Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

The
Baheyeld
Dynasty
The journey for wisdom starts with knowledge
Home About Site Map Contact

George Saliba: Seeking the Origins of Modern Science?

Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba

Submitted by Khalid on Sun, 2004/03/07 - 14:40

Essay, Exchange of Views, I


Toby E. Huff
The Rise of Early Modern Science:
A Reply to George Saliba (1)

Copyright © 2002 Royal Institute for Inter-Faith Studies. All rights reserved. BRIIFS vol. 4 no 2, 2002.
Republished on Baheyeldin.com by permission of Dr. Saliba.

Use the menus on the right, or at the bottom of this page, to read the original article, or Dr. Saliba's reply to this
response.

Read George Saliba's original article, and Dr. Saliba's response to the reply.

An author, such as myself, can only be grateful when a leading historian of Arabic science takes one of his
books so seriously as to write a long review article on it. Professor George Saliba calls The Rise of Early
Modern Science: Islam, China and the West a refreshing and welcome contribution to the field documenting . . .
a whole array of the achievements of Arabic/Islamic (and Chinese) science in the ongoing project of modern
science (143, 144). At the same time, Professor Saliba raises a host of issues, not all of equal importance, nor
even connected to the main thesis of my book. In this reply, I shall present my comments under four headings
with the intention of making the themes and thesis of my book evident to the reader. These headings address the
main issues raised in Saliba’s essay, namely, the nature of ‘modern’ science, the possibility that economic
factors have played a significant role in its rise, innovation in Arabic/Islamic astronomy after Ibn al-Shatir and
We use cookies on this site to enhance your user experienceBy
the fourteenth century, and the nature and role of free inquiry. OK, I agree No, thanks
clicking any link on this page you are giving your consent for us to set
cookies. No, give me more info

https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 1/17
8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

At the outset, one must say that there is a defensiveness in Professor Saliba’s essay, which, as it unfolds,
repeatedly begs the question that was at the centre of my original inquiry. In addition, Saliba rather surprisingly
opposes the idea that past and present human communities, institutions, governments and so on ought to grant
greater freedom of expression, inquiry and action to their participants. This is surely counter-intuitive.

Saliba gets started on the wrong track by labeling the study of the rise of ‘modern’ science as the search for
origins, a term I never use. Throughout my book, I suggest that the propensity to look into the nature of
existence and to propose explanations for it is universal. If we start with that assumption, then we can focus
upon the beginnings that people made in various places around the world to construct proto-scientific theories
and explanations. Clearly, some groups, communities, societies and civilizations have been more successful than
others in this process and the question then becomes one of analyzing contrasting cultural and institutional
settings that either encouraged or impeded the progress of scientific inquiry.

My particular inquiry began with what I called the ‘problem’ of Arabic science, namely, the intellectual question
of how it happened that scholars communicating mainly in Arabic excelled in scientific inquiries during certain
periods of time and, yet, failed to continue those inquires so that there was a decline, indeed, such a steep and
long-lasting decline that people in later centuries might conclude that the ‘Arabs’ had never been masters of
science.(2) I submit that this is a fascinating and vexatious intellectual problem. It is also obvious that dozens of
Middle Eastern scholars and observers have agonized over this puzzle and sought to understand it for a very
long time.

Moreover, in my book, I reviewed the most impressive advances in astronomy and mathematics that were
accomplished by Middle Eastern scholars by the end of the fourteenth century; in later chapters, I also recounted
a number of achievements in medicine. Then, I asked why this development did not lead to ‘modern’ science in
the Arabic/Islamic context. It is curious that Professor Saliba does not want to acknowledge that this is an
intellectual puzzle worthy of intense study. For, as he himself points out in his review, Arabic science was
superior to Western science (140) prior to the Renaissance. He even claims that the most innovative
mathematical and astronomical ideas that were employed during the European Renaissance were themselves
borrowed from Arabic/ Islamic civilization.(3) If these great advances were the very ideas that made the
astronomy of the European Renaissance possible, in the mathematical technical sense, (143) why did they not
make it possible in the Arabic/Islamic context? Indeed, the first four pages of Saliba’s review, with their
apparent emphasis on ‘methodological’ issues, serve no purpose other than to avoid facing this central problem.
Stated differently, it is claimed by Saliba that certain advances in astronomy in Arabic lands made modern
astronomy possible in Europe, but apparently not in the Middle East. This is surely an intellectual problem
worth investigating, one that goes far beyond his methodological diversions.

In so far as astronomy is concerned, conventional wisdom says that the breakthrough to modern astronomy
occurred with the appearance of Nicholas Copernicus’ The Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres in 1543. This
was the book in which the author proposed abandoning the geocentric orientation of the celestial system in
favour of a heliocentric one. It was revolutionary not only in this astronomical sense, but in that it challenged the
We use cookies on this site to enhance your user experienceBy
authority of the Christian Church. Copernicus (who was a Church administrator OK, Ihimself)
agree and
No, his
thanks
followers thus
clicking any link on this page you are giving your consent for us to set
claimed to know the composition of the universe better than the official Church hierarchy. This is a perfectly
cookies. No, give me more info

https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 2/17
8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

good landmark for establishing the advent of modern science, as it unleashed a whole series of intellectual
struggles within the scientific community and within the established religious authority of Europe. Furthermore,
it is obvious that the work of Galileo directly derived from Copernicus’ great hypothesis and it was he who
bluntly challenged the Church on virtually all epistemological grounds, claiming that there was a source of
knowledge about the world other than religion and the Bible?namely, natural science.

My book focuses upon the preceding legal, institutional and intellectual developments that made the Copernican
innovation possible. That is, long before Copernicus and Galileo, there was an intellectual tradition established
in Europe, above all in the universities, that, yes, institutionalized the study of natural phenomena, particularly
by placing the corpus of Aristotle, along with a number of Arabic works and commentaries, at the centre of the
university curriculum. This occurred in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries. In short, the Copernican revolution
was a product of the educational system put in place by Europeans several hundred years earlier. As is well-
known, the madrasas of the Middle Eastern world systematically excluded philosophy and the natural sciences
from any ‘formal’ teaching conducted within their confines during this period of time. (I put ‘formal’ in
quotation marks because there was no formal curriculum in the madrasas.) Evidently, the teaching of philosophy
and the natural sciences ran against the religious commitments and identity of the madrasas, an identity that
persisted into the twentieth century.(4) This was a major issue in my book, but Professor Saliba is entirely silent
on the subject. I shall return to it later. Whether or not Copernicus benefited directly from Arab astronomers,
other than possibly borrowing ‘the Tusi couple,’ remains an open question, one upon which I remain to be
convinced.(5)

The highly significant Copernican year of 1543 also contains another milestone in the rise of modern science:
the publication of Vesalius’ nonpareil, On the Fabric of the Human Body. This famous work, containing a huge
number of highly-detailed anatomical drawings, is generally regarded as laying the foundations for modern
medicine because of its illustrations of the human body’s main systems?bones, muscles, veins, nerves and
internal organs. At the same time, it represents the expression of an empirical agenda, the first-hand examination
of the body through human dissection (autopsy). This was the culmination of several centuries of empirical
anatomical investigation extending back to the twelfth and thirteenth centuries. As we know, human dissection
was generally considered to be forbidden in Islamic thought and practice, mainly, it seems, because it was seen
as a form of ‘mutilation’ that was forbidden by various legal texts.(6) Briefly, then, this is another area in which
we may point to a new spirit of inquiry (and routinized activity) that encouraged modern science. It broke with
various intellectual and moral traditions of the past and subjected various claims to empirical testing. And again,
unlike the madrasas, the universities incorporated medical training, including the practice of human dissection,
into their curricula.

In an effort to deflect the reader from focusing upon these disparities between the progressive nature of modern
science and the stagnating nature of scientific thought in the Arabic/Islamic context, Saliba cites a comment
from A. C. Graham to the effect that we cannot know whether the ancients or the moderns have come closer to
scientific truth. Yet, it should not escape our attention that Copernicus and Galileo did argue about the truth of
their workWeor,use
at cookies
least, about which
on this site set ofyour
to enhance hypothetical constructions, those of the geocentric or the heliocentric
user experienceBy
OK, I agree No, thanks
system, better described
clicking the
any link on thisworld. Despite
page you Saliba’s
are giving role for
your consent as us
devil’s
to set advocate, I think that we can fairly conclude

cookies. No,
that heliocentrism is give me more
a better info
description of the world and that, although the Copernican system is not a complete
https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 3/17
8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

and final theory, it is a better approximation of the celestial movements than the geocentric view. ‘Science,’ as I
understand it, entails this element of seeking to arrive at a better description of the world and is not just a
calculating device.

Similarly, the anatomical drawings of Vesalius and his discussion of all the parts and systems of the body are, in
fact, a better description of the human body than the one provided by Galen. Indeed, Vesalius claimed to have
corrected over 200 errors in Galen’s account of human anatomy, which was based almost wholly upon animal
dissections. Moreover, Vesalius’ illustrations are far superior to anything to be found in the Arabic/Islamic
tradition (where pictorial representation of the human body was particularly suspect) or, for that matter, in the
Chinese and (I presume) Indian traditions.(7) This is not to sound a note of triumph, but rather to clarify the
point that modern science represents scientific progress, a point that Saliba seeks to obscure. Thus, Saliba is
correct to say that no one seems to question the proposition that the ‘modern’ scientific tradition made its first
appearance in the West (140), a term that he finds problematic, which I grant, in part. This is so because there is
a scholarly consensus on this point and it comes after at least a century of intense exploration of the historical
records of other sciences and civilizations, above all the Arabic and the Chinese traditions.

A year after my book was first published, Professor Saliba published an article about the sixteenth-century
astronomer, Shams al-Din al-Khafri (d. 1550).(8) According to Saliba, Khafri was a figure of creative continuity
in Arab astronomy and he?and perhaps others of that period?represented a new ‘golden age’ of Arab astronomy,
not a period of decline. On the basis of this, Saliba suggests that all that I say in my book on this subject,
especially the idea of decline in Arab astronomy, has to be reassessed (148). Saliba makes many other claims in
this connection, most of which I consider excessive.

Although I have no special training in astronomy and the jury is still out among historians of science regarding
Saliba’s claims, the suggestion that Khafri was a progressive innovative astronomer, given the fact that he
apparently sought to preserve and perfect the Ptolemaic system, seems highly improbable. As suggested above,
the Copernican model was a progressive new model that brought us closer to the true constitution of the
universe than the Ptolemaic system. As A. I. Sabra put it, speaking of Khafri’s work, it would be odd to call
‘revolutionary’ a reformist project intended to consolidate Ptolemaic astronomy by bringing it into line with its
own principles.(9) Saliba’s effort to take refuge in the argument that, without a theory of universal gravitation,
this new cosmology (of Copernicus) could not be developed (150) is counterfactual. As Noel Swerdlow says,
Kepler went far beyond Ptolemy’s methods, and discovered entirely new principles for the precise description of
the motions of bodies in the heavens based upon an entirely new physics.(10) The new Copernican theory was
fleshed out by a variety of astronomers who followed, above all by Kepler. It was he who proved the elliptical
(and hence not perfectly circular) orbit of Mars and related astronomical theorems on the basis of the
assumption that the sun was the approximate centre of our universe. He was also aided by the more exact
observations of Tycho Brahe. The absence of a universal theory of gravitation until the time of Newton was no
impediment to the early adopters of Copernicanism and even Tycho Brahe, who developed a geo-heliocentric
model, was not stymied by this putative absence, even after he discovered that the planets were not encased in
‘crystalline’
We spheres.
use cookiesThis came
on this site toabout with
enhance yourthe
userobservation
experienceBy of the comets of 1577 and 1585, whose trajectories
OK, I agree No, thanks
took themclicking
through anywhat would
link on have
this page you been the your
are giving ambiguously understood
consent for us to set ‘crystalline’ spheres of Venus and
Mercury. To No, give
be sure,
cookies. me more
he was not a info
committed follower of Copernicus, but he was willing to entertain a theory
https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 4/17
8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

that entailed a partially heliocentric orientation and without the possibility of crystalline spheres holding the
planets in place.

In a word, the absence of a universal theory of gravitation offered no impediment to Copernicus himself, nor to
his student Rheticus, nor to Galileo, Maestlin, Kepler, Tycho Brahe, Christoph Rothmann and the other
Copernicans. Thus, rather than showing how Europeans might have been held back from pursuing all of the
implications of the new Copernican hypothesis, Saliba’s comments make us wonder all the more just why Arab
astronomers, who were, according to Saliba, experiencing a golden age (Khafri died only seven years after
Copernicus), were so reluctant to advance bold new theories, theories that would break with the unworkable
Ptolemaic model. At the same time, the wide discussion?pro and con?of the new Copernican hypothesis over all
of Europe points again to the fact that the study of modern science, especially astronomy, had been
institutionalized, that is, that it had been made a regular and acceptable part of public discussion (and teaching)
in universities, royal courts and so on. This stands in contrast to the situation in the madrasas of the
Arab/Muslim lands.

Before taking up the putative role of economic factors, I want to consider the issue of ‘neutral space’ and free
inquiry. It is most puzzling that Saliba rejects these ideas so vehemently, discussing them no less than six times
in as many pages. In my book, I argued that the twelfth and thirteenth centuries witnessed a social, intellectual
and legal revolution that laid the intellectual and institutional foundations upon which modern science was later
constructed. At the heart of this development was the jurisprudential idea of a corporation, a collection of
individuals who were recognized as a singular ‘whole body’ and granted legitimate legal autonomy.

Such entities were given the right to sue and be sued, to buy and sell property, to make rules and laws regulating
their activities, to adjudicate those laws and to operate according to the principle of election by consent as well
as the Roman legal aphorism, what affects everyone should be considered and approved by everyone. Among
the entities granted status as legitimate corporations were cities and towns, charitable organizations, professional
guilds (especially of physicians) and, of course, universities. Nothing comparable to this kind of legal autonomy
emerged in China or under Islam. In short, the European medievals created autonomous, self-governing
institutions of higher learning and then imported into them a methodologically powerful and metaphysically rich
cosmology that directly challenged and contradicted many aspects of the traditional Christian world-view. This
disinterested agenda was no longer a private, personal, or idiosyncratic preoccupation, but involved a shared set
of texts, questions, commentaries and, in some cases, centuries-old expositions of unsolved physical and
metaphysical questions that set the highest standards of intellectual inquiry. Through the incorporation of
Aristotle’s books on natural science into the curriculum of the medieval universities, a disinterested agenda of
naturalistic inquiry was institutionalized. It was institutionalized as a curriculum, a course of study.(11)

Since these bodies were, in fact, legally entitled to study and teach whatever they elected to make part of the
curriculum, one could say that they occupied a neutral zone protected by and from political and religious
authorities. At the centre of their curriculum was the main body of Aristotle’s natural philosophy, that is, his
Physics, On the Heavens, On Generation and Corruption, On the Soul, Meteorology and Small Works on
We use cookies on this site to enhance your user experienceBy
OK,and
Natural Things, and biology, such as his History of Animals, Parts of Animals I agree No, thanks
Generation of Animals. It is
clicking any link on this page you are giving your consent for us to set
in these books, as Professor Edward Grant argues, that we find the treatises that formed the comprehensive
cookies. No, give me more info

https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 5/17
8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

foundation for the medieval conception of the physical world and its operation.(12) In contrast to this, the
Islamic madrasas deliberately excluded all of the natural works of Aristotle, as well as philosophy, logic and
natural theology. Instead, they taught the ‘Islamic sciences,’ consisting of the Qur’an, the Sunna, Islamic law,
Arabic poetry, literature, history and genealogy, and some arithmetic. (Later, they did admit the teaching of logic
and Islamic theology.) Furthermore, in Europe (for example, in Paris), the study of the Aristotelian corpus was
fully legitimized by statute in 1255, although it remained in dispute. As a result, the universities generated a
whole literature of naturalistic questions that became, in turn, a shared agenda of naturalistic studies. Centred
upon Aristotelian natural philosophy, this agenda served as the intellectual core of university instruction for the
next 400 years (including the education of Copernicus, Galileo, Kepler and others).

Speculative questions were pursued, such as whether the world is singular or plural; whether the earth turns on
its axis or is stationary; whether every effecting thing is the cause of that which it is effecting; whether things
can happen by chance; whether a vacuum is possible; whether the natural state of an object is stationary or in
motion; whether luminous celestial bodies are hot; whether the sea has tides; and so on for virtually every
charted field of enquiry.(13) Surely, the permissibility of these studies in an officially-recognized and legally-
defined context suggests something more than a random, spasmodic pursuit of the natural sciences and
something more than the pursuit of economic gain. I submit that they also indicate the existence of a very
significant intellectual zone of free inquiry that was publicly available to scholars, as well as laymen. The
continuity of this ongoing, university-centred debate with respect to Copernicus’ heliocentric hypothesis has
recently been reiterated. As Bernard Goldstein puts it, Copernicus’ initial commitment to heliocentrism was a
response to an issue debated in the philosophical community at the time when he attended universities in Italy,
ca. 1500.(14)

At least three additional points need to be made. The legal autonomy that existed in the European universities
did not exist in the Muslim world because the legal concept of a corporation, a groups of actors treated as a
collective whole, did not exist. This legal defect had major implications for Islamic civilization, not least in the
sphere of economic development, as Timor Kuran has made clear.(15)

Second, it is one thing if an activity is pursued randomly by various actors; it is something else altogether if that
activity is carried on collectively as a result of a regularized process?that is, an institutionalization of the activity
by the enactment of rules, norms and regulations. Clearly, the pursuit of science in Europe via its
institutionalization in the universities provided it with a powerful advantage unknown in the Arab/Muslim world
until very recently.(16)

Third, this institutionalization of scientific pursuits gave European scholars a surprising degree of freedom of
inquiry, not least of all to subject the Holy Book?the Bible?to naturalistic explanation. As I argued in my book,
some scholarly clerics actually sought to separate the ‘natural’ from the ‘supernatural’ in an attempt to explain
by naturalistic means certain problematic passages in the Bible. For example, a certain Andrew of St. Victor
argued that one should first consider all naturalistic possibilities before offering miracles as explanations in the
interpretation of Scripture. The interpreter, he wrote, should realize this: in expounding Scripture, when the
We use cookies on this site to enhance your user experienceBy
event described admits of no naturalistic explanation, then and only then should OK, Iwe
agree No, thanks
have recourse to miracles.
clicking any link on this page you are giving your consent for us to set
(17) Scholars have pointed to such discussions during this period of time as the beginning of so-called ‘Higher
cookies. No, give me more info

https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 6/17
8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

Criticism,’ the intellectual task of evaluating all of the strands, sources and meanings of the Judaeo-Christian
scriptures. I submit that this level of freedom of inquiry did not exist in the Arab/Muslim world then and does
not exist now. Anyone who has had contact with Muslim circles in the West or elsewhere in the world knows
that this subject is one of utmost sensitivity to the Muslim community. H. A. R. Gibb gives the example of an
Egyptian shaykh who published, in 1930, an annotated edition of the Qur’an that criticized the old
commentaries and interpreted supernatural references in simple, naturalistic ways. Although the purpose of the
work was to encourage the younger generation to study the Qur’an, the book was confiscated by the police and
an injunction was secured to prevent the writer from preaching or holding religious meetings.(18) This sort of
response is what I meant when I wrote of the barriers to freedom of thought, expression, and action in the
interests of primordial religious and ethnic identities, but which Saliba apparently doubts (145). Today, one
could also add the various restrictions on internet use in various parts of the world to indicate such restrictions.
(More on which below.)

While there are always some constraints on intellectual inquiry, I am not as jaundiced as Professor Saliba who
seems to believe that free inquiry is essentially a fiction determined, for the most part, by the exigencies of the
market place (144). This sad commentary takes us back to the putative role of economic factors that constitutes
Saliba’s pet theory.

I have suggested that the breakthrough to modern astronomy (with all its implications) and the anatomical
investigations of European medical students are constitutive of modern science.(19) But what, we might ask,
was the economic motive of Copernicus, Galileo, Kepler, Tycho Brahe and all the others, to fashion the new
astronomy? I don’t know of any. There was no profit to be made by their inquiries, which elicited?especially in
the early stages?the wrath of traditionalists and even religious authorities. Likewise, what was the economic
motive of all those physicians from the thirteenth through sixteenth centuries who carried out and documented
anatomical inquiries based upon dissection? Although Church authorities approved of this practice and, in at
least two cases, ordered autopsies for forensic purposes, it must be said that human dissection is repulsive to
most people. Moreover, these practitioners were hardly in a position to perform new surgical procedures upon
live subjects, for which they might expect remuneration. Finally, medieval medical practice had been such as to
stigmatize those who used their hands in the practice of medicine; this is why some forms of surgery and,
especially, human dissection had previously been given over to barbers and uneducated folk. This was a custom
that Vesalius specifically rejected in his master-work. In general, there was no application for this new
knowledge, although a certain prestige probably accrued to those who had an intimate knowledge of human
anatomy.

The capstone of this whole line of inquiry was William Harvey’s discovery, in the early seventeenth century, of
the greater circulation of blood throughout the body. But that knowledge did not lead to major changes in
surgical procedures until the twentieth century, when blood types and a whole range of other discoveries made
transfusions, for example, possible. It seems more plausible to say, as Roger French has, that the knowledge of
anatomy gained by the medieval and early modern physicians allowed them to argue with each other over the
makeup ofWetheusebody and
cookies on to
thisdisprove various
site to enhance your medical authorities, especially Galen,
user experienceBy who may
OK, I agree
have got it wrong.
No, thanks
(20) clicking any link on this page you are giving your consent for us to set

cookies. No, give me more info

https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 7/17
8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

If we push back the institutionalizing of naturalistic inquiry to the medieval universities of the twelfth and
thirteenth centuries, I am again baffled as to how this might be interpreted as an expression of powerful
economic forces. It is the implicit crude Marxism of Professor Saliba’s assertion that clouds vision here. As
indicated in my book, there was indeed a ‘commercial revolution’ sweeping Europe from about the twelfth
century, but that hardly explains the great interest in Aristotle in the universities of that period or the decision by
medical practitioners to undertake dissections and to incorporate medical education into the university
curriculum. Similarly, there was another rise in commercial activities in the sixteenth century, but this hardly
explains either the motivation of the clerical Copernicus, or of Galileo, Kepler, or Tycho Brahe in developing a
new astronomy against the interests of the Church.

Finally, I offer some comments about the general role of science in society?a role about which Saliba is highly
skeptical. Indeed, Saliba’s essay is replete with disparaging remarks about science and its utility, not to mention
the benefits of freedom of expression. It is my view that scientific inquiry includes not just the natural sciences,
but all of the social sciences. It is not unreasonable to suppose that the social sciences? economics, political
science, psychology and sociology?have added something to our understanding about how governments and
economies work. Social and economic development are not aided solely by scientific production, as Saliba
proposes (146), but by a vast array of insights drawn from the social sciences concerning, for instance, the
nature of labour and financial markets, the role of technology and other factors in production, and social and
political processes. It should also be obvious that the social sciences (and the natural sciences) cannot function
properly in societies where there is great secrecy, where all information is considered the unique purview of the
government, where permission must be received from state officials before any surveys or related inquiries may
be carried out, and where there are prohibitions against the release of such information. Nevertheless, Saliba is
of the opinion that (i)t is foolhardy to urge underdeveloped countries to adopt the imagined benefits of such
slogans as ‘freedom of thought and expression’ in order to obtain the golden key to modernity assumed to be so
intrinsically embedded in the processes of modern science (146). This is such a counter-intuitive claim that I
leave it for others to defend. More neutral observers will have noticed that the recently released Arab Human
Development Report 2002, sponsored by the United Nations and written entirely by Arab scholars, specifically
points to the lack of freedom as one of three major factors holding back development in Arab societies.(21)
What is needed is a great enlargement of what many would call the public sphere (and I called neutral space),
that zone of interaction in which public and private needs and aspirations merge, so that new alternatives to
prevailing ideas and policies may be proposed, discussed and evaluated without fear of personal harm. The
prevailing inhibition of the free flow of information, scientific and non-scientific, in the Arab world is
dramatically highlighted by the authors of the Arab development report when they estimate that Spain translates
more books in a single year than have been translated into Arabic since the beginning of the Arabic/Islamic era.

This brings me to Saliba’s objection to my suggestion that science is especially the natural enemy of
authoritarian regimes (145). If we begin with the assumption that the social sciences have a place alongside the
‘hard’ sciences, then it seems evident that authoritarian regimes in general cannot maintain their grip on power
while allowing free rein to economists, sociologists, political scientists, or environmentalists. Their national
We use cookies on this site to enhance your user experienceBy
accounts simply will not balance and they know it. Hence, they routinely crack OK,down
I agreeuponNo, thanks
those who offer
clicking any link on this page you are giving your consent for us to set
accounts of the way things are that differ from the official line. I am not aware of the tremendous achievements
cookies. No, give me more info

https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 8/17
8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

of science during the Nazi regime. If one considers the highly-developed state of scientific knowledge in
Germany prior to the Nazi takeover and then compares it with the results achieved by the end of the regime, its
scientific achievements seem unimpressive. Hundreds, if not thousands, of highly trained scientists fled Nazi
Germany?to the great benefit of the United States and England, among others. Recently, a great debate has
broken out over the fact that the Nazis were unable to develop the atomic bomb, despite considerable effort. The
Nazis did carry out a large number of absolutely horrendous medical experiments on human subjects who lost
their lives in the process. I would not count this as a tremendous achievement, although it is true that some of
the information gathered is unique, precisely because of the inhumanity involved in its collection. Nothing I
have written discounts the possibility that totalitarian regimes may embark upon some grand research project for
nationalistic purposes and actually be quite successful for a time. On the other hand, I believe all such regimes
are doomed and that, in the final accounting, their scientific achievements are likely to be marginal.

Soviet Russia was, perhaps, the most successful of such regimes but, in the end, it did collapse, exposing all of
the social, economic and environmental damage that it had done. A not insignificant point seems to be that such
a regime was only able to persist so long as it maintained a very large repressive apparatus, stifling dissent
(people like the physicist Andre Sakharov and hundreds of others) and preventing disinterested inquiry into its
economic and ecological problems, patterns of governance and so on. Indeed, Manuel Castells has made a good
case for the proposition that the Soviet Empire collapsed precisely because it could no longer control
information in a computer age, with the result that significant numbers of citizens, including crucial members of
the power structure, called for radical reform.(22)

But let me add one final example of a global scientific movement that is clearly not motivated by greed,
anticipated remuneration, national aggrandizement, or the exigencies of the market place: the international
environmental movement. It is evident that there is presently a global view according to which the environment
can and must be treated as a single system of natural processes. It is also evident that this point of view was
created and shaped by natural scientists who carried out the studies illustrating this fact. And, third, it is now
evident that preserving the environment costs money. The champions of environmentalism wish to show that
preserving the environment is in the global interest, but the irreducible fact is that the human community, and,
hence, all nation-states, will have to pay financially and in terms of economic development for the apparently
long-term interests revealed by science. Scientists and sympathetic laymen have rallied to the cause, in effect
creating a global environmental movement complete with all sorts of international treaties and organizations, the
objective being what some call a global institution dedicated to preserving the environment.(23) Moreover, this
movement began in the nineteenth century and continued to strengthen throughout the twentieth and now the
twenty-first.(24) This is as good an example of ‘free inquiry’ being carried out in the service of the human
community as one can find. It clearly shows that scientists investigate natural phenomena with a view to
improving more than the financial bottom line. This is not so say that vested interests, for example, chemical
and pharmaceutical companies, have never paid scientists to pursue scientific questions that have purely
commercial applications for those interests. It is only to say that the claim that all free inquiry is just a fiction
supporting the market-place is greatly exaggerated. I continue to believe in the possibility and the necessity of
We use cookies on this site to enhance your user experienceBy
OK, I agree
dispassionate inquiry?of the past as of the present?for the purpose of better understanding No,
howthanks
the world came
clicking any link on this page you are giving your consent for us to set
to be the way it is and, not least of all, for making the future better than the past.
cookies. No, give me more info

https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 9/17
8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

Notes
1. George Saliba, Seeking the Origins of Modern Science? Bulletin of the Royal Institute for Inter-Faith
Studies 1, no. 2 (1999) : 139-152, a review article on Toby E. Huff, The Rise of Early Modern Science:
Islam, China and the West (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993). The revised second edition of
The Rise of Early Modern Science will be published in the spring of 2003.
2. The reader should note that, in my book, I stated clearly that I used the term ‘Arab’ to refer collectively
to the whole range of people from diverse ethnic groups throughout the broader Middle East. For the
purposes of my study, this common identity was based upon the language they employed, not ethnic
identity in the strict sense. From my point of view, science is always a civilizational undertaking produced
through the cooperation of individuals from diverse societies and communities who share, nonetheless, an
identity on the highest levels, especially regarding religion and law.
3. I am omitting comments on Chinese science in the main text here for simplicity’s sake. I should say,
however, that I think Saliba greatly exaggerates the contributions and influence of Chinese science, above
all its putative influence on the West. As I pointed out in my book (especially chapters seven and eight),
Joseph Needham, in his many volumes on Chinese science and technology, says that there were no Chinese
precursors to Galileo in the area of physics; similarly, Chinese optics was not as advanced as Arabic optics
under Ibn al-Haytham; and, clearly, Chinese astronomy lagged severely behind the level of Arabic
astronomy, as it lacked its geometrical foundation. In addition, trigonometry, which has generally been
conceded to have been an ‘Arab’ invention, was absent in Chinese mathematics. Consequently, no one has
ever shown?and surely not Joseph Needham?that Chinese science had any impact on the disciplines in the
West known as physics, astronomy, optics, or upon the mathematics of the Renaissance. Moreover, Chinese
medicine has been studied by some historians of science, contrary to Saliba’s suggestion, and Needham, for
example, has had many things to say about it. However, it is also true that the Chinese rarely practiced
human dissection so that they were unable to make significant contributions to the fundamental medical
science of anatomy.
4. English readers are familiar with three major studies of the madrasas based upon original Arabic sources:
George Makdisi, The Rise of Colleges: Institutions of Learning in Islam and the West (Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press, 1981); Jonathan Berkey, The Transmission of Knowledge in Medieval Cairo:
A Social History of Islamic Education (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992); and Michael
Chamberlain, Knowledge and Social Practice in Medieval Damascus, 1190-1350 (New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1994).
5. I say this after having read the fascinating recent study by F. Jamail Ragep, Tusi and Copernicus: The
Earth’s Motion in Context, Science in Context 14, nos. 1-2 (2001) : 145-163. The similarity of arguments
regarding the possible daily axial rotation of the Earth in the writings of Copernicus and many other writers
extending back to the Greeks?and including many Muslim astronomers?provides evidence not only of
possible influence, but more strongly of the often simultaneous, independent, and multiple discovery of
major ideas in the history of science. Hundreds of such cases have been documented by William F. Ogburn
(in theWe1920s) andonRobert
use cookies this siteMerton (inyour
to enhance theuser
1960s); for this literature and discussion, see The Rise of Early
experienceBy
OK, I agree No, thanks
Modern Science,
clicking 149-51.
any link In the
on this page you present
are givingcontext, I can
your consent for recall
us to setthree independent discoveries of the physical

cookies. No, give me more info

https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 10/17
8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

explanation of the rainbow?by Theodoric of Freiburg (ca. 1304), by al-Shirazi and by Kamal al-Din al
Farisi (ca. 1310).
6. I have discussed these issues in Attitudes towards Dissection in the History of European and Arabic
Medicine, in Science: Locality and Universality, ed. Bennacer El Bouazzati (Rabat, Morocco: Mohamed V
University, 2002), 1-26; and also in the revised edition of The Rise of Early Modern Science.
7. For the Asian tradition regarding dissection, see Saki Shizu, Concepts of Anatomy in Traditional Chinese
and Japanese Medicine, in History of Traditional Medicine: Proceedings of the 1st and 2nd International
Symposia on the Comparative Study of Medicine: East and West, ed. Teizo Ogawa (Osaka: Division of
Medical History, the Taniguchi Foundation, 1986), 287-302.
8. George Saliba, A Sixteenth-Century Arabic Critique of Ptolemaic Astronomy: The Work of Shams al-
Din al-Khafri, Journal for the History of Astronomy 25 (1994) : 15-38.
9. A. I. Sabra, Configuring the Universe: Aporetic, Problem Solving, and Kinematic Modeling as Themes
of Arabic Astronomy, Perspectives on Science 6, no. 3 (1998) : 322. For Saliba’s response and Sabra’s
reply, see George Saliba, Arabic versus Greek Astronomy: A Debate over the Foundation of Science,
Perspectives on Science 8, no. 4 (2000) : 328-41 and A. I. Sabra, Reply to Saliba, Perspectives on Science
8, no. 4 (2000) : 342-45.
10. Noel M. Swerdlow, Astronomy in the Renaissance, in Astronomy before the Telescope, ed. Christopher
Walker (London: British Museum, 1996), 187 and 214ff.
11. The material in this and the following paragraphs is taken from my book, The Rise of Early Modern
Science, 187-89 and 335-338.
12. Edward Grant, Science and the Medieval University, in Rebirth, Reform, and Resilience: Universities in
Transition, 1350-1770, eds. James Kittelson and Pamela Transue (Columbus: Ohio State University Press,
1984), 78. After the publication of my book, Ed Grant considerably expanded his analysis of science in the
medieval universities; see Edward Grant, The Foundations of Modern Science in the Middle Ages
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
13. See Edward Grant, ed., A Source Book in Medieval Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1974), 199-200; and Grant, Science and the Medieval University, 82ff. In his impressive study,
Planets, Stars, and Orbs: The Medieval Cosmos, 1200-1687 (New York: Cambridge University Press,
1994), Professor Grant has catalogued 400 questions in the area of cosmology alone that were raised during
the period that the medieval cosmology persisted. This generated 1,176 known responses and these were by
no means slavish replies. Many contained innovations: During the 14th century, other dramatic departures
from Aristotle occurred when scholastic natural philosophers demonstrated that an infinite extracosmic void
space might lie beyond the world itself; that motion in a hypothetical vacuum was feasible; that the
existence of other worlds was possible; and that the daily axial rotation of the earth was an intelligible,
astronomical concept, even though it was ultimately rejected (677).
14. Bernard R. Goldstein, Copernicus and the Origin of His Heliocentric System, Journal for the History of
Astronomy 33 (2002) : 231.
15. Among his various papers on this topic, see Timur Kuran, The Islamic Commercial Crisis: Institutional
We use cookies on this site to enhance your user experienceBy
Roots of Economic Underdevelopment in the Middle East, USC CenterOK, for ILaw,
agreeEconomics
No, thanks
&
clicking any link on this page you are giving your consent for us to set
cookies. No, give me more info

https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 11/17
8/29/2020 Toby Huff: Reply to George Saliba | The Baheyeldin Dynasty

Organization, Research Paper No. C-1-12, 20 November 2001. This is one of a series of papers he has
written on this subject. See .
16. I discuss the fate of higher learning in the Arab/Muslim world from the eighteenth century to the
present in the new epilogue to The Rise of Early Modern Science (2d ed.) and in a forthcoming article,
Science and Civilization ‘East’ and ‘West’: The Legacy of the Past in the Internet World, Society.
17. As cited in M.-D. Chenu, Nature, Man and Society in the Twelfth Century (Boston: Little Brown,
1968), 17, n. 35.
18. H. A. R. Gibb, Modern Trends in Islam (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1947), 54.
19. This is not the place to enter into a broader discussion of the epistemological foundations of the
scientific revolution. A highly informed analysis of the conceptual, mathematical and empirical aspects of
the revolution, including a discussion of issues in the medical revolution can be found in John Henry, The
Scientific Revolution and the Origins of Modern Science (London: Macmillan, 1997), especially chapter
two.
20. Roger French, Dissection and Vivisection in the European Renaissance (Aldershot: Ashgate, 1999).
21. See United Nations Development Program, Arab Human Development Report 2002; available online at
.
22. Castells has made this argument on the basis of Russian documents and field work in the former Soviet
Union; see Manuel Castells, The Information Age: Economy, Society and Culture (Malden, MA:
Blackwell, 1998), vol. 3, chapter 1. A useful comparative analysis of the science and technology programs
of these two totalitarian regimes may be found in Paul R. Josephson, Totalitarian Science and Technology
(Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1996).
23. David John Frank, Ann Hironaka and Evan Schofer, Environmentalism as a Global Institution,
American Sociological Review 65 (February 2000) : 122-27.
24. There is now a significant amount of literature on this subject; see, among others, David John Frank,
Science, Nature, and the Globalization of the Environment, 1870-1990, Social Forces 76, no. 2 (1997) :
409-37; and Evan Schofer, Rationalized Environmental Discourse in World Policy Formation, in World
Policy Formation, eds. John Boli and George M. Thomas (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1999), 81-
99.

Read George Saliba's original article, and Dr. Saliba's response to the reply.

Contents: 
Culture History

‹ George Saliba: Seeking the Origins of up


Modern Science? George Saliba: Flying Goats And Other
Obsessions - A Response to Toby Huff's
Reply ›
We use cookies on this site to enhance your user experienceBy
OK, I agree No, thanks
Add new comment
clicking any link on this page you are giving your consent for us to set

cookies. No, give me more info

https://baheyeldin.com/history/toby-huff-1.html 12/17

You might also like