Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

Author's personal copy

Unconscious Cognition
J F Kihlstrom, University of California, Berkeley, CA, USA
ã 2009 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.

Glossary Inattentional blindness – Failure to


consciously perceive an object in the visual
Automaticity – The label given to cognitive
field because one’s attention is directed
and other mental operations that are
elsewhere. In various forms of ‘attentional
executed outside phenomenal awareness
blindness,’ such as repetition blindness, the
and voluntary control. Automatic processes
attentional blink, and change blindness,
contrast with controlled processes in terms of
the subject fails to perceive an object (or a
four canonical features: they are inevitably
change in an object) despite the fact that
evoked by the presence of a particular
attention is properly directed to the
stimulus; incorrigibly executed, in a ballistic
appropriate portion of the visual field.
fashion, once evoked; effortless, meaning
Learning – A relatively permanent change in
that they consume little or no cognitive
knowledge which occurs as a result of
capacity; and efficient, in that they create little
experience. ‘Explicit learning’ covers cases
or no interference with other cognitive
where the subject is consciously aware of this
activities.
new knowledge. ‘Implicit learning’ refers to
Conscious shyness – The resistance of
any effect of acquired knowledge affects
psychology and other cognitive sciences to
experience, thought, or action in the absence
making consciousness a focus of inquiry. As
of conscious awareness of what has been
described by Owen Flanagan, conscious
learned.
shyness has four facets: ‘positivistic reserve,’
Limen – In classical psychophysics, the
or a preference for publicly verifiable
‘threshold,’ or minimum amount of stimulus
behavioral data over introspective self-reports;
energy needed for an observer to
‘piecemeal approach,’ the assumption that an
consciously detect the presence of, or
understanding of consciousness will emerge
change in, a stimulus. In ‘subliminal
from more narrowly defined studies of
perception’ the stimulus is too weak to be
perception, memory, and the like; ‘conscious
consciously perceived, or has been
inessentialism,’ the view that consciousness is
degraded by virtue of brief presentation,
not necessary for certain cognitive functions,
a masking stimulus, or the deployment of
such as perceiving and remembering; and
attention elsewhere.
‘epiphenomenalism,’ the view that
consciousness plays no causal role in Memory – The mental representation of
mental life. some past event. ‘Explicit memory’ entails
Dissociation – An experimental outcome in conscious recollection of some past event, as
which one independent variable, such as in recall or recognition. ‘Implicit memory’
brain damage, has different (e.g., opposite) refers to any effect on experience, thought, or
effects on two or more dependent variables. action of a past event, in the absence of
Many studies of unconscious cognition conscious recollection of that event.
indicate that some variable (such as brain Perception – The mental representation of
damage or the direction of attention) an event in the current stimulus environment,
dissociates, or has different effects on, or that of the very recent past. ‘Explicit
explicit and implicit expressions of perception’ is indicated by the observer’s
perception, memory, and the like. conscious awareness of the size, shape,

411

Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421


Author's personal copy

412 Unconscious Cognition

distance, motion, and identity of some


Unconscious Cognition
stimulus. ‘Implicit perception’ refers to any
As psychology developed as an empirical science,
effect on experience, thought, or action of
theory and research focused on those mental
such an event, in the absence of conscious
states that were accessible to consciousness, as
perception of that event.
represented by classical psychophysics (with its
Preattentive processes – Perceptual and
interest in sensory thresholds), the structuralists’
cognitive operations that occur before
method of introspection, and William James’ clas-
attention has been paid to a stimulus.
sic essay, in the Principles of Psychology, on the
Priming – The facilitation (or impairment) of
stream of consciousness. Following the onslaught
processing of a stimulus (the target) by prior
of radical behaviorism, interest in consciousness
presentation of another stimulus (the prime).
declined precipitously in the years after World
In ‘repetition priming,’ the prime physically
War I. Woodworth’s work on the span of appre-
resembles the target; in ‘semantic priming,’
hension was an exception, and consciousness was
the prime and target are related in terms of
the subtext of the Gestalt approach to perception.
meaning.
But serious scientific interest in consciousness had
Process-dissociation procedure –
to await the cognitive revolution, with its interest
A method, invented by Jacoby, for
in attention, short-term memory, and mental imag-
quantifying the contributions of automatic
ery. The widespread current interest in conscious-
and controlled processes to task
ness is illustrated by the very existence of
performance by pitting the one against the
encyclopedias like the present one.
other. In the ‘Inclusion’ condition, automatic
Even in the nineteenth century, however, psy-
and controlled processes are allowed to work
chologists recognized that the mental structures
in the same direction; in the ‘Exclusion’
and processes underlying experience, thought,
condition, automatic processes are placed in
and action were not completely encompassed
opposition to controlled processes.
within the span of conscious awareness. Herbart’s
Thought – As a verb, thinking refers to
‘limen’ made room for Leibniz’s ‘petites perceptions,’
various cognitive operations, such as
and of course Helmholtz argued that conscious
reasoning, problem-solving, judgment, and
perception was based on unconscious inferences.
decision-making. As a noun, thought refers to
Perhaps the most forceful advocate of noncon-
any mental representation, such as the idea
scious mental life was William James, who (again
or an image of a thing, which is itself neither a
in the Principles) held that mental states could be
percept (a mental representation of a
unconscious in at least two different senses. First, a
stimulus in the current environment) nor a
mental event can be deliberately excluded from
memory (a mental representation of a past
attention or consciousness: ‘‘We can neglect to
stimulus).
attend to that which we nevertheless feel’’ (p. 201).
Unconscious inference – As described by
These unattended, unconscious thoughts and feel-
Helmholtz, the inferences or thought
ings are themselves mental states. Second, and
processes that, automatically and
more important, James drew on clinical observa-
unconsciously, generate conscious
tions of cases of hysteria and multiple personality
perception from stimulus information. For
to argue for a division of consciousness into pri-
example, perceivers unconsciously apply the
mary and secondary (and, for that matter, tertiary
size–distance rule to take information about
and more) consciousnesses (sic), only one of which
size into account when judging the distance
is accessible to phenomenal awareness at any point
of an object, and vice-versa, to create the
in time. To avoid possible oxymoron in the nega-
‘moon illusion’ and other perceptual effects.
tion of consciousness, James preferred to speak
of ‘co-conscious’ or ‘subconscious’ mental states,

Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421


Author's personal copy

Unconscious Cognition 413

rather than ‘unconscious’ ones. There, was, in fact, make it past the filter was not. This same atten-
considerable interest in unconscious mental life in tional filter was also the threshold which had to be
the early twentieth century – even setting aside the crossed for information to be represented in phe-
work of Sigmund Freud. But, as with conscious- nomenal awareness. The filter theories of attention,
ness, the entire topic was banished from serious in turn, raised questions about how permeable the
discourse by behaviorism. attentional filter was, and how much information
History repeated itself in the latter half of the processing could occur preattentively. Was preat-
twentieth century, as the ‘consciousness revolu- tentive – preconscious – processing limited to ele-
tion’ which followed on the cognitive revolution mentary physical features of the stimulus, or could
spun off an interest in unconscious mental life as it extend to the meaning of the stimulus as well?
well. This happened slowly. For a long time, if the In part to solve these problems, the notion of an
unconscious was discussed at all, it was construed attentional filter was replaced by the notion of
merely as a repository for unattended percepts attentional capacity. Capacity theories, such as
and forgotten memories. But in addition to this the one proposed by Kahneman in the early
wastebasket view of the unconscious, the classic 1970s, began with the assumption that human
multistore model of information processing made information-processing capacity is limited, and
room for the unconscious by identifying uncon- proposed that the ability to perform one or more
scious mental life with early, ‘preattentive’ mental task(s) depended both on the resources available
processes that occur prior to the formation of and the resources required by the task(s) them-
a mental representation of an event in primary selves. Whereas the filter models conceived of infor-
memory. However, by implicitly identifying con- mation processing as serial in nature, the capacity
sciousness with ‘higher’ mental processes, the models implied that several tasks could be carried
classic multistore model left little or no room out simultaneously, so long as their attentional
for a more interesting view of the ‘psychological requirements did not exceed available resources.
unconscious’ – complex mental structures and The capacity view, in turn, led in the mid-1970s
processes, and full-fledged mental states, that influ- to a distinction between two types of cognitive
ence experience, thought, and action, but which are processes, ‘controlled’ and ‘automatic.’ Controlled
nevertheless inaccessible to phenomenal awareness, processes are conscious, deliberate, and consume
insusceptible to voluntary control, or both. cognitive capacity – they are what most people
The rediscovery of the unconscious by modern mean by cognition. By contrast, automatic pro-
scientific psychology began with comparisons cesses are more involuntary. That is, they are
between automatic and effortful mental processes ‘inevitably evoked’ by the presentation of specific
and between explicit and implicit memory. Since stimulus inputs, regardless of any intention on the
then, it has continued with the extension of the part of the subject. And once evoked by an effective
explicit–implicit distinction into the domains of environmental stimulus, they are ‘incorrigibly exe-
perception, learning, and thought. Taken together, cuted,’ in a ballistic fashion. Automatic processes
this literature describes the ‘cognitive unconscious.’ are ‘effortless,’ in that they consume little or no
attentional capacity. And they are ‘efficient,’ in that
they do not interfere with other ongoing mental
Attention, Automaticity, and activities. Perhaps because they are fast, or perhaps
Unconscious Processing because they do not consume cognitive capacity,
automatic processes are unconscious in the strict
The earliest information-processing theories of sense that they are inaccessible to phenomenal
attention, such as those proposed in the 1950s by awareness under any circumstances, and can be
Broadbent and others, were based, to one degree or known only by inference.
another, on the metaphor of the filter. Information Automatic processes are exemplified by the
which made it past the filter was available for Stroop color-word task, in which subjects must
‘higher’ information-processing activities, such as name the color of ink in which words are printed:
semantic analysis, while information which did not Subjects show a great deal of interference when the

Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421


Author's personal copy

414 Unconscious Cognition

word names a color that is different from that in certain judgments made about it, or cannot control
which the word is printed. Apparently, subjects their response to it. The further possibility, that
simply cannot help reading the words. Helmholtz’s cognitive processes can operate on mental states –
unconscious inferences may be viewed, in retro- percepts, memories, and the like – that are not
spect, as an early foreshadowing of the concept themselves accessible to conscious awareness, was
of automaticity. More recently, linguists such as first raised in modern psychology by observations
Chomsky have argued that the universal grammar of priming in neurological patients with the ‘amne-
that underlies our ability to use language operates sic syndrome’ resulting from bilateral damage to
unconsciously and automatically. the medial temporal lobe, including the hippo-
Over subsequent decades, the concept of auto- campus. These patients could not remember
maticity has evolved further. For example, some words that they had just studied, but nevertheless
theorists proposed that automatic processes have showed normal levels of priming on tasks such as
properties other than the four canonical ones out- word-fragment completion and stem completion.
lined above. Others have suggested that the fea- On the basis of results such as these, Schacter
tures represent continuous dimensions, so that drew a distinction between explicit memory, which
processes can be more or less automatic in nature. involves the conscious recollection of some past
There has been some question as to whether all the event, and implicit memory, which is revealed by
canonical features must be present to identify a any change in task performance that is attributable
process as automatic: the four canonical features to that event. Explicit memory, in this view, is
might comprise a kind of prototype of automatic- identified with the typical sorts of memory tasks,
ity, rather than being singly necessary and jointly such as recall or recognition. Following Schacter,
sufficient to define a process as automatic. Even we may define implicit memory formally as the
the automaticity of the Stroop effect has been effect of a past event on the subject’s ongoing
cast into doubt. Challenges to capacity theory, experience, thought, and action, in the absence
from which the earliest ideas about automaticity of, or independent of, conscious recollection of
emerged, have led to alternative theoretical concep- that event. Implicit memory is, in these terms,
tualizations in terms of memory rather than atten- unconscious memory.
tion. Nevertheless, the concept of automaticity has Spared priming has also been observed in various
gained a firm foothold in the literature of cognitive other forms of amnesia, including the anterograde
psychology, and investigators have sought to develop and retrograde amnesia associated with electro-
methods, such as Jacoby’s ‘process-dissociation pro- convulsive therapy for depression; the anterograde
cedure,’ to distinguish between the automatic and amnesia produced by general anesthesia adminis-
controlled contributions to task performance. tered to surgical patients, as well as that associated
with conscious sedation in outpatient surgery;
memory disorders observed in dementia, including
Implicit Memory Alzheimer’s disease, as well as those encountered in
normal aging; hypnotic and posthypnotic amnesia
While automatic processes may be considered to following appropriate suggestions to hypnotizable
be unconscious, the mental contents on which subjects; and the ‘functional’ or ‘psychogenic’ amne-
they operate, and which they in turn generate, sias encountered in genuine cases of dissociative
are ordinarily thought to be available to conscious disorder, including dissociative amnesia, dissocia-
awareness – just as Helmholtz’s unconscious infer- tive fugue, and the interpersonality amnesia of dis-
ences took consciously accessible stimulus infor- sociative identity disorder (also known as multiple
mation and operated unconsciously to generate personality disorder). In each of these cases, the
the conscious perception of distance and size. memory disorder primarily impairs explicit mem-
Thus, we generally assume that people notice ory and spares implicit memory, which is either
and can describe the salient features of an object wholly or relatively intact. It is in this sense that
or event, even if they cannot articulate the way in implicit memory can be observed in the absence of
which those features have been integrated to form explicit memory.

Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421


Author's personal copy

Unconscious Cognition 415

However, implicit memory can be observed in brain-damaged patients, while single-systems the-
individuals with normal memory functions as well. ories have been developed in the context of data
For example, normal subjects show significant sav- collected from neurologically intact subjects.
ings in relearning for items that they can neither Activation theories seem to imply that priming
recall nor recognize. In principle, such phenomena cannot occur for novel materials, for which sub-
as proactive and retroactive inhibition might also jects have no pre-existing mental representations
be expressions of implicit memory, if the interfer- to activate. Priming can occur for novel materials,
ence occurred in the absence of conscious recol- in apparent contradiction to the activation view;
lection for the interfering list. For the most part, but priming is greatest for novel materials that are
however, documented dissociations between composed of familiar elements, lending support
explicit and implicit memory in individuals with to the activation view after all.
normal memory function take the form of experi- Despite this theoretical controversy, the essen-
mental dissociations, in which some variable is tial concept of implicit memory, including its dis-
shown to affect explicit but not implicit memory, sociation from explicit memory, is now widely
or vice-versa. For example, depth of processing has accepted within cognitive psychology. The theo-
a substantial effect on explicit memory, but rela- retical debate is likely to persist until investigators in
tively little impact on many priming effects. Even the field recognize that most subsequent research
when explicit memory is not impaired, implicit on implicit memory, whether in neurologically imp-
memory may be said to be independent of explicit aired patients or intact subjects, has been dominated
memory, in that priming does not depend on by studies of repetition priming effects of the sort
whether the prime is consciously remembered. observed in lexical decision, perceptual identifica-
The nature of implicit memory is the subject of tion, stem-completion, and fragment-completion
continuing theoretical controversy. The earliest tasks. However, there is more to priming than repe-
view was that priming reflected the activation, tition priming. Semantic and conceptual priming
through perception and attention, of stimulus- effects can also be observed in amnesia, as on free
relevant knowledge already stored in memory. association and category generation tasks. These
More recently, under the influence of the doctrine priming effects require some analysis of the meaning
of modularity in cognitive neuroscience, explicit and of the stimulus, going beyond mere physical struc-
implicit memory have been attributed to the opera- ture. Understanding the nature of implicit memory,
tion of separate and independent (thus dissociable) when it is spared and when it is impaired, and the
memory systems in the brain – or, alternatively, to relations between implicit and explicit memory,
brain systems dedicated to perception, action, and requires research on these other expressions of
conceptual analysis that have the capacity to learn. unconscious memory.
Other theories hold that explicit and implicit mem-
ory are the products of a single memory system, but
differ in terms of the processes that are deployed
at the time of encoding and retrieval. For example, Implicit Learning
many priming tasks are held to be perceptually
driven, while recall and recognition is concep- Closely related to implicit memory is the concept
tually driven. Alternatively, priming may occur of ‘implicit learning’ – a term introduced to psy-
automatically, while recall and recognition require chological discourse by Reber’s pioneering experi-
conscious effort in retrieval. Along these lines, some ments on artificial-grammar learning. In these
theorists have redefined implicit memory as invol- experiments, subjects first studied a set of letter
untary memory, thus making conscious control strings which had been generated by an artificial
rather than conscious awareness, the defining fea- grammar. Later, they were asked to examine a new
ture of the phenomenon. set of letter strings, and identify those that con-
The various theories have proved hard to test formed to the grammar. They were able to do so at
against each other. By and large, multiple-memory better than chance levels, suggesting that they had
systems theories have emerged from studies of induced the grammatical rule from the study set.

Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421


Author's personal copy

416 Unconscious Cognition

Nevertheless, Reber reported that the subjects learning reflects unconscious knowledge, just as
were not able to describe the grammar itself. implicit memory reflects unconscious memory.
In a paradigm somewhat similar to artificial Whether implicit learning can be dissociated
grammar learning, subjects have learned to iden- from explicit learning remains an open question.
tify instances of novel concepts, such as patterns of The fact that subjects cannot articulate the Markov
dots that vary around a prototype, without being process by which grammatical strings were gener-
able to describe the defining or characteristic fea- ated does not mean that they are unaware of what
tures of the concepts themselves. They can also they have learned. Above-chance classification per-
detect the covariation between two features, such formance could well result from partial knowledge
as hair length and personality, even though they which is consciously accessible. The same argument
cannot identify the basis for their predictions. holds true for other paradigms in which implicit
They can learn the sequence in which certain learning has been ostensibly demonstrated. The
stimuli will occur, without being able to specify best that can be said, for now, is that the subjects
the sequence itself. And they can learn to control in artificial grammar and sequence learning experi-
the output of a complex system by manipulating ments often experience themselves as behaving ran-
an input variable, without being able to specify the domly, without an awareness of what they are doing.
relationship between the two. In each case, subjects However, this assumption rests on relatively infor-
appear to have acquired new knowledge through mal evidence. The careful matching of explicit
experience – the very definition of learning – but and implicit tasks that is characteristic of studies
were apparently unable to gain conscious access to on implicit memory has not generally been imp-
this knowledge. Thus, it appears that explicit orted into the study of implicit learning. A major
learning can be dissociated from implicit learning. agenda item in the study of implicit learning is to
Following the model of implicit memory, imp- carry out more detailed analyses of subjects’ experi-
licit learning may be defined as a relatively per- ences in implicit learning situations, to make sure
manent change in knowledge, resulting from that they are really unconscious of what they evi-
experience, in the absence of conscious awareness dently know and put into action.
of what has been learned. Demonstrations that It is sometimes claimed that implicit learning is
amnesic patients retain the ability to learn, even more powerful than conscious knowledge acquisi-
though they do not remember the learning experi- tion – that, for example, subjects can learn more
ences themselves, have led some theorists to con- complicated things, and more quickly, implicitly
strue implicit learning as a variant on implicit than they can explicitly. There may be cases in
memory. However, there is an important distinc- which this is true – for example, the learning of
tion between the two concepts: implicit memory is one’s native language(s). But for the most part, such
a feature of episodic knowledge, in which subjects claims are rarely supported by adequately designed
lack conscious memory for a specific event in their experiments. Most studies of implicit memory
lives. By contrast, in implicit learning subjects lack are little more than demonstration experiments,
conscious access to certain pieces of semantic or showing that something can be learned without
procedural knowledge acquired through a learning any instruction or intention to do so, and with little
experience. Cases where subjects are aware of conscious representation of what has been learned.
knowledge acquired through a learning experi- But by and large, they lack the careful control
ence, but cannot consciously recollect the learning conditions that would enable the investigators
experience itself, are better classified as ‘source to pit conscious and unconscious learning against
amnesia,’ a variant on implicit memory. Implicit each other.
learning is also distinguished from merely ‘inciden-
tal’ learning, in which new knowledge is acquired in
the absence of instructions or intention to learn, Implicit Perception
but the subject retains conscious access to that
knowledge. Incidental learning is unintended, just Just as there are palpable effects on experience,
as involuntary memory is unintended; but implicit thought, and action of past events that cannot be

Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421


Author's personal copy

Unconscious Cognition 417

consciously remembered, there also appear to be observed in the ‘functional’ disorders of percep-
similar effects of events in the current stimulus tion, such as cases of ‘hysterical’ blindness and
environment, which cannot be consciously per- deafness (now relabeled ‘conversion disorder’), as
ceived. By analogy with memory, explicit percep- well as in normal subjects given hypnotic sugges-
tion may be identified with the subject’s conscious tions for blindness and deafness. Also in normals,
perception of some object in the current environ- implicit perception has also been observed in sub-
ment, or the environment of the very recent past, jects whose attention has been deflected from the
as reflected in his or her ability to report the stimulus, so that it is processed outside conscious
presence, location, form, identity, and/or activity awareness, as in parafoveal vision and dichotic
of that object. By the same token, implicit percep- listening. Priming has also been observed in nor-
tion entails any change in the person’s experience, mal failures of conscious perception such as ‘inat-
thought, or action which is attributable to such an tentional blindness,’ as well as some forms of
event, in the absence of (or independent of) con- ‘attentional’ blindness such as ‘repetition blind-
scious perception of that event. Implicit percep- ness,’ and the ‘attentional blink’ (conscious per-
tion is exemplified by what has been called ception also fails in the phenomenon of ‘change
‘subliminal’ perception, involving stimuli that are blindness,’ but to date there have been no demon-
in some sense too weak to cross the threshold strations of priming in this phenomenon).
(limen) of conscious perception. As with implicit learning, implicit perception
In the earliest demonstrations of subliminal effects are sometimes discussed under the rubric
perception, the stimuli in question were of very of implicit memory. Indeed, the prime in most
low intensity – ‘subliminal’ in the very strict sense implicit perception studies does occur in the
of the term. Later, stimuli of higher, supraliminal past, but it is the past of only a few moments ago,
levels of intensity were rendered ‘subliminal’ by with no intervening distraction – what James
virtue of extremely brief presentations, or by the called the ‘specious present,’ and well within the
addition of a ‘masking’ stimulus which for all span of primary memory. Implicit perception can
practical purposes rendered the stimuli invisible. be distinguished from implicit memory as follows:
Subliminal perception quickly entered everyday In implicit memory, the subject was perceptually
vocabulary, as in the controversy over subliminal aware of the event at the time it occurred; but the
advertising and the marketing of subliminal self- memory of that event has been lost to conscious
help tapes. Almost from the beginning of this line recollection. In implicit perception, the subjects
of research, a variety of methodological critiques were unaware of the event at the time it occurred;
sought to undercut claims for subliminal percep- conscious recollection may be vitiated by the fail-
tion. However, beginning with the now-classic ure of conscious perception, but it is the percep-
studies of Marcel, followed by the work Merikle, tion itself, not memory, that is unconscious.
Greenwald, and their associates, an increasing body Preserved priming in general anesthesia might be
of literature has demonstrated subliminal percep- construed as an instance of implicit memory,
tion, broadly defined, in a manner that convincingly because the test of memory occurs some time
addresses these criticisms. after the primes were presented; on the other
The adjective ‘implicit’ is preferable to ‘sublim- hand, because the patients were not aware of the
inal,’ because there are many cases of unconscious primes at the time they were presented, the same
perception in which the stimulus is not subliminal phenomenon should also count as an instance of
in the technical sense of the term. The most dra- implicit perception.
matic example is that of ‘blindsight’ in patients With subliminal and other forms of implicit
with lesions in striate cortex. Implicit perception perception now demonstrated to the methodolog-
can also be observed in the syndromes of visual ical satisfaction of (almost) everyone, most of the
neglect resulting from temporoparietal damage, remaining controversy concerns the extent of its
and in discriminative physiological responses to influence. Dramatic claims for the power of sub-
familiar and unfamiliar faces in cases of prosopag- liminal influence, popularized by Vance Packard’s
nosia. Priming and related effects have also been expose ‘The Hidden Persuaders’ and revived in

Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421


Author's personal copy

418 Unconscious Cognition

the American presidential election of 2000 by a distinction through learning. Similarly, Shames’
Republican television advertisement that appeared semantic priming effect resembles those observed
to present the word ‘rats’ subliminally when dis- in implicit perception and memory – except that
cussing the Democrats, appear to be grossly exag- the prime is neither a perceptual representation of
gerated. In the past, debate focused on whether a current stimulus nor a representation available
subliminal perception was limited to the analysis in memory of a stimulus presented in the past.
of the physical characteristics of the subliminal The subjects in these experiments appear to exp-
stimulus, as in repetition priming, or could extend erience a ‘feeling of knowing’ analogous to that
to meaning analyses, leading to semantic priming. observed in metamemory tasks. Their choices
The work of Marcel, Merikle, and Greenwald are clearly being guided by something that is nei-
come down squarely in favor of semantic priming, ther a percept (because the solution is not cur-
but even here subliminal perception appears to be rently being presented to them) nor a memory
analytically limited. (because the solution has not been presented in
the past). By analogy to implicit perception and
memory, we may define ‘implicit thought’ as a
Implicit Thought mental representation – an idea or an image, for
example – that influences ongoing experience,
Thinking and consciousness are so closely related thought, and action in the absence of conscious
that the notion of unconscious thought seems to be awareness of that representation.
a contradiction in terms – certainly James thought Implicit thought may underlie the intuition
so. In line with Helmholtz’s concept of uncon- stage of insight problem solving: the subject has
scious inferences, it is now generally accepted not yet consciously arrived at the solution, as a
that many of the thought processes that intervene conscious insight, but knows that a solution is
between perception and action are automatic, and possible, the solution itself is unconscious. In this
it is in this sense that we may say that at least some analysis, the incubation stage may be thought of as
thinking can occur outside of awareness. However, the process by which the transformation from
there is some evidence that thoughts themselves, unconscious influence to conscious access takes
and not just the process of generating them, can be place. Siegler and Stern may have observed this
unconscious. In one example, Bowers and his transformation in children who were learning to
associates found that subjects could distinguish solve a particular kind of problem, who showed by
between soluble and insoluble puzzles, without their reaction times that they had achieved an
knowing what the solution to the soluble puzzle insight into the solution of the problem, even
was. Subsequent research has showed priming though their verbal reports indicated that they
effects on lexical decision from the solutions to were not yet consciously aware of their insight.
word problems, even when subjects were unaware Although intuition is commonly viewed as a
of the solution itself. It has also been shown that source of error in human judgment, it may also
subjects can display changes in skin-conductance be an adaptive component of the creative process –
response when making objectively risky choices, gut feelings that motivate the problem-solver to
even when they cannot subjectively distinguish keep working. In fact, Dijksterhuis and his collea-
between those that are risky and those that are gues have argued that a reliance on intuition, or
safe – much as prosopagnosic patients show differ- unconscious thinking, may be especially valuable in
ential physiological responses to objectively famil- situations involving complex decision-making.
iar faces that they cannot recognize.
In some sense, the ability of Bowers’ subjects to
discriminate between soluble and insoluble puz- The Unconscious beyond Cognition
zles resembles the ability of Reber’s subjects to
discriminate between grammatical and ungram- Intentional mental states go beyond cognitive
matical letter strings – with the exception that states of perceiving, remembering, knowing, and
they have had no opportunity to acquire the believing: they also include affective states, such as

Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421


Author's personal copy

Unconscious Cognition 419

feelings of pleasure and pain, and motivational even though the subject has diverted attention
states, such as the desire to approach or avoid. If away from the problem he is trying to solve. Atten-
cognitive states can be unconscious, perhaps affec- tion, then, is neither necessary nor sufficient
tive and conative states can be unconscious as for consciousness.
well. Certainly, conscious feelings and desires can
be generated automatically, in response to the
appearance of effective stimuli in the environment. The Cognitive Unconscious and
In addition, conscious feelings and desires can Conscious Shyness
emerge as expressions of implicit perception,
memory, and thought – as in the subliminal mere The discovery of the unconscious is commonly
exposure effect, by which subjects come to prefer (and erroneously) attributed to Sigmund Freud,
stimuli to which they have been exposed, even if and there has been some tendency to claim that
they were not consciously aware of the exposures, the literature on the cognitive unconscious pro-
and cannot consciously remember them. Although vides support for the psychoanalytic conception
most authorities currently hold the view that of unconscious mental life. This is not the case:
unconscious feelings and desires are almost con- the unconscious percepts and memories revealed
tradictions in terms, the general acceptance of the by contemporary cognitive psychology bear no
cognitive unconscious suggests that we should resemblance to Freud’s primitive, infantile, sexual
be prepared to accept the existence of an affective and aggressive urges. Moreover, the distinction
unconscious, and of a conative unconscious, as between conscious and unconscious mental life
well. Evidence in this regard is just beginning to appears to be a matter of cognitive architecture,
trickle in, and at this point neither unconscious rather than of repression. Freud’s metapsychologi-
emotion nor unconscious motivation has been cal proposition that some aspects of mental life are
as well established as unconscious memory and unconscious is correct, but this is a proposition
perception. that is not unique to psychoanalytic theory. The
more specific propositions of psychoanalytic the-
ory, to the extent that they are testable at all, have
Attention and Consciousness all failed to find empirical support.
Revisited Still, just as Freud believed that unconscious
processes dominated mental life, so some psychol-
One implication of research on implicit percep- ogists and other cognitive scientists have taken
tion, memory, and thought is that consciousness evidence of unconscious perception, learning,
is not as closely tied to attention as the distinc- and memory as reason for thinking that conscious
tion between automatic and controlled processing mental activity plays little or no role in behavior.
implies. It may seem obvious that attention is the For example, some personality and social psychol-
means by which objects and events are brought ogists have shifted from ‘dual-process’ theories that
into consciousness, and that consciousness entails some processes in social cognition and behavior are
paying attention to such things. But in the case of consciously controlled, and others unconscious
implicit perception, subjects may pay close atten- and automatic, to a view that social cognition and
tion to the spatial location where a stimulus will behavior is dominated by unconscious, automatic
appear, without being aware of the stimulus itself. processes, to the virtual exclusion of conscious,
In implicit memory, subjects may have attended controlled ones. Some writers have gone so far as
to the study list at the time of learning, but fail to replace Freud’s view of the primacy of uncon-
to consciously recollect it later. In implicit learn- scious sexual and aggressive motives with the more
ing, subjects are attending to the manifest task modern concept of automaticity.
which has been set for them, while being unaware Actually, there is no evidence (such as might be
of knowledge they may have acquired in the provided by the process-dissociation procedure)
course of task performance. And in implicit supporting the proposition that automaticity dom-
thought, an insight may emerge into consciousness inates the conscious control of experience, thought,

Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421


Author's personal copy

420 Unconscious Cognition

and action. Accordingly, the popularity of the view At the psychological level of analysis, uncon-
that it does reflects a persisting ‘shyness’ about scious priming effects underscore the first-person
consciousness noted by the philosopher Owen nature of the intentionality that underlies con-
Flanagan. At the very least, evidence for automa- scious perception and memory. As James noted in
ticity, and for unconscious perception, learning, the Principles, every conscious percept, memory, or
and memory provide support for conscious ines- thought is part of a personal consciousness: ‘‘The
sentialism, which holds that consciousness is not universal conscious fact is not ‘feelings exist’ or
necessary for adaptive cognition and action to ‘thoughts exist’ but ‘I think’ and ‘I feel.’ ’’ Similarly,
occur. Conscious inessentialism, in turn, can lead when subjects complete tests of explicit perception
to epiphenomenalism, or the view that conscious- and memory, their answers are always couched in
ness has no causal function at all. But it should be the first person: I see, I hear, I recall, or I recognize
understood that the literature summarized here ‘X.’ By contrast, tests of implicit perception and
only reveals the reality of unconscious cognition. memory are conducted in the third person: sub-
It does not by any means negate consciousness. jects are asked to complete a word stem or frag-
ment, or identify a word, and by and large their
answers lack this element of self-reference: that
Neural and Psychological Correlates word is ‘X.’ Certainly, the subjects are conscious,
of Consciousness and conscious of what they are doing, but in gen-
eral implicit expressions of perception, memory,
The advent of brain-imaging research has added a learning, and thought lack the integration of the
new dimension to research on unconscious mental percept, memory, or thought with the self that
life, as researchers search for the neural correlates seems critical for conscious awareness.
of conscious and unconscious processing. It seems
clear, for example, that the striate cortex is required See also: Implicit Social Cognition; Unconscious Goals
for conscious vision, but not for the unconscious and Motivation.
vision revealed by blindsight. And the hippocam-
pus and other portions of the medial temporal lobe
appear to be necessary for conscious remembering,
but not for priming and other aspects of uncon- Suggested Readings
scious memory.
Bargh JA and Ferguson MJ (2000) Beyond behaviorism: On
More generally, comparisons of automatic ver- the automaticity of higher mental processes.
sus conscious processing, and of implicit versus Psychological Bulletin 126(6 special issue): 925–945.
explicit perception, learning, and memory, may Dehaene S, Changeux JP, Naccache L, Sackur J, and
Sergent C (2006) Conscious, preconscious, and
provide the comparison conditions necessary to subliminal processing: A testable taxonomy. Trends in
identify the neural correlates of consciousness – Cognitive Sciences 10(5): 204–211.
which is to say, not the neural correlates of Dijksterhuis A and Nordgren LF (2006) A theory of
conscious wakefulness (as opposed to general anes- unconscious thought. Perspectives on Psychological
Science 1(2): 95–109.
thesia or sleep), but rather the neural correlates of Ellenberger HF (1970) The Discovery of the Unconscious:
conscious acts of perception, learning, memory, The History and Evolution of Dynamic Psychiatry.
and thought. For example, automatic processing New York: Basic Books.
Kihlstrom JF, Barnhardt TM, and Tataryn DJ (1992) Implicit
appears to activate the sensory and motor repre- perception. In: Bornstein RF and Pittman TS (eds.)
sentation areas of the brain, such as the primary Perception without Awareness: Cognitive, Clinical, and
auditory cortex, while controlled processing is Social Perspectives, pp. 17–54. New York: The Guilford
Press.
associated with areas of association cortex. Simi- Kihlstrom JF, Mulvaney S, Tobias BA, and Tobis IP (2000)
larly, presentation of a masked visual stimulus The emotional unconscious. In: Eich E, Kihlstrom JF,
activates areas of the visual cortex (naturally), Bower GH, Forgas JP, and Niedenthal PM (eds.) Cognition
while processing of the same stimulus unmasked, and Emotion, pp. 30–86. New York: Oxford University
Press.
activates a wider network of brain areas including Kihlstrom JF, Shames VA, and Dorfman J (1996) Intimations
parietal and frontal regions. of memory and thought. In: Reder LM (ed.) Implicit

Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421


Author's personal copy

Unconscious Cognition 421

Memory and Metacognition, pp. 1–23. Mahwah, NJ: Personality: Theory and Research, 3rd edn. New York:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Guilford.
Koch C and Tsuchiya N (2007) Attention and consciousness: Stadler MA and Frensch PA (eds.) (1998) Handbook of
Two distinct brain processes. Trends in Cognitive Implicit Learning. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Sciences 11(1): 16–22. Underwood G (ed.) (1996) Implicit Cognition. Oxford: Oxford
Moors A and DeHouwer J (2006) Automaticity: A theoretical University Press.
and conceptual analysis. Psychological Bulletin 132(2): Weiskrantz L (1997) Consciousness Lost and Found:
297–326. A Neuropsychological Exploration. Oxford: Oxford
Schacter DL (1987) Implicit memory: History and current University Press.
status. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Westen D (1999) The scientific status of unconscious
Memory, and Cognition 13: 501–518. processes: Is Freud really dead? Journal of the
Schultheiss OC (2008) Implicit motives. In: John OP, American Psychoanalytic Association 47(4): 1061–1106.
Robins RW, and Pervin LA (eds.) Handbook of

Biographical Sketch

John F. Kihlstrom received his PhD in personality and experimental psychopathology from the University of Pennsylvania in 1975,
and is currently a professor in the Department of Psychology, University of California, Berkeley, where he also directs the
undergraduate program in cognitive science. Kihlstrom previously held faculty positions at Harvard, Wisconsin, Arizona, and Yale.
He is perhaps best known for his research on hypnosis, a field in which he has won many awards. His 1987 Science paper on
‘The cognitive unconscious’ is often credited with consolidating the emerging literature on unconscious mental life. He also
expanded the concept of implicit memory to perception, thinking, and emotion.

Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421


This article was originally published in the Encyclopedia of Consciousness
published by Elsevier, and the attached copy is provided by Elsevier for the
author's benefit and for the benefit of the author's institution, for non-
commercial research and educational use including without limitation use in
instruction at your institution, sending it to specific colleagues who you know,
and providing a copy to your institution’s administrator.

All other uses, reproduction and distribution, including without limitation


commercial reprints, selling or licensing copies or access, or posting on open
internet sites, your personal or institution’s website or repository, are
prohibited. For exceptions, permission may be sought for such use through
Elsevier's permissions site at:

http://www.elsevier.com/locate/permissionusematerial

Kihlstrom J F (2009), Unconscious Cognition. In: William P. Banks, (Editor),


Encyclopedia of Consciousness. volume 2, pp. 411-421. Oxford: Elsevier.

You might also like