Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

American Political Science Review Vol. 109, No.

1 February 2015
doi:10.1017/S0003055414000550 
c American Political Science Association 2015

How to Rule the World: An Introduction to Xenophon’s The Education


of Cyrus
ROBERT C. BARTLETT Boston College

A
s a contribution to the study of empire and imperial ambition, the present study considers
the greatest analysis—Xenophon’s The Education of Cyrus—of one of the greatest empires of
antiquity—the Persian. Xenophon’s lively and engaging account permits us to watch Cyrus as
he builds a transnational empire, at once vast and stable. Yet Xenophon is ultimately highly critical of
Cyrus, because he lacks the self-knowledge requisite to happiness, and of the empire, whose stability
is purchased at the price of freedom. Cyrus finally appears as a kind of divinity who strives to supply
the reward for moral excellence that the gods evidently do not. Xenophon implies that any truly global
empire would have to present itself as a universal providential power capable of bestowing on human
beings a blessed happiness that as such transcends our very mortality.

rom the fact that the globe is no longer clearly promises to all who truly deserve it a blessed happiness

F divided among competing empires, it would be


reckless to assume that the longings or hopes that
once drove the great world empires have either van-
that as such transcends death itself. It remains to be
seen whether a new form of empire may emerge in
modern times that somehow speaks powerfully to our
ished from the human soul or been safely diverted into most prominent moral concerns, that promises to re-
other channels—those supplied, for example, by inter- ward (or punish) all according to merit, and that holds
national trade and commerce. As for this latter possi- out the prospect of conquering, in addition to all other
bility, scholars of globalization rightly remind us that mundane evils, our very mortality.
domination need not be overtly political but may take
other forms, among them the spread of an apparently
philanthropic technology (e.g., Hawkin 2004). This sug- ∗∗∗
gests already the persistence in our time of great am- The Education of Cyrus is a wonderful book.2 Among
bition. As for political ambition proper, prudence de- its many wonders are the immediacy and power with
mands that we try to understand it. It is with a view to which it still speaks especially to those young people
meeting this demand eventually that the present study whose souls smolder or burn with grand ambition. In
takes up the greatest analysis—Xenophon’s Education it we witness the astounding rise of Cyrus of Persia,
of Cyrus—of one of the greatest empires of antiquity— from a boyhood that, though it promises much, cannot
the Persian. That Cyrus the Great deserves considera- quite foretell the greatness of the man: starting out
tion can be established by recourse to authorities who with a small army of Persians, Cyrus in short order
otherwise agree about little else: Niccolo Machiavelli crushes the aggressive expansion of the Assyrian Em-
pays Cyrus the high compliment of including him in pire, establishes himself as King of the new empire, and
his list of four “armed prophets,” in the company of then reigns unchallenged over it in all its prosperity and
Moses himself; and the Hebrew Bible goes so far as peace. He can accomplish these things not least because
to call Cyrus the “anointed” one who, as liberator of he is always attentive to what he owes to gods and to
the Israelites from captivity in Babylon, carried out the human beings, in compliance with the stern demands
Lord’s task—“though you do not know me.”1 of piety and justice. The Education of Cyrus also puts
To be sure, Xenophon has reasons of his own to before us the impressive sight of what martial courage
consider Cyrus, and this essay cannot do more than can accomplish when it is under the yoke of moderation
begin to elucidate them. Xenophon’s account of the or self-restraint. And it holds out to readers, however
imperial project of Cyrus suggests this much: political dismal their present circumstances, the possibility of a
domination on a grand scale requires an appeal to the community that fully meets the highest standards for
moral seriousness of human beings that does not forget political life; it holds out even the possibility of a world
the profound hopes attending it, among them that the in which nobility and goodness are inseparable in the
world be such as to foster and reward moral excel- sense that moral excellence there always receives its
lence and, when necessary, to punish depravity; and due. These are among the accomplishments of Cyrus
this in turn calls for a universal providential power that the Great, and they account for no small part of the
allure of Xenophon’s book.
Robert C. Bartlett is Behrakis Professor of Hellenic Political Studies,
Boston College (robert.bartlett@bc.edu).
The author wishes to dedicate this study to Robert K. Faulkner, 2 Translations are my own, although I have benefited from Wayne
colleague and mentor, on the happy occasion of his eightieth Ambler’s fine edition of The Education of Cyrus (Xenophon 2001). I
birthday. have used the Teubner edition of the Greek text originally prepared
1 Machiavelli, The Prince, Ch. 6 ( = Machiavelli 1998, 21–25); Isaiah by W. Gemoll and revised by J. Peters: Xenophon 1968. Citations are
44:28 and 45:1–13. On Machiavelli’s complex relation to Xenophon, by book, chapter, section, and, where appropriate, line number, as
consider Nadon 2001, 13–25, Rasmussen 2009, and Newell 2013, 228– these appear in the edition cited. All references in the body of the
70. text are to works by Xenophon, unless indicated otherwise.

143
How to Rule the World February 2015

It is however more difficult than it might first seem to The terms in which Xenophon sets forth what is evi-
identify the sort of book the Education of Cyrus is, and dently the problem of politics suggest that it is solvable
Xenophon himself does not state the genre to which only if human rulers can somehow become indisputably
it belongs (compare, e.g., Xenophon 1954 5:58; Gera superior to those whom they rule. And he implies that
1993, 1–2). It cannot be accounted a political history this would come to pass if the rulers were to stand to the
of the kind we are accustomed to or, for that matter, ruled as do herders to their herds. This state of affairs
of the kind the author of the Hellenica proved himself in turn could arise either by making the ruled resemble
capable of writing. For while making use of such famous herd animals as closely as possible or by making the
events of the past as the fall of Babylon, Xenophon rulers transcend the merely human in the direction of
does not otherwise even pretend to historical accuracy: a divine supremacy. With these possibilities in mind,
he has his Persians swear by Greek gods, for example we ask: what constitutes the “education of Cyrus”
(consider the glaring exception that proves the rule: that permitted him to rule human beings on the basis
7.5.53), just as at one point he refers to the Assyrians of knowledge (epistamenōs: 1.1.3) and so to achieve
and their allies as “barbarians,” evidently to distinguish the kind of stability that had seemed to Xenophon
them from the Persians (3.3.26–27; consider also 7.4.9); impossible?
he invents out of whole cloth private conversations to
which no one could have been privy (e.g., 1.6.2–46;
6.4.5–11); and he makes frequent use of the expression
“as was likely” or “as was only to be expected” (hōs THE EDUCATIONS OF CYRUS
eikos), in this way noting or confessing that the “facts”
he thus records are only intelligent surmises.3 Let it After describing briefly Cyrus’s lineage and the “na-
suffice to add that Xenophon has his aged Cyrus meet ture” of his bodily form as well as soul, Xenophon
a peaceful end in bed, surrounded by family and other turns to an account of the education Cyrus received.
well-wishers; the historical record suggests that he died The most striking fact about that education is the inter-
violently in battle and in more or less his prime.4 ruption that marks it. For having spent the first twelve
The Education of Cyrus cannot be called a biog- or so years in republican Persia, Cyrus then went with
raphy either, even allowing for Xenophon’s freedom Mandane, his mother, to neighboring Media at the
from slavish adherence to the historical record. For request of Astyages, his maternal grandfather; Cyrus
Xenophon suggests at the outset that his book was ended up living in Media for some four or five years
prompted by a reflection he (“we”) once had concern- (consider 1.2.8, end; 1.3.1; 1.4.16; and 1.5.1). Astyages
ing the instability of all democracies, monarchies, oli- was the king or rather “tyrant” of the place (consider
garchies, and especially tyrannies. So fraught is the rule 1.3.18 [14]), and he wished to see for himself what the
of human beings by other human beings that the diffi- reports had suggested—that his grandson was “noble
culty of it extends even to households large or small, to and good.” To understand the education of Cyrus, then,
the subpolitical community. And this difficulty is only one must first understand the education on offer in each
heightened by the comparison Xenophon here makes country, and this in turn requires that one understand
to herd animals that never unite against their rulers but, the laws and customs (nomoi) at work there. For laws,
quite to the contrary, willingly permit them to profit and the way of life they constitute, are one’s first educa-
from them. Reflection on these facts led Xenophon to tion: “Cyrus was educated in the laws of the Persians.”
conclude that “it would be easier for a human being, According to Xenophon, the Persian laws, in their
given his nature, to rule over all the other animals than care for “the common good” (1.2.2; see also 3.3.10,
to rule over human beings” (1.1.3). This problem of the end; 4.5.33 and 46), begin further back than do the
instability of regimes is of course a political one, but it laws of most other cities. Whereas other laws permit
is theoretical too inasmuch as it takes its bearings by citizens to teach their children as they please and then
“nature”; and it is solely as a result of his reflection punish them as adults for the transgressions they all
on this problem so conceived that Xenophon first has too often commit, the laws of Persia take care to form
reason to mention Cyrus (see 1.1.3). Xenophon’s inter- citizens disinclined from the outset to break them. The
est in Cyrus, then, is rooted in a reflection on human laws shape the very souls of citizens, in other words,
nature and on the resulting character of political life. from their earliest youth onward, such that their first
Only because Cyrus presents the solution to this grave and indeed last thought is for the common good. And
problem is he deserving of Xenophon’s attention. to take one’s bearings always by the common good is to
prefer it always to one’s own, merely private good, to
say nothing of pleasure, whenever the two goods con-
3 “It has been noted by many and in detail that Xenophon’s ‘Cyrus’
flict: while it is not strictly speaking illegal for one of the
is only loosely based on the life of Cyrus the Great, that Xenophon’s
‘Persia’ resembles Sparta more than Persia, and that the geography
married youths to visit his wife and so to abandon his
of Asia is adjusted to suit dramatic or didactic necessity” (Ambler age-mates who must as a matter of duty sleep outside
2001, 3 n.1). in the “free square,” the nomos nonetheless has it that
4 Consider Herodotus (1927) 1.214—if Herodotus can be considered
it is not “noble” for him to do so often (1.2.4, end). The
a part of the historical record—and Ctesias Persica 11.7 ( = Stronk laws of Persia teach that goodness consists in nobility,
2010, 317). For helpful comparisons of the presentations of Cyrus
in Xenophon and Herodotus, see Due 1989, 117–35 and Faulkner
in one’s noble dedication to the common good and its
2007, 130–1. For the historical sources more generally, see Sancisi- demands, a dedication that is choiceworthy for its own
Weerdenburg 2010, 439–53. sake and that may well come at some cost to oneself.

144
American Political Science Review Vol. 109, No. 1

The principal traits of soul inculcated by the Per- one’s own good, on the one hand, and to the attainment
sian laws are moderation, obedience, and continence of one’s own truest good or advantage, on the other,
or self-restraint (enkrateia) in matters of food and drink which may well include one’s own pleasure (consider
(1.2.8). Citizens are thus habituated to shun the guid- 1.3.3 [7–8]; compare 1.3.4). In accord with this, the first
ance supplied by the individual or private body (and political speech Cyrus delivers, now as a mature (“com-
indeed soul: 1.3.18 [11–12]) in favor of that supplied plete”) man in Persia, raises explicitly a question that
by the judgment of the rulers. This education takes the would have previously seemed inappropriate to the
form of imitation of the actions of others and so relies Persian Peers—the upper class that rules in Persia and
somewhat more on sight than hearing, to say nothing that is distinguished by its enthusiastically carrying out
of conversation (1.2.8 [18, 21, 24]; compare 1.6; 3.1.14– “what the city lawfully holds [nomidzei] to be noble”
30; 7.2.15–29). As for piety, it would be wrong to sup- (1.5.7). For Cyrus notes in this speech that, while their
pose that it is not among the virtues prized (compare ancestors were not inferior to them in spending all their
Sandridge 2012, 70; Nadon 2001, 37), but it appears time too practicing the things that are held to be the
there under the heading of gratitude. That is, it is illegal deeds of virtue, Cyrus for his part cannot yet see “what
among the Persians to be ungrateful, “for they suppose good they acquired by being such.” What benefit or
that the ungrateful especially would be neglectful both advantage did our ancestors themselves receive, each
as regards gods and as regards parents and fatherland of them, from their dutiful attention to virtue or their
and friends” (1.2.7). But at the center of the Persian noble service to the common good? If the Persians of
education is the training in justice that the boys receive old were taught to ask only what they can do for Per-
at a special school or schools, attendance at which is sia, Cyrus now introduces, as a necessary and indeed
the prerequisite to holding political office in later life respectable consideration, also what Persia can do for
(1.2.15); as Xenophon notes, the Persian boys learn jus- them; he holds out the prospect to them of the enjoy-
tice at school the way Greek boys learn letters (1.2.6). ment of “much wealth, much happiness, and great hon-
(Do the Persian boys learn letters?) When Mandane ors, both for them themselves and for the city” (1.5.9,
subsequently worries that Cyrus will fail to (continue end). Not without reason, this speech has been singled
to) learn justice if he extends his initial stay in Media, out for its “subversive and revolutionary character”
we discover more of the character of that education. (Nadon 2001, 55) and even as an act of “corruption”
Cyrus tells his mother that he already knows “alto- (Bruell 1987, 99 and 102; Strauss 2013, 181–2; compare
gether precisely” what justice is. For one day he was Tatum 1989, 83–4).
asked to judge a dispute between two boys: a large boy It would be wrong, then, to underestimate the change
with a small tunic had taken the large tunic of a small that Cyrus thus seeks to effect. Still, the step Cyrus
boy and given his own in exchange for it. Thus both here takes, while jarring, does receive some authoriza-
boys now had suitably fitting tunics, large and small. tion from the very standards of old Persia. For old
Cyrus judged, on just this ground, that all was as it Persia promised its citizens that, in submitting to the
should be. His teacher, however, beat him for his ruling, comprehensive education that the law conveys, they
because the teacher had asked Cyrus to judge, not the would become not only noble but also good:
fitting or suitable, but the just, and justice demands that they would become kaloikagathoi or “gentlemen.”5
each boy have the property that is his by law. Persian They would embody that excellence that is the pos-
justice, then, is exhausted by the dictates of the law. session of what is good, guided or limited and elevated
The Persian “education” to justice or the law includes by what is noble. To put the point more sharply: did old
beatings; and by them Cyrus was prevented from pur- Persia say that it was utterly indifferent to the welfare,
suing his initial supposition that justice, whatever it is, to the “happiness” (1.5.9), of its citizens? Did old Persia
must be good for those who act justly or are treated mean to say that the citizens’ dedication to virtue would
justly (1.3.16–18). render them—miserable? This is impossible, precisely
What then is the contribution of Media to the edu- if “the common good” to which one is devoted is both
cation of Cyrus? Whereas in Persia a certain equality genuinely good and truly common. Accordingly, we
is the law, in Media Astyages the tyrant “has made learn that the elders govern the boys so as to make
himself master of everything” and “supposes that he them “supremely good” or “best” (beltistoi), just as
ought to have more than all [others]” (1.3.18). In Per- the mature men govern the youths so as to make them
sia Cyrus learned to sacrifice his own good so as to “supremely good” or “best” (1.2.5; consider also 1.2.15,
be noble, and in Astyages’ Media he saw first-hand end). In keeping with this, the practice of the austere
the great delights of the pursuit of one’s own good, virtues of old Persia was defended partly in terms of
including one’s own pleasure. As Cyrus puts it play- the pleasure of the virtuous themselves, the pleasures
fully to his mother, Astyages has “educated” everyone of food and drink included (see 1.2.11). Cyrus could
there to have less than he himself has, and so Cyrus not have secured the ready agreement of the Persian
too will learn that lesson (1.3.18, end)—but he surely Peers to transform the Persian commoners into close-
sees things more from the point of the “educator” than range fighters—a privilege previously reserved for the
from that of the “educated.” Persia stands to Media, Peers alone—if the Peers’ attachment to virtue for its
one may say provisionally, as the noble stands to the
good. And we cannot understand Cyrus without seeing 5 For the phrase, see again 1.3.1 [7]; also 1.4.27; 1.5.11; 1.6.7; 2.1.15;
that he is deeply attracted to both—to virtue or nobility 2.2.23; 2.3.5; 3.1.38; 3.3.6; 4.3.23; 5.1.6; 5.1.14; 5.3.29; 5.5.19; 7.1.49;
(consider 1.3.3), which may well demand the sacrifice of 7.2.12; 7.2.17; 7.5.84; and 7.5.86.

145
How to Rule the World February 2015

own sake were not “vulnerable to temptation” (Bruell That Cyrus seeks to combine a clear-eyed calculation
1987, 97 and 99). of his advantage with the dedication to noble virtue
If in this way Cyrus does receive from old Persia a sort means that, as he insists to his men, it is precisely
of permission to raise the question of the good of the virtue that is the greatest good for the virtuous them-
virtuous themselves, it is certainly true that he makes selves. Such was already the import of his “corruption”
the greatest possible use of it: he destroys the idea that speech. It is Cyrus’s hope that “all will say in the future
virtue must be practiced for its own sake alone. Those that nothing is more profitable than virtue” (7.1.18);
who fail to see this calculation miss something impor- it is possible in principle for soldiers in war to possess
tant about the man. Of the many examples one might simultaneously “safety, justice, and happiness” (6.2.55;
cite, this is perhaps the most important: When the Per- consider also 3.3.8). When Cyrus exhorts his soldiers to
sian allies capture Panthea, “the most beautiful woman aid Gadatas, a man who has taken the dangerous step of
in Asia,” Cyrus, far from violating her as she assumes he revolting from the Assyrian in favor of Cyrus, he states
will, refuses even to see her. But what she understand- that it is “noble” to aid their benefactor, “just” to pay
ably regards as the most extraordinary virtue—piety, back the favors done them—and “advantageous for
moderation, and pity above all (6.1.47)—is better ex- ourselves” to do so: far from there being some tension
plained by his calculation that she could prove valuable between the demands of what is just, what is noble,
to them one day, as indeed she does. Her gratitude, and what is advantageous, they go together to form a
and especially that of her powerful husband, is more seamless whole (5.3.31). As Cyrus explains to Croesus
useful to this “cold king” (8.4.22–23) than any fleeting of Lydia, he is “happiest” who is “able to acquire the
pleasure she might afford him could ever be (Faulkner most while keeping to what is just and to use the most
2007, 155). As a general rule, Cyrus eagerly forgoes a while keeping to what is noble” (8.2.23): justice must
little gain now—what to the world appears to be the strictly guide or limit acquisition, and nobility must
most remarkable moderation or self-restraint—for the strictly guide or limit its use. But it is precisely in being
sake of the greatest possible gain later (see especially so “limited” that one reaps the greatest possible reward
4.2.43–44). “I too have an insatiable greed [aplēstos] or profit for oneself and one’s friends.
for money, as do the others,” but Cyrus invests that As others have suggested, the title of Xenophon’s
money in gaining such “friendship” as permits him to book may point, not to the excellence of the educa-
“harvest safety and glory” (8.2.20 and 22). tion Cyrus received, but to its limits.6 We recall that,
Yet this calculation of advantage does not exhaust in his youth, Cyrus had claimed to know justice alto-
the concerns of the man or quite do justice to the phe- gether precisely: justice is the law. Cyrus at that point
nomena. Just as those who fail to see Cyrus’s calculating would have been as untroubled by Socrates’s question
nature misunderstand him, so too do those who see in “what is just?” (Memorabilia 1.1.16) as he was by Man-
all his actions nothing but such calculation: “Cyrus’s dane’s observation that, since laws differ from place to
outlook cannot be reduced simply to the instrumen- place, so too must justice: this suggests that there is
tal” (Faulkner 2007, 152). Cyrus is not an accountant, nothing just by nature or that justice is entirely con-
let alone a gangster. At one point the common coun- ventional. And, as Mandane adds, if Cyrus practices
cil of Persia decides to send out an armed expedition Median justice in Persia, he will be beaten to death.
to aid Cyaxares, now the ruler of Media, in a strictly Perhaps because he was beaten for having attempted
defensive operation meant to push back the expansion to separate justice from the law, in the name of the
of the Assyrian Empire that threatens Persia too; and fitting or the good, Cyrus does not then take the first
Cyrus explains and defends this mission to his fellow step in wondering about justice, about what our hopes
Peers in these terms: “Let us set forth boldly, since for it really are and what it must be to meet them.
the appearance of unjustly aiming at what belongs to It is certainly true that, upon his return from Media,
others is far from impeding us, for now our enemies are Cyrus contends that the deeds of virtue, those of justice
coming, they who have begun the unjust deeds, whereas included, must be good for the virtuous themselves,
our friends are summoning us as auxiliaries. What is and to this extent he restores the connection between
more just than defending ourselves or more noble than justice and the good. But that Cyrus has not thought
aiding friends?” (1.5.13). In this way Cyrus indicates— sufficiently about justice in its relation to the good is
in the course of his very “corruption” speech—that suggested by the dramatic highpoint of his conversation
he takes seriously and wishes his men to take seriously with his father (1.6). For there Cambyses contends that
the knowledge that their deeds are both just and noble. precisely justice demands getting the advantage over
And once Cyrus and his soldiers have not only repulsed the enemy in everything, and it is impossible to say in
the Assyrian forces but destroyed the Empire, Cyrus advance what this laudable goal may require: plotting,
insists that the gods will be with them (still), “for we dissembling, trickiness, cheating, stealing, rapacity, and
are not unjust, having plotted against others, but rather so on (1.6.27). Swearing for the only time “by Her-
being plotted against, we sought vengeance” (7.5.77). acles,” Cyrus is astonished by this. For he had been
Moreover, once Cyrus has installed himself as King,
he insists that his courtiers devote themselves to the
6 Bruell 1987, 102; Nadon 2001, 179; Strauss 1939, 526; com-
practice of “virtue” and that the children they raise
pare Tatum 1989, 90–91 and Bizos 1971, v. See also the helpful
there be dedicated to “spending their day in noble and remarks of Sandridge on the title and its possible mean-
good practices, not even seeing or hearing anything ing or meanings: http://www.cyropaedia.org/book-1/chapter-1–1-the-
shameful” (7.5.70 and context; 7.5.86). problem-of-ruling-men-and-the-solution-of-cyrus/.

146
American Political Science Review Vol. 109, No. 1

taught that deception, for example, is always unjust; he just before the first great clash with the Assyrian forces.
learns now that it may well be just, which means that it In response to Chrysantas’ concern that Cyrus is giving
is neither simply the one nor the other. This change in no exhortation to his men as the leader of the Assyrians
the status of deception is due, not to a change in law, but has just given to his, Cyrus assures him that no single
to the complex demands of serving the common good; speech or argument (logos), uttered on a single day, is
deception can be judged only by its contribution to sufficient to improve men’s souls, not even if it should
the end it properly serves, helping friends and harming be “nobly spoken” (3.3.55, end). No such logos, that is,
enemies. Cambyses tells Cyrus that this more adequate could fill the men with the requisite respect or sense
education to justice had been attempted in Persia but of awe (aidōs) or keep them from ignoble acts, just as
had had to be abandoned. For it proved to be only it could not urge them to take upon themselves every
a small step, at least for those with “good natures” toil and every risk “for the sake of praise” (3.3.51). No
(1.6.32), from the thought that lying or cheating in the logos, moreover, could prompt the soldiers to “grasp
name of the common good is acceptable, to the thought firmly, by means of the judgments [they form], that it
that lying or cheating for my own good is acceptable is more choiceworthy to die while fighting than to save
too; it is possible to glean from the dedication to the themselves by fleeing” (3.3.51). This last formulation is
common good an approval of the concern for one’s especially striking, since Cyrus has never uttered and
own good, especially if the former can be shown to be will never utter such a thought, in such blunt terms, to
incapable of fulfilling its promise to supply the latter. his men—that is, to prefer “death” (apothnēiskein) to
And so Persia reverted to the simple teaching—that flight and to do so only for the good that is “praise”
justice is the law and the law always prohibits deception (compare the immediately preceding remarks of the
and the rest—a teaching whose principal merit is the Assyrian leader: 3.3.45 [apothnēiskousi]).7 Is this the
fostering of “gentler” or “tamer” citizens (1.6.33, end). whole of the “profit” or “advantage,” including the
Cambyses’ teaching is not an amoral one, or still pleasure, that actions in accord with the peak of nobility
less an immoral one, since its central concern is jus- procure for one?
tice understood as the common good. It does however What is more, in order for these judgments to be
demonstrate the inadequacy of any attempt to bind by “inscribed” in human beings and remain fixed in them,
unalterable rules what the common good may require, there must be, first, such “laws” as will secure for those
especially in war. Cyrus thus leaves Persia with much who are good a life characterized here and now by both
less respect for the law and a greater appreciation for honor and freedom and, for the bad, a lifetime that is
the “flexibility” that precisely justice, in its promise to miserable, painful, and indeed unlivable. But even laws
give to each the fitting or good, demands. Accordingly, are not enough to secure this end. The soldiers, Cyrus
Cyrus is all but silent about the law as he builds his continues, must also have “teachers and rulers” over
empire (3.3.52; 4.3.22) and, at its peak, presents himself them who will “correctly show and teach and habituate
as a “seeing law” above any written law (8.1.22; also them” so to act, until it is “inbred in them” (engenētai
7.5.73 [“eternal law”]; 8.2.27). That is, he by himself autois) “to believe” or “hold” (nomidzein) that the
does or seeks to do what the law wishes to do but, given best and renowned “really are happiest” (3.3.53). This
its generality and inflexibility, cannot: he sees that all, conviction, then, of the supreme happiness of the best
friend or enemy, receive their due. so defined, requires not only teachers but also “rulers,”
not just an education but also “habituation”: the con-
viction concerning the supreme happiness of those who
prefer death to flight is not according to Cyrus a logos
THE PROBLEM OF VIRTUE
that as such can be known but must be largely, and
If we accept Cyrus’s principal contention to his subordi- merely, believed; one must come to feel it in one’s bones
nates that nobility and profit go hand in hand, we must rather than understand it.
conclude that the world in general and political life in That Cyrus never says as much to his troops is hardly
particular are altogether suited to human life, to life at surprising. His general approach is indicated by the fol-
its best or finest. For there is then no tension, to repeat, lowing example. After their victory in the first battle,
between the demands of nobility or virtue—“Persia”— Cyrus tells his troops this: you “may always judge for
and our own good—“Media.” It hardly needs to be said yourselves whether virtue saves lives more than does
that this view of things is deeply attractive (e.g., Danzig flight, whether those who are willing to fight escape
2012); much of modern political philosophy relies for more easily than do those who are not willing, and
its efficacy on the attractions of “self-interest rightly what sort of pleasure victory supplies” (4.1.5). It is not
understood” or on the allure of the perfect coinci- death to life, then, that the soldiers must understand
dence of duty and rights. Only a certain Aglaı̈tadas, themselves to be choosing—even if they are making
who represents old Persia at its most austere, voices that choice in fact—so much as the choice for victory
an objection to Cyrus’s new order; and even he is to and, with it, safety, ease, and pleasure. Cyrus goes so
some extent “corrupted” by it, to the amusement of his far, in his conversation with Chrysantas, as to call this
colleagues (see 2.2.11–16). But for this very reason it
is surprising that Cyrus himself proves to have reser- 7 Cyrus uses the verb “to die,” as distinguished from “meeting one’s
vations concerning its truth. Of particular interest is a end” or “passing away,” only in speaking of others, and especially of
private conversation Cyrus has with his closest confi- the enemy (5.2.9; 5.2.32; 6.1.12), or, as here, in private conversation:
dant, the Persian Peer Chrysantas, which takes place see also 7.1.19 (to Hystaspas: “none of us will die”).

147
How to Rule the World February 2015

capacity to stick to the conviction indicated “the great- greater hope of attaining what he needs or asks for
est virtue” (3.3.54, end; consider also Plato 1902, Re- (1.6.3–4). The pleasure afforded by the anticipation of
public 429b8–d1). But such a virtue, whatever its other attaining something good: this must be an integral part
merits, surely cannot always “save lives,” at least not of Cyrus’s piety.
the lives of the virtuous themselves. Yet precisely the teaching of Cambyses, in what is the
Cyrus is aware, then, that there may well be a discrep- longest and most complex conversation in the book
ancy between noble dedication and deserved reward. (1.6), suggests that the gods remain mysterious in a
One might suppose that this thought could prompt matter of great importance to human beings. For both
Cyrus to return to the austere virtues of old Persia, the first and the last topic Cambyses takes up is the
whose lingering effects he still relies on: let what is gods, and to begin with he suggests only that the dif-
noble regain its as it were natural ascendancy above ficulty Cyrus faces is the manipulation to which the
the good, or let sacrifice for the common good appear interpretation of the divine signs is subject, it being a
in its splendor as what it is. But such a return seems matter of human art. This implies that there is a diffi-
impossible. For, as we have suggested, the very laws of culty, not with the signs themselves or with those who
Persia give at least tacit approval of Cyrus’s concern send them, but with the all-too-human interpreters of
for the good because they too do not so clearly or them, the prophets who may wish to deceive Cyrus
consistently separate the noble from the good. It is to for their own ends: prophetic signs may be made to
Cyrus’s credit that he discerns within the dedication to serve altogether political purposes. And this problem
virtue its promise of happiness; Xenophon’s Socrates had already been solved, at the time of the conversa-
too seems to hold to the identity of the noble and tion, because Cambyses had taken care to teach Cyrus
the good or to the advantageous character of what the art of prophecy (mantikē: 1.6.2, end).8 The graver
is noble (e.g., Memorabilia 3.8.5–6; Symposium 5.4– difficulty appears only when Cambyses returns to the
7). Beyond that, the “common good” by which the subject of the gods, at the end of the conversation and
Persian laws take their bearings proves to be deeply hence just before Cyrus crosses into Median territory
flawed, as Xenophon makes plain and Cyrus himself (1.6.44–46). Cambyses now broaches what he himself
indicates. Though by law a democracy whose political calls “the greatest” matters (1.6.44). All human action
offices are open to all citizens alike, Persia is in fact a is based on nothing more than guesswork, since human
narrow oligarchy of the rich for the benefit of the rich; beings “do not know from which [actions] the good
if the makeup of the army is any indication, the many things will be theirs.” And they do not know this be-
poor may outnumber the few rich by a ratio of thirty to cause “human wisdom no more knows how to choose
one (see 1.5.5). Persia thus presents itself as something what is best than if somebody should cast lots and do
other than it is in fact or practice. In fact it is based what the lot determines.” This assertion of the impo-
on a fraud facilitated by the innocuous demand that all tence of human wisdom is in tension with Cambyses’
rulers attend, in their youth, the all-important justice earlier account of the power of human prudence, which,
school: having of necessity to work, the sons of the while it certainly needs to be supplemented by divine
poor are of course excluded from doing so, not by the prophecy, was quite capable in its realm (1.6.23 and
rich, but “by necessity” (consider 1.2.6 and 15; 2.1.15; context). Still, one could well suppose that precisely
2.3.13–15). One can respect Cyrus’s dissatisfaction with “the lot” is only another means the gods have to make
old Persia—but can the new project succeed? known their will, to those to whom they are propitious
(compare 6.3.35–36 with 7.1.15), and so the impotence
of human wisdom or prudence is fully compensated for.
Yet Cambyses contends, in the words that constitute his
THE PIETY OF CYRUS
farewell to his son, that the omniscient gods may not,
Hardly more than a glance at the text is needed to see because they need not, advise one what to do and what
the course that Cyrus follows in his pursuit of what is not to do: “if they [the gods] are unwilling to give coun-
noble and good: he begins every work with the gods and sel to all, that is nothing to be wondered at. For it is not
always pays heed to their signs, both in the sacrifices necessary [anangkē] for them to care for those whom
and in or from the heavens (consider, e.g., 2.1.1; 3.3.21; they do not wish to care for” (1.6.46; consider, even in
6.4.12–7.1.3; also Memorabilia 1.1.7–9). For surely only the earlier statement, the “likely” [eikotōs] at 1.6.3 [5]).
gods could bridge the gap that sometimes opens be- Cambyses does not indicate a way to ensure that one
tween our hopes and our fate—gods, that is, who exist be among those whom the gods favor. In other words,
always and know all things past and present and what- the gods may remain silent even to those who observe
ever will result from each of these (1.6.46; consider also the most exacting piety (consider also Oeconomicus
Memorabilia 1.1.19 and Symposium 4.47–48). As Cyrus 8.16 and 11.8); the gods as such are above “necessity.”
learned from his father, it is only by remembering the Far from questioning this teaching or objecting to it—
gods especially when we are faring well, rather than by let alone permitting it to deflate his ambitions—Cyrus
flattering them when we are in want, that we are likely responds to it in deed: he crosses the border, praying
to have greater success in action. And it is on account of both before and after doing so (2.1.1).
just such care or diligence that Cyrus may approach the
gods with greater pleasure, when he intends to make a 8 If Cyrus later relies on the priestly class of the Magi, it is clear
request of them, just as it is his awareness of the fact enough that it is he who commands them (4.5.14; see also 4.5.51;
that he has never neglected the gods that gives him 4.6.11; 5.3.4; 7.3.1; 7.5.35 and 57; 8.1.23; 8.3.11 and 24).

148
American Political Science Review Vol. 109, No. 1

Yet if Cyrus took his father’s teaching to heart, he also 3.3.40 and 42, end; 6.2.6; 8.1.23 and 25; 8.7.22).
must see that, the gods being under no necessity to aid Still, the fact that Cyrus sees in pious observance a
him, there can be no certainty that the just or virtuous certain political utility does not by itself establish the
will receive what is in a sense theirs. Or is it not rather insincerity of his practice of it, as little as his conviction
the fact that Cyrus has received this education, an ed- of the utility of virtue means that his is a strictly low
ucation that goes beyond what either Persia or Media or mercenary view of virtue. For the happiness Cyrus
offers, that he knows of the discrepancy in question? seeks he wishes to deserve, and desert seems pegged
If this is so, then Cyrus must know that recourse to to compliance with a standard one regards as kalos,
the gods does not solve the problem of virtue in the as beautiful or noble or high. Cyrus would not be as
manner one would wish (hence, perhaps, the possibility hopeful as he is, then, if he did not understand himself
of blaming or reproaching gods: 7.1.11 and 7.5.42; also to be complying with an extraordinarily demanding
5.2.12, end). Political events support this conclusion. standard that as such he admires.
Astyages, for example, seems to have died peacefully
of old age, his “tyrannical” ways notwithstanding: evi-
dently no one succeeded in poisoning him (1.3.9, end).
THE PROVIDENTIAL RULE OF CYRUS
We may consider in this regard also Cyrus’s encounter
with Gadatas, whom the present Assyrian King had had We have argued that Cyrus is dedicated to what is noble
seized and castrated when the King’s mistress had men- or virtuous, even as he seeks in all things the good
tioned Gadatas’ nobility or beauty (5.2.28). Gadatas is or advantageous, and that he knows that the world
thus an enemy of the Assyrian but subjugated by him, does not so simply support his genuine wish to see
and when Cyrus appears, Gadatas understandably sees moral excellence unfailingly attended by just reward:
him as a possible avenger of the grievous wrong done such a view must be buttressed by laws and an alogon
him: “And I swear to you, Cyrus, by the gods who both habituation, since it is not reliably supported even by
see all and hear all, that I have suffered even though omniscient gods. But we suggest now that what the
I have neither said nor done anything either unjust or world or cosmos may not supply, Cyrus himself strives
shameful” (5.4.31). Gadatas weeps bitterly at his for- to supply. Cyrus is intent, that is, on constructing a new
tune, as he says these things, and is so overcome that he order that is in principle open to all who are good as
can no longer speak. Like Cambyses, then, Gadatas too he understands goodness, regardless of their wealth or
holds the gods to be all-knowing—at any rate, they see status or nationality (consider 2.2.26), a truly universal
and hear “all things” and therefore also his suffering— meritocracy that to a degree looks to nature (e.g., 2.1.15
and yet they have done nothing either to protect him and especially 2.3.7–10); and in that new order, through
before the fact or to avenge him after it. Gadatas thus the scrupulous attentions of Cyrus himself, merit will
vividly illustrates the problem sketched in outline by always receive its earned recompense. Accordingly, im-
Cambyses. As just and noble as Gadatas has been and mediately after the first great triumph over the Assyr-
is, the gods have permitted his misery; they have looked ian forces, Cyrus himself sees to it that Chrysantas,
on in apparent indifference (consider also 6.1.3). As for who most distinguished himself in the battle, receives
Cyrus’s own fastidious and ostentatious piety, perhaps the reward of a promotion (4.1.3). Cyrus is constantly
it is a product of a persistent hopefulness—that the on the lookout for those deserving of reward, be it
gods may, even if they need not, intervene for him money or praise or honor, and he directs his officers
(consider also Oeconomicus 7.7 and 11.8–9). to do the same (e.g., 3.3.6). It is solely through the
It is true that Machiavelli compels us at least to con- this-worldly deeds of Cyrus that Gadatas the eunuch is
sider a rather different possibility, according to which finally permitted the vengeance he longs for: Gadatas
Cyrus’s piety is less the expression of a heartfelt and and Gobryas (whose son was murdered by the Assyr-
hopeful duty than an infinitely useful device serving a ian) are directly responsible for the execution of the
military or political purpose. After all, if the prophets Assyrian King (7.5.30–31). And although Xenophon is
can manipulate the divine signs or their interpretation, reluctant to mention it, Cyrus must also demote or pun-
so can Cyrus. As we have noted, Machiavelli identifies ish, for the undeserving can never profit or be seen to
Cyrus—Xenophon’s Cyrus (Prince, Chap. 14)—as one profit. When, for example, the disobedient Chaldaeans
of four “armed prophets” and so places him, together (consider 3.2.7 and 25–26) begin to plunder, against
with Romulus and Theseus, in the company of Moses Cyrus’s direct order, they are saved from expulsion
as great founders: “and if their particular actions and in enemy territory only when they agree to give all
orders are considered, they will appear no different they have plundered to the good troops who as such
from those of Moses, who had so great a teacher” remained at their posts (7.2.5–8; also 2.2.25, end).
(Machiavelli 1998, 22–23). In other words, Moses spoke The depth of Cyrus’s attachment to virtue or no-
to God as much as Cyrus did: not at all. Xenophon’s bility is perhaps clearest on those occasions when the
Cyrus too can be called an “armed prophet” inasmuch well-being of the virtuous is most exposed. In such
as he is both heavily armed and trained in the art of circumstances, one can even say, Cyrus takes on the
prophecy. And although Xenophon is far more cau- role of a providential god; he attempts to do here and
tious or reserved than Machiavelli on this score, he too now what the gods evidently do not. Cyrus’s concern
indicates occasionally the political or military utility of for “the noble and the good,” for the union of “Persia”
pious observance: soldiers who are fearful of the divine and “Media,” compels him to go beyond the limits
fear human beings less, for example (3.3.58; consider of all ordinary politics in the direction of a universal

149
How to Rule the World February 2015

providence. No wonder, then, that some men are even for a time to silence. He does not know what to say.
of the view that Cyrus is descended from gods, that is, Cyrus has cattle, horses, and many sheep brought along
is himself a god (see 4.2.24, end; 7.2.24; also 1.2.1). In so they may be slaughtered in sacrifice for Abradatas,
the confusion of the battle against the allied Assyrian as befits a good man (7.3.11, end), and he attempts to
forces, Cyrus surveys the scene from atop one of the console Panthea with the thought that Abradatas has
moveable towers he has had built. From that vantage received “the noblest end, for he has met his end while
point he catches sight of the Egyptians, his enemies, being victorious” (7.3.11). Thus the noblest man has
who alone are standing their ground. But being in im- received the end most fitting for him—although there
possible circumstances, they simply form themselves is no suggestion in the text that Abradatas died with
into a circle and sit down under such cover as their the knowledge that victory was theirs (compare, e.g.,
shields provide. Here they begin to suffer “many ter- Thucydides 1942, 5.10.11). Cyrus also promises that a
rible things” (7.1.40). No longer able to fight, in other great memorial mound will be raised for Abradatas.
words, the Egyptians submit to a slaughter. Cyrus’s re- Yet Panthea is consoled by none of this, and she makes
action to this sight is telling: he is filled with both admi- a remark that is as disturbing in its way as is the corpse
ration and pity, “because they were perishing, despite that lies in pieces beside her (7.3.8–10): “I know . . . that
being good men” (7.1.41). Accordingly, Cyrus inter- [Abradatas] suffered these things on my account not
venes in an effort to save them, and he manages to do so least, but perhaps [or equally] also on account of you,
when he allays their sole concern—that their salvation Cyrus, no less. For I—the fool!—I uttered many exhor-
be somehow compatible with what is “noble” (7.1.42). tations to him to act in this way, so that he would be a
The Egyptians, then, show by deed that they prefer worthy friend to you. And I myself know that he did not
a noble death to an ignoble salvation, just as Cyrus reflect on whatever he would suffer, but rather on what
shows his abiding concern that men of extraordinary he might do in gratitude to you” (7.3.10). If Panthea re-
virtue not meet a harsh end: he intervenes to save the mains true to her earlier statement that she would pre-
stoutest of his enemies—the very ones, as the reader fer a noble end with her husband to an ignoble life—she
knows but Cyrus does not, who are responsible for the immediately commits suicide, an act that leaves Cyrus
death of that man of the most outstanding nobility in “dumbstruck” (7.4.15)—she does so with deep regret:
Cyrus’s army, Abradatas of Susa, husband of Panthea surely her statement here means that, were it possible
(7.1.31–32). for her, she would in fact prefer the continuation of her
The case of Abradatas and Panthea too is revealing. life with Abradatas, noble or not. She regards herself
Abradatas expresses in prayer his gratitude to Cyrus now as a “fool.” This scene reveals simultaneously the
for the treatment accorded his captured wife: “Greatest limits of Cyrus’s own power to reward the virtuous and
Zeus, grant that I may come to light as a husband wor- the limits of the noblest outlook taken on its own terms.
thy of Panthea, and a friend worthy of Cyrus” (6.4.9). That the honors or rewards arranged by Cyrus fail
And it is Panthea who exhorts her husband to aid Cyrus to satisfy Panthea is clear enough; Xenophon himself
in an outstandingly noble way: she would prefer to be refers to the memorial mound for Abradatas as “the
under the earth with her husband than live on with him memorial mound of the eunuchs,” the eunuchs, that is,
in shame, should he fail to acquit himself well in battle who immediately imitate the suicide of their mistress:
(6.4.6 and context). In addition to her misattribution were it not for the artful intervention of Xenophon, as
of Cyrus’ treatment of her to his selfless virtue, she still distinguished from that of Cyrus, the eunuchs would be
labors under the false opinion that she is responsible at least as well remembered as Abradatas and Panthea.
for the end of the friendship of Cyrus and Araspas, The noble dedication to virtue seems to call out for
a friendship that in fact survives but whose apparent immortality—Panthea had spoken of the possibility,
demise Cyrus uses to great advantage (6.1.45–51 and not indeed of death, but of her being together with her
6.4.8; compare 5.1.2–18; 6.1.31–44; 6.3.11–16). Panthea husband in or under the earth, once he has shown him-
and Abradatas together are exceedingly noble or beau- self to be a good man (6.4.6)—and this Cyrus cannot
tiful in every way: in bodily appearance, in adornment, supply. In attempting to jettison what is noble insofar
in character. So little do they seek their own advantage as it transcends the good, must not Cyrus jettison also
or profit that the very arms and clothing Panthea has the hope undergirding Panthea’s words to Abradatas?
had specially crafted for her husband are noteworthy
for their beauty as distinguished from their utility (con-
sider 6.4.2), just as his chariot would seem to be best for
THE UNIVERSAL RULE OF CYRUS AND THE
driving straight into enemy lines, whereas the chariots
PROBLEM OF REGIME STABILITY
of Cyrus’s new design seem rather more maneuverable We hope to have shown that Cyrus is both deeply at-
and are themselves a lethal weapon merely by being in tractive9 and deeply flawed. He seeks to preserve some-
motion (compare 6.1.51 and 6.4.2, beg., with 6.1.29–30 thing of the beauty of noble or moral action even as he
and 52; 6.2.17). insists that such action is always good for those who so
When Cyrus learns the news of the death of Abra- act. Insofar as he sees that neither human beings nor
datas in battle, he reacts in an unprecedented way.
Striking his thigh in vexation or grief, he rides imme- 9 “One will not grasp the problem of a Cyrus if one does not grasp
diately to the corpse—thus seeing Panthea for the first his grandeur, that is, what makes him stand out from boyhood as
time—begins to weep and weep bitterly (7.3.6, 8 [15] admirable and attractive as well as able and intimidating” (Faulkner
and 11 [7]; compare 1.4.26 and 5.5.10), and is reduced 2007, 134–35).

150
American Political Science Review Vol. 109, No. 1

gods always make this so, he himself enters the breach: routinely called “father” by his subjects—which means
Cyrus takes upon himself the offices of a providential that they, both slaves and “the best,” are themselves
despotēs or “master” (e.g., 4.6.2–3; 5.3.28; 7.2.9; 7.3.3; akin to children (8.1.1 and 44; 8.2.9; 8.8.1, end) and
consider also 7.5.61–62). At one point he assures the come to prefer him to their own brothers, fathers, and
Persian commoners that he, “together with the gods,” children (8.2.9). Or, since “familial” rule too can be
will overcome a certain “necessity” (2.1.15): Cyrus ap- difficult (recall 1.1.1 [8–13]), Cyrus also calls himself
pears in the company of gods, above necessity. Yet he “shepherd,” which means that his subjects are akin
lacks the omniscience such providence would require. to sheep (8.2.14). A saying of Cyrus is remembered:
If he can bestow on Chrysantas the requisite honor “as the shepherd ought to use his flocks while making
because he himself saw him in battle, Cyrus must rely them happy—in the happiness of sheep of course—so
on hearsay reports in distributing the other honors (see a king ought similarly to use cities and human beings
again 4.1.2–3); he wishes to be, but cannot be, a “see- while making them happy.” Cyrus fails to add: “in the
ing law.” That there is a grave difficulty with Cyrus’s happiness of human beings of course.” It is striking
enterprise is obvious no later than his accession to the how frequently Cyrus takes his bearings, in dealing
throne and the organization of his empire (7.5.37 and with his soldiers and subjects, by observation of herd
following). There he attempts to make up for his lack of or pack animals (e.g., 2.1.28–29; 7.5.62; 8.1.9 and 44;
knowledge by means of the so-called “Ears and Eyes of 8.2.4); the significance of Xenophon’s early juxtaposi-
the King”—that is, a clandestine network of informants tion of human beings and herd animals is now apparent
who report whatever it may be useful for him to know. (recall 1.1.2). In accord with all of this, Cyrus replaces
The result of this, which Stalin could approve of, is that political rule or judgment or deliberation (e.g., 1.5.5;
the people “are everywhere afraid to say what is not 5.5.43) by “management,” “household management”
advantageous to the King, just as if he himself were (e.g., 7.5.58; 8.1.14 and 15).
listening, and to do whatever is not advantageous, just Cyrus distinguishes between those in his circle and
as if he himself were present” (8.2.10–12). The distance those whom he is “preparing for slavery,” and in the
between omniscience and the native human capaci- former especially he instills piety, justice, respect or
ties is compensated for by the judicious use of fear awe, obedience, moderation, and continence (8.1.23–
(consider already 1.1.5 [23–25]) and perhaps also by 33; compare 1.2.8). Yet the line between the two begins
“technological” inventions or contrivances (consider, to blur. As Chrysantas has it, the distinction between
e.g., 8.6.17–18). And this in the chapter devoted to ex- free and slave is that the free are willingly, slaves un-
plaining how Cyrus won over his “friends” (see 8.1.48, willingly, obedient (8.1.4; on “freedom,” consider also
end and 8.2.28)! Accordingly, Cyrus sees to it that the 3.1.10, end; 8.3.21): everyone must always be eager to
first grand procession from the palace is both “most dance a Persian jig before Cyrus (see 8.4.12 and con-
noble” and “most frightening” (8.3.5). Cyrus knows text). The “education of Cyrus” informed him that a
that it is not enough just to be better than his sub- great many human beings will obey if such obedience
jects; he must also “beguile” or “bewitch” them—with brings with it “the good things” and their preservation
makeup, elevator shoes, elaborate dress—so as to im- (8.1.3; the speaker is Chrysantas: compare 1.6.19 [13–
prove on “nature” (8.1.40–41). Because many enemies 14] and 8.4.12 [17–20]). First among those goods are
surround him in Babylon, he must surround himself the pleasures of food and drink (8.2.2) and clothing
with the only people he can now trust, a coterie of and adornments (8.2.8), on the one hand, and bodily
eunuchs, who are of course themselves unnatural and health on the other. Accordingly, Cyrus encourages the
are without the natural attachments (7.5.58–65); those more-than-Median refinement that goes together with
who do not have (Gobryas) or cannot have issue (Ga- the division of labor, whose products he alone con-
datas) are especially dependent on Cyrus (consider also trols (8.2.5), and he maintains a monopoly on access
the implication of the apparently inapt metaphor of to “health care” (8.2.24–25). Much of life in the new
Cyrus the King Bee at 5.1.24). The crowning moment of empire, then, is taken up with procuring and enjoying
Cyrus’s first procession occurs when the vast audience, the bodily pleasures or their close cousins—a “sheep-
partly spontaneously and partly by prior arrangement, like” happiness. Insofar as Cyrus’s providential rule
prostrates itself before him. And this means in turn seeks to preserve mere life and to supply comforts—
that, for the first time, the Commoners and Peers of comfortable self-preservation—these must be accord-
Persia—republican Persia—too abase themselves be- ing to Xenophon important motives bringing the peo-
fore the man, who hardly seems to be a mere man ple to the adulation of Cyrus; awareness of the fragility
any longer (8.3.14; see also 4.4.13; 5.3.18; and 7.5.32; of life and of its attendant pleasures may be sufficient
compare 2.4.19 and Anabasis of Cyrus 3.2.13). to bring some human beings to the worship of beings
Here we may return to the opening of the Ed- who present themselves as providential.
ucation of Cyrus and recall—what becomes easy to The emptiness of the life Cyrus creates at the peak
forget—that the book presents itself as a high praise of of empire becomes clear in his attempts to answer
Cyrus. Yet Xenophon’s praise of Cyrus rests on a single the question of what the empire, with all its striving
ground: that Cyrus solved, on the basis of knowledge, and strife and hardship, is for. In his first speech af-
the problem of political instability. It gradually be- ter becoming king, Cyrus contends, before the Peers
comes clear that he solved this problem, for so long as and those who have proved themselves best, that if so
he solved it, by destroying politics in favor of something great a success as the empire renders it impossible “to
on the model of the family. That is, Cyrus the King is have leisure either for oneself or to enjoy oneself with

151
How to Rule the World February 2015

friends, I bid farewell to this happiness” (7.5.42; com- a freedom worthy of the name, is not worse than the
pare 8.7.12, end and context). The practice of virtue, problem itself.
we can now say, is for the sake of empire, which is
for the sake of leisure, for oneself and with one’s
CONCLUSION
friends. Everything rests, then, on Cyrus’s conception
of the concern or activity that properly fills that leisure. The Education of Cyrus can easily lay claim to being
Artabazus, the Mede who from youth has been in love among the most political of Xenophon’s writings, and
with Cyrus, suggests that such leisure be given over to a Cyrus is surely the greatest political figure in them. By
kind of private life shared by Cyrus’s friends from the the end of the Education of Cyrus, however, we are
beginning—Artabazus has in mind a love affair with possessed by the thought that the political life even at
Cyrus—but Cyrus regards this suggestion as risible: he its greatest is defective according to Xenophon. And in
openly laughs at it (7.5.48–55; for a different reading of this altogether political book, the private life scarcely
this passage, see Nadon 2001, 112). Instead, since the appears. This is especially the case with what Xenophon
empire must be not only maintained but also expanded, must regard as the peak of the private life, the philo-
Cyrus indicates that his men “must not slacken in their sophic life (consider Memorabilia 4.8.11). We hear, it
practice of virtue”: virtue is for the sake of empire, is true, of a book of wise sayings of (or owned by) Go-
which is for the sake of leisure, which is for the sake bryas, a book in which Cyrus shows no interest (8.4.16
of the practice of virtue, which in turn maintains the and 25; compare 7.4.12). And when Cyrus is reunited
empire that is for the sake of . . . leisure? Given the cir- in Armenia with his boyhood acquaintance Tigranes,
cularity of this, Cyrus is compelled to raise the following he recalls that Tigranes once had a wise teacher whom
question: “If someone is reflecting on such things as Tigranes admired greatly. But Tigranes’ father had had
these—‘so what profit is there for us to have accom- that noble and good teacher killed on the grounds that
plished the things we desired, if it will still be obliga- he was “corrupting” Tigranes—in fact, as Tigranes’ fa-
tory for us to practice endurance while being hungry ther now admits, he envied the respect the son showed
and thirsty and while laboring and being diligent?’— the teacher. The execution of a wise teacher on a charge
he must understand that one enjoys the goods things of corrupting the young that stemmed from the envy
more insofar as one labors first before proceeding to of the fathers: Xenophon thus alludes to the fate of
them” (7.5.80). As this suggests, the only clear answer his own teacher, Socrates (consider also 1.6.31). The
Cyrus can give to his question is enjoyment or “plea- education of Tigranes (Xenophon) is apparent not only
sure,” which he mentions six times in the context. But in the skillful speech he gives that probably saves his
this answer is problematic. For these promised plea- father’s life, but also in the reserve he shows in his
sures always lie just around the corner, and the austere esteem for Cyrus: “Tigranes,” able rhetorician and ex-
pleasures subsequent to hunger and thirst must lose cellent soldier, has another center of gravity (consider
their allure amid the Babylonian splendor, eventually 3.1.41; 5.1.27; and 8.4.1).
if not immediately (consider 8.8). And to the extent Xenophon’s clearest pointer in the direction of the
that Cyrus hesitates to make an avowed hedonism the private life is the subtheme of erotic love that appears
core of the self-understanding of the Persians, at least, early on and throughout (1.4.27–28; 2.2.28–31; 3.1.36
he is compelled to “repeat” old Persia at the peak of and 41; 5.1.18 and context; 6.1.47 and context; 7.2.28;
the new (see 7.5.85). Cyrus, that is, must also encourage 8.4.24). If such love is first treated as the stuff of com-
something akin to virtue’s being practiced for its own edy, it becomes, in the story of Araspas’ illicit love of
sake alone, after having done so much to destroy it: Panthea, much more serious than that and, in the case
“those whom I see making a regular practice of the of Panthea and Abradatas, something approaching the
noble things and the good things, these I will honor” tragic. Cyrus himself is not a lover in any ordinary
(7.5.85, end; the formulation is compatible with the sense—being a “cold king” (8.4.22–23), his contention
separation of the noble from the good). that he runs a great risk in looking upon the beau-
If Cyrus did indeed solve the problem of regime tiful Panthea should probably be taken with a grain
stability, at least during his lifetime (8.8, with all of salt10 —and when he eventually marries it is for a
the MSS; also 1.2.16; compare Agesilaos 1.4, end), and strictly political reason.11 It is true that he is attracted
if the empire needed to solve it becomes more repellent to beauty. But he is attracted especially to those things
the more we see of it, then political stability must be whose allure is much enhanced for him by their death
judged the floor rather than the ceiling of healthy po- (consider 1.4.11 [11–12] and 1.4. 24). Only once does
litical life. Xenophon is able to praise Cyrus as he does Xenophon speak of an erotic desire of Cyrus: for the
only by lowering the standard by which he judges polit-
ical life: Xenophon must cease to judge political life by 10 5.1.8; also Nadon 2001, 152 and 155 (but compare 159 top); Mem-
its highest aspiration, to secure for all citizens the good orabilia 3.11.1–18. Consider also Strauss 2013, 203: “Xenophon’s
or best way life, if he is to praise Cyrus. Such stability Cyrus is a cold and unerotic nature. That is to say, the ruler is not
may be the necessary condition of happiness, at least motivated by true or Socratic eros because he does not know what a
of the community (compare Apology of Socrates to the well ordered soul is . . . . The ruler is in fact dominated by love based
Jury 18); it is not its sufficient condition. One is led to on need in the common meaning of need, or by mercenary love.”
11 Xenophon tells us that some writers wrongly report the marriage
wonder, in other words, whether Cyrus’s solution to the of Cyrus and his aunt, who would have been quite elderly at the
problem of political stability, which is indeed possible time (8.5.28); he tells us this because, though erroneous, the report
and includes the destruction of politics together with is entirely plausible.

152
American Political Science Review Vol. 109, No. 1

practice of horsemanship and hunting, the latter espe- having them seated next to him at dinner, the some-
cially being a training for warfare (1.4.5). what less honored on his right (and less vulnerable)
Xenophon also indicates the price Cyrus pays for his side, the more honored on Cyrus’s (more vulnerable)
“coldness.” For after Araspas has recovered from his left; Xenophon notes however that such an honor was
disastrous love of Panthea, he is prompted to reflect not “immortal” (athanaton: 8.4.5), the only time this
on his own soul more seriously than he ever has. It is term appears in the book (compare aenaōteron [“more
the experience of eros that brings home to him how everlasting” or “more ever-flowing”] at 4.2.44). A little
little he knows his own soul and so prompts him to later, when Artabazus sees Cyrus kiss Chrysantas and
“philosophize”— the only appearance of “philosophy” Cyrus tells Artabazus that he may have to wait thirty
in the Education of Cyrus. It is here, then, that these years for his own kiss, Artabazus—still very much in
two parts of the private life converge (6.1.41). What- love with Cyrus—replies: “I will be waiting and I will
ever one may think of Araspas’ doctrine of the two not die” (8.4.27). “I will not die”: do not some human
souls, he has greater self-knowledge than before; he beings, dissatisfied with or disgusted by the “sheep-
knows, for example, that the love in whose grip he was, like” happiness that comes with a full belly and petty
cannot be said to be voluntary. And as is made clear baubles, long for precisely what is immortal? Cyrus
by Croesus, now defeated and dethroned, progress in himself demonstrates such a concern, at least inasmuch
self-knowledge—in fulfilling the Delphic-Socratic dic- he believes he has a just claim to be remembered “for
tum, “Know Thyself” (Memorabilia 4.2.24)—leads to all time” as happy (8.7.9): at the moment when it may
a clearer understanding of the true demands of hap- matter most, Cyrus states that he wishes to be praised,
piness. In Croesus’s case, at least, that understanding not just by “all,” but also forever. Yet in the course
leads to his eager embrace of a private life akin to that of that very deathbed speech, Cyrus makes clear that
led by his wife, an eagerness Cyrus cannot quite fathom he does not know—he does not seem to have thought
or credit (7.2.28–29). Tigranes too evidently returns, much about—whether his own soul is mortal or im-
and happily, to the private life (8.4.24 and 28; consider mortal (compare 8.7.18–20 with 22). Xenophon can
3.1.36). Cyrus the “cold king,” then, never having phi- praise Cyrus as he does at the book’s beginning not
losophized, must be said to lack self-knowledge. This only because he “forgets” every political good higher
amounts to saying that he does not quite know what it than stability, as we noted, but also because he abstracts
is that he longs for. He appears from the beginning to from the concern for eternity. It is as if Cyrus, in found-
have fixed on praise, the praise of “all human beings,” ing a stable empire for a few decades, has accomplished
as the end that justifies all striving (1.2.1, end; 3.2.31); everything one could possibly wish for.
on his deathbed he seems more anxious to secure the Yet is not this concern or this longing so powerful
reputation for happiness than he is to have had the thing and so deeply rooted in us that it leads some to wor-
itself (8.7.6 and 9 beginning). But the grand procession ship at the feet of Cyrus or look to him as to a god,
from the palace indicates that it is impossible for “all in order that the world come to sight as what they
human beings” to know who one is, and so they must wish it to be? And must not any god-like ruler speak
praise or revere a figment of their imagination. Those to the highest aspiration of the human soul, as this is
who are truly serious about praise or honor “seek to be expressed in love, for example, and in the dedication
honored by the prudent, and by those to whom they are to noble action? We suggest that Xenophon’s depic-
known, and for their virtue” (Aristotle, Nicomachean tion of grand empire contains his analysis of a moral
Ethics 1095b26–29). As for Cyrus’s famous “philan- seriousness that looks for its completion to a divine
thropy,” or his fondness for human beings as such, it providential order. In that depiction, in other words,
prompts him to benefit others so as to win their friend- one begins to see what it is according to Xenophon
ship or praise (consider 1.2.1; 1.4.1; 7.5.73; and 8.7.25 that leads human beings to seek to worship—and what
in the light of 8.2.1 and 8.4.7–8; compare Sandridge it is that those who long for a truly universal rule
2012 and Danzig 2012, 509–11). Though perhaps not must become: (armed) prophets. The disappointment
much of a boaster in other respects (7.1.17), in this with Cyrus’ empire, which Xenophon induces in his
Cyrus was very much a boaster: he thought he knew readers, invites them to reflect, with Croesus, on the
the truly good things or the best life. Or, to put this political life and on the hopes that fuel it. Such dis-
another way, Cambyses regards it as “sufficient” for appointment could then constitute the beginning of
a man to be able to exercise such diligence that he the education that Cyrus himself did not receive but
himself become genuinely (dokimōs) noble and good, that Xenophon, a man at once thoroughly political
while also providing for his family and leading others and altogether philosophical, most emphatically did
to be such as they ought to be; Cyrus replies that he receive. Xenophon thus prepares us to encounter his
agrees—and that it seems to him an “extraordinarily own teacher, Socrates, in the four writings he devoted
great task to rule nobly”: Cambyses had not spoken of to him.
“rule” at all (compare prostateuein at 1.6.7), and the
youthful Cyrus assumes that he already is a noble and
good man (1.6.7–8).
∗∗∗
With his customary light touch, Xenophon suggests
what it is that Cyrus fails to see about himself and The Education of Cyrus has been called a “historical
others, or at any rate what he fails to take seriously romance” (Grant 1883, 124). More cautiously one can
enough. We learn that Cyrus would honor some by say that it is an act of philosophical poēsis: like Plato

153
How to Rule the World February 2015

in his portrait of Socrates, Xenophon in his portrait of Machiavelli, Niccolo. 1998. The Prince. 2nd ed. Ed. and trans.
Cyrus presents the life of an extraordinary individual in Harvey C. Mansfield. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
such a way as to permit his readers to learn a universal Nadon, Christopher. 2001. Xenophon’s Prince: Republic and Empire
in the Cyropaedia. California: University of California Press.
truth or truths from it—retail fabrication in the service Newell, Waller R. 2013. Tyranny: A New Interpretation. Cambridge:
of wholesale truth-telling. The “education” of the title Cambridge University Press.
may include not only the education that Cyrus received Plato. 1902. Opera. Ed. John Burnet. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
but also the education that he makes possible for us, Rasmussen, Paul J. 2009. Excellence Unleashed: Machiavelli’s Cri-
tique of Xenophon and the Moral Foundations of Politics. Lanham,
thanks to the artfulness of Xenophon. MD: Lexington Books.
Sancisi-Weerdenburg, 2010. “The Death of Cyrus: Xenophon’s Cy-
ropaedia as a Source for Iranian History.” In Gray 2010, 439–
REFERENCES 53.
Sandridge, Norman B. 2012. Loving Humanity, Learning, and Being
Ambler, Wayne. 2001. “Introduction.” The Education of Cyrus. Ed. Honored: The Foundations of Leadership in Xenophon’s Educa-
and trans. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. tion of Cyrus. Washington, D.C.: Center for Hellenic Studies.
Bizos, Marcel. 1971. “Notice.” In Xenophon 1971. Sandridge, Norman. 2012. “Cyrus’ Paradise: The World’s First On-
Bruell, Christopher. 1987. “Xenophon.” In History of Political line Collaborative Commentary to an Ancient Text.” http://www.
Philosophy. 3rd edition. Ed. Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey. cyropaedia.org/author/norman/. Accessed August 10, 2014.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Strauss, Leo. 2013 [originally published 1961]. On Tyranny: Cor-
Danzig, Gabriel. 2012. “The Best of the Achaemenids: Benevolence, rected and Exanded Edition Including the Strauss-Kojève Corre-
Self-Interest, and the ‘Ironic’ Reading of Cyropaedia.” In Hobden spondence. Ed. Victor Gourevitch and Michael S. Roth. Chicago:
and Tuplin, 2012, 499–539. University of Chicago Press.
Due, Bodil. 1989. The Cyropaedia: Xenophon’s Aims and Methods. Strauss, Leo. 1939. “The Spirit of Sparta or the Taste of Xenophon.”
Aarhus: Aarhus University Press. Social Research. 6 (4): 502–36.
Faulkner, Robert. 2007. “Imperial Grandeur and Imperial Hollow- Stronk, Jan P. 2010. Ctesias’ Persian History: Part 1: Introduction,
ness: Xenophon’s Cyrus the Great.” In The Case for Greatness: Text, and Translation. Duesseldorf: Wellem Verlag.
Honorable Ambition and Its Critics. New Haven: Yale University Tatum, James. 1989. Xenophon’s Imperial Fiction: On the Education
Press. of Cyrus. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Grant, Alexander. 1883. Xenophon. Edinburgh: Blackwood. Thucydides, . 1942. Historiae. 2 Vols. Ed. H.S. Jones. Oxford: Claren-
Gray, Vivienne, ed. 2010. Xenophon. Oxford: Oxford University don Press.
Press. Xenophon. 1954. Opera Omnia, 5 vols. Ed. E.C. Marchant. Oxford:
Hawkin, David J. 2004. The Twenty-first Century Confronts Its Gods: Clarendon Press.
Globalization, Technology, and War. Albany: SUNY Press. Xenophon. 1968. Xenophontis Institutio Cyri. Ed. G. Gemoll and
Herodotus, . 1927. Historiae. 2 Vols. Ed. C. Hude. Oxford: Clarendon revised by J. Peters. Leipzig: B.G. Teubner.
Press. Xenophon. 1971. Cyropédie. Vol. 1. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.
Hobden, Fiona, and Christopher Tuplin. 2012. Xenophon: Ethical Xenophon. 2001. The Education of Cyrus. Ed. and trans. Wayne Am-
Principles and Historical Inquiry. Leiden: Brill. bler. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

154

You might also like