Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9

Also available from Continuum: What Philosophy Is

What Philosophers Thin~ edited by Julian Baggini and Jeremy Contemporary Philosophy in Action
Stangroom

GreatThinkers A-Z, edited by Julian Bagginl and Jeremy Edited by Havl Carel and David Gamez
Stangroom
With a Foreword by Simon Blackburn

:.... continuum 2004 .


• ~'LONOON. NEW YORK
What Philosophy Is 141
.140

negative - as I have suggested is more generally true of the disci ­


plines called ' fo unda tions of education'.17
Doe could mention here Mackie 's notion of an inus condition
(an insufficient but necessary part of an unnecessary but sufficient
condition). Mackie introduced this structure in an investigation of
.causation, but it is one that can find usefuJ application elsewhere-IS
Getting the right answer to a particular question in a multiple-choice
test is often an inus condition ofpassing the test I have suggested tha t
seeing this structural feature (of literacy, say, in relation to leading a
worthwhile life in modern societies) and how it connects with ideas
of justification can illuminate discussions of the place of compulsory
education.l? This example also allows us to see a case where philo­
sophical improvements may not be of wider utility. One migbt agree
that Bennett" is right in thinking that his own 115 account of causa­
tion (a necessary part of a sufficient condition) is more general and
elegant than Mackie's but refuse the improvement on the grounds Julian Baggini
that Mackie's even-bandedly draws OUI attention to the gaps on
either side: the possible insufficiency of the part and the possible lack
of necessity of the whole of which it is a part These gaps are worth Anglo-American" philosophy prides itself on its adherence to logic
seeing when one reflects on our thought about needs, for instance. and rigour in argument However, most philosophers would agree
Most physicists are neither at the cutting edge of theoretical work 'that really good philosophizing requires something more, something
nor at the forefront of its experimental testing. I have referred to we might call insight or judgement. The problem is that although this
Popper's disdain for this sort of unoriginal work that I think is the fact is recognized, little is said about it, and its consequences for how
implicit judgement of the philosophical community on itself It is a we view the project of philosophy are too often not drawn out It is
commonplace in philosophy of science that engineers (physicists not some additional 'factor X' that allied to sound logic yields good
indeed) routinely use Newtonian theories we know are false, and that philosopby; judgement or insight is an inherent part of the philo­
this is more sensible than trying to do everything from Einstein or sophical process. Furthermore, it is something which brings value
Bohr up, I suggest we grant a similar indulgence to philosophical judgements with it.
theses or distinctions that can serve to shed light on intellectual prob­ My purpose in this paper is to put into focus some characteristics
lems , even when we know they may not be the whole truth and of philosophy and rationality that I hope will be recognized as famil­
nothing but the truth. I suggest that we ask ourselves wbat attitudes iar. By drawing our attention to them in a systematic way I hope to
are appropriate once we acknowledge the fallibilityofour own philo­ contribute to an increased self-consciousness in philosophy about
sophical results, and that we reconsider the place of philosophical the role of judgement. I will conclude by sketching out some of the
insight in a defensible liberal education, if our paymasters permit ways in which I think the picture I'll be painting can help explain
such an apparent anachronism to survive. some of philosophy's puzzling characteristics.
'·1i~?1i.~ ·
'ii-if
142 What Philosophy Is F~i~i1OS0Ph ' ca ' Method 143
~" "I. '
,~~~• .,;t?~·

'"r
Philosophy's dirty secret ': ' j~tf ~ th something to say about formal logic and the structure of argu­
';' : :~;~::;i~:i.Jl en ts than it is to come up with some real insight into the nature of
1 !: ,!.'I:?,· :i'· · ...J h t
I define judgement as a cognitive faculty required to reach conclu­ .~ ' ~f.;;· :i ~d u "t>em en .

sions or form theories, the truth or falsity of which cannot be deter­ 'i" :'~:~l::~;~/;>Th
;':,;!,'. •,!.~" .
e second reason concerns the academicization of philosophy.


min ed by an appeal to facts and/or logic alone. .:: .. ~ri1 Por better or for worse, th e work of a~denuc p~osopl~y increas­
A paradigmatic example of the use of judgement in philosophy is .~? ly~';'''~7f ingIy takes place at the level of fine detail. Professional philosophers
.th e decision to accept an argument that has a counter-intuitive con­ li*~~~'~ eed to publish, and by applying the formal, analytic" skills of phil ­
':0:
clusion and is not falsified by experience as either sound or a reduc­ ~~~· ir~~~jt~~Ophy . t~ prob~ems which have ~ready bee~l explored .in some
tioad absurdum.. In accepting that the argument is a reductio or biting . .:. ~:rJ.~,~epth , It 15 possible to come up with something that satisfies the
the bullet of its implausible conclusion it is clear that one is going ""\" 'y'?:?~~~
~"" " " "~' .
~qUlremen ts 0 f' an aca demi . . aI',to pro d uce a
elDJC paper to b e ' ongrn
beyond that which is demanded by logic or the facts:
Indeed, what ); ~~ti1t~cresul t'
and to display high professional standards. There is therefore
one is often doing in sum an argument is judging whether the logic 1f~: premium on the analytic, logical side of philosophy because this
of the argument has a greater claim on us than the facts its conclu­ ~;ke ts results faster, even if the result is uninteresting.
sion seems to deny. It is dear that in making such a judgement one is 'Jf,Jfh e third reason is perhaps more significant Judgement repre­
going beyond what the facts and/or logic demand, not least because c 15 the ineliminable limits of rational argument, and because phil­
they appear to be demanding different things. ~oph y always aims to pursue rationality as far as it can go, it is an
Of course, the judgement is informed by other arguments and ·ilt~rel en ting quest to reduce as far as possible- since it cannot entirely
other facts. Bu t one would have to be an extremely optimistic kind of • ':":~", .". ' r£il}m inate - the role of judgement. We require as little as possible in
rationalist to suppose that these other arguments and facts settle the :, I~i~~PiUlosophy to depend on judgement while at the same time know
matter and there is no role left for judgement, as I have defined it. '~~"'1ha t we cannot do without it Because our arguments become more
As anyone who does philosophy must surely know, this kind of :~tion al the less they depend on judgement, we can make our argu­
judgement is an important part of good philosophizing. Interest­ iints appear more rational by disguising or concealing the place of
ingly, however, I have found that it is a fact Dot often discussed in the ,.' dgemen t in them. Judgement is therefore philosophy's dirty secret.
standard literature. But in the context of an interview or discussion,
for example, philosophers are happy to acknowledge tha t 'insight' or
'judgement', something that cannot be reduced to the mechanical
logical calculations of a Thring machine, is needed in order to
produce good, interesting philosophy. I
But while we have got very far with systematizing and developing
criteria for good arguments and reasoning. we have bad less to say
about what constitutes 'good judgement' and acknowledging its
indispensability. I think there are at least three reasons why judge­
ment has been sidelined in the literature. The first is that the logical
side of philosophy can be schematized and formalized in a way that , .
judgement obviously cannot, Therefore it is just easier to come up ,,' .
~.
144 What Philosophy Is 145

enquiry. Philosophy is, however, a particularly pure form of rational formally, they agree that we must in this case accept the statement 'P
enquiry in that its only real resource other than the data of ordinary P:
& not in defiance of the law 0 f non -contradiction. There are many
experience is rationality, and because the nature of rationality is itself ' I'" ~<~~
.ways to respond to such a finding, which J would summarize under
a subject of philosophy. , ;;/:;~~~ , -three broad headings: denial, revision and rejection.
The importance of this for our present purposes is that it shows ,:':';~~~):;, Denial is the position that this cannot possibly be true, since it
how, in order to understand what philosophy is, we need to under­ ;; >i:'i~~ 'entails a breach of the logical principle of bivalence, or the excluded
stand what rationality is and the role of judgement in it "':,~Y~~i!i' middle, which states that any proposition has to be true or false and
Central to my understanding of the role of judgemen t in rational­ ;I, ,?~, ·,there 1$
~""/>,'U'I' ' no thiird al terna trve,
.
ity and rationality in philosophy is the claim that deductive logic is a "
: c?~:~i'. , Revision is the position that this may be t rue and that the princi­
resource of rationality, not the essence of it This is one of those prop­ { ;,t~~i~t:,ple of bivalence is true, because logic is a self-contained system and
ositions which some see as scandalous and others see as obvious. { ::'\r}~ th e world itself mayor may not conform to logical principles. The
Which view one takes may well depend on how it is interpreted. ~,.. :: ':W Jt,:.r,,:':·! ,
I ,-' .!,,·,,·
assumption is that it does, because working on this assumption has
This claim has a strong and a weak.version. On the weak version, ": ~1J,?fi~f.: proven to be a fruitful way of conducting empirical" enquiry. But
rationality is not coextensive with deductive logic (henceforth I shall ~! ,;~1?i!!!/
lo .• •• ~ '.~, •
there is no a priori reason why the assumption must be true, and if

just speak of 'logic') just because there are many forms of rational ;~ ,the evidence for this strange finding about the position of particles is
argument, such as induction and abduction, which are by definition .' overwhelming, we have merely discovered one of the limits of apply­
, not themselves deductive in character. There should be nothing sur­ ::,ingl ogic to the real world.
prising or objectionable here to anyone who accepts something like {f;:. .Rejection is the more radical position tha t the finding destroys the
Hume's distinction between reasoning concerning matters of fact ': ~very basis of logic and shows that its founding principles are false.
and matters of logic- 2
Hume's goal was to show that rationality does }., Let us not worry about which of these responses would be correct
not just consist of deductive logic; he was not trying to show that rea­ UMypoint is simply that we can sensibly ask which response is more
soning concerning matters of fact is irrational. Ifbe had thought this, ',:rationaL The very fact that such a question makes sense shows that
then he would have thought that his own argument against miracles, ;/ our conception of rationality does not seem to be necessarily con­
for example, was non-rational or irrational, since it is based wholly >istrain ed by or coextensive with our conception of logic, for what is
on inductive principles. This weak version of the claim is, I hope, - precisely at issue is how far, if at all, it is rational in such a case to
uncontroversial. :-accept, revise or reject what logic appears to demand. The apparent
The stronger version is that although rationality is ordinarily CQn­ 'illogicality of the finding is not sufficient reason to reject it on ra­
strained by the fundamental laws of logic, there are no a priori" .lPt:mal grounds unless one has some other good reason to believe that
grounds for sayi.ng that it is necessarily alwaysso constrained. Let me ,; ,~(fc""", ika tionali ty's sovereign is logic. If logic is on at least one occasion
give one example to illustrate what I mean. Imagine that scientific ,L,\tt~, rneithe r necessary nor sufficient for rational argument, then rational­
~ rr ~ll ·;·;~'''-T_~0
enquiry leads to a logically paradoxical finding, For instance, theoret­ ' ~' .1<JJ;;1~j,i Jity cannot be necessarily constrained by the demand to follow the
ical physicists come to agree that the only way to understand the inde­ -71,:,,) ~N
.:- f4«:~~. · . . " .
!baslc laws of logic. LogIC becomes one thing rationality uses, not the
terminacy of the position of particles is that it is neither true nor false , ~.•j~~t~~ essence of rationality itself.
that a given particle It is at location a or b. (I am not claiming that this l~ ,t;i~~t::, I don't think that my argument needs the strong claim. Even with
t', "> "i:f '"
conclusion is what is currently demanded by quantum theory.) Put ,: ~7 P:~:~!,t , th e weak claim we are left with two pressing questions which I think
i~' '~! ' ;'~ilij~'
~J ~lil~,
'.~:'!u.', .f~·.2 ~i·~ ,
146 What Philosophy 15 147

'. 'r
" my argument answers. The first is what is rationality if it is not coex­ >+::tional argument just is to provide objective reasons for belief, reasons
tensive with logic? The second is what is the role of Logic in rational­ ~~,:r' .which can include both evidence and argumentative moves .
ity? To say that it is a tool of rationality is to say too little, for it is not :;l(.;::;; Objective and hence rational arguments have a own ber of features
something we can just pick up or put down at will; it clearly has some .:::':?~~" which I will now enumerate. I would not '\.IIMt to suggest, however,
kind of force tha t we have to recognize, like it or not. I am not making • I •• :~:;}~; that this list is exhaustive. What it aims to do is describe the main
'. the popular mistake of using an apparen1.limit on logic to justify a " ' :~.:· :3':h characteristics of objective rational arguments.
wholesale rejection of it. ~~~~r(~;.,: '

The two questions, I think, only require one answer, which comes
from an understanding of wha t rationality is. The view of rationality
:'~J~r[ ' (~J Comprehensibility

''' I '''Y·;~~-
I am going to offer explains not only why logic is so important but ::; :"~"1t{; the characteristic feature of objectivity is that it moves from a par­
also why judgement is vital. For this reason the next section is prob­ ~; -,~f~:':;: ticular viewpoint to a more general one. One consequerrce of this
ably the most important part of my thesis . ,J) {~~, . tnl?ve is that the terms of explanation offered in an objective account
~. ~If~~. are in principle comprehensible by more rational agents than those
_~ ::~it ' in a subjective account, So, a physics which is in principle com pre­
The nature of rational argument ~{'~.~;i~~!!f: ".Ii. lmsible .by M~s .wbo lack the typical sensory appar~tus of
~~- , humans IS more objective than one that depends upon a particularly
I want to define rational argument as the giving of objective reasons .~~!:
human way of experiencing the world . 1 would conjecture that this
for belief. This definition is an attempt to provide a conception of ':);i~ ki n d ofincreased objectivity is a constitutive feature of rational argu­
rationality that is broad enough to encapsulate both its deductive and h ment, An argument that is in principle comprehensible by ally ra­
non-deductive aspects, and catholic enough to appeal to those who tional agent is more rational than one that is only comprehensible by
think rational argument aims at truth and to those who think there · \~:;g~kh' certain types of rational agent.
is no such thing as truth (or at least Truth). To flesh it out I need to ," ~~t'it. ~ ,.
'1" t-;'. lffii t:
~ ~~~'::t i ~?;,~.; ..
say more about what I mean by objectivity and what it comprises. ,I ~u.~.~ .. '
The conception of objectivity at work here is based on that of ¥!I~' fgJ;Assessability
, ' #o ,{(.r.,~;j'

Thomas Nagel.' Objectivity for Nagel admits of degrees, and a posi­ . ~;':': ~ It is not enough that a rational argument is comprehensible by any

';0¥.i:~ ' f·
tion is more objective the nearer it gets to the unachievable 'view (Tom 'J }'~~1§\ rational agent. It must also be assessable. This is not a crude appeal
nowhere: The value of objectivity is that it takes us away from subjec­ /
It'
f.:~~·~Yt·
.. •.
to'verificationism or falsificationism, It is not for me to legislate here
, . ~;{,~ ~

tive viewpoints which are more partial, both in the sense of reflecting ~' ~J£j! }io",: : exacuy rational arguments are to ~e ass~ed. B~t it should be
our biases and preferences and in the sense of invoking a more limited "'1;lt-St obvrous that an argument cannot be rational if there 15 no way at all
range of reasons and experiences. Because objective arguments do not .(. .Qfassessing it The only a priori restriction on the types of assessabil­
depend so much on OUf local perspectives, it is also to be hoped that .: ~iJ'~~'t,; tty, that are admissible is that they should be methods of assessment
-I: .,••:U' r. .~

they depend less on personal judgemen t, although, as I am arguing, it .~ : :\\f;;~g .W hich are in principle employable by any rational agent.

is wrong to think judgement can be altogether dispensed with. .~,: ~~;:a~i; ,'; It is worth noting here that I have now twice invoked the concept

Rationality and objectivity are usually seen as natural bedfellows. :.~ f,Hi~f of a rational agent in my explanation of what rationality is. This

I would suggest their link is more intimate than this, To offer a ra­ ," ~ I ~.
l"'':'­

;~~;w:;. might appear to be circular and in some ways it certainly is. BUI I am
1.~'. ~q~I.~\(;),
.t ui!"'l··
~r,, '!!1J : .:,~-';'
=: ._= ••~
M.O;: • .~.-!l"' ~.~. -----------------------_.
- .[,~ .. . .~~
148 What Philosophy Is
. ;~l :?:~~;;:: i;f'l
}1 '~f l,~, ~

\~ ", { ~:;{.·".Phiiosoph lC3 I Method 149


- -, .. .
,~~ " ',~~'

not sure that the circularity is vicious. A rational agent is on e who can ~;?> 'f:: 1t might seem natural here to say that my example is not a ra­
"l'

understand and assess objective arguments and an obj ective argu ­ " "': tional argument that 1+ 1=3, but simply a rational argument why it
ment is rational if it can be understood and assessed. These terms all . '\;1" '; is' prndcl1t to believe 1 + 1 =3. Because I have, for reasons already
hang together. "I' ...:,} ~lained, characterized rational argument as the providing of
. .. ~: ",~!'i; ' 'objective reasons for belief. I cannot help myself to the simple dis­

(c) Defeasibility
<:r·r,;'lL'·tinction between an argument that X is true and an argument that
,·;',::H\·r ;youshould believe that JC My distinctions need to be between differ­
• "_':':~1 \t)"1
A rational argument is always in principle defeasible (capable of . ,,;','j)'t'J:p,ent kinds of reason for belief.
being shown to be wrong) by public criteria of argument and evi­ A, ~t r\ i~I',.,;'I;" .ri'!'
li:~<t" ' J;think thi s dis"nnction can be rna de quite
. na turall yon th e b asis. 0 f
dence. I think this is just a corollary of (a) and (b), because to give a , ~~ i;f;~~;;~; tl1 e , fa ct that I am here looking for objective reasons for belief, and
'1:". , ot)'\'l~~ ~, -"
rational argument is to say that others can understand and assess it t '!~~;\Plf. reasons which appeal to my desires, values and interests are 1e5S
This leaves open the possibility that their assessment might he nega­ ~~: ;\~Wj'~Lobjective than ones which make no reference to the particuJar inter­
tive or that their understanding might be superior to one's own. It '~ :§'i~~:4)sts, values and desires of living creatures. Hence, the kinds of reasons
certainly seems ~ntrary to the spirit of rational enquiry to rule out Ci:~.({~f ;· 'ih a t serve the basis of objective, rational arguments need to be those
the possibility that what one bas decided is true could not possibly ~ ~~~:~. that I'd call interest-neutral. Any reasons which appeal to what
be false. And even if there are some indefeasible rational arguments, :~~ <~Y people desire are not interest-neutral. since they only have any pur­
they form a very narrow set of non-empirical a priori arguments. :". :~r:Ll;~ .•.chase if we. think that people's desires are a reason for doing
However, of all my criteria for the objectivity of rational argument, .~~ t~~mething.
this is the one I feel is least important "~,; I This interest-neutrality of rational argument is central, since the
<~~~~~Lwhole point of a rational argument is that it does not resist brute
~!,'I ~'J~~'l "
~(.'M~\iil~'reali ty and does not bend before will. It is important to note that this
(d) Interest-neutrality
.~ t4:~~{do es not imply any metaphysical" commitments vis-a-vis realism",
So far, what bas been admitted as the currency of objective, rational :& ~~·~~·,\ i i:lealism " and so on. In fact, it is essential that our conception of
~ '",'INt"'':' ·
discourse is a little too wide, since such reasons could include those ,,~ fi.f;~tr5):a tlonality is free from such commitments, since it is by means of
which appeal to desires. interests and values which are not ultimately ·nll!.l~ ':, ration
i''4; ;~;:'~~.'; • al argument t h at we attempt 10 determi
etemune w hi ch metap hvsical
YSI
grounded in rational arguments. For instance, in an odd circum­ of ;iW?Jf;'lstance it is appropriate to take. Accepting the resistance of an objec­
stance where a lunatic will destroy the universe unless I pass a lie :~~ ~~t,k 'ljve, rational accoun t of the world to our will is simply 3 precondi­
detector test saying that 1+ 1=3, I might be able to produce compre­ ~.;:;: ~~iijg, · tion for any rational enquiry in to the nature of that world.
.~_ ~1J~~ay~,

hensible, assessable and defeasible reasons for believing tha tl + 1 =3, ~ ,. ~;~'i!~~:

on th e basis that believing this is the only way to save the universe. ;~ f~·~";!. ;· .

}'.f; i~.·.~.' ;1~~·r.; (e) Compulsion

But this does not seem to make the belief that 1+ 1=3 objectively ~ :~~~~ ~ <l·~.
':,Yi!,\; - u­
.
rational . It makes it rational if I have a desire , interest or value which ~:~ , ~\..fu;. 11~\ lt is, however, more than possible to have a very weak argument

rr' "J~· t,l'


favours the universe continuing to exist, but this is a form of practi­ ,~, ~\~~1~t that offers comprehensible, assessable, defeasibl e and value-neutral
cal rationality, not the kind of objective rationality which is asso­ ' :~; a!~{~\J~~y, reasons for believing that X For the argument to have objective force
.\: ~i>r1.l\' ~ . . . .
ciated with what has traditionally been called the pursuit of truth. ~' J}:!.iX;/ It must ill some way be compelling. Thrned over and examined on all
:;~ . .'ij ~!jK\.~;~·
"" ~:; .&~~t ·il{'...·

r
r ·.,
~
1:.0 VV,,~t PftUosoptly Is ' phUosophlQlI Method _
151
\I~ I '·', '!,

~ f K :~.rl ,.·~
iN,·.. , ,.,~i.

sides, any rational agent that understands the argument should find l.~ -:::o for belief is to say that others sbould accept these reasons.
This means
(I . •.,'
t ~

herself forced to accept the conclusion, whether she likes it or DoL · ".',;' ," that rationality contains a normative element: it demands that we
• ,. r'(~ .•,
Furthermore, this compulsion should be a consequence only of the I.;,'tz:.',· should believe certain things.
kind of features of the argumen t already set out: i.e. the comprehen­ · , ,: ~. However, not all judgement is usually thought of as being norma­
sible, assessable and interest-neutral ones. If something else, such as ':, .k', tive. For example, if I am given a colour sample and asked to judge
personal incredulity or wishful thinking, makes someone feel they ." "'<
' , which of two other samples il is closest to, there seems to be no
are compelled to believe something, then this is not the kind of com ­ ·' ;";'j;,:::' 'ough t' implied in my judgement Bu t in the case of ration ality, when
. pulsion which is found in a rational argument, ;';::~~f
-·t1" ~ .r~
r-
:we judge that a reason provides objective grounds for belief- that is
This is plain enough, but it is very difficult to explain what makes ~:3;~;; to say, it is comprehensible, assessable, defeasible, interest-neutral
an argument compelling in this sense. It would not seem adequate to .{i-, ,~~ r.·' ' an d compellin g - IS
.6:·:~:": ' th ere r eally no kind
' 0 I" aug h t • presentr~ I d 0 not
give a psychological explanation. For the moment, I can only leave .;: ~:,f~;;Ahin.k that we can sustain this position. Making such a judgement
this requirement as a placeholder for the fuller account that is clearly {~,~~~: ~'ad~ u~ to saying that this reason h~ a claim on us: it is. a reason
needed. For now, all I need to be accepted is that a rational argument ; ~.:!~r~whi c.h.' we
~ long as Wld~rsta.nd I t, sl1;u~ ~ake us believe ~ha t
Jus.t
must have some force: its conclusions are in some sense demanded 'J .-tj~~H;F Jwe think 11 IS a reason to believe . To say this 15 a comprehensible,
by it, not merely invited.. TIlls is what I am trying to capture by use of 1~ 1}:1{'.'~[~·W . a ssessable,
". ..·:t':N;J.·
defeasible, interest-neutral and compelling reason for
the term 'compulsion'. ';~ ,;AbiY. .believing that X' is to say that you should believe that X on the
Th e demand for comprehensible, assessable, defeasible, value­ ;~~ff.' grounds of the reason offered . This is not a moral 'o ugh t'. It is rather
neutral and compelling reasons for believing that X is a tough one. l~ F~~~r rationality's own 'ought', the 'o ugh t' we recognize in statements such
So, although judgement is required at every level to construct or ., ~;~~~ is
'given the evidence, you ought to be able to see that smoking is
analyse a rational argument, to say judgement is required is not a ~·~I;:.;J<.'}&'rr iiiili eal thy "
vague way of saying that everything is up for grabs or down to per­ .r%li: .," :'.The
r.l- -;'i.f~ •
reason for this is provided by.the objective Da~ o.r r~tional
sonal inclination. A rational argument must meet certain standards ! f~~;'.e: · .arguments, Part of what makes a rational argument objective IS that
. . ~ oj ~~ '"
of objectivity and it is the existence of these standards which ~ r{~j~~})i t is compelling: in one's own case one feels one must accept it. But
ensures judgement does not have a free rein but plays a very spe ­ 4, !~:~'i
,:hU l< .
.the grounds upon which the argument is based are in principle com­
cific role. .~ ~~W,'\preb ensib l e and assessable by others. So if you feel you must accept
My account of rationality also explains why logic is such a vital . !').~~~~;' the argument, you must also feel others should. Since the grounds are
tool for rationality without being sovereign. All other things being ;, , 'f":~";W" i .
f~:if:~' also interest-neutral, it does not matter that others have different
equal, logic-preserving arguments are more objective than logic­ :; ;~iit#: . desires or preferences to you. This is irrelevant to the soundness of a
i· ·~~ih · . nal argument,
defying ones. It is just that all other things are not always equal. ',. ','J~1!.~~T• •, ratio
. ...
.~ ' : , ~r: ')i.

~1~~;r: . So rational arguments are compelling - they make us feel we


,.~ J ~~1·..'tl~; ·
,:~ t';~~~~)\ 'ough t to accept them - and they are compelling for reasons which
"'~ l' . ~\~, ~
.
,.,

The nonnativity of rationality ~~: '~~;;(t( are, in principle, equally compelling for other rational agents.
": ::?1~: . T herefore, to accept that an argument is rati.anal and ~b~ective is to
If my account of rationality is broadly correct (and it is almost cer­ : :~~,~~} accept that oneself and others ought to believe what It IS an argu­
tainly incorrect in matters of detail), then to offer objective reasons
, ,,~;:~~
,::.~ .
'''!rf,J[ ·' ment for.
i'f :I;~ ;~'i.~~l
,"~-- ~~~l ~~'t,.l""
· ~ ·+~r~;.f
_t
,.. ... "
152 What Philosophy Is ~' fl~\t')W:; ~,~ ,'PhilasophlCllI Melhod 153
·;,. Iif":" .' .

This reveals something very interesting about the place of norma­ ~ ~:.::<:.~:2f~ r objective rational arguments severely limit the range of possible
tiviry in rationality. Many have argued that rationality has a normative - ,:~· :i ..::;- 'accoun ts we can give of the world . It suggests that good judgement is
component. This is usually interpreted to mean : ,:,'., ',': ,much more than mere opinion, and something less than the mere
', J 1i'.:I:

If X is rational then one ought to believe it,


J':; " .following of logical rules. .
,:"';"i'ti~'..(. Twould like to conclude by tentatively gesturing towards five ways
Here. the normative consequent follows from a factual antece­ .;.,}i.y.' inwhich this conception of rationality might help us to explain some
dent.' Wh ether or not X is rational is a factual matter. Having estab­ .r,·,:':.::·;;· othenv ise puzzling features of philosophy.
." I .~' . '
lished that. in fact, X is rational, it is argued that we ought to believe ":{ : IJ~~1-W:'::! ~ First, f think that my characterization of rationality should be
it. .•
~t:, ~.~.;;~~it:; C q U all Y recognizable by 'analytic' and 'continental" philosophers.
However, on my account, the normativity enters into our concep­ :.; .:J~': Such resistance as there may be from either camp may have as much
.:Jl'-"r~·.~' " •

tion of rationality ear lier. This is because the antecedent is not purely :- : ti+~~ to do with my choice of words as the substance of my argumen 1.
factual . To say that X is rational requires one to make a judgement. :~fi~i~( ·\.iI t is helpful if my account of rationality explains why it is, despite
But. as I have just argued, normativiry is integral to making that j~ , !~1i1{1\\ the differences, both analytics and continentals are both basically
judgement. In judgiog that something is a sound. objective, rational t ~h~~~ 'doing philosophy. But if the account cannot help explain why, none­
argumen t one is at tile same time saying that one ought to believe i t, '}l {~I;~ theless, th~y sometimes a~pear to be d~ing quite different ~gs,.it
So it is more accurate to locate the normativi ty of rationality in the 'i':i"J",f · would be inadequate. I think the room m my account for this lies In

antecedent of a conditional formulation: , ~.~ :~t.;~!~ the acceptance that wha t counts as an objective reason for belief does
X is rational if and only if one ought to believeit because mere are objec­
.
. ~ ~ : ~~i:~ in.the end depend in part on judgement. 1 think that, on the whole,
tive reasons for doing so. '~:1. :~~~~rt ' the analytic and. con tinental ~ion is at ~east ~ part a prod~ct, not
), A~;l ~o much of a different ~onceptJon of ratJon~ty, but of a ~erent
In fact, although this formulation makes the contrast with the tra­ ;; ~~~i JUdgeme~t abo~t what .~ds of reasons are pruna.T¥' To put ~t far too
ditional view stark, it is a little misleading. It is not so much that X is ;~ :~~!~ : crudely (if not Just plain incorrectly), much continental philosophy
v' ' .'11 ~,Ji~:"

rational as a consequence of a normative judgement. It is rather that :.~ ~1:f~ ~ ' regards the data of phenomenology* as the most fruitful source of

judgement, objectivity and normativity cannot be separated. None Y; j f reasons for belief, while in the analytic tradition the analysis of con ­
bas priority over the oth ers. In order to provide a proper account of
rationality we need to appeal to all three.
}~l~
}~.~, ;
_,'.
ce~ts is ~rimary. So. i~ is not that the~e are. different conceptio~s of
rationality at work.it IS rather that rationality gels to work on differ­
4~ r,1 '1'{).~,.
~~~t"1i ent raw data: the analysis of phenomena and the analysis of concepts.
J. ~ .'~:; ' A second division my account may help explain is that between
,~:J",
Consequences !( ~r't"Ii. : those who see philosophy as being continuous with natural science
and those who do not. Here again. the distinction can be seen to cut
This view of rationality and philosophy. if correct, has important across a common conception ofrationality. Put simply, the former are
consequences for our conception of what philosophy is. It shows how much more impressed by natural science thao the latter and therefore
it is possible to abandon the idea that truth in philosophy is entirely believe that our most objective reasons for belief are grounded in
determined by objective facts and logic without necessarily embra­ natural science . If this is so. then there may often be no deep disagree­
cing total relativism. since the strong constraints on the requirements ment between the two camps about the nature of philosophy.
~~~;1 '
,,,,,,~, ;
I~ ··p't .~ ..
154 What Philosophy Is ,'::~~'*,I;Philosoph lal Mfthod $TATE OFll-lEART 155
:'1'~~~~\1 Jf~·~Z" -'
A third puzzle about philosophy is why philosophers get so very ~- Z::(~~;· a Ccep tan c e that rational argument does not lead linearly to only one
, . ,:. 101(-,../,.

worked up about their arguments and ideas. Philosophy has a repu- : ·~i~}}y:. answer, since you cannot take judgement away from rationality. Our
tation as a dry discipline, but we all know from experience that ." L~f[~".f· reliance on
, '. ,;:,if.... ..:; ,•
~
rationality as our sole resource makes US both rigorous
people care passionately abou t their arguments and ideas. There may :7. '~;.t1J1:'" thinkers and condemned ultimately to use our own best judgement
be many reasons for this. I want to suggest one of them, which is that !d ~~~~i;: ;; .L Understanding how it is that philosophy demands the rigour of
-_when we think we have a rational argument for X we inescapably -, .\ 't';lWr rational argument, but that rational argument itself demands the use
think that others should believe it This is only mitigated by the .~. ~~"i':'!HI~J!.. of.judgement, helps us understand why it is that philosophy pushes
.' :,:~" t~ \'r' "
strength of our conviction that the argument works and our own :: ; :,;"i:~~~t - us so hard intellectually yet cannot compel equally intelligent think-
" , f",I'"
belief in the defeasibility of what is being put forward. These are the : ;!-~ AN~t ds to agree.
. C~?,l. ' ''' ,..._,,,
reins that hold in our otherwise unavoidable belief that others ought
to agree with us.
A fourth problem of philosophy is how there can be radical dis-
agreement without it being possible to definitively pinpoint an error
which shows one side is wrong. Such. is the case with idealism and
realism, for example. If philosophy required no judgements, the exis-
tence of these kinds of radical disagreements would be puzzling. I
would suggest that it is precisely because rational argument ulti-
mately depends on judgements rather than logical algorithms that
the existence of such disagreements is Dot only comprehensible but
probably inevitable.
:,.
The final odd feature of philosophy that I think my account helps
to explain is how it is both the most rigorous discipline in its employ-
ment of arguments but also one of the most indeterminate in respect
Philosophy as Nomadism
of its findings. Consensus is omniabsent in philosophy yet the argu-
ments of philosophers are among the most rationally rigorous in the Simon Glendinning
humanities or the sciences.
I think my account helps makes sense of this because it shows how
rationality is highly rigorous both in its demand for objective reasons Everyday aporia
[or belief and in the way deductive logic is one of its most powerful
tools. But unlike the natural sciences, the raw data of philosophy is Karl Popper hated the idea, the idea he associated closely with
not quantifiable data from empirical experiment. It is rather the Wittgenstein*, that philosophy might be concerned only with
whole of human experience. Philosophy also lacks the set tled, agreed 'puzzles;' One can certainly sympathize. Wittgenstein's way of
methods of a science that enables consensus. Philosophy, then, relies coming to terms with, or at least on occasion finding an English
entirely on rationality and nothing but. This involves a high degree expression for, his understanding of the natur: of philosophical
of commitment to the rigours of argument but also, ultimately, an problems seems only to trivialize them, reducing them to difficulties

You might also like