Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 8

OMEGA The Int. JI of Mgmt Sci., Vol. It, No. 4, pp. 321-328, 1983 0305-0483/83 $3.00+0.

00
Printed in Great Britain. All rights reserved Copyright ~ 1983 Pergamon Press Ltd

Decision-making, Problem-solving and


Organizational Learning
DAVID DERY
Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Israel

(Received July 1982: m revised form December 1982)

Problem-solving behavior is normally depleted within a decision-making approach. The maze has been
advanced as a suitable abstract model for mo~t kinds of decision-making and pcoblem-solving activity.
Rather than relate to managers as decision-makers--as those who primarily explore mazes--my
proposal is to consider their role in maze-building. The paper discusses a number of deficiencies in
current decision-making concepts, primarily those that neglect to account for goal setting and
resetting. The paper then concludes with imp|icatioas for the notion of organizational learning.

INTRODUCTION I believe has been left out in the traditional


decision-making approach to problem-solving.
TRADITIONALLY, students of organizations The neglect of making an adequate dis-
have focused on decision-making behavior. tinction between a decision problem and a
Policy-makers and managers, in this view, are problem, between decision-making and prob-
primarily decision-makers and to the extent that lem-solving, seems to have emerged from the
one is interested in understanding or improving widely accepted view of organizational goals as
their behavior, one would normally concentrate pre-existent givens. The tendency in s y s t e m s
on decisional processes and the variables sur- analysis to believe in the objective existence of
rounding them. The realization that managers problems (and systems), has also supported the
engage in problem-solving as well has not inter- notion of pre-existent goals and values. This
fered with this approach to administrative be- notion, in turn, has influenced our conception of
havior, for 'problems' are not normally dis- problem-solving and learning behavior with the
tinguished from 'decision problems' (see effect that organizational goals are normally
[36, 39, 12, 25]). It takes a decision to solve a excluded from scrutiny and modification. In
problem and so problem-solving behavior is what follows I briefly present the view of man-
also treated within a decision-making frame- agers as maze-builders to prepare the ground for
work. the discussion of some central deficiencies in
The maze has long been advanced as a suit- current decision-making concepts. I then con-
able abstract model for most kinds of problem- clude with some implications for a theory of
solving activity. In problem-solving, as with organizational learning.
decision-making, individuals presumably en-
gage in selective trial and error search within the MAZES FROM WITHOUT AND
confinement of a maze--a set of paths, some WITHIN
subsets of which, the ~correct' paths, have re-
wards at their termini [29, 30]. But somebody Decision-making theories normally focus on
must have built the mazes that managers (qua how or why managers choose a certain course
decision-makers) are supposed to be exploring. of action, their primary concern is with ques-
'Building mazes', rather than running through tions of 'what to do'. Information support for
one, is employed here as a metaphor for what managers is hence exclusively 'decision-support'
321
322 Defy--Decision-making. Problem-solving and Organizational Learning

(see [18]); the value of information is (concep- straints and opportunities. Unlike a decision-
tually) measured along an index of decision maker for whom goals are pre-existent entities
relevance. But the pre-decisional phase of [22] a problem-solver is continuously engaged
defining or formulating a problem remains with goal setting and resetting. While decision-
largely outside the scope of decision-making makers search for the correct path in a complex
schemes and information support systems. maze [30], problem-solvers engage in maze-
Managers in a decision-making approach some- building. The failure to relate to managers and
how know what the problem is, what values to policy-makers as maze-builders has resulted in a
serve via solution and what requirements to number of deficiencies in current concep-
satisfy while solving that problem. A problem- tualizations of what it takes to solve a problem.
defining problem-solving view, on the other
hand, is primarily concerned with questions of
'what to want' (see [42]). Deciding what ought (1) Problems are not decision problems
to exist is deciding what is the problem that The view that problems do not come with
needs solving (see [3]). To better appreciate the identifying tags, that they require (explicit or
maze-building task one needs to relate to man- implicit) definition, has been traditionally left
agers from within the maze, to adopt a rat's out of most decision-making theories. The
view of its 'manager' rather than a psychol- decision-making literature displays great care-
ogist's view of his rat. lessness in its treatment of the notion of the
If we want to learn about problem-solving problem. One notable deficiency is the tendency
behavior in animals or humans, we pose a to equate problems with decision or choice
problem to our subjects and observe their be- problems, thus equating choice-making with
havior. We hang a bunch of bananas in a cage, solving, as if goals were given and alternatives
high enough so that our ape cannot reach it by were given. "Every tool of management decision
simply stretching its arms or by jumping up, but that is currently a part of management science,
not too high--outside the reach of our ape if it operation research or decision theory," writes
chooses to climb on the box we put in the cage's March, "assumes the prior existence of consis-
corner. We put a piece of cheese at one end of tent goals" [22, p. 572].
the maze and a starved rat at the other. In real Decision-makers, very much like our ape or
life problem-solving managers may aim at a rat, are believed to be facing pre-defined prob-
bunch of bananas--the 'ought to be' situation-- lems. If they know the consequences of alterna-
except that there is nobody around to put in a tive courses of action, they are said to be
box or a latch--the relevant tools or facts one engaged with decision-making under certainty.
may use to bridge the gap between 'what is' and If they do not know the consequences for sure,
'what ought to be'. In real life problem-solving only the probability of possible events that may
managers have to discern the relevant aspects of follow different actions, then they operate in a
reality. Nor are they then provided with the risk situation. And if they know the range of
objective. Bananas are hanging up there, along possible events but not their probability distri-
with other cherished values. They choose at bution, they are engaged in decision-making
what to aim and what values to maintain. under uncertainty. The only difference between
A problem-solving view of managerial behav- certainty, risk and uncertainty has to do with
ior recognizes that problems do not present the availability of information about the likely
themselves as such; that problems are not objec- consequences of alternative courses of action,
tive entities in their own right, that problems not the availability of alternatives or goals. It is
require formulation (see [l l, 33, 44]). A man- true that the choice among alternative courses
ager, in this view, does not normally face a of action ('selection') .is normally taken as
choice situation, but events that call for evalu- merely one phase in the decision-making pro-
ation and interpretation. Unlike an ape or rat in cess; one which is preceded by, for example,
the psychologist's laboratory, where the goal is 'recognition' and 'diagnosis' [28]. Yet, as Mintz-
externally decided and isolated and the means berg et al. contend, "researchers have paid
for achieving that goal are provided, managers almost no attention to diagnosis preferring in-
need themselves to decide on ends and means stead to focus on the selection routines" [28, p,
within a set of (what is interpreted as) con- 274].
Omega. Vol. I1. No. 4 323

The stages that are supposedly involved in obstacle rather than a primary requirement. In
decision-making processes have consistently Cooper et al.'s interpretation, the technology of
avoided the question of the nature of problems foolishness, unlike economic rationality or
that decision-makers aim at solving. Simon's bounded rationality models, relaxes the notion
'intelligence' phase, for example, is "'searching of problem-solving as the essence of decision-
the environment for conditions calling for deci- making [8, p. 177].
sions". His second phase--'design'--has to do Perhaps, being a victim of our culture, I am
with "'inventing, developing and analyzing not escaping the logic of my reason, as March
possible courses of action" [36, p. 2]. Janis would like us to do so that rational imperatives
and Mann's "step one' is 'challenge ap- towards consistency may be suspended [22, p.
praisal'--being exposed to information about a 578]. But it seems to me that neither have March
threat or opportunity that effectively challenges and his colleagues. A technology of foolishness,
a current course of action. Their "step two' is, if I understand correctly, is a rational proposi-
then, a survey of alternative means to deal with tion. It is not advanced as a goal in itself but as
the challenge [17, p. 172]. Anthony and Dear- a means toward better management, or more
den's conception of the control system identifies specifically toward goal discovery. Actions (the
three components: a 'sensor'--a measuring de- ingredients of 'foolishness'--rationalization,
vice which detects what is happening; a 'selec- imitation, inconsistency and playfulness in-
tor'--which assesses the desirability of sensed cluded) are rational not necessarily by virtue of
events; and an 'effector'--a device for altering serving pre-existent goals. Actions may be con-
behavior [4, pp. 3-4]. The common feature in sidered rational also if they serve other goals,
these three examples is the notion that decision- such as learning about new goals. March's
makers are expected to somehow know what question is not 'which foolish things we ought
sort of alternative courses of action to look for to do', but "which of the many foolish things
as soon as they sense an opportunity or that that we might do now will lead to attractive
something is wrong. Furthermore, since alterna- value consequences?" [22, p. 576]. It appears
tives exist only in relation to some specified that what is being replaced is not rationality but
goals, decision-makers are also expected to the goal to be served. Learning about new goals
know what goals to aim at. So interpreted, it and values is considered more important than
appears that as soon as something wrong is serving or learning to better serve old ones and
sensed the organizational eternal dictum is 'get the technology of foolishness is in turn consid-
rid of it!'. Or the organization is expected to have ered an appropriate means toward that end.
had developed an elaborate manual of goals to In other words, I take the technology of
account for all or most contingencies, rules and foolishness as a must, not as an escape from the
rules for breaking the rules. What remains for emphasis on problem-solving, but due to this
Administrative Man in this scheme is to look it emphasis, due to the need that is inherent in any
up and search for alternatives. problem-solving to examine and discover goals.
The 'garbage-can model of organizational No problem is solved, resolved or avoided
choice" [7], the 'technology of foolishness' (i.e. ('flight' or "oversight' in the 'garbage-can
rationalization, imitation, coercion, inconsis- model') unless certain goals are reached or
tency and playfulness) [22] and Weick's insis- maintained. If goals are not pre-existent entities,
tence that organizations are sense-making enti- then problem-solving is first and foremost about
ties [43] have challenged the notion of the discovering or constructing goals. The tradi-
pre-existence of goals, indeed the very notion of tional notion of decision-making portrays an
intelligent behavior and rationality. 'Goal- effort that begins when goal construction is
seeking behavior' is taken literally to denote over.
search for goals. " H u m a n choice behavior is at Effectiveness, efficiency, sufficiency, indeed
least as much a process for discovering goals as the common notion of rationality depict
for acting on them" [22, p. 573]. But then different types of relationships between means
rationality--"the procedure for deciding what is and ends. Ends and means are somehow given,
correct behavior by relating consequences sys- their nature if not their exact identity. The
tematically to objectives" [22, p. 572], t h a t introduction of retrospective sense-making, of
thinking should precede action--becomes an imitation, inconsistency and playfulness is
324 Dery--Decision-making, Problem-soh'mg and Organizational Learning

foreima to this notion of rationality but not to Organizational activities, it is commonly held,
rationality. The tendency in the 'technology of are first treated as non-programmed and, as
foolishness" to divorce itself from problem- experience or knowledge accumulate, or-
solving and rationality is perhaps under- ganizations develop routine procedures for
standable in the light of the "over-rationalistic' handling them. Management, unlike control, is
connotations that come with problem-solving, experimental. It aims at learning--acquiring
where problem-solving and learning are consid- that body of knowledge that will allow for
ered mutually exclusive [27], but not in the light (routine) control [20], The statistical type I error
of what it takes to actually solve a problem. is thus interpreted as the attempt to 'manage'
problems that should be 'controlled'. And type
(2) Structured decision problems are structured II errors stand for 'premature programming', or
because we choose to treat them as such the attempt to 'control' a problem that should
A second deficiency in current decision- be 'managed' [20, 16]. Again, whether a certain
making theories has to do with the notion of problem should be managed or controlled
ill-structured, or non-programmed decisions. would, in this view, depend on our knowledge.
The notion of "programmed decisions' as dis- This would seem true, however, only to the
tinguished from 'non-programmed' has become extent that we keep goals constant. The assump-
an integral part of our research, consulting and tion that knowledge is the only driving force
everyday managerial talk. Structured or pro- behind routinization, behind the transformation
grammed decision problems have definite pro- of the non-programmed into programmed, pre-
cedures for handling them, ill-structured do not sumes that goals, unlike technique, do not
[36, 28, 25]. That managers treat certain prob- change over time or by practice. For if we allow
lems by pre-developed procedures while for for goal transformation, e.g. if we become more
other problems they develop custom-tailored ambitious, it would make sense to de-routinize,
treatments is obvious. It is also obvious that, or to unlearn (see [14]). All problems of all types
given their limited resources and attention ca- and attributes are, or were, subject to definition
pacity, they should do so. There is no sense in (explicit or implicit). Thus reference to 'struc-
re-inventing the wheel time and again. But a tured decision problems' is a reference to situ-
wheel is a wheel. It can serve certain purposes, ations that have been encountered in the past in
but not others. A definite procedure to handle a manner that is then considered suitable for
a given class of problems is by definition a future treatment of similar situations, not a
closed set of ends and means. Alternative means reference to a situation that is objectively struc-
that are not embraced in a given definite pro- tured. It follows that 'ill-structured decision
cedure are excluded from consideration. Nor problems may well denote a situation which has
would additional or different ends be aimed at been encountered in the past and for which a
through definite procedures. What is less obvi- definite procedure has been developed; alas,
ous in the distinction between programmed and given the (new) goals we now want to pursue,
non-programmed decisions is that the choice that procedure is considered inadequate.
(many times arrived at through definite pro- Let me approach this point from a different
cedures) to handle a certain problem through perspective. If problems are not objective enti-
given standard operating procedures is inher- ties in their own right, then attributes or prop-
ently a choice of goals to aim at and a class of erties of problems cannot be said to have a
means to consider. Supposedly the notion of separate objective existence. Problems do not
ill-structuredness denotes those situations present themselves as structured or ill-
decision-makers face where problems do not structured, nor do they come as decision-
come pre-defined. But unfortunately the problems, complex or simple. Facts do not
dividing line between programmed and non- organize themselves just by being observed. The
programmed, well-structured and ill-structured situations which decision-makers attend to are
decisions has nothing to do with whether or not there, but 'the facts of the situation', that is the
goals are treated as given. Rather, this dis- relevant facts, do not present themselves as
tinction goes along the line of the relative such. To state the facts or describe the situation
newness of, or experience in treating, a given is to interpret not to copy it (see [13]). The
decision-problem, interpretation of a situation as a 'choice prob-
Omega, Vol. II, No. 4, 325

lem" must be preceded by a choice of goals to Opponents of comprehensiveness have


aim at, and that of alternative courses of action; mainly argued that such an approach is more
only then can the task be one of choosing the than our state of the art or mental capacity can
most attractive alternative. afford, that it burdens an already difficult task
of calculation, and that it is costly in both
(3) Comprehensiveness rests on value judgment monetary and political terms. Comprehen-
that contradicts the call for comprehensive inter- siveness, in other words, is not usually opposed
t'ention in principle, only as a practical guide for action.
This point leads me to a third deficiency in My argument, on the other hand, will be that
decision-making theories, essentially those ad- the holistic approach rests on a contradiction
vocating a holistic, comprehensive approach. between the notion of complexity, where the call
The tendency in systems analysis has been to for comprehensiveness originates, and the em-
believe in the reality of an objectively defined phasis on examination of goals.
problem (or system), as Eden and Sims put it, If problems are not objective entities, com-
which is assumed to be self-evident to all intel- plexity (as the adjective in "complex problems')
ligent people [11, p. 120]. An elephant is an cannot be said to exist "out there'. Complexity
elephant; only a blind man would confuse it is not a function of objective attributes of reality
with a wall, rope or hose (see [6]). "Simple, my but a product (if at all) of one's formulation of
dear", explains the instructor in a nicely put problems. More specifically, the degree of com-
Socratic dialogue on systems, "[by calling three plexity of a problem is primarily a function of
rocks on the ground a triangle] you are con- those goals we choose to pursue via solution (see
fusing a reality with a set of perceptions or [37, p. 16]). To the extent that our goals do not
mental structuring imposed on reality. The tri- conflict with other goals we may hold (and the
angle formed by the three rocks is a function of available means for pursuing these goals do not
your mental processes, not the rocks them- violate other values), then the problem at hand
s e l v e s . . . T h e truth is you created the can be said to be simple. If, on the other hand,
configuration in your mind. It is not a function the goals we choose to pursue do conflict with
of reality" [3t, p. 279]. He who sees the blind other goals (e.g. fight inflation and reduce un-
man touch the elephant sees the elephant. The employment) our problem may be considered
problem (or system) is there, the 'real' problem complex.
that is to say, and the systems analyst's task is The observation that "real-world problems
to uncover its 'true' nature, its 'true' inter- are inherently 'complex', 'wicked' or 'squishy'"
relatedness with other problems. "In dealing [26, 34, 38] does not simply denote 'the state of
with a problematic situation," writes Ackoff, "a the world' but expresses value judgment. It
decision maker must develop a concept--a rep- holds that the values one considers worth pur-
resentation or a model--of it. He attempts to suing conflict or are interdependent with other
solve the problem as he conceives it. Thus if his values that are also deemed worth pursuing or
conception is wrong, the solution to the prob- worth maintaining. Now, if we commence with
lem as conceived may not solve the problem as a clear vision of the values we ought to serve
it exists" ([1, p. 13] my italics). and maintain, what remains for exploration in
Systems analysis thus suggests that given the the realm of values? And if goal exploration
complexity of real life problems, the traditional aims at revealing those values that can actually
piecemeal approach need give way to a system be realized, what do we gain by revealing those
view of the world. The system's orientation, 'true' values which cannot be served unless
write Ackoff and Rivett, " . . . deliberately ex- other 'true' values are also served or main-
pands and complicates the statements and prob- tained; what do we gain by rendering problems
lems until all the significantly interacting com- unsolvable?
ponents are contained within it" [2, p. 10]. Goal That problems are inherently complex simply
exploration, the importance of choosing the means that values are treated as given. This
'right' objectives, has been stressed in most contention advances a Pareto--optimum view of
formulations of systems analysis [32, 35, 15] as the world where service to one set of cherished
an integral part of the systematic-comprehen- values (or one group of people) necessarily
sive approach. inflicts damage upon other cherished values (or
326 Dery--Decision-raaking. Problern-solring and Organi'_ational Learning

groups) and thus renders any intervention not whether that maze is worth exploring. And,
unjustified. As Marcuse points out, to the extent this is the crucial point, what is taken as Nven
that values are stated in absolute ethical terms, is, by definition, not subject to change. To learn
then "'there is no justification for any sup- about the adequacy of certain means we put
pression and sacrifice for the sake of future them to the experimental test only to learn that
freedom and happiness, revolutionary or other- these means are or are not adequate to achieve
wise" [24, p. 145]. In short, the view that 'the certain goals. But the adequacy of goals remains
solution to any real world problem has some- unchallenged (see [10]).
thing to do with the solution to other real world This bias in favor of improving means via
problems' stands in contradiction to the call for learning is also apparent in intervention strate-
examination of values and comprehensive inter- gies that focus on the individual member, sup-
vention. One cannot hold to certain goals and posedly the organizational learning agent.
values (and, given these values, argue that March and Olsen's learning cycle has in its
everything is related to everything else) and at center the individual--his beliefs that "produce'
the same time decline to take these goals actions and then are transformed by the en-
seriously as a guide for action. vironmental responses that are evoked by his
actions [23]. Argyris and Schon's model also
CONCLUSION: MAZE-BUILDING proposes that organizations learn through their
AND O R G A N I Z A T I O N A L members. They therefore call for educational
LEARNING intervention at the individual level [5], but or-
ganizational premises remain untouched. To the
Thus far I have attempted to show that goal extent that members' learning is bounded by
setting and resetting is an integral part of any organizational premises, presumably those
solving. But learning about new goals and val- premises that turn a mob into an organization
ues is not provided for in current conceptions of [9], premises are not subjected to learning and
organizational learning. When an organization modification. That goal accomplishment breeds
is said to be engaged in learning, we do not seem complacency and reinforces current behavior
to be occupied with what that organization is [14] should be taken as a warning sign whenever
supposed to be learning. To explain the appar- we call for more (means-oriented) learning.
ent contradiction between lack of improvement A closely related issue has to do with the
over time and survival (which presumably indi- notion of 'problems trigger learning' [14], If
cates the presence of learning) it has been problems are not objective entities but are the
suggested that organizations may 'learn to sur- product of interpretation, what may (or may
vive' (as the cybernetic paradigm would have it not) trigger learning has to do with inter-
[37]) but still may not 'learn', i.e. improve their pretation not events, circumstances or
practice over time [9]. Could it be that certain difficulties. Difficulties (that seem to be referred
intervention strategies to promote learning have to as problems) such as funds shortages, falling
certain types of learning in mind? What would revenues or diminishing popular support may
these types be? Could it be that by promoting mount, yet without necessarily triggering learn-
one type of learning we sacrifice other types? ing or unlearning. To the extent that an or-
These questions, I think, deserve serious con- ganization chooses, for example, to handle such
sideration. To show their importance I will draw difficulties by pre-developed definite procedures,
a few observations from our previous dis- no learning can be said to have taken place.
cussion. The promotion of experimentation as a Mounting difficulties may indicate the need for
means to improve learning appears self- learning. They may moreover provide an oppor-
evidently 'good'. The problem of organizational tunity to re-examine current policies. But
learning is often viewed in terms of the near whether learning may take place would be
impossibility of being truly experimental largely insensitive to the mere presence of un-
[14, 40]. What is overlooked in such conceptions desirable events. The fact that problem-ridden
is the fact that experimentation can at best organizations would not normally be considered
provide knowledge or new hypotheses with re- the best innovators may suggest that difficulties
gard to the relationship between means and are not the only triggers for learning [14, p. 17].
ends--how to run better through a given maze, More importantly, it may also suggest that the
Omega, Vol. 11, No. 4 327

obstacle to learning rests with inadequate in- 15. HITCH CJ (1960) On the choice of objectives in systems
terpretation of events or, with regard to goal studies. Rand Corporation, P-1955. Santa Monica,
California.
discovery, inadequate treatment of or- 16. Ho~'rEDE G ( 198 l ) Management control of public and
ganizational goals in problem-solving. not-for-profit activities. Account. Org. Soc. 6~3),
If we are willing to conceive of organizations 193-211.
17. JA~1SIL and MANN L (t977) Decision Making. The Free
as learning entities, then we have to accept that Press, New York.
these entities must have an epistemology of their 18. KEEN PGW and SCOTT-MoRTON MS (1978) Decision
own; a theory of knowledge that mediates be- Support Systems: an Organizational Perspective.
Addison-Wesley, Reading, Massachusetts.
tween the organization and the welter of experi- 19. LA,",~AU M (1973) On the concept of a self-correcting
ence. Organizations cannot capture the truth of organization. Publ. Admin. Rev. 33(6), 533-542.
experience, to use CI Lewis' metaphor [21, p. 20. LANDAU M and Srou-r R JR (1979) To manage is not
to control: or the folly of type II errors. Publ. Admin.
307], if they have no net to catch it in. "We must Rev. 39(2), 148-156.
first be in possession of criteria which tell us 21. LEWISCI (1956) Mindandthe WorMOrder. Dover, New
what experiences could answer what questions, York.
22. M~CH JG (1971) The technology of foolishness. Publ.
and how, before observation or experiment (1980) in Readings in Management Psychology (3rd edn)
could tell us anything" [21, p. 259]. Before we (Eds LEAvrr'r H J, PONDY LR and BOJE DM), pp.
hurriedly prescribe a better epistemology (our 570-580. University of Chicago Press, Illinois.
own scientific theory of knowledge, naturally, 23. MARCHJG and Or,SEN JP (1976) Ambiguity and Choice
in Organizations. Universitetsforlaget, Bergen.
[19]), a theory of organizational learning must 24. MARCUSEH (1966) Ethics and revolution. In Ethics and
first account for the epistemology or episte- Society (Ed. DE GEORGE RT), pp. 133-148. Doubleday.
New York.
mologies organizations do use in the attempt to
25. MASON RO and M1TRO~ II (1973) A program for
make sense of the chaotic phenomenal world. research on management information systems. Mgmt
Sci. 19(5), 475--487.
26. MASONROand MI'rRo~ II (1981) Challenging Strategic
Planning Assumptions. John Wiley, New York.
27. METCAL~ L (1981) Designing precarious partnerships.
REFERENCES In Handbook of Organizational Design, Vol. 1 (Eds
NYs'rROM PC and STARBUCKWH), pp. 503-530. Oxford
1. ACKOFF RL (1978) The Art of Problem-solving. John University Press, New York.
Wiley, New York. 28. MINTZBERGH, RAISINGHANID and THEORET A (1976)
2. AcKo~ RL and RaVETTP (1963) A Manager's Guide to The structure of 'unstructured' decision processes.
Operations Research. John Wiley, New York. Adminve Sci. Q. 21, 246--275.
3. AGRE GN (1982) The concept of problem. Educ. Stud. 29. NEWELLA, SHAWJC and StMON HA (1962) The process
13(2), 121-142. of creative thinking. In Contemporary Approaches to
4. ANTHONY RN and DEARDEN J (1980) Management Creative Thinking (Eds GRU~ER HE, TERRELL G and
Control Systems. Irwin, Homewood, Illinois. WERTHEIMER M), pp. 63-119. Atherton, New York.
5. ARGYRIS C and SCHON DA (1978) Organizational 30. NEWELL A and SIMON HA (1972) Human Problem
Learning. Addison-Wesley, Reading, Massachusetts. Solving. Prentice Hall, New Jersey.
6. CHURCHMANCW (1968) The Systems Approach. Delta 31. OLIVA TA and CAPOEVILLE CU (1980) Can systems
Books, New York. really be taught? Acad. Mgmt Re,,. 5(2), 277-279.
7. COHENMD, MARCHJG and OLSENJP (1972) A garbage 32. QUADEES (1973) Military systems analysis. In Systems
can model of organizational choice. Adminve Sci. Q. Analysis (Ed. OPTNERSL), pp. 12 l - 140. Penguin Books.
March, 1-25. 33. REIN M and SCHONDH (1977) Problem setting is policy
8. COOPER DJ, HAYES D and WOLF F (1981) Accounting research. In Using Social Research in Public Policy
in organized anarchies: understanding and designing Making (Ed. WEISS C). Lexington Books, Massachu-
accounting systems in ambiguous situations. Account. setts.
Org. Soc. 6(3), 175--191. 34. RITTEL HWS and WEBBER MM (1973) Dilemmas in a
9. DERY D (1982) Erring and learning: an organizational general theory of planning. Policy Sci. 4, 155--164.
analysis. Account. Org. Soc. 7(3), 217-223. 35. SCHULTZE CL (1968) The Politics and Economics of
10. DERY D (1982) Evaluation and problem redefinition. Jl Public Spending. The Brookings Institution, Washing-
publ. Policy 2(1 ), 23-30. ton, DC.
11. EDEN C and SIMS D (1979) On the nature of problems 36. StMON HA (1960) The New Science of Management
in consulting practice. Omega 7(2), 114-127. Decisions. Harper, New York.
12. GORRY GA and SCOTT-MORTON MS (1971) A frame- 37. S'rEINBRUI~RJD (1974) The Cybernetic Theory of Deci-
work for management information systems. Sloan sion. Princeton University Press, New Jersey.
Mgmt Re,'. 13, 55-70. 38. STRAUCH RE (1975) 'Squishy' problems and quan-
13. HAMPSmRE S (1949) Fallacies in moral philosophy. titative methods. Policy Sci. 6(2), 175-184.
Publ. (1966) in Contemporary Ethical Theory (Ed. 39. TAYLOR DW (1965) Decision making and problem
MARGOLISJ), pp. 157-175. Random House, New York. solving. In Handbook of Organizations (Ed. MARCH
14. HEDSERG B (1981) How organizations learn and un- JG), pp. 48-86. Rand McNally, Chicago.
learn. In Handbook of Organizational Design, Vo[. 1 40. TAYLOR RN and VERTINSKY I (1981) Experimenting
(Eds NYSTROM PC and STARBUCK WH), pp. 3-27. with organizational behavior. In Handbook of Or-
Oxford University Press, New York. ganizational Design, Vol. I (Eds NYSTROM PC and
328 Dery--Decision-making,
Problem-solving and Organizational Learning

STaRSUCK WH), pp. 13%166. Oxford University Press, 44. WILt~^vsI~Y A (1979) The Art and Craft of Policy"
New York. Analysis. Macmillan, New York.
41. VICKERS G (1965) The Art of Judgment. Basic Books,
New York.
42. VICK~RSG (1970) Value Systems and Social Processes.
Penguin Books. ADDRESS FOR CORRESPONDENCE: Mr David Defy, Department
43. WEtCK K E (1969) The Social Psychology of Organizing. of Political Science, Hebrew University of Jerusalem,
Addison-Wesley. Reading, Massachusetts. Jerusalem, Israel.

You might also like