Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 25

Progress in Human Geography 22,1 (1998) pp.

15±38

How far should we care? On the


spatial scope of bene®cence
David M. Smith
Department of Geography, Queen Mary and West®eld College,
University of London, Mile End Road, London E1 4NS, UK

Abstract: The question of how far we should care for others, or the spatial scope of beneficence,
raises important issues at the interface of geography and moral philosophy. After introducing
what is at stake, this article reviews partiality conventions manifest in favouring nearest and
dearest people. The possibility of extending the scope of care, in the spirit of impartiality, raises
questions concerning spatial relationships, human similarity and care as a moral value. Attention
then turns to indications of a contemporary resurgence of partiality. Possible reconciliations of
impartiality and an ethic of care are outlined, leading to the conclusion that care should be related
to an egalitarian theory of justice.

Do not judge unfairly,


God abhors partiality,
Regard one you know like one you don't know,
One near you like one far from you (instructions to the Vizier Rekhmire, official of Pharaoh Thutmose III,
c. 1500 BC, quoted in Solomon, 1995: 287).
Hardly any moral philosopher, these days, would deny that we are each entitled to favor our loved ones. Some
would say, even more strongly, that we ought to favor them, that it is not simply a moral option . . . intimacy and
close relationships require partiality (Friedman, 1991: 818).

I Introduction

In a chapter entitled `Justice as vengeance, vengeance as justice', Solomon (1995) stresses


the role of passion or the emotions, `negative' as well as `positive', in the development of
a sense of justice. Invoking vengeance in this way is a provocative challenge to the
Enlightenment tradition of impartial rationality, with its classical roots: `from Plato to
Rawls, philosophical discussions of justice have emphasised the supremacy of reason
and rationality, and there has been too little appreciation of the role of feelings'
(Solomon, 1995: 251). Just as the conventional favouritism of the age of the Pharaohs
invited exhortations to the contrary, so the impartiality which is widely regarded as a
hallmark of modern reason now attracts dissent from a variety of sources. Thus,
Solomon's stress on emotional engagement finds echoes in other contemporary voices

*
c Arnold 1998 0309±1325(98)PH180RA
16 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

(as above, in Friedman, 1991), notably from strands of feminism which counterpose
feeling and reason in justice and morality (e.g., Okin, 1989) and of communitarianism
where Selznick (1992: 387) contrasts piety (`personal, passionate, and particularist') with
civility (`impersonal, rational, and inclusive') as sources of moral integration.
This article takes up one of Solomon's `positive' emotions: that of care. The notion of
an ethic of care has figured prominently in moral philosophy since introduced by
Gilligan (1982) as what was initially claimed to be a distinctively female perspective,
subsequently developed into a broader critique of mainstream thinking by Tronto (1993),
Hekman (1995) and Clement (1996), among others. `Care ethics raises caring, nurturing,
and the maintenance of interpersonal relationships to the status of foundational moral
importance' (Friedman, 1993: 147), such that gestures in this direction can now be found
in works otherwise devoted to impartiality (e.g., Barry, 1995: 246±55). In exploring the
question of how far we should care, I hope to show that an emphasis on feeling rather
than reason is a double-edged weapon, the wielding of which cuts into the foundations
of an ethics which prioritizes the practice of partiality, as well as undermining an
approach based exclusively on impartiality. While the deconstruction of dualisms is not
my primary purpose, what follows should at least raise questions concerning rigid
distinctions between reason and feeling, impartiality and partiality, universalism and
particularism, and especially justice and care.1 That space is deeply implicated in all this
is but one illustration of the interest currently being found at the interface of geography
and ethics or moral philosophy (Smith, 1997b), with a promise of enhanced understand-
ing of the spatial as well as the moral.
The question posed in the title is deliberately ambiguous. The issue of how far could be
read as to what extent in the sense of how much, as well as how far in geographical
space: the focus here is on the spatial, while recognizing that this may have a bearing on
the kind of care involved. The meaning of care could be that of caring for others as well
as caring about them: the focus here is on beneficence as doing good or showing active
kindness, rather than on benevolence as merely the desire to do good or charitable feeling
(following the distinction in the Concise Oxford Dictionary). Care is understood as
motivated by what Baier (1987: 43) describes as `a felt concern for the good of others and
for community with them', a warmer virtue than the cold calculations of justice, but
strong and principled enough to have practical and defensible consequences for people
in need. The collective `we' could refer to disadvantaged people, too preoccupied with
feeling the need for care, or with the difficulty of providing it, to think of much else: the
more familiar perspective of those of us in the advantaged parts of the world looking
outwards with the luxury of philosophical deliberation is the one adopted here. The
question is sometimes posed as that of responsibility to distant people or strangers
(e.g., Sterba, 1981; Corbridge, 1993).
Considering the spatial scope of beneficence involves more than the apparent
contradiction between the abstract universalist ideal of impartiality and the particularist
sentiment and practice of partiality. It also raises another distinction central to contemp-
orary debate in geography and philosophy: between human sameness and difference.
While partiality can involve people dear to us who are not necessarily near to us, and
while nearness is no guarantee of beneficence, the crucial issue raised by these two related
tensions is whether geographical proximity is a relevant difference with the moral force to
temper wider and perhaps universal humanitarian sentiments based on the recognition
that all persons are in some significant way the same or at least very similar. Or, to turn
the issue round, are universal similarities sufficient to transcend local particularities?
David M. Smith 17

Underlying the discussion is another common distinction, or dualism: between


universalism and relativism. `Morality is always contextual and historicized, even when
it claims to be universal', Tronto (1993: 62) asserts, pointing out that even such a
dedicated Kantian as Habermas (1990: 208) recognizes that moral universalism is `a
historical result'. Morality, as the ethics people actually discuss and practice, is also a
geographical result, in the sense that it arises in distinctive and changing geographical
circumstances. This refers not only to the particular local conditions in which moral
codes become an integral part of a people's culture or way of life but also to the spatial
relationships with other peoples which have a bearing on how they are understood,
represented and regarded as possible subjects of moral responsibility.
However, conceding the contextuality of moral thinking does not mean that all talk of
universals is ruled out. Human reason and experience may yet discover or create
something with claims to moral truth. Indeed, there are philosophers who insist that
such truth can already be found. This article works towards attempts to reconcile tension
between universalism and particularism (or parochialism) in the theory and practice of
care, suggesting that an ethic of care gains moral force to the extent that it is connected to
a theory of justice relating need for care to capacity to care. As a version of social justice
as equalization (elaborated in Smith, 1994), such a project has universal pretensions.

II Conventional partiality
The increasingly known and interdependent world, which today we take for granted, is
a very recent phenomenon in human history. To favour people in close proximity was an
understandable convention of the small-scale societies which prevailed, for the most
part, until the modern era. Attitudes to strangers protected local group security: prud-
ence born of experience tended to prevail over more altruistic sentiments. Those posing a
threat were repulsed. Care for outsiders was confined to codes of hospitality, which
could be quite specific as to the extent and duration of sustenance and shelter which
hosts were obliged to provide before the visitor had to explain or move on.
Social relations in small-scale societies were frequently of the kind now referred to as
communitarian. Personal identity reinforced an exclusive sense of a localized `we' rather
than an autonomous `I': `one of us' could be interpreted as `part of us'. To quote
MacIntyre (1981: 33±34):
In many pre-modern, traditional societies it is through his or her membership in a variety of social groups that the
individual identifies himself or herself and is identified by others. I am brother, cousin and grandson, member of
this household, that village, this tribe. These are not characteristics that belong to human beings accidentally, to be
stripped away in order to discover `the real me'. They are part of my substance, defining partially at least and
sometimes wholly my obligations and my duties. Individuals inherit a particular space within an interlocking set
of social relationships; lacking that space, they are nobody, or at best a stranger or an outcast.

Spatiality and place were strong, indeed essential, features of these relationships.
Lack of knowledge could justify the exclusion from ethical consideration of unknown
others, with whom geography denied the possibility of a relationship. For example,
O'Neill (1996: 105) explains the cases of the inhabitants of Anglo-Saxon England and
their T'ang Chinese contemporaries:
the two groups lived in unconnected worlds, ignorant of one another's very existence: their activities assumed no
connection to those in the other group, whom they accorded no ethical standing . . . Members of each group could
legitimately limit their ethical consideration to exclude their contemporaries of whom we now know, but who
lived beyond their horizons.
18 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

They also lived beyond possible inadvertent impact, in a world where trading relations
tended to be transparent and where environmental degradation was locally confined
rather than universalized as global warming and so on.
That the benefits of insider group membership could be carefully elaborated in terms
of citizenship rights was demonstrated in ancient Greece. Participation in the public
sphere, where reason was supposed to prevail over emotion, was denied to slaves and
women, the latter banished to the private sphere of home. Aristotle insisted that to try to
extend the bounds of familial love to everyone destroys family bonds themselves (Tronto,
1987: 659); in any case, the public sphere required more impersonal relations. There was
also a well defined status to which anyone from outside could be assigned; civilized
societies were characterized by how they treated strangers (MacIntyre, 1981: 124).
Nevertheless, Aristotle believed that, while Greeks should not enslave each other, it was
not morally reprehensible to enslave `barbarians' whose language and customs he did
not understand (Benhabib, 1992: 63). Some classical myths depicted the lands and seas
beyond the Mediterranean as inhabited by savages or monsters, constructions which
helped to legitimize the unsympathetic way distant peoples were dealt with. Similarly, in
ancient Egypt foreigners living away from the Nile were grouped with animals in some
literature. In Hebrew scripture: `You shall have but one law for the home-born and for
the outsider who lives among you' (Exodus 12: 49, quoted in Larue, 1991: 37), yet
distinctions were common.
Response to others involved emotion as well as custom and law. Ginzburg (1994: 108)
finds the following in Aristotle's Rhetoric: `the nearness of the terrible makes men pity.
Men also pity those who resemble them . . . for all such relations make a man more likely
to think that their misfortune may befall him as well . . . sufferings are pitiable when they
appear close at hand.' Extreme distance leads to indifference, while extreme closeness can
lead to pity, or to such other emotions as envy and destructive rivalry: part of the
everyday experience of face-to-face society. The role of the emotions in ancient times is
identified in what Solomon (1995: 256) describes as `justice personal, passionate and
situated', like retribution in Homer's epics. He also finds a personal virtue employing the
passions in Plato and Aristotle, exemplified in Republic where the debate between
Socrates and Polymarchus reveals judgements about justice to be essentially contextual,
depending on the situation and on relationships between the parties involved.
The situation, including the spatial relations involved, could generate something more
than a simple distinction between favoured insiders and outsiders treated differently.
The wider the known world became, with the approach of modernity, the more subtle
the spatial discrimination that might be involved. For example, there are suggestions of a
distance decay and gravity model in the work of the Scottish Enlightenment writer
Francis Hutcheson (quoted in Tronto, 1993: 41):
This universal Benevolence toward all Men, we may compare to that Principle of Gravitation, which perhaps extends
to all Bodys in the Universe; but, the Love of Benevolence, increases as the Distance is dimminish'd, and is strongest
when Bodys come to touch each other.
Bauman (1993: 166) makes a similar point, suggesting that `moral concern would reach
its highest intensity where knowledge of the other is at its richest and most intimate, and
that it would thin out as knowledge tapers off and intimacy is gradually transformed
into estrangement'. Becker (1992: 716) refers to a `radiating benevolence', in which self-
love is strongest, followed by love for family and friends, neighbours and so on, out to a
weak concern for the remotest imaginable person, and notes that Confucius was
associated with this view (see also Tuan, 1989: 44±45, 177±78).
David M. Smith 19

A major concern of Enlightenment thinking on morality was the supposed distinction


between reason and feeling (or natural passion) inherited from classical literature. The
former found its most influential expression in the abstract universalism of Immanuel
Kant, who wrote in The Doctrine of Virtue: `No moral principle is based . . . on any feeling
whatsoever . . . For feeling, no matter by what it is aroused, always belongs to the order
of nature' (quoted in Okin, 1989: 231). However, feelings still engaged some of those
dedicated to formalizing the subject of ethics. For example, David Hume, in his A Treatise
of Human Nature, makes the following observations on what is taken to be the
self-evident character of partiality with a spatial expression (quoted in Ginzburg, 1994:
116±17):
We find in common life that men are principally concern'd about those objects, which are not much remov'd
either in space or time, enjoying the present, and leaving what is afar off to the care of chance and fortune . . . The
breaking of a mirror gives us more concern when at home, than the burning of a house, when abroad, and some
hundred leagues distant.

Hume thought of justice as an artificial passion, required to complement the natural


passion of benevolence (Tronto, 1987: 659), thus anticipating the contemporary interest in
their combination or fusion (see part V).
The kind of people involved, as well as their location, could form the basis for
commonsense differentiation. As Henry Sidgwick explained in The Methods of Ethics
(quoted in Belsey, 1992: 38), reflecting gender exclusivity as well as the racism of the
times:
We should all agree that each of us is bound to show kindness to his parents and spouse and children, and to
other kinsmen in a less degree: and to those who have rendered services to him, and any others whom he may
have admitted to his intimacy and called friends: and to neighbours and to fellow countrymen more than others:
and perhaps we may say to those of our own race more than to black or yellow men, and generally to human
beings in proportion to their affinity to ourselves.

However, Sidgwick goes on to say: `those who are in distress or urgent need have a claim
on us for special kindness' (Belsey, 1992: 48, note 11).
As the known world continued to expand, one of the major challenges became how to
live with distant strangers some of whose moral claims could not be ignored. In the new
spatial order which had begun to emerge by the end of the eighteenth century, moral
theories that drew on the localized worlds which hitherto predominated were no longer
viable, leading to a requirement for alternatives capable of dealing with more distant
peoples (Tronto, 1993: 38±43). This was achieved by such triumphs of Enlightenment
reasoning as impartiality and universality. Benhabib (1992: 32) explains:
Universalizability enjoins us to reverse perspectives among members of a `moral community' and judge from the
point of view of the other(s). Such reversibility is essential to the ties of reciprocity that bind human communities
together. All human communities define some `significant others' in relation to whom reversibility and reciprocity
must be exercised ± be they members of my kin group, my tribe, my city-state, my nation, my co-religionists.
What distinguished `modern' from `premodern' ethical theories is the assumption of the former that the moral
community is coextensive with all beings capable of speech and action, and potentially with all of humanity.

But again, it was not simply a matter of physical distance to be overcome. Discourses of
racial superiority helped to legitimize the inferior treatment of others, who could be
dehumanized as clearly as the monsters of Greek myths. Sibley (1995: 49±50) points to
the expansion of European empires and the development of the capitalist world
economy requiring the fitting of dependent territories and peoples into the cosmic order
of the dominant powers: `Beyond the spatial limits of civilization, there were untamed
people and untamed nature to be incorporated . . . a spatial and cultural boundary was
20 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

drawn between civilization and various uncivilized, deviant ``others''.' At the extreme,
such peoples could be killed in large numbers for their land and other wealth, or hunted
for sport by alien beings temporarily deprived of access to foxes and pheasants.
Within the context of the emerging modern city, with its anomie enhanced by spatial
segmentation, the problem was one of relationships with different others living in close
proximity. The American city, with its patchwork of immigrant ghettos, became the
archetype of a new urban form. Familiar social space could stop at the neighbourhood's
boundary, on the other side of which was what might be perceived as the territory of the
alien, beyond familiar social norms. To Bauman (1993: 158), the internal organization of
the city was responsible for `isolating homely spots from the wilderness in between'. The
strange outsiders were now within, and it took the wider threat of an exploitive economy
to forge solidarity across ethnic divides.
If anything other than class consciousness, or the melting pot of cultural homogeniza-
tion, could solve modernity's problem of how to live with close as well as distant
strangers, it was the impersonal rules of pecuniary transactions which came to dominate
social relations hitherto conducted largely on the basis of reciprocity and trust among
people familiar with one another. Part of the price was the dehumanization of important
realms of social interaction, along with the commodification of labour as an inanimate
factor of production subject to the impartial evaluation of Adam Smith's `hidden hand'
of market forces.
While the philosopher's solution ± universalism expressed in the Enlightenment ideal
of impartiality ± may have worked at a theoretical level, premodern conventions of
partiality continued to prevail in many contexts. As O'Neill (1996: 11, note 1) explains:
`The fact that many universalists have in practice narrowed the scope of their principles
to exclude certain others ± barbarians, women, slaves, the heathen, foreigners ± shows
that the principles by which they actually lived have far-less-than cosmopolitan scope.'
The Enlightenment discourse of impartial reason, along with such other innovations as
(spatially restricted) rights of citizenship, served to mask the reality of continuing spatial
discrimination in the exercise of beneficence, along with some far from benevolent
practices (with extensive spatial scope) associated with colonialism and imperialism as
well as with capitalism.

III Extending the scope of care

Historical evidence and everyday experience suggest that favouring our nearest and
dearest is a natural human sentiment, for which there are good reasons in a prudential as
well as moral sense. Horrified reactions to such deviations as child abuse, granny
bashing or `beggar my neighbour' underline the expectation that familial and com-
munity bonds will ensure beneficence. This raises the question of how far humankind is
capable of extending these relations of care to `outsiders'. Lest this problem be thought of
as specific to modernity, reference can be made to philosophical conflict in ancient China,
where Confucius believed that love begins within the family and from there irradiates the
rest of the world, while followers of Mo-tzu believed in universal love and saw narrow
loyalties as degenerate (Tuan, 1989: 177±78). It has been customary in western moral
thought, particularly since Kant, to see a rupture between the public virtue of justice and
the private virtue of goodness, but to argue that this can be mediated by extending the
sympathy we naturally feel towards those closest to us on to larger human groups
David M. Smith 21

(Benhabib, 1992: 140). The problem is that of translating this ideal into practice, in a
world in which local relationships remain strong binding forces in human identity and
solidarity.
Tronto (1987: 660±61) recognizes that an ethic of care could become a defence of caring
for one's family, friends, group or nation, and indeed of any set of conventional
relationships. Advocates of an ethic of care therefore need to consider the appropriate
boundaries of caring, how far they should be expanded, and how to ensure that the web
of relationships is spun widely enough that some people are not beyond its reach. Hence
(1987, 660±61): `Whatever the weakness of Kantian universalism, its premise of equal
moral worth and dignity of all humans is attractive because it avoids this problem.' She
claims that the central questions of current moral theory are about `how to treat morally
distant others who we think are similar to ourselves' (Tronto, 1993: 13). Further:
`Whether we can conceive of a way to think of morality that extends some form of
sympathy further than our own group remains perhaps the fundamental moral question
for contemporary life', so `only when we expand our moral boundaries to include a
concept of care' will we be able to deal with the implications of tribalism and racism
which undermine common responsibility (Tronto, 1993: 59).
Three distinct but related themes may be excavated from Tronto's not entirely
transparent spatial imagery, which are crucial to the question of extending the scope of
care as beneficence, or active responsibility for others. These are the spatial relationships
within which people live, the grounds for recognition of human similarity, and the
importance of prioritizing care as a moral value. Each of these will be examined briefly.

1 Spatial relationships
It is a common observation that various processes subsumed under the concept of
globalization have greatly changed the spatial organization of human life in recent
decades, and with it the ways in which people in different parts of the world have come
to interact with one another. Knowledge of the operation of these processes, of how `we'
in the affluent parts of the world impact on the lives and environments of distant others,
can lead to an extension of a sense of responsibility. Boycotting certain goods, as an
expression of opposition to apartheid in South Africa or to child labour in Indian carpet
factories, are obvious cases of `ethical consumption'. Corbridge (1993: 463) generalizes as
follows:
To the extent that we can show that our lives are radically entwined with the lives of different strangers ± through
studies of colonialism, of flows of capital and commodities, of modern telecommunications and so on ± we can
argue more powerfully for change within the global system . . . there is no logical reason to suppose that moral
boundaries should coincide with the boundaries of our everyday community: not least because these latter
boundaries are themselves not closed, but rather are defined in part by an increasing set of exchanges with distant
strangers.

Current preoccupations with porous places, hybrid identities, and dissolving the distinc-
tion between global and local underline growing recognition of a world of changing
experience of people in space.
Telecommunication provides an illustration. Modern media can create a sense of
involvement in distant lives, by means of visual recognition as opposed to written
language: `recognition is . . . the basis of moral inclusion and intellectual engagement'
(Adams, 1996: 424). This is revealed in the occupation of Tiananmen Square in 1989,
which involved the use of this symbolic monumental space to draw wider attention to
22 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

political dissent: `occupation of the Square was a deliberate attempt to transcend the
Square, to use this place to open China up to the gaze of distant bystanders' (Adams,
1996: 425). Empathizing with peoples whose suffering is viewed on TV can motivate
practical if transient care, as in such extravaganzas as Live-aid and Children in Need. But
it might also induce numbness, indifference or worse: Martin (1996: 588±89) refers to the
`trap' of aerial distance, enabling horrors even to be made picturesque.
Another case is the creation of `virtual communities' in `cyberspace', where a wide
range of social intercourse is possible. For example (Rheingold, 1993: 3):
People in virtual communities use words on screen to exchange pleasantries and argue, engage in intellectual
discourse, conduct commerce, exchange knowledge, share emotional support, make plans, brainstorm, gossip,
feud, fall in love, find friends and lose them, play games, flirt, create a little high art and a lot of idle talk.

In short, people engage possibly far distant others in ways usually associated with close
proximity, but without face-to-face interaction or bodily contact. Such networks are
capable of developing their own moral codes based on reciprocity, as mutually
understood or even formalized social contracts: `a kind of gift economy in which people
do things for one another out of a spirit of building something between them, rather than
a spreadsheet-calculated quid pro quo' (Rheingold, 1993: 59). However, these virtual
communities are a luxury of well-to-do members of affluent societies, whose scope for
caring relationships via the Internet is confined to others with similar resources. They
may therefore do nothing more than reinforce relative privilege. Furthermore, there are
some relationships of mutuality and care which actually require knowledge of the other
as physically embodied, capable of touch, which cannot be regulated by the choice to
switch on the computer. Remote communication may also promote evil, such as sexual
exploitation and violence, by facilitating interaction among people who enjoy such
things, and even encouraging acts which face-to-face relations might constrain.
The importance of knowing the other with the intimacy of face-to-face contact is by no
means uncontroversial. Work on the holocaust has revealed differences over the effect of
physical (and psychological) distance between an act and its consequences, in suspend-
ing moral inhibition (Smith, 1997a: 25). Bauman (1989: 155, 192) points to an inverse ratio
of readiness to cruelty and proximity to its victim, suggesting that `morality . . . looms
large and thick close to the eye'. It may be easier to kill at a distance than face to face,
facilitated by modern methods of warfare which reduce the annihilation of people to a
technical exercise, like the bureaucratic routine of mass murder in Nazi concentration
camps and the clinical bombing of Iraq in the Gulf war. Bauman (1989: 151±68) and
others cite the experiment of Milgram (1974), who observed that the proportion of
subjects in experiments who would inflict pain on another increased from when it
required physical contact to when it involved manipulating an instrument, and to when
victims were hidden from view.
Vetlesen (1993: 382±83) has challenged Bauman's interpretation, arguing that moral
capacity arises in small-scale interaction and that it was the removal of Jews from such
settings, as well as from the sight of others (e.g., in ghettos), which enabled them to be
mistreated. Rorty (1989) suggests that the extent to which Jews were protected by
gentiles differed in Denmark and Italy from Belgium because in the former Jews were
recognized as fellow members of some group, like Milanese, Jutlanders, union members
or professionals: `our sense of solidarity is strongest when those with whom solidarity is
expressed are thought of as ``one of us'', where the ``us'' means something smaller and
more local than the human race' (Rorty, 1989: 191). However, Geras (1995) has shown
David M. Smith 23

that people responsible for rescuing Jews were motivated by universalist sentiments,
as well as by familiarity with specific Jews. Referring to one set of findings (Geras,
1995: 22):
a large majority of rescuers emphasized the ethical meaning for them of the help they gave: some of these in terms
of the value of equity or fairness; more of them in terms of the value of care; but in any case with a sense of
responsibility common amongst them that was `broadly inclusive in character, extending to all human beings'.

Thus, however much physical proximity may help to induce sympathy and beneficence,
some people are able to transcend this kind of particularism, and to find moral value in
so doing.

2 Human similarity
All this raises the second issue introduced above: the basis on which people might
recognize sameness, or close similarity, as significant aspects of how they should treat
others. How do people develop a capacity to transcend conventional identification with
local and particular others, to extend their scope for care? And, do spatial relationships
matter in this process?
Rorty (1989: 192) comments as follows, in his account of human solidarity as created
and contingent rather than based on recognition of common humanity:
feelings of solidarity are necessarily a matter of which similarities and dissimilarities strike us as salient . . . there is
such a thing as moral progress [which is] in the direction of greater human solidarity. But that solidarity is not
thought of as recognition of a core self, the human essence, in all human beings. Rather, it is thought of as the
ability to see more and more traditional differences (of tribe, religion, race, customs, and the like) as unimportant
when compared with similarities with respect to pain and humiliation ± the ability to think of people wildly
different from ourselves as included in the range of `us'.

He exhorts us to expand our sense of `us' as far as we can, including ever more distant
and different others, looking for marginalized people and trying to notice our similarities
with them (Rorty, 1989: 196).
However, Rorty's minimal recognition of common human susceptibility to that special
sort of pain associated with humiliation is a very narrow notion of similarity. Eagleton
(1996: 14) argues for a naturalism and essentialism critical of the reductionism (or
`culturalism') which, he claims, `drastically under-values what men and women have in
common as natural, material creatures, foolishly suspects all talk of nature as insidiously
mystifying, and overestimates the significance of cultural difference'. He elaborates
(Eagleton, 1996: 47):
If another creature is able in principle to speak to us, engage in material labour alongside us, sexually interact with
us, produce something which looks vaguely like art in the sense that it appears fairly pointless, suffer, joke and
die, then we can deduce from these biological facts a huge number of moral and even political consequences . . .
Because of the form of their bodies, we would know more or less what attitudes to these animals it was
appropriate to take up, such as respect, compassion, not cutting off their feet for the fun of it and the like.

This kind of recognition of sameness in the other features quite prominently in con-
temporary development studies and related philosophical writings, in which a form of
essentialism implicit in the identification of common (perhaps `basic') human needs is
espoused and defended (e.g., Nussbaum, 1992). It is also central to the theory of human
need set out by Doyal and Gough (1991), which challenges cultural relativism. Corbridge
(1993: 464) also reflects these views, suggesting that the strategy (after Rawls, 1971) of
putting ourselves in the position of those who, for no good reason, are worse off than we
24 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

are assists recognition that the needs of such strangers could, but for the accident of birth,
be ours. Thus (Corbridge, 1993: 466, 469):
I am not willing to deconstruct further certain minimally universalist claims, of the type that involuntary death
from hunger, or involuntary malnutrition, or involuntary homelessness, or slavery, or torture are bad things
which must be struggled against . . . The postmodern dilemma is avoided as and when we accept that certain
human needs and rights, at least, can be taken to be `universal', and when we learn that in attending to these
needs and rights we are not so much dictating to others as dictating to ourselves.

Of course, much depends on the nature of these selves. Feminist writings on the ethic of
care stress a relational rather than autonomous conception of the self, formed locally in
relationship with close others. Yet this experience can itself lead to the spatial extension
of concern, as Clement (1996: 85) explains, `we learn to care for distant others by first
developing close relationships to nearby others, and then recognizing the similarities
between close and distant others'. We learn what it is like for children close to home to
starve, and then recognize that distant children are like those close to home. An obvious
limitation of this argument is that some people in some places are protected from the
direct experience of children starving, and from other misfortunes from which poor
people elsewhere suffer. Clement (1996: 73), following Goodin (1985), invokes another
aspect of the recognition of similarity as follows:
our obligations to care for family and friends are based on the fact that our family and friends are particularly
vulnerable to our actions and choices . . . But many people beyond our family and friends are also vulnerable to our
actions and choices, and thus the ethic of care has implications beyond our sphere of personal relationships. Those
closer to us will tend to be more vulnerable to our actions and choices than those distant from us, and thus we are
not obliged to weigh everyone's interests exactly equally. Yet insofar as those distant from us are particularly
vulnerable to our actions and choices, we have special obligations to care for them. And to that extent, the
conventional boundaries of the ethic of care break down.

Against the `nonfeminist partialists' who actually oppose the notion of global moral
concern, and those feminists for whom care is necessarily local, she argues that feminist
partiality actually implies global moral concern. She finds Friedman (1993: 86-87) in
support:
Feminist partialists . . . devote much more theoretical attention to developing concern for those who are not `one's
own'. This is the significance of all the work that feminists put into theorizing `difference' and into trying to
incorporate a diversity of racial and class consciousness into feminist theory. Cross-cultural connections,
theoretical and practical, are highly revered feminist achievements. Thus, for feminists, `global moral concern'
does not call for exactly equal consideration of the interests of all persons, but it does call for substantially more
concern for distant or different people than is recommended by nonfeminist partialists.

This concern arises not only from experience mediated by social and spatial relationships
but also from the extent to which feminism esteems caring in itself.

3 Care as a moral value


This leads to the third issue raised above: the importance of prioritizing care as a moral
value. If human needs entail rights (itself a contentious issue), then meeting such needs
in the form of the provision of care is the consequent duty, irrespective of any particular
sentiments which may motivate unconditional care for special others. Care might be
regarded as the most general, and universal, need ± from cradle to grave: `humans are
not fully autonomous, but must always be understood in a condition of interdependence
. . . all humans need care' (Tronto, 1993: 162). There may be specific forms of human
relationships and societies effective in the experience of care; thus, `some of the basic
needs of each individual are to belong to a community, to be recognized, to share, to
David M. Smith 25

care, and to be cared for' (Markovic, 1990: 132). However, to provide or receive effective
care can seldom be entirely an individual, family or local responsibility, as the means
may not coincide with the needs: a crucial point to which we return in the next section.
Tronto (1993: 126) summarizes her case for the prioritization of care as follows,
stressing both personal and societal responsibility:
To be a morally good person requires, among other things, that a person strives to meet the demands of caring
that present themselves in his or her life. For a society to be judged as a morally admirable society, it must, among
other things, adequately provide for care of its members and its territory.

The reference here to territory provides a reminder of the ecological dimension, usually
overlooked in elaborations of an ethic of care, but emphasized in contemporary
environmental ethics and ecofeminism (a link not pursued by Tronto, or in this article,
but worth more attention). The societal and personal mesh with the universal and
particular (Tronto, 1993: 137):
To meet one's caring responsibilities has both universal and particular components. On the one hand, it requires a
determination of what caring responsibilities are, in general. On the other hand, it requires a focus upon the
particular kinds of responsibilities and burdens that we might assume because of who, and where, we are
situated.

Attention to `the particular location in which people find themselves in various processes
of care' further underlines Tronto's sensitivity to the context, to the geographical
situation.
Against the evidence of parochialism in the actual practice of care is a faith in the
possibility of its more extensive expression in the form of the feminist partiality referred
to above. For example: `Human beings can and do care ± and are capable of caring far
more than most do at present ± about the suffering of children quite distant from them,
about the prospects for future generations, and about the well-being of the globe'
(Held, 1993: 53). The challenge, elaborated by Tronto (1993), is to give substance to such
faith, in the form of feasible political practice. The provision of care has to be institu-
tionalized, not only for effectiveness but also because a right to care, as with positive
welfare rights in general, cannot convincingly be linked to individual duty (unlike
negative liberty rights which entail individual duties of noninterference). The pre-
disposition towards care as merely felt concern is not enough.

4 Some mainstream perspectives


It remains in this section to take brief note of some arguments for universal beneficence
emanating from what might be regarded as mainstream moral philosophy, rather than
from the feminist reaction exemplified by inheritors of Gilligan's ethic of care. In an early
article calling for an alteration in the way people in affluent countries react to such
situations as famine in poorer parts of the world, Singer (1972: 23) elaborated the
following principle: `if it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening,
without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought,
morally, to do it'. This principle takes no account of proximity or distance (Singer,
1972: 24):
The fact that a person is physically near to us, so that we have personal contact with him, may make it more likely
that we shall assist him, but this does not show that we ought to help him rather than another who happens to be
further away. If we accept any principle of impartiality, universalizability, equality, or whatever, we cannot
discriminate against someone merely because he is far away from us.
26 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

Singer concludes that we ought to give as much as possible to famine relief and so on,
perhaps to the point of marginal utility at which by giving more we would cause
ourselves more suffering than we would prevent. The underlying argument is similar to
the one sometimes deployed to justify redistribution of income from rich to poor people
to the point of equality, in a utilitarian calculus assuming decreasing marginal utility of
money with increasing affluence (see Smith, 1994: 62±64). While this is an extreme
position, Singer (1995: 222) still argues along these lines, proposing that to live ethically
is to act on the conclusions of reflection, which if done properly will lead to the point of
view of the universe rather than sectional interests: `From this perspective, we can see
that our own sufferings and pleasures are very like the sufferings and pleasures of others,
and that there is no reason to give less consideration to the sufferings of others, just
because they are ``others''.' However, the perspective appears to have shifted from
utilitarianism to the sort of mutual recognition of similarity which grounds some other
contemporary universalist accounts.
Another influential contribution is that of Sterba (1981). He claims that, of the various
moral grounds justifying the welfare rights of distant peoples, possibly the most evident
are those which appeal to either a right to life or a right to fair treatment. A right to life is
defined both as a positive right to the satisfaction of a person's basic needs, and as a
negative right requiring that everyone in a position to do so not interfere with a person's
attempts to meet their basic needs. This is an inversion of the conventional conception of
welfare rights as positive, which shifts the consequent duty from (societal) provision to
(individual) noninterference, raising the question of whether persons with goods and
resources surplus to their basic needs are justified in prohibiting others from satisfying
their basic needs so that the former can favour their own nonbasic needs. Sterba (1981:
102) concludes:
For most people their right to acquire the goods and resources necessary to satisfy their basic needs would have
priority over any other person's property rights to surplus possessions, or alternatively, they would conceive of
property rights such that no one could have property rights to any surplus possessions which were required to
satisfy their own basic needs.

This echoes a point made by Singer (1972: 29): `From the moral point of view, the
prevention of the starvation of millions of people outside our society must be considered
at least as pressing as the upholding of property norms within our society.'
Sterba's right to fairness involves the proposition that, from a position of disinterest,
people would endorse limitations to a right to accumulate goods and resources, so as to
guarantee `a minimum sufficient to provide each person with the goods and resources
necessary to satisfy his or her basic needs' (Sterba, 1981: 104). Basic needs are defined in
much the same way as in development literature (see also Doyal and Gough, 1991): those
which must be satisfied in order not to endanger seriously health and sanity, preserving
life in the fullest sense, including food, shelter, medical care, protection, companionship
and self-development.
Sterba (1981) offers a parallel argument with respect to future generations, concluding
that their welfare rights, understood as the right to receive or acquire the goods and
resources necessary to satisfy their basic needs, can be justified by the rights to life and to
fair treatment. This, like Tronto's reference to care for territory, links into contemporary
environmental ethics, raising the question of how far into the future moral responsibility
should be extended. Here at least, there are limits to universalism.
One of the strengths of Sterba's approach is its recognition of deep structural
impediments to meeting the needs of the poor, in the form of the property rights which
David M. Smith 27

under capitalism protect the accumulated wealth of others. By comparison, the literature
on an ethic of care has little to say on such matters, beyond bemoaning the marginaliza-
tion of the values and practices of caring, nurturance, compassion and so on in a
masculinist world. However, Tronto (1993: 175) goes so far as to say that an emphasis on
care `is probably ultimately anti-capitalistic because it posits meeting needs for care,
rather than the pursuit of profit, as the highest social goal'. The political economy of a
caring society requires much more attention, but is beyond the scope of this article.

IV Resurgent partiality
The previous section reviewed some arguments from the ethic of care and from
mainstream moral philosophy for the spatial extension of care very widely and possibly
universally. The mainstream reflects the customary Enlightenment position of impart-
iality grounded in utilitarianism or rights, while the alternative ethics respects partiality
but recognizes a case for its broader reach. Both positions encounter not only residual
partialist sentiments from premodern conventions but also what might be described
(somewhat provocatively) as a contemporary resurgence of partiality found in some
strands of communitarianism and feminism, and in other intellectual currents of late
(or post-) modernity.
The abiding strength of some premodern concepts of morality as essentially con-
textual, historically and geographically, encourages (indeed requires) a restricted spatial
scope of concern for others. To MacIntyre (1981: 126-27), `all morality is always to some
degree tied to the socially local and particular . . . the aspirations of the morality of
modernity to a universality freed from all particularity is an illusion'. While a number of
moral philosophers have found ways of preserving something of the Enlightenment
vision of universality and impartiality in the face of a strong critique from historicism,
the stance exemplified by MacIntyre's focus on the virtues of premodern society rests
comfortably with other forms of resurgent partiality.

1 Communitarianism2
Communitarianism is experiencing a revival, in the hands of politicians on both sides of
the Atlantic as well as in moral and political philosophy. Much of the philosophical
discussion concerns the ongoing debate with liberalism (e.g., Mulhall and Swift, 1996).
Communitarians find the good of mutuality in groups of people living together with a
shared value system, usually in close proximity, and involving an identity in which
people realize themselves through relations with others. Such a stance almost inevitably
invites parochialism, favouring members of the community (however defined) over
outsiders, and protecting borders to preserve group integrity and exclude different
others (e.g., Walzer, 1983: Chap. 2).
The recent assertion of the `spirit of community' by Etzioni (1995) provides a revealing
text. A hierarchy of moral responsibility with an implicit spatial dimension is suggested.
First, people should help themselves as best they can; the second line of responsibility
lies with those closest, `including kin, friends, neighbors, and other community
members' (Etzioni, 1995: 144). However, there is also recognition that `one of the gravest
dangers in rebuilding communities is that they will tend to become insular and
indifferent to the fate of outsiders', so, last but not least, societies (as `communities of
communities') must help those communities whose ability to help their members is
28 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

severely limited: `We start with our responsibility to ourselves and to members of our
community; we expand the reach of our moral claims and duties from there' (Etzioni,
1995: 146±47).
Widening the reach of community in this way is described by Etzioni (1995: 155) as
`pluralism-within-unity'. The existence, values and needs of diverse groups are
acknowledged, along with some scope to critique the prevailing way of life. However,
the plurality of conceptions of the good characteristic of liberalism is clearly rejected, for
the communitarianism envisaged seeks unity from the perspective of one dominant
value system: that of `American society'. Without a sense of this one supracommunity,
there is a danger that the constituent communities will turn on one another. Certain core
values must therefore be recognized: `democracy, individual rights, and mutual respect',
which are claimed to be western: those committed to them `will find little comfort in
other major cultural traditions' (Etzioni, 1995: 159). His attitude to fundamentalist
Islamic countries suggests that they may be beyond the community of communities, and
of the reach of care if not of concern.
More sensitivity to difference is to be found in Selznick (1992), who argues that a
proper sociological understanding of community presumes diversity and pluralism as
well as social integration. As to the (spatial) extension of community, Selznick (1992: 194,
201, note 33) defines particularism as bounded altruism and universalism as inclusive
altruism, claiming that the ethos of universalism `pushes outwards the bounds of
community, expands obligation, and celebrates the impersonal standpoint'. However,
particularism is the more secure, universalism the more precarious. Recognizing a quest
for community that looks outward rather than inward, `A crucial step is the embrace of
strangers. When strangers are treated with the respect due to members of an enlarged
community, a moral watershed is reached' (Selznick, 1992: 196).
However, even within this evolving strand of `liberal democratic' communitarianism,
little attention is given to external relations among communities (Bader, 1995: 222). These
involve parochial closure, and such power asymmetries as domination, oppression and
exclusion. Closure can constrain outward orientation as well as inward population
movement, while differential imbalances of political and economic power can help to
perpetuate those material inequalities which generate disparities in need for care, and in
capacity to provide it: the central problem of justice in care towards which this discussion
is moving. Etzioni (1995: 146) recognizes that social justice has an intercommunity
dimension, but neither he nor other contemporary communitarians show much interest
in inequality (with the notable exception of Walzer, 1983).
If we take the contextuality of moral thinking seriously, we might well ask why
communitarianism elicits such a positive response these days (apart from its attraction to
politicians seeking something between the excesses of liberal individualism and socialist
collectivism). There is more to this than mourning the loss of Gemeinschaft, of the
traditional (premodern) community, the idealization of which obscures its social
hierarchy, patriarchy and intolerance of dissent. O'Neill (1996: 28±29) explains how, in
early modern and subsequent times, a form of universalism was required in a world
where local communities were being incorporated into modern states, and Europeans
were colonizing the lands of others. Recognizing the upsurge of communitarian thinking
in the 1980s, against the reality of economic and political structures becoming more
cosmopolitan, she asks (1996: 28±29):
Might it reflect the fact that cosmopolitan claims are no longer advantageous to elites, as they perhaps were or
were thought to be in the recent past of imperialism? In a post-imperial world, cosmopolitan arrangements
David M. Smith 29

threaten rich states with uncontrolled economic forces and immigration and demands that human rights be
guaranteed across boundaries.

Immigration controls and a miserly response to the needs of poor countries for develop-
ment aid, debt relief and so on are too familiar to require elaboration. And it is not just a
case of some `fortress Europe' defending its privileged way of life against third-world
peoples, after the fashion of walled suburbs protecting the urban rich from the poor.
Eastern Europe is now involved, and most of this new impoverished world seems
beyond the scope of anything other than American and western European self-interest.
O'Neill (1996: 114±15) puts it brutally: `a background assumption of most affluent lives is
that state power will effectively keep most distant strangers more or less in their place
and in their poverty.' Corbridge (1993: 462) suggest that `New Right' authors tend to
internalize in their work a `distance-decay model of morality (charity begins at home if it
has to begin anywhere)'. The danger is that such a resurgent parochialism in the more
respectable guise of communitarianism could become universalized.

2 Feminism
Feminism, in various guises, has emerged as a major challenge to deep-seated modes of
thought and practice, not only to masculinism and male domination but also to such
established Enlightenment conceptions as impartiality and the priority of reason over
feeling in morality and social justice. But feminism has its internal tensions and
contradictions, reflecting a diversity of views hinted at earlier in this article. There is a
risks of overprioritizing the mutuality of face-to-face relationships, which is also found in
communitarianism. Clement (1996: 16±17) notes the emphasis in some feminist writing
on the importance of knowing the concrete other for whom we care, in the active sense of
for rather than about, exemplified by the fact that to Noddings (1984) caring for distant
peoples is care in name only: we cannot care for people we do not know.
There is an important practical point to be recognized here: that some people may be
better placed than others (literally, in a geographical sense) to care for those in need.
Friedman (1991: 822) articulates what might appear to be the commonsense assertion
that `being uniquely situated to answer to someone's needs derives from an ongoing
relationship . . . I am in frequent proximity of her, and I know her needs and desires
better than you do'. Jagger (1995: 132) refers to `a kind of caring that requires knowing
people in their concrete particularity rather than as representatives of certain dis-
advantaged groups', a crucial aspect of which is a focus on particular individuals rather
than the abstractions of masculine thought like equality and reciprocity. Jagger (1995:
142) goes on: `feminist caring is not impersonal but instead requires knowing the
specific situation of the putative recipients of care, especially whether they need or
want the type of care envisioned.' Even Tronto (1993: 178) is not immune to paroch-
ialism; she advocates `a universalist moral principle, such as: one should care for those
around one or in one's society'. However, critics of the more parochial readings of an
ethic of care have provoked the reaction that we might construct ever-widening circles
of care, and press those nearby the distant needy to care for them (Clement, 1996: 17;
see also Friedman, 1993: Chap. 3, for more on the partiality debate within feminist
ethics).
Returning to the practical issue, it is debatable to what extent close familiarity with
the needs of others is actually required for care, whether to recognize the specific needs
30 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

or to meet then most effectively. Singer (1972: 26) concedes that we may be in a better
position to judge what needs to be done to help a near person than one far away, and
perhaps also to provide the assistance necessary: `If this were the case, it would be a
reason for helping those near to us first.' But he goes on to say that, while once this
may have been so, instant communication and swift transport enable aid to be
disseminated, with the assistance of expert observers and supervisors (1972: 26): `There
would seem, therefore, to be no possible justification for discriminating on geographical
grounds.' While everyday experience confirms that the needs of family members, for
example, may be first identified within the family, and that some kinds of care may be
possible only within the family, the diagnosis of need and the provision of effective
care can seldom be so confined. However, the danger of outsiders, whether aid
agencies or professional workers, imposing inappropriate remedies suggests that some
insider knowledge of the situation is helpful. This leads to broader issues concerning
the distribution and institutionalization of the means of caring, to which we turn in the
next section.

3 Some other perspectives


Another aspect of resurgent partiality is associated with what is known as the new
evolutionary ethics, which claims that there is some uniformity of moral beliefs beneath
cultural variations and that these are innate rather than learnt. Altruism is interpreted in
the context of human adaptation and co-operation, serving the biological end of
successful reproduction. Ruse (1991: 505) explains the implications as follows:
not all social interactions are going to have the same pay-off. All other things being equal, your best reproductive
investments are going to be in helping close kin. Then, probably, more distant kin and those non-relatives who
offer most likelihood of reciprocation . . . Finally, one reaches the outer limit, where one is dealing with strangers
and, indeed, where the possibility of danger from the unknown may well exceed any virtues of possible
reciprocation . . . not only will one's feelings of affection fall away as one moves beyond one's immediate family
but so also will one's sense of moral obligation . . . Even with non-relatives there will be a moral differential, with a
stronger sense of obligation within one's own society than towards those without.

It is therefore foolish to pretend that we have an equal obligation. This perspective


naturalizes a form of parochial partiality based on self-interest, which sits easily with
some contemporary attitudes in which altruism forms part of a cold, perhaps pecuniary,
calculation of costs and benefits in the face of which the very meaning of care becomes
debased.
In so far as postmodern thinking, with its disdain for meta-theory and universals, is
relevant to such a grand question as how far we should care, it is likely to encourage
parochialism. The stress on difference and particularity, while drawing attention to the
specific needs of various groups of hitherto marginalized `others', dilutes the force of an
argument from human sameness or similarity supporting spatially extensive responsi-
bility for people who are recognizably like ourselves in morally significant respects in
spite of some differences. Postmodernism shares with communitarianism the con-
servative risk of undermining grounds for critique of parochial selfishness, playing into
the hands of those who seek not so much to defend group or local privilege as to avoid
having to defend it. Thus, the moral relativism (or nihilism) encouraged in some
postmodern thinking is far from politically benign; instead of being merely an
intellectual indulgence of the well-to-do, this perspective helps to entrench their
privilege.3
David M. Smith 31

V Possible reconciliations

The final section of this article reviews some attempts at reconciliation of tension between
the conflicting claims of impartiality in the sense of universalizing some conception of
beneficence, and partiality as caring confined to particular (nearest and dearest) people.
Baier (1987) refers to `harmonization', in relation to the alternatives of justice and care
which is another way in which the conflict could be expressed (following Gilligan, 1982).
In the conventional account, justice refers to the supposedly masculine practice of
approaching moral issues equipped with general principles rather than attention to
contextual detail, compared with the supposedly feminist perspective based on con-
textual decision-making and the priority of maintaining relationships. The spatial
convention is that justice is for the public realm, care for the private.
The stark distinctions implied here have already been substantially eroded in debates
following the introduction of the ethic of care. Gilligan (1987: 20) herself remarks:
Since everyone is vulnerable both to oppression and to abandonment, two moral visions ± one of justice and one
of care ± recur in human experience. The moral injunctions, not to act unfairly toward others, and not to turn
away from someone in need, capture these different concerns.
What is at issue is to collapse a false dualism, which might otherwise force an unneces-
sary choice between a conservative parochialism and a universalism tainted by
Enlightenment error. A warning at the outset: the works reviewed here have their own
distinct philosophical agendas beyond the concerns of this article, and by no means
exhaust what the contemporary literature has to say which is relevant to the issue under
discussion. Quotations enable the texts to speak largely for themselves.
First to the insight provided by Friedman (1991: see also 1993), in an article which
begins with the recognition of the moral strength of partiality: `intimacy and close
relationships require partiality [which] seems instrumentally essential to integrity and
the good life. There seems, in addition, to be sheer intrinsic value in the very benefiting
of friends and loved ones' (Friedman, 1991: 818). However, she has serious reservations.
The first concerns the actual context; she argues that the moral value of partiality
depends on the actual relationships it helps to sustain, which can be supportive but
which could be abusive or oppressive ± as in the case of a paedophile ring or the Ku-
Klux-Klan, for example. Hence, partiality is morally required in a relationship to the
extent that it contributes to protection of the vulnerable.
Her second, more weighty reservation refers to the unequal distribution of means of
favouring loved ones. Taking Luke's exhortation to `love thy neighbor as thyself' to refer
to anyone in need, she states (Friedman, 1991: 828):
It is not really the `neighbor' as such who needs the moral attention of others. The one who really needs general
moral attention is the person who lacks resources and who would not be adequately cared for even if all her
friends and family were as partial to her as they could be because they, too, lack resources. There are systematic
social inequalities among different `neighborhoods' in the distribution of the resources for loving and caring.
This must matter to the partialist stance. She goes on (Friedman, 1991: 829):
whether or not, and to what extent, someone benefits from certain partialist relationship conventions has a lot to
do with her `social location', the sort of luck she had in being born to, adopted by, or linked by marriage to,
relations with adequate resources for caretaking, nurturing, and protecting.
And from the perspective of the giver, she points out that partiality untempered by any
redistribution of wealth or resources promotes the integrity and fulfilment of only those
people who are able to care. Thus (Friedman, 1991: 830±31):
If partiality is everyone's moral prerogative and, more so, if it is everyone's responsibility, then, on certain
partialist grounds alone, there ought to be a distribution of the resources for caring, nurturing, and otherwise
32 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

favoring loved ones which permits as many of us as possible to do so in a fulfilling and integrity-conferring
manner . . . by viewing partiality as morally valuable because of what it ultimately contributes to integrity and
human fulfilment, and by considering the reality of unequally distributed resources, we are led to a notion that
sounds suspiciously like the requirement of moral impartiality.

She concludes that partialists might differ from impartialists in placing less, perhaps too
little, emphasis on global moral concerns.
The crucial geographical point in all this is that a person's spatial location is very likely
to reflect good or bad fortune similar to the accident of birth. Spatial inequalities in
capacity to care (or disparities between capacity and need) will thus tend to perpetuate
patterns of uneven development which are morally indefensible unless people deserve
the luck of being in a particular place with particular resources, and in a particular
network of (more or less) caring relationships.
An attempt at reconciliation from the perspective of impartiality is provided by Barry
(1995), who seeks universal principles of justice. His central proposition is that justice as
impartiality turns on a specific criterion of acceptability: `it would widely be acknowl-
edged as a sign of an unjust arrangement that those who do badly under it could
reasonably reject it' (Barry, 1995: 7). He considers that the `battle' between impartialists
and nonimpartialists is bogus, because they are talking about different things (Barry,
1995: 194):
What the supporters of impartiality are defending is second-order impartiality. Impartiality is here seen as a test
to be applied to the moral and legal rules of a society: one which asks about their acceptability among free and
equal people. The critics are talking about first-order impartiality ± impartiality as a maxim of behaviour in
everyday life.

He claims that universal first-order impartiality is rarely advocated; as Friedman (1991:


818) points out, few moral philosophers these days would oppose partiality in everyday
life. Barry (1995: 201) goes on:
All of us have only a finite amount of time, attention, care, and affection to devote to other people (or to ourselves
for that matter), and life would scarcely be worthy living if we could not decide for ourselves ± once we had met
our general social obligations ± on whom these should be bestowed.

The caveat is vital: general social obligations come first, within a set of institutions
consistent with second-order impartiality based on the principle of reasonable rejection.
Thus (Barry, 1995: 206 ± 207):
What is required is a set of rules of justice. . . that provide everybody with a fair opportunity of living a good life,
whatever their conception of the good may be, while leaving room for the kind of discretion in shaping one's life
that is an essential constituent in every conception of the good life.

Hence impartial justice and Gilligan-inspired care can be reconciled: they function at
different orders or levels of moral deliberation.
Another attempt, this time from Kantian constructionism, is provided by O'Neill
(1996). She argues against the separation of justice (with its universalist aspirations) and
virtue (with its particularist tendencies), suggesting that this arises from defects in under-
lying conceptions of reasoning about action. Like Barry (1995), she defends universal
principles against particularism. There is strong spatiality in her emphasis on who counts
in ethical consideration, whether universal (`more or less cosmopolitan') or restricted in
scope, with different `stretches' in different circumstances and borders defining insiders
and outsiders. `Connections will peter out at differing boundaries for different agents
and in activities of differing sorts in different circumstances' (O'Neill, 1996: 117). She
David M. Smith 33

introduces a meta-ethical dimension of spatial scope, in describing the urge towards


universalism as follows (O'Neill, 1996: 53±54):
in justifying what we do, in criticizing what others do, we constantly appeal to a wider group, of whose
boundaries we usually lack any very definite conception . . . some thinking about and justifications of action must
be presentable, hence followable and exchangable, not merely among an immediate group of participants, or of
those present, or of the like minded, or even among fellow-citizens, but among more diverse and often more
dispersed others, whose exact boundaries cannot readily be defined . . . they must be capacious in a world of
multiple and diverse audiences who are linked rather than separated by porous state and regional boundaries,
global telecommunications and interlocking and overlapping practices and polities.

We cannot hope to live by spatially restricted reasoning, though its necessary extent
remains fuzzy.
She constructs a general principle of justice in the style of Kantian universalization,
based on the prevention of injury (O'Neill, 1996: 179, 191):
justice is in the first instance a matter of living lives and of seeking supporting institutions and policies that reject
injury . . . commitment to universal principles of justice is most effectively expressed through specific institutions
that limit risks of injury, so helping to secure and maintain basic capacities and capabilities for action for all.

She approaches the virtues with a similar form of constructive argument, leading to the
conclusion that indifference to and neglect of others cannot be universalized (we all
depend on not being treated so); therefore some form of care and concern follows. But it
is bound to be selective (O'Neill, 1996: 195):
Although many ethical traditions extol universal benevolence, love for all mankind, or concern for all, their
rhetoric misleads. Justice can be observed in relations with all others; social virtues cannot . . . nobody can provide
help or care for all others [instead people should] take some care to sustain some others in some ways . . . The social
virtues . . . do not require generalized or maximal benevolence or beneficence . . . but only selective and feasible help,
care, love, generosity, support or solidarity.

There are compelling reasons for directing much care and concern to those who have
become dear or near, for they have come to expect it. There can be no universal
obligation, to which rights to care can be linked, only choice and opportunity. Those who
seek a complete algorithm to guide caring should give this up or find what O'Neill (1996:
199, note 11) describes as the `consolations of utilitarianism'.
However, solidarity and rescue may offer more universal scope (O'Neill, 1996: 197):
Solidarity can be expressed across large spatial and social distances, to others who are neither near nor dear,
through forms of help and support for distant strangers, especially those who are destitute or oppressed . . . Acts
of rescue are more dramatic expressions of care and concern, directed towards others in present danger and
misfortune, who may also be neither near nor dear.

Examples include charities and disaster relief. Such institutionalized activities differ from
those kinds of care which seem intrinsically local.
There are substantial differences between the philosophical approaches of Friedman,
Barry and O'Neill. Friedman espouses a feminism critically aware of the parochial
limitations of partiality, Barry is committed to impartiality embedded in liberal perspect-
ives on justice, while O'Neill combines Kantian universalism with virtue ethics. But what
is more interesting is the similarity of their conclusions. All three find impartiality as
justice and partiality as care compatible, if in somewhat different ways.
Similar conclusions can be found in the work of other contemporaries, including some
cited earlier in this article. For example, Dancy (1993: 178) combines the demands of
benevolence as a neutral (impartial) virtue and the flexibility of the agent-relative
(partial) virtue of care for one's family and friends: `These virtues are in tension, perhaps,
in terms of the demands they place on action. But they are not contradictory . . . It is
34 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

possible for the same person to have both virtues at once.' Miller (1992: 200±201) echoes
Barry (1995) in referring to different spheres, with partiality towards family practised
against background institutions directed towards improving the lot of the disadvant-
aged. To Benhabib (1992: 180), `Gilligan's work to date does not provide us with
sufficient reasons to want to reject universalist moral philosophies'; it is more a
contribution to contextual sensitivity. `In any world where relations are not entirely face
to face . . . and [in] a discussion about wide-ranging solidarity such as might reach people
who are many and distant, the necessity of a generalizing moral rationality to work
together with decent human sentiments would seem to be elementary' (Geras, 1995: 98):
thus, a combination of universalizing notions and empathy is required.
A fusion from communitarianism is suggested by Selznick (1992: 521). The `communal
democracy' which he advocates, like community itself, is both particularist and
universalist. Early life is characterized by concrete affinities, with families, peer groups
and so on, but by themselves these are isolating and parochial. `To sustain community as
a framework for the whole of life and for the flourishing of multiple groups, a transition
must be made from piety to civility, and from bounded to inclusive altruism' (1992: 521).
Tronto (1993: 171) gets to the heart of the matter: `care needs to be connected to a
theory of justice'. For Solomon (1995: 259±60): `Without emotion, without caring, a
theory of justice is just another numbers game . . . Reason and emotion are not two
conflicting and antagonistic aspects of the soul. Together they provide justice, which is
neither dispassionate nor ``merely emotional''.' For Mendus (1993: 25): `unsupported by
considerations of justice and equality, care may simply not extend reliably beyond the
immediacy of one's own family, or group, or clan, to the wider world of unknown
others.' And for Held (1993: 76), an exclusive focus on care may lead us to accept a
particular economic stratification in which the rich care for the rich and the poor for the
poor. Even one (exceptional) contrary voice is ambiguous: `the union between the care
perspective of cultural feminists and the justice perspective of liberals, while essential, is
unattainable' (Sypnowich, 1993: 496).
A more expansive version of the central conclusion towards which these works point
is provided by Mulhall and Swift (1996: 293), in an attempt to reconcile some aspects of
liberalism and communitarianism:
This emphasis upon equality [in liberalism] does not conflict with our ordinary ethical beliefs in the rightness of
discriminating between the virtuous and the viscous, or favouring one's family and friends; on the contrary, it
licenses them. If justice is a soft normative parameter of well-being, then whenever its demands are not met, the
goodness of our lives (and so the goodness of our ethical practice of partiality) is significantly reduced. But, once
its demands have been met, we are normally entitled to use our resources partially if we so wish. No use of my
own fair share of resources can make the share of resources received by others any less fair; so my non-political
partialities cannot be condemned as even indirectly contributing to injustice. Our natural partiality is not in
conflict with egalitarian politics; it is rather in conflict with any other kind.

Clement (1996) provides the most thorough account of what it means to integrate the
care and justice perspectives. She argues that both are involved in how people live and
evaluate: both can shed different light on situations, each is required for the other, both
are distinctive as well as interdependent. `Properly understood, the ethic of justice
requires not just abstract principles but contextual details as well. Likewise, the ethic of
care requires not only contextual details but general principles as well' (Clement, 1996:
76). For example, a focus on care could provoke questions about the justice of treatment
of care workers, while a focus on justice could raise questions about the distribution of
resources for care. Thus, care and justice should not be seen as competitors, but as allies
`indispensable to one another in our attempts to create a world more conducive to
David M. Smith 35

human well-being' (Clement, 1996: 109). As to the spatial scope of beneficence (Clement,
1996: 85):
far from undermining our relations of justice to people distant from us, care helps us recognize our justice
obligations to those distant from us . . . if we want to take these obligations seriously, we should try to extend our
sense of social connection by eliminating the barriers, such as ignorance, that make us feel disconnected from
those physically and culturally distant from us.
This observation gets to the core of a problem on which the aspirations of global concern
manifest in beneficence or active care may yet founder. The problem is one of meta-
ethics: of self-identity and moral motivation. If, as has been suggested by various writers,
extending the spatial scope of beneficence depends on the capacity to empathize with
distant others whom we understand to be similar to ourselves, this requires something
more than the kind of relational (or social) self found in feminism and communitarian-
ism, imbued with a special emotion or passion capable of motivating care for nearest and
dearest but which may remain parochially confined. As Friedman (1993: 87±88) puts it,
extending empathetic capacities developed in relationships with closely known persons
to those more distant does not come solely from motives rooted in self-identity: it also
requires reasoning and analogical insight. She goes on (1993: 88):
global moral concern is a rational achievement but not an immediate motivation. It is, furthermore, an
achievement only for some selves. It is a result of moral thinking that has no necessary motivational source in the
self, so not everyone will find it convincing . . . This result does not threaten the conception of the social self.
However, it brings us face to face with what seems to be one important limit of that concept: its inability to
ground the wider sort of concern for others in unmediated constituents of the self. We, thus, confront the apparent
fragility of the human motivation of global concern, even in socially constituted selves.
To achieve the grounding required, and the moral progress implied, may be no less a
task than the completion of a transformation of human identity initiated when people
were first inclined to look beyond their own highly localized experience, to see others
with self-recognition and a trace of sympathy.

VI Conclusion
it is ultimately caring that counts, and it is not reason (as opposed to emotion) that allows us to extend our reach
to the universal but rather the expansive scope of the emotions themselves (Solomon, 1995: 263).
we have limited resources for caring. We cannot care for everyone or do everything that a caring approach
suggests. We need moral guidelines for ordering priorities. Though the hunger of our own children comes before
the hunger of children we do not know, the hunger of children in Africa ought to come before some of the
expensive amusements we may feel like providing for our own children. These are moral problems calling to some
extent for principled answers (Held, 1993: 74±75).
while care is essential to a morally adequate life and society, so too is justice (Clement, 1996: 116).
An ethic of care is an important supplement, or corrective, to the preoccupation of
mainstream moral thinking with impartiality. But care, and the emotions usually
associated with it, are not enough for an ethics capable of engaging the problems of the
contemporary world. Once the importance of an ethic of care is recognized, attention has
to be given to the context in which the practice of care takes place, to its political
economy and institutional arrangements as well as to the kind of lives and needs which
people are experiencing. Introducing the missing dimension of justice requires a version
of social justice as equalization (Smith, 1994). Specifically, the resources required to care
for those in need must be brought into balance with the need for care, at a spatial scale
relevant to the provision of care by both individuals and institutions of the state. Then
the natural strength of feelings of partiality for nearest and dearest can be brought to bear
locally, making for empathetic as well as effective care.
36 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

But it is not a simple unidimensional ordering, with justice implemented by impartial


reason prioritized over feelings motivating care. If justice is to prevail, it will require
more than reason. Only if `we', in the privileged parts of the world, can empathize with
less fortunate others elsewhere, and strongly enough to motivate much more equal
provision of the means of caring, will something like a universal ethic of care have any
chance of challenging the combination of ethical hedonism and resurgent parochial self-
interest into which much of the world appears to be sinking. No less than an overarching
conception of the good incorporating care for others is required, and this will need all the
emotion as well as the reason that can be mustered in its support. Indeed, the distinction
itself collapses, as we understand their deep entanglement and interdependence in moral
motivation and action.
The primary purpose of this article has not, however, been to solve meta-ethical
problems, far less to propagate a particular theory of the good. The aim, as set out at the
start, has been more modest: to demonstrate something of the interest of engaging a new
disciplinary interface. The geographical question of how far we should care has enabled
us to touch on the debate between the impartiality of global concern in the Enlight-
enment tradition of universalism and the partiality purveyed in some versions of
feminism and communitarianism. As anticipated in the introduction, unrestrained
partiality easily leads to conservative parochialism, which, as a restricted ethic of care,
may merely reproduce or exacerbate patterns of inequality manifest in the differential
availability of resources for the satisfaction of human need. However, the strength of
partialist sentiments, including that of caring for close people, reveals abstract impartial-
ity to be a cold, dispassionate project, important though rights and rules may be in the
pursuit of justice for those needing care. As the debate continues, it is hoped that the
geography will be increasingly recognized, and that this will help to make for a more
caring world.

Acknowledgements
This is a revised version of a paper prepared for the Annual Conference of the Royal
Geographical Society (with the Institute of British Geographers) held in Exeter, January
1997. Thanks to Ron Johnston for encouraging its submission and for his editorial
indulgence over length. Thanks also to Judith Gerber and three anonymous referees for
drawing attention to some important issues, full treatment of which would have required
substantial additions to the article. Steve Everett and Tom Walker of my readings group
at QMW also made helpful suggestions. This article is for Tracey.

Notes
1. Judith Gerber responded to a draft of this article by questioning my treatment of reason and
emotion as distinct, stressing the role played by the body and emotion in reasoning and the social
construction of emotions (see Gerber, 1997: 8±9). While my revision does not address her points
adequately, it may help to erode the distinction.
2. This discussion of communitarianism is highly selective. Some broader links between geography,
morality and community are explored in Smith (1998), submitted for publication long before this article
but overtaken by the protracted process of producing special issues of journals.
3. An anonymous referee commented that my `broadside' against postmodernism fails to
acknowledge that the recognition of politically salient forms of difference may have helped to counter
David M. Smith 37

the oppressive aspects of a universalizing modernism. I do acknowledge this, but also note that the
struggles with which I am most familar ± for black civil rights in the USA and against apartheid in
South Africa ± were more a case of the universalist notion of equal moral worth countering particular
social constructions of difference. On the `illusions' of postmodernism, see Eagleton (1996).

References
Adams, P.C. 1996: Protest and the scale politics of Geras, N. 1995: Solidarity in the conversation of
telecommunications. Political Geography 15, humankind: the ungroundable liberalism of Richard
419±41. Rorty. London: Verso.
Gerber, J. 1997: Beyond dualism ± the social
Bader, V. 1995: Citizenship and exclusion: radical construction of nature and the natural and
democracy, community, and justice. Or, what is social construction of human beings. Progress in
wrong with communitarianism? Political Theory Human Geography 21, 1±17.
23, 211±46. Gilligan, C. 1982: In a different voice: psychological
Baier, A.C. 1987: The need for more than justice. theory and woman's development. Cambridge, MA:
Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13, 41±56. Harvard University Press.
Barry, B. 1995: Justice as impartiality (a treatise on ÐÐ 1987: Moral orientation and moral develop-
social justice. Volume II). Oxford: Clarendon Press. ment. In Kittay, E. and Meyers, D., editors,
Bauman, Z. 1989: Modernity and the holocaust. Women and moral theory, Totowa, NJ: Rowman &
Cambridge: Polity Press. Littlefield, 19±33.
ÐÐ 1993: Postmodern ethics. Oxford: Blackwell. Ginzburg, C. 1994: Killing a Chinese mandarin: the
Becker, L.C. 1992: Places for pluralism. Ethics 102, moral implications of distance. New Left Review
707±19. 208, 107±20.
Belsey, A. 1992: World poverty, justice and inequal- Goodin, R. 1985: Protecting the vulnerable. Chicago,
ity. In Attfield, R. and Watkins, B., editors, IL: University of Chicago Press.
International justice and the third world, London:
Routledge, 35±49. Habermas, J. 1990: Moral consciousness and commu-
Benhabib, S. 1992: Situating the self: gender, com- nicative action. Cambridge: Polity Press.
munity and postmodernism in contemporary ethics. Hekman, S. J. 1995: Moral voices, moral selves: Carol
Oxford: Polity Press. Gilligan and feminist moral theory. Oxford: Polity
Press.
Clement, C. 1996: Care, autonomy, and justice: Held, V. 1993: Feminist morality: transforming
feminism and the ethic of care. Oxford: Westview culture, society, and politics. Chicago, IL: Univers-
Press. ity of Chicago Press.
Corbridge, S. 1993: Marxisms, modernities, and
moralities: development praxis and the claims of
Jagger, A.M. 1995: Toward a feminist conception of
distant strangers. Environment and Planning D:
moral reasoning. In Sterba, J.P., Machan, T.R.,
Society and Space 11, 449±72.
Jagger, A.M., Galston, W.A., Gould, C.C., Fisk,
M. and Solomon, R.C., editors, Morality and social
Dancy, J. 1993: Moral reasons. Oxford: Blackwell.
justice: point/counterpoint, London: Rowman &
Doyal, L. and Gough, I. 1991: A theory of human
Littlefield, 115±46.
need. London: Macmillan.

Eagleton, T. 1996: The illusions of postmodernism. Largue, G.A. 1991: Ancient ethics. In Singer, P.,
Oxford: Blackwell. editor, A companion to ethics, Oxford: Blackwell,
Etzioni, A. 1995: The spirit of community: rights, 29±40.
responsibilities and the communitarian agenda.
London: Fontana. MacIntyre, A. 1981: After virtue: a study in moral
theory (2nd edn, 1995). London: Duckworth.
Friedman, M. 1991: The practice of partiality. Ethics Markovic, M. 1990: The development vision of
101, 818±35. socialist humanism. In Engel, J.R. and Engel, J.G.,
ÐÐ 1993: What are friends for? Feminist perspectives editors, Ethics of environment and development:
on personal relationships and moral theory. Ithica, global challenge, international response, London:
NY, and London: Cornell University Press. Belhaven Press, 127±36.
38 On the spatial scope of bene®cence

Martin J.R. 1996: Aerial distance, esotericism, and ÐÐ editor, 1991: A Companion to ethics. Oxford:
other closely related traps. Signs: Journal of Blackwell.
Women in Culture and Society 21, 584±614. ÐÐ 1995: How are we to live? Ethics in an age of self-
Mendus, S. 1993: Different voices, still lives: interest. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.
problems in the ethics of care. Journal of Applied Smith, D.M. 1994: Geography and social justice.
Philosophy 10, 17±27. Oxford: Blackwell.
Milgram, S. 1974: Obedience to authority: an experi- ÐÐ 1997a: Back to the good life: towards an
mental view. London: Tavistock. enlarged conception of social justice. Environment
Miller, R.W. 1992: Moral differences: truth, justice and and Planning D: Society and Space 15, 19±35.
conscience in a world of conflict. Princeton, NJ: ÐÐ 1997b: Geography and ethics: a moral turn?
Princeton University Press. Progess in Human Geography 21, 596±603.
Mulhall, S. and Swift, A. 1996: Liberals and ÐÐ 1998: Geography, morality and community.
communitarians (2nd edn). Oxford: Blackwell. Environment and Planning A (forthcoming).
Solomon, R.C. 1995: Justice as vengeance, ven-
Noddings, N. 1984: Caring: a feminine approach to geance as justice: a partial defence of Poly-
ethics and moral education. Berkeley, CA: Univer- marchus. In Sterba, J.P., Machan, T.R., Jagger,
sity of California Press. A.M., Galston, W.A., Gould, C.C., Fisk, M. and
Nussbaum, M.C. 1992: Human functioning and Solomon, R.C., editors, Morality and social justice:
social justice: in defence of Aristotelian essenti- point/counterpoint, London: Rowman & Little-
alism. Political Theory 20, 220±46. field, 251±300.
Sterba, J.P. 1981: The welfare rights of distant
Okin, S.M. 1989: Reason and feeling in thinking peoples and future generations: moral side-
about justice. Ethics 99, 229±49. constraints on social policy. Social Theory and
O'Neill, O. 1996: Toward justice and virtue: a con- Practice 7, 99±119.
structive account of practical reasoning. Cambridge: Sterba, J.P., Machan, T.R., Jagger, A.M., Galston,
Cambridge University Press. W.A., Gould, C.C., Fisk, M. and Solomon, R.C.
editors, 1995: Morality and social justice: point/
Rawls, J. 1971: A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: counterpoint. London: Rowman & Littlefield.
Harvard University Press. Sypnowich, C. 1993: Justice, community, and
Rheingold, H. 1993: The virtual community: home- antinomies of feminist theory. Political Theory
steading on the electronic frontier. Reading, MA: 21, 484±506.
Addison-Wesley.
Rorty, R. 1989: Contingency, irony, and solidarity. Tronto, J. 1987: Beyond gender difference to a
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. theory of care. Signs: Journal of Women in Culture
Ruse, M. 1991: The significance of evolution. In and Society 12, 645±63.
Singer, P., editor, A companion to ethics, Oxford: ÐÐ 1993: Moral boundaries: a political argument for
Blackwell, 500±10. an ethic of care. London: Routledge.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1989: Morality and imagination: paradoxes
Selznic, P. 1992: The moral commonwealth: social of progress. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin
theory and the promise of community. Berkeley, CA: Press.
University of California Press.
Sibley, D. 1995: Geographies of exclusion: society and Vetlesen, A.J. 1993: Why does proximity make a
difference in the west, London: Routledge. moral difference? Coming to terms with lessons
Singer, P. 1972: Famine, affluence and morality. learned from the holocaust. Praxis International
Philosophy and Public Affairs 1, 229±43, reprinted 12, 371±86.
in Laslett, P. and Fishkin, J., editors, Philosophy,
politics and society (5th series), Oxford: Blackwell, Walzer, M. 1983: Spheres of justice: a defence of
21±35. pluralism and equality. Oxford: Blackwell.

You might also like