Philosophy Now 2016 - August - September PDF

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 60

ISSUE 115 AUGUST / SEPTEMBER 2016 UK £3.75 USA $7.99 CANADA $8.

99

PhilosophyNow
a magazine of ideas

God, Science
& Ockham’s
Razor

Fallacies:
a field guide

EXISTENTIALISM
Simone de Beauvoir, Jean-Paul Sartre,
Albert Camus, Søren Kierkegaard,
authenticity, absurdity, freedom
new from tiger bark press
From the author of How to Be Bertrand Russell, Public In
Intellectual
an Existentialist,, Gary Cox Tim Madigan and Peter Stone, Editors

From being pursued The consistently first-rate papers


in the collection Bertrand Russell,
by a giant lobster,
Public IIn
ntellectual serve as a pow- w
to his complex erful reminder of the breadth and
relationship with depth of the contributions from
Simone de Beauvoir, one of the leading philosophers
of the twentieth century...This text
this is a fast- is an invaluable resource fo for stu-
paced and at times dents of Russell’s liffee aand thought.
deeply moving new
—Alan Schwerin, Associate Professor
biography of Sartre.
of Philosophy, Monmouth University
and ffoormer President of
of
the Bertrand Russell Society

25% OFF
with code
SARTRE2016*

9781474235334 | £16.99 | $29.95 | September 2016 | Hardback available


available no
now
waat
t
www.bloomsbury.com
www.tigerbarkpress.com
www
w.tigerbarkpress.com
*Enter discount code SARTRE2016 at the checkout on www.bloomsbury.com.
Discount is valid until 11:59pm 30 October 2016, on hardback and epub editions.

www.internationalschoolofphilosophy.org

A new web-based college providing online lecture & seminar courses and essay feedback for students or
anyone interested in Philosophy.

As a special introductory offer for readers of Philosophy Now, we are pleased to offer our 20 week
courses for only £240 - a 40% discount on the regular price!*
• Introduction to Philosophy
• Ethics: Historical Perspectives
• Epistemology
• Logic
Courses start October 2016
The courses reflect the content of those of the University of London International Programme Philosophy BA
so should be especially useful for those studying that degree.
*Discount code: PN40
www.internationalschoolofphilosophy.org
Philosophy Now ISSUE 115 Aug/Sept 2016
Philosophy Now, EDITORIAL & NEWS
43a Jerningham Road, 4 You Always Have a Choice! Rick Lewis
Telegraph Hill,
London SE14 5NQ 5 News in Brief
United Kingdom 51 Thinkers Against Xenophobia: Anja Steinbauer
Tel. 020 7639 7314
editors@philosophynow.org EXISTENTIALISM

SISYPHUS BY ANTONIO ZANCHI, 1665


philosophynow.org 6 On Being an Existentialist
Editor-in-Chief Rick Lewis
Stuart Greenstreet tells us what existentialism is
Editors Anja Steinbauer, Grant Bartley 9 Authenticity and the Treatment of Depression
Digital Editor Bora Dogan Alisa Anokhina on how existentialist thinking could help
Graphic Design Grant Bartley, Katy
Baker, Anja Steinbauer 10 Is Kierkegaard Still Relevant Today?
Book Reviews Editor Teresa Britton Lucian Lupescu says he dares us to live
Film Editor Thomas Wartenberg 11 Simone’s Existentialist Ethics
Marketing Manager Sue Roberts
Administration Ewa Stacey, Katy Baker Anja Steinbauer on de Beauvoir’s Ethics of Ambiguity
Advertising Team 12 Existentialism as Punk Philosophy
Jay Sanders, Ellen Stevens
jay.sanders@philosophynow.org
Stuart Hanscomb explains existentialism through punk rock
UK Editorial Board 14 The Absurd Heroics of Monsieur Mersault
Rick Lewis, Anja Steinbauer,
Bora Dogan, Grant Bartley
Existentialism Alex Holzman reveals Albert Camus’ absurd vision of heroism
US Editorial Board Zut alors! Pages 6-22 16 Why Camus Was Not An Existentialist
Dr Timothy J. Madigan (St John Fisher Greg Stone spills the beings
College), Prof. Charles Echelbarger, 18 “all the consequences of this”
Prof. Raymond Pfeiffer, Prof. Massimo
Pigliucci (CUNY - City College), Prof. Kile Jones argues that only atheists make authentic existentialists
Teresa Britton (Eastern Illinois Univ.)
Contributing Editors
LES GENERAL ARTICLES
Alexander Razin (Moscow State Univ.) 23 Facts & Opinions
Laura Roberts (Univ. of Queensland) Christoffer Lammer-Heindel tells us what they are, and aren’t
David Boersema (Pacific University)
UK Editorial Advisors 26 Bad Arguments That Make You Smarter
Piers Benn, Constantine Sandis, Gordon Henrik Schoeneberg provides a field guide to fallacies
Giles, Paul Gregory, John Heawood 28 The Philosophy Professor and the Holy Book of Baseball
US Editorial Advisors
Prof. Raymond Angelo Belliotti, Toni Chris Christensen on a yearning for logical consistency
Vogel Carey, Prof. Walter Sinnott- 30 Science, Ockham’s Razor and God
Armstrong, Prof. Harvey Siegel
Cover Image Simone de Beauvoir
David Glass & Mark McCartney say science doesn’t cut out God
by Gail Campbell 2016 38 The Consequences of Accepting Consequentialism
Katy Baker says they’re not good
Printed by The Manson Group Ltd
8 Porters Wood, Valley Road Industrial
Estate, St Albans AL3 6PZ

UK newstrade distribution through:


Science LES REVIEWS
44 Book: Modality & Explanatory Reasoning, by Boris Kment
reviewed by Richard Baron
Comag Specialist Division,
Tavistock Works, Tavistock Rd,
West Drayton, Middlesex UB7 7QX
Tel. 01895 433800
or God?
Page 30
46

47
Book: The Making of An Atheist, by Jason Spiegel
reviewed by Matt DeStefano
Book: Berkeley’s Puzzle by John Campbell & Quassim Cassam
reviewed by Nick Everitt
US & Canadian bookstores through:
Disticor Magazine Distribution Services
48 Film: Star Wars: The Force Awakens
© WALT DISNEY STUDIOS 2015

695 Westney Road S., Unit 14, Jason Eberl & Kevin Decker on a franchise reboot far, far away
Ajax, Ontario L1S 6M9
Tel. (905) 619 6565 LES REGULARS
33 Philosophical Haiku: Søren Kierkegaard
Australian newstrade distribution:
Gordon & Gotch pty
Terence Green encapsulates the early existentialist
Level 2, 9 Rodborough Road 34 Question of the Month: Is Morality Objective?
French’s Forest, NSW 2086 See if there are any morally objectionable answers from our readers
Tel. 02 9972 8800
POSTER

41 Letters to the Editor


The opinions expressed in this magazine 52 Brief Lives: Xunzi
FORCE AWAKENS

do not necessarily reflect the views of Dale DeBakcsy tells us about an anti-conservative Confucian
the editor or editorial board of
Philosophy Now. 56 Tallis in Wonderland: Time & Change
Raymond Tallis wonders how they relate
Philosophy Now is published by
Anja Publications Ltd LE FICTION
ISSN 0961-5970

Shop p.54
Awaken The Force! 58 Inadequate Options In Adequate Space
Kevin Robson’s hero finds you can’t escape having to choose
Subscriptions p.55 Film Review, p.48
August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 3
Editorial
You Always Have a Choice!
Given the current fashion for referendums Rick Lewis has decided to offer you
a choice of editorials. Pick wisely!
Despairing Editorial Hopeful Editorial

W elcome to Philosophy Now’s new issue on Existentialism.


We have to do an Existentialism-themed issue every
couple of years because you people apparently never get tired
W elcome to Philosophy Now’s new issue on Existentialism,
one of the most important and fascinating philo-
sophical movements of modern times. Its popularity never
of those gloomy, angst-ridden, black-polo-necked, coffee- dims, because its concerns are not merely of interest to
swilling Parisian poseurs. I hope you realise how tough it is scholars: it grapples with some of the biggest questions we all
for us, having to produce features on Sisyphus and the face in our own lives – questions of meaning, of freedom, of
meaninglessness of life over and over again. It seems like we responsibility, of personal identity and authenticity, of
are trapped in an Eternal Return of the same, and yet at the religious belief, of mortality, of the apparent absurdity of life.
same time we are reproached and taunted at every moment by These questions also, of course, run through much of
the knowledge that we are actually completely and inescapably culture including art, music, theatre, cinema and literature. So
free – free to turn Philosophy Now into a golfing magazine, free it isn’t surprising that people use Existentialist ideas to under-
to paint the editorial office bright purple, free even to end it stand works of art, or that some of the key philosophers of
all (for example by selling the magazine to the Vasto Existentialism were novelists or playwrights as well.
Publishing Corporation and running off to Brazil with the So what is this philosophy? What are its central assump-
proceeds, if we can get a really cheap flight). So why do we tions and its central claims? It starts with the assumption that
not do so? Our failure to constantly weigh these options we are thrown into a universe that doesn’t care about us, and
clearly shows we are in Bad Faith. Why, oh why, do we allow that we have no pre-determined purpose in being here and no
ourselves to be trapped in a little room with Camus, Sartre pre-determined essence of who we are. So our existence
and Simone de Beauvoir until finally it feels like an eternity in comes first, and who we then become through our freely-
hell? And why do we assume that you will buy this issue, just chosen actions is up to us. Or, in the popular Existentialist
because you all did so the previous times we produced an slogan, “existence preceeds essence”. To find out more, read
Existentialism-themed issue? Perhaps us putting the issue Stuart Greenstreet’s introduction. This issue also contains a
together at all is a Leap of Faith? selection of articles about Existentialist thinkers including
We’ve now been publishing this magazine for twenty five Søren Kierkegaard, Jean-Paul Sartre, Simone de Beauvoir and
years. Twenty five! Though to be honest it feels a lot longer. their sometime friend Albert ‘I’m-Not-Really-An-
Bah humbug. Existentialist’ Camus. It applies their ideas to life and art
[The Editor has gone for a little lie down. He thought you might including the treatment of depression and understanding punk
like this photo of Sartre and de Beauvoir’s favourite café, Les Deux rock music. We even take a look at de Beauvoir’s Existentialist
Magots in Saint-Germain-des-Prés, Paris] ethics. So enjoy the articles in this issue but remember that
they barely scratch the surface of this subject.
Existentialism is a very rich philosophy; let’s take just one
of its concepts as an example: Bad Faith. According to Sartre,
we can be in Bad Faith in two different ways. One kind of Bad
Photo by Rick Lewis, Paris, 2015. In memory of Marilu.

Faith is when we refuse to face up to particular facts about our


lives (“Yes, he beats me up, but I know that deep down he
loves me.”). A second kind is when we refuse to recognize our
own freedom (“I can’t join the circus because I’m head waiter
and this café needs me.”). Sartre believes that we always have
choices, even if the various alternatives open to us may not
always be very appealing. This one concept of Bad Faith
alone, carefully applied, offers so much potential for under-
standing and indeed improving our lives; and that’s before we
even get started on concepts like authenticity and absurdity. If
you think that philosophy should have the potential to change
the way people live, then Existentialism is one school of
thought you really have to study!

4 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


• Self-Driving Car Studies Cast Light on
Attitudes to Ethics • Nussbaum Wins Prize

News
• Heidegger Has A New Book Out •
News reports by Anja Steinbauer.

The Rise of Chinese Philosophy fear that its moral algorithm might subor- was asked to give lectures all over
Chinese philosophy has now become dinate their own safety or that of their Germany. Perhaps this new volume can
the third most popular undergraduate loved ones to that of a greater number of throw light on the controversial thinker’s
course at Harvard University, eclipsed only strangers outside the car. This means that allure.
by Computer Sciences and Economics. the advantage of self-drive cars saving more
Michael Puett, Professor of Chinese lives may be lost if people are unwilling to Nussbaum Wins Kyoto Prize
History at Harvard, says that works of clas- use them. Prominent American philosopher
sical Chinese philosophy are thought of as Martha Nussbaum of the University of
fulfilling the function of a ‘philosophy of Chicago has been given the Kyoto Prize in
life’, giving guidance and providing princi- Arts and Philosophy by Japan’s Inamori
ples to good living. As well as Chinese Foundation. The annual prize, one of the
philosophy, great works of Chinese poetry top international honours for scholarly
are also enjoying popularity, especially work, is given only once every four years in
those of Du Fu (712-770), who is now the sub-category of thought and ethics.
hailed as the ‘Chinese Shakespeare’. The Foundation says that Professor Nuss-
baum has “led global discourse on philo-
Ethics and Self-Driving Cars sophical topics that influence the human
A recent academic study of the Self-driving car condition in profound ways, including
processing of moral dilemmas by self- contemporary theories of justice, law,
driving cars may throw some light on a Elie Wiesel Dies education, feminism and international
more general ethical problem. Enthusiasts Nobel Peace Laureate Elie Wiesel has development assistance,” adding that “she
for self-driving cars have argued that they died at the age of 87. German President established a new theory of justice that
will drastically reduce the number of traffic Joachim Gauck remarked: “We have lost a ensures the inclusion of the weak and
accidents. However, the computers great person, an extraordinary scholar and marginalized, who are deprived of oppor-
controlling them will occasionally confront writer.” The Holocaust surviver who lost tunities to develop their capabilities in
crisis situations, just as human drivers do, all his family to the horror of the Nazi society, and has proposed ways to apply
in which they must choose between the period had dedicated his life to fighting for this theory in the real world.”
safety of those inside the vehicle and that human rights. President Obama referred to
of people outside the vehicle – pedestrians Wiesel as “one of the great moral voices of Bishops, Ethics and Politics
or other motorists. How should they be our time”, a “conscience of the world.” For the first time in their history,
programmed to deal with such dilemmas? Wiesel published extensively about the Catholic bishops from both sides of the
An article in Science in June has done much Holocaust and set up a foundation against Atlantic have published a common position
to clarify this difficulty. French and Amer- intolerance and indifference. In 1986 he on a political issue. The Transatlantic
ican researchers J.-F. Bonnefon, Azim was awarded the Nobel Peace Prize for his Trade and Investment Partnership (TTIP)
Shariff and Iyal Rahwan presented six efforts in combatting violence and racism. treaty will, when completed, directly affect
online questionnaires to 2,000 people the lives of almost a billion people in the
asking in varying ways about priorities of New Heidegger Manuscripts EU and the USA, as well as having a
passenger safety versus the safety of others A scholarly volume just published profound impact on many other countries.
outside the car. Though the responses contains lectures given by existentialist Seeing that the debate concerning of the
varied depending on the precise questions philosopher Martin Heidegger from 1915- agreement is highly polarized, the
asked, they all showed to the same broad 1932. The book mainly contains lectures Commission of the Bishops’ Conferences
preferences. The authors concluded that from the 1920’s, dating from before the of the European Community (COMECE)
the surveys showed a threefold result: 1927 publication of Heidegger’s magnum and the United States’ Conference of
Firstly, most respondents agreed that self- opus Being and Time. Even then, Heidegger Catholic Bishops (USCCB) have jointly
drive cars should be programmed to always had a reputation as a brilliant young announced a ‘toolbox’ of nine moral prin-
prioritize the lives of many over the lives of thinker and was much in demand not only ciples for the evaluation of TTIP. While
fewer individuals. Secondly, respondents at the universities but far beyond. The they acknowledge that trade can be truly
believed it a good idea for people to use general public had a great interest in beneficial for all, they say it must be struc-
such cars. Thirdly, however, they did not philosophy at the time; there were tured in such a way as to help reduce
want to drive such a car themselves – for numerous ‘Kant Societies’ and Heidegger inequality and injustice.

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 5


Existentialism
On Being An Existentialist
Stuart Greenstreet chooses to tell us how to become authentically existentialist.

I
t took almost a century of thought before existentialism humanity. That makes it futile to seek a code for behaviour
came to fruition as a popular movement – almost a craze – anywhere outside of ourselves. Each individual has to create his
in post-war France in the nineteen-forties and fifties. This or her own value by living and affirming it, and must do so in a
was the time of its greatest influence, not only on philosophy way that satisfies a single governing norm of ‘authenticity’ – in
but also on literature, drama and film-making, extending far perhaps oversimplistic terms, through always ‘being myself’.
beyond France. But here I am dealing with existentialism solely Existentialism is obsessed with how individuals choose to
as a school of philosophy – one which arose mainly from the live their lives. Our choices are demonstrated by our acts, and
work of five men and one woman: Søren Kierkegaard, Friedrich always concern matters within our power. To choose, then,
Nietzsche, Edmund Husserl, Martin Heidegger, Jean-Paul involves deliberating about things that are in our control and
Sartre, and Simone de Beauvoir. (Although Albert Camus is attainable by our action. Then by whatever actions we choose
often called an existentialist, he himself denied he was one [see to take, we define and create the selves that we gradually
later, ed].) Of these, Sartre was the only one to accept the name become. For example, we become ‘just’ by performing just acts,
‘existentialist’ and employ all of its key concepts: ‘anguish’, ‘bad and similarly as regards other virtues. This is not meant as a
faith’, ‘facticity’, ‘commitment’, and ‘authenticity’. moral point – no ‘should’ or ‘ought’ is implied – but as a fact
All philosophers in the existentialist camp shared the same about the nature of the world and of human choice: that my
mission: to make us recognise that human beings are free to choices of good or evil will determine my character and make
choose, not only what to do when faced with moral choices, me the kind of human being that I turn out to be.
but what to value and how to live. They want these facts about
human freedom to be not merely accepted, but absorbed by Authentic Being
each person for him- or herself, so that when they have Existentialism obviously rests on some pretty bold ontologi-
absorbed them their whole view of life will be different. Existen- cal assumptions, then – claims about what exists and how it
tialism as a cultural movement belongs to the past. But as a phi- exists. The first is that values are not part of the fabric of the
losophy with this utterly practical mission it can be as liberating world, in the sense of existing independently of us. To live your
to us now as it was to men and women in war-torn Europe. life as if your values were somehow given from outside, as
though to adopt the attitude of an uptight, conventional person
Basics whose duties all seem to be laid out for them, would amount to
When readers of the Parisian newspaper Le Monde began to a refusal to face up to your freedom. In that case, you wrongly
take notice of existentialism, the newspaper published an arti- think you can escape your freedom by taking refuge in a fixed
cle in December 1945 to tell them what it meant. Although it role, or essence. But even when people do passively adopt
did its best, Le Monde finally felt it had to admit that “Existen- ready-made values in this way, they still choose to do so, albeit in
tialism, like faith, cannot be explained; it can only be lived.” a way that has failed to live up to the standard of authenticity,
Why is existentialism like faith? Because to base one’s con- because it doesn’t recognise their inalienable freedom.
duct on a belief that one is free to choose is an act of faith, for My attitude is authentic when I engage in my projects as my
there’s no way of knowing for sure whether it’s true or false. own. My attitude would not be authentic if keeping my
And what makes existentialism hard to explain? Perhaps it is its promises, for instance, is something I do just because that’s
claim that no objective moral order exists, independently of ‘what one does’ – what ‘moral people’ normally do – or because
it is what society expects of me. My way of behaving is authentic
if and only if my action is a reflection of my choice – that is, when
I commit myself to behave in that sort of way because that is
what I expect of myself whether or not it is socially sanctioned.
PLEASE VISIT THOMASTOONS.WIX.COM/CARTOONS
CARTOON © THOMASTOONS/BILL THOMAS 2016.

Choosing Value
Existentialism makes every individual responsible for decid-
ing for him- or herself how to evaluate their choices. Sartre
further remarked that it is in the nature of values that they
make demands on us. I do not just see the homeless person; I
encounter him as someone ‘to be helped’. Why ought I help the
homeless? The answer can be revealed, Sartre thought, only to
a free agent who makes the value exist by the fact of recogniz-
ing it as such. You judge a homeless man as someone to be
helped only because you have already chosen yourself as a person
who helps people. There is an answer to ‘Why ought I help the

6 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Existentialism
essentially anything, except that we are essentially free. We
become self-created beings by virtue of our actions and our rela-
tions with other people. Hence the existentialist slogan ‘exis-
tence precedes essence’.
That each one of us has absolute freedom of choice is an
existentialist article of faith – to the existentialist it is a truth so
‘CONDEMNED TO BE FREE’ © PETER PULLEN 2016 PLEASE VISIT WWW.PETERPULLEN.COM

self-evident that it never needs to be proved or even argued


for. And who needs theoretical proof of something indispens-
able to the practical business of living? To an existentialist,
“My freedom is my essence and my salvation. I cannot lose it
without ceasing to be” (Roger Scruton, Modern Philosophy,
2012). So every honest person must recognize my freedom.
Obviously no one chooses entirely what he or she becomes,
or is. Each of us has a set of given natural and social properties
that influence the kind of person we become. Sartre gave to
these features the collective name ‘facticity’. One’s facticity
comprises all those properties another person could discover
and investigate. They include natural properties, such as sex,
weight, height, and skin colour; social facts, such as race, class,
and nationality; psychological properties, such as my extant
web of beliefs, desires, and character traits; and historical facts,
such as my family background, schooling; and so forth.
Our own facticity hardly ever occupies our own minds in
this third-person kind of way, even though it does weigh on us
and colour our moods and approach to life. However, when I
do step back and take a third-person, objective, view of my fac-
ticity, then these given facts about me may strike me as pre-
cisely what does define who I am. But for an existentialist, to
think this would be a radical mistake, not because my factual
properties are misleading, but because the person each one of
us is cannot be defined in third-person terms. No objective
account of my properties could ever describe my subjective
experience of what it’s like to be me, the person who has them.
So someone observing me can make out my skin colour, class,
or ethnicity; but the moment he attempts to identify me in
homeless?’ from within that prior ‘self-making’ choice; but terms of these properties, he encounters a paradox, since the
outside of it there is none. Moreover, the principle of helping – kind of being I am is defined, among other things, by the atti-
say kindliness or compassion – is sanctioned by your action, tude I adopt towards my own facticity – by how I choose to
rather than the action by the principle. interpret it – and that is not fixed by the facts. Who I am
To value a certain way of acting more highly than any alter- depends (among other things) on what I make of my facticity,
native is to choose that particular way as a goal – to set it up as on how I try to go beyond, or transcend it. In other words,
an ideal to be aimed at. For although the values you adopt are whatever my facticity, and no matter how fixed it may be, it
indeed your values, they do not merely express your private does not curtail my freedom. I am still free to decide what
feelings about what is right or wrong. If in some particular values to ascribe to my facticity, and what stance to take
instance you judge that tax evasion is wrong then, whether you towards it. To become the person you choose to be despite the
realise it or not, you have judged that it is wrong in general. burden of your facticity is the only authentic way to live your
For the concept of ‘choice’ entails the idea of whatever is life, whereas to live it as though you were at the mercy of your
chosen is the right thing to do, and ‘right’ means ‘right for facticity – to pretend that it has robbed you of your freedom –
everyone’. As Sartre put it, “when a man chooses for himself is inauthenticity. It would be to lose both one’s autonomy and
he chooses for mankind” (Existentialism is a Humanism, 1946) – one’s integrity, and in this way give in to determinism.
meaning that every action that he (and we) choose provides an
example for the rest of humanity. If I choose a particular good The Price of Freedom
for myself such as freedom, I am thereby committed to choos- It would be hard to feel otherwise about freedom and
ing freedom for everyone. choice if you had lived in occupied France between 1940 and
1945, when existentialism came of age as the philosophie officielle
The Facts of Freedom of the resistance movement. In those years, and even during
Existentialism’s most basic premise is that human beings the post-1945 reconstruction, it exerted a powerful appeal that
have no pre-existing or set nature or character. We are not was as much emotional as intellectual. If “man is nothing but

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 7


Existentialism
gle to free their country, or to resign themselves to Nazi domi-
Creating Yourself nation. They had to choose, and it was a time when they faced
Elizabeth Bevington their freedom in great anguish. Some were unable to bear the
2016
thought of their freedom, and in order to escape its pressure
adopted the cover of what Sartre called ‘bad faith’, perhaps the
most important concept of his philosophy. (Note how he too
turned to the word ‘faith’.) Someone is in bad faith when, in
order to protect himself from the anxiety of having to choose,
he pretends to himself that he is not as free as he actually is. It
is a specific kind of self-deception, a core betrayal of one’s self.
A common type of bad faith is the denial of one’s freedom in
the form of an excuse, typically beginning with “I couldn’t help
it…” We hear this in the excuse made by those Nazi soldiers
who insisted “I could not do otherwise” or “I was just doing my
duty.” One can always do otherwise: one can quit, or run away,
or even choose to be shot. The cost might enormous – even
one’s life – but it is never a case of cannot, always of will not. They
chose to continue to obey orders: it was not determined by their
nature. Existentialism doesn’t allow excuses. There is never a
legitimate reason for denying one’s freedom. No matter how
oppressed we may be by our situation or circumstances, we
know we can always imagine alternatives – and act on them too,
if we’re brave enough. The only way to stay in good faith is hon-
estly to continually own up and respond to being free to choose,
and accountable for whatever you decide to do.

Thinking & Living


I detect in the language I use here the characteristic ‘mis-
sionary’ tone of existentialism, which implores us all to experi-
ence our freedom to choose, and to practice it. Existentialism is a
coherent theory rooted in an idealist (that is, a consciousness-
based) metaphysics; but it is not enough merely to understand
that which he makes of himself” (Sartre), then no one is bound it intellectually in that way. To grasp it properly, one has to
by fate, or by forces outside their control. By uniting with like- engage with it as a practical and committed philosophy – in
minded people, the individual can challenge authority – even other words, to commit to being an existentialist. Then you
tyrannical power – and change things. He or she can choose to would see yourself as free and autonomous in way you did not
oppose the Nazis, or to create a more just society than had recognize before, and by so doing acquire the power to tran-
existed before the war. Only by exercising their personal free- scend your facticity.
dom could people regain their civil liberties. ‘Facticity’ and ‘transcendence’ are the grand concepts of exis-
But there is a price to be paid for the freedom to do whatever tentialism. Our facticity defines our situation and who we are up
you choose at every juncture. No one can decide on your behalf; to this point in our lives. Transcendence opens up the world of
the choice of action is always yours and yours alone. And no one possibilities: what we can now go on to make of that situation
can ever avoid the personal responsibility for judging what the and of ourselves, given who or what we have become so far.
morally right thing to do is. You thus suffer the potential Existentialism is absolutely not ‘academic’. It is the antithe-
anguish of having to endure an endless series of choices in the sis of the purely analytical (normally Anglo-American)
knowledge that only you can decide, that you may evaluate approach to philosophy, the prime purpose of which seems to
anything as you please, and that you have no character to guide be to deliver mental hygiene. The whole point of existential-
your choice other than the one you’re forming for yourself. ism is to practice its liberating ideas, to apply them to becoming
Not everyone can cope with the burden of an existentialist the person one chooses to be.
approach to shaping their lives and characters. Some may try to That we can be the authors of our own lives and characters
flee the tyranny of choice by hiding from themselves the truth strikes me as a very appealing thought. It means that a life can
that we are all, as Sartre said, “condemned to be free” – which in a sense itself become the stuff of art – something to be
means not free to cease being free. All our acts inevitably pre- shaped according to one’s own vision of oneself.
suppose choice; and so we are still choosing even when we think © STUART GREENSTREET 2016
we are not – even when we have deliberately chosen not to choose. Stuart Greenstreet earned his living as a business manager and
When France was over-run and occupied by the German writer and was awarded a diploma in philosophy by Birkbeck College.
army in 1940, every French man and woman was forced to London. After graduating from the Open University he did further
think about their values and decide whether to resist and strug- philosophy at the University of Sussex.

8 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Existentialism
Authenticity & Treatment For Depression
Alisa Anokhina on how the quest for authenticity can help in treating depression.

C
olloquially, the word ‘depression’ is often used for list- of the self. Severe depression can be crippling, but these phases
lessness, extreme sadness, or a profound sense of loss. will often naturally give way to periods of remission. In these
It’s no wonder that so many people with a diagnosis of states a beneficial reevaluation of perception can be sought.
depression struggle to be taken seriously: to the unaffected, the This can involve questioning deeply ingrained thought pat-
problem sounds akin to a diagnosis of ‘sadness’. But sadness, in terns, (re)assessing personal values, and evaluating one’s per-
fact, is not the only or even the main complaint: a clinical diag- sonal development. Because the immediate causes of depres-
nosis of Major Depressive Disorder requires at least five symp- sion will be different for every person afflicted with it, over-
toms, and only one of those refers to a ‘depressed mood’. coming it also requires introspection.
Depression is exhausting. Feelings of listlessness and fatigue The issue of agency comes into play here. Often, depression
saturate life, and everyday tasks become laborious, as though can arise seemingly out of nowhere, causing significant confu-
wading through tar. Things which previously gave joy or rest sion and distress to a person. Other times, depression follows a
become encumbering; socializing is a chore. Shadows creep catalyst: the loss of a loved one, or a significant personal failure.
across the walls of the mind. Depression is not the same as sad- The negative aspects of life which can serve to exacerbate
ness. Sadness is transient – depression is pervasive. depression can sometimes be removed; for example, a toxic
Depression is like schizophrenia in the sense that both are relationship, or an unfulfilling job. However, we must accept
disorders of perception. It is difficult to accept the extent to that our agency is limited. We will always be tethered to our
which our emotions warp our reality. Writer Andrew Solomon basic biological needs, and constricted by social rules. The only
has said that, in a depressed state, “you think that the veil has way in which we are infinitely flexible is in the construction of
been taken away, the veil of happiness, and that now you are our values. This is, perhaps, the only sphere in which our own
seeing truly” (see www.ted.com/talks/andrew_solomon_depres- agency is absolute. The pursuit of authenticity allows us to set
sion_the_secret_we_share). The depressive comes to believe the our own parameters here. Ultimately, depression is the conse-
worthlessness – either their own or the world’s – and this belief quence of genetic predisposition, chemical dysfunction, and, in
appears infallible, despite evidence to the contrary. many cases, a catalyst. We cannot undo the loss of a loved one,
The nature of the link between perception and reality is per- or escape the confines of social norms. However, fallacies in
haps one of the oldest philosophical debates. The debate is also perception and interpretation perpetuate depression, and we
one without a resolution. Even if what we perceive as reality have the agency to alter these.
might not be reality, we have no choice but to continue behav- People with depression are often reluctant to try drug thera-
ing as if it were. Yet from a neuropsychological perspective, the pies because they worry about warping their reality and sacri-
possibility that our grasp of reality is limited, or even corrupted, ficing their authenticity: Is the medicated mind artificial, or
is almost a certainty. Our brains provide our only window to the does medication restore normality to a mind which is defi-
world, and, like any other organ, they’re fallible and prone to cient? Am I still myself if every day I swallow a powder which
malfunction. Our brains are capable of creating false memories; changes how I think and feel? Seeking treatment can also feel
we mistake dreams for reality; and we fall for optical illusions. like lying to yourself: if one is unworthy of life, then one is cer-
Hallucinogenic drugs systematically distort perception. tainly unworthy of treatment. In a state of depression, worth-
Existentialist philosophers discuss the nature of experience lessness appears to be a fact, a complete certainty. Viewing the
from the perspective of meaning and morality, arguing that the world through depression can give the impression of finally
world is intrinsically meaningless. This realisation can be the seeing things for what they are. Through existentialist think-
source of anguish and anxiety: if life is intrinsically meaning- ing, however, it is possible to break down these sorts of
less, then why live? The existentialist solution to this nihilistic assumptions: if no values are objectively true, then the
dread is autonomy. Within existentialist philosophy, the onus is depressed mind can be reevaluated. Here medication is noth-
on us to define our values, and to act in a way that is consistent ing more than a repair mechanism for a malfunctioning organ.
with them, so shaping our selves. We are thus to reject the Of course, not all medications work equally for everyone, and
social roles and assumptions thrust upon us by others, and dis- side effects are a valid concern. However, through existentialist
cover our authentic selves. The self only becomes authentic eyes, we can see that refusing treatment on the basis of its
when it is consciously constructed; until we do that we are effects on one’s ‘objective’ reality or on the ‘authentic unmed-
merely a patchwork of our genes, culture, upbringing, and icated self’ is invalid.
experiences. Discovering the authentic self also means making Depression can often be devastating – but in cases where
decisions about the version of reality we choose to accept. By subjective reevaluation can lead to the creation of an authentic
definition, this process is subjective. And it can be applied to self, the person can be transformed.
help treat clinical depression. © DR ALISA ANOKHINA 2016
People who have overcome depression talk about it as a Alisa Anokhina obtained her PhD in Psychology at University Col-
restorative process: a disintegration and subsequent rebuilding lege London. She works in London as a research psychologist.

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 9


Existentialism
Is Kierkegaard Still Relevant Today?
Lucian Lupescu says the disputatious Dane dares us to live.

T
here is a general tendency in the non-philosophical be able to propound the meaning of Christianity, to explain many separate
world to dismiss philosophy as being purely theoreti- facts, if it had no deeper meaning for myself and my life? One must first
cal, with no connection to the types of prob- learn to know oneself before knowing anything else… Only when the
person has inwardly understood himself, and then sees the way
lems that people are confronted within their
forward on his path, does his life acquire repose and meaning.”
everyday lives. But this is not necessarily true. (Kierkegaard’s Journals and Notebooks, vol.1, p.22, 2008)
Many philosophers struggled to find ways to
improve people’s lives, by drawing attention Kierkegaard used pseudonyms to, in a way, dis-
KIERKEGAARD PORTRAIT © ATHAMOS STRADIS 2010

to, and making people think about, funda- tance himself from the ideas in each book.
mental aspects of life. A good example Each persona is an embodiment of a way of
would be Søren Kierkegaard (1813-1855). seeing the world, a way of living your life.
Feeling discontent with Hegel’s then- Across his works he suggests three main
dominant philosophical system (and paths of life: the aesthetic, the ethical, and
with every other philosophy popular in the religious (for him, Christian). The aes-
his time), Kierkegaard sought to answer thete sees the world through an interest-
life’s questions by turning back to ancient ing/boring dichotomy. For him, life is made
times, and a thinker to whom he felt to live, to experience, and there are no serious
closer in mind and spirit. Socrates, ‘the choices. Life is immediacy. For the ethicist, on
gadfly of Athens’, became the role-model the contrary, there are only serious choices. For
for the young Kierkegaard, who wanted to him, life is what you make of it. It is not enough to
continue his spiritual mentor’s art of ‘philosoph- just live it; you must make concrete choices that will
ical midwifery’, and become himself ‘the gadfly of give shape to your existence, to your self. Life is respon-
Copenhagen’. Just as Socrates did, Kierkegaard tried to sibility. The ethicist’s dichotomy is, let’s say, good versus evil.
challenge the common beliefs of his time. He wanted to show The Christian, on the other hand, acknowledges that you
that the only truth that is important is subjective truth. For cannot succeed in creating a perfect self. But through faith in
Kierkegaard, only through a deep and honest analysis of one- God’s forgiveness you can accept your imperfect condition, and
self, can one truly know what one is or is not, what are one’s live your life as yourself. However, although these options look
values and beliefs, what are one’s truths. a lot like they represent ultimate solutions, Kierkegaard’s life
Unlike Socrates, whose ideas we know only through other possibilities are just that – possibilities. None of them repre-
sources, Kierkegaard was a prolific writer. He left behind a sents an ‘ultimate truth’. As Kierkegaard sees them, they are
collection of writings centered on particular themes and inter- merely choices that one can make in one’s life.
ests. His works may seem contradictory at first glance. How- Kierkegaard’s Socratic approach is still relevant because of
ever, on a closer reading, one can see that they follow the same its focus on the individual. Each of us feels the need for pur-
‘negative’ scheme as Socrates. The ancient philosopher pose. What Kierkegaard, and Socrates, teach us, is that this
believed that no one had a privileged claim to absolute knowl- purpose can be gained only by our choices, our actions, the
edge (hence the title ‘negative’, as opposed to ‘positive’, phi- way we live our lives. No one, neither philosopher nor priest,
losophy), and that each individual can and should think for can tell us who or what we are, or what we should do. We must
themselves and so find their own paths in life, and their own discover and decide that for ourselves, in our inner, most inti-
values. This can be done by a close examination of one’s think- mate place, where we can make our true self come to light,
ing. Socrates called his technique of helping people become then shine upon our own, singular path. It is important for us
aware of their inner knowledge maieutic, or midwifery. to know ourselves, to discover what are really our values, our
Socrates humbled himself, claiming he didn’t know anything, beliefs – our truths – in order to live a more fulfilling life. It is
and would ask his interlocutor a series of questions that aimed important to know who we truly are, so that nobody can
to reveal that person’s knowledge, or lack of it. These dia- manipulate us into doing what is contrary to our inner selves.
logues usually ended in aporia – a state of puzzlement about Kierkegaard does not present us with absolute, objective
the subject being discussed, without finding a solution, but the truths, but challenges us to discover subjective truths for our-
person thus realizing his ignorance. selves. He proposes to encourage us to become independent:
Kierkegaard embraced Socrates’ project, analyzing his own “The phrase ‘know yourself’ means: separate yourself from the
thinking, and in doing so, realized that: other” (The Concept of Irony, 1841, trans H.V. Hong and E.H.
Hong, p.177, 1989). In the end, what Kierkegaard does is dare
“the thing is to find a truth which is a truth for me, to find the idea for
which I am willing to live and die…. What use would it be in this respect
us to live, by choosing how we live, and by taking responsibility
if I were to discover a so-called objective truth, or if I worked my way for our lives. Can we rise to his expectations?
through the philosophers’ systems…? And what use would it be in that © LUCIAN LUPESCU 2016
respect to be able to work out a theory of the state…which I myself did Lucian Lupescu is a freelance translator. He can be found at
not inhabit but merely held up for others to see? What use would it be to LLTranslator.com, or at ASynonymForRambling.wordpress.com

10 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Existentialism
Simone’s Existentialist Ethics
Anja Steinbauer on Simone de Beauvoir’s Ethics of Ambiguity


My life is my work,” Simone de Beauvoir once said. jects. Beauvoir gives examples of how many of us make poor use,
Spoken like a true Existentialist: to her, life and thought or no use at all, of our freedom. She even explains how freedom
were inextricably linked; we are what we do. Existentialism for children differs from adult freedom. Children can do what
is a philosophy that outlines the conditions of human existence they like to an extent, without being morally judged for it,
but rejects any conception of human nature; a philosophy that because they are largely free of responsibilities to others. Not so
affirms human freedom but emphasises that it brings with it not adults, yet some adults still try and live in the naïve freedom of
happy empowerment but anguish and despair, a philosophy that childhood. Others try to control or manipulate people in an
stresses that humans have choices but expresses little optimism attempt to limit their freedom – a tactic that according to Beau-
that we will make good use of them or even understand what it voir is ironically doomed to end in self-deception and the limit-
would mean to make the right choice. It is on this last point that ing of one’s own freedom. A mature and constructive use of our
Simone de Beauvoir most markedly departs from her lifelong freedom, our only chance of fulfilling ourselves as individuals,
partner Jean-Paul Sartre. involves making a ‘plea’ to others, appealing to them for their
Beauvoir’s Existentialism is scattered through her many attention and cooperation.
works, both literary and theoretical, including her classic femi- This short space is utterly inadequate to give you a proper
nist text The Second Sex. However, it finds it’s clearest and most idea of how rich Beauvoir’s ethics truly is. So you will just have to
rigorous form in her relatively underrated book The Ethics of read The Ethics of Ambiguity yourselves. It is beautifully written –
Ambiguity. The title is intriguing and unattractive at the same don’t forget that Beauvoir was a highly acclaimed novelist and
time: The fact that an Existentialist talks explicitly about ethics author, and worked hard to show her ideas’ relevance not just to
(rather than simply stressing our inescapable freedom) is a rare moral theorists but to all human beings. Why? Because all our
treat, but surely an ethics that bonds itself to ambiguity is hardly lives are marked by living with others, by ambiguity and free-
promising to propose any useful answers to moral problems? dom. That much is completely unambiguous.
This is exactly as Beauvoir intended. She accepts Sartre’s © DR ANJA STEINBAUER 2016
Existentialist tenets that there is no human nature and that Anja Steinbauer teaches at the London School of Philosophy and is an
human freedom is absolute, i.e. that in any situation whatever Editor for Philosophy Now.
we always have a choice. In other words, human life is not on
autopilot, nor is there an instruction manual telling us how to
make the right decisions. This means that there is a good deal Simone de Beauvoir
Portrait by
of ambiguity, and, in short, Beauvoir tells us to face up to it and
Gail Campbell
live with it. Given this ambiguity there would seem to be very 2016
little opportunity for moral theorising. Not so, objects Beauvoir
to this standard Existentialist conclusion. We must not expect
absolute solutions and lasting answers: “Man fulfils himself in
the transitory or not at all.” But this doesn’t mean that all ways
of living, and all courses of action, are equally good. The way
forward is to look at the nature of our relationship to other
people.
Sartre’s Existentialism leads to a clear individualism, in which
the fact that there are other people presents a constant threat of
falling into ‘bad faith’. Others judge us and impose limits on us
to the unbearable degree that “hell is other people”. By con-
trast, Beauvoir’s own individualism is more nuanced, in a Kant-
ian way: “Is this kind of ethics individualistic, or not? Yes, if one
means by that that it accords to the individual an absolute value
and recognises in him alone the power of laying the foundations
of his own existence. …The individual is defined only by his
relationship to the world and to other individuals…. His free-
dom can only be achieved through the freedom of others.”
And here we finally have it: “No existence can be validly ful-
filled if it is limited to itself.” Beauvoir’s ethics views the exis-
tence of others as an opportunity. In fact it is the only opportu-
nity we have to give reality and meaning to what we do and
therefore to what we are: We must invite others to join our pro-

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 11


Existentialism
EXISTENTIALISM AS PUNK PHILOSOPHY
Stuart Hanscomb argues that existentialism is punk philosophy par excellence.

W
henever I’m asked “So, what exactly is existentialism?” I desire, and the body. Hegel was the Prog Rock of philosophy.
experience a sinking feeling. It’s a difficult philosophy to
explain; efforts typically end up trivializing or obfuscat- ‘Right Guard will not help you here’: Extremes
ing so much about it that is important, original, and relevant. The most radical element of this ‘anti’ stance, inheres as
A number of things account for this, but an important one is much in the subversive nature of existentialism’s metaphors and
that existentialism is a state of mind as much as it is a collec- stories as in its theory of the human situation (as valid as that
tion of ideas. As Kierkegaard’s ‘aesthetic’ works, and the novels theory is).
and plays of Sartre, de Beauvoir, and Camus demonstrate, the Punk was “a politics of energy” (Stewart Home, The Assault
communication of this form of philosophy benefits from being on Culture, 1988), and also traded in extremes: short songs
indirect. To appreciate its significance you have to be there, in aggressively delivered, Mohican haircuts, ripped PVC, and the
amongst the detailed stories, rolling critiques and inspirational pogo dance. The medium, like the message, was intense and to
prose: you have to catch a dose of it through its resonance with the point. Similarly, the existential in Kafka is firmly linked to
your own often unarticulated fears and aspirations. Along the surreal and grotesque worlds of dung beetles, hunger artists,
these lines I am offering a new way in; a hook in the form of and burrow-dwellers; Camus presents murder, despotism,
an analogy with a movement in pop and rock music. Existen- plagues, and the punishment of Sisyphus; Sartre began with the
tialism, I want to claim, is the punk rock of philosophy. neo-horror of Nausea (1938) and moved on to suicide squads,
Punk rock I’m characterizing as nihilistic, extreme, passion- jealous assassins, and condemned prisoners; Kierkegaard used
ate, liberating, inclusive, amateur, and violent. It had precur- seducers and infanticide to illuminate the human condition; and
sors, and it still exists, but Malcolm McLaren, the Sex Pistols Nietzsche styled himself as the anti-Christ. Since human exis-
and all that they catalysed in the mid-Seventies are its most tence is so vividly exposed by exploring its boundaries, extreme
important moment of impact. Punk was a wake-up snarl to an situations present the existentialist with a perfect method.
atrophied establishment – a “loud raucous ‘No!’ ” (Garry Mul-
holland, Fear of Music, 2006). It sought to destroy, and in the The Filth and the Fury: Passion
ruins left behind it flexed its gnarly uneducated wings and “Punk broke out across the face of Britain like a disfiguring
expressed anger and frustration in a crude but deliberate sub- rash” (Stuart Maconie, Cider With Roadies, 2004). The Sex Pis-
version of the previous rock scene. In place of refinement and tols were an “attraction/repulsion machine” (England’s Dream-
privilege, it offered energy and inclusiveness. The distance ing). At a punk gig, to be spat at was a compliment. The emo-
between band and audience shrank, and sometimes disap- tions and moods at the epicentre of existentialism are anxiety
peared. In place of a rider of white wine, Evian and cocaine, it and disgust. Anxiety recognizes the instability and contingency
offered spit, sweat and blood. In place of systems, plans, in life; and disgust is often manifested as anger and cynicism
improvable pasts and functional futures, it offered an exhilarat- towards a complacent bourgeoisie who are insensitive to possi-
ing and dangerous present like a hyperactive adolescent. It bility and the fragility of their forms of life. In the grotesque or
couldn’t be stage-managed. It wasn’t a performance in any immoral lurks a strange beauty that corresponds with the unset-
conventional sense of the word, but a happening. tling ambivalence that often results from existential aesthetics.

no future: Nihilism Babylon’s Burning: Inclusive


Dada is art that is anti-art. Punk is music that is anti-music . We refer to authors as ‘existential’ as much because of their
Existentialism is a philosophy that is anti-philosophy. anti-systematising intensity as for their distinctive ideas. This is
How do they avoid the contradiction? They walk a not a trivial point. The style models both the fact that only you
tightrope, which is part of the point. Punk music is an “outsider can know what it’s like to be you, and the desire to inspire the
aesthetic” (Jon Savage, England’s Dreaming, 1991), but it’s still reader to wake up and take responsibility. Kafka wanted to
an aesthetic. Likewise, existentialism must recognize a place for ‘shake us awake’; Kierkegaard described his life as an “epigram
reflective rational discourse, since that’s necessary to philoso- calculated to make people aware”; and Sartre stressed that exis-
phy; but part of its agenda is to identify the limits of such dis- tentialism is a philosophy of action, not quietism. We are all the
course, and in so doing redirect us to what this perspective philosophers of our own lives. Existentialism is therefore inclu-
marginalizes and represses. It will rail against conceits such as sive. Punk attitude is “reacting from your own self, your own
the possibility of absolute knowledge, universal moral codes, an spirit ... and not accepting what’s supposed to be established.”
ultimate meaning of life, a final harmony between individual (Jim Jarmusch, in Don Letts’ film Punk Attitude, 2005). We can
and state, or between the self and its possibilities. It will, in all live authentically. Anyone can start a band. Bassist Sid
short, point to the limits of rational enquiry, and accordingly, Vicious became the whole point of the Sex Pistols and couldn’t
the limits of the rational mind’s jurisdiction over emotion, even play his instrument.

12 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Existentialism
Like the boiling lines of the punk cartoon Roobarb and Cus-
tard, existence is shaky, and the unemployed are more aware of
this than most. A career and the training or education it
implies is a source of stability which can create a halo that fal-
sifies existence as a whole. The punk is granted no such illu-
sion. Cult punk spoken word guru Henry Rollins wasn’t
aiming at anything like a career in music, but he was dedicated
SARTRE PORTRAIT © ATHAMOS STRADIS 2010

to punk and to the spirit of his band Black Flag. Nor did he
WITH HAIRSTYLING BY KATY BAKER 2016

aim to be a stand up comedian, but he turned his hand to


something like it, and the results are his highly unusual spoken
word performances. He’s an amateur and an auteur, himself
inspired by Dostoyevsky and by Nietzsche’s ‘pithy one liners’.
He imagines Nietzsche’s return as a stand up comic: “There’s
the crazy crowd at the back – Whatever doesn’t kill you makes
you stronger!” (Sweatbox, 1992).

White Riot: Violent


There is good violence, such as violence against oppression,
or violence serving as a metaphor for the ostensibly harmless
expression of frustration. Most punk is good violence. But of
course there is bad violence, and punk has a truly nasty fascist
wing. Nietzsche and Heidegger were violent philosophers; they
challenged the entire canon of Western philosophy and with it
the infrastructure of civilized values. But to apply a cultural
purgative is to run risks. By ‘philosophizing with a hammer’
Nietzsche courted misappropriation. Heidegger was for a while
existentialism’s Nazi Punk.
Oh Bondage Up Yours: Liberation I have here attempted an indirect and partial illumination of
Nihilism – that “desperate stubborn refusal of the world” the well-known but little-understood philosophy that is existen-
(England’s Dreaming), is not an end-point but a rite of passage, tialism. It’s not the whole picture for sure; the punk analogy
a temporary descent into the underworld. Existentialism isn’t can’t encompass its gentler claims about the mysteries of the
just a reaction against rational or academic excess, it also pro- human condition and its more harmonious ties to the academic
motes self-creation and spontaneity. Equally, Malcolm establishment via, phenomenology, hermeneutics, psychother-
McLaren’s mantra was “get a life and do something with it.” apy and virtue theory. Nevertheless, more than any other West-
His stepson recalls how “he made up the best bedtime stories, ern philosophy, it’s one to be inhaled with keen personal aware-
but they always stopped in the middle and you had to finish ness and exhaled in the living moment. For this reason its
them yourself” (The Word magazine, June 2010). proper force must be communicated indirectly.
Punk shouldn’t be just listened to, and even dancing isn’t Punk, says Jon Savage, was “at its most powerful when
enough. It’s about a mood that needs full commitment – not impossible to define” (England’s Dreaming). There is some-
just appreciation of grooves and tunes, but the total attune- thing about vitality that precludes satisfying definitions or
ment of one’s rebellious, absurd self. To dwell too soberly on manifestos, and so all the time existentialism defies clear cate-
Dostoyevsky’s Notes from Underground or Nietzsche’s Thus gorization there’s reason to believe it’s alive and well.
Spoke Zarathustra also misses the point. They are designed to © STUART HANSCOMB 2016
capture and create adrenalized moments with the escape veloc- Stuart Hanscomb is lecturer in philosophy at University of Glasgow’s
ity to inspire life-changing self-awareness. School of Interdisciplinary Studies (Dumfries). A version of this arti-
cle appeared in Café Philosophy (Auckland) in 2014.
Do it Yourself: Amateur
A high proportion of philosophers classed as ‘existentialist’ Glossary
have had tenuous relationships with the academic establish- no future Song from the album Never Mind the Bollocks, Here’s
ment. This doesn’t necessarily make their output ‘amateur’ in the Sex Pistols
the pejorative sense (though Camus was accused of this), but it ‘Right Guard will not help you here’ A line from the Dead
does in the sense of placing them outside of the establishment. Kennedys’ song Holiday in Cambodia
The result can be a freedom and spontaneity in their ideas, and The Filth and the Fury The biopic of the Sex Pistols
a perspective on life less biased by the analytical gaze of an aca- Oh Bondage Up Yours A song by X-Ray Spex
demic persona. Also, to be on the outside creates a kind of anx- Babylon’s Burning A song by The Ruts
iety that focuses thoughts on the concrete content of life as Do it Yourself An album by Ian Dury and the Blockheads
lived. The outsiders feel more in need of a home than those White Riot A song by The Clash
employed by an institution.

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 13


Existentialism
The Absurd Heroics of Monsieur Meursault
Alex Holzman asks what a hero is, and if Camus’ infamous character qualifies.

H
eroics lie near the heart of both literary and historical cal, existentialist or moralist, has demonstrated both fear and the
culture. Something about the ‘greatness’ of heroes equivalent bravery.
lends context to and brings to vivid life the events in If bravery is the necessary trait of heroes, its contrary can aid
which they took part and often come to represent. They are us in understanding its singularity. What constitutes cowardice,
anchors in the sea of history, often cast by desperate people; the opposite of bravery? For a soldier, the greatest coward is
and like an anchor, they often alter the course of the vessel. undoubtedly the deserter – the fellow soldier who abandons his
Heroes, fictional or otherwise, are quite diverse. We revere comrades and flees from the battle. Traditionally, captured
Odysseus for his guile and tenacity, Atticus Finch for his just- deserters were executed; in modern times, they are tried to the
ness and morality, and Christ for his self-sacrifice; others we fullest extent of military law. On one hand, this severity is due
exalt for their military exploits, ethical guidance, ideological to the perceived attack on martial camaraderie that desertion
commitment, civic service, or rebelliousness. Heroes can be represents. On the other, it is a punishment for cowardice in
controversial – perhaps even necessarily so for non-fictional the face of some conflict.
heroes. Neither Caesar nor Napoleon were without fault, to This situating is absolutely essential. The coalescent theme of
say the very least, yet they command a place of respect in the all heroics is that they represent the human experience of some
annals of history. Why is this the case? What do heroes cap- conflict or struggle. Heroes can win and heroes can lose; but if
ture in people’s minds that us historical wallflowers cannot? there is nothing to win and nothing to lose, then there can be
no heroics. One is neither hero nor coward while watching tele-
The Essence of Heroism vision. And the greatest and most uncontroversial of heroes are
The answer lies perhaps in a deconstruction of the terms those who, in the face of unimaginable opposition and personal
‘heroic’ and ‘heroic deeds’. What does it mean to behave hero- terror, overcome and propagate the best qualities of humanity,
ically? Self-sacrifice, generosity, piety, humility, and such traits be they humility, intelligence, compassion, or fortitude.
are sometimes considered central to heroics, but that’s certainly
not always the case. This is a conflation of moral heroics with Sisyphus & The Absurd
heroics of a more general nature. Many historical and fictional Monsieur Meursault, the protagonist of Albert Camus’ novel
heroes were neither unwaveringly moral nor particularly inter- The Stranger, is surely an intentionally unconventional hero.
ested in morality. A more Hegelian conception of ‘hero’ might The Stranger was first published in 1942, after WWI, and
simply be an influential figure in history – a Napoleon or therefore marked by extreme pessimism, and in the midst of
Caesar, a Stalin or Mao: someone who moves the historical WWII, and therefore belonging to a world thoroughly in
process along. The similarities between these barbarous heroes upheaval. Correspondingly, the philosophy underscoring The
and the more palatable ones (Christ, Gandhi, etc) are scarce, but Stranger is one of listlessness, dissatisfaction, cynicism, and
essential to understanding the nature of heroics. exhaustion. In short, the novel is consumed wholly by a preoccu-
An existentialist understanding of heroics may indeed dis- pation with the absurd. Camus’ conception of heroics inevitably
pense with moral considerations altogether. If for the sake of reflects this preoccupation, and subsequently, so does Meursault’s
argument we accept the core existentialist idea that morality is heroism. However, it is in The Myth of Sisyphus (also 1942) that
self-imposed, so that no one can be objectively more or less Camus most explicitly describes the heroics of absurdity. There
moral than anyone else, would it follow that heroism cannot he writes: “You have already grasped that Sisyphus is the absurd
exist? This seems unlikely: existentialists from Kierkegaard to hero. He is, as much through his passions as through his torture.
Camus have made reference to heroics despite their preclusion of His scorn of the gods, his hatred of death, and his passion for life
objective morality. So morality cannot be the basis of heroism, as won him that unspeakable penalty in which the whole being is
heroes no doubt exist but morality may not. Justness and moral exerted towards accomplishing nothing. This is the price that
conscientiousness may be sufficient for heroism, given certain must be paid for the passions of life.”
contexts and standards; but from an existentialist perspective, it Like many legendary heros, Sisyphus struggled (and, if myth is
cannot be necessary. Indeed, Kierkegaard’s greatest hero, Abra- to be believed, continues to struggle) against the will of the gods
ham, was but a few heartbeats away from murdering his own son. themselves. Sisyphus sought eternal life by challenging Death and
If morality is occasionally sufficient for heroism, but not nec- Hades, and so was punished with ceaseless, meaningless toil, by
essary for it, what trait unifies all heroes necessarily? It can be having to push a boulder up a hill only to watch it tumble back
nothing but bravery. Indeed, heroism and bravery are nearly syn- down again, for all eternity. This punishment is an attempt by the
onymous in the common vernacular. ‘Bravery’ can be under- gods to suppress Sisyphus’s freedom of choice, to make him into a
stood as performing actions even when one is afraid of either the mere object. However, to call it an ‘attempt’ reveals the possibility
actions themselves or of their consequences. To some profound for heroics for Sisyphus. The primordial authority of the
extent, then, bravery, and subsequently heroism, is defined Olympian gods bore down on Sisyphus, and to some extent, he
largely in response to fear – or, fear is the vacuum into which had no power but to submit; but even in the hopelessness of this
bravery and heroism flows. Every great hero, fictional or histori- unending torture, there remains the possibility of transcendence:

14 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Existentialism
this. For the legal system, crimes must have intent; there must
“Sisyphus, the proletarian of the gods, powerless and rebellious, knows the have been a motive. So as a matter of course, Meursault is
whole extent of his wretched condition; it is what he thinks of during his (justly) condemned by this institutional reaction to the absurd.
descent. The lucidity that was to constitute his torture at the same time crowns But in a certain sense, the legal system has become another
his victory. There is no fate that cannot be surmounted by scorn… if the component of Meursault’s consciousness of absurdity.
descent is thus sometimes performed in sorrow, it can also take place in joy.” He is sentenced to death, the most severe punishment
allowable by law. The absurd has ensnared Meursault, just as it
If Sisyphus were but a disembodied soul, there would be no did Sisyphus, snatched from the sea and sand to his toilsome
suffering. But we imagine him as an aching and ancient man, stone. Led to his cell, Meursault is expected to either repent
toiling in the mud and filth for all eternity. Yet in a great irony, and surrender to the whims of man, or suffer in terror until
the locus of Sisyphus’s intended suffering is the same as that of the drop of the blade. This expectation is predicated upon
his heroics: his embodied consciousness. We imagine him as both his consciousness of experiencing imprisonment and an
conscious of his suffering; but if one is conscious of his suffer- expectation of a consciousness of fear, to be terminated by his
ing, surely he can choose to be conscious of something else death. And for a time it works as intended: Meursault quakes
instead. As Camus says, there is no fate for consciousness that in his bunk each morning, awaiting the heavy footsteps of the
cannot be surmounted by consciousness of something else – by guard coming to take him to his end. It is not until after his
scorn for the gods’ decree, for example. And there is no scorn climactic rage against the prison chaplain that Meursault’s
so cutting and permanent as heroic joy. “We must imagine deconstruction of traditional expectations becomes clear.
Sisyphus happy,” Camus writes. Meursault was content with the pleasures and passions of
his world. He loved and longed for the sea and the bends of
Meursault’s Absurdity the coast, the alluring touch of a young lover, and the other
Let’s return to Meursault. In a world without gods, in which aesthetic joys of a casual life, just as did (or does) Sisyphus.
human experience reigns as the sole transcendence, heroism is When asked by the chaplain what he’d desire in death, Meur-
defined not by a scorn for the will of the gods, but instead by a sault replies curtly that he desires nothing more or less than
scorn for the machinations of man and for the contingency of his own life again – what else could a man desire at the end?
the universe. With this established, Meursault is the realization In the face of religion, Meursault remains unrepentant.
of an absurd hero. The absurd swirls around Meursault as it And in the face of society, he feels no guilt. He does not suffer
does us all, lurking beneath our glib rationalizations. For the concerns of others, nor does he submit to a fear of the
instance, we grind our noses against the absurd in the nauseat- absurd. The absurdity of Meursault’s world – personified and
ingly alien moments of semantic satiation, where the meaning- punctuated by his companions, the Arabs, the magistrate, the
fulness of the arbitrary structures of grammar and language prosecutor, the judges, and the priest – seeks to collapse him
collapse through the repetition of words. We also face the into a choiceless object, whose only remaining transcendence
absurd in those uncomfortably inexplicable but thankfully will be his suffering and death. But Meursault, the Algerian
momentary experiences of disembodiment. Sisyphus, resists this reduction to a choiceless nothingness,
The absurd is similar in operation to Sartre’s nothingness, in and in doing so, affirms his own transcendence. At the sight of
that it is first and foremost a function of consciousness. Only con- his own great stone tumbling down for the final time, Meur-
sciousness can offer the awareness of the absurd – thereby creat- sault merely shrugs his shoulders and begins his descent.
ing absurdity; and once experienced, it can never be forgotten.
The struggle against the absurd is consciousness’s ultimate battle. Absurd Heroics
Death is the supreme symbol of the absurd, since death rep- It is only conscious life that separates us from death, and
resents both the cessation of consciousness and an unknowable death can only come at the end of consciousness. Yet we fear it
phenomenon. It is in the depths of the struggle against absurdist as though it is something to be suffered, like an illness. Rather,
death that we find death is simply a bracketing of conscious life – no different in
Meursault at the end of function than birth. Fear of death is in actuality an expression
The Stranger. The crime of love for life. It is the fear of an unknown that steals our pos-
that has led him to the sibilities from us. But it is only while fearful that one can
guillotine was pointless, choose instead to be brave; and it is only while brave that one
insofar as we can tell: he can be a hero. Meursault routinely demonstrates radical brav-
has murdered an Arab, ery in the face of the absurd. He is not a good man; but he
but not out of passion attains a level of authenticity that few ever mimic. And he
or spite, nor even faces death with contentedness, taking responsibility for the
bloodlust. The act was man he chose to be. Thus he opens himself to the happiness
contingent upon noth- of Sisyphus. Hades kneels before Chaos, and Meursault awaits
ing but the bright sun. the scornful cries, comforted by their familiarity.
It simply happened. It © ALEX HOLZMAN 2016
was an absurd act. Alex Holzman is studying Political Science, Philosophy, and Psychol-
Marcello Mastroianni as Mersault in Of course, human law ogy at The College of New Jersey.
Visconti’s adaptation of The Stranger cannot comprehend

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 15


Existentialism
Why Camus Was NOT An Existentialist
Greg Stone presents the evidence.

W
hen Johnny Depp raises a wry eyebrow on screen, it, Sisyphus would have experienced nausea as he contemplated
it’s an ‘existential performance’. When Donald the alien substantiality – the ‘being-in-itself’ – of the rock.
Rumsfeld says there are ‘unknown unknowns’, So what is existentialism, and why does Camus not qualify?
they call it ‘existential poetry’. Though many politicians and In simple terms, Sartre believed that existence precedes
entertainers welcome the label, Albert Camus certainly did essence; Camus however contended that essence precedes exis-
not. Even so, many people, even in academic publications, tence. That is to say, in Sartre’s bleak cosmos, man becomes
have inaccurately identified him as an existentialist. What in conscious primarily of his existence as a free agent, and is then
the name of Nietszche is going on? condemned to forge his own identity – his essence – in a world
In an interview in Les Nouvelles Littéraires, 15 November, without God. Camus, on the other hand, was willing to posit
1945, Camus said point-blank: “I am not an existentialist.” He legal rules so absolute that they could be said to point to
went on to say, “Sartre and I are always surprised to see our ‘essences’ – among them a belief that almost all violence is
names linked. We have even thought of publishing a short immoral. Therein lies the foul: dogmatic principles for living,
statement in which the undersigned declare that they have no matter how well intentioned, are not ‘existential’.
nothing in common with each other and refuse to be held Although Camus is invariably linked with Sartre, whose
responsible for the debts they might respectively incur. It’s a name is synonymous with existentialism, they were an odd
joke actually. Sartre and I published our books without excep- couple, who clashed like Voltaire and Rousseau, or Verlaine
tion before we had ever met. When we did get to know each and Rimbaud. Sartre was tiny, plump, and ugly; Camus tall,
other, it was to realize how much we differed. Sartre is an exis- elegant, and handsome: Sartre played Quasimodo to Camus’
tentialist, and the only book of ideas that I have published, The Humphrey Bogart. Sartre famously described man as a “useless
Myth of Sisyphus, was directed against the so-called existentialist passion”; Camus described himself as a man of passion. Sartre
philosophers.” Camus compared existentialism to “philosophi- felt most at home in the dark cafés of Paris; Camus in the blaz-
cal suicide,” causing followers to “deify what crushes them” – ing sunlight of the Algeria of his childhood. Sartre wrote at
saying, in effect, that they turn negation into a religion. Camus Mozartian speed; Camus at Beethoven’s tortured pace.
in turn had a religion of his own – a quasi-pagan quasi-Greek Their political differences spilled into public view in 1952, in
reverence for nature. Case in point: Sisyphus, his hero of the the pages of Sartre’s newspaper Les Temps Modernes. By this time,
absurd, who is condemned to push a heavy boulder up a hill for Sartre’s views had evolved to include support for communism,
eternity, only to watch it roll down each time into the valley which Camus regarded as the extension of a harsh Teutonic
below. Sisyphus achieves a serene unity with the physical world: tradition stretching from Hegel to Marx, and reaching a per-
“The cheek tight against the stone, the shoulder bracing the verse conclusion in Stalin’s labor camps. He decried Marx’s
clay-covered mass, the foot wedging it, the fresh start with theory of history, dialectical materialism, and its use by com-
arms outstretched, the wholly human security of two earth- munists to “authorize any excess” in their quest for a classless
clotted hands” (The Myth of Sisyphus, 1942). In Camus’ version society. In his view there are no privileged executioners.
of the story, Sisyphus is happy. If Jean-Paul Sartre had written In his fashion, Sartre also opposed Stalin’s methods – while at
the same time claiming that mass imprisonment in the Soviet
Union was not as bad as one lynching in the United States. He
objected, however, to the exploitation of Stalin’s labor camps by
the ‘bourgeois press’ to fuel their anti-communist propaganda.
But after Camus’ taunt that Sartre was a detached intellectual
who merely pointed his armchair at history, Sartre stabbed back:
“My dear Camus: our friendship was not easy, but I will miss
it… I don’t dare advise you to go back to Being and Nothingness,
since reading it would be needlessly difficult for you… You are
only half-alive among us.” Privately, Sartre characterized
Camus as “a kind of schoolteacher, worthless in philosophy.”
Whew. I sum it up this way: Camus was a poet who wished
CARTOON © PHIL WITTE 2016

he could be an influential thinker; Sartre a deep thinker who


wished he could attain the eloquence of a poet. Camus stum-
bled with the minutiae of philosophical logic, and Sartre with
words – as anyone who has tried to read either closely will
quickly discover. Yet only one of them was an existentialist.
© GREG STONE 2016

Sisyphus sighs Greg Stone is a media consultant, independent producer and existen-
tial thinker in the Boston area.

16 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Albert Camus
by Woodrow Cowher
More work of his can be seen at
instagram.com/woodrawspictures August/September 2016● Philosophy Now 17
Existentialism
“all the consequences of this”
Kile Jones argues that atheistic existentialism is more compelling than
religious existentialism.
xistentialism, as I understand it, is primarily a philosophy (Danish for ‘dread’ or ‘anxiety’) in his famous work The Concept

E of tragedy. It often speaks of tragedy as bound up with


existence – that you cannot have one without the other.
of Dread (1844). Dread, according to Kierkegaard, comes from
within the individual (spirit) and from without (as an ‘alien
power’). Kierkegaard connects dread with the entrance of sin
Tragedy into human existence, the Fall of Adam and Eve. This brought
Before the rise of German, and in turn French, existential- with it dread, not of something external to the individual, but
ism, tragedy was considered primarily a poetic and literary style. as dread of one’s own self: “one will encounter the phenome-
We can think of Aeschylus’ Oresteia, Sophocles’ Oedipus Rex, or non that a man seems to become guilty merely for dread of
Euripides’ Alcestis as well-known examples of tragedy. Centuries himself.” Man also finds dread in his longing for release from
later, in Germany, the writings of Hegel, Schopenhauer, Niet- guilt. Kierkegaard writes, “the expression for such a longing is
zsche, and Jaspers. elevated tragedy outside of literary expres- dread, for in dread the state out of which a man longs to be
sion to a place of philosophical and existential importance. delivered announces itself…” The central existential paradox
Arthur Schopenhauer’s magnum opus, The World as Will and regarding dread is that man “cannot flee from dread, for he
Representation (1818) raises tragedy to “the summit of poetic art” loves it; really he does not love it, for he flees from it.” With
as it expresses “the terrible side of life”; Nietzsche’s early work dread, man continues the vicious cycle of: freedom-fall-dread-
The Birth of Tragedy (1872) argues strongly for a Dionysian rev- guilt, freedom-fall-dread-guilt, ad infinitum.
elry in tragedy; and Jasper’s Tragedy Is Not Enough (1969) finds Kierkegaard’s response to dread (and to most other prob-
tragedy to be a condition for the experience of transcendence. lems) is faith. He writes:
Karl Jaspers (1883-1969) was an existentialist philosopher
who saw tragedy as a launching pad for authentic faith. What “The one and only thing which is able to disarm the sophistry of remorse
he calls ‘tragic knowledge’ or ‘absolute and radical tragedy,’ is is faith… courage to renounce dread without any dread, which only faith is
comparable to Sartre’s or Camus’ notions of meaninglessness capable of – not that it annihilates dread, but remaining ever young, it is
or absurdity. Jaspers’ kind of tragedy is opposed to salvation or continually developing itself out of the death throes of dread. Only faith is
redemption, since they are both answers to it. As Jaspers says, capable of doing this, for only in faith is the synthesis eternally and every
tragedy is not enough – implying that we can, and ought to, instant possible.” (p.104)
move beyond the brute tragedy of existence. He says that “the
chance of being saved destroys the tragic sense of being Dread, like tragedy, should lead you somewhere; and in this
trapped without chance of escape.” In contrast, many atheist case, where you’re led is faith. Kierkegaard thinks that tragedy,
existentialists see the whole of human existence as tragic. paradox, and dread should lead one out of attempts to rationalize
The fact that Jaspers retains his ideas in the face of the tragic and towards a subjective ‘leap of faith’. Although Kierkegaard
nature of existence shows how he differs from atheist existential-
Oedipus and Antigone
ists (e.g. Heidegger, Sartre, Camus). These – myself included –
by Eugéne-Ernest
argue that the tragic nature of existence does not have an Hillemacher
answer; it is just how existence is. We cannot escape it, avoid it,
or supply a remedy for it. Therefore I argue that the atheist
existentialists develop a more authentic form of existentialism,
since they accept absolute tragedy and do not seek to dodge its
consequences. Sartre says, “when we speak of forlornness, a
term Heidegger was fond of, we mean only that God does not
exist and that we have to face all the consequences of this” (Exis-
tentialism and Human Emotions, 1957). So Sartre and other athe-
ist existentialists “face all the consequences of this” – while reli-
gious existentialists (such as Kierkegaard, Jaspers, and Marcel)
do not. They would be uneasy with Sartre’s notion, put forward
in his novel Nausea (1938), which carries radical tragedy to its
logical conclusion: “Every existing thing is born without reason,
prolongs itself out of weakness and dies by chance.”

Dread
Søren Kierkegaard (1813-1855) examined the philosophi-
cal, psychological, and theological implications of angest

18 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Existentialism
acknowledges that faith does not do away with dread, he thinks weak, and passive, a victim of forces beyond his control.
that it develops “out of the death throes of dread” and that faith The greatness of Nietzsche’s philosophy is that it encour-
is the courage to “renounce dread without any dread.” But what ages, uplifts, empowers, and revitalizes. It tells the individual
is renouncing other than conquering and moving beyond? And to conquer fear and self-pity by affirming her unique power in
what if, on the contrary, dread should lead you nowhere? the world. He tells us that the “greatness and fruitfulness and
Both Kierkegaard and Gabriel Marcel (1889-1973) argue the greatest enjoyment of existence is: to live dangerously.
against purely rationalistic answers to existential problems, since Build your cities under Vesuvius! Send your ships into
rationality cannot completely explain the subjective experiences uncharted seas! Live at war with your peers and yourselves! Be
of paradox and mystery. Rationalism also assumes a scientific robbers and conquerors, as long as you cannot be rulers and
stance of ‘objectivity’ that tacitly thinks it can gain certainty owners, you lovers of knowledge!” (The Gay Science, 1882).
about the external world and humanity’s relationship to it. Nietzsche, who was at once an admirer of Schopenhauer, later
Marcel is especially opposed to this. He thinks this kind of ‘sci- rejected Schopenhauer’s idea that one should resign oneself to
entific’ posture poses all inquiry in the form of problem and the cosmic Will. Nietzsche would rather think of the individ-
answer, and leaves out, or completely ignores, the idea of mys- ual as actively engaged in the world, and not, like Schopen-
tery. “A problem” Marcel says, “is something which I meet, hauer or Kafka, as a passive product of circumstances.
which I find complete before me, but which I can therefore lay Kafka, by contrast, shows how powerless humans are in the
siege to and reduce. But a mystery is something in which I face of forces beyond their control. His most popular fiction,
myself am involved” (Being and Having, 1965). He also says, “a The Metamorphosis (1915) is the story of Gregor Samsa, who
mystery, by definition, transcends every conceivable technique.” awakes to find himself turned into “a monstrous vermin” (usu-
Both Kierkegaard and Marcel acknowledge the role anxiety ally thought of as a cockroach). He cannot answer his door, he
plays in human experience, and yet they both see subjective can barely move, and the struggles he endures to get out of bed
experience as pointing towards something ‘beyond,’ and ‘tran- seem almost endless: “no matter how hard he threw himself
scendent’. They note how language cannot penetrate this realm onto his right side, he always rocked onto his back again.” The
beyond normal human experience, but they still choose to keep Metamorphosis has been thought to represent many different
this realm as a possibility. Why they choose to do so is beyond aspects of Kafka’s life and thought; but no matter what one
comprehension for rationalist atheist existentialists, who would thinks the story is an allegory of, the theme of powerlessness is
ask, why believe in anything indescribable or beyond compre- central. The never-ending struggle of any of Gregor’s projects
hension? Why not simply accept human existence on its own is illustrative of the torment experienced by those who feel
terms, as something radically and absolutely tragic, riddled with powerless. If placed in Camus’ story The Myth of Sisyphus,
anxiety and dread, from which there is no escape? So I think
both Kierkegaard and Marcel do not take anxiety and existen-
tial angst seriously because they think it points beyond itself to
a transcendental realm. The contradiction in Marcel’s thought
is that although he is against the scientific manner of framing
inquiry as problem/answer, he nonetheless retains mystery and
transcendence as potential answers to the problems posed by
existence. To be consistent, he and Kierkegaard, should have
abandoned those elusive phantasms, and carry tragedy and

PUPPETEER IMAGE © VADIM DOZMOROV 2016. PLEASE VISIT VADIM.CREVADO.COM


angst to their logical conclusions as Sartre argues.

Powerlessness
Many existential philosophers have described, sometimes in
vivid detail, what it is like to feel powerless. Social and political
forces external to you can take away your freedoms and
impugn you with guilt, creating a sense of powerlessness. Psy-
chological forces internal to you can do the same thing. The
internal forces are especially frightening because they occur
inside you and yet can feel beyond your control. They can
inculcate feelings of isolation, fear, and dread, along with a
sense of being trapped in your own personality.
A good way to explore the feeling of powerlessness is through
the work of those who have examined it in great detail. For me
the best exemplars of this are Nietzsche and the novelist Franz
Kafka. Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900) is well acquainted
with the forces, both internal and external, and thinks that we
ought to harness the power of our desires and affirm ourselves
by willing to live with dangerous confidence. Kafka (1883-
1924), on the other hand, depicts the individual as powerless,

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 19


“K. ends up in a constant war against
the bureaucracy and social norms of
the village surrounding the castle.”
Portrait of Franz Kafka by
Darren McAndrew 2016

20 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Existentialism
Gregor Samsa would spend his whole time struggling to move dity of the human condition. Those caught in the plague have
the boulder, and one can only imagine him unhappy. to deal with their own individual existential crises, but eventu-
Kafka’s protagonists are all similar. In The Trial (1925), Josef ally find themselves in solidarity with the infected.
K. is hauled off by authorities he does not meet for a crime of Many religiously-inclined people have argued that Sartre’s
which he is not even aware. At the end of his thirty-first year of and Camus’ thoughts on meaninglessness and absurdity lead
incarceration, Josef K. is executed. In The Castle (1926), protago- people to immorality, nihilism, and despair. Camus responds to
nist K. is sent (the story never says by whom) as a land-surveyor this idea in the ‘Three Interviews’ section of Lyrical and Critical
to a remote mountain village surrounding a castle. He is sent to Essays (1968). He’s asked, “Doesn’t a philosophy that insists
and fro, never being able to meet Count Westwest and so begin upon the absurdity of the world run the risk of driving people
his task. He ends up in a constant war against the invisible to despair?” and he responds, “Accepting the absurdity of
bureaucracy and social norms of the village. He eventually dies everything around us is one step, a necessary experience: it
there, never knowing what his purpose was, never completing should not become a dead end. It arouses a revolt that can
his task, and never coming to terms with the strangeness of the become fruitful.” So a recognition of absurdity can create an
village. Each of these characters are subject to the whims of impetus for positive social change.
powers outside of their control. Although they try, they never
accomplish any meaningful changes in the lot they were given. Atheistic Existentialists Take These Themes Seriously
As Sartre would say, they “prolong … out of weakness.” My argument is that only atheistic existentialists take exis-
Wisdom involves knowing when you can change things and tential themes seriously. They take them seriously because they
when you cannot. Reinhold Niebuhr contemplated this and are taken on their own terms: they do not try to remedy them
composed his famous ‘Serenity Prayer’, which asks God to with faith, mystery, or paradox. For instance, it is my con-
“grant me the serenity to accept the things I cannot change; tention that theistic existentialism is incompatible with what
courage to change the things I can; and wisdom to know the Jaspers calls “absolute and radical tragedy.” Tragedy and absur-
difference.” This prayer contains a kernel of truth. Whether or dity are given, partially understood by the intellect, and deeply
not we ought to orientate ourselves in a manner similar to felt at the level of the emotions. But in religious existentialism
Nietzsche or Kafka is a different question. I am of the opinion there is always something to which tragedy and absurdity point,
that even though the world is much as Kafka depicts it, we whereas I agree with Sartre and Camus that tragedy and absur-
should still have a Nietzschean orientation. We ought to act as dity point nowhere. They are not means to an end.
if we can change things, conquer fears, and affirm our lives. As To take tragedy and absurdity and the other issues seriously
Sartre constantly points out, the responsibility of our lives, our is to accept them as legitimate – not to be solved by resorting
projects, and our personalities, is on ourselves. We are the either to rational answers or to mystery and paradox, but to be
authors of our own life stories. pondered and investigated. But how does God’s existence or
non-existence factor into this? Does God’s existence or non-
Absurdity existence really make any difference? Sartre says of some
Absurdity is another important theme in existentialism. French teachers who tried to set up a secular ethic that, like
Absurdity in the existentialist sense is the contrast between Laplace, they thought of God as a “useless and costly hypothe-
human values, hopes and projects, and a universe which seems sis” (Existentialism and Human Emotions). He also said, “This, I
mockingly indifferent to them. Kierkegaard wrote about it in believe, is the tendency of everything called reformism in
his Fear and Trembling (1843), The Sickness Unto Death (1849), France – nothing will be changed if God does not exist.”
and in his posthumously collected Journals and Papers (1967). Against this type of thinking he says “the existentialist, on the
In Fear and Trembling, Kierkegaard praises Abraham because contrary, thinks it very distressing that God does not exist,
he “believed on the strength of the absurd.” In his Journals and because all possibility of finding values in a heaven of ideas dis-
Papers, Kierkegaard juxtaposes understanding and the absurd: appears along with Him.”
“Faith hopes for this life also, but, note well, by virtue of the Mary Warnock says the opposite to Sartre: “We may note in
absurd, not by virtue of human understanding.” He also thinks passing how little difference it makes to Existentialist theory
that “to see God or to see the miracle is by virtue of the whether it includes or does not include belief in God. For in
absurd, for understanding must step aside.” In this way practice there is no help to be found in believing in God” (Exis-
Kierkegaard uses absurdity to express the limits of reason, and tentialism, 1970). I disagree. Sartre was right that it makes all the
especially of ‘pure reason’. In this sense, Kierkegaard is in difference if a God exists or not. If He does, there are radical
agreement with atheist existentialists, who often speak of the consequences, not only metaphysically, but also existentially, psy-
impotence of human reason; but he is in disagreement with chologically, and practically; and if he does not there are similar
them when he speaks of a God reached by ‘the leap of faith’. radical consequences, many of which Sartre notes. If God exists,
Against Kierkegaard, Albert Camus (1913-1960) treats it would be strange to think of life as absolutely and radically
absurdity not just as something opposed to reason, but as a cen- tragic, because God, it is traditionally thought, gives meaning
tral quality of human existence. In The Stranger (1942), Camus’ to existence. So taking tragedy and absurdity seriously requires
protagonist Meursault does not conform to the social system he a belief in the non-existence of God, gods, and an afterlife.
is born into because he sees life as absurd. Camus says of him Many existentialists, Sartre included, think that the non-
that he is “condemned because he does not play the game.” In existence of God is ‘distressing’ and ‘disturbing’, since it
The Plague (1947), Camus uses an epidemic to reveal the absur- negates universal values. Indeed, the idea of a Godless world,

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 21


Existentialism
where humans are forlorn and abandoned, is frightening to can experience your pain and death for you. Your pain and
many people. This may be what keeps many people believing your death are yours only. So even in the face of the most diffi-
in God. However, I think, as Christopher Hitchens did, that cult existential experience, “God is of no use to us.” The
the idea of God’s non-existence may be disturbing at first, but responsibility can be only on the individual.
eventually you come to understand how horrific the idea of the
existence of God itself seems. Atheists may be without univer- Atheistic Existentialism Provides A Life-Affirming
sal values, but at least we’re not constantly watched and Philosophy For The Twenty-First Century
judged. This idea of God is similar to Orwell’s Big Brother: the If atheist existentialism takes tragedy, anxiety, powerlessness,
elusive ruler who controls everything, whom you must fear and absurdity seriously and to their logical conclusions, then it
and love, and who watches your every thought. This kind of is easy to see how this can give us a radical and life-affirming
God-created world is also ‘distressing’ and ‘disturbing’. philosophy for the twenty-first century. If we accept the themes
of the existentialist literature with seriousness, and if all respon-
Atheistic Existentialists Take These Themes sibility is on us, then since the themes of existentialism cannot
To Their Logical Conclusions be answered, remedied, or overcome, they should be embraced
When Sartre says, “God does not exist and we have to face and used as a way of affirming one’s individuality and as an
all the consequences of this” he is saying that we should take impetus towards living authentically. What follows from this is
the idea of a Godless world to its conclusions. In other words, a philosophy of action. And if there were ever a time when an
tragedy, anxiety, powerlessness, and absurdity fit perfectly with existential philosophy of human responsibility were needed, it
a Godless world, but when they’re given religious spin they would surely be now. Political unrest, globalization, social
lose their strength and fecundity. Tragedy, taken to its logical change, and the loss of modernist certainties, are only a few of
conclusion, is absolute; anxiety, taken to its logical conclusion, the paradigm shifts occurring at the present time. Feeling pow-
is anxiety without an answer; powerlessness, taken to its logical erless is an all-too-common phenomenon in the twenty-first
conclusion, shows how embedded we are in this world; and century. ‘Resignation’ and ‘life; have become almost synony-
absurdity, taken to its logical conclusion, is complete. To live mous, since political, social, and individual change often appear
authentically in the face of these themes is not to supply an to be utterly beyond our power. The bombardment of informa-
answer to them, but to know there is none. tion also stirs a sense of confusion, skepticism, and disdain.
One of the main reasons why I think atheistic existentialism The thinking of the millennial generation mirrors atheistic
is more authentic than religious existentialism, is that the existentialism in many ways. Its focus on the individual, on
former accepts the idea of radical responsibility. This kind of doubt, and on disenchantment with political systems, echoes
responsibility – usually associated with Sartre – says that we French intellectual life from the forties through the sixties.
cannot look beyond ourselves to find accountability. It’s true Although we are offered many ‘solutions’ to our current
that Kierkegaard, Jaspers, and Marcel also place responsibility predicament – New Age spirituality, religious hope, psychics,
in the agency of the individual; but they do so thinking that consumer commodities, lifestyle enhancers, pharmaceuticals –
God is watching, even if we do not take the leap of faith, or none of these offers seem authentic or realistic. They are
accept the mystery of being, transcendence, or the encompass- simply veils that hide the void between the haves (who present
ing. This is incompatible with an absolute idea of human themselves as happy) and the have-nots (who have limited
responsibility. Walter Kaufmann got it right when discussing venues to present themselves at all). Instead of examining and
Sartre. He wrote, “All man’s alibis are unacceptable: no gods evaluating the ways in which people orient their lives, we are
are responsible for his condition; no original sin; no heredity offered quick and easy ‘answers’. But we don’t need ‘answers’
and no environment; no race, no caste, no father, and no as much as we need honesty. Atheistic existentialism can help
mother; no wrong-headed education, no governess, no modern society by providing people with a philosophy that
teacher” (Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre, 1956). The accepts the tragedy and absurdity of existence while promoting
God of religious existentialism, no matter how elusive, myste- responsibility and authentic living. It can help people move
rious, and paradoxical, is still an alibi. past resignation into an orientation that affirms the uniqueness
Camus wrote an interesting story about the uselessness of of the individual and her projects. Her subjectivity, when seen
God when facing despair and other existential crises. In Irony in relationship to others, can create a sense of sympathy and
(1937), Camus tells of an old woman who is slowly dying and empathy. So against the idea of an ‘infinite distance between
is terrified by her isolation, and of dying alone, even though the self and the Other’ (see Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and
she’s religious; “her whole life was reduced to God.” She finds Infinity, 1961), I believe genuine and authentic communication
comfort only in a young man who tries his best to listen to and can take place, even if made difficult by the distance between
care for her. When the old woman’s relatives leave for the the individual’s authentic private self and her public expres-
movies, the young man hesitates out of pity: then “she saw that sions. Existentialism provides an ethic that honors individual
the one person who had taken an interest in her was leaving. projects and social responsibility, and encourages the sympathy
She didn’t want to be alone. She could already feel the horror and empathy that arise through communication.
of loneliness, the long, sleepless hours, the frustrating intimacy © KILE JONES 2016
with God. She was afraid, could now only rely on man… God Kile Jones is an atheist who does interfaith work. He has a Masters of
was of no use for her. All He did was cut her off from people Sacred Theology from Boston University, as well as a Masters of The-
and make her lonely.” This story illustrates that not even God ological Studies from the same place. His Twitter is @KileBJones

22 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Facts & Opinions
Christoffer Lammer-Heindel tells us some important facts about them.

F
rom a very young age we are encouraged to distinguish Facts & Knowledge
facts from opinions. Now the ability to distinguish facts Still, it is sometimes asked in response to controversial
from merely alleged facts, and the ability to distinguish issues, “Who determines what the facts are?”
opinions from considered judgments, is an important skill. This is an ambiguous question. On the one hand, the ques-
However, the fact-opinion duality is a false dichotomy which tion can be understood as asking, “Who would be in a position
rests on a category mistake. In claiming that facts and opinions to discern what the facts are?” This is a perfectly reasonable
stand in a dichotomous relationship, we ignore the two classes question to ask, since some of us are more equipped than
which stand in genuine opposition to each set in turn: facts are others to discern the facts in a certain area. For example, I
properly opposed to what we variously call non-facts, merely know very little about automobiles. As a consequence, I am in
alleged facts, fictions, or falsehoods; and opinions really stand no position to pronounce on whether the clicking noise I hear
in opposition to considered judgments. when I start up my car is caused by the fuel system, the timing
belt, or whatever. By contrast, I am in a position to determine,
A Fact Is Whatever Is The Case in the sense of discern or figure out, whether my wife picked
When someone asks, “Is that a fact?” they can be understood up our child from school this afternoon, whereas you are not.
as asking, “Is that really the case?” or “Is that ultimately true?” The ability to make an informed judgment as to what the facts
When someone says, “It is a fact that…” they are telling us, in are in a certain situation is a function of available evidence,
other words, “It is the case that…” or “It is true that…” That is, experience, training, and so forth. And of course, with respect
facts are not the statements themselves; they are, rather, the state to some issues, no one is in a position to discern the facts. (We
of affairs or the reality to which a true statement corresponds. will return to this point in a moment.)
Now it is neither necessary nor useful – indeed, it is posi- On the other hand, the question, “Who determines what
tively misleading – to define ‘fact’ in terms of what is indis- the facts are?” could be understood as asking, “Who makes it so
putably the case – yet people sometimes do. We should resist that something is or is not a fact?” When applied to the ques-
the temptation to endorse this qualification, for the simple tion of whether God exists, the answer is obvious: no one does.
reason that whether a particular matter is disputable or not has Neither the existence nor the non-existence of God (whatever
no bearing on what is the case. Moreover, there is very little the fact of the matter may be) is caused by human action; so no
that is not, at least in some sense, disputable. one makes it a fact that God exists, and no one makes it a fact
To appreciate that disputability has no bearing on whether
something is or is not a fact, consider the following case. It is
well-known that some people believe that Lee Harvey Oswald
did not kill John F. Kennedy, while many others believe that he
did. Both views are backed up by reasons and supported by at
least some evidence. So this is clearly a disputable issue. To say
that a point is disputable is to say, at the very least, that differ-
ent individuals hold different views on it. Nevertheless, there
is a fact of the matter as to whether Oswald was involved in the
assassination: he either was or he wasn’t. One of the two
options must be the case.
The same thing can be said about the question of whether
God exists. This is clearly a disputable issue, but we must recog-
nize that it either is the case that the being referred to by the
term ‘God’ (let us say, ‘creator of the universe’) exists, or it is not
the case that such a being exists. (The fact that people have dif-
fering conceptions of God doesn’t serve to undermine this point,
but simply to make it more complicated: for each conception
of God, the being so conceived either does or does not exist.)
Arguing about an issue doesn’t somehow make it into an
issue about which there is no answer. Indeed, genuine dispute
is only meaningful when there is an answer. It’s basically point-
less to engage in a dispute about something for which there is
no fact of the matter.

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 23


that God doesn’t exist. In this case, the fact of the matter is facts or opinions, and that no statement could express both.
totally independent of us. In the case of Oswald’s involvement McBrayer rightly points out that, contrary to the assumption
or lack of involvement in the assassination of President that forms the basis of that standard, the fact-opinion
Kennedy, Oswald was the one who made the fact what it is. dichotomy is a false dichotomy.
We, looking back on the incident and the evidence, do not. To say that statements must either express facts or express
This illustrates an obvious but rather important point. To the opinions, but not both, is a bit like saying that all fruit must
extent that people act, they clearly do make various things the either be an apple, or be produce available at my local grocer.
case and various things not the case. If I place my coffee cup on While a banana is clearly produce available at my local grocer
the table, I’ve made it a fact that the coffee cup is on the table but not an apple, and a Red Astrakhan – a relatively rare heir-
and I’ve made it a falsehood that the coffee cup is in the cup- loom apple – is an apple but not available at my local grocer, it
board. This is because I can interact with the physical world and is simply not true that every fruit must either be an apple or
change physical states of affairs, thus to that extent determining available at my grocer. Nor is it true that a fruit could not be
what the physical facts are. There are, however, facts beyond neither. The Granny Smith sitting in my fridge is clearly both
physical facts. For example, sometimes our actions take on an apple and available at my grocer, while physalis – sometimes
meaning and so create facts because of institutional rules that are known as giant ground cherries – are neither apples nor avail-
in place. When a sufficient number of individuals on a college’s able at my grocer.
board of trustees all vote to divest the college’s holdings in Com- To appreciate this analogy, we must clarify what an opinion
pany X, then it becomes a matter of institutional fact that the is. Clearly, the term ‘opinion’ denotes a kind of belief. In
college is not to hold shares in Company X. Similarly, when the common usage, an opinion is a belief which has not been suffi-
Pope speaks ex cathedra [meaning, with the agreement of all the ciently well-supported or substantiated to count as a consid-
cardinals, Ed] on matters of faith or morals, he makes it the case ered judgment. Indeed, beliefs can be usefully classified as
that those things become, as a matter of fact, Catholic doctrine. either opinions (beliefs which do not enjoy sufficient support
They will be Catholic doctrine whether other Catholics (and or justification) or considered judgments (beliefs which do
non-Catholics) agree with the proclamation or not, and regard- enjoy sufficient support or justification). This is a perfectly
less of whether we even care. appropriate dichotomy. Note, however, that it should not be
In these and myriad other ways, people do determine the confused with another equally important and legitimate
facts in the sense of make them. dichotomy: namely, the distinction between true beliefs and
false beliefs. Both every opinion and every considered judg-
Something Can Be A Fact Even If We Can’t Know It ment – in other words, every belief – will either be true or
Consider the claim, “At precisely the moment that the US false. This is a function of the fact that beliefs are about things
National Institute of Standards and Technology’s atomic clock or states of affairs and they will either comport with the facts
struck 15:00:00 on the afternoon of March 4, 2015, there were or not. So as with the fruit example, it is not true that a belief
an odd number of people inside the New York Public Library’s is either a fact or an opinion. Rather, an opinion may or may
Main Reading Room.” This claim is either true or false: it either not express a fact, just as a considered judgment may or may
was the case that an odd number of people were (completely) not express a fact. (And again, it is a separate issue whether the
inside the room at that time, or it was not the case. Now, if it was fact in question can ever be known or not.)
the case, then the claim would express a fact. If it wasn’t the case, It should be noted that a belief being false doesn’t automati-
it would express merely an alleged fact, which was (in fact) false. cally render it a mere opinion. Suppose that, in addition to
Notice, however, that we probably can’t know whether the claim lying to their child by telling her that Santa Claus exists, a
is true or false – which is to say that we can’t know whether it is couple also set out to create an elaborate ruse to provide the
a fact or not. Such is life. There are, quite literally, an infinite child with evidence (albeit concocted, misleading evidence) that
number of possible claims that we could make that we know Santa exists. It is perfectly possible that the child’s false belief
must be either true or false (it is a fact that there is a fact about in Santa has then risen to the level of a considered judgment.
it!), but we cannot possibly figure out their truth-values. For It is also worth noting that whether a particular belief is a
another example, it either is or is not a fact that Julius Caesar mere opinion or a considered judgment is highly variable: it’s
was red-green color blind; but it is doubtful that anyone will relative to the individual believer, and to a particular time in
ever now know what the fact of the matter is. their life, too. To return to the automobile example, my
mechanic and I could independently arrive at the belief that
Facts Are Not Properly Contrasted With Opinions the clicking noise I hear when starting up my car is caused by a
As I mentioned at the outset, facts are often presented as faulty valve in the engine. In my case, and considering the state
the opposite of opinions. Justin P. McBrayer, a philosophy pro- of my current knowledge (that is, my current ignorance), this
fessor at Fort Lewis College, Colorado, reported in the New would be nothing more than an opinion – just short of a wild
York Times' blog, The Stone in 2015(‘Why Our Children Don’t guess, really – whereas in the case of my mechanic, it would be
Think There Are Moral Facts’) that national education stan- a considered judgment (or so I hope). Now, let’s suppose that
dards in the United States require elementary school children the clicking noise is in fact caused by a faulty valve. In this
to learn to categorize statements according to whether they case, the statement “My car engine has a faulty valve”
express facts or express opinions – the assumption being that expresses a fact; but before my conferring with my mechanic,
all of the statements with which they’re provided express either my own belief would nevertheless be a mere opinion.

24 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


the matter under dispute, although we can and perhaps should
admit that the facts are sometimes very difficult to discern. Fur-
ther, as J.L. Mackie argued in his book Ethics: Inventing Right and
Wrong (1977), if there are no moral facts, it will turn out that all
beliefs dependent upon supposed moral facts will be false beliefs.
Philosophers have also long debated what kinds of facts
moral facts would be. Some have sought to reduce them to
other kinds of facts – for example, institutional facts or psycho-
logical facts – while others have claimed they are a unique and
irreducible type of fact. Matters of taste are sometimes thought
to be a close cousin of value judgments. Indeed, various
philosophers (such as David Hume) have entertained the pos-
sibility that moral judgments are nothing more than matters of
taste. Such views are interesting and worthy of careful, critical
PLEASE VISIT SIMONANDFINN.COM

examination, although it is beyond the scope of the present


article to consider them. What is within our scope is the wide-
spread claim that matters of taste are simply opinions.

Matters of Taste Are Not Opinions


Suppose someone declares that licorice is disgusting; we could
imagine another person responding by saying, “That’s simply
SIMON + FINN CARTOON © MELISSA FELDER 2016

your opinion.” In such a case, this latter claim clearly means


something like, “That’s just a matter of your personal taste.”
Now it is surely correct to say that whether licorice is dis-
gusting or pleasing is a matter of personal taste. To that extent,
labeling it a matter of opinion is understandable. Notice, how-
ever, that the meaning of ‘opinion’ here is very different from
the meaning used above, where an opinion is an insufficiently
supported belief. This difference in meaning is significant, for
in ordinary circumstances it would be a mistake to say that
one’s report that one finds licorice disgusting is an insuffi-
ciently supported belief. If one has tasted it and found it unap-
pealing, one’s declaration concerning its disgustingness is per-
fectly well-supported, so long as the disgustingness is under-
stood as being relative to the subject and not implied to be an
observer-independent (objective) quality of the licorice. Put
another way, it is a fact that this person finds licorice distaste-
ful; and this is perfectly compatible with it being a fact that a
different person finds it quite satisfying.

Conclusion
Properly understood, the term ‘fact’ refers to a state of
affairs or an aspect of reality, not to a class of beliefs. By con-
Moral Facts and Moral Opinions trast, ‘opinions’ and ‘considered judgments’ are types of beliefs,
In the context of a heated discussion about a controversial and those labels are most usefully used to distinguish suffi-
moral issue, it is not uncommon to hear the retort, “Well, ciently well-supported from insufficiently well-supported
that’s just your opinion,” where this is intended to mean that beliefs. The primary thing these distinctions reveal is that it is
the matter in question is something about which there can inappropriate to contrast facts with opinions. To do so is to
only be opinions, for there are no moral facts. make a category mistake: it is to treat facts in themselves as a
This is a view that enjoys a fair amount of currency in con- species of beliefs. Of course we have beliefs about what the
temporary society, and unlike some, I do not think it is a view facts are, and there are also psychological facts about what
that should be dismissed out of hand. It could end up being the individuals believe. However, maintaining a fact-opinion
case that those who believe that there are moral facts are mis- dichotomy only serves to cloud discussions that would be more
taken. There is nothing obviously incoherent about that view. productively oriented towards figuring out whether our beliefs
Yet it must also be emphasized that it isn’t obviously true that are justified and whether they conform to the facts.
there are no facts about what is moral, good, right, just, etc. © DR CHRISTOFFER S. LAMMER-HEINDEL 2016
There may well be objective moral facts. If moral matters are Christoffer Lammer-Heindel is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at
genuinely disputable, we must assume that there is some fact of Loras College, Dubuque, Iowa.

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 25


Bad Arguments That Make You Smarter
Henrik Schoeneberg gets smart about fallacious reasoning.

H
ave you ever heard of the Straw Man fallacy, or the Many fallacious arguments might seem trivial at first glance.
Red Herring fallacy? If not, perhaps you will be inter- Of course it is not right to assume that one rude tourist repre-
ested to know that these form parts of a set of con- sents an entire nation’s attitude; shouldn’t we know that? We
cepts that have the potential to enhance your thinking power. should, but we often don’t: in practice people often fall victim
In fact, by the time you finish reading this article you will have to the hasty generalization fallacy. Or how many of us have not
become smarter, because you will see the flaws in your own committed the argument from emotion fallacy; for instance, when
and others’ arguments more clearly. we unjustly blame each other because we’re upset? It would
Think of your brain as a toolbox. In the same way that have been better if we had calmed ourselves down before
there are tools for building, there are what philosopher Daniel trying to talk things through. But in fact, it is just because we
Dennett calls ‘thinking tools’. Language, for instance, is a are so prone to irrational thinking that it is very useful to be
thinking tool, because it enables us to think better, through acquainted with even the most apparently trivial types of fallac-
internal dialogue and by the sharing of ideas with others. ies. This way we’re reminded of our own irrational shortcom-
Whenever a useful new word is invented, a new thinking tool ings and we can better keep them in check. As they say at
is made available. addiction clinics, the first step toward being cured is to
It didn’t used to be thought that we require tools for think- acknowledge that you have a problem. Furthermore we
ing better. Classical economic theory, for instance, is based on become better at analyzing the arguments of others when we
the assumption that we tend to make rational decisions. How- know about what types of bad arguments there are. Categoriz-
ever, in the last hundred years, cognitive science has made it ing and naming bad arguments helps to systematize our
increasingly evident that we largely see the world through thoughts so that we can quickly point out what exactly is wrong
biases, and do not reliably think either rationally or objectively with an argument. So when we are acquainted with fallacies we
when left to our own devices, including in our economic become more persuasive debaters. Another handy attribute of
choices. To counteract these psychological tendencies, we need fallacies is that in talking about them we can use terminology
to make better use of the thinking tools that have been devel- that has the authority of logic! It may carry more weight if I
oped since Aristotle’s invention of logic. tell you that you’re using an ad hominem argument against me,
A particular step forward has been the identification and than if I simply say that I think it’s a bad way of arguing to
labelling of various different types of bad argument, collec- attack my character instead of my argument. So when we call
tively known as informal fallacies. These now go by widely-rec- someone out for using an ad hominem argument, they might
ognized and sometimes colourful names. For instance, an ad think, “If what she is pointing out to me has a technical name –
hominem (Latin for ‘to the man’) is a type of fallacy where you ad hominem – perhaps she really is onto something?”
counteract the force of someone’s argument by attacking their
character instead of their argument. This is a bad way of argu- More Biases & Fallacies
ing because what is usually important is not the messenger but The concept of fallacies is closely tied to the concept of
the message. Nonetheless, ad hominem arguments are widely biases. Some biases even have the word ‘fallacy’ in their names,
used in all kinds of situations – for instance in political cam- such as the gambler’s fallacy.
paigns, where disproportionate, irrelevant or downright dishon- A bias is a prejudice or a preconceived notion. Biases are
est personal attacks are often used to overshadow an opponent’s upheld either through pure ignorance or through fallacies. It is
actual arguments. a distorted interpretation of facts, and you need bad arguments

26 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


to support such views. So you can reduce your biases by
becoming more acquainted with fallacies and their illegitimate
claims to reason.
One of the most prevalent types of biases is the confirmation
bias. This is our tendency to seek out or notice information
that supports our pre-existing ideas, rather than to look for
unbiased information that draw us nearer to the truth. You can
see the confirmation bias operating in claims like this: “I’ve
read the health warnings, but my uncle smokes and he’s fine, happens that he thinks that
so smoking can’t be so bad.” In this case, the fallacy of general- energy supply is also important, and
ising from limited anecdotal evidence is used to counter the that priorities have to be chosen. A red
widely-established scientific finding that smoking can kill you. herring argument also presents itself if
someone says that it is wrong to be con-
A Dream of Reason cerned with animal welfare when there is so
Just being acquainted with some of the tools of reason can much human suffering going on. The concern for animals is not
change our frame of mind and make us more prone to think related to the point concerning human suffering, and bringing
rationally. This is why philosopher Ken Taylor’s twist on an unrelated argument into a debate in order to justify your
Plato’s ideal state ruled by philosopher kings isn’t so far position is a red herring. But in the case of both fallacies, as Rus-
fetched. Plato was right, he says; people generally are ruled by sell says, you have to make sure that you “look only at what are
appetite and passion rather than reason, so philosophers the facts and what is the truth that the facts bear out.” Otherwise
trained in the use of reason should rule. But not just an elite you risk jumping to hasty conclusions and falling into argumen-
few of them; instead we should strive to make philosopher tative traps.
kings – clear rational deep thinkers – out of everyone. Actively striving to follow the truth above all else and not
This was also the dream of Bertrand Russell. He too wanted taking for granted that we do is necessary for critical thinking,
to make us all better critical thinkers. When asked in a 1959 and this can be encouraged by getting acquainted with various
BBC television interview what advice he would give to future types of fallacies. It might surprise you how many straw men,
generations, Russell responded in a way that rather nicely pins red herrings, ad hominem attacks, hasty generalizations, and
down what any discussion of biases and fallacies amounts to: arguments from emotion, you can find all around you; and
“When you are studying any matter or considering a philoso- how much smarter it makes you just to have knowledge of
phy, ask yourself only what are the facts and what is the truth these fallacies.
that the facts bear out. Never let yourself be diverted either by © HENRIK SCHOENEBERG 2016
what you wish to believe or by what you think would have Henrik Schoeneberg has a masters degree in philosophy of science. In
beneficent social effects if it were believed, but look only and his home country of Denmark he is also the highest authority in the
surely at what are the facts.” field of Veterinary Communication – a subject he introduced to the
Danish veterinary profession. Teaching communication is one reason
Straw Men Eat Red Herrings why he has an interest in the subject of fallacies.
In light of this advice, let’s look at the concepts I mentioned
at the start.
The Straw Man is a fallacy where someone attacks a weaker Some Other Informal Fallacies
version of someone’s argument, or perhaps a weaker, different
argument for the same point – just as when soldiers train with • No True Scotsman
bayonets by attacking a straw man rather than the real enemy. (“No Scotsman puts sugar on his porridge” “No? But my Uncle Hamish
The Red Herring fallacy is a kind of distraction whereby some- does!” “Oh... well, no true Scotsman puts sugar on his porridge.”)
one wishing to oppose some conclusion produces and tears • Begging the Question (petitio principii)
down not just a weaker distorted version of the original argu- A type of circular reasoning where the conclusion supposedly to be
ment, but an entirely unrelated argument. The fallacy takes its proved is smuggled into the premises of the argument.
name from when a piece of smoked herring is thrown at fox • Appeal to Authority
hounds to lead them in another direction. In the following An illegitimate attempt to win argument by irrelevant claim of expertise
example, Sandy’s response to Peter is a red herring: • Appeal to the Stone (Argumentum ad lapidum)
The fallacy of dismissing a claim as obviously absurd without providing
Peter: “I don’t think we should build a new homeless shelter proof of its absurdity.
right now. We need more money to maintain the power grid.”
Sandy: “How can you not care about the homeless? That’s just Informal fallacies should not be confused with formal fallacies,
heartless.” which always involve a flaw in the logical structure of an inductive or
deductive argument. One example of a formal fallacy is Affirming the
Sandy attacks a different argument than Peter’s own point. Consequent. “If A is true, then B is true. B is true. Therefore A is true.”
Peter didn’t say he didn’t care about the homeless; he might be (This argument is flawed because B might be true even if A is not true).
volunteering at a soup kitchen for all Sandy knows. It just so

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 27


The Philosophy Professor &
The Holy Book of Baseball
Chris Christensen tells a story of contradictory rules and faith broken and restored.
softball game, a sliver of doubt pierced the professor’s pride. He
“If you look closely enough at a rule, the cosmos will appear in all its physi-
was sure of the rule, but what if he were wrong? Better check
cal, metaphysical, moral and spiritual aspects, presenting you a life’s work.”
– Ted Cohen the rule book. Rule 6.05(j): “A batter is out when after ... he hits
a fair ball, he or first base is tagged before he touches the base.”

T
ed Cohen, a philosophy professor at the Uni- So he was right. A tie means the batter is safe. But
versity of Chicago, was a fan of baseball Cohen continued reading, and found Rule 7.08(e):
and a student of its rule book. More “Any runner is out when he fails to reach the next
than a student, he considered The Official Rules base before a fielder tags him or the base …”
of Major League Baseball a divine document. “This was stupefying,” recalled Cohen. “The
Bertrand Russell once wrote, “Mathematics, anomaly seemed marvelous: if a runner is forced
I believe, is the chief source of the belief in to second base, he is out if he doesn’t reach
eternal and exact truth... In Plato, St Augustine, second before the ball, the opposite of the call at
Thomas Aquinas, Descartes, Spinoza, and Kant first base.” Checking further, Cohen comes
there is an intimate blending of religion and rea- across the stark brevity of Rule 6.09(a): “The batter
soning, of moral aspiration with logical admiration The professor becomes a runner when he hits a fair ball.”
of what is timeless... which comes from Pythagoras.” (A “My God,” Cohen continued, “I saw at once that with
History of Western Philosophy, 1945). Russell’s observation cap- 6.09(a) in the works, it was not merely an anomaly that I had
tures Professor Cohen’s reverence for baseball’s rule book. uncovered but that 6.05(j) and 7.08(e) are inconsistent with one
Cohen saw in its pages a Platonic ideal; it fitted Russell’s blend another. I cannot help putting it this way; I am a philosopher.
of mathematical logic and metaphysical longing, he thought. These two rules are contradictory. You see it, don’t you? The
He loved the book’s precise array of paragraphs and sub-para- rules in Section 6 concern the batter. Section 7 is about the
graphs; he reveled in its quaint, nineteenth century idiom, such runner. This led me to believe they could not ever be in conflict.
as: “The pitcher shall deliver the pitch to the batter who may But 6.09 tells us that under certain circumstances the batter is a
elect to strike the ball, or who may not offer at it, as he runner ... and if he arrives at first base simultaneously with the
chooses.” To Cohen the rule book was a thing of beauty, an throw, 6.05(j) says that he’s safe, while 7.08(e) says that he’s out.”
instrument of flawless perfection – until the day he found a flaw Cohen was deeply troubled by the logical rot that he had dis-
in the holy book, a day that changed his life. covered in the official baseball rules: “I had become extremely
It happened on a day in early June 1982. Cohen, along with fond of the rules,” he mused. “They have charm and, so I
a few other adults, organized a picnic and softball game for thought, precision ... Now I found them wanting to their core.”
Chicago youths. During the game, a batter hit a ground ball to
third and ran to first base, arriving at the same time as the Strike One
thrown ball. “Safe!” cried the team at bat. “Out!” yelled the He decided to write to Major League Baseball about the
team in the field. A dispute ensued, ending when an adult said, contradiction. He acquired the address of an executive, the
“It was a tie. Let’s let him be safe.” That satisfied the children, Administrator of the National League of Professional Baseball
but not the philosophy professor, who chimed in, “If it was a Clubs. Before he began writing, his wife offered two sugges-
tie, then you don’t have to let him be safe; he was safe. The tions that she thought would enhance his chances. First, he
rule says that the runner is safe unless the ball arrives before should use University of Chicago stationery. He hesitated,
him. If the ball arrives at the same time, then it doesn’t arrive thinking it might compromise his university and his depart-
before him, and so he is safe.” Cohen had silenced the other ment. “But my wife saw the truth,” he later wrote, “that my case
adult while gaining the awe and respect of the children. “I was was proper and urgent, and indeed the university should be
trembling with a sense of moral triumph,” he recalled. “I can proud that another of its faculty was entering history.” Her
remember nothing else from that game.” second suggestion was that he write “with no attempt at humor
The professor had an overbearing streak, to be sure, but he or irony, but that I just do the job.” So he wrote “seriously and
was the first to acknowledge it. He was also known to be a carefully, with all the lucidity” he could manage. Still, he
kind and loving man. He was liked and respected enough to thought he might be dismissed by the Administrator as a crank,
have served as the Chairman of the Philosophy Department, his letter consigned to a trash can. But to his delight he got a
and was also elected President of the American Philosophical reply a week later from the Administrator of the National
Association (2006-7). He adored music, was a drummer in a League, who thanked him and said the Rules Committee would
jazz band, and loved a good joke. He even published a wonder- look into his “interpretation” at its December meeting.
ful book on the philosophy of jokes. He was ecstatic. Already upon finding the flaw in the rules,
But the rule book was no laughing matter. Soon after the Cohen had “anticipated the statutory immortality that would

28 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


be due me.” Now he was truly energized. “Before it had been a he walked to the plate, Cohen knew exactly what he would do.
lark,” he said. “Now it was a serious lark.” He would use Rule 6.09(b): “The batter becomes a runner when
This correspondence took place in the fall of 1982, a few the third strike called by the umpire is not caught...”
months after the softball game. December, the month of Rules He swung weakly at the first two fastballs, then hoped for a
Committee meetings, came and went. Cohen got no word. He wild pitch. He got one. “This time the ball sailed at least five
waited until June and wrote again, asking what had happened. feet over my head, and I swung. I did not swing unvoluntarily,
In his reply the executive explained that umpires present at the nor was I enfeebled by fear. I did it on purpose, with calcula-
meeting said there were never any ties at first base, adding that tion, and I immediately dashed for first base. I was safe by a
to make a ‘special’ rule allowing for ties would be too confusing. mile.” He stood on first base, thrilled to the core. “I had never
Cohen was dismayed. He asked himself, “What am I to say been as proud of myself athletically as I was in that moment, in
of that?” and consulted a friend, a professor of physics, who which I had overcome the finest pitcher I knew. I could not do
assured him that “it is perfectly possible for a foot to touch a it by hitting, but I had done it by knowing the rules and think-
base at the same time as a ball touches a glove.” He had an ing fast despite a nearly paralyzing fear. And then my soul was
urge to write again, marshalling a new argument, but he now squeezed. By my teammates. They did not care for what I had
realized that Major League Baseball didn’t really care, and done. They regarded me as someone who did not really grasp
would think he truly was a crank. “But I cannot rest,” he the nature of the game; they knew the game in some other
wrote. “If anything in this world could be right, it is baseball; way. It was this ache that reappeared when I heard the last word
but baseball isn’t right with its current rules. I can’t stand it.” from the National League of Professional Baseball Clubs.”
What good are the rules if no one knows them? What good
A Philosopher At First Base is it to know the rules when no one believes you? And what if
Despondent, he retreated to memories of his youth: “I have they believe you but just don’t care?
been reminded, with pain, melancholy, and sweetness, of my
personal discovery that I could never play baseball at a high Fixing The Rules
level.” His realization came as a high-school player, when he Thoroughly demoralized, Professor Cohen returned to his
came to bat against a fastball pitcher renowned for his wildness. academic life. But he wasn’t done. He may not have been
The first two pitches zipped by – both strikes. Cohen describes aware of it, but something started percolating. It percolated for
what happened next: “The third pitch was wild, coming right at ten years. Then he sat down and wrote a prize-winning essay
my head; at least as I saw it, and I leaped backward in terror. recounting his impasse with the rules committee. ‘There Are
The terror is still with me. It is permanent.” He struck out on No Ties at First Base’ (from which the framework of this story
the next pitch. “I knew that I would always strike out against is taken) was first published in the Yale Review in 1992. Later
that pitcher. And that was painful, but it was not the occasion for that year it was reprinted in Elysian Fields Quarterly, a literary
the metaphysical pain that I recalled when I struck out with the journal devoted to baseball. It’s quite probable that some read-
rules committee.” That pain came with the next time at bat. As ers of the essay wrote to the rules committee, asking why it
hadn’t fixed the flaw found by the professor. Probably because
the amount of mail was small, the committee ignored it. But it
couldn’t ignore the third printing of the essay twelve years
later. In 2004, ‘There Are No Ties at First Base’ was published
in a briskly-selling anthology titled Baseball and Philosophy. By
then the internet and email were in full stride. It’s more than
probable that the trickle of mail from the earlier printings
grew into a steady stream, if not a torrent. The committee
could no longer turn a blind eye. At long last, in 2010, the cor-
rection appeared – or rather, the contradiction of the rules dis-
appeared – from The Official Rules of Major League Baseball. It
took 28 years, but thanks to the power of the professor’s pen,
combined with a small army of lesser pens, Professor Cohen’s
broken rule book was made whole.
Ted Cohen died on March 14, 2014. He was 74. He never
got credit from the rules committee, but his ‘statutory immor-
tality’ lives on among his fellow fans of philosophy and base-
ball. As for the members of the rules committee, they no doubt
looked closely at the rules in order to fix them, but one may
doubt that when they did so the cosmos appeared to them in
all its physical, metaphysical, moral and spiritual aspects.
© CHRIS CHRISTENSEN 2016
Chris Christensen is a delivery driver in Portland, Oregon. In addi-
tion to studying philosophy, he and his wife Bobbie produce a blog,
Baseball
Red Stitches: Mostly Baseball.

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 29


Science, Ockham’s Razor
& God
David Glass and Mark McCartney say Ockham’s razor doesn’t cut it with God.

T
he idea that science has explained God away is very the world … Two thousand years ago, it was perfectly reason-
popular. The suggestion is that as science explains able to invoke God as an explanation for natural phenomena;
more and more about the world there is less and less now, we can do much better.” (The Blackwell Companion to Sci-
need for God. Sometimes this is expressed in terms of ence and Christianity, eds J.B. Stump and A.G. Padgett, p.196,
Ockham’s razor. William of Ockham was a medieval philoso- 2012).
pher and theologian, and his famous ‘razor’ is the idea that “It But some caution is needed. If Ockham’s razor is used prop-
is futile to do with more things that which can be done with erly it can be a very helpful tool, but if used incorrectly it can
fewer.” Applied to science and God, the implication seems to become a dangerous instrument. First, consider a scenario
be that if science can explain the world around us on its own, where Ockham’s razor works. Suppose your car won’t start.
there is no need for science and God. There is no need for two Two possible explanations are a) that the battery is faulty and b)
explanations when one will do. that the starter motor is faulty. You call a mechanic who quickly
This kind of reasoning is central to the New Atheism. The determines that there is indeed a problem with the battery.
late Christopher Hitchens appealed explicitly to Ockham’s Since this would explain why the car didn’t start, there is no
razor as part of his case against God and the same idea is found longer any reason to think that there is a problem with the
in Richard Dawkins’ The God Delusion (2006) where he claims starter motor. Ockham’s razor removes the need for the further
that “Historically, religion aspired to explain our own exis- explanation. Or to put it another way, the truth of the faulty
tence and the nature of the universe in which we find our- battery hypothesis has explained away the faulty starter motor
selves. In this role it is now completely superseded by science.” hypothesis. Of course, it is possible that there is a problem with
In claiming that science explains God away, Dawkins focuses both the battery and the starter motor. That cannot be ruled out
in particular on “Darwin’s destruction of the argument from until the car starts, but it would be really unlucky; based on the
design.” Outside the New Atheism, cosmologist Sean Carroll evidence so far and the application of Ockham’s razor, one
sums up the view clearly, “Over the past five hundred years, explanation is sufficient.
the progress of science has worked to strip away God’s roles in Now consider another scenario. A road traffic accident has
taken place near a set of traffic lights. Based on preliminary evi-
dence relating to the scene and the condition of one of the dri-
vers, the police propose two possible explanations: a) that the
driver of one of the cars went through a red light and b) that
this same driver had been drinking. Sure enough, further evi-
dence confirms that the driver had indeed been drinking.
Could we now apply Ockham’s razor as before and conclude
that there is no longer any reason to think the car went
through a red light? No, in this case it is quite plausible to
think that the two explanations go together. The two hypothe-
ses are needed to account for all the evidence and alcohol con-
sumption could explain why the driver went through a red
light. It would be inappropriate to apply Ockham’s razor in this
case since doing so could very easily lead us astray.

Cut Here!
So how do you decide in a particular case whether Ockham’s
razor can be applied legitimately to use one hypothesis, A, to dis-
miss another hypothesis, B? In some recent work (‘Can evidence
for design be explained away?’, in Probability in the Philosophy of
Religion, eds J. Chandler and V. Harrison, 2012; and ‘Explaining
and explaining away in science and religion’, Theology and Science,
12(4), 2014), we’ve proposed both a formal account based on

30 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


probability theory and an informal account based on answering a burne, it still makes sense to search for an
number of questions including the following: explanation for the fact that the uni-
verse operates according to such
Question 1: Are the two hypotheses A and B mutually exclu- laws and the best explanation is
sive? If so, then accepting A requires rejecting B and indeed provided by theism. Here, the
vice versa. Clearly, this can give rise to a trivial version of idea is that theism provides a dif-
Ockham’s razor, but it is much more interesting to consider ferent kind of explanation; a per-
cases where A and B are not mutually exclusive. sonal, not a scientific, explanation.
Question 2: Does one of the hypotheses depend on the other? Design arguments based on the
If so, that reduces the potential for applying Ockham’s razor. fine-tuning of physical parame-
Question 3: How likely is it that the available evidence would ters would provide a further
have been produced by each hypothesis on its own? If the reason for thinking that science
answer is ‘very likely’, that increases the potential for Ockham’s depends on theism, as would the-
razor. istic arguments based on the com-
Question 4: Is there good reason to accept hypothesis A? If prehensibility and mathematical
not, this reduces the impact of Ockham’s razor in cases where it nature of the universe. Others have
could occur. argued for a historical dependence
between science and theism on the
Let’s apply these questions to our two scenarios. In the case grounds that modern science devel-
of the car not starting, while the two explanations were not oped in a theistic context and that it
mutually exclusive (Question 1), the answers to Questions 2-4 was because of theistic beliefs, such as
help us see why Ockham’s razor is appropriately applied. It belief in God as a rational creator and
seems that neither hypothesis depends strongly on the other God’s freedom in creation, that sci-
(Question 2), either explanation could account for the evidence ence took off.
on its own (Question 3), and the mechanic has found out that If there is in fact any kind of depen-
one of them is indeed true (Question 4). In the case of the road dence of science on theism and hence a
traffic accident, the two explanations are not mutually exclusive positive answer to Question 2, the case
(Question 1), there is a dependence between them since one for applying Ockham’s razor to explain
could explain the other (Question 2), and both are needed to God away through science is very weak
account for all the evidence (Question 3). In this case, confir- indeed. Proponents of applying Ockham’s
mation that the drink driving hypothesis is true (Question 4) razor in this way will be quick to object to
does nothing to undermine the other explanation. the theistic arguments in the last paragraph;
How does all of this relate to science and God? How can we our purpose here is not to defend them but
use it to evaluate the claim that via an application of Ockham’s to draw attention to the fact that a
razor the progress of science explains God away? Let’s consider number of them, as well as objections
each of our questions in turn. to them, are relevant to our discus-
In response to Question 1, it is clear that science and theism sion and that serious philosoph-
are not mutually exclusive. Sometimes atheist popularisers ical points are put forward
might claim that they are, but there’s no good reason to think on both sides. The point
that science and theism are logically incompatible. If one is to is that proponents of
argue that science removes the need for God, it will have to be applying Ockham’s
an argument – like that of the New Atheists – that involves a razor against
non-trivial application of Ockham’s razor. The point would be,
not that science logically refutes God’s existence, but that it
makes God redundant.
Question 2 asks whether there is a dependence between sci-
ence and theism. Many theists have argued that there is indeed.
Some versions of the cosmological argument claim that the
very existence of the universe, and hence science, depend on
God. Similarly, an important version of the design argument
defended by Richard Swinburne in The Existence of God
(2004) is that theism provides the best explanation for William of Ockham’s actual
the order in the universe expressed in the laws of sci- razor, recently discovered in a
ence. The point of that argument is not to undermine drawer in a Belgian
science, but just to say that it cannot do the impossible monastery
since whatever the most fundamental scientific laws (or
law perhaps) turn out to be, they cannot themselves be
given a scientific explanation. Yet, maintains Swin-

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 31


God can’t simply assume that these theistic arguments fail if
their use of Ockham’s razor is to have any force. Maybe there
are serious flaws in these theistic arguments, maybe not, but to
avoid begging the question in their application of Ockham’s
razor, its proponents need to engage in detailed philosophical
work to show that these theistic arguments fail, or else risk a
positive answer to Question 2.
This weakens the appeal of the strategy. It might have been
thought that a combination of science and Ockham’s razor
would somehow shortcut this process by avoiding the need to
refute detailed philosophical arguments for God’s existence,
but that is not the case. It’s worth comparing this argument
against God with the problem of evil (the claim that the exis-
tence of suffering in the world makes it unlikely that there is a
God who is simultaneously all-good, all-powerful and all-
knowing). Whatever the merits of the problem of evil as an
argument against God, it can be considered to some extent in
isolation from other theistic arguments. One could argue that
the problem of evil has some force against the existence of
God while setting aside the question of whether other argu-
ments might count in favour of God’s existence. Given the
importance of Question 2 in determining whether Ockham’s
razor can be applied, it seems that this isolation from other
theistic arguments isn’t available in the current context. It’s
interesting to note that while using science and Ockham’s
razor to explain God away is very popular in the New Atheism
and in Internet discussion, such an argument is rarely to be
found in the philosophical literature. Atheist philosophers tend
to focus on more standard objections to belief in God such as
the problem of evil and are perhaps aware of just how difficult
it is to make a convincing argument based on science and an
application of Ockham’s razor.
Question 3 is more difficult to answer in an abstract sense, accept what science tells us about the world, while also accept-
but becomes more relevant in particular cases where science ing that science is fallible. In some cases, the truth of a hypoth-
might be thought to explain God away. We will consider it esis could make the application of Ockham’s razor much more
presently in a specific discussion of evolution. It is important plausible, as it did in the earlier example of the car not starting.
to note that theists often think about theistic explanations of In other cases, like the road traffic example, Ockham’s razor
features of the world as working not in isolation from science, does not apply and so Question 4 is not relevant. Learning the
but via scientific laws. Natural phenomena are to be explained truth of one hypothesis in this case does not undermine, and
directly by science and only indirectly by God. One way of may well enhance, the other. Even in cases where Ockham’s
putting this is to say that God acts through causes which can razor might be applicable, the mere possibility of one hypothe-
be described scientifically. Think of this is in terms of a causal sis being true is not sufficient for its application. For example,
chain where A causes B and B in turn causes C; A’s influence in the case of the car not starting, Ockham’s razor can be
on C comes via B. An interesting result of our formal account applied once we have good reason to believe that there is a
of the applicability of Ockham’s razor was to show that it does problem with the battery, but the mere possibility of there
not apply to causal chains. Here’s a simple example. Suppose being such a problem would not merit application of the razor.
your friend has arranged to get the train and meet you at the This is relevant here because sometimes ideas that are not sci-
railway station after work, but he isn’t there at the specified entifically well established are appealed to by atheists in just
time. One explanation might be that he missed the train while this way. For example, in response to the apparent fine-tuning
another might be that he was delayed at work. The evidence of natural laws as evidence for God, it is sometimes claimed
shows he missed the train, but even so, Ockham’s razor clearly that the possibility of a multiverse removes the need for God.
wouldn’t dispose of the hypothesis that he was delayed at work. Whatever the merits of fine-tuning arguments, it should be
Why? Because his being delayed at work could have caused clear that pointing to the mere possibility of a multiverse is
him to miss the train. Similarly, if the above account of God inadequate as a response.
acting through natural causes is correct, then Ockham’s razor
cannot be applied against God even if natural causes appeared Evolving Explanations
to explain all of the physical evidence available to us. The most famous specific topic in science which might be
What about Question 4? We surely do have good reasons to thought to explain God away is, of course, evolution and

32 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Philosophical Haiku
design. Given the success of Darwin’s theory of evolution by
natural selection (and so a positive answer to Question 4),
does it remove the need for God as an explanation of intelli-
gent life? In response to Question 1, evolution and God are
not mutually exclusive. Some people might claim that evolu-
tion requires atheism, but this far outstrips any claim that sci-
entific evidence can establish. Besides, those like Dawkins,
who use evolution to argue against God do so not on the
basis of their logical incompatibility, but in terms of
Ockham’s razor since evolution is claimed to remove, not dis-
prove, God.
With regards to Question 2, there are multiple reasons
that could be given by theists for thinking that evolution
depends on God. Clearly, evolution requires an orderly,
physical universe with appropriate scientific laws in place as
well as the very fine-tuning of its physical parameters. All of
these features of the universe form the basis of some of the
main theistic arguments found in the contemporary litera- SØREN KIERKEGAARD (1813–1855)
ture. As with our earlier discussion of Question 2, propo- Laughter masks despair
nents of an evolutionary case against God will reject these Reason crucified by faith
arguments, but given their relevance they cannot be set aside We must ourselves choose.
without begging the question. In other words, showing that
evolution explains God away will require detailed arguments ierkegaard is seen today as one of the founders of existential-
to show that the features of the world that are necessary for
evolution do not also support a belief in God.
With regards to Question 3, the likelihood of intelligent
K ism, with its emphasis on the need to choose for oneself how to
find meaning in this godless life. But existentialism of this kind is
not exactly what Kierkegaard had in mind. Over the course of his short
life having arisen solely through unguided evolutionary life, and writing under a bewildering range of pseudonyms (which help-
processes is far from clear. This is not a criticism of the fully allowed him to criticise his own works later on), he knitted
theory of natural selection, but just recognises that the evolu- together the disparate skeins of moral psychology and Christian theol-
tion of intelligent life might well be dependent on some ogy to form an elaborate garment quite unlike anything seen before
highly fortuitous events having occurred in the history of life (and not necessarily one you’d want to wear out of the house). Project-
on Earth. Richard Dawkins, for example, says of the origin of ing his own misery onto the world, he diagnosed a collective case of
life as well as other evolutionary transitions that they might despair as the world’s great ill. Many people don’t even realise they are
have needed to be ‘bridged by sheer luck’ (The God Delusion, suffering this despair, foolishly mistaking it for joy – that’s how ignorant
p.140). Irrespective of whether, and if so how, God might people can be! You’re laughing, but really you should be crying!
have guided natural processes to bring about intelligent life, We are free to choose for ourselves how we will live, and indeed we
this suggests a negative answer to Question 3 and so raises a must do so – this is the human condition. Yet Kierkegaard argued that
serious problem for attempts to apply Ockham’s razor in this with no philosophical basis for the spirit, there’s no basis for composed
context. This brief discussion of evolution suggests that it is selfhood, so we are left to drift hither and yon at the whims of the tide,
very doubtful that Ockham’s razor can be applied here. And if directionless, lost, and bewildered. Thus, in the spiritual wasteland that
it can’t be applied here, it seems unlikely it can be applied is the world, people turn to religious cults, worship false idols such as
successfully anywhere in an attempt to explain God away. Beauty, delude themselves with utopian political visions (quo vadis,
In conclusion, we have attempted to show why using sci- Proudhon?), or just wearily give themselves up to insanity (my pre-
ence and Ockham’s razor to explain God away is very ferred approach) – anything to escape the frightening emptiness. But in
unlikely to be successful. No doubt it is a tempting strategy his humorous [sic] analysis of this condition entitled The Sickness unto
for some atheists. Its appeal both to science and to a legiti- Death (1849), Kierkegaard held out the possibility of meaningful exis-
mate tool of scientific reasoning – the razor itself – seems to tence. We can establish a basis for our selves by accepting the possi-
offer the possibility of a powerful and straightforward argu- bility of a transcendent power through faith. But we are in error if we
ment against theism that circumvents the need to get seek this condition through the exercise of reason – it is not for reason
involved in the details of standard philosophical arguments to comprehend the mysteries of faith. In this, Kierkegaard sounds
for the existence of God. However, our analysis of the valid much like William James, who talked of the ‘will to believe’.
uses of Ockham’s razor suggests that nothing could be fur- Shortly before he died, Kierkegaard spoke with a friend, saying, “I
ther from the truth. pray to be free of despair at the time of my death.” Don’t we all.
© DAVID H. GLASS AND MARK MCCARTNEY 2016 © TERENCE GREEN 2016
David Glass and Mark McCartney are Senior Lecturers in the Terence is a peripatetic (though not Peripatetic) writer, historian and
School of Computing and Mathematics at Ulster University. This lecturer. He holds a PhD in the history of political thought from
article is based on work that was carried out as part of a project Columbia University, NYC, and lives with his wife and their dog in
funded by the John Templeton Foundation. Wellington, NZ. He blogs at hardlysurprised.blogspot.co.nz

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 33


Question of the Month
Is Morality Objective?
???
The following answers to this key philosophical question each win a random book.
into which they are incarnated. For instance, it has never been
I t is clear that morality is a feature of humanity. However, if
morality were objective then every member of our species
would share the same moral values. But it is patent that we do
the case (as far as we know) in any culture, at any time, that a
man (even the chief) can take whichever woman he wants to be
not share the same moral values. For example, there’s clearly a his wife. In Britain today she has to be over sixteen, and in
lack of moral consensus with respect to our views on euthana- other countries her age may be higher or lower. Also, someone
sia, abortion, or our treatment towards non-human animals. has to give consent to the marriage; either the woman herself,
For any given moral situation various factors exist that must or her family, or the elders of the tribe, or the chief’s other
be taken into account. So, before we can judge whether an act wives! Whatever the ‘subjective’ cultural differences, the same
is right or wrong we need to evaluate several things: the differ- objective moral principle applies.
ent personalities of the people involved – their emotions, inten- We can no more invent a subjective morality than we can
tions, intuitions – as well as the consequences of the act. These invent a new primary colour. We can no more come up with a
factors can relativize the morality of an action. For example, an novel morality which is in no way connected to an objective
uptight person may expect us to always tell the truth no matter morality than we can come up with a new way of breathing.
what, but in a situation where someone is extremely sensitive it KARL WRAY
might be justified to tell a lie to spare their feelings. CARLISLE, CUMBRIA
Even great moral philosophers disagree about the nature of
morality. Immanuel Kant’s influential duty-based theory of
ethics maintains that truth-telling is universally binding on all
rational beings. Thus, if a serial killer demands to know where
H ere I will treat ‘objectivity’ as the property of an idea or
object that let’s it be evaluated in the same way indepen-
dently of who the evaluator is. Evaluating morality in light of
you’re hiding your sibling, Kant’s absolute system would aver this, we face two components that pose a potential threat to
that you tell the truth because it is not possible to consistently moral objectivity: space and time. For instance, when the Con-
universalize the act of telling any kind of lie. On the other quistadors arrived in South America at the beginning of the
hand, John Stuart Mill’s utilitarianism would insist that you lie Sixteenth Century, they were shocked at various rituals of
to the serial killer because this would most likely maximize the human sacrifice practiced by the Incas. Those rituals were
greatest amount of happiness or pleasure by minimizing the morally wrong to the Spanish, who had been brought up with
unhappiness or pain for you and your sibling. the morals of another culture on a different continent. The
In a pristine world of crystallized moral ideals, perhaps vast majority of people in South America today will likely
morality could be objective and universally binding on all peo- agree that human sacrifice is wrong, so we can see that
ple. However, we live in a world of moral flux, impermanence, accepted morality has strongly depended on time and place.
and flexibility. And it is because of this that morality is not nor However, with the increasing interconnectedness among
could ever be objective. mankind through the internet and especially social media, I
ALBERT FILICE suppose that the spatial component will get lost some day. We
SCOTTSDALE, AZ may see this in vegetarianism and veganism. Although both
diets existed in ancient times, there had never been a spread of
those ideas as remarkable as in these times of hashtags, blogs
Y es, morality is objective. (By ‘morality’ I mean that which
we all recognise as right behaviour – that which we call
‘good’). Have you ever tried making up your own morality and
and the international exchange of bits within milliseconds.
Furthermore, although a high number of people are still being
applying it to your family and friends? If you have, you could treated unethically, we also must acknowledge that we have
well be reading this magazine whilst sitting in a prison cell or an come to a more or less internationally congruent understand-
asylum. ing of a morally correct treatment of people.
Certainly many people have attempted to invent their own How objective should we rate this development? On the
morality and then impose it on others, for instance, Stalin, one hand, we have never been closer to an objective (in terms
Hitler, Mao Zedong, and Pol Pot. And look what they created of a universally acceptable) morality. On the other hand, we
– a new Humanity, a new Society! Does anyone fancy living in need to ask ourselves whether the temporal component may
their morally subjective worlds? Each led to inhumanity and still pose a threat. If you asked Plato whether 2 plus 2 equals 4,
madness. It is also a fact that none of the great moral teachers you would certainly have received the same answer as you’ll
of our world ever invented a morality of their own. For exam- receive today, whereas answers to questions of morality are
ple, Jesus didn’t teach new morality, but rather he elaborated highly dependant on the time in which they’re asked. There-
on what already existed. ‘Love thy neighbour as thyself’ already fore, morality cannot be seen as objective, but perhaps rather
was, and is, a universal and eternal principle. as developing towards a set of globally shared morals.
It is of course the case that moral codes, although objective, JEANETTE LANG
are tailored to, or tailored by, the particular culture and age HEUSWEILER, SAARLAND, GERMANY

34 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016 Question: Is Morality Objective?


agree on what smoke looks like than on what an immoral or
M orality is objective. That is, moral claims are true or false
about aspects of human interaction that involve the ideas
of rights and obligations. Further, the fundamental moral max-
evil act looks like. Smith and Jones might agree that someone
just stole a loaf of bread from the grocer, but disagree as to the
ims apply universally, and reasonable people can agree on their ‘wrongness’ of the act. For example, suppose the thief was pen-
truth. niless, starving and had no other recourse. It appears there is
There are really just two alternatives to moral objectivism: no objective means of adjudicating the matter.
moral relativism, and all the rest. But all the rest lead to absur- However, philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre’s ‘virtue ethics’
dity: if I truly believe that I cannot know right from wrong suggests that a degree of moral objectivity is possible – within
(moral skepticism), or that all moral claims are false (moral the confines of certain communities and their shared values.
error theory), or that there is no right or wrong (moral For MacIntyre, there are objective standards of virtue found
nihilism and non-cognitivism), then I must conclude I don’t within a tradition, such as the ethical traditions of ancient
know what I should do. However, as a social animal I must Athens. For MacIntyre, in a given society, the moral code is
interact with others. Thus, I find myself in the dilemma of hav- based on what is agreed to be the shared end of the society and
ing to act but not knowing how to act. Any theory that leads to the best way to achieve it, which also gives each member their
this absurd state of mind must be rejected. proper role in the society and their own proper tasks. Thus, in
Moral relativism then is the only credible challenge to a society one of whose shared aims is the protection of private
moral objectivism. The case for moral relativism is that differ- property, it would be objectively wrong to steal a loaf of bread,
ent societies have different moral judgments. However, most all other things being equal. So, morality itself may not be objec-
more complex moral judgments are derived from a few basic tive, but for people who share a worldview expressed by the
ones, with components that vary with the material conditions community, morality has context and a shared meaning.
of different societies. But the fact that different societies make RONALD W. PIES M.D.
different moral judgments does not prove relativism. To prove LEXINGTON, MA
their position, relativists must dig down to the fundamental
moral judgments in every society, and then show that these
judgments are not shared by societies. This they have not done.
This is the indirect case for moral objectivism. The direct
Y ou are ugly and grossly overweight. Consider how you feel
after reading that. Keep that feeling to hand for the
moment. That sentence is an insult, and I shouldn’t have writ-
case includes the following ideas: (1) All societies share certain ten it, due to the feeling it has most certainly caused in you, and
values necessary for any society to function (for example, no would cause in me had such an insult been aimed at me, regard-
lying, promise-keeping, nurturing children) (2) Objectivism less of its truth or falsity. A wrong has been committed, a moral
appeals to reason over feeling and offers a better chance for law has been broken. It’s not a law contained in a spelt-out legal
humanity to solve its many problems; (3) The purpose of ethics system; but it doesn’t have to be spelt-out to be real. Instead, the
is to provide guidance, and humanity needs guidance for world hurt feelings in the insulted person make the offence fairly
affairs and not just within any particular society, and (4) objective. By ‘objective’ here, I mean existing universally, or vir-
Nations and societies must cooperate, and this requires agree- tually universally: anyone and everyone would feel insulted,
ment on core values. assuming they understood the words. By those words I have
Ethics first; meta-ethics [that is, thinking about the founda- created something that’s out there: it’s objective. You can’t see it,
tions of ethics] second. Meta-ethics should not be an obstacle but you feel its sting. It registers.
to the pragmatic project of seeking guidance for human social You will of course have realised that I didn’t mean what I
interaction grounded on something we can all agree on, which wrote; but for that initial moment the feeling was real. It is in
I believe is a common human nature. those kinds of moments where morality is shown to be objec-
JOHN TALLEY tive, where everyone ‘sees’ the offence: when the ghost in the
RUTHERFORDTON, NC machine (if I may borrow that phrase) becomes solid. This kind
of ‘real’ is clearly not the same real as, say, the keyboard with

I should like to reformulate the question as follows: Can we


demonstrate that any moral claim is objectively true? My reply is
‘Yes and No’.
which I wrote the sentence, but there are many types of real:
real love, real bananas, real quantum particles. While the feeling
isn’t empirical evidence as are results taken with a ruler or beeps
It seems clear that to answer this rephrased question, we on a Geiger Counter, it is real evidence of a different kind. I
must have a notional idea of what the term ‘objective’ means. can’t proclaim an area safe from radiation with a ruler, it’s the
Not surprisingly, its meaning is highly contested. wrong detector. I need the correct tool, a Geiger Counter, to do
The economist and philosopher Amartya Sen has described that. We, human beings, are the morality detectors. We all feel
two central features of objectivity: observation dependence and the sting when something wrong has been created, say an insult
impersonality. In effect, Sen meant here that objectivity requires has been slung – and therein lies the objectivity.
both careful observation and inter-observer corroboration. KRISTINE KERR (who reckons you are beautiful and fit),
Thus, on Sen’s view, if I say, “I truly and deeply believe that GOUROCK, RENFREWSHIRE
your house is on fire” without having observed your house, I
am making a subjective claim. In contrast, if two people simul-
taneously witness smoke coming from your house and say, “We
believe your house is on fire,” Sen would argue that they are
O ne reason for denying that morality is objective is the claim
that science will provide an exhaustive description of
objective reality which leaves no room for objective moral facts,
making a type of objective statement. and so morality must be either subjective or a matter of conven-
But Sen’s use of ‘objective’ doesn’t seem to work well for tion. However, it could be argued that mathematics faces the
moral claims. After all, it is much easier to get two people to same problem here as morality. Mathematical objects such as

Question: Is Morality Objective? August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 35


?? numbers do not appear in the list of items in the natural world
that science can detect. They cannot be observed as part of the
physical universe – even though they are a prerequisite for the
success of science. But we should notice that this does not pre-
vent us from regarding mathematical truths as objective. In fact
mathematics, as the Greeks recognised, is the paradigm of
objective truth. Thus the claim that objective truths must be
scientific truths seems simply a metaphysical prejudice.
T he mind is caused by the brain. But the brain doesn’t have
a ‘nodule of morality’ or even a ‘deciding zone’ any more
than it has a ‘chocolate-liking tubercle’. Rather, decision-mak-
ing, which includes moral decisions, is performed by the whole
neural net. This process is entirely objective, not just as a phe-
nomenon, but the mechanics of the brain’s decision-making
activity are thoroughly physical, visible, solid, and testable.
Our neural net makes our decisions by a fairly simple
If we allow for the possibility of objective moral truths, how process of one-on-one comparison-and-match. This means
might such truths be identified? Science boasts replicable that the results of the process look like the simple comparisons
empirical research that has identified entities which seem uncon- they are, and moral decisions seem to be comparative.
troversially objective, such as atoms. Mathematics uses logic to But then again, there does seem to be a definitive, objective,
prove mathematical theorems. In contrast, there is no accepted fixed and unshakeable system of knowing-what’s-right behind
procedure that enables us to settle moral debate, which often it all. Not just feelings but experience tells us so. And indeed,
seems interminable. There is no experiment, for example, there is such a definitive system – it is the fixed and objective
which can determine whether abortion is morally acceptable. process by which the moral comparison is done.
Nevertheless, the controversial nature of morality is itself a So, morality is comparative, and is determined by an objec-
reason to think that there are objective truths at stake. We do tive system. Which is not only an explanation of how moral
not seriously debate matters of taste (e.g. whether coffee or tea judgement works, but an explanation of why the apparent con-
is the better drink ), because we do not believe there is an flict between objective and comparative accounts of morality
objective answer. occurs. Tarraaaa!
Moreover, the distinction should be made between proce- GLYN HUGHES
dures for identifying objective reality, and objective reality SQUASHED PHILOSOPHERS (SQAPO.COM)
itself. Atoms possessed objectivity before the scientific methods
were established that confirmed their existence. So a lack of
scientific method does not necessarily mean a lack of objectiv-
ity. And, although much ethical debate seems interminable,
M orality has both subjective and objective components.
The objective component is provided by the laws of
Game Theory. The subjective element is the strategy selected
progress has been made here. For example, we have surely by a player attempting to maximise their personal reward.
established that slavery is objectively wrong, although formerly Game theory describes the competitive or collaborative
this was a controversial issue. strategies that a rational agent can use to maximise their benefit
Moral debate does not deliver clear-cut answers in the way in any situation. (In this context, a rational agent is someone
science appears to, but this does not mean that it cannot deliver capable of thinking about then acting in their own best inter-
objective conclusions at all. The process is just more difficult. est.) Often, cooperation provides the optimum outcome for all
Because of the success of science in identifying objective truths, interacting parties, but at any time an agent might break the
beliefs that are established by non-scientific means are assumed contract in an attempt to increase their own rewards. Such an
to lack objectivity. But is this justified? Surely ‘It is wrong to action might have short term benefits, but it has been shown
torture babies’ is as objectively true as anything in science. that in a series of interaction games, such a cheat will lose out
MARTIN BUTLER because the others will soon refuse further cooperation. There
LANCASTER are, therefore, substantial individual and group advantages to
keeping such a contract. This ‘reciprocal altruism’, where the
group rewards collaboration and punishes the cheat, is mod-
elled by the ‘tit-for-tat’ strategy in Game Theory.
I would argue with the Mathematical Platonists that abstract
TO SEE HIS SCULPTURES, PLEASE VISIT WWW.HARVEYGALLERY.COM

mathematical ideas are mind-independent entities. Like any


other object, they can be discovered and verified by anyone
with the right equipment – in this case a skill in mathematics.
CARTOON © CAMERON HARVEY 2016

Therefore, the outcome of our moral behaviour, subject to the


laws of relationships determined by the mathematical objects of
Game Theory, in this sense are objective. However, the strate-
gies are subjectively chosen by agents acting in what they per-
ceive to be their own best interest. Their choices may or may
not coincide with supporting the social order.
Human civilization is highly dependent on the operation of
Game Theory’s reciprocal altruism. A society’s moral codes are
attempts to ensure that individuals choose the collaborative
strategy over many ‘plays’, that is, social interactions. Although
the moral rules encapsulated by the Golden Rule (‘Do unto oth-
ers...’) and Law of Retaliation (‘an eye for an eye’) are simple, in
practice they can become very complex. Human agents are play-

“Would you go back in time to kill Col. Sanders?”


ing many parallel games in an ever-changing social and physical
environment, with no guarantee of group success. To retain

36 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016 Question: Is Morality Objective?


social cohesion, the moral code may incorporate many complex
taboos or ritualistic actions, lack of compliance with which can
be used as an explanation of the group’s failures. An agent, how-
ever, is always free to challenge the code by choosing the antiso-
cial strategy. In such cases the agent will find themselves in peril
of retribution in the form of tribal or civil law.
DR STEVE BREWER
CARBIS BAY, ST IVES
of a critically ill child, or lying to someone over the where-
abouts of your friend whom they express an intention to kill.
However, people would not necessarily give the same reasons
why these are exceptions to the rule. Some may argue there is
greater moral responsibility to a friend than to a stranger, so,
in this circumstance, lying in their defence is acceptable; but
others may argue a hierarchy of moral actions: so although
lying, or stealing, is ethically wrong, not acting to prevent a
??
murder, or to save the life of a child, is a far greater wrong.

T wo types of morality co-exist virtually everywhere and at


all times, yet they are, for the most part, poles apart.
They are morality in theory and morality in practice, and they
Others still may stress the importance of social mores in ethi-
cal situations.
In conclusion, despite a widespread belief there are things
align with objective morality and subjective morality respec- that are inherently morally correct apart from in exceptional
tively. I will demonstrate what I mean by example, but first let circumstances, there is lack of consensus on what these exemp-
me elaborate on morality as it is practiced. tions are, or when and why they are acceptable. This is what
For most people, morality stems from their surrounding makes debate over whether there is truly an objective morality
cultural norms. That is, many people rely on their conscience uncertain, and makes moral philosophy the challenging preoc-
to point their moral compass; but one’s conscience is a social cupation it is.
construct largely determined by one’s upbringing. For exam- JONATHAN TIPTON
ple, in some societies, one can be made to feel guilty about the PRESTON, LANCASHIRE
most natural sexual impulses. Guilt and sex have been associ-
ated over generations, but it is usually lop-sided: women are
often forced to carry the greater burden of guilt, and homo-
sexuals can be forced to feel criminal. Both these examples
T he common belief is that there are two kinds of knowl-
edge: subjective and objective. The latter is held to be
more certain than the former, and is usually contrasted with it.
illustrate how cultural norms can determine the morality one However, the distinction is ultimately untenable. Objective
accepts. knowledge is actually derived from subjective knowledge. This
In some societies there are cultural clashes – usually genera- is because of the absolute privacy of conscious experience,
tional – where the same moral issue can inflame opposing atti- which ensures that there can be no composite or collective
tudes. In India in December 2012, a young woman, Jyoti view of reality. So every so-called ‘objective fact’ is derivative –
Singh, was raped and murdered on a bus after she went to a that is, it is derived from the private observations of individuals
movie with her boyfriend. A documentary by British film- insofar as they seem to agree with each other.
maker Leslee Udwin explored the cultural schism in India over The process of arriving at a moral truth is in principle
this issue. Some (including the lawyers representing the gang exactly the same as that: by inquiry and agreement among
who committed the crime) believed that the girl was responsi- autonomous individuals. The status of a value would thus be
ble for her own fate, whereas others campaigned to have the no less (and no more) ‘objective’ than that of a ‘fact’. (Unfortu-
rape laws strengthened. This demonstrates starkly how some- nately, in traditional societies, it is the authority of the past
one’s specific cultural influences can set moral values that which is usually deferred to.)
become normative and then intransigent. Moreover, no ‘objective facts’ can be arrived at unless cer-
In many cultures it is taught that God or the gods deter- tain values are observed. These values are arrived at in the
mine moral values, yet these are often the most prescriptive, same way as we arrive at facts: namely by mutual agreement.
oppressive, and misogynistic examples of enforced cultural They include (1) Respect for reason and truth, (2) Recognition
mores. People who hold to this perspective often claim that of knowledge, (3) Respect for each other’s freedom and auton-
theirs is the only true objective morality, but unfortunately it omy, (4) Respect for each other’s conscious experience, and (5)
seems that when one evokes God [or indeed, any other Frankness, even where this involves admitting one’s own mis-
absolute, Ed] to rationalise one’s morality, anything, including takes. It will be seen that the Golden Rule is implicit here. We
the most savage actions, can thereby be ostensively justified. require therefore moral values when seeking out facts – values
On the other hand, morality in theory is very simple: it is to are at the root of so-called ‘facts’. And we may assert that both
treat everyone the same and give everyone the same rights, be facts and values are derived from individual human experience,
they men, women, homosexuals, people of different faith, or and so are as ‘objective’, or not, as each other.
with a different skin colour. However, one only has to look at GRAHAM DUNSTAN MARTIN
the treatment of refugees to realise how even the most liberal EDINBURGH
societies struggle with this precept.
PAUL MEALING In honour both of Albert Camus and William Shakespeare, the next
MELBOURNE question is: To Be or Not To Be – What Is The Answer?
Please both give and justify your sagacity in less than 400 words. The

T his question initially seems simple, as there appear to be


many things that most people would automatically
believe to be intrinsically morally wrong, in all times and
prize is a semi-random book from our book mountain. Subject lines
should be marked ‘Question of the Month’, and must be received by
17th October 2016. If you want a chance of getting a book, please
place, such as murder, lying, and theft. But after reflection,
include your physical address. Submission is permission to repro-
many would agree there are also cases where these things may
duce your answer physically and electronically. Thanks.
be acceptable. For example, stealing medicine to save the life

Question: Is Morality Objective? August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 37


The Consequences of
Accepting
Consequentialism
Katy Baker on the demands of consequentialist theories of morality.
“Jim finds himself in the central square of a small South American town. sequentialism disregards the agent’s own personal commit-
Tied up against the wall are a row of twenty Indians, most terrified, a few ments and allows for negative responsibility. I intend to show
defiant, in front of them several armed men in uniform. A heavy man in a that expecting individuals to take an impersonal standpoint in a
sweat-stained khaki shirt turns out to be the captain in charge and, after a decision that so greatly affects them is unrealistic and leads to
good deal of questioning of Jim which establishes that he got there by alienation. Consequentialists may try to respond by arguing
accident while on a botanical expedition, explains that the Indians are a that alienation and taking an impersonal standpoint can be a
random group of the inhabitants who, after recent acts of protest against virtue, but this seems a high price to pay if the agent is
the government, are just about to be killed to remind other possible pro- expected to disregard her most fundamental relationships, leav-
testors of the advantages of not protesting. However, since Jim is an hon- ing her deeply unhappy. For a theory often touted as promot-
oured visitor from another land, the captain is happy to offer him a guest’s ing happiness, this is a problem.
privilege of killing one of the Indians himself. If Jim accepts, then as a spe-
cial mark of the occasion, the other Indians will be let off. Of course, if Jim A Utilitarian Approach
refuses, then there is no special occasion, and Pedro here will do what he Consequentialism focuses on promoting the best conse-
was about to do when Jim arrived, and kill them all... The men against the quences, but what kind of consequences are the best? The best-
wall and the other villagers understand the situation, and are obviously known consequentialist ethical theory is utilitarianism, which
begging him to accept. What should he do?” says that the wrongness or rightness of an action depends on
Bernard Williams in the book Utilitarianism: For and Against, the amount of overall good or ‘utility’ that is produced. So, to
by J.J.C. Smart and Bernard Williams, 1973 decide whether or not to take some step, we must calculate
whether it will produce the best overall outcome for the high-
est number of people. Many utilitarians take a hedonistic

C
onsequentialism is the theory in moral philosophy that approach, saying that utility equates to happiness, so we should
says our actions should aim at producing the best con- act to produce the greatest happiness, and to minimize pain
sequences. A consequence of consequentialism, how- and unhappiness. For example, if I have the choice between
ever, is that it fails to respect the integrity of the individuals saving one of my two cats, Benjy and Oliver, from a house fire,
involved. As what matters is only the end result, who is acting I should save the cat that would produce the most utility over
or how they arrive at the decisions they make is irrelevant. the other one. So, if Oliver had a wide network of adoring cat
The lack of respect for the integrity of the individual is raised lovers because of his friendly, playful nature, unlike Benjy who
by Bernard Williams’ famous ‘Jim and the Indians’ thought prefers a life of peaceful solitude I should save Oliver as this
experiment, quoted above. Williams’ example shows that con- would cause the least pain and produce the most pleasure for

hard times are on their way

38 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Who would you save?

the people that know him. For consequentialism, life is a num- would feel not need to be taken into account when looking at
bers game; an action should aim to make the majority happy, the best overall outcome? Killing the one Indian is going to
regardless of who they are, and should aim to go for actions have a profound effect on Jim’s life but for the consequential-
that produce minimal pain. Williams furthers this explanation; ist, Jim’s values are irrelevant. What matters in this example is
“making the best of a bad job is one of its maxims, and it will saving the highest number of lives, and how this is attained is
have something to say even on the difference between mas- unimportant.
sacring seven million, and massacring seven million and one”
(Consequentialism and its Critics, 1988). So whilst both acts are Can The Consequentialist Adequately Respond?
morally abhorrent, the consequentialist will inevitably say that In response to criticism of the unappealing idea that by
if these are the only options available then not only should we doing nothing Jim is as responsible for the deaths of the
choose to massacre seven million, but that it would be right to twenty Indians as the captain, the consequentialist can choose
do so. What matters is not so much the horrific act in itself but to bite the bullet by accepting the idea of negative responsibil-
the outcome of that act. ity; that is, to accept that we can be held morally responsible
for not acting. Our duty to others can be illustrated using
Jim & The Indians another example, one used by contemporary utilitarian
As consequentialism only looks at the consequences it philosopher Peter Singer. Imagine you are in your local park
allows for negative responsibility; that is, being held morally feeding the ducks on the pond when you hear a loud splash; a
accountable not for some action, but for failing to act to pre- child has fallen into the pond and is struggling to swim. No
vent bad things happening. Also, it does not matter who per- other adults or swimmers are anywhere to be seen, so without
forms the action, only the action itself as Williams’ example your help the child will drown. It is not unreasonable to say
shows. that in this example you should pause your duck feeding and
For the consequentialist it is obvious that the right choice jump in to save the child. If you don’t, you should be held
for Jim would be to kill one Indian in order to save the lives of partly responsible for the child’s death. The same could be said
the other nineteen. If Jim refuses to kill anyone then he is for Jim who by doing nothing is responsible for the lives of the
therefore responsible for the deaths of the others. From a twenty Indians. But Jim has to actively kill someone unlike the
consequentialist point of view it doesn’t matter who commits duck feeder for whom the only bad consequences are that he
the murder, merely the amount of lives lost in the end, so Jim will get wet and muddy. Whilst the drowning child example
would be just as responsible for the deaths as the captain is – seems to support the existence of negative responsibility, it dif-
surely an absurd outcome. So what exactly is wrong with it? fers in that there are no commitments or beliefs preventing us
By saying that Jim should shoot the one Indian the conse- from saving the child. And this is the central problem; that
quentialist fails to take into account the impact that this would Jim’s values are seen as unimportant when it comes to deciding
have on Jim’s life. In one moment Jim goes from being a how he should act in the given situation.
tourist in a foreign country to becoming a murderer for the The consequentialist could retort that in calculating what
sake of morality. He is likely to have his own commitments in course of action is right, the individual’s integrity can be taken
which murder (rather than letting others die) would go into account. Perhaps it can in some way be quantified, so that
against his most fundamental beliefs. Does the pain that Jim if carrying out some act would damage the integrity of the

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 39


Consequentialism and the
CARTOON © BILL STOTT 2016 FOR MORE, PLEASE VISIT WWW.BILLSTOTT.CO.UK

Demands of Morality, Philosophy


and Public Affairs 1984). Rather
than taking into account our
own attitudes towards an
action, by taking an objective
standpoint we are able to
remove ourselves from our
usual social groups and ideolo-
gies which affect the way in
which we act and look at a situ-
ation, and instead we should act
without bias. In practice this a
very difficult thing to do – to
step outside of the values we
have been brought up with –
and the state of being alienated
The meaning of life? Well, that depends what sort of mood I’m in. itself often causes unhappiness
within the individual. For con-
individual so grievously that the maximum utility could be sequentialism this is not a problem, as the individual is just a
reached only if they failed to act, then not acting would be the mechanism for maximising overall happiness; they are instru-
right thing to do. But in Jim’s case his pain at killing one mental. Through alienating ourselves Railton shows that
person is a relatively minor consideration when the very lives “adopting one’s exclusive ultimate end in life in the pursuit of
of nineteen others (and the happiness of their families and maximum happiness may well prevent one from having experi-
friends) is at stake. Furthermore, whilst the consequentialist ences or engaging in certain sorts of commitments that are
can agree that the individual agent’s integrity should not be among the greatest sources of happiness” (‘Alienation, Conse-
ignored, as Williams explains, “(h)is own substantial projects quentialism and the Demands of Morality’, Philosophy and Public
and commitments come into it, but only as one lot among Affairs, 1984). Again, consequentialism forces us to put our
others.” (Ethics, 1994) As our integrity is one among many commitments second, regardless of how strongly we are con-
others and consequentialism expects us all to take an imper- nected to them or how much pleasure we derive from them.
sonal standpoint, it would follow that everyone would need to The happiness of the individual is overridden by the happiness
disregard their personal commitments, which is likely to lead of the masses.
in turn to overall unhappiness, a problem for a moral theory Using the example of Jim and the Indians, Williams success-
with hedonistic tendencies. fully illustrates that consequentialism fails to respect the
integrity of the individual because in deciding what is wrong or
Alienation right what really matters is not the action but the outcome of it.
Even if the damage to Jim’s integrity is taken into account, Any prior commitments are disregarded or, if taken into consid-
there is another problem: the consequentialist would regard eration, are unlikely to have any substantial effect on the out-
Jim’s killing another person not merely as preferable, but as come. Consequentialism entails that we can be held morally
morally required. It is a problem that consequentialism forces responsible for a lack of action, and whilst the case of the
us to take an impersonal, objective view of situations and over- drowning child shows that it is possible to be indirectly respon-
ride some of our most cherished beliefs because of its require- sible by not acting, in cases like Jim’s it involves going further
ment that we focus exclusively on the final result. Taking an than can be reasonably expected. The consequence of conse-
impersonal standpoint leads to alienation; this is the state of quentialism is that by taking an impersonal standpoint we alien-
someone who has become separated from their commitments ate ourselves and whilst the consequentialist can argue that this
to themselves and others. This makes consequentialist theories should be a virtue, the expected result of unhappiness shows its
very demanding on the agent involved. Consequentialism inadequacy for this is a high price to pay for a view that values
requires that the agent should step outside herself, as it were, happiness. If consequentialism is to take a hedonistic approach –
and assess the consequences not in terms of prior commit- that we should act so as to maximise overall happiness – then it
ments, but just on the results produced. results in a contradiction. Disregarding our integrity and alien-
To this objection, the consequentialist can protest that alien- ating ourselves from our values and social ideas is likely to result
ation can be a virtue. In effect we become moral martyrs, sur- in a life of unhappiness. If this is demanded of all moral agents,
rendering our integrity (leading to alienation) in order to then general unhappiness is likely to ensue rather than the
achieve what they believe is morally right. Some consequential- opposite. So by treating the individual as merely a means to an
ists even argue that alienation is necessary for social progress. end, consequentialism may turn out to be self-defeating.
As Peter Railton says: “The alienation of some individuals or © KATY BAKER 2016
groups from their milieu may at times be necessary for funda- Katy Baker studied Philosophy at the University of Kent and is now
mental social criticism or cultural innovation” (Alienation, part of the Philosophy Now team.

40 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Letters
When inspiration strikes, don’t bottle it up!
Write to me at: Philosophy Now
43a Jerningham Road • London • SE14 5NQ, U.K.
or email rick.lewis@philosophynow.org
Keep them short and keep them coming!

The Reflective Turn Scientific Limits DEAR EDITOR: In ‘Catherine Malabou &
DEAR EDITOR: I read Tim Wilkinson’s DEAR EDITOR: Grant Bartley in his edito- the Continental Philosophy of Brains’,
article on mirrors (PN 114) with interest rial in Issue 114 is too timid and too brave. Issue 114, Dale DeBakcsy mentions that
as, many years ago, I came up with a If some scientists think of philosophy as a Jacques Derrida thought that there is
different theory of why mirrors appear poor man’s version of science this is good. always something elusive about our
to reverse left and right but not up and Gives everyone involved something to attempts to experience ourselves – here
down. My argument is that the effect is argue about. The fact is, everyone has a the ‘I’ seems to need to treat itself as an
due to the direction in which we turn license to think: it’s called a brain, and Other. I wonder if Derrida was familiar
round – the axis around which we rotate moreover you can think about anything at with psychiatrist Roberto Assioli’s
– when we change from looking at an all. Absolutely anything. Wow! And if you concept of ‘I, the observer’ being separate
object to looking at its reflection. take advantage of this freedom you are and distinct from ‘I, the personal self’?
Imagine that you are standing in doing philosophy. Science is a fairly RAY SHERMAN, DUARTE, CA
front of a large mirror and that, behind respectable part of that. So is mathematics,
you, is a large square. Each corner of the a different part. But that leaves an awful More Women In Philosophy
square is coloured differently. You turn lot of other things to think about. And DEAR EDITOR: I read the letter by
from looking at the actual square to what is being done by engineers and scien- Marthe Kerkwijk in Issue 114 with great
looking at its reflection in the mirror. tists these days would have been dismissed interest, and a lot of questions. I struggle
The reflection appears to reverse the left as philosophical lunacy a century ago. to comprehend Prof. David Papineau’s
and right side of the square, but not to On the other hand the idea that you get apparent claim that one solution to the
reverse top and bottom. Now imagine any help from Kant in understanding problem of the underrepresentation of
you are a different kind of creature, that space and time is rather silly. A philoso- women in academic philosophy could be
turns round by turning head over heels pher argued that Einstein had to be wrong for philosophy departments to cut out
(in other words, by rotating vertically because he contradicted Kant. Einstein some of the technical, scholastic bits, on
around a horizontal axis, instead of and others had a far deeper insight than the basis that these deter women.
around the vertical axis as we usually Kant. Argue with me about this when you Although I agree that some areas of
do). Now when you rotate from looking understand what the Lorentz group has to philosophy are seen as less applicable to
at the square to looking at its reflection, do with space and time. the competitive employment market, the
the square seems to get turned upside MIKE ALDER, PERTH, AUSTRALIA answer is to show that the technical
down, but what appeared to be on the nature of these topics inculcates valuable
left still appears on the left when you DEAR EDITOR: Some scientists believe transferrable skills, not to remove this
look at the reflection. This principle can that philosophy is unnecessary for under- element so that women won’t be ‘put
be illustrated by a tree reflected in a standing our world, but I don’t think we off’. Such technical elements are the
lake. In going from looking at the tree to could have survived the mental distress training needed to have a sharp mind
looking at its reflection, we rotate our and chaos experienced after the calamitous and well-honed analytical skills when
line of sight vertically (around a hori- events of the Holocaust and the dropping tackling any other area of philosophy or
zontal axis ). What is on the left of the of the atomic bombs on Japan without debate. They are not irrelevant.
tree still appears to be on the left of the engaging in philosophy. I’m sure science There was an expectation that Mary
reflection, but what is at the top of the alone couldn’t have dealt with the mental Warnock, as one of our most celebrated
tree is at the bottom of the reflection. and moral anguish we faced after those female philosophers, would be a feminist
My point is that reflection inverts along events. Moreover, I think that if we were mouthpiece, but she refused to be so.
the direction in which we rotate our line left with only cold scientific thinking we Her views can be found in What Philoso-
of sight when we go from looking at the could easily have fallen into repeating phers Think (ed. Baggini and Stan-
object to looking at the reflection. If we those events. It’s mostly through philoso- groom). She denied that philosophy
usually turned around a horizontal axis, phizing about them that we’ve gained an produced by women is being ‘passed
rather than a vertical one, we would understanding into what triggered them, over’: rather, there isn’t much of it. This
think that mirrors inverted up and down which then put us on a course of trying to echoes Marthe’s hypothesis that women
but not left and right. Perhaps some- avoid repeating them. It’s not science self-select out of the subject. Warnock
where in the universe there is a species alone that has given us the understanding attributes some of her own academic
that’s puzzled about why mirrors do that. and fortitude to overcome our history. success to the fact that at the time,
PETER SPURRIER, HALSTEAD, ESSEX DAVID AIRTH, TORONTO women’s colleges in Oxford and

August/September 2016 l Philosophy Now 41


Letters
Cambridge employed only female lectur- my intellect. I don’t think anyone of any context, then it is only our minds that can
ers. She also suggested that women, when gender, class, ethnicity or sexual orienta- choose the questions, and only reality that
busy having children, tend to publish less tion should be made to feel like that. can choose the answers. So we can only
than men, putting them at a disadvantage Eleanor Roosevelt claimed no-one can ‘invent’ the questions, and only ‘discover’
when looking for academic jobs. Having make you feel inferior without your the answers. This has important philo-
two children myself, I know that there consent, but that’s simplifying the issue. sophical consequences, including:
isn’t the time to read the journals and There aren’t enough female philoso- • There are no ‘things in themselves’ –
books one would want to, let alone phers, especially in the ‘hard’ subjects. but there is a ‘reality in itself’ which does
produce publications (and I wouldn’t This is because either a) They aren’t not comprise individual ‘things’. We
change a second of it, by the way). clever enough; b) Their work is ignored know of this reality in itself because of its
Warnock also mentions the concentra- by male academics; or c) They’re not function in setting the answers to our
tion of women in the ‘soft’ subjects of producing the work in the first place. I questions (or in NR terms, its affordance
philosophy, in particular religion and take it as a given that a) is false. But if it is of and resistance to our models).
ethics. One reason she gives for the inter- c), then we’re not providing the environ- • However, we cannot be said to fully
est in religion is that women were often ment for young bright minds to develop know this reality in itself – not because of
locked in their traditional, supportive, philosophically, which is a tragedy. its ‘mystery’, or because of a ‘barrier’ or
probably religious role in the family. Perhaps we need to tell young girls that ‘veil’, but simply because of its indefinite
Another is that they have ‘divided lives’, to spend hours on a metaphysical prob- complexity. Yet we can always know more
and so whilst trying to keep many plates lem is a perfectly good use of her time. by increasing the accuracy of our models
spinning, tend to excel at the subjects that SALLY LATHAM, SUTTON COLDFIELD of individuals and classes.
‘take less concentration’. She speaks auto- • Realism and Constructivism are thus
biographically here, referring to the ‘soft’ Reality’s Limits not alternatives, but complementary.
subjects as not requiring the hours in the DEAR EDITOR: Judging by your feature Shouldn’t we therefore rather aim for
library, or even hours sitting undisturbed on it in Issue 113, New Realism has a lot ‘Constructive Realism’? John Searle’s
as you work out a logical problem. I was of promising features, but there does claim that external Realism is consistent
riled by this. So men are able to sit peace- seem to be a problem in its claim that with conceptual relativity is one precedent
fully and do modal logic, but women can individuals exist outside of thought in for this approach (cf ‘The Construction of
think about God while they sweep the the way that classes do not. Social Reality’). Another is Davis &
floors?! However, I also have to admit Consider the individual object that we Hersh’s reconciliation of the claims of
that I’m writing parts of this letter while call the planet Venus. Is the atmosphere of Platonism and formalism in mathematics,
getting the kids’ tea ready. I also remem- Venus part of this object, or not? The in The Mathematical Experience.
ber a PhD student writing to me (yes, a answer may be ‘yes’ or ‘no’ according to ROGER HAINES, LONDON
letter on paper) after my first year under- the context, and more importantly, the
graduate exams, telling me to select the obvious answer in most cases is that it DEAR EDITOR: I’m glad that you
modules that “would get me more doesn’t matter. When a meteorite strikes published Sam Woolfe’s article on the
respect” in the department – namely, not Venus, in which nanosecond do two ideas of Max Tegmark in Issue 113. In his
religion and ethics. Unfortunately I had objects become one? Again, it never book, Our Mathematical Universe (2014),
already decided to do a dissertation on matters, except perhaps within rough Tegmark defines his Mathematical
neo-Wittgensteinian fideism by then; but limits. This shows that when we speak of Universe Hypothesis (MUH) as: “Our
I also took philosophy of mind and meta- Venus as an object we speak of an idea external physical reality is a mathematical
physics. But, again, whatever the reasons that is less precise than the reality – a structure.” Woolfe presents Tegmark’s
for the lack of women in the ‘hard’ mental model that elides irrelevant hypothesis as if it were metaphysical spec-
subject, the solution is not to remove distinctions. The New Realists are right to ulation, but Tegmark’s argument on this,
these elements from courses. emphasise that material reality has a as well as the multiverse models Woolfe
I don’t claim to have the answers. I mind-independent structure; but to get discusses, are based upon general relativ-
can’t claim to be a career philosopher. I from that structure to individual ‘objects’ ity and quantum field theory, together
teach, I write, I get involved in projects. I requires that a boundary be drawn with cosmological inflation theory.
have rarely experienced any discrimina- between what is part of a particular object Let me confess straightaway that my
tion, probably because I never climbed and what is not – and it is not reality which initial reaction to MUH was that it was
high enough up the academic ladder. draws those boundaries, but our attempts simply a category mistake. I have long
There have been encounters with male to understand it. Typically, reality itself is argued that mathematical entities were
academics where I have felt that I was characterised by constellations of closely abstract and not physical objects. No
viewed as inferior, but I was not sure what concentric or overlapping boundaries matter how you combine any number of
the reason was. I did consider that it which afford approximate descriptions in 7s or πs or special unitary groups or
might be because I am female; but I also terms of ‘objects’ whose precise bound- circles, you can’t construct the Eiffel
considered that it might be because I have aries are not fully defined, and, as far as Tower or an elephant. For me Tegmark’s
a Brummy accent, or (more likely) not they matter, are context-dependent. most persuasive argument is a reduction-
enough letters after my name. There have There is a helpful shorthand for this ist one. Every physical object is
certainly been times when I have begun to situation that has a wide application. If composed of subatomic particles. Their
lose confidence, to question myself and ‘facts’ are answers to questions in a given properties are now well displayed in the

42 Philosophy Now l August/September 2016


Letters
Standard Model of particle physics. This his all-encompassing Level IV mathe- conservatism as a strain of conservatism.
model comprises fields, together with 17 matical multiverse. Cantor’s theory of It is more helpful to distinguish a politi-
particles. Tegmark claims that these transfinite numbers is a perfectly legiti- cal type– right-wing politics – from its
fields and particles have no properties mate mathematical structure; but tokens, conservatism and neo-conser-
other than purely mathematical ones, so Tegmark omits discussion of it alto- vatism: Whereas conservatism is a poli-
at its root physical reality is mathemati- gether – a strange oversight indeed. tics of scepticism, neo-conservatism,
cal. As we move up the physical scale PHIL HOFFMANN, CALGARY, CANADA with its belief in ‘progressive abso-
through atoms, cells, organisms, stars, lutism’, is clearly a politics of faith.
galaxies, new properties emerge, provid- DEAR EDITOR: I believe your correspon- Thus, although they are both to the
ing us with a conceptual framework dent in Issue 114, Tom Graham, may be right of the political spectrum, they are
which allows us to understand the world, somewhat confused about the nature of charged very differently. One could say
but they are not fundamental to reality. the infinite. Something being infinite that epistemologically speaking, they are
Tegmark refers to them as ‘baggage’. does not imply that nothing can exist polar opposites.
Intelligent beings from another galaxy, outside it. There are infinitely many FRODE BJERKÅS, OSLO, NORWAY
or intelligent machines here, are likely numbers between zero and one; but
to use utterly different concepts. there are also an infinite number of More Philosophy Now Slip-Ups
In regard to mathematics, Tegmark is numbers between one and two, and so DEAR EDITOR: Although Mary Gregg
a Platonist as opposed to a formalist. on: in fact, an infinite number of such correctly distinguishes between savoir
Platonists view mathematical objects as infinities! Would it not therefore be and connaître in the article ‘Knowledge
real: they objectively exist outside of phys- possible that each individual multiverse and Language’ in Issue 114, she uses the
ical space and time quite independently of is like each of these infinities, so an infi- word être instead of faire in the sentence
our knowledge of them. Here mathemati- nite number of them could exist without ‘je sais que deux et deux sont quatre’.
cians are somewhat like scientists in overlapping? I am not suggesting that Although it does not make any differ-
discovering and exploring a pre-existing the analogy from numbers to space is ence to her argument, the correct
reality, which will remain unchanged for direct, but I believe it demonstrates that version is, ‘je sais que deux et deux font
all time. In contrast, formalism, which there is no contradiction in multiple infi- quatre’. However, what if Descartes had
was introduced by David Hilbert, holds nite universes. said ‘Je pense, donc je suis’ instead of ‘cogito
that all mathematics can be reduced to NICHOLAS DYSON, YORK ergo sum’? Also, why is the spelling of
rules for manipulating formulas. It has ordinateur correct in the text, but not in
been claimed that most mathematicians Liberal Conservatism the cartoon?
are Platonists on week-days when they are DEAR EDITOR: Musa al-Gharbi in EVA TYSON, DALGETY BAY, FIFE
working, but formalists on Sundays when, Issue113 is certainly right in contrasting
in philosophical mode, they reflect on conservatism with its opposite, progres- DEAR EDITOR: I’ve just got the new
their work. The question seems sivism, and in holding that conservatives’ Philosophy Now (114), and upon seeing
completely irresolvable. But one can see inclination towards tradition is a feature the title of one of the articles – ‘Is Žižek
that Tegmark being a Platonist might of conservatism, not its essence. I was the Elvis of Philosophy?’ – I couldn’t
make MUH attractive to him. I strongly however surprised to read that he chose resist to check it out immediately. But as
recommend that Philosophy Now readers to include neo-conservatives among what Slavoj Žižek’s compatriot, and thus
read Tegmark’s excellent book, which is he called ‘other conservative strains”. As fluent in Slovenian, I was really disap-
written in an engaging style. he says, they embrace “progressive abso- pointed when I saw at the end of the
JOHN RADCLIFFE, lutism”, including “forcibly spreading article a quote saying that the southern
WELWYN GARDEN CITY liberalism around the world.” Surely this Slav (Yugoslav) word for ‘Cheers’ is
is not very conservative? ‘Zivali’. Unfortunately, there is no
DEAR EDITOR: I enjoyed Sam Woolfe’s In his posthumously published book southern Slav word zivali. The situation
article on Max Tegmark’s hierarchy of The Politics of Faith and the Politics of Scep- changes if you add a circumflex to the Z,
multiverses, but Woolfe let Tegmark off ticism, philosopher Michael Oakeshott to make it Živali. In this case you get a
lightly in terms of any discussion of (1901-1990) identifies two styles or poles word, but I am afraid Žižek might get
weaknesses and gaps in his position. For in the last 500 years of political history. confused or offended by this kind of
example, Tegmark assumes that his four Whereas the ‘politics of faith’ is charged toast, since it means animals! If you want
levels of multiverses form a consistent by grand designs and absolutist forms of to make a toast in Slovenia or any neigh-
hierarchy, but his Level I and II multi- government, the ‘politics of scepticism’ is bouring countries that share Slavic
verses are not purely quantum mechani- very much reluctant to believe strongly roots, you should say ‘Živeli!’
cal as his Level III is, but rather, cosmo- in any given scheme, and absolutist SABINA PLESNAR KASCA, ROME
logical in scale; and since quantum schemes in particular. Now, although
theory and relativity are still not fully conservatism understood as the opposite DEAR EDITOR: Regarding the excellent
unified, his assumption of congruency is of progressivism probably exemplify a article by Geoff Sheehan, ‘Socrates &
dubious. Secondly, Tegmark is some- politics of scepticism, Oakeshott includes Zen’, in Issue 113, the parable attributed
what suspicious of infinities in physics. left- as well as right-wing politics into to Mark Vernon should be attributed to
Understandably so, but he is surpris- both poles or charges. On this account, it Swami Vivekananda (1863-1902).
ingly silent about the role of infinities in becomes a stretch too far to hold neo- DOROTHY BERRY, PRESCOTT, AZ

August/September 2016 l Philosophy Now 43


Richard Baron explains modal reasoning, while Matt
DeStefano is unswayed by an argument explaining

Books atheism by immorality, & Nick Everitt experiences views


on the nature of experience’s that don’t yield knowledge.

Modality & Explana- the game was only drawn and the cup fell case in at least one possible world, whether
tory Reasoning to the floor. There is a close possible close or distant. If there is a possible world
by Boris Kment world – close because only a little bit dif- in which people live to age 500, then such
ferent – in which the game was won. That lifespans are possible. We can also talk
YOUR FOOTBALL TEAM world is very similar to the actual world, about things being necessary if they are the
only drew a game yester- up to the time when the opposing team case in every possible world. For example,
day. But things could tries to score. There is just a slight differ- in every possible world, 2 + 2 = 4.
very easily have been different. If your ence in the position of the goalkeeper. Philosophers bring possibility and
goalkeeper had been standing two inches to There is another possible world, much necessity under the banner of modality –
the right at the crucial moment, the oppos- more distant, in which the dropped cup the first word in Boris Kment’s title. One
ing team would not have scored the fateful does not fall to the floor. In that world, reason why modality is important is its
goal and your team would have won. Still there is an amazingly strong updraught at connection with explanation. How do we
annoyed this morning, you dropped a cup just the right moment. explain that your dropped cup fell? We
and it fell to the floor. Given that you These possible worlds are not located in talk about gravity. Gravity makes it neces-
dropped the cup, it was very likely to fall. It our Universe, a million miles or a million sary for objects to fall, unless something
might not have fallen, but only if there had light years away. They are imaginary holds them up, and if there were no grav-
been a sudden updraught of air. Unlike worlds. So ‘close’ and ‘distant’ are just ity it would be possible for unsupported
with the goal, the outcome could only have vivid ways to talk about worlds being very objects not to fall. So gravity is at least part
been different if something quite extraordi- similar to ours or radically different from of the explanation of the cup’s falling.
nary had happened. ours. But it is jolly useful to talk in terms Kment’s book explores the connections
When philosophers try to get a grip on of possible worlds, because they allow us between necessity, possibility and explana-
the idea that some things could easily have to think systematically about what might tion. He also weaves in another thread:
been different, while other things could easily have been the case, and what might counterfactuals. These are claims about what
only have been different in quite extraordi- only have been the case if things had been did not happen but could have happened:
nary circumstances, they talk about possible very different. At the extreme, we can talk “If our goalkeeper had stood two inches to
worlds. We live in the actual world, where about things being possible if they are the the right, we would have won”; “If there

If only the goalkeeper had


been two inches to the right

44 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016 Book Reviews


Books

“ When philosophers try to get a grip on the idea that some


things could easily have been different, while other things could
only have been different in quite extraordinary circumstances,
they talk about possible worlds.

had been a sudden updraught of air, the


cup would not have fallen to the floor.”
Counterfactuals need to be brought
into the picture because they also central
to explanation. Suppose we think that if
the goalkeeper had stood two inches to
the right, we would have won. Then we
think that the goalkeeper’s actual posi-
majority of this book. The discussion is
detailed and technical. This is all to the
good. The devil often lies in the detail, so
details need to be explored. Kment does so
in a way that is as clear as it can be, given
his decision to write continuous prose that
will make sense to most philosophers with-
out their having to do extra reading. But

counterfactuals to define what counts as an
explanation. Kment puts forward the
thought that it is the other way round. We
want to explain things, and we develop
ideas of necessity and possibility, and the
tool of counterfactual thought, in order to
allow us to find explanations. The desire to
explain comes first. So naturally enough,
tion explains, or at least helps to explain, his discussion might have been even having shown how to use counterfactuals,
our not winning. Counterfactuals can also clearer if he had been a bit more technical, Kment acknowledges that this tool does
underpin attempts to explain what hap- and had used mathematical concepts to not always give the right answers when we
pens in scientific contexts. Suppose that define the properties of the space in which use it to establish what explains what. He
you mix two chemicals, and the mixture all possible worlds are laid out. He needs also notes that we sometimes have to make
does nothing until you heat it. Then the enough of a conception of the distances ad hoc adjustments to the ways in which we
chemicals react and create a new com- between possible worlds to say that some use counterfactuals, in order to reach sensi-
pound. You say “If I had not heated the are closer to the actual world than others, ble conclusions about what explains what.
chemicals, they would not have reacted.” to pick out the ones closest to the actual Kment discusses how ideas about neces-
That encourages you to say “The heating world, and to classify worlds as tolerably sity and so on serve our purposes. In doing
explains the reaction.” close (where physical laws like the law of so, he writes of grades of necessity, and of
Modality and counterfactuals are gravity still hold) or as very distant (where wide or narrow ranges of possible worlds
brought together by their connection some physical laws are different). On the that we might consider. (If we pick a narrow
with the idea of possible worlds. Neces- other hand, he does not want distances to range, it will be relatively easy for things to
sity is being the case in every possible be too exact. He does not want us to be be necessary: they need only be the case
world. Possibility is being the case in at able to say that one world is twice as far throughout that narrow range.) This
least one possible world. And a counter- away as another. If the required mathe- reflects our ordinary thinking. For example,
factual is true if the consequent would be matical structure and how to measure and when we seek to explain a rise in the stock
true in the closest worlds in which the use distances had been spelt out in full at market by considering what might have
antecedent was true. “If the goalkeeper the beginning, rather than the require- been different in the business world and
had stood two inches to the right, we ments being outlined at the start and the what effects those differences would have
would have won” is true because in details then filled in gradually as ways to had on share prices, we just take it for
worlds very close to the actual world, in overcome difficulties, that would have granted that there is a stock market in
which we just move the goalkeeper a given a different shape to the discussion. which supply and demand determine prices,
little bit and make very few other Similarly, he might usefully have been that investors can move their money
changes, the goalkeeper blocks the more explicitly mathematical in his discus- around, and so on. But we could go beyond
incoming ball. We do not need to con- sion of how some facts are ‘explanatory this practical attitude, and consider whether
sider more distant worlds, for example ancestors’ of other facts, in the sense that necessity is merely something we have
those in which the goalkeeper stands two they directly or indirectly explain the invented because we want to explain things,
inches to the right but a sudden very others. He could also have set out all the rather than something real that we have dis-
strong gust of wind diverts the ball to the necessary definitions at the start. These covered. Kment does not take that bold
left. Likewise, “If I had not heated the are not concerns about this book alone. step, although he does not think that facts
chemicals, they would not have reacted” Many works of philosophy could benefit about necessity are fundamental. But if
is true because in close possible worlds, in from giving the whole game away at the anyone were to be inspired by this intricate
which you do not light the Bunsen start, before going on to justify the views and exhilarating book to take the step, then
burner but nearly everything else is the stated. Kment’s admirable synopsis in David Hume, a philosopher with whom
same, there is no reaction. We do not chapter 1 doesn’t give away quite as much Kment disagrees on natural laws, would
need to consider more distant worlds, in as it could. allow himself a wry smile from the grave.
which some strange atmospheric condi- The exciting claims come in the con- © RICHARD BARON 2016
tions lead to a chemical reaction. cluding chapters. We have seen how neces- Richard Baron is a philosopher in London. His
The discussion of counterfactuals, and sity, possibility and counterfactuals are website is www.rbphilo.com
of how to work out which possible worlds connected with explanation. But this does
are closest so we can use counterfactuals not prove that the idea of explanation is • Modality and Explanatory Reasoning, Boris
to work out what explains what without built on top of ideas of necessity and possi- Kment, Oxford University Press, 2014, xii + 362
making too many mistakes, takes up the bility. Nor does it mean that we must use pages, £48.00 hb, ISBN 978-0-19-960468-5

Book Reviews August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 45


Books
are, generally speaking, morally deficient
The Making of An Paul Vitz
creatures who are for instance blinded by
Atheist their own rampant sexual deviances, or led
by Jason Spiegel astray by troublesome relationships with
their fathers.
C.S. LEWIS HAD GREAT One of Spiegel’s predominant argu-
disdain for the argument ments to explain the existence of atheists is
that theism was simply a a poor relationship with one’s father. His
matter of wish-fulfillment – that a belief in major support is Paul Vitz’s highly contro-
God’s existence was just a manifestation of versial work, Faith of the Fatherless (1999).
a desire for an eternal afterlife. However, Vitz’s work stems from an idiosyncratic
he also had sharp words for arguments that interpretation of the psychoanalytic tradi-
went in reverse – that disbelief in God is tion. Spiegel recites Vitz’s anecdotal evi-
just due to fear of an eternal afterlife – dence from a case study of fifteen histori-
which is the main argument offered by cal atheists who either had their father die
Jason Spiegel in this book. As Lewis wrote, at an early age or had tumultuous relation-
“Men wish on both sides: and again, there is ships with them. Fifteen people is a hor-
fear-fulfillment as well as wish-fulfillment, rendously small sample size for any type of
and hypochondriac temperaments will analysis, and especially of a group as large
always tend to think that true what they and as diverse as atheism. And Vitz’s work
most wish to be false... as a general explana- has already been the subject of intense
tion of [either atheism or theism] they will scrutiny and scepticism in the psychologi- in such a being is an important one. Argu-
not help us” (On Obstinacy in Belief, 1960). cal community, a fact that Spiegel glosses ments from divine hiddenness and other
I’m sympathetic to Lewis’s view about over completely. A serious scholarly work reasons for non-belief have been predomi-
these types of arguments, and that’s why I will seek to address significant arguments nant in philosophy, and a good answer to
found Spiegel’s book so troubling. Two of in the literature against their position, but these arguments would be an important step
the cardinal sins in philosophy are ad Spiegel avoids this throughout his work. A in making a case for theism. It’s clear, how-
hominem (that is, personal) attacks on your footnote in Spiegel’s book argues that Vitz ever, that Spiegel is far off the mark. Resort-
interlocutor, and making sweeping universal succeeds because he also examined several ing to an over-easy explanation – those who
claims without warrant. In The Making of An famous theists. But the problem isn’t that disagree with me are immoral – is rarely a
Atheist, Spiegel manages to commit both, Vitz failed to address either believers or good tactic in rational disagreement. His
quite frequently. The book is mostly invec- non-believers, but that his analysis does tired arguments have already been decisively
tive. But when he wades into the depths of not map onto the general population, and refuted, and if Spiegel had bothered to do
argumentation, the author is beyond his ken. only seems plausible because of the sub- his research, he might have seen this.
Spiegel’s goal is straightforward: to stantial limitation on the cases examined. Spiegel’s egregious thesis about non-belief
explain the existence of atheism given the The other major claim Spiegel makes is strikes out on nearly all counts, and only
evidence for the existence of God. His that atheists reject God in an effort to ratio- serves to move the debate backwards.
answer is that atheists are not actively nalize their sexual misconduct. I find this At the end of a section entitled ‘Where
engaging the evidence (otherwise they’d be particularly shocking as it is pretty clear that Atheists are Correct’, Spiegel writes that
theists), but rather, that they are rebelling sexual misconduct is not limited to the secu- Christians should be epistemically humble:
against God. According to Spiegel, atheists lar community. Whether it is the scandalous they should admit that the supernatural is
treatment of sexual mysterious, especially with regard to the
offenses by the Trinity and other doctrinal positions.
Catholic Church, or When Christians err, either through
STAINED GLASS BY ALFRED HANDEL, 1945. PHOTO © TOBY HUDSON 2009

the high rates of porn hypocrisy, malpractice by the church, or


consumption by con- overconfidence in theological matters,
servative American “Christians should be grateful for atheists’
Christians, or the cor- perceptiveness in pointing them out; we
relation between should be willing to repent of these
increased religiosity errors.” This advice seems relevant to the
and higher teen birth content of his own book, and we should
rates, we can see that hope that he takes it.
people do not need to © MATT DESTEFANO 2016
become atheists in Matt is a PhD student in philosophy at the Uni-
order to engage in the versity of Arizona. His main interests are in
behavior that Spiegel philosophy of mind and cognitive science. He also
finds intolerable. has substantial interests in philosophy of religion.
If one truly
believes that God • The Making of An Atheist: How Immorality
exists, Spiegel’s task Leads to Unbelief by Jason Spiegel, Moody Publishers,
to explain non-belief 2010, $12.99, ISBN: 978-0-8024-7611-1

46 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Book Reviews
Books
Berkeley’s Puzzle most direct way, is the table itself. a physical object is to know what its identity
by John Campbell & This idea faces an immediate obvious conditions are, and in particular, how its
Quassim Cassam problem. Hallucinations present us with identity at one time is causally dependent on
cases where I can have an apparent visual its identity at an earlier time.
IT SEEMS PLAUSIBLE TO experience of, say, a table, even when there Aside from the detailed reservations one
say that we have some is no table present – when, for example the can have about the individual theses
knowledge of some of the objects in the experience has been caused by some brain defended by Campbell and Cassam, there
world around us. I know now, for example, malfunction. So, how can experience be a are two further problems with what they
that I am sitting at a table, that the table is relation in the way Campbell supposes – both say. Firstly, their main question is
roughly rectangular, and that it is a shade that is, how can experience of a table guar- how sensory experience gives rise to reli-
of brown. It also seems plausible to say that antee the presence of the real, mind-inde- able knowledge of a mind-independent
we have knowledge of this kind because of pendent object? world. But at best they show only how to
the sensory experiences we have. These Campbell’s response to this objection is cross the gap between ‘John has a sensory
claims seem reassuringly, perhaps even rather curious: he denies that there are any experience of something table-like’ and
boringly, secure. hallucinations in the sense intended by the ‘John sees a table’. This is inadequate as an
These seeming truisms form the basis of objection. He says that if you subtract the explanation of perception-based knowledge,
a debate between John Campbell, profes- presence of the table from the visual expe- because John can well see something red
sor of philosophy at Berkeley, who defends rience you have when you look at the table, without gaining any knowledge at all: he
a so-called ‘relational’ view of sensory you are left with… nothing at all! may for example still wrongly think that
experience, and Quassim Cassam, profes- This claim seems so obviously mistaken what he sees is blue or yellow. He may
sor of philosophy at Warwick, who that it is natural to wonder if he really even believe that he’s hallucinating, and
defends a so-called ‘representational’ view. means it. But it seems he does: speaking of therefore not believe that he’s seeing any-
The difference between these views con- hallucinating an airport, he says “Subtract thing mind-independent at all. What still
sists in how the concept of sensory experi- the airport [from your visual experience], needs explaining is how to get from ‘John
ence is to be understood, in particular con- and there is nothing left to inspect” (p.92). sees something red’ to ‘John knows that
cerning the way in which it underpins the Although Cassam does not himself there is something red and mind-indepen-
knowledge we have of the world around us. advance this objection to Campbell’s rela- dent in his line of sight’. Without that link,
According to Campbell’s view, as the tionist account of sense experience, he nev- we will still have no complete account of
label suggests, sense experiences are rela- ertheless maintains that Campbell’s position how our knowledge of the world around us
tions between perceivers and external objects. is mistaken, and that we should instead hold arises from our sensory experience.
To say for example that I have a visual a representationalist view. In general terms, The second problem concerns the fact
experience of the table, is to say that there this is the claim that “sensory experience has that neither of the authors lays out what
exist two things – myself and the table – representational content” (p.105 footnote). they take knowledge to be. There are cur-
and there is a relation between us. What I Thus we perceive chairs and tables by rently half a dozen or more well-defended
am aware of, says Campbell, is not some having representational experiences whose accounts of what knowledge is. Without
item intermediate between myself and the content is chair or table. For Cassam it is not some specification of which notion of
table such as a visual image or visual sensa- simply that the objects of our awareness are knowledge is being presupposed, it is not
tion, from which I (usually automatically, mental images of chairs and tables, such that clear exactly what question is being asked
that is, nonconsciously) infer the presence those images represent the things. Rather, by someone who asks ‘How do our sense
of the table. Rather, what I aware of, in the to see a real table is, in part, to have an expe- experiences give rise to knowledge of the
rience with a table world round us?’
Do we perceive things content. In spite of a seductively beautiful cover,
as they really are?
Woven into this this not a text for the lay reader, even one
debate about the rela- prepared to make a serious effort. Too
tion between our much of the debate is left implicit, too
minds, our sense many technical terms introduced without
experiences, and the adequate explanation, and the style is heavy
external world, both going throughout. So it is hard to believe
authors are concerned that this book would add much to such a
with the further ques- reader’s grasp of sense perception, or of
tion ‘How does our their knowledge of the external world.
sensory experience © NICK EVERITT 2016
ground our conception Nick Everitt, now retired, was Senior Lecturer
of objects that exist in Philosophy at the University of East Anglia.
independently of our He is the author of The Non-Existence of
perceiving them?’ God (Routledge).
This question is
answered, says Camp- • Berkeley’s Puzzle by John Campbell and Quassim
bell, by accepting that Cassam, OUP, 2014, 224 pages, £19.99, ISBN:
to have the concept of 0198716257

Book Reviews August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 47


STAR WARS:
The Force Awakens
Films ow do you reboot a classic sci fi fran-
Jason Eberl and Kevin Decker
awaken the philosophy of the Force.
DuBois, the ‘Other’ in existentialist literature Running Circles

H chise under new corporate and direc-


torial control while pleasing loyal
legions of international fans? You give it to
and Lacanian psychoanalysis, and in many
other philosophies. As Bryan Seitz of Babson
College puts it in his article ‘Philosophy and
In his book Truth and Method (1960),
Hans-Georg Gadamer wrote, “The circle of
whole and part is not dissolved in perfect
J.J. Abrams, apparently – as his recent big- the Double’, “Philosophy finds power and understanding, but, on the contrary, is most
budget Star Trek and Star Wars films both security in the double but from it simultane- fully realized.” Correspondingly, each of the
demonstrate. The six original episodes of the ously inherits countless forms of depen- Star Wars films needs to be interpreted in
Star Wars franchise are ripe for philosophical, dence and instability.” The same inheritance terms of the whole story cycle. Our under-
psychological, and religious analysis. But of dependence and instability is true of Star standing and appreciation of these films is
what Abrams brings to the newest install- Wars. In The Force Awakens, a new masked dependent upon what has come before and
ment, Episode VII: The Force Awakens villain, Kylo Ren, addresses the burnt-out hel- what we know is coming or anticipate com-
(2015), also demands a meta-philosophical met of his grandfather Darth Vader, promising ing later in the saga. (Episode VII does the lat-
approach. to “finish what you started”; but later, the ter brilliantly in withholding the person of
film’s heroine Rey discovers that Kylo Ren is Luke Skywalker for so long.)
Seeing Double afraid that he’ll never be as strong as Vader. In the original film, Darth Vader taunted
The internal mythology of Star Wars rests The Force Awakens as a whole is itself a Obi-Wan Kenobi with the words, “The circle
on a kind of dualism, with the dark and light double of the original Star Wars film (now is now complete.” To complete the narrative
sides of the Force, but Episode VII also deals known as Episode IV: A New Hope), with circle, the heavy emphasis on the doubling of
with a lot of doubles. Critics have pointed some key elements of Episode V: The characters, situations, and plot in The Force
out how in The Force Awakens Rey doubles Empire Strikes Back thrown in. Some com- Awakens will have to be redeemed by
for Luke Skywalker, Finn – as both comic plain that Abrams simply retells the original Episode VIII, in which our investment in the
relief and a source of moral ambiguity – dou- story, with the First Order as ‘Empire 2.0’, new characters must be rewarded by taking
bles for Han Solo, and once again we have a and the Starkiller weapon as a bigger Death real risks in a darker, more psychologically-
wise, short, and comically odd character in Star, among other direct parallels. This fact driven plot, as The Empire Strikes Back did in
the form of Maz Kanata (cf Yoda). The idea has troubled many fans who left the theater 1980.
of doubles is a recurrent trope of fiction, exhilarated as John Williams’ latest score Alternatively, it might be said that, on the
which has taken basic problems of reality thundered away, only to reach home feeling contrary, Star Wars seems to be trapped
and appearance from the very start of phi- cheated by the lack of originality in the plot. within its own narrative structures, endlessly
losophy. Think for instance of Plato and Aris- It’s lmost as if, in order to help the audience replicating doubles of its original characters
totle’s use of the idea of mimesis – artistic overlook the much-derided prequel trilogy and setting them against each other in new
creation understood as the re-presentation (Episodes I-III), Abrams wanted to reassure concatenations. Perhaps this is done inten-
of nature. The ‘doubles’ theme also appears everyone that “This is your father’s Star tionally by the filmmakers, bringing us back
in the ‘double consciousness’ of W.E.B. Wars.” to the mythological origins of the film saga
by invoking the concept of ‘eternal recur-
Dreyja vu:
rence’ or the ‘karmic cycle’.
two apparent
Loss & Recovery
orphans
If the prequel trilogy was guilty of deca-
dence (both in terms of the moral decay of
the Republic and the films’ own over-
wrought production values), then the
newest film must be characterized in terms
of loss and recovery. In its final act, classic
heroes Han Solo and Chewbacca join with
ex-stormtrooper Finn to infiltrate and dis-
able the shields surrounding the evil First
Order’s planet-sized Starkiller weapon,
which is capable of obliterating entire plane-
tary systems light-years away. Upon discov-
ering that Finn’s job was in sanitation, Han
complains that the entire galaxy is counting
on them to lower the shields so Resistance

48 Philosophy Now l August/September 2016


Here comes trouble
at the double

forces can fly in and destroy it. Finn even Han Solo’s demanding epistemic stan-
Films
between the Force and the physical world
responds, “We’ll figure it out, we’ll use the dards. that certain philosophers of mind (such as
Force!” Han retorts, “That’s not how the David Chalmers in The Conscious Mind,
Force works!” Re-Enchanting The Galaxy 1996) allege to exist between immaterial
Finn’s misunderstanding stems from his Abrams and Co. have eschewed the mental properties – beliefs, desires, propo-
having grown up in a society in which the sappy romance, details of galactic eco- sitional knowledge etc – and neural corre-
Jedi Order and the Force have been rele- nomics, and over-reliance on computer-gen- lates in the brain. That is to say, just
gated to mythological status. Finn’s world is erated characters and settings that led to because there’s a physical correlate of
what Charles Taylor, in his A Secular Age fan derision of the prequel trilogy. Also one’s ability to access the Force doesn’t
(2007), would call ‘disenchanted’. In a disen- apparently abandoned from the prequels is mean that the Force itself doesn’t remain
chanted world, belief in anything beyond the seeming reduction of the Force from a something immaterial, transcendental. (A
what is evident to the senses or that can be mystical energy field to ‘midi-chlorians’ – physical correlate is arguably necessary to
rationally inferred from them has been tiny life-forms. Instead, the Force has been explain how sensitivity to the Force tends to
largely abandoned. Han Solo himself, nearly returned to its rightful place as something run in families.)
forty years before, professed his preference both mysterious and ubiquitous. In the Is the Star Wars galaxy better off for hav-
for more pragmatic solutions to life’s battles recent film, even non-Jedis, such as the ing been re-enchanted in The Force Awak-
to aspiring Jedi Luke Skywalker, saying: ancient and wise barkeep Maz Kanata, are ens? One valuable by-product of belief in
“Hokey religions and ancient weapons are able to sense the omnipresent Force. Kylo the Force as a mystical power is that it
no match for a good blaster at your side, Ren also uses the Force in new ways: not allows for clear distinctions to be drawn
kid… I’ve never seen anything to make me just planting mild telepathic suggestions in between good and evil. So even though Kylo
believe there’s one all-powerful Force con- the weak-minded, but pillaging his victims’ Ren feels an internal struggle between the
trolling everything… It’s all a lot of simple minds for information. light and darkness within himself, he seems
tricks and nonsense.” Clearly, everything he Combining both views of the Force, one to have a clear idea of the difference of the
has since seen of the Force has satisfied could describe a similar relationship two sides of the Force. The sacrifice he

A galaxy of adventure
reawakens

ALL FORCE AWAKENS IMAGES © WALT DISNEY STUDIOS 2015


LUKE SKYWALKER IMAGE © 20TH CENTURY FOX 1977

August/September 2016 l Philosophy Now 49


Looks familiar:
Not the first vision of universal order

must make to cement his alliance with the Order & Disorder for the next two episodes. The strength of
dark side, while difficult to go through with, The political atmosphere depicted in The Abrams’ direction in extracting dramatic and
is nevertheless very evident to him. Force Awakens thematically mirrors both the physical performances, especially from the
galactic politics of the saga’s previous trilogies new leads, makes us genuinely invested in the
Heroes & Villains and the moral motivations of their heroes and successes and failures of the next generation
If a movie writer cares to follow Aristo- villains. ‘The First Order’ is aptly named, since of the Resistance in ways that the flat perfor-
tle’s advice in his Nicomachean Ethics, that General Hux decries its enemies, the politically mances of Lucas’s characters in Episodes I-III
cultivating moral virtue from youth is all- dominant New Republic, as “a regime that simply could not. What it fails to accomplish,
important, then a perennial issue for a cine- acquiesces to disorder.” In the prequel trilogy, however – on its own at least – is to move the
matic saga that aims for universal appeal Chancellor Palpatine fabricated a galactic civil story forward in a novel direction that intro-
not only across cultures but also across war to destabilize the Old Republic, allowing duces new and distinct philosophical ques-
generations is that a good morality tale him to transform a diverse and democratic tions or issues. As we considered, Star Wars
must be graspable even by young minds. In government into a tyrannical Empire through might now be trapped within its own narra-
this, Star Wars is arguably no different from his manipulation of senators desiring “a safe tive. At the very least, Abrams and his collabo-
The Lord of the Rings, The Chronicles of and secure society.” While the senators’ moti- rators have once again channeled the persis-
Narnia, or the Harry Potter series. The vation in trading liberty for security is under- tent appeal of the ‘hero’s journey’ as
trade-off for moral simplicity, however, is standable (even if wrongheaded and short- described by mythologist Joseph Campbell in
that there is correspondingly less represen- sighted), Hux’s disdain for the ‘disorder’ of the his The Hero with a Thousand Faces (1949).
tation of the complexities of human moral New Republic appears unmotivated; there Whether it’s Anakin Skywalker, Luke Sky-
psychology. The story of the fall and seems to be no evident conflict or strife within walker, or Rey (Skywalker?), we see a young
redemption of Anakin Skywalker (Darth the new democratic regime other than what protagonist with a mysterious past living in a
Vader), as told in the previous six films, the First Order itself introduces. desert place, guided by a wise elder, who is
does show a degree of complexity, as Perhaps it is worth reflecting here on led to discover his or her innate potential, and
Anakin seeks to balance his love for his wife Abrams’ intentional use of Nazi imagery eventually faces a moment of choice between
and unborn children with his duties as a Jedi when Hux addresses his troops before firing using their power for good or evil. Maybe this
Knight. As Augustine would put it in On Free the Starkiller weapon. The First Order is not oft-repeated cycle also captures the essence
Choice of the Will, Anakin ultimately falls so much combatting the perceived inherent of the human condition: a relatively immature
because of his “inordinate desire for tempo- disorder of democratic society, but rather species, living in a hostile and unforgiving
ral goods” or, as the Buddha (and Yoda) asserting its own ‘will to power’ – to cite world whose origin is not fully understood,
would contend, his inability to detach him- Nietzsche’s concept of the fundamental drive guided by the wisdom of our philosophical
self from what is perishable and transitory. of all living beings. Perhaps that same moti- elders as we endeavor to discover our inher-
Complexity is lacking, though, in the vation drove Anakin Skywalker towards his ent collective potential, continually facing the
repeated refrain of there being a single destiny as Darth Vader as he strove to con- choice to employ our rationality and auton-
moment of turning from the light side to the trol his own fate and that of those he loves – omy to better or to worsen the world. May the
dark, or vice versa: Anakin becomes Vader with the classically tragic outcome that he Force be with us all – we’ll need it!
the moment he attacks Mace Windu in ended up causing the very death he was © PROFS JASON T. EBERL & KEVIN S. DECKER 2016
Revenge of the Sith. Then he’s unrepen- seeking the power to avoid. Jason T. Eberl is the Semler Endowed Chair
tantly evil for over two decades until the for Medical Ethics and Professor of Philoso-
moment he kills the Emperor and is Star Wars Reawakens phy at Marian University, Indianapolis. Kevin
redeemed. Similarly, Kylo Ren struggles with As the first in a new trilogy of Star Wars S. Decker is Professor of Philosophy at East-
his turn to the dark side until the moment films, The Force Awakens succeeds tremen- ern Washington University. They are the edi-
he makes a dire decision which many fans dously in revitalizing the spirit of the original tors of The Ultimate Star Wars and Philoso-
think now makes him irredeemable. films and functions as an effective foundation phy (Wiley-Blackwell).

50 Philosophy Now l August/September 2016


Thinkers Against Xenophobia
How To Deal with Pride and Prejudice
Anja Steinbauer

W
ho are you, and who am I? As a reader of Philoso- Arthur Schopenhauer was one of those extraordinary
phy Now you have probably come across such thinkers who early on recognized this dangerous power of
questions many times. We ask them in meta- prejudice: “The discovery of truth is prevented more effec-
physics, the philosophy of mind, epistemology, as well as the tively, not by the false appearance things present and which
philosophy of psychology and related areas. However, mislead into error, not directly by weakness of the reasoning
nowhere does the problem of the supposed identity of self and powers, but by preconceived opinion, by prejudice.” What
other wreak havoc as it does in the area of human relation- makes prejudice so tricky to expose for what it is and fight
ships – moral, social and political. effectively is that often it is shared and thereby reinforced,
When we think about who we are, we also think about who sometimes even a majority view and generally held to be true.
we are not; we define ourselves off against an ‘other’. How do Mary Wollstonecraft observes that “when any prevailing preju-
we deal with the existence of the other? dice is attacked, the wise will consider, and
G.W.F. Hegel thought that the encounter leave the narrow-minded to rail with thought-
between two self-conscious beings is best less vehemence at innovation.”
described as a ‘life-and-death’ struggle. We must do more than that. We must calmly
Luckily, not all encounters with others are and constructively, yet unrelentingly challenge
like that. We can develop sincere bonds, prejudice wherever we find it. I believe that
friendships that mean happiness rather this is at the heart of what Hannah Arendt
than a threat. However, as the existence of wants to say when she says that human lives
racism, xenophobia, sexism and other can only find true fulfillment in the political
kinds of prejudice suggest, there is plenty context.
of potential for it to go wrong. When Nietzsche referred to the philosopher
Why do we ever react to the existence as a dangerous explosive in the presence of
to other people with prejudice and rejec- which nothing is safe – he was right. Philoso-
tion? Many explanations of the causes of phy can unmask our own prejudices as well as
prejudice have been suggested. Philosoph- show up those of others. This is what we
ical, psychological and sociological theo- intend to do over the next few months and
ries abound: social inequality, peer pres- years, and should it be necessary to the end of
sure, the desire to elevate one’s own status, our lives. We want to explore the issues
the ‘horns effect’, in-group bias, tribalism and many more. concerning xenophobia, its roots, forms and rationality, the
Immanuel Kant thought that prejudice arises from a natural nature of prejudice generally, racism, sexism and homophobia,
preference for oneself and one’s interests over those of others. multiculturalism, globalisation, democracy in a globalised
However, although this kind of ‘logical egoism’ affects most of world, and overcome prejudice by honest and constructive
us, it is the ability to relativise this selfishness and put it in dialogue.
proper social perspective that allows us to overcome prejudice. Philosophy Now calls on all thinkers of the world, inside and
One of the worst forms of prejudice, and strangely also out of academia, to join us in taking a stand against xenopho-
perhaps the one that is easiest to understand is xenophobia: we bia. We believe that to fight prejudice in all its forms is a major
tend to fear what we don’t know, and we exaggerate what responsibility of all thinking individuals. In order to raise
we’re afraid of. There seem to be so many things that divide awareness of these issues we will organise a number of events,
us, and in a climate of social uncertainty and injustices it is which we will advertise on our website (philosophynow.org)
tempting to focus on these. We have seen the rise of this to a and on Facebook. We also invite articles on all aspects of xeno-
worrying degree in all corners of the globe. phobia and general prejudice, as well as about relevant values
There are many reasons to be deeply worried about xeno- such as cosmopolitanism and solidarity.
phobia and other forms of social prejudice: reasons connected Join us in our battle against xenophobia! Albert Einstein is
with flawed moral thinking, reasons having to do with devas- rumoured to have bemoaned the fact that “it is harder to crack
tating political and social consequences. In many ways, preju- a prejudice than an atom.” The atom has been cracked; preju-
dice is the nemesis of the philosopher. It is one of the things to dice is next.
which Philosophy Now tries to draw attention with its annual © DR ANJA STEINBAUER 2016
Award For Contributions in the Fight Against Stupidity: prej- Anja Steinbauer teaches at the London School of Philosophy and is an
udice annuls truth. Editor for Philosophy Now.

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 51


Brief Lives
Xunzi (c.320-235 BCE)
Dale DeBakcsy thinks diligently about Xunzi’s psychological Confucianism.

O
ne of the intellectual administration – many of the major figures we know today led
crutches you’re first dual lives as thinkers and as organizers of men, which is another
given as a Western reason why pragmatism rules the day in their writings.
student of Chinese philoso-
phy is the idea of Confucius Xunzi’s Revolutionary Conservatism
as Socrates, Mencius as Plato, Xunzi is deeply paradoxical in that, in the name of preserv-
and Xunzi as Aristotle. Thus ing tradition he made antiquity’s most thorough-going attacks
we remember Confucius on traditional belief. He stood by Confucius to the letter, but
(551-479 BCE) as the foun- swept a million ancestral spirits out the back door. That is, he
dational moralist who speaks couldn’t abide a single alteration in the terms and distinctions
only through his students; that delineated the Confucian limits of each person’s social
Mencius (372-289 BCE) as duty and expectations, but he denied as a matter of basic fact
the eloquent inheritor of the the efficacy of all prayer.
founder whose praise con- At first glance, this may not make sense: he fights with gusto
tained a subtle push of his and spite for the preservation of a name, and shrugs his shoul-
master’s words in a new ders at the loss of personal immortality. But if we expand our
How do we make a society that works? direction; and Xunzi (c.320- perspective on his times, his startlingly destructive conser-
235 BCE) as the logician who vatism starts making sense. He lived during the last years of the
put everything together. There’s broad truth in that. Like most Warring States era, when everything that the Chinese thought
crutches, this gets you walking – but not incredibly well. For they knew about society was ground to tatters under the wheels
there’s also a good deal in the comparison that blanches one of of warfare. During that era of shifting power and armed diplo-
the most interesting figures in world philosophy – for Xunzi macy, Confucius’s concern with lavish funeral procedures and
was a fearless thinker who trimmed philosophy of any clutter linguistic accuracy seemed downright quaint, and a number of
that didn’t address the question, ‘How do we make a society philosophers rushed to say so. The founding sage was openly
that works?’ mocked, and sophists not so different from those whom
Socrates sparred against (at about the same time in Athens),
A Long Life Briefly Related rose to profit from the abuse of the crumbling Confucian
For all of Xunzi’s importance in the Chinese tradition, we order. By playing wild games with words – confusing their
know virtually nothing about him. The two earliest sources we common meanings and referents – these Chinese sophists cre-
have are those of Sze-ma Ch’ien, written a hundred years after ated cracks in the justice system through which any manner of
Xunzi’s death, and Liu Hsian, about another fifty years after charlatan might romp with ease, while the common people sat-
that. These accounts begin with Xunzi entering the court of isfied themselves with prayers to the ancestors rather than con-
the king of Ts’i around 270 BCE, at the age of fifty. The king certed action to actually improve their lot.
actively cultivated the development of philosophy by founding Here is Xunzi analyzing the efficacy of spirit propitiation:
a college at Ts’i-hsia and luring eminent philosophers there
through the granting of honorary ranks. “If people pray for rain and get rain, why is that? I answer: There is no
Of course, we all know what happens when you get a group reason for it. If people do not pray for rain, it will nevertheless rain. When
of eminent philosophers together. Envy and the mad scramble people save the sun or moon from being eaten, or when they pray for rain in
for status bred the usual slander, and Xunzi, as the most a drought, or when they decide an important affair only after divination –
famous philosopher of the time, received the brunt of these this is not because they think in this way they will get what they seek, but
sotto voce machinations. The king ultimately dismissed him, only to gloss over the matter. Hence the prince thinks it is glossing over the
and he was left to wander China in search of a wise royal matter, but the people think it supernatural. He who thinks it is glossing over
master who would heed his anti-war, pro-Confucian counsel. the matter is fortunate; he who thinks it is supernatural is unfortunate.”
Now, speaking against war during the Warring States era of (The Works of Hsuntze, Bk XVII, Concerning Heaven, trans H.H. Dubs, 1928.)
Chinese history might seem like a hard sell; and it was. Xunzi
never found his wise, peace-loving ruler, and instead settled for That’s the honesty of a man who has been an administrator
a lowly position as a district magistrate for Prince Ch’uin- and is willing to at last reveal the cynics behind the curtain.
shen. He held that position until his eighty-third year, when And he’s not nearly done:
his prince was assassinated and the new ruler promptly
drummed Xunzi out of office, prompting him to retire from “How can exalting Heaven and wishing for its gifts be as good as heaping
public work. At 82, he probably deserved the rest. up wealth and using it advantageously? How can obeying Heaven and
This course of career was typical for a philosopher in ancient praising it be as good as adapting oneself to the appointments of Heaven
China. During that era, philosophy went hand in hand with and using them? How can hoping for the proper time and waiting for it be

52 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Brief Lives
as good as seizing the opportunity and acting? How can relying on things gain, it’s about having a recognized vehicle for cathartically
increasing of themselves be as good as putting forth one’s energy and purging anguish. The ceremonial aspect allows those who feel
developing things? How can thinking of things and comparing them be as too little to not be conspicuously offensive, and prevents those
good as looking after things and not losing them? How can wishing that who feel too much from collapsing. Ceremony provides the
things may come to pass be as good as taking what one has and bringing middle ground that allows everybody to comfortably and reas-
things to pass? Therefore if a person neglects what men can do and seeks suringly go through the waystations of life, and therefore it is
for what Heaven does, he fails to understand the nature of things” (ibid). valuable in a way that tradition had refused to expound upon.
Explanations like these, which explore the human necessity and
That is about as unambiguous a statement of the impotence subtle benefits of precisely those institutions the Warring State
of religiosity and the primacy of purely human action that you sophists savagely mocked, kept Xunzi in the canon even as his
will see this side of Pietro Pomponazzi (1462-1525), and it view of humanity’s evil but perfectible nature lost ground to
could only have come from a culture where the lawmaker and Mencius’s more cheerful assessment. He assembled and ana-
the philosophical theorist were one and the same. lyzed the crucial texts of China’s rich intellectual past, and
transmitted them in a form that the future could recognize as
A Shock To The System something as beyond mere Tradition For Tradition’s Sake.
Xunzi saw all the chaos and opportunism, the wasted yam-
mering towards an indifferent sky, and at once perceived the A Chinese Leviathan
root problem: that people were putting too much faith in the Like Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679), Xunzi was the sort of
unknowable, and not enough in the simple social principles conservative whose traditionalism ended up being more radical
that had bound person to person in China since times of than the most liberal of his contemporaries. The parallels are
legend. They needed to spend less time meditating and striking: both lived in an age of civil war, and took from it simi-
hoping, and more time learning and acting. They needed a lar lessons about the need for civilization to protect oppression-
profound philosophical shock that would upset intellectual prone minorities – which lessons are remembered almost exclu-
complacency and tell unpleasant truths that could seal the sively, and unfairly, for their negative content. Both men also
breaches that had been made in the Confucian societal fabric. rejected much of the religious thinking of their day in favor of a
He delivered that shock in a series of writings of such stark psychology-based approach to human institutions and motivations.
realism and frankness that they have no equal in antiquity, But let’s not forget their conservative content: Hobbes ulti-
Western or Eastern. As opposed to Mencius, who had hypoth- mately defended the unifying potential of monarchy, and Xunzi
esized that humans are basically good, and improve upon that was an acidic critic of anything that smacked of unorthodoxy
basic nature through following Confucian principles, Xunzi with regards to Confucianism. His sixth book is little more than
leveled with us. Human beings are innately evil. They are pro- an extended rap against every philosopher of his age who had
pelled by desires that bring them into conflicts that are decided the audacity to not interpret Confucius the way that he did.
to the detriment of the weak. Mencius’s pretty talk about us However, unlike Hobbes, who was an avid, if often unfortunate
being basically good might make us feel nice; but it is contra- mathematician, Xunzi had no interest in furthering the sciences,
dicted by our need for extensive laws and governance. We or any discernible curiosity in how things work. He considered
make and strictly enforce laws to protect us from ourselves – a those questions to be as useless as metaphysical queries. Who
fact that makes no sense if we’re inherently good, but which cares what heat is, we need to keep filial piety well-defined!
follows readily if our nature is basically evil. Xunzi’s ideal world is static, where terms stay comfortably
That’s the bad news. The good news is that, evil though we what they are because nothing changes, and where people seek
are by nature, we are boundlessly perfectible through culture. wisdom through study of an approved list of books, and enjoy
Xunzi is astoundingly democratic in his notion of human comfort through a reasonable and ordered relation to their
improvement. Anybody can become a great sage, no matter society mediated by universally understood ceremony. Nothing
what their origins, as long as they resolve to study, to avoid evolves in this place, and, for a man who lived through the last
questions that consume time with no profit (such as anything years of the Warring States era, that’s perfectly fine. Beneath
hinting of metaphysics), and to seek and follow useful criticism. that inertia, however, there is a pulsing spirit that refuses to be
His faith in the improving power of civilization and the self- fooled, that cuts through sophistry and theology to insist that if
transformative power of intellectual cultivation is unshakeable. we are to improve our lot it’s down to us and our willingness to
Even living in desperate times, where everything he loved act with mutual consideration for each other’s weaknesses.
about Chinese culture was being summarily trashed in the Xunzi had an ecstatic appreciation of our ability to cultivate
name of territory, he held to the idea that correct speech would ourselves through education. He exploded the big deceptions of
become correct behavior, would become a beautiful society. But popular belief in order to illuminate the little truths of day-to-
he recast that restored vision of Confucian civilization in a day civility. That intellectual daring warrants something more
thoroughly secular form, replacing its occasional spiritualism than the indifferent title of ‘the Eastern Aristotle’.
with an instinct for psychological truth. He defended the Con- © DALE DEBAKCSY 2016
fucian funerary practices not in the name of propitiation of Dale DeBakcsy writes the ‘History of Humanism’ feature at The-
ancestral spirits or reward from Heaven, but as a beautiful and Humanist.com and is the co-writer of the twice-weekly history and
useful way of transitioning people through the pangs of grief. philosophy webcomic Frederick the Great: A Most Lamentable
Thus sacrificing to the spirits is not about receiving tangible Comedy.

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 53


Philosophy Now
Shop
Digital Editions (for more info visit philosophynow.org/digital)
Philoso
phy Now

Apps for iPad/iPhone, Android and Kindle Fire Zinio


Philosophy Now’s very own app is available in Apple’s App There is also an edition for the Zinio app on iPad
Store. The Android version of it is in the Google Play store and and Android. Single issue or ongoing
there is a Kindle Fire version too. Free sample issue included. subscription.

Kindle PN Website Subscriptions


Philosophy Now is available for Amazon’s Kindle. You can buy a Individual print subscriptions to Philosophy Now don’t include
single issue or an ongoing subscription. (30 day free trial period) Kindle, Nook, app etc but do include a password for our website
edition plus our archive of 2,000+ articles from past issues.
Nook (Your password is available on request or is sent automatically if
Philosophy Now’s edition for Barnes & Noble’s Nook reader also you subscribe online.) We also sell these web subscriptions
works brilliantly on the Nook app on iPhones. (14 day free trial) separately, from our store at philosophynow.org/shop

Back Issues – Paper


Issue 100 Philosophy & Language: Chomsky, Davidson, Derrida, Deleuze, Issue 112 Free Will: libertarianism, determinism, compatibilism, akrasia... /
Proust / Happiness / Rorty / What is Knowledge, Truth, Causation? self-interest / Nietzsche & Dali / Wilson’s Life / Singer is wrong
Issue 101 Plato & Democracy: Critiques & Analyses / Kant and Rand / Issue 113 New Realism: Markus Gabriel, Maurizio Ferraris etc / The Use of
Feelings & Philosophy / Gandhi Opera review / Obit. Colin Wilson Embryos / Drugs / Cocktails / Mathematical Universe / Socs & Zen
Issue 102 Ethics in Society: Prison; Consumer Responsibility; Drugs in Sport; Issue 114 Philosophical Science: Brains, Chaos, Feynman, Mirrors / Zizek /
Judging Islamic Culture / Brief Life: Marx / Existence / Empiricism Whitehead / Nietzsche / Schopenhauer / Language / Poetry
Issue 103 Wittgenstein, Tractatus: Cannons, Cases & Codes / Lenk on Dewey / We also still have copies of these earlier back issues:
Midgley on History of Philosophy / Consequentialism is impossible Issues 2, 4, 35, 39-47, 55-80, 82, 84, 85, 87-89, 91-99
Issue 104 The Other Greeks: Pre-Socratics, Democritus, Diogenes, Epicurus / Back issues cost £3.75 each if you live in the UK (inc p&p) or
Nietzsche on Love / The Morality Machine / Obscurantism / Fichte
US$10/Can$10/A$10/NZ$12/UK£6.50 elsewhere (via airmail).
Issue 105 Peace: Innate Violence?; Pacificism not passivism; personal peace; love
& happiness / Darwin / Berkeley’s 4th Dialogue / Short Hist of Phil
For every three back issues you buy, we’ll give you a fourth for
Issue 106 How to Think: Critically Reason, Solve Paradoxes, Not Refute free (please tell us which you would like). For full details and
Yourself, etc / Hegel’s heirs reviews / Aliens vs Vegetarians / Rorty tables of contents of all back issues, please visit our website shop
Issue 107 Modern French Philosophy: Foucault, Derrida, Baudrillard, Kristeva, at philosophynow.org/shop
Badiou / Je Suis Liberal / Noam Chomsky speech / Personal Identity
Issue 108 Art: Encountering it, problems with it, what is it, and where’s it PDFs: Our website shop also sells individual back issues as
going? / Music / Descartes vs Animals / Self-interest in morality downloadable PDFs.
Issue 109 Science & Morality / Einstein’s Ethics / Prisoner’s Dilemma and
Evolution / Defending Badiou / Atheism on Trial / Clueless Binders: Why not give your back issues a secure and happy
Issue 110 Liberty & Equality, inc. Redistribution, Surveillance, Paradoxes,
Philosopher Citizens / Scepticism / Albert Camus / Common Sense
home? Our smart green Philosophy Now binders each hold 12
Issue 111 Humo(u)r: the reasons, ethics & limits of humo(u)r, and beyond / magazines. Price per binder: UK£8.75, USA $25, Australia A$27,
Scrooge’s free will / Justice for apes / Wittgenstein vs Occam / Tarski Canada Can$27, New Zealand NZ$34, or Rest of World UK£15.
BACK ISSUES VOLUME ONE

Back Issues on CD Philosophy Now


a magazine of ideas

Philosophy Now has been published since 1991, so it is hardly surprising that
BACK ISSUES VOLUME TWO

we’re often asked for back issues which have long since sold out. Therefore Philosophy Now
a magazine of ideas

we’ve put our first eighty issues onto four CDs in PDF format. The CDs work
Issues 1-20

equally well on Mac and PC, and when opened on your computer screen will
BACK ISSUES

Philosophy Now
a magazine of ideas

look very much like the pages in the original magazines.


Issues 21-40

Vol. 1: Issues 01-20; Vol. 2: Issues 21-40; Vol. 3: Issues 41-60; Vol. 4: Issues 61-80
Issues 41-60
VOLUME THREE

Single vol. (1, 2, 3 or 4) UK£15 US$23 Can$35 Aus$35 NZ$40 RoW£17


Two volumes: UK£25 US$40 Can$55 Aus$55 NZ$65 RoW£30
Three volumes: UK£35 US$55 Can$75 Aus$75 NZ$90 RoW£40
Four volumes: UK£45 US$69 Can$95 Aus$95 NZ$115 RoW£51

IP-BASED ONLINE ACCESS is available for institutions – please visit philosophynow.org/institutions

54 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Philosophy Now
Subscriptions
Philosophy Now is sold from newsstands and
bookstores in more than a dozen countries – but if you
subscribe you can have each new issue delivered to
your own front door and save money too. Better still,
individual print subscriptions include password access
to our website edition and the complete archive of past
issues. Subscribe today at philosophynow.org or fill
out and return one of the coupons below.

6 IDEA-PACKED ISSUES FOR £15.50/US$32!


Questions and inquiries: please email subscriptions@philosophynow.org or phone 01959 534171
To tell us about a change of address, please email addresschange@philosophynow.org

U.K. / Rest of World United States


Name Name
Address Address

Email (for password) Email (for password)


Please circle or underline one of the options below: Please select from the options below:
• I’d like to subscribe to Philosophy Now for 6 issues, • I’d like to subscribe to Philosophy Now for 6 issues, at a
UK £15.50 Australia Aus $40 cost of $32.00 starting with #115/#116 (delete as appropriate)
Canada Can $37 Europe £16.50 • I’d like to subscribe to Philosophy Now for 12 issues, at a
New Zealand NZ $49 Rest of World £19.50
cost of $59.00 starting with #115/#116 (delete as appropriate)
• I’d like to subscribe to Philosophy Now for 12 issues,
UK £28.00 Australia Aus $75 • I’d like to buy these Philosophy Now Back Issues CDs:
Canada Can $69 Europe £31.00 Volume 1/Volume 2/Volume 3/Volume 4. (please circle)
New Zealand NZ $93 Rest of World £35.00
starting with Issue 115/Issue 116 (delete as appropriate) • I’d like to buy the following paper back issues:
______________________________________
• I’d like to buy these Philosophy Now Back Issues CDs:
Volume 1/Volume 2/Volume 3/Volume 4. (please circle) • I’d like to buy ___ binders to hold my back issues.

• I’d like to buy the following paper back issues: TOTAL AMOUNT PAYABLE: $_______
______________________________________
Please make your check payable to ‘Philosophy Documentation Center’
• I’d like to buy ___ binders to hold my back issues. or fill in your card details below:
Card no.
TOTAL AMOUNT PAYABLE: _________
Expiry______ Security Code______ Name on card___________________
Please make your cheque payable to ‘Philosophy Now’ or fill in your
Mastercard /Visa /Maestro card details below: and send it to: Philosophy Documentation Center,
Card no. P.O. Box 7147,
Expiry______ Security Code______ Name on card___________________ Charlottesville, VA 22906-7147
and send it to: Philosophy Now Subscriptions U.S.A.
Kelvin House, Grays Road,
Westerham, Kent TN16 2JB,
(You can also order on 800-444-2419 or email pkswope@pdcnet.org)
United Kingdom

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 55


T allis Time & Change
in
Wonderland Take the time to allow Raymond Tallis to change your
view on time and change. Or leave it unchanged.
‘The ball is in position 1’ and ‘The ball is tain times are propitious for the occurrence
in position 2’, or ‘The ball is green all of certain events. This plausibly reduces to
over’ and ‘The ball is red all over’. All four the idea that certain circumstances that hap-
propositions can be true if we add ‘at time pen to be prevailing at one time rather than
t1’ and ‘at time t2’ to the first and second another predispose to certain events. With
members of the pairs respectively. Time, it this interpretation, we can cut out the mid-
appears, is permissive of change. dle man – time – from the causal process. It
is not ‘12 noon on 5th June 2016’ that
Permissiveness Problems causes the events that happen immediately
There are at least two problems with this after 12 noon, but how things are, and what
seemingly innocent truism. The first is that is already ongoing, at 12 noon.
it is difficult to see how we get from a gen- It is not time, but fibroblasts or the
eral permissiveness to the distinctive aspects spirit of forgiveness, that heal wounds.
of time we have already alluded to: duration And perhaps we need to row back from the
quick glance through back issues of (the quantity of time changes take); location idea of time as generally ‘permissive’ of

A Philosophy Now tells me that I have


managed to resist writing about time
for a full year. This seems a decent interval,
(when the changes occur); and temporal
relations between events (simultaneity and
precedence). The second is the danger of
change. Many things are not permitted
(even independent of the constraints of
logical contradiction). What’s more, a
so I hope you will forgive me for returning translating permission into causation. global permissiveness would permit noth-
to a topic which has been my main philo- There are many problems with the idea of ing in particular: if everything were per-
sophical preoccupation for the decade I time as a cause, or, more generally, of time mitted, nothing could happen. Worse still,
have been writing Of Time and Lamentation: being characterised by something it does. the idea that time itself prevents contradic-
Reflections on Transience, which is due out If time itself really were a cause, then tion imports the logic of propositions (‘not
next Spring. One of its many concerns has every event would have two causes: the (p and not-p)’) into the material world,
been the puzzling relationship between cause in the usual sense of ‘a prior event’, including those parts of it, such as the uni-
time and change. such as lightning causing thunder; and a verse prior to sentient beings (which is
It seems that change and time are insep- second cause, time. This would be an exam- most of its history), that are innocent of
arable: changes take time; are located and ple of what philosophers call ‘causal over- logic, discourse, and consciousness.
ordered in time; and they are separated by determination’. More worryingly, it is diffi-
time. The inseparability of time and cult to see how the two causes could work Is Changeless Time No Time At All?
change is a kind of logical truth. Time, it together to assume joint responsibility for So even though change clearly takes
has often been said, stops everything from the effect. How, anyway, would time oper- time (as all changes occur at a finite rate),
happening at once. If everything happened ate at a particular point (in space and time) time does not seem to make change. But is
at once, the material world would seem to to bring about a particular effect? And given the reverse true? Does change make time?
be in a permanent state of self-contradic- that time is homogenous and is present at Should we agree with Aristotle in his
tion. And agency would impossible: I all times, it is even more difficult to see how Physics that “time does not exist without
would be simultaneously setting out for it could make a distinctive contribution to change,” such that time without change is
and returning from holiday. But there is a the unfolding of events, helping to cause the equivalent of dehydrated water? Could
flaw in this way of conceiving things, this event rather than that. There is also an there be periods when time ‘passes’ and yet
flagged up by the phrase ‘at once’. This important ambiguity in the notion of time nothing at all is happening in the entire
phrase itself implies a time relationship – as a cause, identified by W.H. Newton- universe? Is it legitimate to admit the pos-
simultaneity. Time, it seems, would not be Smith in The Structure of Time (1980). New- sibility of a temporal vacuum unoccupied
required to stop everything happening at ton-Smith distinguishes ‘date causation’ by changes, analogous to a spatial vacuum
once (this is the kind of thing that passes (with each moment in time putatively unoccupied by objects or fields?
for a joke in metaphysical circles) if there bringing its distinctive causal contribution Some thought experiments – such as
were no time in the first place. to the unfolding of events) from ‘duration that by Sydney Shoemaker in ‘Time with-
There is, of course, a more serious point causation’ (where the causal contribution of out Change’ (Journal of Philosophy, 1969) –
behind this assertion. Time allows differ- time would be a reflection of the quantity of defend the conceivability of temporal
ence without contradiction. Think of pairs time deployed). The idea of date causation, vacua by envisaging them as being
of apparently incompatible propositions: however, merely reflects the fact that cer- achieved by a stepwise ‘freezing’ or ‘emp-

56 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


tying’ of the world part by part. This is a set of events. ‘A year’ there would be
way of getting round the difficulty of the empty of meaning. There would be noth-
necessary disappearance of the observer ing to distinguish a period of total freezing
(and consequently, observations) in a in the entire universe that lasted an instant
wholly frozen universe. There has to be an from one that lasted forever. In addition,
unfrozen outside to observe the temporally
frozen part of the world since (as is com-
as Ken Warmbrod has pointed out, there
would be nothing occurring to re-start a
T allis
monly believed) observations are the result frozen universe, so no freezing could be
in
of causal interactions between the observer
and the observed. Shoemaker circumvents
this difficulty by imagining that the uni-
verse has three parts, A, B, and C, which
confined to a year, or to any non-infinite
period of time (‘Temporal Vacua’, The
Philosophical Quarterly, 2004).
Wonderland
take it in turns to freeze. Crucially, their Relatively Insubstantial
freezing has different periodicity: A freezes Irrespective of whether Shoemaker’s
for a year once every three years, B once thought experiment is coherent, it is useful
every four years, and C once every five for examining whether time can be con-
years. There will be one year in sixty in ceived as existing independently of the pos-
which all three regions are frozen at once, sibility of change. Is Richard Feynman’s
and the entire universe is changeless. joke that “time is what happens when noth-
While the wholly frozen universe cannot ing else does” based on a fallacy? Is time
be observed, its occurrence can be inferred. something that happens? Is it, as Isaac
Unfortunately, the thought experiment Newton claimed, something “of itself and
does not work. The inhabitants of the uni- from its own nature” that “flows equably
verse are expected, as an inference from and without regards to anything external”?
their observation of the frozen parts A, B, This is the so-called substantivalist view of
and C, to arrive at the conclusion that once time. The opposite view, originally associ- 1985). Ordinary matter starts to look as
every sixty years there would be a total ated with Leibniz, and underpinning the insubstantial, as unreal, as space-time.
freeze. But what basis would there be for Special Theory of Relativity, is that time The problems began as they so often
observation of the frozen state even of the boils down to the relations between events, do, with the solution to another problem.
parts? How can anything which does not and hence cannot be separated from them. The idea of time and space as absolute
emit any energy (because nothing is hap- Those who subscribe to a relational the- containers separate from the changes
pening in it) be observed from without? ory of time get into trouble when they spec- occurring in them was offensive to empiri-
What’s more, if the entire universe became ify what kinds of relations they are talking cal science because empty time and empty
frozen at Year 60, there would be no about. The relations are of course temporal space would be unobservable. Ernst Mach,
grounds for thinking of the duration of the relations. But to reduce time to, for example, the philosopher-physicist who inspired
freeze as a definite period of time, between simultaneity exhibited in successive moments, Einstein, argued that we could not directly
Year 59 and Year 61: there would seem to is not to reduce it at all. So the issue of measure the quantity of time. “Quite the
be a direct movement from Year 59 to (so- whether time is separable from change – contrary, time is an abstraction, at which
called) Year 61. At any rate, there would be from events – or whether it is in some sense we arrive by means of the changes of
no measurable time periods in the vacuum, the product of events, remains unresolved. things.” Clocks do not directly measure
because measurement requires, indeed is, a Anyone looking to physics for assistance time: they are sources of events that are
is going to be disappointed. Einstein began compared with other events.
as a relationist, denying that space and
time were independent of events and Still In Search of Lost Time
rejecting Newton’s idea of space and time The relationship between time and
as an absolute background or ‘frame of ref- change remains elusive. Giving time prior-
erence’. In his fully developed General ity over change, and imagining time con-
Relativity, however, space and time have tinuing in the absence of events, have
morphed into the more substantial space- unsatisfactory consequences. It is no less
time. Now, as twin aspects of curved unsatisfactory to see time as generated
space-time, space and time are active play- from, or subsisting in, the relations
ers in the universe, having observable between events, if only because this leaves
effects on the motion of material objects in us with the seeming impossibility of char-
the form of gravitational and inertial acterising the nature of that relationship
forces. And things get even more messy without mentioning the word ‘time’.
and confusing. As Lawrence Sklar has Time, perhaps, to change the subject.
argued, a consistent reduction of space- © PROF. RAYMOND TALLIS 2016
time to relations between events threatens Raymond Tallis’s latest book The Mystery of
to “move ordinary matter into the same Being Human: God, Freedom and the
dispensable category as substantival space- NHS will be published in September. His
time…” (Philosophy and Space-Time Physics, website is raymondtallis.com.

August/September 2016 ● Philosophy Now 57


Inadequate Options in Adequate Space
Kevin Robson’s existential hero finds that you can’t escape having to choose.
ames Emerson 5 sits at the controls of his “Yes, I’ve an aunt on M223c, she’ll pay my bond.”

J one-man craft. It’s an unglamorous


cargo carrier, with just enough fuel
for this interstellar hop. His cargo, as
The view is
pretty but bleak
“I’m afraid it’s more serious than that. We’re not
going to M223c. In fact, very soon we’re not
gonna be going anywhere.” He points at
far as has been explained to him, is the orange lights: “We’re off course,
17.55kg of archive: paper docu- we’re running out of fuel, we’re losing
ments, bound for the nearest desti- speed, and we’re too far away from any-
nation, the planet M223a. where for anyone to help us.”
The vessel is automatic, so “I’m… sorry,” she ventures.
there’s little for James to do. His “You said that…” James replies. “Not
duties are just to sign the cargo that it matters – why did you do this?
on board and gain a signature for What were you hoping to gain?”
its transfer at the other end. The By way of answer, she rolls up her sleeve.
ship has no distraction or entertain- At first, James thinks that she’s showing
ment: in keeping with the austere him a soiled and bloody undershirt; he then
rationing, it’s been streamlined for maxi- realises with a start that the skin is missing
mum fuel economy. One of the reasons from a patch of her arm. “This is how my uncle
James himself has been able to gain employment treats me,” she says. “Never my face, or anywhere it
on board is his small, skinny frame. Were it not for the might show.” All James can say is “Oh my dear God!”
signatures, they wouldn’t need him at all. The thought gives “Everyone thinks he’s a saint for giving me a home when my
him no comfort. parents died. He knows what he’s doing to me. I wasn’t going
James morose and bored; the chair, a synthetic lightweight to hang around and find out how far he would take it. That’s
raffia; the lights green for OK on screens showing distance and why I’ve done this.”
fuel remaining, speed, and bearing. Green. Green. Green. “I do understand,” responds James. He searches his brain
Orange. This is the first inkling that anything’s wrong. for the right words. The right words don’t come.
James taps the errant screen. It remains orange. It’s the She speaks again, “I’m Sandra. What’s your name?” She says
screen monitoring the ship’s course. If the message is true, he’s it brightly, as if this is a tourist trip. No reply from James, so
off course, with no means to correct it. she adds, “This isn’t much like I thought it would look. I
He taps it again. No change. Obviously a malfunction, he thought it would be huge and luxurious, like in the movies.
reassures himself. When do we eat? I’m starved!”
Then the speedo joins in with the bearing screen, both dis- “Sandra, there’s no food here. There’s not much of anything.”
plays flashing orange. Tapping the glass helps not. And the cir- “So what do we do? How do you pass the time?”
cuit boards are cased and inaccessible. “It passes.” James is starting to become irritable. “Sandra,
Perhaps there is a problem. I’d like you to listen to me. Listen very carefully.”
Moments later the fuel screen also shows orange. The fuel “Okay.”
is running out early. “This vessel is built for one, and there’s no way of correcting
Only one conclusion: a stowaway. And there is only one what you’ve done just by being here. We can’t both survive
possible place that anyone can hide. with the fuel we have.”
When James removes the panel, there she is, no more than “But you can radio for help, yes?”
sixteen Earth years, and very frightened. Large eyes, curled on “No. There is no long-range comms equipment onboard. It
her side in the foetal position. He motions her out and up, but would add unnecessary mass to the ship.”
she’s paralysed with fear. “I won’t hurt you.” His own voice, Sandra tries again “An escape pod? That’d be exciting.”
rarely used, rarely needed, sounds strange to his ears. James shakes his head dolefully: “Not even a pressure suit.”
After a while she emerges. She’s taller than him, just. Per- The situation suddenly becomes clear to Sandra: “You
haps a little heavier. She stands, out of reach, by the airlock mean…?”
hatch. James shifts round to face her. “Yes.” James nods, “That’s what I’ve been trying to tell you.”
“Do you know what you’ve done?” He takes one last look at her face, then enters the airlock. As he
She nods slowly. James waits for her to speak. A small voice: ejects himself into the inky blackness, his final thought is that
“I’m sorry, I know this’ll get you into trouble. You can tell she just might, somehow or other, make it alone.
them it’s my fault.” © KEVIN ROBSON 2016
“And that’s it, is it…?” James is angry, but his voice is still Kevin Robson’s book of short stories and skits, Funder, Chunder,
level: “You thought this would be a telling off?” Reign Asunder, is available as an ebook for 99p.

58 Philosophy Now ● August/September 2016


Advertise in
Philosophy Now
jay.sanders@philosophynow.org

Philosophy Now
Very App-ealing!
There is now a Philosophy Now app for Apple, Android and
Kindle Fire devices. Our app works on tablets and smartphones.
You can download the app for free (it includes one free sample
issue) then buy a subscription within the app to read the mag-
azine. App subscriptions include a 1-month free trial period. All
of our back issues are available for purchase within the app
too. Purchased issues can be downloaded to your device for
reading without an internet connection.
Please visit the Apple App Store, Google Play, or Amazon Appstore for details.

(Please note: when you purchase an app subscription you are buying it from Apple, Google or Amazon, and it does not
include a Philosophy Now print or website subscription. Similarly, our print and website subscriptions do not include an
app subscription. For print/website subscriptions please see p.55 or visit philosophynow.org)
THE MAKERS OF OUR
MODERN WORLD
Who are the people behind the inventions, the discoveries, the
WUHPHQGRXV VFLHQWLÀF DGYDQFHV RI WKH ODVW PLOOHQQLXP" +RZ
did they come to play such a key role in making our modern
ZRUOG" )URP 1HZWRQ WR (LQVWHLQ 5XVVHOO WR :LWWJHQVWHLQ
)RUGWR-REVWKLVFROOHFWLRQRISHQSRUWUDLWVVKHGVOLJKWRQWKH
ELRJUDSK\EHKLQGWKHVFLHQFHDQGWKHVLJQLÀFDQWFRQWULEXWLRQ
RIPRUHWKDQIRUW\LQGLYLGXDOVZKRKDYHFKDQJHGRXUZRUOG

This popular
science book is
widely available as a
paperback and ebook
on Amazon and other
online retailers.

You might also like