Domenico Fontana and The Vatican Obelisk: Things That Move

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 6

The Stockholm Bubble Tim Anstey

24 See the collaborative project website I am currently part of called


Homefullness, http://homefullness.net.
25 Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Commonwealth (Cambridge: The
Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2009), 7, 8. THINGS THAT MOVE
DOMENICO FONTANA AND
1 Deleuze and Guattari explain that the hylomorphic model, which they 26 Gilles Deleuze, “Postscript on Societies of Control,” in Negotiations
associate with what they call Royal science, implies a ”form that organises (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995), 181.

THE VATICAN OBELISK


matter and a matter prepared for the form.” They extend their critique 27 Deleuze, “Postscript on Societies of Control,” 181.
of hylomorphism further to describe a politics of the relations of power 28 See Hans Lind, “Price Bubbles in Housing Markets: Concept Theory
between ”governors and the governed," suggesting that the multitude are and Indicators”, in IJMA (International Journal of Housing Markets and
merely so much matter to be molded by the powerful. Gilles Deleuze and
Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia [1980]
Analysis), vol. 2, no. 1 (2009), 78–90. I want to thank Hans Lind for the
time he took to talk me through some aspects of real estate theory and
Tim Anstey, KTH School of Architecture
(Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), 369. what is a housing bubble.

M
2 An argument against the concept of hylomorphism can also be found 29 Lind, “Price Bubbles in Housing Markets,” 81.
in Gilbert Simondon’s discussion of the process of individuation. Simon- 30 Ibid., 81.
don is, in turn, frequently cited by Gilles Deleuze. See Gilbert Simondon, 31 Ibid., 84. any of the internal and external structures of
“The Genesis of the Individual,” in Incorporations, ed. Jonathan Crary and 32 See booli website, http://www.booli.se/ and Hemnet website, http:// expectation surrounding architectural prac-
Sanford Kwinter (New York: Zone, 1992), 296–319. See Gilles Deleuze, www.hemnet.se/. tice assess the value of architectural agency
“On Gilbert Simondon,” in Desert Islands and Other Texts 1953–1974 33 Deleuze and Guattari, Anti-Oedipus, 109. through judgements of the “built work,” its
(Paris: Semiotext(e), 2002), 86–89. 34 Thrift, Non-Representational Theory, 55. originality and functionality. Often, the
3 See Jane Bennett, Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things (Dur- 35 Thrift, Non-Representational Theory, 39. assumption will be that in order for an architect to be taken
ham and London: Duke University Press, 2010). seriously—really seriously—substantial parts of that work need
4 For further discussions concerning the politics of affect, see “Spati- to be constituted by new construction. A Priztker Prize–win-
alities of Feeling,” in Non-Representational Theory: Space, Politics, Affect ning architect will be valued for the creation of new composi-
(London: Routledge, 2008); Brian Massumi, “The Autonomy of Affect,” in tions of which, it can be declared, that architect is the author.
Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation (Durham and Lon- Although subject to periodic challenge, this “work-author”
don: Duke University Press, 2002). connection (applied to the way building production intersects
5 Bennett, Vibrant Matter, 23, 24. the activities of architects) continues fundamentally to affect
6 Bennett, Vibrant Matter, 5. how architects think about themselves, how others see them,
7 Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature the way in which architects approach tasks, and the roles they
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986), 81. claim within project processes.1 Although the nature of archi-
8 Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, 311. tectural consultancy evidently varies worldwide, increasing
9 Gilles Deleuze, “Spinoza and the Three ‘Ethics,’” in Essays Critical and globalization means this framing narrative is becoming more
Clinical (London: Verso, 1998), 145. prevalent rather than less.
10 Deleuze and Guattari, What is Philosophy? (London: Verso, 1994), 179. This essay returns to the roots of modern architectural
11 Guattari uses the term Integrated World Capitalism (IWC) to describe theory both to explore how this came to be the case, and to
post-industrial capitalism. See Félix Guattari, The Three Ecologies (Lon- challenge that model of architectural “work.” The exploration
don: Athlone, 2000), 47. is made through reconsidering the text De re aedificatoria, writ-
12 Guattari, The Three Ecologies, 41, 45. ten by Leon Battista Alberti and first circulated around 1452,
13 Bennett, Vibrant Matter, 21. where the modern system of valuing architects according to
14 Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, Anti-Oedipus, trans. Robert Hurley, an assessment of the building as an artefact is adumbrated.2
Mark Seem and Helen R. Lane (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota The challenge is made through reviewing in some detail one
Press, 1983), 86. image from an architectural treatise produced around 150
15 Deleuze and Guattari, What is Philosophy?, 177. years later, Della Trasportatione dell’ Obelisco Vaticano, e delle
16 Doina Petrescu, Altering Practices: Feminist Politics and Poetics of Fabriche di Nostro Signore Papa Sisto V, by Domenico Fontana.
Space (London: Routledge, 2007), 3. Sandwiched between these two accounts is a brief speculation
17 Thrift, “Spatialities of Feeling,” 172. about a collateral effect that the architect/author/work clas-
18 Ibid., 173. sification had on the way in which the developing discipline
19 “We need to ‘kick the habit’ of sedative discourse, particularly the ‘fix’ of architecture dealt with questions of representation during
of television, in order to be able to apprehend the world through the inter- the sixteenth century, evident in architectural treatises such
changeable lenses or points of view of the three ecologies.” See Guattari, as those of Serlio, Palladio, or Vignola. The conclusions are Domenico Fontana, Della Trasportatione dell’ Obelisco Vaticano
The Three Ecologies, 40. intended to be useful for a developing contemporary discus- (Rome, 1590).
20 Thrift, “Spatialities of Feeling,” 187. sion relating to how we think about roles and credit in archi-
21 Gilles Deleuze, Les cours des Gilles Deleuze website, “Deleuze/Spinoza: tectural design today, particularly in relation to the question and even fame he will achieve, or conversely . . . what contempt
Cours Vincennes—24/01/1978,” accessed May 5, 2012, http://www.web- of alteration. and hatred he will receive, and how eloquent, how obvious, pat-
deleuze.com/php/texte.php?cle=14&groupe=Spinoza&langue=2. ent and lasting a testimony of his folly he will leave his fellow
22 Gilles Deleuze, “Three Kinds of Knowledge,” Pli, vol. 14 (2003), 1–20, Judging the architectural work men.”3 How then, according to Alberti, should this judgement
11. In the opening sections of De re aedificatoria Leon Battista of the virtue of an architect be made? The answer is that archi-
23 Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, “Capitalism: A Very Special Delir- Alberti makes clear that the work of an architect can gain that tects will be subject to judgement via the physical compositions
ium,” in Hatred of Capitalism, ed. Chris Kraus and Sylvère Lotringer, (New person fame and credit, or conversely shame and blame: “He their agency produces.4 Much, it is made clear, depends on the
York: Semiotext[e], 2001), 215. must calculate . . . the amount of praise, remuneration, thanks “arrangement of the parts” in those compositions. According

46 NORDIC JOURNAL OF ARCHITECTURE NO. 3. VOL. 2. 2012 47


Things that Move Tim Anstey

to an idealized Albertian account of the world, the architect it will be most effective. For Vitruvius this resolved itself as a
will be able to define that arrangement autonomously and in problem in physics. Thus the final sections of De architectura,
advance, having taken into account all the circumstances of Books 8–10, consider the principles of mechanics and the con-
the context.5 This “art of arrangement” is both a prediction of struction of machines that move things about.11
where the superficies that make up a projected building will Alberti’s De re aedificatoria reflects De architectura, and the
be and a guarantee of their phenomenal success (i.e., the effec- overlap between these two accounts of the art of building was
tiveness on all levels of the object that is created following the to become crucial in defining the principle system of valuing
architect’s instructions). To this extent, the emphasis in Alberti architects’ work during the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries.
is very much on “placement”—the prediction of the proper posi- However it is very unlikely that Alberti’s distinction between
tion for elements that make up compositions that are read as lineamenta (defined places, predetermined by the architect in
buildings. At the commencement of the treatise Alberti informs advance of construction) and structura (the material stuff that
the reader that “the whole matter of building is composed of must be moved to fill those places) emerges out of Vitruvius.12
lineaments [lineamenta] and structure [structura]…. It is the Alberti has a general predeliction to consider the skill of art-
function and duty of lineaments, then, to presecribe an appro- ists—those whose agency makes manifest compositions that
priate place.”6 In this respect De re aedificatoria was critical for are experienced in the world—in precisely these terms. Artists
the development of the modern notion that an architect can be are to be valued for their ability to predict correct “placement,”
read as the “author” of a new work. Architects will themselves on the one hand, versus their skill in arranging the executive
be judged through judgements about the superficies of the built actions that make this idea of placement tangible in a particular
work their agency produces. place and time on the other. This is evident throughout Alberti’s
If lineamenta defines where things should be put, the other ouvre and emerges before the period in which the text of De re
side of Alberti’s definition, structura, concerns everything aedificatoria was crystallized. It is present in Alberti’s defini-
that has to be put there. Alberti’s arguments, in De re aedifica- tion of the art of painting as the action of placing stuff (paint)
toria and in other texts he produced that consider the effec- into sets of predetermined outlines (places) to produce experi-
tiveness of various kinds of phenomenal compositions within ential compositions to be judged (De pictura, 1435); it emerges
the world (notably, buildings, paintings, statues, and ciphers), in his description of the art of the sculptor, who can predict the Domenico Fontana, Della Trasportatione dell’ Obelisco Vaticano (Rome, 1590). Plate 28. Stockholm, Kungliga Biblioteket.
suggest that an equal and slightly distinct virtue resides in the position of the superficies of a body which will be occupied by
action of placing things —that is to say, in the ability to organ- the material the sculptor has the skill to carve; it is evident also found both in producing that composition where everything is The disappearance of process
ize the world such that its materials come to rest in a particular in the theorization of the system of ciphers made in De com- the “right” place, but also in an almost magical facility for plac- Notably, De re aedificatoria is unillustrated. It lays the basis for
position.7 Where in the architect’s case the first kind of virtue ponendis cifris, which relies on a distinction between an under- ing those “things”—be they words, letters, stones, or timbers— a discipline of architecture that was to become obsessed with
appears bound up with notions of stasis—a kind of inevitability standing of letter “places” that guarantee the meaning in a text that make up the composition to best effect.18 graphic representation, but makes its own representations in
that emerges when the world is arranged according to a particu- and material letter “sounds” that fill those places and make the A number of interesting things happen out of this applica- text alone. What is very noticeable in the set of architectural
lar vision, as if things could not be arranged in any other way text manifest—audible to the ear or legible to the eye.13 tion of a theory for analysing one mode of human activity—the treatises that follow Alberti’s De re aedificatoria is the emer-
(“nothing could be altered but for the worse, as Alberti writes in It seems very likely that the root for this habit of thinking production of political speeches in the extremely specific con- gence and eventual dominance of graphic over textual repre-
De re aedificatoria)—the second kind of virtue must be all about in Alberti, which no doubt provided the matrix that informed text of the Roman Senate—to another—the multiple processes sentation. This translation has been much studied and to good
striving, effort, motion, and movement: the action of placing his interpretation of Vitruvius and indirectly informed later involved in ordering and organizing the built environment for effect.19 One aspect about it, though, that still seems important
physical stuff, of relocating it and reforming it from one state interpretations of that text, emerges out of an intellectual cul- human habitation. One is the emergence of the idea of the “pro- to emphasize is the probable relationship between the messy
to another.8 Alberti relates this virtue specifically back to the ture that was rooted in the tradition of oratory. On one side ject” (in the modern sense) into architectural thought. Politi- context of building operations and the ideals of a system that
question of how architects are judged, but with a notable caveat. this culture was provided by Alberti’s education in the disci- cal orators have a project—an intention about how the world was based on judging architects by judging the built compo-
Placing is also an activity that exposes the architect to judge- pline of Law, in which the methods of aural argument were should be—that goes beyond “fitting” their words to the circum- sitions that they were involved in creating. What can be seen
ment; in this case however, the risk to reward relationship is central. On another it was cemented by the study of the theory stances or the make-up of a specific political speech. The pres- as very useful about graphic representation is that it provides
somewhat skewed: of oratory, as codified in ancient texts by Cicero among others, ence of the idea that within architectural agency a wider ethical architects, and architecture as a discipline, with a prosthetic
which were reread by humanists in early Renaissance Italy.14 and political stance is at stake—that the architect somehow has through which judgements about architectural virtue can be
Whenever you intend to move great weights, it is as well to That tradition concerned the creation of the most ephemeral a responsibility and a potential beyond providing this or that made without those judgements resting entirely on the produc-
approach the task gradually, with caution. . . Nor will you kind of sensory compositions—the positioning of words to cre- tyrant with comfortable accommodation—can be dated from tion of built work. Virtue can be judged by potential; drawings
receive as much respect and praise for your ability if your ate effective political speeches.15 Oratory is an art of placing in Alberti’s infiltration of the methods of oratory into the ques- can show the effect of the built work that could result from the
undertaking follows your plan and succeeds, as the disre- real time. Its theory analyses the skill of how to assemble words tion of how to organize building practices. What concerns this architect’s agency, and can describe, in great and precise detail,
spect and contempt for your temerity if it fails.9 together effectively at the crucial moment in order to achieve essay more is how this overlap navigated the fact that political every aspect of “placement” that the architect’s agency seeks to
the aim of persuasion. It also, in its classical form, included the speeches, and speeches in general, are compositions that are produce. As virtual buildings, such projections have one great
In one sense this double emphasis in Alberti follows logically techniques of mnemonics which enabled aural speeches to be always new and transitory, whereas the production of buildings quality—they can be controlled completely and securely such
out of the structure of Vitruvius’ De architectura, which Alberti reaassembled from memory.16 and built forms is just the opposite: turgid, slow, mortgaged to that the superficies they describe really reflect the architect’s
was adapting and clarifying for a modern audience. Vitruvius From Cicero’s account (which Alberti certainly read) this existing conditions, encompassed by conflicting desires, and intention and will.20
also dwells to a great extent on methods and formulae for ability to decide placement, on the spot, but in advance of the very unlikely to be comprehensible in terms of a dazzling dis- In terms of Alberti’s and Vitruvius’ distinction between
guaranteeing that the “placement” of elements in experienced audience’s reception, imbues the orator with an almost magici- play of juggling from a sole author. What happens when a sys- the ability to define decorous compositions and the skill in
compositions will be “correct”—he even adduces a rule for this, cal quality. It is extremely difficult to predict what will be the tem based on valuing “placement” and “placing,” in which the mechanics that could move materials into position in those
the notion of decorum or appropriate placement.10 At the same right thing to say in advance; good orators are like conjurors, relation between these two can be fluid, inevitable, and under compositions, this development of graphic representation has
time, Vitruvius classifies the actions of an architect into two able to move people in ways that would not be thought pos- the sole control of a single mind and voice, encounters a context great significance. For the kind of architectural virtue that can
fields, of which one is this facility to predict what placement sible.17 Alberti’s understanding about how artists and artistic dominated by existing superstructures where many voices and be communicated persuasively through drawing is, or tends to
will be correct in a composition. The other set of actions that works operate seems most indebted to this schooling in ora- minds meet? be, that concerned with placement. Drawings make it possible
Vitruvius describes for the architect concerns precisely the tory: that the creator can be judged by the sensorial effect of to experience in advance and at a distance the effect of the built
problematics of moving material into the position in which the composition produced; that the skill of the creator is to be composition—the built work. That other kind of work in which

48 NORDIC JOURNAL OF ARCHITECTURE NO. 3. VOL. 2. 2012 49


Things that Move Tim Anstey

action of arranging circumstances such that materials can be with nuances of Serlio’s intention around the projection of
moved to the positions defined in these drawings. Construction built works as artefacts, modern and ancient.25 This statement
process may enter in, but often in the form of ruins—of aban- could be made even more confidently about the treatise of Pal-
doned building sites, where pieces of construction lie stranded ladio. Here, architectural compositions are drained of almost
and over-given. Building, then, becomes read as a copy of inten- all their material quality; the “stuffiness” of materials is dealt
tion and the process of copying is not considered, per se as, with in minimal chapters of four paragraphs each (twelve for
central to defining architectural virtue.22 This is not to say that metals); and nothing is said about the issue of moving these
architects such as Palladio neglected or were unskilled in the things about.26 Equipped with the treatise, you could accurately
3 other arts—those which I have broadly termed “placing” here. say where everything should go, but you would have no idea of
Far from it; Palladio was clearly established as an authority how to get it there. By the time of Vignola, the sovereignty of
over all aspects of building process. Yet such processes through this paper plane is entirely established. Graphic representa-
5-
which this authority and virtue worked are not at the centre of tion comprises a complete and developed system, which facili-
Palladio’s books of architecture. What must be communicated tates one kind of discussion about what architectural intention
there is, fundamentally, the projected surfaces of compositions entails. In that discussion placement rules supreme; placing
read as built or projected “works.” And we know, from a further has been almost entirely relegated to a space beyond the pages
450 years of history, that it is through precisely those projected of the text.27
“works” that architecture as a discipline has chosen to value
Palladio and claim him as one of history’s greatest architects. Challenging the model
In the systems of graphic representation that develop within It seems very important to acknowledge that a particular idea
architectural treatises during the sixteenth century, one must about the architectural work is built into the systems of rep-
almost inevitably infer that a hierarchy is established between resentation through which architects were communicating
these two orders of activity. In terms of valuing architectural towards the end of the sixteenth century, and that this idea
agency, skill in placement, which can be described through was in some senses exclusive. In terms of looking for a histori-
graphical projection, is valued over that skill in mechanics and cal locus in which a contemporary challenge to that idea of the
the control of physical labour that places material. There is a architectural work might be mounted, there is one text, pro-
paradox is here, one to which perhaps more attention could duced at the very end of the sixteenth century, which appears
be given. During the sixteenth century, the architectural dis- unique.
cipline created a virtual world in which, with more and more Della Trasportatione dell’ Obelisco Vaticano, e delle Fabriche
sophistication, buildings could exist without being materially di Nostro Signore Papa Sisto V, written by Domenico Fontana
constructed. One might expect that given the endless fluid- and published in Rome in 1590, combines a re-evaluation of Domenico Fontana, Della Trasportatione dell’ Obelisco Vaticano (Rome,
ity that emerges in the virtual—drawings can reflect infinite architectural agency with a lucid description of the experiential 1590). Frontispiece.
changes in intention in a way that buildings cannot—this world impact of construction process.28 The text is written in part to
might have been preoccupied by the possibility of change—of advertise, precisely, the judgment of Fontana as an architect. Della Trasportatione dell’ Obelisco Vaticano defines the archi-
the fluidity of intention in which a thousand possibilities can It appears to conform to the conventions, implicit in the texts tectural work in terms of processes as much as objects. The
be contemplated in a minute. Instead, in terms of its rhetoric, of Serlio, Palladio, and Vignola, that such publication required: subtext of the frontispiece, like the text of the title, is very
Jacopo Barozzi da Vignola, Regole delli cinque ordini d’architetttura architecture became more and more concerned with decorum, Fontana stands as the author; the book combines text, costly explicit about this. The medal Fontana holds out is the mate-
(Rome 1562), Plate XIII with the absolute stasis that limits compositions of brick and production, and fabulous illustrations; and it describes what, rial token of a decision made by Sixtus V, and through Sixtus by
stone.23 Peculiarly, the more architecture could exist on paper, since the framing of architecture as an artistic and intellectual the Roman people, precisely to honour Fontana’s judgement as
architects might be involved—political negotiation, lobbying, the more it considered itself beholden to ideas of the hierachi- discipline at the start of the modern era, must be considered as an architect.30 This reward was given not for any normal defi-
organization of workforces, knowledge of mechanics such that cal value of the absolutely permanent, as if decisions could architectural “works.”29 nition, on Fontana’s part, of “lines and angles” in a projected
great weights can be lifted—can certainly be described visually, never be reversed. Although Alberti applied to architecture a At first glance the frontispiece to the book emphasizes its artefact, nor for a conventional demonstration of his predictive
but not, perhaps to such great effect. By nature such work is system of valuing that saluted both skill in placement and skill alignment with this tradition. Here Fontana is represented, knowledge of the correct place for all the parts in a composi-
process based, mortgaged to the specific circumstances of con- in placing, and although Vitruvius identified both control of like Serlio, like Vignola, beard bristling in three-quarter view. tion such that “nothing could be added or taken away but for
text and site, and transient; a machination which facilitates but static composition and control of fluid process as central to He stands at a table bearing the tools essential to his calling, the worse.” Indeed it was not given for defining the lineaments
does not finally condition that “correct disposition of the parts the architect’s work, within the system of valuation and credit clutching an architectural body, that of an obelisk, to his breast. of any object at all. Rather, it was awarded for his prowess in
such that nothing could be added or taken away”, and which that developed through architecture’s encounter with the print The suggestion one almost inevitably derives from this is one designing, organizing, and predicting the results of a process. Of
is invisible to a system of representation developed to record during the sixteenth century, process gave way to artefact and of ownership between a built work presented via a projective the several projects in Fontana’s treatise, the most spectacular,
such things. ideas of the permanent and the transient became employed in drawing (the obelisk, represented in perspective) and the archi- which gives its name to the book and which informs the frontis-
It is possible to see in the development of the architectural a specific way. tect pictured: the obelisk stands on Fontana’s table among his piece, concerns the removal of the Egyptian obelisk that, since
treatises that emerged in Europe, first in Italy and then rapidly With this in mind, it is interesting to read again the archi- other possessions. But on closer examination disturbances are antiquity, had stood to the south of what became the basilica of
in other geographic locations between the middle of the fif- tectural treatises of the mid-sixteenth century, and recent com- to be found in this reading. There is something strange both St. Peter in Rome. In 1585 Fontana obtained the commission to
teenth and the end of the sixteenth centuries, a steady tendency mentaries on them. The multiple means of projection on which about the placing of the obelisk on Fontana’s table (balanced translate the obelisk to a new location axially before the facade
to lift the architectural project away from the actuality of build- Serlio dwells, exhaustively—ichonografia, profilo, ortografia, on the rear edge) and about the positioning of Fontana’s hands. of the church, then in the process of reconstruction, in what is
ing processes.21 Although Francesco di Giorgio in the 1470s sciografia, and scenografia—all concern, in one way or another, The right appears to have got caught up in the chain and medal- now known as Piazza San Pietro. The work took exactly one
devoted pages to the description of machines for lifting and car- the representation of what might be termed the permanent lion hanging around his neck—why, one wonders, must Fontana year, from 25 September 1585 to 26 September 1586. It con-
rying, in Filarete’s Libro Architettonico these had already disap- architectural work—the trace, in stone, of architectural inten- run chains through his fingers in order to hold the obelisk? And sisted of moving a single piece of stone, weighing around 400
peared. In the treatises of Serlio and onwards through Palladio tion frozen.24 They tell us almost nothing about how that stone the fingers of the left hand appear to be in motion, as if holding tonnes, a distance of 250 metres.31
and Vignola, what is represented in greater and greater detail is arrived in its place. It is exactly these aspects of Serlio that have the obelisk required constant effort, as if it were a snake, or a What is created here, and what must be described to illus-
the result, the full stop, the final effect of architectural intention been subject to much scholarly attention. Authoritative inter- fish, hard to grasp, apt to escape. What, kind of work, then, is trate Fontana’s judgement, is not, then, a projected artefact,
in defining superficies. What is represented less and less is the pretations of his text concern themselves almost exclusively Fontana describing to articulate his virtue? but an event—a staging, a happening. Fontana adds very little

50 NORDIC JOURNAL OF ARCHITECTURE NO. 3. VOL. 2. 2012 51


artistic creativity in relation to the physiognomy of the obelisk; concentric rings, each with a kind of piglet’s tail and mouse’s
indeed, the reverse is rather the case—his goal is to translate it nose—are connected by lines to small circles that cluster in
without material change, alteration, or damage. What is cre- their turn in and around the squares marking the central cross.
ated through Fontana’s “work” is the extraordinary process that
moving the obelisk entailed. Yet in the reading and writing of Transient artefact and permanent process
architectural history, to value an architectural work in this way In this drawing Fontana makes visible that which is usually
is unusual. It is perhaps this condition that resonates with the excluded from architectural representation—the temporary
hand gestures in Fontana’s frontispiece. Moving the obelisk supports, tools, workers, and scaffolding that allow material
was obviously a very difficult task technically.32 But I would construction to come into being. Indeed, Fontana’s whole work
suggest that for an architect in 1590 it was also already a chal- revolves around such objects, challenging that hierarchy that
lenge theoretically to dignify the action of moving the obelisk usually privileges the representation of the built over that of
as a bona fide architectural work.33 Thus the richness in Fon- building. But because such an hierarchical order was already
tana’s architectural treatise is its celebration and vindication inscribed into the systems of representation Fontana was
of this other kind of work, experienced by a crowd of thousands, using, he has to twist the rules of those systems to make his
of lifting, rotating, and dragging a gargantuan object with the description.
means available, and of directing, organizing, bullying, and Reading into Fontana’s picture, one starts naturally out-
negotiating the context in which this could happen. Much of side the plan with the scene at the base, which provides both
the intriguing quality of the treatise emerges out of this ambi- a foreground introduction and implicitly a foundation for the
tion to celebrate one kind of idea of the exemplary architectural meaning of everything else. This scene represents only things
work (concerned, exclusively, with “placing") via the conven- that move and whose manifestation is temporary—animate ste-
tions evolved to communicate another (the system of graphic vedores, horses, whips in hand, circumambulate an inanimate
representation developed in architectural treatises since Serlio windlass. As one moves from the perspective scene into the
to describe “placement” in architectural compositions, or the plan drawing it is clear that each of the circles in the swarm fill-
definition of superficies in the stationary, if virtual, object). ing the plan’s space represents such an assembly. In this trans-
Fontana accomplishes this task through ten carefully lation from perspective to plan, however, the most “temporary”
composed plates and through an accompanying text.34 These objects are lost to the conventions of representation (the peo-
plates follow almost completely conventions of architectural ple and animals disappear) and what remains marked on the
draftsmanship developed to represent architectural works as paper is the outline of the slightly more permanent and inani-
artefacts: plan, section, and elevation; perspective; and an iso- mate objects on which they exert force—windlasses, ropes and
lation from and a filtering of contextual information to com- the rotational track of the moving figures. So the first stepping
municate content. All these are theorized by Serlio and all are point highlighted in this combinatory drawing is that between
used through Palladio and Vignola to underline the centrality animated objects (that move freely and diurnally) and inani-
of defining placement to the architect’s task. Yet what is clearly mate ones—winches and ropes.
articulated in Fontana’s depictions is not the final, static, mon- The next step that one can impute is one between vary-
umental capacity of the obelisk itself, but the moment before ing orders of permanency in temporary objects concerning
this capacity is realized—the drama of “placing”—or “displac- whether their job is to move—rotationally or linearly—or to
ing”—what, for the extended duration of the moment in the guide movement—to resist force and orientate translation.
book (it took three years to complete), must be considered The articulation of this spatio-temporal step between classes
a temporary, movable, and ephemeral object. The drawings of transience and permanence is also built into the represen-
deserve to be studied as a series, but the ways in which Fon- tational convention of the picture. The slippery nature of the
tana adjusts convention in order to achieve his aims, and much windlasses is indicated by their contrasting degrees of rotation
of the alternative idea of the architectural work implicit in the in plan relative to the axis of the picture; the nature of the cas-
treatise, can be exemplified by looking carefully at one image. tello orientates its cross orthogonally on the paper. The cas-
The second plate in Fontana’s series is based on a plan rep- tello, which anchors the picture, might be seen as a kind of pin
resentation of the urban space that surrounded the obelisk in connecting the worlds of “building” (as an action) and build-
its “original” position south of the cathedral, that is to say, the ings (as artefacts)—or perhaps one could say as one side of a
place it occupied before Fontana’s work. This consisted of a central link in the chain of connection the drawing suggests,
rough piazza containing the obelisk and a circular fourth-cen- between the class of the temporary and the class of the per-
tury sacristy (shown central and free standing on plan), edged manent. Like the windlasses the castello is a temporary mani-
by the construction of the church to the east (on the right) and festation—it existed during one year in two different locations,
by dwellings to the south and west (whose walls show as frag- and its internal material connections were designed such that
ments in conventionally hatched plan). Within this space, in all the elements in its assembly could be reused and disappear
Fontana’s representation, a series of patterns are marked. At into other constructions. But its classification as “temporary”
the centre is a cross of small squares marking the assembly of becomes highly complex, for what is most important about the
temporary piles that made up an enormous scaffold, the “cas- castello, in fact, is its absolute permanency in relation to the
tello” built around the obelisk, in which Fontana would first enduring moment in which the obelisk must be lowered from
pivot and then lower it. Filling the remaining space of the paper vertical to horizontal. Thus the castello derives an aura of per-
and the experiential urban space contained by the “permanent” manence through its task of resisting and modulating forces
structures already mentioned, a further set of revolutions are that are absolute and permanent. And so the whole of Fontana’s
marked. A series of forty crosses—each circumscribed by two drawing, as this section of the whole event, becomes orientated Domenico Fontana, Della Trasportatione dell’ Obelisco Vaticano (Rome, 1590).

52 NORDIC JOURNAL OF ARCHITECTURE NO. 3. VOL. 2. 2012 53


Things that Move Nils-Ole
Tim Anstey
Lund

around the orthogonal propriety of this object. The castello can Architectural work of that environment. However, although the experience Fon-
be seen as the stationary element around which all the other It should be emphasized that Fontana’s treatise is not a pro- tana conveys is partly emotive—horses strain, windlasses creak,
urban structures revolve, and in its representation only fixed jective set of instructions about how to move the obelisk. It hemp cable groans—behind this lies a choreographic scheme;
items concerned in the movement of the obelisk are shown. is, rather, a reflective account a posteriori (and three years in fixed relationships of contract and risk; links that, although not
There is therefore a very subtle change of drawing convention the making) about having moved it. In terms of its historical manifest permanently in any one location, have their own kind 1 See Tim Anstey, Katja Grillner, and Rolf Hughes, Architecture and
between the windlasses and the castello; in drawing the latter, context, this account is significant in that it curates and makes of permanence through repetition. The phenomena amounts Authorship (London: Black Dog Publishing, 2007); Jeremy Till, Architec-
the lines representing the mobile rope disappear and only the visible an aspect of the architectural work that goes beyond to another urban pattern replete with its own tightly con- ture Depends (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2010).
beams that will support the obelisk and the pulleys that will the definition and recording of projected artefacts. Indeed, trolled formal structure. Fontana’s distortion of renaissance 2 Leon Battista Alberti, De re aedificatoria, On the Art of Building in
channel the motive forces in the cables are shown.35 the significance of the architectural “work” articulated in the modes of architectural representation—and celebration of Ten Books, trans. J. Rykwert, R. Tavernor, N. Leach (Cambridge, Mass.:
The permanence and fixed nature of the castello is spelt drawings only really emerges as one reads Fontana’s descrip- the architectural significance of process—appears valuable in MIT Press, 1988), hereafter abbrieviated as De re aed. See also Giovanni
out clearly in the detailed plan superimposed, at larger scale, tion of the logistic context of legislative, economic, and ecologi- theorizing architectural agency today. The move to redefine the Orlandi, L. B. Alberti, L’archittetura, ed. G. Orlandi and P. Portoghesi, 2
midway up the picture. The main part of this plan shows the cal agency that was necessary to support the project. Working architectural work as something process based is of particular vols (Milan: Ed. E. Polifio, 1966)), and the facsimile of the 1485 edition
blocks (doubled pulleys are shown with a doubled ellipse) and outwards from the obelisk, Fontana lists the following: the cal- relevance at several levels. The materials we use to build, what prepared by Hans-Karl Lücke, Alberti Index: Leon Battista Alberti, De re
beams that were to channel forces in a reflected ceiling plan culations in building statics made to estimate its weight; the we have to do to them in order to make them serviceable, where Aedificatoria, 4 vols [Florence, 1485] (Munich: Prestel, 1975).
view (i.e., a view imagined as looking up from the underside). design of the timber castello that should bear and rotate this they come from, and the ways in which we join them together, 3 De re aed., IX, 10, 315.
But this plan too includes a representational flip. At the centre, mass; the sourcing and geographical transport of the timber; are all matters suddenly fraught with potential in a sustain- 4 On the various backgrounds to Alberti’s identification of the possibility
the obelisk is shown, viewed from directly above as opposed to the papal bulls required to secure the commodities involved able society. Fontana’s description of the logistic background of judging architects through the built work, see Mario Carpo, The Alpha-
beneath, the lines of its pyramidal top crossing at the centre. and assistance at the right price; the estimate of the number to moving the obelisk has the same panoscopic fascination bet and the Algorithm (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2011) and my own
As one crosses from describing a temporary-but-permanent of horses (and therefore the amount of horsepower) required that emerges in life-cycle cost analysis today. In re-evaluating “Authorship and Authority in L. B. Alberti’s De re aedificatoria,” Nordic
object to a permanent-but-transient object, one must literally as motive force; the breaking strain of hemp cable; the supply architectural agency, our acknowledgement of the management Journal of Architectural Research, 4 (2003), 19–25.
invert one’s mental view of the picture. One can take this ana- of the hemp; cable manufacture; the stabling of the horses; the of such webs will become increasingly central. To include, as 5 Carpo, The Alphabet and the Algorithm, 20–26.
lysis further to embrace the framing images of the obelisk in removal of men; the provision of foodstuffs; et cetera.37 As one Fontana’s treatise does, this “theatre of construction” within 6 De re aed., I, 1, 7.
profile that surround the plan. In the four elevational views reads one understands Fontana’s awareness that this “preg- the definition of the architectural is to make visible, in a very 7 Alberti’s position vis-à-vis the architect’s involvement in the action
that frame Fontana’s drawing one is never permitted to view nant” moment of moving the obelisk, like a piece of military specific way, the technological, carbon-significant processes on of “placing” might be debated. On one side, in De re aedificatoria Alberti
the obelisk directly. Each view is protected by a sheathing layer, strategy hanging in the balance, is at the centre of a national which habitation depends. makes clear that the architect need not control actions on the building
lying between the obelisk and the castello, the obelisk and the network of supply, transit, climate, and administration that is For architectural works are defined, precisely, by their site, but can leave such matters to a “zealous, circumspect and strict clerk
viewer’s eye, and between the obelisk and harm. Following and must be ongoing. spectacular quality—to define something as a work is to make of works” (De re aed. IX, 11, 318). This might suggest a determined disin-
elevation convention, the representation here is nearly lifelike To record this and to give it virtue (which is what Fontana it visible—to criticism and to aesthetic judgement. Defining ele- terest in the action of placing material as an area of concern for architects.
again, showing the blocks and tackles that will move the object; achieves in his treatise) is to do a number of interesting things, ments of process as integral to the notion of the architectural At the same time, in the introduction to the Italian edition of his treatise
the detail of iron connecting rods and bindings; shadow relief then. Fontana is obviously interested in architecture as an work is to raise the stakes in regard to such processes and to on painting, Della Pittura, Alberti praises Brunelleschi’s virtue in con-
on the bundled timbers. Together this assembly of straps and action, as the “placing of material,” in Alberti’s terms. There is position them as matters of central import to the self-definition structing the dome of S. Maria del Fiore, which “if I am not mistaken . . .
pulleys and timbers creates the device that allows a translation also a strong resonance between Fontana’s textual description of architecture as a discipline. To shift one’s emphasis from people did not believe possible in these days and was probably unknown
between two contrasting notions of the absolute—the one tem- and Vitruvius’ observations in Books 8–10 of De architectura understanding architectural intention as the organizational and unimaginable to the ancients” (Della Pittura, Introduction, 34–35.)
porary and permanent (an obelisk that will last until the end of (i.e., those sections not concerned with decorum or the appro- composition of built artefacts to valuing a microscopic under- This expressed concern can be linked to the structures of De pictura, De
the world but that will soon move); the other the constructional priate placing of elements within built compositions, but with standing of process is to shift how one values a Le Corbusier statua and De componendis cifris. The classical examination of the rela-
and platonic (a network of forces that act on this object and the process of placing and the knowledge and facility necessary or a Cedric Price, or more latterly a SHoP architects in New tionships between these works is contained in Joan Gadol, Leon Battista
condition its placing, manifest in the castello that will last a to control such processes).38 York or a Lacaton & Vassal in Paris. There is nothing particu- Alberti: Universal Man of the Early Renaissance (Chicago: Chicago Uni-
year but in which movement is untenable). But it seems important also to reiterate the extent to which larly moralizing in this proposal—the aim is not to produce a versity Press, 1969).
From the clothed obelisk it is possible to descend into the this treatise appears bound to Alberti’s notion that architects humbler or somehow more worthy discipline, one in which 8 The location within De re aedificatoria of Alberti’s discussion on the
plan drawing of the picture again to follow a further set of steps. will be judged according to the experienced composition their the actors eschew their designer clothes and take on sack cloth movement of large weights occurs at the centre of his treatise within the
Where the drawing up to now has communicated the absolute, agency produces. Technical and mathematical details; bureau- and ashes; rather, the aim would be to make integral a notion of crucial Book 6 on Ornament (that is to say, it is divorced from the discus-
and in platonic terms “permanent,” nature of the seemingly cratic machinery; spectacle, including the identity of the audi- material construction into the central vanity that must accom- sions of materials that occupy Books 2, Materials and 3, Construction,
transient (windlasses, castello), it now relates the temporari- ence; and religious rites—all are bound together into an idea pany actions within a discipline that, from its roots, is defined which deal largely with the function of materials in place. See De re aed.,
ness of apparently permanent structures. Lineamenta, those that must still be interrogated in terms of architects, authors, as artistic and creative. And it perhaps allows a new kind of VIII, 6–8, 164–175.
lines and angles that define the superficies of buildings as arte- and works. Fontana’s drawing signals the experiential presence definition of what architecture is and what we value in terms 9 De re aed., VI, 8, 175.
facts and which can so easily be represented by drawing, may be of the “discovered” permanencies that are implied by the invis- of the actions that create it. It would be productive to think of 10 M. Vitruvius Pollio, De architectura. Translated as Vitruvius, The Ten
absolute in space. But Fontana’s twisting of convention makes ible path of the obelisk or the rotations of the temporary wind- architecture as the art of getting things moved about from one Books on Architecture, trans. by Morris Hicky Morgan (New York: Dover
clear that they are provisional in time. A transience conditions lasses. Like a political speech or a piece of music, this transient place to another, at a rather slow speed, with the intention that Publications, 1960). For a description of Vitruvius’ use of decorum see
architecture-as-artefact that effects every single “permanent” “work” would have created powerful responses; the agency that they will stay for a while and create value. An art of placing, or John Onians, Bearers of Meaning: The Classical Orders in Antiquity, the
structure represented in Fontana’s picture.36 Any hierarchical controlled it could certainly be judged through this effect. displacing material. An important enquiry within such a defi- Middle Ages and the Renaissance (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
order assumed between the significance of determining place- In looking at architecture we are still conditioned to a great nition is to understand which elements are critical in creating 1988), 36–39. On the subsequent history of this term, see Vaughan Hart
ment in permanent structures and organizing the placing of extent by representational systems that facilitate the judge- such actions within a framework that also includes an idea of and Peter Hicks, Paper Palaces: The Rise of the Renaissance Treatise (New
their “transient” construction is challenged in this drawing. ment of architectural agency via the description of projected ethical responsibility. Haven: Yale University Press, 1998).
The permanent condition it alludes to concerns not only the artefacts. At their most extreme, Fontana’s illustrations appear 11 Vitruvius considers, first, the behaviour of materials in their place, i.e.,
absolute nature of the context of forces that produces change to develop a system of representation that directly confronts the problem of knowing that materials will do appropriate things once
in buildings—that moves materials and re-places objects—but this tradition, as radical as any drawing from Cedric Price or they are included in the new composition; second, the characteristics that
the also the constant translation, removal, and transience of Superstudio. It might be suggested that the transient events guarantee a fit between use and organistation; and third, the appropriate-
what we usually think of as solid built works that these forces Fontana’s text describes hold a secondary status—that they ness of appearance, such that the building signals the correct fit between
act upon. cannot be viewed as part of the syntax that makes the built envi- its occupants and their social or racial or hierarchical status. All these
ronment meaningful, or that is central in judging the designers aspects of the treatise are dedicated to guaranteeing the stasis of the built

54 NORDIC JOURNAL OF ARCHITECTURE NO. 3. VOL. 2. 2012 55


Things that Move Tim Anstey

composition (Books 1 to 7). Books 8 to 10 consider, in order, the problems imperative of what must be said) and a cornucopia of explosive, sensible processes—to move weights, to organize men—can be as crucial as any from Fontana’s own drawings, see Fontana, Della trasportatione dell’
that condition the actual movement of materials to a new site of occupa- content, that gave speeches their emotive quality but which had to be kept other facility in gaining an architect praise or vilification. Rather, it seems obelisco Vaticano, Rome 1590, CD-ROM, “Introduction,” 10.
tion, and deal, in principle, with “machines.” On the compositional struc- in check, located, by the frame.The contrast between these registers, as proper to say that sixteenth-century architects sampled, and very spe- 35 There is a very specific change in terms of representation between
ture of Vitruvius see, among others, Ingrid Roland, “Vitruvius in Print and well as much of the structure and tradition that the humanists attempted cifically, from Vitruvius’ text exactly those aspects that could be of use in Fontana’s preparatory drawing for this plate and the final engraving,
in Vernacular Translation: Fra Giocondo, Bramante, Raphael and Cesare to recover from antique oratory is evident in Cicero, On the Ideal Orator guaranteeing a new system for valuing their activities. In that system, two which suggests that this omission was very carefully considered. In Fon-
Cesariano,” in Paper Palaces: the Rise of the Renaissance Architectural (De oratore), trans. James M. May and Jakob Wisse (Oxford: Oxford Uni- components were central—the development of graphic systems of repre- tana’s drawing the lines indicating ropes are carried into the representa-
Treatise, ed. Vaughan Hart and Peter Hicks (New Haven: Yale University versity Press, 2001). sentation that could communicate projected buildings without building tion of the castello; in the engraving these lines are omitted.
Press, 1998), 105–121. For a recent and acute analysis, see Bernard Cache, 16 De re aedificatoria’s distinction between lineaments and structure them, and the emphasis that the central and staple virtue of the architect 36 Directly above the castello at the centre of the plan, and heavily
“Vitruvius Machinator Terminator,” in Projectiles (London: Architectural also resonates strongly with the mnemonic classification of compositions is the ability to make such projections. hatched, stand the walls of the circular fourth-century sacristy, gashed
Association, 2011), 119–139. as being made up of ordered loci and effective imagines which fill these 28 Domenico Fontana, Della trasportatione dell’ obelisco Vaticano, e della top and bottom by the invisible and partial path of the obelisk as it is
12 For recent studies of the intellectual background to Alberti’s text on places. On the wider implications of mnemonic theory for Alberti’s writ- fabriche di Sisto V is published in facsimile with an introduction by Paolo lowered to horizontal. Away to the bottom left of the plan, walls and tow-
architecture, see Caroline Van Eck, Classical Rhetoric and the Visual Arts ing, see Tim Anstey, “The Dangers of Decorum,” in Architecture Research Portoghesi in Domenico Fontana, Della trasportatione dell’ obelisco Vati- ers of houses close the space at the bottom of the paper, but others have
in Early Modern Europe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007); Quarterly, vol. 10, no. 2 (2006), 131–139. cano 1590, ed. Adriano Carugo (Milan: Edizione Polifilo, 1978) and is avail- been demolished, Fontana explains in the legend, to make space for the
Alina A.Payne, The Architectural Treatise in the Italian Renaissance: 17 “Who is it who sends shivers down your spine? At whom do people able in facsimile with an English translation and introduction by Ingrid D. operation. At the head of the picture (the composition is closed by a timber
Architectural Invention, Ornament and Literary Culture (Cambridge: stare in stunned amazement when he speaks?” (De oratore, trans. May Roland in the CD-ROM series of the Rare Books and Special Collections paling) fencing must be removed to allow access to the “sledge” that will
Cambridge University Press, 1999); and now Caspar Pearson, Human- and Wisse, 3.53, 238, 239). It was extremely difficult to give rules for how Division, Library of Congress, as Domenico Fontana, Della trasportatione later transport the obelisk to its destination. Finally, to the right of the
ism and the Urban World: Leon Battista Alberti and the Renaissance City this should happen, qua Cicero: “As in life so in rhetoric, nothing is more dell’ obelisco Vaticano, Rome 1590 (Oakland, CA: Octavo, 2002). drawing stands the church around which all this activity will take place,
(University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 2012). difficult than to judge what is appropriate [quod deceat]” (Cicero, Orator, 29 On the history of the Fontana’s project for moving the obelisk, see shown as two separate and disconnected things. In the upper section of
13 For a comparison of these texts, see Gadol, Leon Battista Alberti. On is a short profile that models the ideal orator on his own technique; see Brian Curran et al., Obelisk: A History (Cambridge, Mass.: Burndy Library, the plan is the new construction around the dome of S. Peters not yet built;
Descriptio urbis Romæ, see additionally M. Carpo, “Descriptio urbis Romæ: Cicero, Brutus. Orator, trans. G. L. Hendrickson and H. M. Hubbell, Loeb 2009), 103–140; Giovanni Cipriani, Gli Obelischi Egizi, Politica e Cultura in the lower section, the wall of the Constantinian basilica, in the process
Ekfrasis geografica e cultura visuale all’ alba della rivoluzione tipografica,” Classical Library (London: William Heinemann Ltd, 1939), 70); and “It is, nella Roma Barocca (Florence: Leo S. Oschki, 1993); Marcello Pagiolo, and of demolition.
Albertiana 1 (1998), 121–143. For translations of Alberti’s mathemati- of course, obvious that no single style is fitting for every case or every audi- Maria Luisa Madonna, eds, Sisto V, vol. I, Roma e il Lazio (Rome: Istituto 37 Della trasportatione, 5v, 6r–8v (contents of papal bull empowering
cal works, including De componendis cifris see Kim Williams, Stephen ence or every person involved or every occasion . . . So it seems that there Oligrafico e Zecca Dello Stato, 1992); and Erik Iversen, Obelisks in Exile, Fontana to expedite process and collect materials), 9r–10r (calculation
R. Wassell, Lionel March, eds. The Mathematical works of Leon Battista is really no rule I could give you at this point” (De oratore, trans. May and vol. 1, The Obelisks of Rome (Copenhagen: Gad, 1968). of weights), 10r (cables and windlasses), 10v–13r (scaffold and timbers),
Alberti (Basel: Birkhauser, 2010). De pictura and De statua were trans- Wisse, 3.210, 290). One side of this difficulty concerns the composition 30 Curran et al., Obelisk, 134. 13v– (process of movement).
lated with an introduction in The Latin Texts of De pictura and De statua, experienced, on which the orator is judged; one side concerns the skill of 31 The conversion of weights and distances from Roman into metric 38 In this respect Fontana may be indebted to a development in later
trans. and ed. C. Grayson, London, 1972. Joan Gadol’s analysis of Alberti’s the oratory which lies precisely in this action of placing. measures are my own. The height and weight of the obelisk were calcu- interpretations of Vitruvius that celebrated the architect’s role as a
thinking successfully demonstrated the structural similarities that exist 18 This celebration of the magical attributes of an architect in the pro- lated by and are recorded in the text, Della trasportatione, 9r-10v. On the governor of process, which was to inform later commentaries on the De
between De componendis cifris, De pictura, De statua and Descriptio cess of placing is evident in Alberti’s dedication of the Italian version of history of the process, Curran, Obelisk, 103–140. architectura. This strand started early in northern texts based on Vitru-
urbis Romæ. This structure also describes the work of the sculptor, who, On Painting to Fillipo Brunellsechi. Della Pittura [1435] in Leon Battista 32 It was difficult in terms of what actually had to be done. The strong- vius, for example, John Shute, First and Chief Grovndes of Architecture.
in Alberti’s terms, positions sensible substances—timber, stone, clay— Alberti. Opere volgari, ed. Cecil Grayson, vol. 3 (Bari: G. Laterza, 1973), est motive power unit at the time was a horse or ox, capable of exerting (London: Thomas Marsh, 1563), emphasizes the scientific aspects of
using the measurements of porre di termini, regulated by the ideals of 5–107. For an analysis of Alberti’s formulation of the potential of archi- a continuous force of around 125 lbs (50 kg) in an unsteady horizontal the architect’s role, and this understanding was strong in the Vitruvian
misura. Likewise, Descriptio urbis Romæ analysed the city of Rome by tects, and of buildings, to affect their viewers, and a comparison of this direction; the strongest cable able to transmit this force could take some- thought developed by John Dee and evident all the way through English
providing a table of “places,” each defined by a unique distance and orien- with the potential attributed to speeches and orators by Cicero, see Tim thing over 20,000 lbs of tension (8 tonnes, 40 times what the horse could attributions of architectural virtue to Inigo Jones and Christopher Wren.
tation from a single origin, and a list of the material objects to be found in Anstey, “Architecture and Rhetoric: Persuasion, Context, Action.” move). However, the obelisk was a single piece of stone, 114 palms high In relation to this, see John Dee, A Preface to Euclid, in John Dee, ed. Ger-
Rome which belonged in these places. As Gadol observes, the mechanisms 19 See particularly Carpo, The Alphabet and the Algorithm, and Carpo, by Fontana’s calculation (around 25 meters), weighing 963,537 35/88 lbs ald Suster (Berkeley, CA: North Atlantic Books, 2003). See also Frances
Alberti proposed to define placement in these texts were related. Thus the “The Emergence of the Typographical Architect,” in Paper Palaces. (Fontana calculates the weight to this precision), about 8,000 times as A. Yates, Theatre of the World (N. p.: Law Book Co of Australasia, 1969)
concentric wheels of De componendis cyfris are echoed in the calibrated 20 See Tim Anstey, “The Ambiguities of Disegno,” in The Journal of Archi- much as a horse could lift through direct traction. and Vaughan Hart, “Inigo Jones’ Site Organization at St. Paul’s Cathe-
disc and measuring plumb line of De statua and the orrizonte of Descriptio tecture, vol. 10, no. 3 (2005), 295–306. 33 Intriguingly, Fontana has never been treated particularly kindly by dral: ‘Pondrous Masses Beheld Hangin in the Air,’” Journal of the Society
urbis Romæ. Alberti’s aim in proposing such mechanisms relates to the 21 For a thorough treatment of the development of the architectural trea- those texts that develop a history of architecture through the descriptions of Architectural Historians, vol. 53, no. 4 (December 1994), 414–427.
tradition of mnemonics both overtly and via the informational structure tise, see Payne, The Architectural Treatise. of architects and works. His removal of the obelisk was celebrated in Gio-
of oratory, of which mnemonics formed a part, and in which Alberti was 22 This argument is rehearsed also by Carpo, The Alphabet and the Algo- vanni Baglione’s undiscriminating Le Vite de Pittori, Scultori, Architetti
schooled. As Mario Carpo has observed, both De statua and Descriptio rithm. e Intagliatori [Naples, 1642], and he was the only architect included in
urbis Romæ provide a means to encode and re-member—in the one case 23 On the development of Vitruvianism and its relationship to decorum, Giovan Pietro Bellori’s Vite [Rome, 1671], on account of the same action.
statues, in the other images of cities—over periods of time. see Paper Palaces. Yet Bellori’s selection itself was rapidly criticized as outdated on stylis-
14 The classic examination of the importance of oratory for fifteenth- 24 Vaughan Hart, “Serlio and the Representation of Architecture,” in tic grounds (Bellori supported traditionalists like Maderno against, say,
century analysis of the visual remains Michael Baxandall’s Giotto and the Paper Palaces. Borromini). For a review of the place of such selection in seventeenth-
Orators: Humanist Observers of Painting in Italy and the Discovery of Pic- 25 See Vaughan Hart and Peter Hicks, “On Sebastiano Serio: Decorum century art history, see Giovan Pietro Bellori, The Lives of the Modern
torial Composition, 1350–1450 [1971] (Oxford: Oxford University Press, and the Art of Architectural Invention” and Carpo, “The Making of the Painters, Sculptors and Architects, trans. and ed. Alice Sedgwick Wohl et
1991). In relation to architecture, see Carol William Westfall, In this Most Typographical Architect,” both in Paper Palaces. al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005). In later history Fon-
Perfect Paradise: Alberti, Nicholas V, and the Invention of Conscious Urban 26 Andrea Palladio, I Quattro Libri di Architettura (Venice: Domenico de’ tana’s projects for new compositions (which include the Lateran palace
Planning in Rome, 1447–55 (University Park: Pennsylvania State Univer- Franceschi,1570), 1: I–VI. and additions to the Quirinale palace) were criticized for their monotony
sity Press, 1974) and Christine Smith, Architecture in the Culture of Early 27 Jacopo Barozzi da Vignola, Regola delli cinque ordini d’architettura and lack of imagination. This image stuck, particularly among the writers
Humanism: Ethics, Aesthetics and Eloquence (Oxford: Oxford University (Rome: No publ., 1562. Although this concern with the decorum (or licen- who forged architectural history as a discipline in the twentieth century.
Press, 1992). tiousness) of projected architectural compositions, which is the subject of For Sigfried Giedion, Fontana belonged to “that artistically mediocre gen-
15 Oratory included the codification of mnemonics, the technique by the paper architecture of the sixteenth century, is often attributed to the eration of architects between Michelangelo and the rise of the Roman
which orators were able to store and recall their compositions. And increasing significance of Vitruvius, such a supposition cannot provide Baroque. His taste was as flavourless as that of his client.” Sigfried Gie-
beyond mnemonics the organisational structures of oratory were con- a complete explanation. This is because Vitruvius, to a far greater extent dion, Space, Time and Architecture (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
ditioned by the notion of an architecture of places, which provided than Alberti, spells out how machination can be seen as a central part Press, 1941), 89.
organization, decorum, orientation (the “points” addressed; the moral of the architect’s activity, and how the ability to organize materials and 34 The plates were made by the engraver Natale Beneficio da Sebenico

56 NORDIC JOURNAL OF ARCHITECTURE NO. 3. VOL. 2. 2012 57

You might also like