methodology can be seen in
synopsis of the variables that the early Keynesians thought Alban W. Phillips’s (1958) mixture of light theory and
most important for a macroeconomic model, and how they statistical analysis in his estimation of the relation between
would be included. wage inflation and unemployment.
5
6 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

sical economics, objected to the casual ways of cal economics: that constrained maximization
these folks. New Classical critics of Keynesian of profit and utility functions is the appropriate
economics insisted instead that these relations microfoundation for macroeconomics. They
be derived from fundamentals. They said that also viewed the neutralities as having a certain
macroeconomic relationships should be derived sort of generality. The neutralities do commonly
from profit-maximizing by firms and from utility- describe equilibria of competitive economies
maximizing by consumers with economic argu- with complete information, irrespective of peo-
ments in their utility functions. ple’s preferences—as long as those preferences
The new methodology had a profound effect correspond to economists’ typical descriptions
on macroeconomics. Five separate neutrality re- of them. The Keynesians then resurrected some—
sults overturned aspects of macroeconomics but not all— of the Keynesian conclusions by add-
that Keynesians had previously considered in- ing a variety of frictions to the New Classical
contestable. These five neutralities are: the in- model. Those frictions include credit constraints,
dependence of consumption and current income market imperfections, information failures, tax
(the life-cycle permanent income hypothesis); distortions, staggered contracts, uncertainty,
the irrelevance of current profits to investment menu costs, and bounded rationality. This formu-
spending (the Modigliani-Miller theorem); the lation preserves many (but not all) Keynesian
long-run independence of inflation and unem- conclusions regarding cyclical fluctuations and
ployment (natural rate theory); the inability of macroeconomic policy.
monetary policy to stabilize output (the rational This lecture will suggest a new stance in
expectations hypothesis); and the irrelevance of regard to each of the five neutralities. Like New
taxes and budget deficits to consumption (Ricar- Classical and New Keynesian economics, it will
dian equivalence).6 These results fly in the face derive behavior from utility and profit maximi-
of Keynesian economics. They undermine its zation. That captures the purposefulness of eco-
conclusions about the behavior of the economy nomic decisions. But this lecture will also
and the impact of stabilization policy. question the generality of the preferences that
The discovery of these five neutrality propo- lead to the five neutralities. There is a sense in
sitions surprised macroeconomists. They had which those preferences are very narrowly de-
not suspected that radically anti-Keynesian con- fined. They have important missing motiva-
clusions were the logical outcome of such seem- tion—since they fail to incorporate the norms of
ingly innocuous maximizing assumptions. the decision makers. Those norms reflect how
the respective decision makers think they and
I. Neutralities and Preferences others should or should not behave, even in the
absence of frictions. Preferences reflecting such
How did macroeconomists react to the dis- norms yield a macroeconomics with important
covery of the five neutralities? On the one hand, remnants of the early Keynesian thinking. They
the New Classical economists viewed their neu- also yield a macroeconomics that, in important
trality results as a telltale: that Keynesian econ- details, cannot be obtained only with frictions.
omists of the previous generation had been We shall see that, with such preferences, even
thinking in the wrong way. In their view, sci- in the absence of frictions, each of the five
entific reasoning was producing a new, leaner, neutralities will be systematically violated. Spe-
more precise economics. cifically:
On the other hand, Keynesian economists, for
the most part, reacted differently. In due course ● A realistic norm regarding consumption be-
they came to view the neutralities as logically havior will make consumption directly de-
impeccable. These New Keynesians accepted pendent on current income, in violation of the
the methodological dictums of the New Classi- neutrality of consumption given wealth;
● A realistic norm will make investment di-
6
rectly dependent on cash flow, in violation of
Of course, it took some time for the implications of Modigliani-Miller;
these neutrality results to be fully appreciated. For example,
life-cycle consumption and Modigliani-Miller were initially ● A realistic norm will make wages and prices
considered as nothing more than useful codicils to Keyne- dependent on nominal considerations and
sian thinking. thus violate natural rate theory;
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 7

● A realistic norm will make income and em- neity may sometimes dampen, but will rarely
ployment dependent on systematic monetary nullify, the conclusions of this lecture.
policy, and thus violate rational expectations
theory; and II. The Five Neutrality Results
● A realistic norm will make current consump-
tion dependent on the current generation’s For clarity, this section will now give an
social security receipts, in violation of Ricar- overview of each of the five neutrality results.
dian equivalence.
A. Dependence of Consumption on Wealth,
Additionally, insofar as the behavior assumed Not Income
by the early Keynesians differed from the be-
havior that produces the neutralities, there is Standard theory tells us that, under only
likely to be a bias in favor of the Keynesians. somewhat special conditions, consumption de-
The Keynesians based their models on their pends on wealth, which is the value of current
observation of motivations, rather than on ab- assets plus the discounted value of future earn-
stract derivations. If there is a difference be- ings.7 Thus there is no tendency for people to
tween real behavior and behavior derived from make their expenditures conform to the pattern
abstract preferences, New Classical economics of their income receipts (as long as their wealth
has no way to pick up those differences. In is given).
contrast, models with norms based on observa- Changes in the pattern of current income that
tion will systematically incorporate such behav- leave overall wealth constant are neutral in their
ior—although, of course, as with any method, effects on current consumption.
there is the possibility for error.
Inclusion of the “missing motivations in mac- B. The Modigliani-Miller Theorem
roeconomics” then combines the observations
of the Keynesians with the intentionality of One version of the Modigliani-Miller Theo-
economic decisions in New Classical econom- rem says that a firm’s investment strategy is
ics. Such a synthesis yields the best of the two totally independent of its liquidity position.8
approaches. Thus, for example, a corporation with an unex-
pected windfall will not spend any additional
Two Disclaimers.—Before beginning in ear- investment dollars. Instead, it will pass the
nest, let me offer two brief disclaimers. First, windfall on to shareholders or seek other finan-
none of the behavior revealing of the norms that cial investments, since it will make only those
are introduced in this lecture will be new. On investments whose risk-adjusted rate of return
the contrary, I have purposefully chosen phe- exceeds the rate of return on capital.
nomena that have been emphasized since The Changes in the firm’s finances will thus be
General Theory by macroeconomists who have neutral in their effect on current investment.
followed Keynes in voicing their continuing
doubts about classical interpretations of macro- C. Natural Rate Theory
economic behavior.
Second, this lecture will discuss different According to Natural Rate Theory, there is
norms that respectively correspond to the five some single rate of unemployment that is the
neutralities. I shall assume that these norms are only level that could be permanently maintained
exogenous. Such assumptions of exogeneity are without ever-increasing inflation or ever-
standard in economic analysis. In a given prob- increasing deflation.9 A fiscal/monetary policy
lem in a given time frame, some terms are mix that sought to maintain employment that
assumed constant, while others are allowed to was any higher would result in permanently
vary. I ask you to withhold your doubts regard- increasing inflation. A fiscal/monetary mix that
ing whether such exogeneity is a correct as-
sumption or not. The incorporation of such 7
See Friedman (1957) and Franco Modigliani and Rich-
endogeneity is the next step—not the first ard Brumberg (1954).
step—in the study of the effect of norms on 8
See Modigliani and Merton H. Miller (1958).
macroeconomics, especially since such endoge- 9
See Edmund S. Phelps (1968) and Friedman (1968).
8 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

sought to maintain employment that was any been very narrowly described. They depend
lower would result in permanently decreasing only on real outcomes. For example, in the
inflation. Fiscal/monetary mixes that yield dif- consumption-neutrality models, utility depends
ferent levels of long-term (steady) inflation will on consumption and leisure; in Modigliani-
thus be neutral in their effects on long-term Miller, it depends only on the discounted real
unemployment. return to shareholders.
But as early as the beginning of the twentieth
D. Rational Expectations century, Vilfredo Pareto pointed out that such
characterizations of utility missed important as-
According to Rational Expectations Theory, pects of motivation.13 According to Pareto, peo-
a systematic response of monetary policy to the ple typically have opinions as to how they
business cycle will have no effect on the stabil- should, or how they should not, behave. They
ity of the macroeconomy.10 Wage and price also have views regarding how others should, or
setters will foresee the systematic component of should not, behave. Such views are called
the money supply; they will raise or lower norms, and they may be individual14 as well as
prices and wages exactly proportionally, and social. The role of norms can be easily repre-
thereby neutralize its effect on demand. sented in people’s preferences by modifying the
The stability of the economy is thus neutral utility function to include losses in utility inso-
with respect to the systematic reaction of mon- far as they, or others, fail to live up to their
etary policy to the business cycle. standards.
Sociology has a further concept that gives an
E. Ricardian Equivalence easy and natural way to add those norms to the
utility function. Sociologists say that people
According to Ricardian Equivalence, under have an ideal for how they should or should not
somewhat special conditions, a representative behave. Furthermore, that ideal is often concep-
consumer who receives a lump-sum intergen- tualized in terms of the behavior of someone
erational transfer (for example, in the form of a they know, or some exemplar whom they do not
social security payment) will not spend a single know. The standard utility function is then mod-
dime extra.11 Instead, she will pass on the whole ified by adding a loss in utility, dependent on
extra income, dollar-for-dollar, to her heirs, the distance of behavior from that ideal.
who will have to pay the higher tax bills nec- Religion and religious identity give us a good
essary to retire the increased debt incurred in example of such norms. Consider the Gospels.
funding the transfer to the previous generation. They are the most sacred texts of Christianity.
The transfer is neutral in its effect on current What do they describe? The life of Christ. How
consumption. should a Christian behave? “His life and con-
versation ought to be worthy of the Gospel of
III. The Missing Motivation: Norms12 Christ [emphasis added].”15 How is a good
Christian supposed to feel when she has not
Each of the neutralities is based on the as- lived up to her conception of that ideal?
sumption that the respective decision makers Ashamed.16
are utility maximizers. But in each case the
utility functions of the decision makers have
13
See Pareto (1920). George C. Homans and Charles P.
10
See Lucas (1972), Thomas J. Sargent (1973), and Curtis (1934) give an excellent summary of Pareto that is
Lucas and Sargent (1979). fully consistent with the emphasis here. Jon Elster (1989)
11
See Robert J. Barro (1974) for the modern reincarna- also presents a similar conception of norms.
14
tion of these ideas, first discovered by Ricardo. For example, the protagonist of the novel Rice Mother
12
This section, including much of its exact wording, has (Rani Manicka 2002) did not believe she should wear red
been taken from a joint manuscript with Rachel Kranton with black.
15
(Akerlof and Kranton 2006). I should emphasize that these See http://www.orthodoxytoday.org/articles/StBasil-
insights have been developed jointly. The initial instigation Behavior.php.
16
of our project is wholly due to Kranton. It is impossible for Of course, there are many interpretations of the Gos-
me to say which ideas or wordings are mine and which are pel, and some of them are even contradictory. But that does
hers. not affect whether the person should be ashamed or not. She
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 9

A. Importance of Norms in Motivation: the money; it is also about living up to an ideal


Some Examples about who they think they should be.
Such belief regarding how people should be-
But religion is only one of the many realms have, and their behavior in accordance with
where people have such an ideal. To appreciate such belief, goes beyond the workplace. It af-
the ubiquity of norms in motivation, it is useful fects disparate areas, from playing golf to life in
to see some further examples. Those examples the family. Betty Friedan’s Feminine Mystique
will demonstrate that people tend to be happy gives what may be as good a description of
when they live up to how they think they should norms and their impact on people’s lives as can
be; and they are, correspondingly, unhappy be found anywhere—in this case regarding the
when they fail to live up to those norms. norms for middle-class women of the previous
For the audience for this lecture, most of generation. Here is a brief sample of her de-
whom are professors, teaching provides an es- scription:
pecially familiar example. We have a view of
what it means to be a good teacher. On our “Millions of women lived their lives in
lucky days, when we live up to our standards the image of those pretty pictures of the
and our classes go well, we tend to be happy; on American suburban housewife, kissing
our off days, when something goes awry in their husbands goodbye in front of the
class, we may even feel quite miserable. picture window, depositing their station-
Such motivation in the workplace is the rule, wagonsful of children at school, and smil-
rather than the exception. Most workers, like ing as they ran the new electric waxer
teachers, care about the conduct of their jobs. over the spotless kitchen floor ... . Their
only dream was to be perfect wives and
Randy Hodson (2001), who surveyed ethnogra- mothers; their highest ambition was to
phies of the US workplace, found that most have five children and a beautiful house,
employees care about their dignity at work. their only fight to get and keep their hus-
They want to conceive of what they do as use- bands ... . They gloried in their role as
ful. And they feel a lack of dignity if they are women, and wrote proudly on the census
thwarted, either by their own actions or by the blank: “Occupation, housewife” (Friedan
actions of others. Those who are unable to get 1963, 18).
such satisfaction are likely to show their dis-
pleasure by acting up in some way or other. Most women lived up to these norms. Some of
Studs Terkel’s Working (1972) captures in a these were dissenters, like Friedan herself, who
single volume much of the ethnographic find- disagreed with them, but felt compelled, never-
ings summarized by Hodson. Terkel interviews theless, to follow a norm with which they dis-
people from many different occupations about agreed. Friedan says they suffered from “the
their feelings about their jobs and concludes that problem without a name.” In our terms, they were
people “search for daily meaning as well as losing utility because they were failing to live up
daily bread” (1972, xi). Some of the interview- to what one part of them thought they should do.
ees are successful in this search: like the stone We may appeal to religious texts, to work
mason, who cruises his Indiana county and ethnographies, and, like Friedan, to women’s
basks in pride as he not infrequently passes his magazines to see the role of norms. But is there
past work. At the opposite extreme is an Illinois yet harder data, some form of natural experi-
steelworker, whose work denies him the dignity ment, that indicates the importance of norms?
he seeks. He takes out his frustration at work by The sociologist Erving Goffman has found such
being disrespectful, and, after hours, by getting an example. He observed the behavior of chil-
into tavern brawls. Most workers are some- dren of different ages when they were brought
where between these extremes, but in all cases, to the local merry-go-round. Because appropri-
following Terkel, they have a feeling for how ate activity differs by age, the children should
they should behave at work. It is not just about have predictably different reactions. For the
toddlers, riding a wooden horse is an accom-
plishment. They show their joy at fulfilling what
thinks she should be ashamed if she fails to live up to her they should do with smiles and waves as they
interpretation of the Gospel. pass by. In contrast, for older children, there is
10 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

a gap between their conception of how they that can also be interpreted in terms of such
should behave and riding the merry-go-round. norms. Becker’s theoretical innovation was to
However much they may enjoy it, they also feel modify plain-vanilla economic utility by the
the need to distance themselves from an activity introduction of a discrimination coefficient. He
that is so age inappropriate. They manifest this defined that as the loss in utility incurred by
distance by riding a frog, rather than a “serious” exchange with someone from a different race—
animal like a horse; alternatively they show off for example, the loss of a white from an ex-
by standing up “dangerously” during the ride. In change with a black. The natural interpretation
some way or other they play the clown. is that the discrimination coefficient represents
Behavior at the merry-go-round is, of course, the loss in utility for the white from physically
just the stuff of kids. But Goffman supplements engaging in an exchange with a black. But this
it with a totally serious example. In surgical representation of the utility function can also be
operations, because of their inexperience, med- interpreted in terms of norms. There is a code as
ical students are given tasks that are ridiculously to how blacks and whites should behave toward
easy.17 They respond in the same way as the each other. The white has a view that she should
older children at the merry-go-round: they also not deal with a black. She loses utility equal to
act the clown.18 the value of the discrimination coefficient—not
In economics, as elsewhere, $500 bills do not from the physical association— but ipso facto
just lie on the street. If living up to norms is from the violation of the code. There is reason
such an important motivation, it must show up to believe that such norm-based interpretation
in many economic examples, even if it is not better reflects the nature of discrimination than
identified in exactly our language. Gary S. a physical exchange– based theory. In the pre–
Becker’s Economics of Discrimination (1957) Civil Rights period, when Becker was writing,
offers an example of now-standard economics there can be no doubt that discrimination, and
the code that upheld it, was stronger in the
South than in the North. Yet exchanges between
17
Goffman (1961) observed the behavior of such stu- blacks and whites were surely much more com-
dents in medical operations.
18 mon in the South than in the North. At least one
Another example, the Milgram experiment (Stanley
Milgram 1963, 1965) demonstrates the strength of such statistic reflects such a difference: there were
motivation— by showing the lengths that people will take to significantly lower levels of residential segrega-
do what they think they should be doing. To see this tion by race in the South than in the North.19
interpretation of this experiment, which is only one of many
ways of viewing it, it is useful to give a brief description. On
arrival, subjects were told that they were involved in a B. Summary
learning experiment. They were put in the role of the
“teacher,” who should administer shocks to a “learner” Our examples are illustrative of behavior that
whenever he gave a wrong answer. The subjects are led to is pervasive. Sociology is dense in examples of
identify with their role as teacher in this experiment, and
feel that they should obey the experimenter. Rather than
people’s views as to how they and others should
being another subject, and, rather than being wired, as it behave, their joy when they live up to those
appeared, actually the learner was an unwired, trained con- standards, and their discomfort and reactions
federate of the experimenter. Subjects were then instructed when they fail to do so.
to administer shocks of escalating voltage as the learner We now turn to examining the role of
made errors. A surprising fraction of subjects escalated their
shocks to the maximum 450 volts— even though such a norms in each of the five macroeconomic neu-
dosage in real life would have been lethal. There are many tralities.20 In each case we shall ask whether
different versions of the experiment, but the version where
the confederate grunts and moans at 75 volts, asks to be let
out of the experiment at 150 volts, and refuses to give any
19
more answers at 300 volts, is typical. Here more than 60 See Douglas S. Massey and Nancy A. Denton (1993,
percent of subjects went all the way. Nor is such motivation table 3.1, 64).
20
limited to the laboratory. The rampage of the Nazi Reserve Some years ago, at a conference in Spoleto, Italy,
Police Battalion #101 in Poland during World War II Edmund Phelps gave a still-unpublished lecture wondering
(Christopher R. Browning 1999) gives a real-world mirror why the economics of the twentieth century had failed to
of the behavior Milgram obtained in the laboratory. Like discover what was central to most of the arts, which was the
Milgram’s subjects, the members of this unit, were just role of subjectivity. This paper is about the direct relevance
Ordinary Men (Browning’s title). They were recruited from of such subjectivity for macroeconomics. I have very much
the most prosaic civilian occupations. benefitted from enjoyable conversations with Professor
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 11

people’s views as to how they should behave is the utility of the child. The parent chooses her
will enter their utility function. In each case, we consumption in period 1 to maximize her utility.
shall see that such views will nullify the respec- Whatever wealth remains, she bequeaths to her
tive neutrality result. Indeed, we shall also see child.
that in each case there will be a natural norm Ricardian equivalence takes the following form
broadly consistent with Keynesians’ views of in this model. Suppose that the government
economic behavior.21 gives a transfer, which we shall call a social
security payment, to the parent in period 1; but
IV. Ricardian Equivalence then in period 2 it taxes the child to retire the
debt caused by this transfer.24 In this case, the
We shall begin our detailed discussion with consumption of a parent who maximizes the
Ricardian equivalence. It was chronologically utility function U1 and who leaves a bequest to
the last of the neutralities to be appreciated by her child will be unaffected by her receipt of
modern economists. But it is also the simplest. social security.
That makes it the best place to begin.22 If there The logic of this result is simple. With and
is missing motivation in the utility function, it without social security the discounted value of
should be easiest to see here. consumption of the parent and of the child is
A very simple model demonstrates the es- constrained by the discounted value of the fam-
sence of Ricardian equivalence, as it was redis- ily’s earnings (plus its initial wealth). Social
covered by Robert Barro after a lapse of almost security leaves that constraint unchanged. If the
two centuries.23 In the model, there are just two parent found (c1, c2) to be the optimal division
periods, periods 1 and 2. There are just two of consumption between herself and her child in
people, a parent and her child. The utility of the the absence of a social security payment, this
parent depends directly upon her own consump- same division of consumption between herself
tion, in period 1; it also depends upon the utility and her child will optimize her utility with a
of her child. That utility depends upon his con- social security payment.
sumption, in period 2. A vast literature explains why such Ricardian
The parent’s utility function can be expressed equivalence is unlikely to be empirically de-
simply as U1(c1, U2(c2)), where c1 is the con- scriptive.25 The long list of reasons includes (a)
sumption of the parent, c2 is the consumption of infinite, rather than finite, horizons; (b) strategic
the child, U1 is the utility of the parent, and U2 bequests to obtain the attention of one’s heirs
while alive; (c) childless families; (d) uncer-
tainty, including bequests made because of un-
Phelps. He has summarized for me the content of that talk certainty about the age of death; (e) differential
in an e-mail. borrowing rates between the government and
21
For each of the five neutralities we see that the inclu- the public; (f) growth of the economy in excess
sion of broader preferences, inclusive of norms, will bring
Keynesian behaviors back to life. But, of course, that does
of the interest rate, allowing steady debt issu-
not mean that the competitive forces and the maximizing ance; (g) lack of foresight regarding the effect
behaviors responsible for the five neutralities are not im- of social security on future taxes; (h) foreign
portant as well.
22
ownership of debt; (i) tax distortions;26, 27, 28 (j)
That appreciation is of course due to Barro (1974).
23
This model is quite close to Ricardo’s original discus-
sion. It is a considerable simplification of Barro’s model.
24
His model had a sequence of overlapping generations, each The tax and the transfer are both lump-sum.
25
of which lived for two periods. Barro’s contribution was not The conventional wisdom is, of course, that social
only to show Ricardian equivalence in the two-generation security will affect aggregate savings. Martin Feldstein
model, but also its extension to a sequence of generations (1974) and Feldstein and Anthony Pellechio (1979) act as if
when parents’ utility depended only on their own utility and increases in social security of the current generation will
the utility of their own children. Ricardo’s discussion, result in increased consumption, so that the next generation
which is close to the two-generation model here, was then will have a lower capital stock.
26
subsequently rediscovered. There is no uncertainty, and all I take this list mainly from the review article by John
taxes are lump-sum. This proposition may be generalized, J. Seater (1993).
27
for example, following Barro, to a model with m overlap- Barro (1989) also gives a careful review of the frictional
ping generations, each of which has different consumption reasons why Ricardian equivalence may not in fact occur.
28
when young and old. Each parent derives utility from his In the case of strategic bequests, the bequest is an
own consumption and the utility of his child. unusual form of incentive payment for a service rendered.
12 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

constraints on the consumption of parents (so they that the parent will make an equal and opposite
do not leave bequests); (k) myopia of the parents offset of her social security transfer in terms of
regarding children’s future tax payments.29 an increased bequest to her child. Something
The preceding list gives empirical reasons for must be missing from the motivation in Barro’s
failure of Ricardian equivalence; but, lengthy as model; otherwise, it would not have given rise
it is, it still ignores its theoretical challenge. to results that are so surprising.
According to that challenge, under economists’ B. Douglas Bernheim and Kyle Bagwell
standard assumptions, with perfect certainty and (1988) give further evidence suggesting that
with perfect foresight, Ricardian equivalence Ricardian equivalence is such a telltale. They
will occur. Such a result had previously been show how the same logic would apply to a
unsuspected by economists.30 network of gift-givers. Remarkably, any
Two possible conclusions can be drawn from member of such a network will be indifferent
this surprise. On the one hand, we might con- whether she receives an extra dollar or any
tinue to assume that classical assumptions de- other participant in the network is the recip-
scribe economic behavior. The five neutralities ient. Such conclusions, suspect as they are,
that are the subject of this paper concern the suggest a problem with the model beyond the
realignment to macroeconomics that occurred lack of realism involved in perfect foresight
as economists gained understanding of the con- and perfect certainty. They also suggest miss-
sequences of classical assumptions from the ing motivation.
mid-1950s to the mid-1970s. James Andreoni (1989) has put his finger on
Economists may have been correct in draw- what that missing motivation might be.31 A
ing the conclusion that the early Keynesian eco- bequest is a type of gift. The parent will receive
nomics was too simplistic and naive. But they utility from giving such a gift. Ricardian equiv-
could have drawn another conclusion from this alence will fail if the parent has utility from
surprise. In this view, Ricardian equivalence is gift-giving. With a social security transfer, more
a telltale: we do not believe, even in the pres- money is hers, and the same consumption allo-
ence of perfect foresight and perfect certainty, cation to herself entails a greater gift to her
child. With declining marginal utility for bequest-
giving, she will then divide an increased social
This argument suggests that a “bequest” is not really what it security transfer between additional consumption
seems. This is an argument where the preferences of the for herself and an additional bequest to her child.32
parent do play a role, but quite different from the type of Andreoni thus describes the utility missing
reason that I think would have surprised the Keynesians. I
want to show that parents who make bequests for the from the standard utility function as that arising
conventional reasons, because they care about the welfare of from the “warm glow” from giving. Such a
their children, will still routinely violate Ricardian equiva- characterization may be accurate. It also sounds
lence, even in the absence of most of the commonplace as if it is very close to classical assumptions—
frictions that almost surely invalidate exact Ricardian equiv- that there is nothing fundamentally different
alence.
29
This was Ricardo’s own reason for dismissal of the about this additional motivation. But this seg-
argument. He said that the parent would alter her bequest ment of the utility function is, in fact, very
because she would not take into account the added tax different from economists’ usual characteriza-
payments of the child (see Gerald P. O’Driscoll Jr. 1977). tion of motivation. We know that the “warm
Uncertainty regarding the size of the future tax payments is
different from such myopia, in which the payment is alto- glow” does not come from the utility the parent
gether ignored. But, with quadratic utility and expected
utility maximization, uncertainty regarding the child’s fu-
ture tax payments will have no effect on the size of the
31
parent’s bequest. See also John Laitner (2002), Laitner and Henry Ohls-
30
For example, Feldstein (1974) and Feldstein and Pel- son (2001), Alan S. Blinder (1975) and Michael D. Hurd
lechio (1979) engage in no theoretical soul-searching re- (1989), who have also modeled the bequest motive as com-
garding the negative effects of social security on current ing from the utility of the parent from giving the bequest.
32
savings. There is a voluminous literature (see Roberto Ric- Formally, she trades off the marginal utility of her
ciuti 2003) examining the empirical validity of Ricardian own consumption against the marginal utility from gift-
equivalence. Largely because of the problem of endogene- giving and the marginal utility she gets from her child’s
ity, it is difficult to come to firm conclusions regarding its consumption. In making this trade-off, she takes due ac-
empirical validity. There are studies with findings both for count of the fact that one unit of consumption today is
and against such crowding out. traded off against (1 ⫹ r) units of consumption next period.
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 13

derives from her own consumption; nor, yet what housewives should do, parents who leave
more tellingly, does it derive from the utility of bequests derive a warm glow from bequests
her child (as the child’s utility depends on its because that is what they think they should do
own consumption). It enters the utility function for their children. Ricardian equivalence then
as a separate term. illustrates how odd neutralities can occur in
What, then, could account for a “warm glow”? models that fail to take such norms into account.
Parent-to-child bequests are a form of gift. If there A comment by David Romer (2001, 539)
is any type of economic transaction that is gov- tells us where we should venture next. He has
erned by norms, it is the giving of gifts.33 Parent- remarked that “quantitatively important” viola-
to-child bequests also occur within families. tions of Ricardian equivalence and of the per-
Therefore, they should also be affected by the manent income/life-cycle hypothesis occur for
norms of family life. We have already seen one the same reasons. Ricardian equivalence is not
example of such norms (Friedan’s portrait of the important for us as an empirical aspect of mac-
proper place of women in the early 1960s). roeconomics. There are so many reasons other
The norms of family life are not constant. They than the role of norms for its violation. But it
vary by culture. They also change over time. As does give us an initial window on the type of
the nature of the ideal family has shifted, so has motivation missing in classical macroeconom-
the ideal bequest. Actual bequests have changed in ics. Inclusion of such motivation will give us a
tandem. For example, the ideal sixteenth century new perspective on the consumption function. It
Anglo-Saxon family was dynastic. The lineage allows us to return to a view in which consump-
passed from father to oldest son.34 Fathers then tion will depend on current income, just as its
left the bulk of their estates to their oldest sons. In inclusion makes it natural to believe that social
the twenty-first century, in the ideal family, sib- security transfers will affect savings and con-
lings are equal. Most bequests are now evenly sumption, even in a world without frictions.
divided between them.35
V. Consumption and Current Income
Summary.—Economic outcomes, such as the
consumption of the parent and the utility of the This takes us to the second neutrality. Ac-
child, are one determinant of bequests. But an- cording to this result, other than its contribution
other possible determinant is parents’ views re- to a consumer’s wealth, current income has no
garding how they should behave toward their independent effect on the consumption of a
children. Just as Friedan’s suburban housewives utility-maximizing consumer.
waxed their floors, because they thought that is Milton Friedman (1957) derived such
consumption-income neutrality in the two-
period model of Irving Fisher. In this model, the
33
consumer chooses her consumption between
The literature on gift-giving is of course replete with two periods. She maximizes her intertemporal
the notion that gift-giving will be determined by what assets
people consider to be theirs and how much of those assets utility function, given by the function U(c1, c2):
should be given to others (Ruth Benedict 1946), rather than c1 denotes her current consumption in the first
by the final utility outcomes for the gift-giver and for the period; c2 denotes consumption in the second
gift-receiver. Theodore Caplow (1984) describes the im- period.36 If she maximizes U(c1, c2), a dollar of
plicit rules for Christmas gift-giving in “Middletown.” Peo-
ple believe that the gifts they should give, and receive, should income earned today will have the same effect
be given according to these rules. Caplow suggests that one on her current consumption as a discounted
might consider these “rules” as norms for gift-giving. dollar earned in the next period. Thus, her con-
34
For the history of the Anglo-Saxon family and the sumption will depend only on the discounted
change of its conception from dynastic to nuclear, see
Lawrence Stone (1977).
value of her current and future income and the
35
Using tax data, Mark D. Wilhelm (1996) found that only rate of interest. This proposition is easy to
10 percent of estates differed by more than 5 percent from prove. It generalizes to many different com-
equality between bequests to siblings. His data are only for modities and to many different time periods,
bequests from estates larger than the federal minimum for
taxation. For a more general population, Jere R. Behrman and
Mark R. Rosenzweig (2004) have examined the difference in
36
bequests to twins. Once measurement error is taken into ac- She receives income of Y1 in period 1, income Y2 in
count, they find no significant differences in the bequests. period 2, and she can borrow and lend at the rate of interest r.
14 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

and, with quadratic utility, to uncertain in- his followers, believed that current income
comes.37 In standard terminology, the value of played an especially important role in the de-
her discounted income is called her wealth; the termination of current consumption.
amount of that wealth that can be spent without
its depletion is called permanent income.38 An “The fundamental psychological law [em-
alternative expression of Friedman’s hypothesis phasis added], upon which we are entitled
is that consumption depends on permanent to depend with great confidence both a
rather than on current income.39 priori from our knowledge of human na-
The permanent income hypothesis may be in ture and from the detailed facts of expe-
accordance with most standard economic mod- rience, is that men are disposed, as a rule
els. Nevertheless, it contradicted prior thinking and on the average, to increase their con-
about the consumption function. Keynes, and sumption as income increases, but not by
as much as the increase in income” (Key-
nes, The General Theory, 1936, 96).
37
The simple proof is that her utility-maximizing con-
sumption will depend upon the intercept and the slope of the It is true that The General Theory discussed a
budget line. The budget line states that the present dis- long list of other factors that could affect con-
counted value of consumption is the present discounted sumption. The list was sufficiently rich to in-
value of her future income, which is what Friedman calls
her wealth. The intercept of the budget line is her wealth.
clude not only current income, but also all the
That is how much she could consume today if she consumed other determinants of wealth, such as expected
nothing tomorrow. And the slope of the budget line is future income and the rate of interest. But that
determined by the rate of interest r: on the budget line for does not make Keynes’s theory identical to
every unit of c1 she gives up (1 ⫹ r) units of c2. Her Friedman’s. In the Keynesian theory, consum-
consumption will be on the highest attainable utility indif-
ference curve. That will be the indifference curve that is just ers are more sensitive to current income than to
tangent to the budget line. As a result, we see that, given the other changes in income that have similar effect
utility function, c1 will be a function of W and r. Note that on the consumer’s wealth.
current income does not come into this expression.
38
Formally, permanent income is the product of the rate A. Empirical Results and Their Explanation
of interest and wealth.
39
The permanent income hypothesis also generalizes to
currently popular models of present bias. In these models A large number of tests have demonstrated the
consumers have present bias in the form of “hyperbolic dis- excess sensitivity of consumption to current in-
counting,” which means that they put extra weight in their come, in concert with the Keynesian consumption
utility functions on their current consumption. In this case, the
typical consumer’s plans will not be consistent, but they can be function. For example, John Y. Campbell and
analyzed as if she has multiple selves. Her self today decides N. Gregory Mankiw (1989) nested both Fried-
on how much to consume today and then passes on the re- man’s view that consumption depends solely on
maining assets to her self tomorrow. There is an exact analogy wealth and the simplified Keynesian view that
to the parent’s maximization in Barro’s model of bequests. In
that model, today’s consumer passes on assets to her child in
consumption depends solely on income. They
the next generation; in consumer theory, today’s consumer suppose that a fraction of consumers ␭ are pure
passes on assets to her new self in the next period. Since the Keynesians, while a fraction (1 ⫺ ␭) behave ac-
standard model of intertemporal consumption and Barro’s cording to the permanent income hypothesis; they
model of consumption are exactly isomorphic, Ricardian estimate ␭ from the extent to which consumption
equivalence then tells us that current consumption—which is
the consumption of the initial self— depends only on the con- overreacts to changes in income that would be
sumer’s wealth. David I. Laibson (1997) thus shows that predictable from past changes in income and con-
consumption with forward-looking consumers with hyperbolic sumption. Usefully, then, ␭ gives a natural mea-
discounting will balance the marginal utility of present con- sure of the departure from the permanent income
sumption out of wealth against the marginal utility of future
consumption according to an Euler condition. Such a condition
hypothesis. The estimates of ␭ are significant sta-
is wealth-based. It is the generalization of the tangency of the tistically and also of significant magnitude eco-
utility indifference curve to the budget line in the two-period nomically: between 40 and 50 percent (depending
model of Irving Fisher. Both Friedman and Laibson obtain upon whether three or five periods are used to
consumption that is determined solely by current income if predict the change in current income).
there is a constraint on current borrowing, and consumers’
desires for current consumption exceed their current income. Other studies corroborate such excess depen-
There is nothing inherent in the preferences in either case that dence on current income: John Shea (1985), for
causes current consumption to be based on current income. union members whose contracts specified their
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 15

future wages; David W. Wilcox (1989), for social think they should consume. Second, what peo-
security recipients who had been earlier notified of ple think they should consume can often be
changes in cost-of-living adjustments; Jonathan viewed either as entitlements or as obligations.
Parker (1999), for payers of social security taxes Finally, in turn, current income is one of the
with predictable inter-year changes; Nicholes S. major determinants of these entitlements, and
Souleles (1999), for changes in disposable income obligations.
net of tax refunds; and James Banks, Richard
Blundell, and Sarah Tanner (1998), and Bern- Sociology of Consumption.—The motivation
heim, Jonathan Skinner, and Steven Weinberg emphasized by sociologists for consumption is
(2001), for retirees. very different from that in the life-cycle model.
Textbooks explain such excess sensitivity by Sociologists describe consumption as largely
a variety of frictions, particularly borrowing determined by the norms regarding what people
constraints. For example, Rudiger Dornbusch should consume. These norms, in turn, are de-
and Stanley Fischer (1987) say: “Given that the pendent upon the individual’s situation and also
permanent income hypothesis is correct [sic], who she thinks she is.
there are two possible explanations.”40 They are Two examples illustrate such dependence on
liquidity constraints for consumers and myopia norms. Following Pierre Bourdieu (1984), peo-
in their projections of future income. ple’s consumption of cultural goods—the liter-
Thus, we see the realignment that occurred ature they read, the music they hear, and the art
because of the life-cycle permanent income hy- they buy—reflects not just their individual
pothesis: excess sensitivity may occur, but only tastes. The upper class should not make lower-
in the presence of credit constraints or myopia. class choices. Correspondingly, the lower class
Such a view cannot have been adopted because should avoid appearing above their station.42
of its empirical support. Few studies have tested The epithet “lace curtain Irish” illustrates. To
this proposition, but those that do have rejected the users of this phrase, those lace curtains were
it. For example, credit constraints cannot ex- indicative of those violating their social place.
plain the reduction in consumption of retirees. Weber’s analysis of the relation between re-
And, neither myopia nor credit constraint can ligion and savings further reflects the role of
explain the reduction in union members’ con- people’s views regarding who they should be.
sumption at the time of wage declines scheduled In The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capi-
in their union contracts (Shea 1995, 996). talism, 43 Weber describes Calvinists as aspiring
The adoption of the permanent income/ to be “worldly ascetics.” He concludes that
life-cycle hypothesis then must rest on theoret- “economic acquisition is no longer subordi-
ical, not empirical, reasons. But the theory fails nated to man as the means for satisfaction of his
to take into account norms regarding what peo- material needs.”44 Here the purpose of saving is
ple think they should, or should not, consume. to live up to an ideal. The Calvinists are thrifty
Such a norm-based theory will nest Keynes’s because they think they should not be consum-
psychological law. Consumption-income neu- ing. That turns the motivation of the life-cycle
trality will occur only in a singular special case.

B. Consumption and the Role of Norms41


42
Bourdieu views this as important because of the role
Why should consumption be overly sensitive of such differential consumption in the transmission of class
to income? This section presents an argument in structure from one generation to the next. The focus on
three steps. First, sociology gives motivations consumption as a reflection of who people want to be can be
seen throughout the sociology of consumption. On the low-
for consumption that are very different from the brow-highbrow scale, a study by Ian Woodward (2003) is at
reasons for it in the life-cycle model. A major the opposite end of the spectrum from Bourdieu: Woodward
determinant of consumption is what people asked Australian housewives about the reasons for their
choice of furniture. Some went for comfort; others, for
aesthetics. But they also indicated, with a surprising degree
of moral fervor, that their choices reflected who they wanted
40
See Dornbusch and Fischer (1987, 284). to be.
41 43
I am extremely grateful to Robert Akerlof for help in See Weber (1958).
44
formulating the argument of this section. Weber (1958, 53).
16 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

model on its head. There people save only because of respondents to a questionnaire said they would
of their desire for consumption in retirement. buy a $10 theater ticket if they arrived at a theater
Luigi Guiso, Paola Sapienza, and Luigi Zin- to see a play and found that they had lost a $10
gales (2003, 2006) have statistically affirmed bill. In contrast, only 46 percent said they would
Weber’s hypothesis that religion is correlated buy a new $10 ticket in the same situation if
both with attitudes toward savings and with they had lost a previously purchased ticket.
actual savings. In addition, they have more gen- Tversky and Kahneman explain this differ-
erally affirmed the quantitative significance of ence by “mental accounts,” but an explanation
culture for savings and consumption; in their in terms of entitlements is equally valid. Tver-
regressions, variables reflecting culture have as sky and Kahneman say that those who have lost
much power as variables derived from the life- the $10 bill do not connect that loss to the play.
cycle hypothesis in explaining cross-country In their mental account, its cost is just $10. But
savings ratios.45 those who have lost the ticket see themselves as
paying for it twice. In their mental account, its
Consumption Entitlements and Obligations.— cost is $20. Those with the lost ticket then tend
While sociology is useful in giving us the gen- to opt out, because they see $20 as too much to
eral insight that consumption depends on cul- pay to see the play. But the difference in behav-
tural norms, we need to be more specific. What ior for those who lost the ticket and those who
is the nature of those norms? They can fre- lost the $10 bill could also have been interpreted
quently be described in two ways: as entitle- in terms of entitlements. Most people want to
ments and, also sometimes, as obligations to think of themselves as responsible human be-
spend. Again some examples will illustrate. ings. When they lose the ticket, they do not feel
First, oddly, people have obligations to entitled to just buy another one. That is not the
spend. Social history is full of the obligation to type of person they aspire to be.
keep up appearances. Most Wall Street bankers, We should also observe that it is not coinci-
for example, do not live like mothers on wel- dental that the lost ticket paradox could be ex-
fare. They do not want to. But, even if they did, plained both by mental accounting and by
it would occasion gossip. It is not what they norms. Formally, any model of mental account-
should do. History is replete with stories of the ing can be translated into a model of norms: just
debt of aristocrats struggling to maintain their replace the rules of mental accounting as the
social obligations.46 As just one example, the norms that people think they should follow.48
debts to British merchants by Southern planters, But even though norms and mental accounting
who were keeping up with the Joneses of the may be equivalent, interpretations in terms of
eighteenth century, are considered a significant norms are important for this lecture. Mental ac-
factor underlying the Southern support of the counting has the connotation, whether rightly or
American Revolution.47 wrongly, of being a heuristic for quick decisions.
In addition to obligations to spend, there are Such a heuristic will, of course, sometimes result
also entitlements. The lost-ticket paradox of in cognitive error. Whether rightly or wrongly,
Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman (1981, most economists would dismiss cognitive error as
457) gives an illustration. Eighty-eight percent unimportant. Why? because in their view people
are smart about what they want, and their deci-
sions are also very purposeful. But norms cannot
45
Guiso, Sapienza, and Zingales (2006, 39) report re- be dismissed so easily. As I argued earlier, people
gressions of savings ratios on GDP growth, dependency feel strongly about adherence to them. Their
ratios, and responses to the question: “Do you consider it
especially important to encourage children to learn thrift
and savings?” A one-standard-deviation difference to GDP
48
growth and to attitude toward thrift both produce a 1.8- But it turns out that there is quite possibly a substan-
percentage-point difference in the savings ratio. (A one- tive difference between the two interpretations. With the
standard-deviation difference in the dependency ratio, mental accounting interpretation the losers of the ticket
which could be the result both of cultural differences and of could be induced to buy one, if only a wise friend would
life-cycle considerations, produces a 3.2-percentage-point make them aware of the logical problems of their reasoning.
difference.) In contrast with the norms interpretation the friend cannot
46
See, for example, David Cannadine (1977). be so helpful. Buying a new ticket is a departure from the
47
See Woody Holton (1999). person’s norm, and she loses utility by it.
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 17

absence from utility constitutes the missing a task. Those who were asked for the dona-
motivation of macroeconomics. tion afterward were more likely to keep the
money than those who were asked before-
The Link of Entitlements and Obligations to hand. Those who had completed the task felt
Current Income.—It remains to relate current that they had earned the money and were thus
spending to current income. Norms may be entitled to keep it for themselves.49
complex. But a web of evidence still reveals a ● The mental accounting model by Hersh M.
strong association between current income and Shefrin and Richard H. Thaler (1988) is espe-
entitlements and obligations to spend. Such a cially useful in our quest for a Keynesian con-
link, in turn, produces the excess sensitivity of sumption function. Norms take many forms, so
consumption on current income in Keynes’s their formal model is not unique.50 But it does
Psychological Law. illustrate a possible link between consumption
A few examples follow. and current income. In this model, people have
three separate mental accounts: current income,
● It is common practice in the United States for current assets, and future income combined
parents, even for rich ones with no budget with pension wealth. As consumers exhaust one
constraint, to expect their children to assume of these accounts and begin to use the next one
financial independence after their graduation for their current consumption, they incur a dis-
from college. They are indicating their belief continuous “penalty.” Those penalties are psy-
in the norm that the child is entitled to spend chological in nature—this is a model of mental
what she earns. (Most parents, of course, give accounting—and they take the form of a loss in
their children a helping hand as they seek utility.51 Corresponding to Shefrin and Thaler’s
their independence. But that does not mean assumptions regarding the nature of these costs,
that they do not also strongly believe that their as consumption rises, consumers will first fi-
children should live on their earnings, since that nance it wholly from current income; then,
norm is only one of their motivations.) from current assets; and, finally, from future
● In a thought experiment, consider a woman income and retirement wealth.
living on $50,000 a year who learns that As we discussed earlier, it should be no sur-
her uncle will die in one year leaving her prise that there is an exact translation of such a
$2,000,000. Even if she has considerable sav- model into one with norms regarding entitle-
ings in the bank, it would be unseemly for her ments to consume. The rules of mental account-
to run down her savings in anticipation of the ing become the norms regarding how money
bequest. She is not entitled to do so. She should be spent. The basic norm is that con-
should stick to spending from her current sumption should come from current income.
income. This gives another example in which
norms regarding entitlements to spend are 49
related to current income, in violation of the These are the results for females. The men gave al-
most nothing so their differentials are irrelevant. The
life-cycle hypothesis. women gave on average about 10 percent of their earnings.
● People’s expenditures are supposed to reflect Those who were asked to donate before the task gave twice
their stations in life, and those stations usu- as much as those who were asked afterward. The task lasted
ally reflect their earnings. Thus, for example, 40 minutes and was to highlight phrases in a manuscript to
be used in making an index.
college students with little earnings are sup- 50
Shefrin and Thaler themselves are explicit about the
posed to live that way—like college students. possibility of other models.
Their current spending is supposed to reflect 51
We should also note that the Shefrin-Thaler model
their current earnings, not what they will be has elements not discussed in the text. In general, the
discontinuous penalties from mental accounting are one
earning in the future. (At the other extreme, reason why consumption might be at a corner solution in
as an obligation, the college president is often one of the three mental accounts. Shefrin and Thaler have
expected to live in the presidential mansion.) another reason. They view saving as taking willpower,
● Preliminary results from an experiment by which entails a cost in terms of lost utility. The less
John Morgan and myself illustrate another people save the less of this costly willpower they need to
expend. This gives another reason why consumption
relation between entitlement and earnings. In might be on one of the boundaries of the mental accounts.
this experiment, subjects were asked to do- It is useful to remember that at one of the boundaries,
nate to a charity before and after completing consumption will conform to current income.
18 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

And the discontinuous penalties correspond to again we see that the current versions of the
the losses of utility due to respective deviations life-cycle hypothesis have left out missing mo-
from that norm. In particular, Shefrin and Tha- tivation that easily justifies the excess sensitiv-
ler assumed that there is no such cost at all if ity of consumption to income in Keynes’s
consumption comes only from current income. psychological law.
That means that current income can be consid-
ered as consumers’ entitlement to spend, since VI. Investment and Cash Flow
any consumption that is less than current in-
come entails no deviation at all from the norm The debate concerning investment has been
regarding the account that should finance it. surprisingly close to the debate about consump-
● Shefrin and Thaler give an impressive array tion. The early Keynesians emphasized two
of econometric facts in support of their variables as determinants of investment: current
model. Insofar as these facts support their cash flow (with profits as a major component),
mental accounting model, they also equally and the firm’s current holdings of liquid assets.
well support its reinterpretation—with the Each of these variables is a measure of funds
norm that current income is an entitlement to available to firms for investment without seek-
spend. Those facts include: differential sav- ing outside finance.56 In contrast, the later liter-
ings out of windfall and current income;52 a ature denied any special role of liquidity in the
less than one-to-one displacement of discre- investment function.
tionary saving by employee pension contri- The first such questioning came from
butions;53 undersaving for retirement;54 and a Modigliani and Miller, who assumed that man-
marginal propensity to consume out of fully agers maximize shareholder value and that mar-
anticipated bonuses that is much greater than kets are frictionless and competitive. In this
the marginal propensity to consume out of case, a firm’s financial position plays no role in
monthly income.55 the value of the firm. The argument for this
● Retired people are commonly believed to independence proceeds as follows. By construc-
tailor their consumption to a concept of tion, Modigliani and Miller show how a com-
income rather than to the value of their petitive equilibrium changes if a firm increases
assets. Shefrin and Statman (1984) have its debt and buys back shares. In the new equi-
viewed this as another form of mental ac- librium, investment will be unchanged, and
counting. They also present considerable shareholders will offset the increase in the
evidence regarding such behavior. firm’s debt by a compensating increase in the
bonds in their respective private portfolios. The
C. Summary reason the equilibrium changes in this way is
straightforward: if the markets for debt cleared
Considerable evidence suggests that people’s in the old equilibrium, they will again clear in
views regarding what they are entitled to spend the new. If managers’ choice of investment
play a major role in their consumption choices. maximized shareholder value in the old equilib-
It also suggests strongly that current income rium, the same choice of investment maximizes
plays a special role in those entitlements. She- it in the new. Investment is therefore indepen-
frin and Thaler have explained such patterns by dent of the firm’s current financial position,
mental accounting. A reinterpretation of their including its current liquidity position and its
model shows that they also could have ex- current cash flow.
plained this behavior in terms of norms. Once The advent of q-theory similarly questioned a
special place for current variables, such as cash
flow and liquid asset holdings in the investment
52
Shefrin and Thaler (1988, 619 –20). decision. In the original version of the theory,
53
Shefrin and Thaler (1988, 622–24). James Tobin (1969) suggested that a firm’s op-
54
Shefrin and Thaler (1988, 626 –27). Especially, they timal investment strategy arbitrages between
say that there would be vast undersaving in the absence of
social security and forced private pensions to prevent it.
There is some ambiguity regarding whether there is under-
56
saving in the presence of these institutions to counteract it. See, especially, John R. Meyer and Edwin Kuh
55
Shefrin and Thaler (1988, 633). (1957).
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 19

the value at which it can sell a unit of its capital tive to available liquidity.59 But, as with credit-
and its investment costs to produce a new unit constraint explanations of consumption, empirical
of capital. In this case, firms should invest up to evidence, such as there is, rejects this hypothesis.
the point where the marginal cost of a new unit Steven N. Kaplan and Zingales (1997) analyzed
of capital is the valuation of such a unit of the subsample of firms that Fazzari, Hubbard,
capital in the stock market. That valuation is the and Petersen had considered most likely to be
market value of the firm’s shares divided by its credit constrained. They find credit constraint to
capital stock, called the q-ratio. If markets are be rare. Furthermore, they also found that those
efficient, q is also the expected discounted value firms with the least constraint had the greatest
of current and expected future profits per unit of sensitivity to cash flows.60
capital.57 Since q-theory says that firms should There is, thus, remarkable similarity between
invest in capital up to the point where the cost of the consumption function and the investment
an extra unit of capital stock is equal to the function. In both cases, economic theory sug-
present discounted value of the stream of earnings gested rejection of earlier views regarding the
from a unit of capital, again, as in Modigliani- role of current flow variables— current income
Miller, investment is independent of the firm’s in the case of consumption, cash flow in the
finance decision.58 case of investment. In both cases, empirical
The empirical testing of q-theory also has a investigation showed the existence of excess
striking parallel to the empirical testing of the sensitivity to the current flow variable. In both
consumption function. Just as Campbell and cases, these rejections support the previous
Mankiw showed that there was excess sensitiv- Keynesian theory. In both cases, economists
ity to current income in the consumption func- have sought to explain the divergence between
tion, Steven M. Fazzari, R. Glenn Hubbard, and practice and theory by the presence of credit
Bruce C. Petersen (1988) showed that invest- constraints. In both cases, the empirical evi-
ment depends not just upon q, but also upon the dence, such as it is, does not support the case
current cash flows. Furthermore, as in the stan- that credit-constraint explanations explain the
dard explanation of excess consumption sensi- theoretical anomaly.
tivity, Fazzari, Hubbard, and Petersen similarly
suggest that credit constraints are responsible A. Theory of Excess Sensitivity of Investment
for the dependence of investment on cash flow. to Cash Flow
They continue with the Modigliani-Miller/
q-theory assumption that managers maximize Whatever the similarities, consumption and
stockholder value. But they posit that the dif- investment differ in one major respect. In the
ference in information between managers and case of investment, economists are already
financiers results in a wedge between the cost of aware of a fundamental reason why investment
internal and external financing. This is clearest will depend on current cash flow. Modigliani-
for firms that are credit constrained—so that Miller and q-theory both assume that managers
credit-constrained firms will be especially sensi-
59
See, for example, Fazzari, Hubbard, and Petersen
(1988). Stewart C. Myers and Nicholas S. Majluf (1984)
also argued that cash flow would affect investment when
57
See Andrew B. Abel (1979), Lawrence H. Summers managers had information not available to investors.
60
(1981), and Fumio Hayashi (1982). An examination of the investment spending of firms
58
This should not be a surprise, because the assumptions with cash windfalls from winning or settling lawsuits sup-
of this version of q-theory are in accord with Modigliani- ports this finding (Olivier J. Blanchard and Florencio
Miller: competitive financial markets and investment that Lopez-de-Silanes 1993). These firms had no problems re-
maximizes shareholder value. Thus, the firm’s current fi- garding credit constraints; yet they invested in projects they
nancial position should play no role in investment. In q- would not have otherwise pursued. Another striking finding
theory, current profits are just one component of the stream also shows excess sensitivity of investment to cash flow. In
of current and future profits that determine the value of q. In 1986, when the price of oil declined dramatically, non-oil
this sense, they play no special role in the determination of subsidiaries of oil companies cut their investment relative to
investment. This de-emphasis of current cash flow (and thus the median in their industry (Owen Lamont 1997). But
current profits) in investment is analogous to the denial of because this study examines the investment implications of
any special role of current income in the permanent income a fall, rather than of a rise, in the price of oil, it is not useful
hypothesis. in resolving the role of credit constraint.
20 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

maximize shareholder value. In the now-standard many instances of lax corporate oversight in favor
theory of the firm, the interests of the shareholders of management interests. For example, he has
and the interests of the managers are viewed as cited the excess exploration and drilling opera-
different. The managers are only the agents of the tions of oil companies when retained earnings
owners, and accordingly they maximize their own were high, from 1975 to 1981,62 and the mainte-
interests instead. Such incentives are said to turn nance of low-return operations in many US indus-
the managers into “empire-builders,”61 who will tries, as in the investments of General Motors
use the resources they control to increase their throughout the 1980s.63 In Jensen’s views, share-
own domains. holders would have fared better if profits had been
Empire-building can result from two types of returned to them, giving them the option of invest-
motivations. On the one hand, managers may ing at a higher rate of return, or perhaps if profits
have only strict economic interests in mind: had been used for takeovers outside the industry.
they care only about their take-home pay, and To cure what he calls the “failure of corporate
their effort on the job. Such managers, for ex- internal control,” Jensen has also suggested that
ample, will be biased in favor of investments firms should issue large amounts of debt, perhaps
whose operation or construction enhances their even by going private. In that case, the added debt
firm-specific human capital, and thereby in- obligations act as a brake on excess investment.
creases their bargaining power. Regarding investment behavior, Jensen is then on
On the other hand, empire-building may be the same page as Keynesian economists such as
pursued as a goal of its own, for its own sake. Klein and Goldberger. They refer to “the prefer-
We saw earlier that most workers have views ence of many businessmen for internal as opposed
regarding how they should or should not per- to external financing” (1955, 12–13) and also con-
form their jobs. Accompanying such views, sider it the major reason for the dependence of
most managers and workers will have the fur- investment on cash flow.
ther view that the firm should be investing in
those jobs. For this reason, the agents making B. Sociology of the Corporation
the investment decision are likely to engage in
empire-building. We can represent such moti- Once again, we have seen a neutrality result
vation by adding a term to the utility function of that depends on the goals of the respective de-
the agent– decision maker. Her utility function cision makers. Accordingly, the norms of cor-
will not only depend on her own pecuniary porate decision makers are central to the
returns and her expenditure of effort. It will also sociology of the corporation. For example, Dirk
include an additional term reflective of her M. Zorn (2004) has examined how the locus of
norms. She will lose utility insofar as the firm’s control has changed in large US firms over the
investment fails to live up to her ideal of what past 40 years. He has shown how this control
she thinks it should be. In this case, the typical has shifted away from those with a production
norm is that she thinks that the firm should or a sales orientation to those with a financial
engage in investment that will enhance her job orientation.64 Empirically, this is seen in the rise
performance. of the chief financial officer. Prior to the 1960s,
Following the logic of Michael Jensen (1986, corporate finances were handled by corporate
1993), empire-building, accompanied by the treasurers, whose duties were mainly restricted
abdication of corporate oversight in favor of to keeping the accounts and producing the bud-
management interests, explains a correlation be- gets. Now, most large corporations have re-
tween investment and cash flow. Furthermore, placed them by a CFO. With the change in title
this correlation will occur regardless of the moti- has come a change in function. CFOs are typi-
vation for the empire-building, whether for purely cally central to major decisions. Such a change
economic reasons as in the principal-agent model, affects investment decisions. If they are com-
or, instead, because of managers’ norms for how mitted to their missions, managers with sales or
they think they should behave. Jensen has given
62
Jensen (1986, 327).
63
See Jensen (1993, 853).
61 64
Empire-building is especially emphasized by Jeremy That distinction was emphasized earlier, for example,
C. Stein (2003), following Jensen (1986, 1993). by Neil Fligstein (1990).
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 21

production orientations will be empire-builders. call its real price—in excess of unity. A standard
In contrast, the role of the conscientious CFO is natural rate model illustrates why this occurs. That
to curb those enthusiasms. Fifty years have model assumes that in each period the typical firm
elapsed since the publication of Modigliani- sets a desired real price for the following period;
Miller. According to Zorn, when it first ap- in each period it also makes a bargain with its
peared, it did not describe the investment labor regarding next period’s real wages. Next
decision of large corporations. Now, quite pos- period’s nominal price and nominal wage are then
sibly, changes in corporate decision-making respectively set by adjusting this desired real price
since that time make it more realistic.65 and this bargained real wage according to infla-
tionary expectations. When demand is higher, the
C. Summary desired real price of the representative firm is
higher for two reasons: on the demand side, be-
The investment decision demonstrates once cause the demand for its product is higher, and, on
again that the respective neutrality result depends the cost side, because the bargained real wage is
on the objective function of the decision makers. higher. That bargained real wage is higher both
because the typical employee’s opportunity costs,
VII. Natural Rate Theory which take into account her chances of being
unemployed, are higher, and because the firm’s
We now turn to natural rate theory. Once desire for her labor is higher. Since the firm’s
again, the debate concerns the behavior of eco- owners, customers, and workers care only about
nomic decision makers. The early Keynesians real prices or real wages, a given level of real
viewed wage setters, and possibly also price aggregate demand will be associated with a given
setters, as setting nominal wages and prices, real wage bargain between the firm and its work-
respectively, without taking full account of in- ers, and a given desired real price for the firm’s
flationary expectations. In contrast, New Clas- product. If unemployment is sufficiently low—
sical revisionists have assumed that wage and below the natural rate—that desired real price will
price setters care only about relative wages or be in excess of unity. If unemployment is above
prices, and therefore wage and price setting will the natural rate, it will be less than unity.
fully incorporate inflationary expectations. Such It is now easy to explain the inflationary and
behavior yields a long-run neutrality result with deflationary spirals in natural rate theory. Con-
severe limits on the ability of monetary and sider what happens when the representative firm
fiscal policy to affect unemployment and out- wishes to set its price above that of other firms.
put. When wage and price setters care only In this case, actual inflation will exceed ex-
about relative wages and relative prices, accel- pected inflation. With such a positive gap be-
erating inflation will occur if unemployment is tween actual and expected inflation, inflationary
below a critical level, called the natural rate; expectations will rise, as inflationary expecta-
accelerating deflation will occur if unemploy- tions are adjusted upward to conform to reality.
ment is above it. But the firm’s desired real price, and therefore
As we shall see, such spirals occur because, the difference between actual and expected in-
at high levels of demand, the representative firm flation, will be unchanged as long as unemploy-
will wish to set the price of its product relative ment is constant. There will be no abatement in
to the price of other firms’ products—which we the rise in expected inflation. Inflationary ex-
pectations will be forever increasing, and infla-
tion will rise with it, as nominal prices and
65
Curiously, the rise of the CFO may have substituted wages adjust the real wage bargains and the
one overenthusiasm (from the point of view of shareholders)
for another. There is considerable division regarding whether
desired real prices for these increasing inflation-
mergers and acquisitions have positive returns to the buyer. ary expectations. By similar logic, if unemploy-
Robert Bruner’s meta-analysis (2002) of many different stud- ment is above the natural rate, there will be a
ies concludes that, on balance, the returns to bidders have been deflationary spiral. The natural rate is the only
zero. This is a poor return for an activity that has involved so sustainable level of unemployment without ac-
much corporate time and initiative. Furthermore, if some op-
portunities can be identified as having positive returns, then, to celerating or decelerating inflation. It corre-
reach an average return of zero, the marginal merger and sponds to the exact level of demand where firms
acquisition has negative payoff. wish to set a real price of exactly one.
22 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

A. Acceptance of Natural Rate Theory dard errors of such estimates are quite large; thus,
they also fail to reject sums whose departure from
Most macroeconomists do not just view nat- one is of sufficient size to result in departures of
ural rate theory as a useful null hypothesis. economically significant magnitude from natural
They also see it as a description of reality. Such rate theory. But the standard treatment of the Phil-
a view is revealed in textbook presentations. lips curve ignores this inconvenient fact.
Economists accept natural theory for theoretical The textbooks thus typically present natural
and empirical reasons. rate theory as a “just-so” story. It runs as fol-
Theoretically, they view the assumptions of lows. The previous Keynesian economists had
natural rate theory as realistic. A standard cri- posited a Phillips curve without a dependence
terion for an economic model is that participants on inflationary expectations. Friedman (1968)
in the economy care only about real outcomes. and Phelps (1968) perceived that such a theory
That is the fundamental assumption of natural could not result from models where the partic-
rate theory. Also, unlike our other neutrality ipants in the economy are concerned only with
results, natural rate theory is insensitive to de- real variables. They modified the relationship so
viations due to “frictions,” such as imperfect that wage and price equations would be affected
information, taxes, myopia, or transaction costs. one for one by inflationary expectations. Such
As long as these “frictions” can be expressed judicious use of economic theory explained the
solely in real terms, the neutrality result of otherwise-mysterious finding of the simulta-
natural rate theory will be robust. neous increases in inflation and unemployment
Empirical considerations have also been in- of the late 1960s/early 1970s. The theory is also
fluential in economists’ acceptance of natural consistent with most econometric estimates.
rate theory. The original Phillips curve showed
a close fit between the rate of change of nominal
wages and the inverse of the unemployment rate B. Nominal Considerations in Wage Behavior
for 97 years of British data, between 1861 and
1957. There was no inflation adjustment in this We now turn to the same question regarding
equation. In the United States in the late 1960s wages that we asked concerning consumption
and early 1970s, however, such a simple inverse and investment. Is there “excess sensitivity”
relation between changes in nominal wages and relative to the respective neutrality? Natural
unemployment broke down, as both price and rate theory is based on the assumption that
wage inflation rose, along with the unemploy- wages and prices are set only with real con-
ment rate. Natural rate theory offered an expla- siderations in mind. “Excess sensitivity” here
nation for this occurrence: it explained the rise
in inflation by the large oil supply shock and
also an increase in inflationary expectations, about the Phillips curve, including the natural rate of un-
employment itself, is considered to be estimated with great
both of which shifted the Phillips curve out- imprecision. Akerlof, William T. Dickens, and George L.
ward; it explained the rise in unemployment by Perry (2000) show a range of estimates for both wage and
a decline in demand. price equations with many different specifications. These
Furthermore, new estimates of Phillips curves estimates, particularly when made for periods of low infla-
seemed to show that the theory closely fit the data. tion, show considerable variation in the sum of the coeffi-
cients on lagged inflation, dependent on the specification.
If inflationary expectations are formed as a simple Another bit of evidence that suggests such estimates will be
lag of past inflation, estimates of Phillips curves sensitive to specification comes from the high standard
should find that the coefficients on past inflation errors on the natural rate itself (Douglas Staiger, James H.
sum to one. Many Phillips curve estimates fail to Stock, and Mark W. Watson 1997); it would be surprising
that the sum of lagged coefficients could be estimated
reject that this sum is equal to one.66, 67 The stan- precisely if another component of the Phillips curve, the
natural rate, could be estimated only with very low preci-
sion. Gordon’s own estimates show very different values for
66
See, for example, Robert J. Gordon (1977, table 3, this sum of coefficients. Of course, there is a theoretical
lines 6 and 7, 260). reason why estimates of such a sum should not be robust.
67
Given the importance of such findings, it is remark- With rational expectations, rather than a simple mechanical
able that their robustness to specifications of time period, theory of formation of inflationary expectations, Sargent
data, and exact specification of the Phillips curve has never (1971) shows that there is no theoretical reason that they
been subjected to tough tests— even though everything else should sum to one.
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 23

takes the form that nominal considerations af- shows such a spiral.71 For example, the United
fect real wage or price setting in some way or States experienced rapid deflation from 1929 to
other. 1933, but inflation systematically neither rose nor
Evidence of one form of violation of the fell for the next decade. The predictions of natural
assumptions of natural rate theory is especially rate theory are thus grossly violated. But sticky
stark. That evidence concerns downward wage wages offer a good explanation for such behavior.
rigidity. Such wage behavior can easily be per- For example, a dynamic simulation of the US
ceived statistically by examining distributions economy with money wage rigidity and with
of wage-changes. These distributions are char- Depression-level unemployment fits the data all
acterized by a bunching of wage changes at but exactly (Akerlof, Dickens, and Perry 1996).72
exactly zero; there are some wage changes just Nominal wage rigidity may not only be sta-
above zero in these distributions, but almost no tistically perceptible; it can also be macroeco-
wage changes just below.68 Careful studies have nomically important, even outside of Great
documented such wage stickiness in Australia, Depressions. Nominal wage rigidity imparts a
Canada, Germany, Japan, Mexico, New Zea- long-run trade-off between unemployment and
land, Switzerland, the United States, and the long-run inflation. This trade-off is of sufficient
United Kingdom.69,70 There seems to be no way size that it should deter central banks from
to account for such nominal wage rigidity with targeting very low levels of inflation. For exam-
the basic assumptions underlying natural rate ple, simulations of the US economy (Akerlof,
theory: that participants in the economy care Dickens, and Perry 1996) show that an increase
only about real prices and real wages. of the inflation target from 0 to 2 percent will
Wage stickiness also explains a macroeco- permanently reduce unemployment by 1.5 per-
nomic observation that is an anomaly for natural centage points.73
rate theory. Unemployment was so massive in
the Great Depression that inflation should have Norms as Explanation for Sticky Money
been below inflationary expectations throughout Wages.—It seems to be impossible, or all but
this long period. With any natural-rate adaptive- impossible, to explain the existence of sticky
expectations Phillips curve, such high unemploy- money wages, without relaxation of the basic
ment would have caused a deflationary spiral. assumption that the utility functions of employ-
Data on inflation are available for 12 countries for ees or of employers contain real arguments. A
the Great Depression. Not a single one of them simple and natural amendment to the standard
model explains such sticky money wages: that
employees have a norm for what wages should
68
These distributions have accumulations at zero, and be. According to that norm, they will lose utility
they are also asymmetric: there are more wage changes from a money wage decline. Sticky money
above zero than below zero. This suggests that the accumu- wages then result, as the bargains between em-
lations at zero do not occur just because there is a menu cost
for changing wages.
ployers and employees reflect the presence of
69
The following studies have all found significant signs this ideal in the utility function.
of nominal wage rigidity: Truman Bewley (1999), David Indeed, the study by Bewley (1999) gives
Card and Dean Hyslop (1997), Shulamit Kahn (1997),
David E. Lebow, Raven E. Saks, and Beth Anne Wilson
71
(1999), and Joseph G. Altonji and Paul J. Devereux (1999) See Janet L. Yellen and Akerlof (2006, 12).
72
for the United States; Pierre Fortin (1996) for Canada; There are other possible reasons for this failure of the
Vincenzo Cassino (1995) and Simon Chapple (1996) for standard predictions from natural rate theory. Inflationary
New Zealand; Jacqueline Dwyer and Kenneth Leong (2000) expectations may not have been adaptive; the failure of
for Australia; Sara G. Castellanos, Rodrigo Garcı́a-Verdú, deflation to accelerate could be due to expectations that the
and David Kaplan (2004) for Mexico; Sachiko Kuroda and price level would return to some normal level. In the United
Isamu Yamamoto (2003a, b, c) and Takeshi Kimura and States, the National Recovery Act, which encouraged firms
Kazuo Ueda (2001) for Japan; Ernst Fehr and Lorenz Goette to increase prices, and unionization, which gave a fillip to
(2003) for Switzerland; Thomas Bauer, Holger Bonin, and wages, could also have affected the trade-off between in-
Uwe Sunde (2003) and Christoph Knoppik and Thomas flation and unemployment. But since unemployment was so
Beissinger (2003) for Germany; Stephen Nickell and very high for so very long, and since the absence of accel-
Glenda Quintini (2001) for the United Kingdom; and Jonas erating deflation was so universal across countries, this still
Agell and Per Lundborg (2003) for Sweden. seems to be a dog that did not bark. It seems to point to a
70
See, for example, Anthony P. O’Brien (1989) and problem with natural rate theory.
73
Christopher Hanes (2000). See Akerlof, Dickens, and Perry (1996, table 4).
24 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

direct evidence that such a norm exists and is siderations in mind, but desired wage changes
responsible for wage stickiness. His extensive will be truncated insofar as they entail money
open-ended interviews sought to elicit why em- wage decreases. To my mind, such a view en-
ployers failed to cut money wages in the Con- tails a theoretical error. As we have seen, the
necticut recession of 1991–1992. Bewley existence of money wage rigidity occurs be-
concludes that, even though substitute labor was cause workers have a norm, which affects their
easily available, employers were reluctant to cut utility function, that their employers should not
wages because of the negative effects of such make such cuts. The message of this finding is
cuts on morale. He says that managers were that norms in the utility function yield at least
afraid that cuts in money wages would cause one clear violation of natural rate theory. That
workers no longer to “identify” with their com- suggests the further empirical possibility that
panies.74 There might be no immediate conse- workers (and also employers and customers)
quences during the recession. But employers may also have other norms regarding what nom-
thought that such cuts would cause workers to inal wages (and prices) should be. All such
shirk after the recession had ended. They also violations are exceptions to natural rate theory,
feared that their best workers would be more and yield reasons for long-run trade-offs be-
likely to quit. These stories indicate that work- tween inflation and unemployment.
ers are not thinking about their wages only in Money wage rigidity is then potentially only
real terms, relative to the price level or the the tip of an iceberg. If there is one way in
wages received by others. They also have a which nominal wages enter utility functions,
special aversion to cuts in wages below their because of employees’ norms regarding what
current nominal levels.75 their employers should or should not do, there
could also be many other ways.
Norms about Wage Increases.—The motiva- There is another natural way whereby such
tion underlying resistance to money wage cuts norms could enter utility functions: employees
is so obvious, and the facts are so unexception- may not only have a norm that they should not
able, that most macroeconomists accept the pos- take wage cuts. They may also have norms
sibility that money wages are sticky. Even so, regarding the nominal rate of increase of their
they rarely appreciate the broader implications wages or salaries. For example, employees may
of such violation of the assumptions of natural believe that their employer should give them a
rate theory. Their adjusted model is that price nominal raise.
and wage decisions are made only with real con- There is little research on the existence of
such norms. The two questionnaire studies that
have investigated it obtain strong and mutually
74
In more detail, Bewley (1999, 1–2) summarizes his reinforcing results. Eldar Shafir, Peter Dia-
findings: “Other theories fail in part because they are based mond, and Tversky (1997) asked respondents to
on unrealistic psychological assumptions that people’s abil-
ities do not depend on their state of mind and that they are
comment on a vignette about two young women
rational in the simplistic sense that they maximize a utility who take their first jobs with the same initial
that depends only on their consumption and working con- income. Specifically they asked respondents
ditions, not on the welfare of others. Wage rigidity is the who will be better off: Barbara, who receives a
product of more complicated employee behavior, in the face 5-percent raise in the presence of 4-percent in-
of which manager reluctance to cut pay is rational. Worker
behavior, however, is not always rational and completely flation; or Ann, who receives a 2-percent raise
understandable. A model that captures the essence of wage when inflation is zero; 79 percent of respon-
rigidity must take into account the capacity of employees to dents correctly said that Barbara would be
identify with their firm and to internalize its objectives. This worse off than Ann economically. Nevertheless,
internalization and workers’ mood have a strong impact on
job performance and call for material, moral, and symbolic
64 percent of respondents also said that Barbara
reciprocation from company leadership.” would be happier.76 Such responses are con-
75
Following the argument by Raj Chetty and Adam trary to the natural rate hypothesis that em-
Szeidl (2006), some employers may have been concerned ployees only care about real returns. But an
with the fact that their employees had fixed mortgages that easy explanation for this phenomenon occurs if
they would find difficult to pay with cuts in nominal wages.
This puts the violation of natural rate theory in another
place: why were these financial contracts in nominal rather
76
than in real terms? Shafir, Diamond, and Tversky (1997, 351–52).
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 25

Barbara and Ann both think that their employer high and therefore also very salient, the answers
should give them a nominal wage increase. to such questionnaires could be very different.
Another study, with a different form of ques- And they could impart a very different shape to
tionnaire, independently found a similar re- the trade-off between macroeconomic demand
sponse. Robert Shiller found that 49 percent of and steady-state inflation.78 In such cases, peo-
a sample of the general public either fully or ple may gain satisfaction only from wage and
weakly agreed with the following statement: “If salary increases that exceed inflation. Such
my pay went up, I would feel more satisfaction norms regarding how employers should behave
in my job, more sense of fulfillment, even if will then necessitate higher real wages (to main-
prices went up as much.” An additional 11 tain the same level of satisfaction) at higher
percent of the general public were undecided, levels of inflation. The long-run inflation-
while only 27 percent completely disagreed. As employment relation will then be downward
in the case of Ann and Barbara, such opinions sloping. Such behavior gives a much stronger
are consistent with the view that workers think rationale, even than current rational-expectations
their employers should give them a nominal credibility models (Barro and Gordon 1983; Ken-
wage increase: they will be disappointed when neth Rogoff 1987), why central banks should
it does not occur. Shiller’s finding may be sim- maintain price stability. Failure to appreciate this
ilar to the public’s view of Ann and Barbara. realistic possibility again may be another case in
But, as he reports, it is also in stark disagree- which the absence of norms from utility functions
ment with the view of professional economists has unduly blinkered macroeconomic thinking.79
that underlies natural rate theory. Ninety per-
cent of economists weakly or strongly disagreed 78
with the statement; 77 percent were in complete Bankruptcy and financial considerations become es-
pecially important when inflation is very high. It is also
disagreement.77 worth noting, at least parenthetically, that high levels of
Such norms—regarding the wage or salary in- bankruptcy at times of high inflation are themselves a symp-
crease that employees think they should receive— tom of money illusion. Such bankruptcies reflect the non-
can be economically consequential. They cause indexation of financial contracts.
79
the long-run inflation-unemployment trade-off In addition to the two questionnaire studies I have
mentioned, indexed contracts give another indicator for the
to be downward sloping. With such a norm, at existence of nominal notions concerning what wage in-
higher levels of inflation workers will not expe- creases should or should not be. Economists are often sur-
rience disappointment from receiving lower prised at the small fraction of union contracts that are
nominal wage increases than they think they indexed at all. (Louis N. Christofides and Amy Chen Peng
2004, for example, analyzed a sample of almost 12,000
should receive; therefore, at higher inflation, Canadian union contracts from 1976 to 2000. The mean
ceteris paribus, wage bargains will result in length of these contracts was slightly more than two years
lower real wages, which will reduce the relative (25 months). Only 19 percent of these contracts were in-
price that the firm wants to set, and therefore dexed.) But even when such indexation occurs, their form
violates the condition that they were struck with only real
raise the rate of sustainable employment. There considerations in mind. For an imperfect index such as the
is a need for further research following Shafir, CPI, which reflects both supply shocks and demand shocks,
Diamond, and Tversky and Shiller regarding the optimal COLA adjustment will be less than one, but it
whether workers have norms regarding the nom- will always be (almost) symmetric for positive and negative
inal wage increases they think they should receive. deviations of inflation from a threshold. (See Jo Anna Gray
1978, Ronald G. Ehrenberg, Leif Danziger, and Gee San
1983, and David Card 1986 for the derivation of optimal
High Inflation.—The opinions expressed re- indexation.) But COLA adjustments are only positive. (Card
garding Barbara and Ann, and also the opinions 1986, S146, has expressed this in terms of a formula: w(t) ⫽
of Shiller’s respondents, suggest that the long- wn(t) ⫹ max{0, ␣[ p(t) ⫺ p␶]}, where w(t) is the nominal
wage, wn(t) is the nominal target, p(t) is the actual price
run trade-off between inflation and employment level, and p␶ is the threshold.) Thus, the form of the contract
is upward sloping. These answers were elicited violates optimality. In practice, this violation is also biting.
in the United States and thus are reflective of For example, in roughly one-third of a large Canadian
respondents’ views in an environment where sample of indexed contracts, inflation was always below the
inflation has been low. But if inflation is very threshold (see Christofides and Peng 2004, 11, fn. 19). Thus,
the form of indexed contracts, when they exist, shows that
union wage negotiators think that COLA adjustments
should never be negative. The form of indexed contracts
77
Shiller (1997, 37). gives another robust indicator that, indeed, wage setters
26 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

C. Prices extensive evidence on price stickiness reveals


violation of the assumptions of natural rate the-
We have just seen that employees’ norms ory, and also the existence of norms regarding
regarding nominal wages may affect bargained price change. Like wage changes, price changes
real wages, and therefore cause trade-offs between also agglomerate at zero. Dennis Carlton (1986)
long-run inflation and long-run unemployment. has shown that prices are often sticky for sig-
Similarly, customers’ norms regarding price levels nificant periods of time.81 Furthermore, prices
and price changes may also cause long-run trade- seem to be especially sticky in customer mar-
offs between output and inflation. kets.82 Alan Kackmeister (2002) has compared
Indeed, models by Katsuhito Iwai (1981), price changes at the end of the nineteenth cen-
Julio J. Rotemberg (1982), and Andrew S. Cap- tury to such changes a bit more than a century
lin and John Leahy (1991) all have long-run later. Price changes of specific goods at retail
trade-offs between inflation and unemployment. stores were recorded from June 1889 to Sep-
Each of these models assumes that there are real tember 1891; Kackmeister revisited the same
costs to nominal price changes. If, instead, there commodities and their price change for a com-
were real costs to real price changes, the as- parable period, from June 1997 to September
sumptions of natural rate theory would still be 1999. Price change in the late twentieth century
satisfied, and no such trade-off would occur. was five times more frequent than a century
These models then pose the question why there earlier. Furthermore, in the nineteenth century,
should be such real costs from nominal price the average spell of constant price for an indi-
changes. Iwai, Rotemberg, and Caplin and vidual good was very long. It was approxi-
Leahy all respectively assume that there is a mately 80 months.83 Such constancy of prices
“menu” cost in making these changes known.80 can easily be explained by customer norms re-
But the physical costs of making such changes, garding price change. The customers have a
as in the printing of new menus, are trivially notion of the price that they ought to pay at
small. Norms regarding price changes, how- stores where they are continued and knowing
ever, give an alternative reason why these costs customers. Kackmeister suggests that the de-
might—indeed— be of sufficient size to induce cline in long-term customer relationships is one
a significant long-run trade-off between infla- factor responsible for greater frequency of price
tion and unemployment. Customers may think change today.
that firms should not raise prices. In that case, Emi Nakamura and Jón Steinsson (2005)
price increases (or increases of greater size) are give an economic reason why customers would
likely to induce angry customers to search for have such a norm that firms should not change
alternative suppliers. At higher steady-state in- prices. They view consumer purchases as habit-
flation, firms will be changing their nominal forming. Thus, by buying a particular brand, or
prices more, and therefore will face more elastic patronizing a particular store, consumers are
demands for their product. Producers’ natural putting themselves in a position where they can
microeconomic response to this increased elas- be exploited. Their loyalty puts the firm in a
ticity—a lower price for their product—will
produce a macroeconomic trade-off between in- 81
flation and aggregate demand. See also Blinder and Don Choi (1990) and Blinder et
al. (1998).
Just as sticky money wages indicated that 82
The meaning of customer markets was especially ex-
employees have norms regarding wage change, plored by Arthur Okun (1978).
similarly, sticky prices indicate that customers 83
I derive this result from Kackmeister’s data in the
have norms regarding price change. Thus, the following way. He finds that in the nineteenth century, only
5 percent of items changed their prices per month. This
means that the average spell of constant prices would have
been 20 months (the inverse). But that is a biased statistic
have notions regarding what nominal wage increases should for the average length of time between price changes for an
or should not be. This, of course, is just one of many item on the shelf. The difference between the average spell
anomalies in the form of indexed contracts. of employment or unemployment and the average spell
80
Marika Karanassou, Hector Sala, and Dennis J. being experienced by an individual suggests a rule of thumb
Snower (2003) find considerable long-run trade-off between ratio for four to one. Using this ratio as a rule of thumb
inflation and unemployment in a model with nominal price suggests that the spell between price changes averaged over
staggering and money growth. the individual items on the shelf would be 80 months.
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 27

position where it can take advantage of the VIII. Rational Expectations Theory
consumer by raising prices. Firms then make an
implicit contract with their customers: they will Our discussion of rational expectations pig-
not change their prices unjustifiably. Since such gybacks on our previous discussion of the nat-
an implicit contract is easier to make (and en- ural rate.
force) regarding nominal prices than real prices, According to rational expectations theory, in-
the implicit guarantee is in nominal terms. Na- sofar as the central bank changes the money
kamura and Steinsson have also discovered a supply systematically in response to employ-
phenomenon that suggests strikingly that firms ment conditions, the public will foresee that
do behave this way. Goods in store 126 (chosen response and change prices and wages exactly
for its completeness of data) of Dominicks Finer to compensate. The public’s anticipation will
Foods chain frequently go on sale; when the then exactly offset the response. Monetary pol-
sale ends, their nominal price returns to the icy is neutral.85
exact same level. Such behavior is consistent There are two key assumptions underlying
with the view that consumers think that prices this neutrality. The obvious one is rational ex-
should not change (for whatever reason); and pectations. To some, rational expectations re-
that they are also likely to retaliate (change garding the effects of the money supply on
brands) when prices do change. prices and wages would seem to be beyond the
I should also remark that in countries where sophistication of most wage and price takers,
inflation is very high, customers will expect and also of most wage and price setters.
price changes to occur frequently, and possibly Even in the case where all those involved in
be of large magnitude. The inhibitions against buying and selling goods and labor services
price changes when inflation is low are eroded have rational expectations, however, the neu-
at high inflation. Thus, while norms concerning trality results of rational expectations theory
prices give a negative long-run trade-off be- require also that nominal considerations do not
tween inflation and unemployment at low infla- enter into the setting of either wages or prices.
tion, at high inflation that trade-off could very The previous descriptions of the ways in which
well be reversed. nominal wages and prices enter into preference
functions, via employees’ views of the wages
D. Summary that ought to be received and consumers’ views
of the prices that ought to be paid, give further
To summarize, there is considerable evidence reason why the neutrality results of rational
of violation of the assumptions and predictions expectations will be violated. If prices and
of natural rate theory. Wages and prices are wages are affected by people’s notions of what
nominally rigid; there were no deflationary spi- their nominal values should be, monetary policy
rals in the Great Depression; and questionnaire can be effective in stabilizing output—and pos-
respondents act as if they have a positive like for sibly in raising its long-run level— even in the
nominal wage increases.84 This evidence sug- presence of rational expectations.
gests that wage earners and customers have
views on what wages and prices should be. The IX. Economic Methodology
reflection of such views in utility functions pro-
duces trade-offs between inflation and unem- We have seen that the absence of norms plays
ployment. Those trade-offs have significant a key role in each of the five neutralities. Why
implications for economic policy. On the one have economists made such systematic omis-
hand, central banks should avoid very low tar- sions? The omission of norms from macroeco-
gets for inflation. On the other hand, they should nomics, as well as from economics more
avoid high inflation, where the trade-offs be-
tween inflation and unemployment may be
85
reversed. Empirically there is a theoretical puzzle of excess
sensitivity to monetary shocks (Lawrence J. Christiano,
Martin Eichenbaum, and Charles L. Evans 1998). Christina
and David Romer (1989) have shown that such a response
84
Also, COLA clauses are asymmetrically positive. See occurs with lags that would be surprisingly long if expected
footnote 79 above. monetary shocks were always neutralized.
28 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

generally, can be explained by economists’ ad- models based only on utility with objective
herence to positive economics.86 Friedman’s variables verified only by statistical hypothesis
(1953) essay on positive economics describes testing— has severe bias against explanations of
the methodological implications of such belief. economic phenomena where norms play a role.
In particular, he says that economic theorists Summers (1986) illustrates the severity of
should strive for parsimonious modeling. Ac- this bias. The conventional test of the efficient
cording to Friedman, they should even forsake markets hypothesis—that stock prices are the
realistic assumptions in pursuit of such parsi- expected value of future returns—looks for au-
mony. Maximization models with only objec- tocorrelations of the excess returns on stocks
tive arguments of utility have been defined as relative to bonds. Following Summers, it would
more parsimonious than models where people, take approximately 5,000 years of data with
additionally, lose utility insofar as they, or oth- such a test to obtain as much as 50 percent
ers, fail to live up to their standards. As a result, rejection of an alternative model where stock
whatever the empirical validity or relevance of prices are more than 30 percent away from their
such norms, positive economics has a method- fundamentals 35 percent of the time. With such
ological bias against their consideration. It priv- lack of power, nulls are important. When they
ileges models without norms. are not rejected, alternative theories, such as
The prescriptions of positive economics re- those with norms, are not even considered. This
garding the conduct of empirical investigation lecture has illustrated such reversion to norm-
compound the bias against norms. Friedman less nulls. Consumption behavior, investment
says that economists should not pay heed to the behavior, and wage and price behavior—the three
stated intentions of decision makers, which most important components of most macro mod-
would include their norms as to how they and els—all display excess sensitivity relative to re-
others should behave. Instead, empirical work spective neutralities. All of these violations could
should test only hypotheses that economists be easily explained by norms. Yet in each case
consider to be based on parsimonious models. economists have sought to explain such viola-
If economic tests had great power, then it tions of classical theory by norm-less models.
would be easy, of course, to follow Friedman’s In contrast to reliance on statistical testing,
dictum of making more and more refined tests disciplines other than economics typically put
of hypotheses with decreasing parsimony. If much greater weight on a naturalistic ap-
norms really do affect behavior, this method proach. This approach involves detailed case
would reject models without norms and in due studies. Such observation of the small often
course would arrive at models where people’s has been the key to the understanding of the
views regarding how they should behave affect large. To me, the most dramatic example of
decision making. But economic tests lack such a relation between the small and the
power. All economic models are very imprecise large occurs in the structure of life itself.
in their specification of the independent vari- Francis Crick and James D. Watson87 conjec-
able, the nature of the dependent variables, the tured correctly that if they could describe the
nature of leads and lags, and the nature of crystalline structure of a single DNA mole-
residuals. Yet worse, most economic problems cule, they would have unlocked the secret of
involve simultaneity (as in supply and demand), life. The duality between the structure of the
making establishment of causality difficult. In DNA molecule and the way in which organ-
almost any instance, such a large number of isms are generated and reproduced is one of
models can be fitted statistically that it is ex- the most beautiful findings of human knowl-
tremely hard—and perhaps impossible—to sta- edge. It indicates the sense in which Crick and
tistically reject all the variants of models Watson were, indeed, profoundly correct.
without norms. As a result, the program of What are the implications for social science?
positive economics—with its initial nulls of Positive economics, with its emphasis on statis-
tical analysis of populations, would suggest that

86
Some of the thoughts and wording in this section have
87
been presented in Akerlof (2005). As dramatically described by Watson (1969).
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 29

the intensive study of a single molecule would economics. In contrast, a more naturalistic ap-
be an all-but-worthless anecdote. In the case of proach would prescribe a different methodol-
DNA, we know that the exact opposite is true: ogy. In this case, economists would observe
because DNA is a template that determines all decision makers as closely as possible, with the
of the cells of the organism, and also its repro- express intent of characterizing their motiva-
duction, one molecule may not tell all, but it tion, and would use such characterization as the
does tell a great deal. Form follows function. basis for modeling of economic structure. In-
Is there some reason to believe that economic deed, sociological and anthropological ethnog-
behavior and economic units are any different? raphers do precisely that: they depict their
Economic decisions may not be as duplicable as subjects’ motivation from close observation.
biological processes, but the basic reason why
science intensively studies the microscopic ap- X. Endogeneity of Norms
plies to economics as well. The individual eco-
nomic unit, be it a firm, a consumer, or an It is now time to discuss the endogeneity of
employee, behaves the way it does for a reason. the norms. There is a special reason for its
And if these actors behave as they do for a consideration. Robert Lucas discovered that,
reason, we can expect to find those reasons from with endogenous rational expectations re-
the structures that we see in close observation; garding inflation, monetary policy that was
and because of those structures their behavior intended to stabilize the macroeconomy
will also tend to be duplicated. This duality would, instead, be exactly neutral. Similarly,
between duplicability and structure explains is it not possible that endogeneity of the
why much of science concerns very close ob- norms, like Lucas’s endogeneity of inflation-
servation, as it also explains why the study of ary expectations, will cause the neutralities
even a single part of a single DNA molecule again to hold? We shall discuss this question
will be revealing. regarding all five neutralities. For the most
Standard economic methodology says that part, we find that the type of government
it is impossible to infer motivation of individ- interventions being considered are usually of
ual actors from intensive case studies. An- such frequency, or of such order of magni-
thropologists and sociologists listen carefully tude, that they should provoke relatively little
to individuals in such studies. When people change in the norms. Endogeneity of the
follow the norms, they use them to explain norms should have little effect, then, on our
their actions; when, on the other hand, they previous conclusions.
violate the norms, they become the subject of
local gossip. Those case studies are revealing A. Ricardian Equivalence
because—like a language, which dictates how
one should speak—the norms are common Let’s begin by returning to Ricardian equiv-
knowledge. In this lecture, we have seen one alence, which is still the simplest case. We
prominent example of the use of such knowl- found that if people have a norm regarding the
edge: Bewley’s interviews uncovered the amount of their bequest, then lump-sum trans-
common understanding of the norms regard- fers to an older generation will not be neutral.
ing wage cuts among Connecticut employers There remains the possibility that the source of
in the early 1990s. the warm glow to the older generation is not the
total bequest, but instead the bequest to the
Summary.—Positive economics systemati- younger generation net of the transfer. In this
cally denies that norms can be understood from case, if the transfers change, then the norm
intensive case study. Precedence given to mod- changes. Ricardian equivalence will again be
els without norms because they are by definition valid. While such changes in norms with the
more parsimonious and statistical tests of low size of transfers are a theoretical possibility,
power then jointly create a firewall against con- they also seem highly unlikely. The size of the
sideration that norms play a role in determining transfers involved— especially for those rich
behavior. For these reasons, current economic enough to make large nonaccidental bequests—
methodology inherently has created a biased would seem to be too small to warrant such a
30 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

sophisticated calculation. Our earlier discussion powerful evidence in favor of norms comes
did discuss at least one change in the norms from employees’ resistance to money wage
regarding bequests, but that resulted from a very cuts and customers’ resistance to nominal
large change in people’s orientation. It resulted price increases. As long as inflation is low, it
from changes in their conception of the family— is doubtful that small changes in inflation will
of their own place within it and of the place of affect such norms. People seem to find it
their heirs. That also occurred over a very long easier to think in nominal, rather than in real,
run— over the course of centuries. terms. Indeed the facilitation of such thinking
is one of the benefits of money according to
B. Life-Cycle Hypothesis the textbook mantra on its three uses: for
transactions, as a store of value, and as a unit
Regarding the life-cycle hypothesis, we ar- of account. Money is useful as a unit of
gued that consumption depends upon current account especially if people think in nominal,
income because norms regarding how much rather than in real, terms. As a result, as long
people think they should spend are linked to as inflation is low, people are unlikely to
it. But such a norm would be highly unlikely forsake making calculations in nominal terms,
to change as a result of the use of fiscal and especially regarding the norms of what wages
monetary policy for stabilization. In the first or prices should be. Of course, if inflation
place, such stabilization will make the adher- increases to high levels, the norms for wages
ence to the norm less costly, not more costly, and prices and the method of calculating
in purely economic terms. Furthermore, mac- those norms will change. Exactly how they
roeconomic sources are responsible for only a change—with the possibility that they under-
small fraction of the variation in individual adjust to increases in inflation when it is low
incomes. As a result, there is further reason and overadjust when it is high—should be
why the role of current income in norms is empirically investigated.
unlikely to change as a result of macroeco-
nomic stabilization. E. Where Do the Norms Come From?

C. Cash Flow and Investment We do not know the general answer to the
question where norms come from. This lecture
The rise of the CFO suggests that norms has tried to make the case that norms, such as
regarding investment have changed in large US they are, could potentially play an important
firms. Quite possibly, this change occurred be- role in macroeconomics. Hopefully, then, it has
cause firms realized the need for financial con- added to the motivation for research on their
trols that compared the returns on inside and microfoundations.88
outside options. Such an endogenous response
would make Modigliani-Miller correct. But, XI. Conclusion
following Zorn (2004), this change took 40
years. In the meantime, in the short run, follow- This lecture has shown that the early Keyne-
ing our earlier logic, investment would have sians got a great deal of the working of the
depended on cash flow. And, of course, even in economic system right, in ways that are denied
the long run the CFO, who is only one voice by the five neutralities. As quoted from Keynes
among many in corporate decisions, may not be earlier, they based their models on “our knowl-
fully effective. edge of human nature and from the detailed
facts of experience.” They used their intuitions
D. Natural Rate Hypothesis and the Role of regarding the norms of how consumers, inves-
Rational Expectations tors, and wage and price setters thought they

Regarding the natural rate hypothesis and 88


also the rational expectations hypothesis, we This lecture has been very much influenced by the
insights of the Ph.D. thesis of Robert Akerlof (2006) on
saw that they will no longer hold if norms of preferences for beliefs. His thinking on this subject has
price and wage setting have nominal compo- influenced many of the sections of this paper, especially on
nents. Regarding prices and wages, the most consumption and the endogeneity of norms.
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 31

should behave. There is systematic reason why Akerlof, George A., ed. 2005. Explorations in
such knowledge and experience are likely to be Pragmatic Economics: Selected Papers of
accurate: by their nature, norms are generated George A. Akerlof (and Co-Authors). Oxford
and known by a whole community. They are and New York: Oxford University Press.
known to those who abide by them, and those Akerlof, George A., William T. Dickens, and
who observe them as well. George L. Perry. 1996. “The Macroeconom-
We have shown ways in which macroeconomic ics of Low Inflation.” Brookings Papers on
variables will be affected by norms. The neutral- Economic Activity, 1: 1–59.
ities say that consumption should have no special Akerlof, George A., William T. Dickens, and
dependence on current income; investment should George L. Perry. 2000. “Near-Rational Wage
be independent of current cash flow; wages and and Price Setting and the Long-Run Phillips
prices should not depend on nominal consider- Curve.” Brookings Papers on Economic Ac-
ations. The very construction of those neutralities tivity, 1: 1– 60.
denies the possibility that peoples’ decisions Akerlof, George A., and Rachel E. Kranton. 2000.
might be influenced by their views regarding how “Economics and Identity.” Quarterly Journal
they, and how others, should behave. In practice, of Economics, 115(3): 715–53.
however, the neutralities are systematically vio- Akerlof, George A., and Rachel E. Kranton. 2002.
lated. Insofar as economists have felt it necessary “Identity and Schooling: Some Lessons for
to explain these violations, they have appealed to the Economics of Education.” Journal of
a variety of different frictions, such as myopia and Economic Literature, 40(4): 1167–1201.
credit constraint. In so doing, they have failed to Akerlof, George A., and Rachel E. Kranton. 2005.
consider that those violations would occur even in “Identity and the Economics of Organiza-
the absence of those frictions: they will occur tions.” Journal of Economic Perspectives,
because of decision makers’ norms. 19(1): 9 –32.
The incorporation of norms based on careful Akerlof, George A., and Rachel E. Kranton. 2006.
observation imparts an appropriate balance to “The Missing Motivation: Economics Made
macroeconomics. The New Classical research Human.” Unpublished.
program was correct in viewing models of the Akerlof, Robert J. 2006. “A Theory of Social
early Keynesians as too primitive. They had not Motivation.” Unpublished.
been sufficiently attentive to the role of human Altonji, Joseph G., and Paul J. Devereux. 1999.
intent in choices regarding consumption, invest- “The Extent and Consequences of Downward
ment, wages, and prices. But that research pro- Nominal Wage Rigidity.” National Bureau of
gram itself has failed to appreciate the extent to Economic Research Working Paper 7236.
which the Keynesians’ views of macroeconom- Andreoni, James. 1989. “Giving with Impure
ics were also reflective of reality, since they Altruism: Applications to Charity and Ricar-
were based on experience and observation. dian Equivalence.” Journal of Political Econ-
A macroeconomics with norms in decision omy, 97(6): 1447–58.
makers’ objective functions combines the best Banks, James, Richard Blundell, and Sarah Tanner.
features of the two approaches. It allows for 1998. “Is There a Retirement-Savings Puzzle?”
observations regarding how people think they American Economic Review, 88(4): 769 – 88.
should behave. It also takes due account of the Barro, Robert J. 1974. “Are Government Bonds
purposefulness of human decisions. Net Wealth?” Journal of Political Economy,
82(6): 1095–1117.
REFERENCES Barro, Robert J. 1989. “The Ricardian Ap-
proach to Budget Deficits.” Journal of Eco-
Abel, Andrew B. 1979. Investment and the Value nomic Perspectives, 3(2): 37–54.
of Capital. New York: Garland Publishing. Barro, Robert J., and David B. Gordon. 1983. “A
Ackley, Gardner. 1961. Macroeconomic Theory. Positive Theory of Monetary Policy in a Nat-
New York: Macmillan. ural Rate Model.” Journal of Political Econ-
Agell, Jonas, and Per Lundborg. 2003. “Survey omy, 91(4): 589 – 610.
Evidence on Wage Rigidity and Unemploy- Bauer, Thomas, Holger Bonin, and Uwe Sunde.
ment: Sweden in the 1990s.” Scandinavian 2003. “Real and Nominal Wage Rigidities
Journal of Economics, 105(1): 15–29. and the Rate of Inflation: Evidence from Ger-
32 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

man Microdata.” Institute for the Study of dence.” In NBER Macroeconomics Annual
Labor Discussion Paper 959. 1989, ed. Olivier J. Blanchard and Stanley
Becker, Gary S. 1957. The Economics of Dis- Fischer, 185–216. Cambridge, MA, and Lon-
crimination. Chicago and London: University don: MIT Press.
of Chicago Press. Cannadine, David N. 1977. “Aristocratic Indebt-
Behrman, Jere R., and Mark R. Rosenzweig. edness in the Nineteenth Century: The Case
2004. “Parental Allocations to Children: New Re-Opened.” Economic History Review Sec-
Evidence on Bequest Differences among Sib- ond Series, 30(4): 624 –50.
lings.” Review of Economics and Statistics, Caplin, Andrew S., and John Leahy. 1991.
86(2): 637– 40. “State-Dependent Pricing and the Dynamics
Benedict, Ruth. 1934. Patterns of Culture. Bos- of Money and Output.” Quarterly Journal of
ton: Houghton Mifflin. Economics, 106(3): 683–708.
Bernheim, B. Douglas, and Kyle Bagwell. 1988. Caplow, Theodore. 1984. “Rule Enforcement
“Is Everything Neutral?” Journal of Political without Visible Means: Christmas Giving in
Economy, 96(2): 308 –38. Middletown.” American Journal of Sociol-
Bernheim, B. Douglas, Jonathan Skinner, and ogy, 89(6): 1306 –23.
Steven Weinberg. 2001. “What Accounts for Card, David. 1986. “An Empirical Model of
the Variation in Retirement Wealth among Wage Indexation Provisions in Union Con-
U.S. Households?” American Economic Re- tracts.” Journal of Political Economy, 94(3):
view, 91(4): 832–57. S144 –75.
Bewley, Truman F. 1999. Why Wages Don’t Fall Card, David, and Dean Hyslop. 1997. “Does In-
During a Recession. Cambridge, MA, and flation Grease the Wheels of the Labor Mar-
London: Harvard University Press. ket?” In Reducing Inflation: Motivation and
Blanchard, Olivier Jean, Florencio Lopez-de- Strategy, ed. Christina D. Romer and David
Silanes, and Andrei Shleifer. 1994. “What Do H. Romer, 71–114. Chicago and London:
Firms Do with Cash Windfalls?” Journal of University of Chicago Press.
Financial Economics, 36(3): 337– 60. Carlton, Dennis W. 1986. “The Rigidity of
Blinder, Alan S. 1975. Toward an Economic Prices.” American Economic Review, 76(4):
Theory of Income Distribution. Cambridge, 637–58.
MA, and London: MIT Press. Cassino, Vincenzo. 1995. “The Distribution of
Blinder, Alan S., Elie R. D. Canetti, David E. Wage and Price Changes in New Zealand.”
Lebow, and Jeremy B. Rudd. 1998. Asking Bank of New Zealand Discussion Paper
About Prices: A New Approach to Under- G95/6.
standing Price Stickiness. New York: Russell Castellanos, Sara G., Rodrigo Garcı́a-Verdú, and
Sage Foundation. David S. Kaplan. 2004. “Nominal Wage Ri-
Blinder, Alan S., and Don H. Choi. 1990. “A gidities in Mexico: Evidence from Social Se-
Shred of Evidence on Theories of Wage curity Records.” National Bureau of
Stickiness.” Quarterly Journal of Economics, Economic Research Working Paper 10383.
105(4): 1003–15. Chapple, Simon. 1996. “Money Wage Rigidity
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1984. Distinction: A Social in New Zealand.” Labour Market Bulletin, 2:
Critique of the Judgment of Taste. Cam- 23–50.
bridge, MA, and London: Harvard University Chetty, Raj, and Adam Szeidl. 2006. “Con-
Press. sumption Commitments and Risk.” Na-
Browning, Christopher R. 1992. Ordinary tional Bureau of Economic Research
Men: Reserve Police Battalion 101 and the Working Paper 12467.
Final Solution in Poland. New York: Harper- Christiano, Lawrence J., Martin Eichenbaum,
Collins. and Charles L. Evans. 1998. “Monetary Pol-
Bruner, Robert F. 2002. “Does M&A Pay? A icy Shocks: What Have We Learned and to
Survey of Evidence for the Decision-Maker.” What End?” National Bureau of Economic
Journal of Applied Finance, 12(1): 48 – 68. Research Working Paper 6400.
Campbell, John Y., and N. Gregory Mankiw. Christofides, Louis N., and Amy Chen Peng.
1989. “Consumption, Income, and Interest 2004. “The Determinants of Major Provi-
Rates: Reinterpreting the Time Series Evi- sions in Union Contracts: Duration, Index-
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 33

ation, and Non-Contingent Wage Friedman, Milton. 1957. A Theory of the Con-
Adjustment.” Unpublished. sumption Function. Princeton: Princeton Uni-
Dernburg, Thomas F., and Duncan M. McDou- versity Press.
gall. 1963. Macroeconomics: The Measure- Friedman, Milton. 1968a. Dollars and Deficits.
ment, Analysis, and Control of Aggregate New York: Prentice Hall.
Economic Activity. 2nd ed. New York, Auck- Friedman, Milton. 1968b. “The Role of Mone-
land, London, and Montreal: McGraw-Hill. tary Policy.” American Economic Review,
Dornbusch, Rudiger, and Stanley Fischer. 1987. 58(1): 1–17.
Macroeconomics. 4th ed. New York, Auck- Goffman, Erving. 1961. Encounters. Indianapo-
land, London, and Montreal: McGraw-Hill. lis: Bobbs-Merrill.
Dwyer, Jacqueline, and Kenneth Leong. 2000. Gordon, Robert J. 1977. “Can the Inflation of
“Nominal Wage Rigidity in Australia.” Re- the 1970s Be Explained?” Brookings Papers
serve Bank of Australia Discussion Paper on Economic Activity, 1: 253–79.
2000-08. Gray, Jo Anna. 1978. “On Indexation and Con-
Ehrenberg, Ronald G., Leif Danziger, and Gee San. tract Length.” Journal of Political Economy,
1983. “Cost-of-Living Adjustment Clauses 86(1): 1–18.
in Union Contracts: A Summary of Re- Guiso, Luigi, Paola Sapienza, and Luigi Zingales.
sults.” Journal of Labor Economics, 1(3): 2003. “People’s Opium? Religion and Eco-
215– 45. nomic Attitudes.” Journal of Monetary Eco-
Elster, Jon. 1989. “Social Norms and Economic nomics, 50(1): 225– 82.
Theory.” Journal of Economic Perspectives, Guiso, Luigi, Paola Sapienza, and Luigi Zingales.
3(4): 99 –117. 2006. “Does Culture Affect Economic Out-
Fazzari, Steven M., R. Glenn Hubbard, and Bruce comes?” Journal of Economic Perspectives,
C. Petersen. 1988. “Financing Constraints and 20(2): 23– 48.
Corporate Investment.” Brookings Papers on Hanes, Christopher. 2000. “Nominal Wage Ri-
Economic Activity, 1: 141–206. gidity and Industry Characteristics in the
Fehr, Ernst, and Lorenz Goette. 2003. “Robust- Downturns of 1893, 1929, and 1981.” Amer-
ness and Real Consequences of Nominal ican Economic Review, 90(5): 1432– 46.
Wage Rigidity.” University of Zurich Insti- Hayashi, Fumio. 1982. “Tobin’s Marginal q and
tute for Empirical Research in Economics Average q: A Neoclassical Interpretation.”
Working Paper 44. Econometrica, 50(1): 213–24.
Feldstein, Martin S. 1974. “Social Security, In- Hodson, Randy. 2001. Dignity at Work. Cam-
duced Retirement, and Aggregate Capital Ac- bridge: Cambridge University Press.
cumulation.” Journal of Political Economy, Holton, Woody. 1999. Forced Founders: In-
82(5): 905–26. dians, Debtors, Slaves, and the Making of
Feldstein, Martin S., and Anthony Pellechio. the American Revolution in Virginia.
1979. “Social Security and Household Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina
Wealth Accumulation: New Microeconomet- Press.
ric Evidence.” Review of Economics and Sta- Homans, George C., and Charles P. Curtis. 1934.
tistics, 61(3): 361– 68. An Introduction to Pareto, His Sociology.
Fligstein, Neil. 1990. The Transformation of New York: Knopf.
Corporate Control. Cambridge, MA, and Hurd, Michael D. 1989. “Mortality Risk and
London: Harvard University Press. Bequests.” Econometrica, 57(4): 779 – 813.
Fortin, Pierre. 1996. “The Great Canadian Iwai, Katsuhito. 1981. Disequilibrium Dynam-
Slump.” Canadian Journal of Economics. ics: A Theoretical Analysis of Inflation and
29(4): 761– 87. Unemployment. New Haven and London:
Friedan, Betty. 1963. The Feminine Mystique. Yale University Press.
New York: W.W. Norton and Co. Jensen, Michael C. 1986. “Agency Costs of Free
Friedman, Milton. 1953. “The Methodology of Cash Flow, Corporate Finance, and Take-
Positive Economics.” In Essays in Positive overs.” American Economic Review (Papers
Economics, ed. Milton Friedman, 3– 43. Chi- and Proceedings), 76(2): 323–29.
cago and London: University of Chicago Jensen, Michael C. 1993. “The Modern Indus-
Press. trial Revolution, Exit, and the Failure of In-
34 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

ternal Control Systems.” Journal of Finance, Laitner, John, and Henry Ohlsson. 2001. “Be-
48(3): 831– 80. quest Motives: A Comparison of Sweden and
Kackmeister, Alan K. 2002. “Has Retail Price the United States.” Journal of Public Eco-
Behavior Changed since 1889? Evidence nomics, 79(1): 205–36.
from Micro Data.” PhD Dissertation. Univer- Lamont, Owen. 1997. “Cash Flow and Invest-
sity of California, Berkeley. ment: Evidence from Internal Capital Mar-
Kahn, Shulamit. 1997. “Evidence of Nominal kets.” Journal of Finance, 52(1): 83–109.
Wage Stickiness from Microdata.” American Lebow, David E., Raven E. Saks, and Beth Anne
Economic Review, 87(5): 993–1008. Wilson. 1999. “Downward Nominal Wage
Kaplan, Steven N., and Luigi Zingales. 1997. “Do Rigidity: Evidence from the Employment
Investment–Cash Flow Sensitivities Provide Cost Index.” U.S. Board of Governors of the
Useful Measures of Financing Constraints.” Federal Reserve System, Finance and Eco-
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112(1): nomics Discussion Paper 1999-31.
169 –215. Lucas, Robert E., Jr. 1972. “Expectations and
Karanassou, Marika, Hector Sala, and Dennis J. the Neutrality of Money.” Journal of Eco-
Snower. 2003. “A Reappraisal of the Inflation– nomic Theory, 4(2):103-24.
Unemployment Tradeoff.” University of Lon- Lucas, Robert E., Jr., and Thomas J. Sargent.
don Working Paper 479. 1978. “After Keynesian Macroeconomics.”
Keynes, John M. 1936. The General Theory of In After the Phillips Curve: Persistence of
Employment, Interest, and Money. New High Inflation and Unemployment, (Proceed-
York: Macmillan. ings of Conference 19). Boston: Federal Re-
Kimura, Takeshi, and Kazuo Ueda. 2001. serve Bank of Boston.
“Downward Nominal Wage Rigidity in Ja- Manicka, Rani. 2002. The Rice Mother. New
pan.” Journal of the Japanese and Interna- York: Penguin.
tional Economies, 15(1): 50 – 67. Massey, Douglas S., and Nancy A. Denton. 1993.
Klein, Lawrence R., and Arthur S. Goldberger. American Apartheid: Segregation and the
1955. An Econometric Model of the United Making of the Underclass. Cambridge, MA,
States 1929 –1952. Amsterdam: North-Holland. and London: Harvard University Press.
Knoppik, Christoph, and Thomas Beissinger. Meyer, John R., and Edwin Kuh. 1957. The In-
2003. “How Rigid Are Nominal Wages? Evi- vestment Decision: An Empirical Study.
dence and Implications for Germany.” Scandi- Cambridge, MA, and London: Harvard Uni-
navian Journal of Economics, 105(4): 619 – 41. versity Press.
Kuroda, Sachiko, and Isamu Yamamoto. 2003a. Milgram, Stanley. 1963. “Behavioral Study of
“Are Japanese Nominal Wages Downwardly Obedience.” Journal of Abnormal and Social
Rigid? (Part I): Examinations of Nominal Psychology, 67(4): 371–78.
Wage Change Distributions.” Monetary and Milgram, Stanley. 1965. “Some Conditions on
Economic Studies, 21(2): 1–29. Obedience and Disobedience to Authority.”
Kuroda, Sachiko, and Isamu Yamamoto. 2003b. In Current Studies in Social Psychology, ed.
“Are Japanese Nominal Wages Downwardly Ivan D. Steiner and Martin Fishbein. New
Rigid? (Part II): Examinations Using a Fric- York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
tion Model.” Monetary and Economic Stud- Modigliani, Franco, and Richard Brumberg.
ies, 21(2): 31– 68. 1954. “Utility Analysis and the Consumption
Kuroda, Sachiko, and Isamu Yamamoto. 2003c. Function: An Interpretation of Cross-Section
“The Impact of Downward Nominal Wage Data.” In Post-Keynesian Economics, ed.
Rigidity on the Unemployment Rate: Quan- Kenneth K. Kurihara, 388 – 436. New Bruns-
titative Evidence from Japan.” Monetary and wick: Rutgers University Press.
Economic Studies, 21(4): 57– 85. Modigliani, Franco, and Merton H. Miller. 1958.
Laibson, David I. 1997. “Golden Eggs and Hy- “The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance
perbolic Discounting.” Quarterly Journal of and the Theory of Investment.” American
Economics, 112(2): 443–77. Economic Review, 48(3): 261–97.
Laitner, John. 2002. “Wealth Inequality and Al- Myers, Stewart C., and Nicholas S. Majluf. 1984.
truistic Bequests.” American Economic Review “Corporate Financing and Investment Deci-
(Papers and Proceedings), 92(2): 270 –73. sions When Firms Have Information That
VOL. 97 NO. 1 AKERLOF: THE MISSING MOTIVATION IN MACROECONOMICS 35

Investors Do Not Have.” Journal of Finan- Adjustment and Aggregate Output.” Review
cial Economics, 13(2): 187–221. of Economic Studies, 49(4): 517–31.
Nakamura, Emi, and Jón Steinsson. 2005. “Price- Samuelson, Paul A. 1964. Economics: An Intro-
Setting in Forward Looking Customer Mar- ductory Analysis. 6th ed. New York, Auck-
kets.” Unpublished. land, London, and Montreal: McGraw-Hill.
Nickell, Stephen, and Glenda Quintini. 2001. Sargent, Thomas J. 1971. “A Note on the ‘Ac-
“Nominal Wage Rigidity and the Rate of celerationist’ Controversy.” Journal of Money,
Inflation.” London School of Economics Dis- Credit, and Banking, 3(3): 721–25.
cussion Paper CEPDP0489. Sargent, Thomas J. 1973. “Rational Expecta-
O’Brien, Anthony Patrick. 1989. “A Behavioral tions, the Real Rate of Interest, and the Nat-
Explanation for Nominal Wage Rigidity Dur- ural Rate of Unemployment.” Brookings
ing the Great Depression.” Quarterly Journal Papers on Economic Activity, 2: 429 –72.
of Economics, 104(4): 719 –35. Seater, John J. 1993. “Ricardian Equivalence.”
O’Driscoll, Gerald P., Jr. 1977. “The Ricardian Journal of Economic Literature, 31(1): 142–90.
Nonequivalence Theorem.” Journal of Polit- Shafir, Eldar, Peter Diamond, and Amos Tversky.
ical Economy, 85(1): 207–10. 1997. “Money Illusion.” Quarterly Journal
Okun, Arthur. 1978. Prices and Quantities: A of Economics, 112(2): 341–74.
Macroeconomic Analysis. Washington, DC: Shea, John. 1995. “Union Contracts and the
Brookings Institution Press. Life-Cycle/Permanent-Income Hypothesis.”
Pareto, Vilfredo. 1980. Compendium of General American Economic Review, 85(1): 186 –200.
Sociology. Abridged in Italian by Giulio Fa- Shefrin, Hersh M., and Meir Statman. 1984. “Ex-
rina from Trattato di Sociologia Generale. plaining Investor Preference for Cash Divi-
Translated by Elisabeth Abbott. Minneapolis: dends.” Journal of Financial Economics,
University of Minnesota Press. 13(2): 253– 82.
Parker, Jonathan A. 1999. “The Reaction of Shefrin, Hersh M., and Richard H. Thaler. 1988.
Household Consumption to Predictable Changes “The Behavioral Life-Cycle Hypothesis.”
in Social Security Taxes.” American Economic Economic Inquiry, 26(4): 609 – 43.
Review, 89(4): 959 –73. Shiller, Robert J. 1997. “Why Do People Dislike
Phelps, Edmund S. 1968. “Money-Wage Dynam- Inflation?” In Reducing Inflation: Motivation
ics and Labor-Market Equilibrium.” Journal of and Strategy, ed. Christina D. Romer and
Political Economy, 76(4) Part 2: 678 –711. David H. Romer, 13– 65. Chicago and Lon-
Phillips, Alban W. 1958. “The Relation between don: University of Chicago Press.
Unemployment and the Rate of Change of Souleles, Nicholas S. 1999. “The Response of
Money Wage Rates in the United Kingdom, Household Consumption to Income Tax Re-
1861–1957.” Economica, 25(100): 283–99. funds.” American Economic Review, 89(4):
Ricciuti, Roberto. 2003. “Assessing Ricardian 947–58.
Equivalence.” Journal of Economic Surveys, Staiger, Douglas, James H. Stock, and Mark W.
17(1): 55–78. Watson. 1997. “How Precise Are Estimates
Rogoff, Kenneth. 1985. “The Optimal Degree of of the Natural Rate of Unemployment?” In
Commitment to an Intermediate Monetary Reducing Inflation: Motivation and Strategy,
Target.” Quarterly Journal of Economics, ed. Christina D. Romer and David H. Romer,
100(4): 1169 – 89. 195–242. Chicago and London: University of
Romer, Christina D., and David H. Romer. 1989. Chicago Press.
“Does Monetary Policy Matter? A New Test Stein, Jeremy C. 2003. “Agency, Information
in the Spirit of Friedman and Schwartz.” In and Corporate Investment.” In Handbook of
NBER Macroeconomics Annual 1989, ed. the Economics of Finance, ed. George M.
Olivier J. Blanchard and Stanley Fischer, Constantinides, Milton Harris and Rene M.
121–70. Cambridge, MA, and London: MIT Stulz, 111– 65. Amsterdam, London, and
Press. New York: Elsevier, North-Holland.
Romer, David H. 2001. Advanced Macroeco- Stock, James H., and Mark W. Watson. 2003. “Has
nomics. New York, Auckland, London, and the Business Cycle Changed? Evidence and
Montreal: McGraw-Hill. Explanations” In Proceedings of a Symposium
Rotemberg, Julio J. 1982. “Monopolistic Price on Monetary Policy and Uncertainty: Adapting
36 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

to a Changing Economy, 9 –56. Kansas City: Personal Account of the Discovery of the
Federal Reserve Bank of Kansas City. Structure of DNA. New York: New American
Stone, Lawrence. 1977. The Family, Sex and Library.
Marriage in England, 1500 –1800. New Weber, Max. 1958. The Protestant Ethic and the
York: Harper and Row. Spirit of Capitalism. New York: Charles
Summers, Lawrence H. 1981. “Taxation and Cor- Scribner’s.
porate Investment: A q-Theory Approach.” Wilcox, David W. 1989. “Social Security Bene-
Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1: fits, Consumption Expenditure, and the Life
67–127. Cycle Hypothesis.” Journal of Political
Summers, Lawrence H. 1986. “Does the Stock Economy, 97(2): 288 –304.
Market Rationally Reflect Fundamental Val- Wilhelm, Mark O. 1996. “Bequest Behavior and
ues?” Journal of Finance (Papers and Pro- the Effect of Heirs’ Earnings: Testing the
ceedings of the Forty-Fourth Annual Meeting Altruistic Model of Bequests.” American
of the American Finance Association), 41(3): Economic Review, 86(4): 874 –92.
591– 601. Woodward, Ian. 2003. “Divergent Narratives in
Terkel, Studs. 1972. Working: People Talk About the Imagining of the Home amongst Middle-
What They Do All Day and How They Feel Class Consumers: Aesthetics, Comfort, and
About What They Do. New York: Pantheon. the Symbolic Boundaries of Self and Home.”
Tobin, James. 1969. “A General Equilibrium Journal of Sociology, 39(4): 391– 412.
Approach to Monetary Theory.” Journal of Yellen, Janet L., and George A. Akerlof. 2006.
Money, Credit, and Banking, 1(1): 15–29. “Stabilization Policy: A Reconsideration.”
Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1981. Economic Inquiry, 44(1): 1–22.
“The Framing of Decisions and the Psychol- Zorn, Dirk M. 2004. “Here a Chief, There a
ogy of Choice.” Science, 211(4481): 453–58. Chief: The Rise of the CFO.” American So-
Watson, James D. 1969. The Double Helix: A ciological Review, 69(3): 345– 64.
This article has been cited by:

1. Roger Frantz. The “Big 3.” Simon, Katona, Leibenstein 25-45. [Crossref]
2. . References 207-231. [Crossref]
3. Susanna Grundmann, Marcus Giamattei, Johann Graf Lambsdorff. 2019. Intentions rather than
money illusion – Why nominal changes induce real effects. European Economic Review 119, 166-178.
[Crossref]
4. Galanou N. Aikaterini, Sotiropoulos Ioannis, Tryfon Vasilagos. 2019. Do external environmental
factors affect on strategic choice decisions of innovation?: The case of service organizations in a cross-
cultural comparison. Journal of Transnational Management 24:3, 185-230. [Crossref]
5. Ziqi Gao, Leye Li, Louise Yi Lu. 2019. Social Capital and Managers’ Use of Corporate Resources.
Journal of Business Ethics 27. . [Crossref]
6. Jawad M Addoum, Stefanos Delikouras, George M Korniotis. 2019. Consumption-Income Sensitivity
and Portfolio Choice. The Review of Asset Pricing Studies 9:1, 91-136. [Crossref]
7. Zagdbazar Davaadorj. 2019. Does social capital affect dividend policy?. Journal of Behavioral and
Experimental Finance 22, 116-128. [Crossref]
8. Alan Fenna, Paul ‘t Hart. The 53-billion-dollar question: Was Australia’s 2009–2010 fiscal stimulus
a good thing? 87-112. [Crossref]
9. Milan Zafirovski. 2019. Always Rational Choice Theory? Lessons from Conventional Economics and
Their Relevance and Potential Benefits for Contemporary Sociologists. The American Sociologist 18. .
[Crossref]
10. Giovanni Dosi, Andrea Roventini. 2019. More is different ... and complex! the case for agent-based
macroeconomics. Journal of Evolutionary Economics 29:1, 1-37. [Crossref]
11. Anand Jha. 2019. Financial Reports and Social Capital. Journal of Business Ethics 155:2, 567-596.
[Crossref]
12. Milan Zafirovski. 2019. A neglected gap in the Weber thesis? The long economic lag of capitalism
from Protestantism. Social Science Information 58:1, 3-56. [Crossref]
13. Ning Gong, Bruce D Grundy. 2019. Can Socially Responsible Firms Survive Competition? An
Analysis of Corporate Employee Matching Grant Schemes*. Review of Finance 23:1, 199-243.
[Crossref]
14. Giovanni Dosi, Andrea Roventini. 2019. More Is Different … and Complex!: The Case for Agent-
Based Macroeconomics. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
15. Abiola John Asaleye, Olabisi Popoola, Adedoyin Isola Lawal, Adeyemi Ogundipe, Omotola Ezenwoke.
2018. The credit channels of monetary policy transmission: implications on output and employment
in Nigeria. Banks and Bank Systems 13:4, 103-118. [Crossref]
16. Milan Zafirovski. 2018. Calvinist Predestination and the Spirit of Capitalism: The Religious
Argument of the Weber Thesis Reexamined. Human Studies 41:4, 565-602. [Crossref]
17. Salman Ahmed Shaikh, Mohd Adib Ismail, Abdul Ghafar Ismail, Shahida Shahimi, Muhammad
Hakimi Mohd Shafiai. 2018. Intertemporal consumption behaviour in OIC countries. International
Journal of Islamic and Middle Eastern Finance and Management 11:4, 529-552. [Crossref]
18. Bruno Contini, Toralf Pusch. 2018. Identifying bounded rationality with panel data: evidence from
the labor markets of Italy and Germany. Mind & Society 17:1-2, 71-84. [Crossref]
19. Jeroen C. J. M. van den Bergh. Human Evolution beyond Biology and Culture 1, . [Crossref]
20. Dieter Bögenhold. 2018. Economics between Insulation and Social-Scienciation: Observations by a
Sociology of Economics. Journal of Economic Issues 52:4, 1125-1142. [Crossref]
21. Milan Zafirovski. 2018. Exploitation in contemporary societies: An exploratory comparative analysis.
The Social Science Journal . [Crossref]
22. Zenu Sharma, Liang Song. 2018. Corporate social responsibility (CSR) practices by SIN firms. Asian
Review of Accounting 26:3, 359-372. [Crossref]
23. Milan Zafirovski. 2018. The Generalized Low-Quality Syndrome. Comparative Sociology 17:5,
557-611. [Crossref]
24. Ferruccio Ponzano, Roberto Ricciuti. 2018. Growth and Inequality in an Experimental AK Model.
Italian Economic Journal 4:2, 313-330. [Crossref]
25. Ernst Fehr, Ivo Schurtenberger. 2018. Normative foundations of human cooperation. Nature Human
Behaviour 2:7, 458-468. [Crossref]
26. Peter Flaschel, Matthieu Charpe, Giorgos Galanis, Christian R. Proaño, Roberto Veneziani. 2018.
Macroeconomic and stock market interactions with endogenous aggregate sentiment dynamics.
Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control 91, 237-256. [Crossref]
27. Milan Zafirovski. 2018. Rational Choice Theory or Pretense? The Claims, Equivalences, and
Analogies of the “Economic Approach to Human Behavior”. Sociological Spectrum 38:3, 194-222.
[Crossref]
28. Milan Zafirovski. 2018. Economics as a Multi-Paradigmatic Science: the ‘Best Kept Secret’ of Irrational
Choice. The American Sociologist 49:1, 37-63. [Crossref]
29. Christopher Long, Bradford F. Mills, Joachim Schleich. 2018. Characteristics or culture?
Determinants of household energy use behavior in Germany and the USA. Energy Efficiency 11:3,
777-798. [Crossref]
30. Dieter Bögenhold. Bounded Rationality and Emotions and How Sociology May Take Profit: Towards
an Interdisciplinary Opening 105-120. [Crossref]
31. Douglas Kriner, Breanna Lechase, Rosella Cappella Zielinski. 2018. Self-interest, partisanship, and
the conditional influence of taxation on support for war in the USA. Conflict Management and Peace
Science 35:1, 43-64. [Crossref]
32. Richard Bookstaber, Alan Kirman. Modeling a Heterogeneous World 769-795. [Crossref]
33. Dieter Bögenhold, Farah Naz. Culture, Advertising and Consumption 53-74. [Crossref]
34. Camille Cornand, Frank Heinemann. 2018. Experiments on Macroeconomics: Methods and
Applications. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
35. Ronald Schettkat. 2018. Revision or Revolution? A Note on Behavioral vs. Neoclassical Economics.
SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
36. Gonzalo Castañeda Ramos, Omar A Guerrero. 2018. Evaluating Policy Priorities under Social
Learning and Endogenous Government Behavior. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
37. Yasuo Ohe. 2018. Educational tourism in agriculture and identity of farm successors. Tourism
Economics 24:2, 167. [Crossref]
38. Saibal Ghosh. 2017. Banking and credit extension: does religious diversity matter?. International
Journal of Social Economics 44:12, 2287-2301. [Crossref]
39. Margaret Schabas. Thought Experiments in Economics 171-182. [Crossref]
40. Christian Pfeifer, Anja Köbrich León. 2017. Religious activity, risk-taking preferences and financial
behaviour: Empirical evidence from German survey data. Journal of Behavioral and Experimental
Economics . [Crossref]
41. Robert J. Shiller. 2017. Narrative Economics. American Economic Review 107:4, 967-1004. [Abstract]
[View PDF article] [PDF with links]
42. Terry Barker. The Economics of Avoiding Dangerous Climate Change 237-263. [Crossref]
43. Milan Zafirovski. 1. [Crossref]
44. Robert J. Shiller. 2017. Narrative Economics. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
45. Masao Ogaki, Saori C. Tanaka. Normative Behavioral Economics 185-207. [Crossref]
46. Demetris Koursaros. 2016. Labor market dynamics when (un)employment is a social norm. Journal
of Economic Behavior & Organization . [Crossref]
47. Milan Zafirovski. 2016. Rational Choice Theory at the Origin? Forms and Social Factors of “Irrational
Choice”. Social Epistemology 30:5-6, 728-763. [Crossref]
48. Sophocles N. Brissimis, Petros M. Migiakis. 2016. Inflation persistence, learning dynamics and the
rationality of inflation expectations. Empirical Economics 51:3, 963-979. [Crossref]
49. James E. McNulty, Aigbe Akhigbe. 2016. What do a bank’s legal expenses reveal about its internal
controls and operational risk?. Journal of Financial Stability . [Crossref]
50. Michael W.M. Roos. 2016. Modeling Radical Uncertainty and Anticipating Uncertain Change with
Models. Forum for Social Economics 1-19. [Crossref]
51. Gianfranco Giulioni, Marcello Silvestri, Edgardo Bucciarelli. 2016. FIRMS’ FINANCE IN AN
EXPERIMENTALLY MICROFOUNDED AGENT-BASED MACROECONOMIC MODEL.
Metroeconomica . [Crossref]
52. Frederick F Wherry. 2016. Relational accounting: A cultural approach. American Journal of Cultural
Sociology 4:2, 131-156. [Crossref]
53. . Macroeconomic fluctuations 183-233. [Crossref]
54. Luigi Guiso, Helios Herrera, Massimo Morelli. 2016. Cultural Differences and Institutional
Integration. Journal of International Economics 99, S97-S113. [Crossref]
55. Zsoka Koczan. 2016. Does identity matter?. Migration Studies mnv021. [Crossref]
56. Milan Zafirovski. 2016. (Pre-)Capitalism and the “Spirit” of Protestantism—The Max Weber Reverse
Thesis of Economic Conditions of Calvinism. Social Epistemology 30:1, 89-129. [Crossref]
57. MILAN ZAFIROVSKI. 2016. THE WEBER THESIS OF CALVINISM AND CAPITALISM-
ITS VARIOUS VERSIONS AND THEIR “FATE” IN SOCIAL SCIENCE. Journal of the History
of the Behavioral Sciences 52:1, 41-58. [Crossref]
58. Shinji Teraji. Why Do People Obey Norms? 65-142. [Crossref]
59. Giorgio Fagiolo. 2016. Macroeconomic Policy in DSGE and Agent-Based Models Redux: New
Developments and Challenges Ahead. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
60. Gustav A. Horn. Mikroökonomische Fundierung: Andere Wege 25-54. [Crossref]
61. Michael Schuhen, Fabian Kunde. Informelles Lernen und ökonomische Bildung 455-466. [Crossref]
62. M. Fabricio Perez, Andriy Shkilko, Konstantin Sokolov. 2015. Factor models for binary financial data.
Journal of Banking & Finance 61, S177-S188. [Crossref]
63. Anand Jha, James Cox. 2015. Corporate social responsibility and social capital. Journal of Banking &
Finance 60, 252-270. [Crossref]
64. Milan Zafirovski. 2015. Toward Economic Sociology/Socio-Economics? Sociological Components in
Contemporary Economics and Implications for Sociology. The American Sociologist . [Crossref]
65. Neil Hart, Peter Kriesler. 2015. Post-Keynesian Economics: A User's Guide. Australian Economic
Review 48:3, 321-332. [Crossref]
66. Yasuo Ohe. Attitudes of Successors in Dairy Farms toward Educational Tourism in Japan 33-44.
[Crossref]
67. Anand Jha, Yu Chen. 2015. Audit Fees and Social Capital. The Accounting Review 90:2, 611-639.
[Crossref]
68. Wolfram Elsner, Torsten Heinrich, Henning Schwardt. The Size Dimension of Complex Economies
—Towards a Meso-Economics 419-447. [Crossref]
69. Michael W. M. Roos. 2015. Die Komplexitätsökonomik und ihre Implikationen für die
Wirtschaftspolitik. Perspektiven der Wirtschaftspolitik 16:4. . [Crossref]
70. . Preface: A Complexity Microeconomics, “Post-Crisis” ix-xxi. [Crossref]
71. Ronald G Bodkin, Kathleen M Day. 2015. The Financial Biography of an Economist: Income, Saving,
and Wealth (Mostly Pension Wealth). Eastern Economic Journal 41:4, 527-536. [Crossref]
72. Peter M Summers. 2015. What’s Right with Macroeconomics?. Eastern Economic Journal 41:4,
612-614. [Crossref]
73. Frank C. Englmann. 2015. Can Public Debt Be Sustainable? - A Contribution to the Theory of the
Sustainability of Public Debt. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
74. Neil Hart, Peter Kriesler. 2015. Post-Keynesian Economics A User's Guide. SSRN Electronic Journal
. [Crossref]
75. Marcos Fabricio Perez, Andriy Shkilko, Konstantin Sokolov. 2015. Factor Models for Binary Financial
Data. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
76. Jesse Aaron Zinn. 2015. Stagflation and the Rejection of Keynesian Economics: A Case of Naive
Falsification. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
77. Michael Schuhen, Fabian Kunde. Informelles Lernen und ökonomische Bildung 1-10. [Crossref]
78. Milan Zafirovski. 2014. Rational Choice Requiem: The Decline of an Economic Paradigm and its
Implications for Sociology. The American Sociologist 45:4, 432-452. [Crossref]
79. Milan Zafirovski. 2014. The protestant ethic and the spirit of democracy: what is the democratic
effect of Calvinism?. International Journal of Sociology and Social Policy 34:9/10, 634-653. [Crossref]
80. John C. Driscoll, Steinar Holden. 2014. Behavioral economics and macroeconomic models. Journal
of Macroeconomics 41, 133-147. [Crossref]
81. Christie A. Klimas. 2014. Environmental Reviews and Case Studies: Importance of Ecological
Economics in the Undergraduate Environmental Sciences and Sustainability Curricula. Environmental
Practice 16:3, 230-238. [Crossref]
82. Anita Kim. 2014. The Curious Case of Self-Interest: Inconsistent Effects and Ambivalence toward a
Widely Accepted Construct. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 44:1, 99-122. [Crossref]
83. Michael J. A. Wohl, Nyla R. Branscombe, Jamey J. Lister. 2014. When the Going Gets Tough. Social
Psychological and Personality Science 5:2, 211-217. [Crossref]
84. Milan Zafirovski. 2014. Sociological dimensions in classical/neoclassical economics: Conceptions of
social economics and economic sociology. Social Science Information 53:1, 76-118. [Crossref]
85. Carsten Herrmann-Pillath. 2014. Naturalizing Institutions: Evolutionary Principles and Application
on the Case of Money. Jahrbücher für Nationalökonomie und Statistik 234:2-3. . [Crossref]
86. Gennaro Zezza. Fiscal and Debt Policies for Sustainable US Growth 237-277. [Crossref]
87. Jawad M. Addoum, Stefanos Delikouras, George M. Korniotis. 2014. License to Spend:
Consumption-Income Sensitivity and Household Portfolio Choice. SSRN Electronic Journal .
[Crossref]
88. James E. McNulty, Aigbe Akhigbe. 2014. Bank Litigation, Bank Performance and Operational Risk:
Evidence from the Financial Crisis. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
89. Dieter Bögenhold. Soziologie des Wirtschaftlichen: Alte und neue Fragen 7-27. [Crossref]
90. Birger P. Priddat. Ludonarrative Dissonance: Economy as a Diversified Language Game Landscape
101-126. [Crossref]
91. Nico Stehr, Marian Thomas Adolf. Der Konsum der Verbraucher 55-70. [Crossref]
92. O. Chernyak, O. Komashko. 2014. THE SIMON KUZNETS'S INFLUENCE ON THE
DEVELOPMENT OF ECONOMETRICS AND ENVIRONMENTAL ECONOMICS. Bulletin of
Taras Shevchenko National University of Kyiv Economics I:160, 98-100. [Crossref]
93. Milan Zafirovski. The sociological core vs. the historical component of the weber thesis: Some deviant
cases revisited 75-128. [Crossref]
94. Irma Clots‐Figueras, Paolo Masella. 2013. Education, Language and Identity. The Economic Journal
123:570, F332-F357. [Crossref]
95. Milan Zafirovski. 2013. What is the Main Significance of Economic for Sociological Theory?. The
American Sociologist 44:2, 177-197. [Crossref]
96. Erin L. Krupka, Roberto A. Weber. 2013. IDENTIFYING SOCIAL NORMS USING
COORDINATION GAMES: WHY DOES DICTATOR GAME SHARING VARY?. Journal of the
European Economic Association 11:3, 495-524. [Crossref]
97. Dieter Bögenhold. 2013. Social Network Analysis and the Sociology of Economics: Filling a Blind
Spot with the Idea of Social Embeddedness. American Journal of Economics and Sociology 72:2, 293-318.
[Crossref]
98. Swee-Sum Lam, Weina Zhang, Reginald Reagan Chua Lee. 2013. The Norm Theory of Capital
Structure: International Evidence*. International Review of Finance 13:1, 111-135. [Crossref]
99. M. Zafirovski. 2013. Beneath rational choice: Elements of 'irrational choice theory'. Current Sociology
61:1, 3-21. [Crossref]
100. Wayne Parsons. 2012. Keynes and the utility of policy relevant knowledge. Critical Policy Studies 6:3,
223-242. [Crossref]
101. WEI-KANG WONG. 2012. CONSUMPTION RESPONSE TO GOVERNMENT TRANSFERS:
BEHAVIORAL MOTIVES REVEALED BY SAVERS AND SPENDERS. Contemporary Economic
Policy 30:4, 489-501. [Crossref]
102. M. ALI CHOUDHARY, THORLAKUR KARLSSON, GYLFI ZOEGA. 2012. Sticky Prices in
Customer Markets*. Economic Record 88:282, 372-390. [Crossref]
103. Louis-Philippe Rochon, Peter Docherty. 2012. Engagement with the Mainstream in the Future of
Post Keynesian Economics. Review of Political Economy 24:3, 503-518. [Crossref]
104. Wayne Eastman, Deirdre Collier. 2012. The Optimal Bargain between the Elite and the Majority:
Party and Managerial Ideologies as Devices to Control Politicians and Managers. Group Decision and
Negotiation 21:4, 475-494. [Crossref]
105. Nigel F. B. Allington, John S. L. McCombie, Maureen Pike. 2012. Lessons not learned: from the
collapse of Long-Term Capital Management to the subprime crisis. Journal of Post Keynesian Economics
34:4, 555-582. [Crossref]
106. Tracey Cronin, Stephen Reysen, Nyla R. Branscombe. 2012. Wal-Mart's Conscientious Objectors:
Perceived Illegitimacy, Moral Anger, and Retaliatory Consumer Behavior. Basic and Applied Social
Psychology 34:4, 322-335. [Crossref]
107. Timothy R. Wojan. 2012. Why People Cooperate: The Role of Social Motivations, by Tom R. Tyler.
Journal of Regional Science 52:2, 378-379. [Crossref]
108. Giorgio Fagiolo, Andrea Roventini. 2012. On the scientific status of economic policy: a tale of
alternative paradigms. The Knowledge Engineering Review 27:2, 163-185. [Crossref]
109. Piero Ferri. 2012. Income distribution and debts in a fragile economy: market processes and macro
constraints. Journal of Economic Interaction and Coordination . [Crossref]
110. Alessandro Tavoni, Maja Schlüter, Simon Levin. 2012. The survival of the conformist: Social pressure
and renewable resource management. Journal of Theoretical Biology 299, 152-161. [Crossref]
111. Bill Martin. A New Look at New Cambridge: Will the UK Private Expenditure Function Stand Up?
76-124. [Crossref]
112. Swee Sum Lam, Weina Zhang, Reginald Reagan Chua Lee. 2012. The Norm Theory of Capital
Structure: International Evidence. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
113. Giorgio Fagiolo, Andrea Roventini. 2012. Macroeconomic Policy in DSGE and Agent-Based Models.
SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
114. Bruno Pecchioli. 2012. Stock Splits on Paris Bourse: A Way to 'Divide and Conquer' - Managers’
Incentives and Investors’ Preferences. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
115. Kenneth R. Ahern. 2012. The Importance of Psychology in Economic Activity: Evidence from
Terrorist Attacks. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
116. Dushko Josheski, Marija Gogova. 2012. The Affects from the Financial Crisis Over the Agro Economy
in Developed and Developing Countries (with Review for Republic of Macedonia). SSRN Electronic
Journal . [Crossref]
117. Mark Setterfield, Shyam Gouri Suresh. 2012. Aggregate Structural Macroeconomic Modelling: A
Reconsideration and Defence. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
118. Steinar Holden. 2012. Implications of Insights from Behavioral Economics for Macroeconomic
Models. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
119. Emilio Barucci, Marco Tolotti. 2011. Identity, reputation and social interaction with an application
to sequential voting. Journal of Economic Interaction and Coordination . [Crossref]
120. Gavin Nicholson, Geoffrey Kiel, Scott Kiel-Chisholm. 2011. The Contribution of Social Norms to
the Global Financial Crisis: A Systemic Actor Focused Model and Proposal for Regulatory Change.
Corporate Governance: An International Review 19:5, 471-488. [Crossref]
121. José Antonio Rodríguez-López. 2011. Prices and Exchange Rates: A Theory of Disconnect. The
Review of Economic Studies 78:3, 1135-1177. [Crossref]
122. Engelbert Stockhammer, Simon Sturn. 2011. The impact of monetary policy on unemployment
hysteresis. Applied Economics 44:21, 2743-2756. [Crossref]
123. Pierpaolo Benigno,, Luca Antonio Ricci. 2011. The Inflation-Output Trade-Off with Downward
Wage Rigidities. American Economic Review 101:4, 1436-1466. [Abstract] [View PDF article] [PDF
with links]
124. Simon Wren-Lewis. 2011. Internal consistency, price rigidity and the microfoundations of
macroeconomics. Journal of Economic Methodology 18:2, 129-146. [Crossref]
125. Joachim Wagner. 2011. From Estimation Results to Stylized Facts Twelve Recommendations for
Empirical Research in International Activities of Heterogeneous Firms. De Economist . [Crossref]
126. C. Simon Fan, Oded Stark. 2011. A THEORY OF MIGRATION AS A RESPONSE TO
OCCUPATIONAL STIGMA*. International Economic Review 52:2, 549-571. [Crossref]
127. Neil Hart. 2011. Mainstream Macroeconomics: A ‘Keynesian’ Revival?. The Economic and Labour
Relations Review 22:1, 17-40. [Crossref]
128. Enzo Dia. 2011. Uncertainty, trust, and the regulation of the banking industry. International Review
of Economics . [Crossref]
129. Isabel Almudi, Julio Sánchez Chóliz. 2011. Sustainable use of renewable resources: an identity
approach. Journal of Bioeconomics . [Crossref]
130. . Referências 329-336. [Crossref]
131. Milan Zafirovski. The Enlightenment, Civil Society, and Economy 225-278. [Crossref]
132. Milan Zafirovski. Modern Democratic Society and the Enlightenment 19-66. [Crossref]
133. Carsten Herrmann-Pillath. 2011. Naturalizing Institutions: Evolutionary Principles and Application
on the Case of Money. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
134. Ning Gong, Bruce D. Grundy. 2011. Can Socially Responsible Firms Survive Competition? An
Analysis of Corporate Employee Matching Grants. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
135. Gennaro Zezza. Income Distribution and Borrowing: Growth and Financial Balances in the US
Economy 87-113. [Crossref]
136. JOHN GOWDY, CHARLES HALL, KENT KLITGAARD, LISI KRALL. 2010. What Every
Conservation Biologist Should Know about Economic Theory. Conservation Biology 24:6, 1440-1447.
[Crossref]
137. Shiping Tang. 2010. The Positional Market and Economic Growth. Journal of Economic Issues 44:4,
915-942. [Crossref]
138. Dieter Bögenhold. 2010. From Heterodoxy to Orthodoxy and Vice Versa: Economics and Social
Sciences in the Division of Academic Work. American Journal of Economics and Sociology 69:5,
1566-1590. [Crossref]
139. Toralf Pusch, Arne Heise. 2010. Central banks, trade unions, and reputation—is there room for an
expansionist maneuver in the European Union?. Journal of Post Keynesian Economics 33:1, 105-126.
[Crossref]
140. Alan Fenna. 2010. The Return of Keynesianism in Australia: The Rudd Government and the Lessons
of Recessions Past. Australian Journal of Political Science 45:3, 353-369. [Crossref]
141. Piero Ferri, Anna Maria Variato. 2010. Uncertainty and Learning in Stochastic Macro Models.
International Advances in Economic Research 16:3, 297-310. [Crossref]
142. Roberto Tamborini. 2010. MONETARY POLICY WITH INVESTMENT-SAVING
IMBALANCES. Metroeconomica 61:3, 473-509. [Crossref]
143. Piero Ferri, AnnaMaria Variato. 2010. Financial Fragility, the Minskian Triad, and Economic
Dynamics. International Journal of Political Economy 39:2, 70-82. [Crossref]
144. Karolina Safarzyńska, Jeroen C.J.M. van den Bergh. 2010. Evolving power and environmental policy:
Explaining institutional change with group selection. Ecological Economics 69:4, 743-752. [Crossref]
145. Mikko Manner, John Gowdy. 2010. The evolution of social and moral behavior: Evolutionary insights
for public policy☆. Ecological Economics 69:4, 753-761. [Crossref]
146. Timothy M. Waring. 2010. New evolutionary foundations: Theoretical requirements for a science of
sustainability. Ecological Economics 69:4, 718-730. [Crossref]
147. Frederic S. Mishkin. Will Monetary Policy Become More of a Science? 81-103. [Crossref]
148. Piero Ferri, Anna Maria Variato. Imperfect Competition, Learning and Fluctuations 215-228.
[Crossref]
149. Roberto Artoni, Alessandra Casarico. 2010. The Duties of the Sovereign: A Brief Guide to the
Literature. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
150. Georgios Chortareas. Macroeconomic Consensus and Political Economy Aspects of Monetary Policy
Design 75-90. [Crossref]
151. Wesley Pech, Marcelo Milan. 2009. Behavioral economics and the economics of Keynes. The Journal
of Socio-Economics 38:6, 891-902. [Crossref]
152. Till van Treeck. 2009. The political economy debate on 'financialization' - a macroeconomic
perspective. Review of International Political Economy 16:5, 907-944. [Crossref]
153. Marina E. Adshade. 2009. THE RICH ARE DIFFERENT FROM THE REST OF US. Review of
Income and Wealth 55:4, 959-967. [Crossref]
154. István Magas, Attila Török, Dóra Győrffy. 2009. Book Reviews. Acta Oeconomica 59:4, 471-489.
[Crossref]
155. David Letson, Carlos E. Laciana, Federico E. Bert, Elke U. Weber, Richard W. Katz, Xavier I.
Gonzalez, Guillermo P. Podestá. 2009. Value of perfect ENSO phase predictions for agriculture:
evaluating the impact of land tenure and decision objectives. Climatic Change 97:1-2, 145-170.
[Crossref]
156. Joachim Wagner. 2009. Exporte und Firmenerfolg: Welche Firmen profitieren wie vom
internationalen Handel?. AStA Wirtschafts- und Sozialstatistisches Archiv 3:2, 109-122. [Crossref]
157. Boris Maciejovsky, David V. Budescu, Dan Ariely. 2009. Research Note —The Researcher as a
Consumer of Scientific Publications: How Do Name-Ordering Conventions Affect Inferences About
Contribution Credits?. Marketing Science 28:3, 589-598. [Crossref]
158. BRUCE IAN CARLIN, SIMON GERVAIS. 2009. Work Ethic, Employment Contracts, and Firm
Value. The Journal of Finance 64:2, 785-821. [Crossref]
159. Dominik H. Enste, Alexandra Haferkamp, Detlef Fetchenhauer. 2009. Unterschiede im Denken
zwischen Ökonomen und Laien - Erklärungsansätze zur Verbesserung der wirtschaftspolitischen
Beratung. Perspektiven der Wirtschaftspolitik 10:1, 60-78. [Crossref]
160. Kutsal Dogan, Ernan Haruvy, Sherry Xin Li. 2009. Group Identity in Markets. SSRN Electronic
Journal . [Crossref]
161. Alfonso Palacio-Vera. Money Wage Rigidity, Monopoly Power and Hysteresis 162-208. [Crossref]
162. Gennaro Zezza. 2009. Fiscal Policy and the Economics of Financial Balances. SSRN Electronic Journal
. [Crossref]
163. Oded Stark, C. Simon Fan. 2009. A Theory of Migration as a Response to Occupational Stigma.
SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
164. Carsten Herrmann-Pillath. 2009. Outline of a Darwinian Theory of Money. SSRN Electronic Journal
. [Crossref]
165. Luca Antonio Ricci, Pierpaolo Benigno. 2009. The Inflation-Unemployment Trade-Off At Low
Inflation. IMF Working Papers 09:34, 1. [Crossref]
166. 2008. Book reviews. The European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 15:4, 695-719. [Crossref]
167. FRITZ HELMEDAG. 2008. INCOME EFFECTS OF INVESTMENTS AND WAGES WHEN
SAVING RATES DIFFER*. Manchester School 76:6, 708-719. [Crossref]
168. Ian M. McDonald. 2008. Behavioural Economics. Australian Economic Review 41:2, 222-228.
[Crossref]
169. Roberto Tamborini. 2008. Monetary Policy with Investment-Saving Imbalances. SSRN Electronic
Journal . [Crossref]
170. Wayne Eastman, Deirdre Collier. 2008. The Bargain between the Elite and the Majority to Control
Politicians and Managers: Party and Managerial Ideologies as Devices to Align Agents. SSRN
Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
171. Carsten Herrmann-Pillath. 2008. The Naturalistic Turn in Economics: Implications for the Theory
of Finance. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
172. Jean-Pierre Danthine, André Kurmann. 2007. The Macroeconomic Consequences of Reciprocity in
Labor Relations. Scandinavian Journal of Economics 109:4, 857-881. [Crossref]
173. An-Chi Tung, Henry Wan. 2007. CO-EVOLUTION OF THE ELECTRONICS INDUSTRY:
POLICY INTERACTIONS ACROSS THE PACIFIC. Pacific Economic Review 12:4, 445-465.
[Crossref]
174. Wing Thye Woo. 2007. Dealing sensibly with the threat of disruption in trade with China: the
analytics of increased economic interdependence and accelerated technological innovation. Economic
Change and Restructuring 40:1-2, 1-26. [Crossref]
175. Carsten Herrmann-Pillath. 2007. The Naturalistic Turn in Economics. SSRN Electronic Journal .
[Crossref]
176. David M. Arseneau, Sanjay K. Chugh. 2007. Bargaining, Fairness, and Price Rigidity in a DSGE
Environment. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
177. William Charles Weld, Shlomo Benartzi, Roni Michaely, Richard H. Thaler. 2007. The Nominal
Price Puzzle. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
178. Bruce I. Carlin, Simon Gervais. 2007. Work Ethic, Employment Contracts, and Firm Value. SSRN
Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
179. Henry Y. Wan, An-Chi Tung. 2007. The Co-Evolution of the Electronics Industry: Policy
Interactions Across the Pacific. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
180. Voxi Heinrich S. Amavilah. 2007. The Effects of Technology-as-Knowledge on the Economic
Performance of Developing Countries: An Econometric Analysis using Annual Publications Data for
Botswana, Namibia, and South Africa, 1976-2004. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
181. Jean-Pierre Danthine, André Kurmann. 2007. The Business Cycle Implications of Reciprocity in
Labor Relations. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]
182. Carsten Herrmann-Pillath. 2007. Neuroeconomics, Naturalism, and Language. SSRN Electronic
Journal . [Crossref]
183. Wing Thye Woo, Geng Xiao. 2007. Facing Protectionism Generated by Trade Disputes: China's
Post-WTO Blues. SSRN Electronic Journal . [Crossref]

You might also like