What Are Human Rights

You might also like

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 3

What are human rights?

Patrick Maclem, December 10th, 2015.


Disponible en https://blog.oup.com/2015/12/what-are-human-rights-moral-political-legal-theory/

On this anniversary of the adoption of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, it is worth reflecting
on the nature of human rights and what functions they perform in moral, political and legal discourse
and practice.

For moral theorists, the dominant approach to the normative foundations of international human
rights conceives of human rights as moral entitlements that all human beings possess by virtue of our
common humanity. What constitutes a human right, according to this approach, isn’t determined by a
positive legal instrument or institution. Human rights are prior to and independent of positive
international human rights law. Just because a legal order declares something to be a human right
doesn’t make it so. Conversely, the fact that a human right doesn’t receive international legal
protection doesn’t mean that it isn’t a human right. The existence or non-existence of a human right
rests on abstract features of what it means to be human and the obligations to which these features
give rise. The mission of the field is to secure international legal protection of universal features of
what it means to be a human being.

On moral accounts such as these, human rights protect essential characteristics or features that all of
us share despite the innumerable historical, geographical, cultural, communal, and other contingencies
that shape our lives and our relations with others in unique ways. They give rise to specifiable duties
that we all owe each other in ethical recognition of what it means to be human. Rights and obligations
can also arise from the bonds of history, community, religion, culture, or nation. But if such rights
relate simply to contingent features of human existence, they don’t constitute human rights and don’t
merit a place on the international legal register. And if we owe each other duties for reasons other
than our common humanity – say, because of friendship, kinship, or citizenship – then these duties
don’t correspond to human rights and shouldn’t be identified as such by international legal
instruments.

In recent years, political theorists have generated a distinctive account of the nature and role of human
rights. Unlike most moral approaches, which focus on universal features of our common humanity,
political conceptions define the nature of human rights in terms of their discursive function in global
politics. Human rights, according to political conceptions, don’t necessarily correlate to the
requirements of moral theory. Global human rights practice, for several political theorists, is a social
practice whose participants invoke or rely on human rights as reasons for certain kinds of actions in
certain circumstances. They represent reasons that social, political, and legal actors rely on in
international arenas to advocate interfering in the internal affairs of a state and to provide assistance
to states to promote their protection. What this practice reveals is that human rights protect urgent
individual interests against certain predictable dangers associated with the exercise of sovereign
power. States have a primary obligation to protect urgent interests of individuals over whom they
exercise sovereign power, but external actors, such as other states and international institutions, have
secondary obligations to secure protection when a state fails to live up to its responsibility.
Legal theorists of human rights, in contrast, typically start from the premise that international law, not
moral theory or political practice, determines their existence. An international human right to food, for
example, exists because the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights enshrines
such a right. Its international legal status as a human right derives from the fact that international law,
according to the principle pacta sunt servanda, provides that a treaty in force between two or more
sovereign states is binding upon the parties to it and must be performed by them in good faith.
Similarly, the right to development is a human right in international law because the UN General
Assembly has declared its legal existence. The international legal validity of a norm – what makes it
part of international law – rests on a relatively straightforward exercise in legal positivism; a norm
possesses international legal validity if its enactment, promulgation, or specification is in accordance
with more general rules that international law lays down for the creation of specific legal rights and
obligations.

Determining the legal validity of an international human right is a relatively simple legal task. But legal
validity doesn’t determine the normative purpose of a human right, and legal conceptions of human
rights that seek to explain their purpose in terms that go beyond positivistic accounts of their legal
production threaten to reintroduce moral and political considerations into the picture, which
undermines the possibility that human rights can be understood in distinctly legal terms.

For example, human rights in international law are legal outcomes of deep political contestation over
the international legal validity of the exercise of certain forms of power. Such contestation doesn’t
cease upon the enactment of an international instrument that enshrines a human right in international
law. Contestation continues over its nature and scope in particular contexts as diverse as individual or
collective disputes requiring international legal resolution, opinions offered by international legal
actors on state compliance with treaty obligations, juridical determinations of the boundaries between
domestic and international legal spheres, and negotiations among state actors that yield binding or
non-binding articulations of international legal obligations. Once transformed from political claim into
legal right, and as subsequently as a result of interpretive acts that elaborate their nature and purpose,
human rights in turn empower new political projects based on the rules they establish to govern the
distribution and exercise of power. How to separate the legal dimensions of human rights from their
political origins and outcomes is a challenge to those who seek to ascribe legitimacy to human rights in
distinctively legal terms.

In my work, I seek to meet this challenge by defining the nature and purpose of human rights in terms
of their capacity to promote a just international legal order. On this account, the mission of
international human rights law is to mitigate the adverse effects of how international law deploys
sovereignty as a legal entitlement to structure global political and economic realities into an
international legal order. It contrasts this legal conception of international human rights with dominant
moral conceptions that treat human rights as protecting universal features of what it means to be a
human being. This account also takes issue with dominant political conceptions of international human
rights, which focus on the function or role that human rights play in global political discourse. It
demonstrates that human rights traditionally thought to lie at the margins of international human
rights law – minority rights, indigenous rights, the right of self-determination, social rights, labour
rights, and the right to development – are central to the normative architecture of the field.
Patrick Macklem is the William C. Graham Professor of Law at the University of Toronto and a Fellow
of the Royal Society of Canada. His most recent book, The Sovereignty of Human Rights, was published
by Oxford University Press in 2015.

You might also like