Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 3

Doing Right and

Being Good:
What It Would Take
for People Living with
Autism to Flourish
Nancy Nyquist Potter

Keywords: good deliberation, prudence (phronesis), low severity of Asperger’s syndrome—can go on


virtuous feelings, non-ideal eudaimonism to flourish. I am skeptical of their conclusions.
The first reservation concerns their understand-
ing of Aristotelian flourishing and the second, the

F
urman and Tuminello (2015) raise a method by which they claim that children with
central question about people living with Asperger’s can flourish. My conclusion is that the
mental illness: What kind of life is possible methods and claims of ABA do not warrant an
for them? Can one live a flourishing life even when application of Aristotle’s flourishing life.
struggling with a mental disorder? The authors
draw on research studies to argue that a technique The Virtues And Flourishing
called Applied Behavioral Analysis (ABA) can im-
Aristotle’s theory of virtue holds us to high
prove the lives of children with autism. One study,
standards: to be virtuous, we must consistently
from 1987, found that 47% of children exposed
reason well both in terms of good deliberation
to ABA attained normal IQ levels, adaptive skills,
and in terms of becoming and being the sort of
and social skills, and other studies replicated these
person who feels and acts rightly. When Furman
results. This is a promising avenue for those living
and Tuminello say that “the child might begin to
with autism.
apply his scientific reasoning towards more prac-
Furman and Tuminello focus on autism, but
tical matters and develop the virtues of thought
their claims, if true, might be extended to other
craftsmanship and prudence” (p. 260), they con-
disorders as well; as they note, people with autism
fuse Aristotle’s different kinds of thought with the
exhibit extremes of excess and deficiency, and these
one kind that is related to flourishing (Aristotle
characteristics also apply to people with border-
1999, Bk.VI). Aristotle distinguishes the scientific
line personality disorder and those with bipolar
part of the soul from the rationally calculating
disorder, so it matters whether or not Furman and
part. Scientific knowledge and craftsmanship have
Tuminello’s claims are right. The authors argue
their own virtues, but not the sort of virtue that
that some autistic children—namely, those with a
concerns action, and action is what virtue ethics

© 2016 by The Johns Hopkins University Press


264 ■ PPP / Vol. 22, No. 4 / December 2015

is concerned about. Scientific knowledge does not I emphasize these more theoretical points be-
admit of being otherwise and, hence, is not open to cause they bear directly on Furman and Tuminel-
deliberation, and craftsmanship does not involve lo’s claims that people with Asperger’s syndrome
action but production. Only prudence (phronesis) can flourish. Furman and Tuminello claim that
is a virtue in the sense of it being the state of the ABA can teach children to reason well enough
soul that helps lead us to flourishing. (Aristotle that many of them eventually can live a flourishing
makes this clearest in 1999, Bk. VI.9; see also Dahl life. Given their description of how virtue works,
1984.) Prudence requires good deliberation about it sounds more like craft production than either
what is good or bad for human beings (Aristotle prudence or virtue of character. The authors cite
1999, 1140b10). It is a kind of correctness in evidence that ABA can teach some autistic children
reasoning, but not just any kind of correctness, as to lead better lives. By this they mean that some
even a base person can reason correctly. That is children, through ABA, can learn to become less
not all it takes to have good deliberation: “Having given to extremes and more socially engaged. In
deliberated well seems, on the contrary, to be some describing how ABA might work for children
sort of good; for the sort of correctness in delib- with least severe forms of autism, the authors
eration that makes it good deliberation is the sort say that the result is “behaviors mirroring social
that reaches a good” (Aristotle 1999, 1142b22). norms” (p. 258, emphasis added). ABA works by
The good that is reached is not one just for the “manipulating a subject’s environment” (p. 256).
individual and regardless of whether it is fine to This approach results in changes that are external
do. The good must be an objectively good action to the sort of person one is.
given the context in which the situation arises, the The children they describe may learn to find
parties involved, and so on. In other words, good the mean in reasoning about houses and other
deliberation is unequivocally ethical: it implicates problems in overselectivity. This is not a skill in the
the sorts of persons we are, how we treat others, virtue of thought that Aristotle calls ‘prudence.’
and what matters to us at our deepest level. They may acquire social skills. But unless those
These clarifications are significant in evaluat- social skills are accompanied by the right feelings,
ing Furman and Tuminello’s claims. For Aristotle, they are a species of craft production, not virtue.
good deliberation is not simply that which finds Take friendliness, for example. This is a virtue the
the most effective means to some end; it is that authors worked through in the general discussion
which contributes to flourishing. Furthermore, of virtue but not as applied to people with autism.
prudence and virtues of character are integrally What would friendliness look like for people with
connected; as Aristotle says, “we cannot be fully autism who have been treated with ABA? If they
good without prudence, or prudent without virtue find the mean for friendliness but do not feel
of character” (Aristotle 1999, 1144b32). And friendly, then they do not have the virtue.
virtue of character requires that we be moved by The question the authors face is whether there is
feelings as well as by the rational desire to per- any more to ABA training than developing a skill
form the right action (Aristotle 1999, Bk. ii.6). set by which people with autism can cope better
The internalization of correct emotional states is in the world. ‘Getting by’ (even ‘getting by’ better
imperative to Aristotelian virtue theory; we cannot than otherwise) is an improvement in their lives,
live well as social beings without proper emotional but it is not the same as the deep internal structure
engagement with others (Sherman 1989). Another of virtue that Aristotle requires for a person to be
way to put the point is that what is produced said to ‘have’ the virtue.
through craft is good if the product has the right
qualities, but the same does not hold for actions Doing Right And Being Good
(Aristotle 1105a27-35). Good actions must be
done from the correct state, and that state includes Virtue theorists make a distinction between do-
that the virtuous person has the right feelings in ing and being. Doing the right thing is primarily a
a given situation. modernist approach to ethics, where the purpose
of ethical theory is to guide people toward choos-
Potter / Flourishing with Autism ■ 265

ing the right action to perform. This is one of the That said, I believe that Aristotle has set the
ways that Aristotle’s virtue ethics is distinguished bar too high in his explication of eudaimonia.
from consequentialist ones. For Mill’s utilitarian- Although I regularly draw on his theory of virtue,
ism, for example, it does not matter how one feels I nevertheless believe that Aristotle’s ideal of flour-
or why one does a right action: what makes an ishing is not achievable by the majority of people
action right is that it produces the best state of in the world. As Lisa Tessman (2005) argues, in
affairs, or at least a better one, than all available our world, structural inequalities and devastating
alternatives. The motive behind doing right does disadvantages and disabilities prevent people from
not matter to the rightness of the action. Aristo- being virtuous in ways that actually enhance their
tle rejects such a view. Virtue theories, whether own flourishing. This fact about the world we live
Aristotle’s or contemporary ones, emphasize the in applies to people living with autism, too. Those
centrality of being a virtuous person through and who struggle with autism are not generic people;
through. This means that not only does the virtu- their existence is shaped and constrained by their
ous person perform right actions, but that she race, gender, and class. This means that the extent
does so from an emotional center and with the to which people with autism can live better lives
intellectual virtue of prudence. with the intervention of ABA will be mediated not
Furman and Tuminello have given us reasons to only by the severity of their disorder, but also by
be optimistic about helping those with Asperger’s the degree to which their lives are advantaged or
and autism to live improved lives. But their claim disadvantaged by the structural order of life in
that their bettered lives are lives of flourishing is various societies. Neither Tessman nor I reject the
too strong—they would not meet the criteria for value of flourishing but, as Tessman argues, the dis-
virtue of character or of thought. Their problem advantaged need a non-ideal eudaimonistic virtue
is with the concept of flourishing they use: for ethics and an ethics in general that recognizes the
people with autism to flourish, they would need to impossible demands that are placed on people and
diminish radically the very problems that charac- thus set us up for moral failure (see Potter in press;
terize their dysfunctions. In particular, they would Tessman 2009, 2015). Even so, I believe that being
need to be able to “be afraid, for instance, or be good requires the internalization of ethical and
confident, or have appetites, or get angry, or feel social norms. I leave a discussion of where those
pity, and in general have pleasure or pain . . . [in norms come from and how to decide which norms
general, to have these] feelings at the right times, are good ones for another time (Potter in press).
about the right things, toward the right people, for
the right end, and in the right way…” (Aristotle References
1999, 1106b16-15). As I say, Aristotle’s account Aristotle. 1999. Nicomachean Ethics, trans. T. Irwin.
of virtue requires a way of being, in terms of feel- Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.
ings, actions, and deliberation, that is internal Dahl, N. 1984. Practical reason, Aristotle, and weakness
to the structure of the personality. A change in of the will. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
problems such as connecting socially and rela-
Furman, T. M., and A. Tuminello. 2015. Aristotle,
tionally to others may just amount to eradicating autism, and applied behavior analysis. Philosophy,
the dysfunction—a possibility that Furman and Psychiatry, & Psychology 22, no. 4:253–62.
Tuminello seem to deny. If they were to jettison Potter, N. N. In Press. The virtue of defiance and psychi-
the idea that living well with autism requires atric engagement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
flourishing, they would be in a more persuasive Sherman, N. 1989. The fabric of character: Aristotle’s
position. I am all in favor of the aim of helping theory of virtue. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Tessman, L. 2005. Burdened virtues: Virtue ethics for
people with mental disorders live better lives (be-
liberatory struggles. Oxford: Oxford University
yond just hanging on by their fingernails), but we Press.
need to be clear on what we mean by ‘better’ and ———. 2009. Feminist eudaimonism as non-ideal
what it would take to move beyond an external- theory. In Feminist ethics and social and political
ist approach to functioning better with respect to philosophy: Theorizing the non-ideal, ed. L. Tess-
individual people and different diagnoses. man, 47-58. New York: Springer.
———. 2015. Moral failure: On the impossible de-
mands of morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

You might also like