Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Happiness

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 39

pdf version of the entry

Happiness
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/happiness/ Happiness
from the Summer 2020 Edition of the First published Wed Jul 6, 2011; substantive revision Thu May 28, 2020

Stanford Encyclopedia There are roughly two philosophical literatures on “happiness,” each
corresponding to a different sense of the term. One uses ‘happiness’ as a
of Philosophy value term, roughly synonymous with well-being or flourishing. The other
body of work uses the word as a purely descriptive psychological term,
akin to ‘depression’ or ‘tranquility’. An important project in the
philosophy of happiness is simply getting clear on what various writers are
talking about: what are the important meanings of the term and how do
they connect? While the “well-being” sense of happiness receives
Edward N. Zalta Uri Nodelman Colin Allen R. Lanier Anderson
significant attention in the contemporary literature on well-being, the
Principal Editor Senior Editor Associate Editor Faculty Sponsor
psychological notion is undergoing a revival as a major focus of
Editorial Board
https://plato.stanford.edu/board.html philosophical inquiry, following on recent developments in the science of
happiness. This entry focuses on the psychological sense of happiness (for
Library of Congress Catalog Data
ISSN: 1095-5054
the well-being notion, see the entry on well-being). The main accounts of
happiness in this sense are hedonism, the life satisfaction theory, and the
Notice: This PDF version was distributed by request to mem- emotional state theory. Leaving verbal questions behind, we find that
bers of the Friends of the SEP Society and by courtesy to SEP happiness in the psychological sense has always been an important
content contributors. It is solely for their fair use. Unauthorized concern of philosophers. Yet the significance of happiness for a good life
distribution is prohibited. To learn how to join the Friends of the
has been hotly disputed in recent decades. Further questions of
SEP Society and obtain authorized PDF versions of SEP entries,
contemporary interest concern the relation between the philosophy and
please visit https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/ .
science of happiness, as well as the role of happiness in social and political
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy decision-making.
Copyright c 2020 by the publisher
The Metaphysics Research Lab 1. The meanings of ‘happiness’
Center for the Study of Language and Information
1.1 Two senses of ‘happiness’
Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305
1.2 Clarifying our inquiry
Happiness
c 2020 by the author
Copyright 2. Theories of happiness
Dan Haybron 2.1 The chief candidates
All rights reserved. 2.2 Methodology: settling on a theory
Copyright policy: https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/info/copyright/

1
Happiness Dan Haybron

2.3 Life satisfaction versus affect-based accounts Philosophers who write about “happiness” typically take their subject
2.4 Hedonism versus emotional state matter to be either of two things, each corresponding to a different sense
2.5 Hybrid accounts of the term:
3. The science of happiness
3.1 Can happiness be measured? 1. A state of mind
3.2 Empirical findings: overview 2. A life that goes well for the person leading it
3.3 The sources of happiness
In the first case our concern is simply a psychological matter. Just as
4. The importance of happiness
inquiry about pleasure or depression fundamentally concerns questions of
4.1 Doubts about the value of happiness
psychology, inquiry about happiness in this sense—call it the (long-term)
4.2 Restoring happiness to the theory of well-being
“psychological sense”—is fundamentally the study of certain mental
4.3 Is happiness overrated?
states. What is this state of mind we call happiness? Typical answers to
5. The pursuit and promotion of happiness
this question include life satisfaction, pleasure, or a positive emotional
5.1 Normative issues
condition.
5.2 Mistakes in the pursuit of happiness
5.3 The politics of happiness Having answered that question, a further question arises: how valuable is
Bibliography this mental state? Since ‘happiness’ in this sense is just a psychological
Academic Tools term, you could intelligibly say that happiness isn’t valuable at all.
Other Internet Resources Perhaps you are a high-achieving intellectual who thinks that only
Related Entries ignoramuses can be happy. On this sort of view, happy people are to be
pitied, not envied. The present article will center on happiness in the
psychological sense.
1. The meanings of ‘happiness’
In the second case, our subject matter is a kind of value, namely what
1.1 Two senses of ‘happiness’ philosophers nowadays tend to call prudential value—or, more commonly,
well-being, welfare, utility or flourishing. (For further discussion, see the
What is happiness? This question has no straightforward answer, because entry on well-being. Whether these terms are really equivalent remains a
the meaning of the question itself is unclear. What exactly is being asked? matter of dispute, but this article will usually treat them as
Perhaps you want to know what the word ‘happiness’ means. In that case interchangeable.) “Happiness” in this sense concerns what benefits a
your inquiry is linguistic. Chances are you had something more interesting person, is good for her, makes her better off, serves her interests, or is
in mind: perhaps you want to know about the thing, happiness, itself. Is it desirable for her for her sake. To be high in well-being is to be faring well,
pleasure, a life of prosperity, something else? Yet we can’t answer that doing well, fortunate, or in an enviable condition. Ill-being, or doing
question until we have some notion of what we mean by the word.

2 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 3


Happiness Dan Haybron

badly, may call for sympathy or pity, whereas we envy or rejoice in the Aristotelian and other objective list theories, count as doing well, or
good fortune of others, and feel gratitude for our own. Being good for leading a happy life.
someone differs from simply being good, period: perhaps it is always
good, period, for you to be honest; yet it may not always be good for you, 1.2 Clarifying our inquiry
as when it entails self-sacrifice. Not coincidentally, the word ‘happiness’
derives from the term for good fortune, or “good hap,” and indeed the Now we can sharpen the initial question somewhat: when you ask what
terms used to translate it in other languages often have similar roots. In happiness is, are you asking what sort of life benefits a person? If so, then
this sense of the term—call it the “well-being sense”—happiness refers to your question concerns matters of value, namely what is good for people
a life of well-being or flourishing: a life that goes well for you. —the sort of thing that ethical theorists are trained to address.
Alternatively, perhaps you simply want to know about the nature of a
Importantly, to ascribe happiness in the well-being sense is to make a certain state of mind—happiness in the psychological sense. In this case,
value judgment: namely, that the person has whatever it is that benefits a some sort of psychological inquiry will be needed, either philosophical or
person.[1] If you and I and have different values, then we may well differ scientific. (Laypersons often have neither sort of question in mind, but are
about which lives we consider happy. I might think Genghis Khan had a really asking about the sources of happiness. Thus it might be claimed,
happy life, because I think what matters for well-being is getting what you say, that “happiness is being with good friends.” This is not a view about
want; while you deny this because you think a life of evildoing, however the nature or definition of happiness, but rather a theory about the sorts of
“successful,” is sad and impoverished. things that tend to make us happy. It leaves unanswered, or takes for
granted, the question of just what happiness is, such that friends are a good
Theories of well-being—and hence of “happiness” in the well-being sense
source of it.)
—come in three basic flavors, according to the best-known taxonomy
(Parfit 1984): hedonism, desire theories, and objective list theories. In short, philosophical “theories of happiness” can be about either of at
Whereas hedonists identify well-being roughly with experiences of least two different things: well-being, or a state of mind.[2] Accordingly,
pleasure, desire theorists equate it with the satisfaction of one’s desires there are essentially two bodies of philosophical literature about
—actually getting what you want, versus merely having certain “happiness” and two sets of debates about its nature, though writers often
experiences. Both hedonism and desire theories are in some sense fail to distinguish them. Such failures have generated much confusion,
subjectivist, since they ground well-being in the individual’s subjective sometimes yielding bogus disagreements that prove to be merely verbal.[3]
states. Objective list theorists, by contrast, think some things benefit us For instance, some psychologists identify “happiness” with attitudes of life
independently of our attitudes or feelings: there are objective prudential satisfaction while remaining neutral on questions of value, or whether
goods. Aristotelians are the best-known example: they take well-being Bentham, Mill, Aristotle, or any other thinker about the good life was
(eudaimonia) to consist in a life of virtuous activity—or more broadly, the correct. Such researchers employ the term in the psychological sense. Yet
fulfillment of our human capacities. A passive but contented couch potato it is sometimes objected against such claims that life satisfaction cannot
may be getting what he wants, and he may enjoy it. But he would not, on suffice for “happiness” because other things, like achievement or

4 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 5


Happiness Dan Haybron

knowledge, matter for human well-being. The objectors are confused: off. (If they are, then the psychology journals that are publishing this
their opponents have made no claims about well-being at all, and the two research may need to revise their peer-review protocols to include ethicists
“sides,” as it were, are simply using ‘happiness’ to talk about different among their referees.) And the many recent popular books on happiness,
things. One might just as sensibly object to an economist’s tract on as well as innumerable media accounts of research on happiness, nearly all
“banks” that it has nothing to say about rivers and streams. appear to take it for granted that they are talking about nothing more than
a psychological condition.
Which use of ‘happiness’ corresponds to the true meaning of the term in
contemporary English? Arguably, both. The well-being usage clearly Henceforth ‘happiness’ will be used in the long-term psychological sense,
dominates in the historical literature through at least the early modern era, unless otherwise specified. Note, however, that a number of important
for instance in translations of the ancient Greeks’ ‘eudaimonia’ or the books and other works on “happiness” in recent decades have employed
Latin ‘beatitudo’, though this translation has long been a source of the well-being sense of the term. Books of this sort appear to include
controversy. Jefferson’s famous reference to “the pursuit of happiness” Almeder 2000, Annas 1993, 2011, Bloomfield 2014, Cahn and Vitrano
probably employed the well-being sense. Even later writers such as Mill 2015, Kenny and Kenny 2006, McMahon 2005, McPherson 2020,
may have used the term in its well-being sense, though it is often difficult Noddings 2003, Russell 2013, White 2006, and Vitrano 2014, though
to tell since well-being itself is often taken to consist in mental states like again it is not always clear how a given author uses the term. For
pleasure. In ordinary usage, the abstract noun ‘happiness’ often invites a discussion of the well-being notion, see the entry on well-being.[4]
well-being reading. And the locution ‘happy life’ may not naturally take a
psychological interpretation, for the simple reason that lives aren’t 2. Theories of happiness
normally regarded as psychological entities.
2.1 The chief candidates
Contrast this with the very different meaning that seems to attach to talk of
“being happy.” Here it is much less clear that we are talking about a Philosophers have most commonly distinguished two accounts of
property of a person’s life; it seems rather to be a property of the person happiness: hedonism, and the life satisfaction theory. Hedonists identify
herself. To be happy, it seems, is just to be in a certain sort of happiness with the individual’s balance of pleasant over unpleasant
psychological state or condition. Similarly when we say that so-and-so “is experience, in the same way that welfare hedonists do.[5] The difference is
happy” (as opposed to saying that he is leading a happy life). This that the hedonist about happiness need not accept the stronger doctrine of
psychological usage, arguably, predominates in the current vernacular. welfare hedonism; this emerges clearly in arguments against the classical
Researchers engaged in the self-described “science of happiness” usually Utilitarian focus on happiness as the aim of social choice. Such arguments
do not take themselves to be making value judgments when they proclaim tend to grant the identification of happiness with pleasure, but challenge
individuals in their studies to be happy. Nor, when asserting that a life the idea that this should be our primary or sole concern, and often as well
satisfaction study shows Utahans to be happier than New Yorkers, are they the idea that happiness is all that matters for well-being.
committing themselves to the tendentious claim that Utahans are better

6 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 7


Happiness Dan Haybron

Life satisfaction theories identify happiness with having a favorable characterized in this proposal as “psychic affirmation,” or “psychic
attitude toward one’s life as a whole. This basic schema can be filled out in flourishing” in pronounced forms.
a variety of ways, but typically involves some sort of global judgment: an
endorsement or affirmation of one’s life as a whole. This judgment may be A fourth family of views, hybrid theories, attempts an irenic solution to
more or less explicit, and may involve or accompany some form of affect. our diverse intuitions about happiness: identify happiness with both life
It may also involve or accompany some aggregate of judgments about satisfaction and pleasure or emotional state, perhaps along with other
particular items or domains within one’s life.[6] states such as domain satisfactions. The most obvious candidate here is
subjective well-being, which is typically defined as a compound of life
A third theory, the emotional state view, departs from hedonism in a satisfaction, domain satisfactions, and positive and negative affect.
different way: instead of identifying happiness with pleasant experience, it (Researchers often seem to identify happiness with subjective well-being,
identifies happiness with an agent’s emotional condition as a whole, of sometimes with life satisfaction, and perhaps most commonly with
what is often called “emotional well-being.”[7] This includes emotional or hedonic state.) The chief appeal of hybrid theories is their
nonexperiential aspects of emotions and moods (or perhaps just moods), inclusiveness: all the components of subjective well-being seem
and excludes pleasures that don’t directly involve the individual’s important, and there is probably no component of subjective well-being
emotional state. It might also include a person’s propensity for that does not at times get included in “happiness” in ordinary usage.
experiencing various moods, which can vary over time, though several
authors have argued against this suggestion (e.g., Hill 2007, Klausen 2015, 2.2 Methodology: settling on a theory
Rossi 2018). Happiness on such a view is more nearly the opposite of
depression or anxiety—a broad psychological condition—whereas How do we determine which theory is correct? Traditional philosophical
hedonistic happiness is simply opposed to unpleasantness. For example, a methods of conceptual or linguistic analysis can give us some guidance,
deeply distressed individual might distract herself enough with constant indicating that some accounts offer a better fit with the ordinary concept of
activity to maintain a mostly pleasant existence—broken only by tearful happiness. Thus it has been argued that hedonism is false to the concept of
breakdowns during the odd quiet moment—thus perhaps counting as happiness as we know it; the intuitions taken to support hedonism point
happy on a hedonistic but not emotional state view. The states involved in instead to an emotional state view (Haybron 2001). And some have argued
happiness, on an emotional state view, can range widely, far more so that that life satisfaction is compatible with profoundly negative emotional
the ordinary notion of mood or emotion. On one proposal, happiness states like depression—a suffering artist might not value emotional
involves three broad categories of affective state, including “endorsement” matters much, and wholeheartedly affirm her life (Carson 1981, Davis
states like joy versus sadness, “engagement” states like flow or a sense of 1981b, Haybron 2005, Feldman 2010). Yet it might seem counterintuitive
vitality, and “attunement” states like tranquility, emotional expansiveness to deem such a person happy. At the same time, people do sometimes use
versus compression, and confidence. Given the departures from ‘happiness’ to denote states of life satisfaction: life satisfaction theories do
commonsensical notions of being in a “good mood,” happiness is seem faithful to some ordinary uses of ‘happiness’. The trouble is that
HAPPINESS appears to be a “mongrel concept,” as Ned Block (1995)

8 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 9


Happiness Dan Haybron

called the concept of consciousness: the ordinary notion is something of a Velleman 1991). Second, life satisfaction seems more closely linked to our
mess. We use the term to denote different things in different contexts, and priorities than affect is, as the suffering artist case illustrates. While a
often have no clear notion of what we are referring to. This suggests that focus on affect makes sense insofar as we care about such matters, most
accounts of happiness must be somewhat revisionary, and that we must people care about other things as well, and how their lives are going
assess theories on grounds other than simple fidelity to the lay concept of relative to their priorities may not be fully mirrored in their affective
happiness—“descriptive adequacy,” in Sumner’s (1996) terms. One states. Life satisfaction theories thus seem to fit more closely with liberal
candidate is practical utility: which conception of happiness best answers ideals of individual sovereignty, on which how well my life is going for
to our interests in the notion? We talk about happiness because we care me is for me to decide. My satisfaction with my life seems to embody that
about it. The question is why we care about it, and which psychological judgment. Of course a theory of happiness need not capture everything
states within the extension of the ordinary term make the most sense of that matters for well-being; the point is that a life satisfaction view might
this concern. Even if there is no simple answer to the question what explain why we should care so much about happiness, and so enjoy
happiness is, it may well turn out that our interests in happiness cluster so substantive as well as intuitive support.[9]
strongly around a particular psychological kind that happiness can best, or
most profitably, be understood in terms of that type of state (Haybron But several objections have been raised against life satisfaction views. The
2003). Alternatively, we may choose to distinguish different varieties of most common complaint has already been noted, namely that a person
happiness. It will be less important how we use the word, however, than could apparently be satisfied with her life even while leading a highly
that we be clear about the nature and significance of the phenomena that unpleasant or emotionally distressed existence, and it can seem
interest us. counterintuitive to regard such a person as happy (see section 2.2). Some
life satisfaction theorists deny that such cases are possible (Benditt 1978),
2.3 Life satisfaction versus affect-based accounts but it could also be argued that such possibilities are part and parcel of life
satisfaction’s appeal: some people may not get much pleasure out of life
The debate over theories of happiness falls along a couple of lines. The because they don’t care particularly about affective matters, and a life
most interesting questions concern the choice between life satisfaction and satisfaction theory allows that they can, in their own fashion, be happy.
affect-based views like hedonism and the emotional state theory.[8]
Two other objections are more substantive, raising questions about
Proponents of life satisfaction see two major advantages to their account.
whether life satisfaction has the right sort of importance. One concern is
First, life satisfaction is holistic, ranging over the whole of one’s life, or
whether people often enough have well-grounded attitudes of life
the totality of one’s life over a certain period of time. It reflects not just the
satisfaction or dissatisfaction. Evaluating one’s life as a whole can be a
aggregate of moments in one’s life, but also the global quality of one’s life
complicated business, and there is some question whether people typically
taken as a whole (but see Raibley 2010). And we seem to care not just
have well-defined attitudes toward their lives that accurately reflect how
about the total quantity of good in our lives, but about its distribution—a
well their lives measure up relative to their priorities. Some research, for
happy ending, say, counts for more than a happy middle (Slote 1982,
instance, suggests that life satisfaction reports tend to reflect judgments

10 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 11


Happiness Dan Haybron

made on the spot, drawing on whatever information comes readily to or pragmatic concerns (e.g., comforting oneself). Shifts in perspective
mind, with substantial influences by transient contextual factors like the might also reasonably alter life satisfaction attitudes. After the funeral, you
weather, finding a dime, etc. (Schwarz and Strack 1999). Debate persists might be highly satisfied with your life, whereas the high school reunion
over whether this work undermines the significance of life satisfaction leaves you dissatisfied; yet neither judgment need be mistaken, or less
judgments, but it does raise a question whether life satisfaction attitudes authoritative.
tend to be well-enough grounded to have the kind of importance that
people normally ascribe to happiness. As a result, life satisfaction attitudes may be poor indicators of well-being,
even from the individual’s own point of view. That people in a given
The third objection is somewhat intricate, so it will require some country register high levels of life satisfaction may reflect nothing more
explaining. The claim is that a wide range of life satisfaction attitudes than that they set the bar extremely low; they might be satisfied with
might be consistent with individuals’ perceptions of how well their lives anything short of pure agony. Another country’s citizens might be
are going relative to what they care about, raising doubts about the dissatisfied with their lives, but only because they set the bar much higher.
importance of life satisfaction (Haybron 2016). You might reasonably be Relative to what they care about, people in the dissatisfied nation could be
satisfied when getting very little of what you want, or dissatisfied when better off than those in the satisfied nation. To take another example, a
getting most of what you want. One reason for this is that people tend to cancer patient might be more satisfied with his life than he was before the
have many incommensurable values, leaving it open how to add them up. diagnosis, for he now looks at his life from a different perspective and
Looking at the various ups and downs of your life, it may be arbitrary emphasizes different virtues like fortitude and gratitude as opposed to
whether to rate your life a four out of ten, or a seven. A second reason is (say) humility and non-complacency. Yet he need not think himself better
that life satisfaction attitudes are not merely assessments of subjective off at all: he might believe himself worse off than he was when he was less
success or personal welfare: they involve assessments of whether one’s satisfied. Neither judgment need seem to him or us to be mistaken: it’s just
life is good enough—satisfactory. Yet people’s values may radically that he now looks at his life differently. Indeed, he might think he’s doing
underdetermine where they should set the bar for a “good enough” life, badly, even as he is satisfied with his life: he endorses it, warts and all, and
again rendering the judgment somewhat arbitrary. Given your values, you is grateful just have his not-so-good life rather than some of the much
might reasonably be satisfied with a two, or require a nine to be satisfied. worse alternatives.
While it may seem important how well people see their lives going
relative to what they care about, it is not obviously so important whether For present purposes, the worry is that life satisfaction may not have the
people see their lives going well enough that they are willing to judge kind of significance happiness is normally thought to have. This may pose
them satisfactory. a difficulty for the identification of life satisfaction with happiness: for
people frequently seem to use happiness as a proxy for well-being, a
If life satisfaction attitudes are substantially arbitrary relative to subjective reasonably concrete and value-free stand-in that facilitates quick-and-dirty
success, then people might reasonably base those attitudes on other assessments of welfare. Given the discovery that someone is happy, we
factors, such as ethical ideals (e.g., valuing gratitude or noncomplacency) might infer that he is doing well; if we learn that someone is unhappy, we

12 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 13


Happiness Dan Haybron

may conclude that she is doing poorly. Such inferences are defeasible: if obvious similarities to hedonism yet excludes many pleasures from
we later find that the happy Ned’s wife and friends secretly hate him, we happiness? The question of motivation appears to be the chief worry
need not decide that he isn’t happy after all; we simply withdraw the facing the emotional state theory: what’s to be gained by focusing on
conclusion that he is doing well. So long as happiness tracks well-being emotional state rather than pleasure?
well enough in most cases, this sort of practice is perfectly respectable.
But if we identify happiness with life satisfaction, then we may have a One argument for taking such a view is intuitive: some find it implausible
problem: maybe Sally is satisfied only because she values being grateful to think that psychologically superficial pleasures invariably make a
for the good things in life. This sort of case may not be merely a difference in how happy one is—the typical pleasure of eating a cracker,
theoretical possibility: perhaps the very high rates of self-reported life say, or even the intense pleasure of an orgasm that nonetheless fails to
satisfaction in the United States and many other places substantially move one, as can happen with meaningless sexual activity. The intuitive
reflects a broad acceptance of norms of gratitude and a general tendency to distinction seems akin to distinctions made by some ancient philosophers;
emphasize the positives, or perhaps a sense that not to endorse your life consider, for instance, the following passage from Epictetus’s Discourses:
amounts to a lack of self-regard. It is not implausible that most people,
‘I have a headache.’ Well, do not say ‘Alas!’ ‘I have an earache.’
even those enduring great hardship, can readily find grounds for
Do not say ‘Alas!’ And I am not saying that it is not permissible to
satisfaction with their lives. Life may have to be pretty hard for a person to
groan, only do not groan in the centre of your being. (Discourses,
be incapable of affirming it.
1.18.19, emphasis added).
Despite these concerns there is significant intuitive appeal in the idea that
The Stoics did not expect us never to feel unpleasant sensations, which
to be happy is to be satisfied with one’s life. Perhaps a different way of
would plainly be impossible; rather, the idea was not to let such things get
conceiving life satisfaction, for instance dispensing with the global
to us, to impact our emotional conditions.
judgment and aggregating particular satisfactions and dissatisfactions,
would lessen the force of these objections. Alternatively, it is possible that Why should anyone care to press such a distinction in characterizing
idealized or qualified forms of life satisfaction would mitigate these happiness? For most people, the hedonic difference between happiness on
concerns for some purposes, such as a theory of well-being.[10] an emotional state versus a hedonistic view is probably minimal. But
while little will be lost, what will be gained? One possibility is that the
2.4 Hedonism versus emotional state more “central” affects involving our emotional conditions may bear a
special relation to the person or the self, whereas more “peripheral”
A second set of issues concerns the differences between the two affect- affects, like the pleasantness of eating a cracker, might pertain to the
based views, hedonism and emotional state. The appeal of hedonism is subpersonal aspects of our psychologies. Since well-being is commonly
fairly obvious: the pleasantness of our experience is plainly a matter of linked to ideas of self-fulfillment, this sort of distinction might signal a
great significance; many have claimed it to be the only thing that matters. difference in the importance of these states. Another reason to focus on
What, by contrast, motivates the emotional state account, which bears

14 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 15


Happiness Dan Haybron

emotional condition rather than experience alone may be the greater though Sumner’s “life satisfaction” theory may best be classified as a
psychological depth of the former: its impact on our mental lives, hybrid (1996; see also Martin 2012). In any event, a hybrid approach
physiology, and behavior is arguably deeper and more pervasive. This draws objections of its own. If we arrive at a hybrid theory by this route, it
enhances the explanatory and predictive significance of happiness, and could seem like either the marriage of two unpromising accounts, or of a
more importantly its desirability: happiness on this view is not merely promising account with an unpromising one. Such a union may not yield
pleasant, but a major source of pleasure and other good outcomes wholesome results. Second, people have different intuitions about what
(Fredrickson 2004, Lyubomirsky, King et al. 2005). Compare health on counts as happiness, so that no theory can accommodate all of them. Any
this score: while many think it matters chiefly or entirely because of its theory that tries to thus risks pleasing no one. A third concern is that the
connection with pleasure, there are few skeptics about the importance of various components of any hybrid are liable to matter for quite different
health. As well, emotional state views may capture the idea that happiness reasons, so that happiness, thus understood, might fail to answer to any
concerns the individual’s psychological orientation or disposition: to be coherent set of concerns. Ascriptions of happiness could be relatively
happy, on an emotional state theory, is not just to be subjected to a certain uninformative if they cast their net too widely.
sequence of experiences, but for one’s very being to manifest a favorable
orientation toward the conditions of one’s life—a kind of psychic 3. The science of happiness
affirmation of one’s life. This reflects a point of similarity with life
satisfaction views of happiness: contra hedonism, both views take 3.1 Can happiness be measured?
happiness to be substantially dispositional, involving some sort of
favorable orientation toward one’s life. But life satisfaction views tend to With the explosive rise of empirical research on happiness, a central
emphasize reflective or rational endorsement, whereas emotional state question is how far, and how, happiness might be measured.[11] There
views emphasize the verdicts of our emotional natures. seems to be no in-principle barrier to the idea of measuring, at least
roughly, how happy people are. Investigators may never enjoy the
While hedonism and emotional state theories are major contenders in the precision of the “hedonimeter” once envisaged by Edgeworth to show just
contemporary literature, all affect-based theories confront the worries, how happy a person is (Edgeworth 1881). Indeed, such a device might be
noted earlier, that motivate life satisfaction views—notably, their looser impossible even in principle, since happiness might involve multiple
connection with people’s priorities, as well as their limited ability to reflect dimensions that either cannot be precisely quantified or summed together.
the quality of people’s lives taken as a whole. If so, it could still be feasible to develop approximate measures of
happiness, or at least its various dimensions. Similarly, depression may not
2.5 Hybrid accounts admit of precise quantification in a single number, yet many useful if
imprecise measures of depression exist. In the case of happiness, it is
Given the limitations of narrower theories of happiness, a hybrid account plausible that even current measures provide information about how
such as a subjective well-being theory may seem an attractive solution. anxious, cheerful, satisfied, etc. people are, and thus tell us something
This strategy has not been fully explored in the philosophical literature,

16 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 17


Happiness Dan Haybron

about their happiness. Even the simplest self-report measures used in the differing norms about happiness may undermine the comparability of self-
literature have been found to correlate well with many intuitively relevant reports. The French might report lower happiness than Americans, for
variables, such as friends’ reports, smiling, physiological measures, health, instance, not because their lives are less satisfying or pleasant, but because
longevity, and so forth (Pavot 2008). they tend to put a less positive spin on things. For this reason it may be
useful to employ instruments, including narrower questions or
Importantly, most scientific research needs only to discern patterns across physiological measures, that are less prone to cultural biasing.[12]
large numbers of individuals—to take an easy case, determining whether
widows tend to be less happy than newlyweds—and this is compatible The discussion thus far has assumed that people can be wrong about how
with substantial unreliability in assessing individual happiness. Similarly, happy they are. Is this plausible? Some have argued that (sincerely) self-
an inaccurate thermometer might be a poor guide to the temperature, but reported happiness cannot, even in principle, be mistaken. If you think
readings from many such thermometers could correlate fairly well with you’re happy, goes a common sentiment, then you are happy. This claim is
actual temperatures—telling us, for instance, that Minnesota is colder than not plausible on a hedonistic or emotional state view of happiness, since
Florida. those theories take judgments of happiness to encompass not just how one
is feeling at the moment but also past states, and memories of those can
This point reveals an important caveat: measures of happiness could obviously be spurious. Further, it has been argued that even judgments of
correlate well with how happy people are, thus telling us which groups of how one feels at the present moment may often be mistaken, particularly
people tend to be happier, while being completely wrong about absolute regarding moods like anxiety.[13]
levels of happiness. Self-reports of happiness, for instance, might correctly
indicate that unemployed people are considerably less happy than those The idea that sincere self-reports of happiness are incorrigible can only be
with jobs. But every one of those reports could be wrong, say if everyone correct, it seems, given a quite specific conception of happiness—a kind of
is unhappy yet claims to be happy, or vice-versa, so long as the life satisfaction theory of happiness on which people count as satisfied
unemployed report lower happiness than the employed. Similarly, bad with their lives so long as they are disposed to judge explicitly that they
thermometers may show that Minnesota is colder than Florida without are satisfied with their lives on the whole. Also assumed here is that self-
giving the correct temperature. reports of happiness are in fact wholly grounded in life satisfaction
judgments like these—that is, that people take questions about
Two morals emerge from these reflections. First, self-report measures of “happiness” to be questions about life satisfaction. Given these
happiness could be reliable guides to relative happiness, though telling us assumptions, we can plausibly conclude that self-reports of happiness are
little about how happy, in absolute terms, people are. We may know who incorrigible. One question is whether happiness, thus conceived, is very
is happier, that is, but not whether people are in fact happy. Second, even important. As well, it is unlikely that respondents invariably interpret
comparisons of relative happiness will be inaccurate if the groups being happiness questions as being about life satisfaction. At any rate, even life
compared systematically bias their reports in different ways. This worry is satisfaction theorists might balk at this variant of the account, since life
particularly acute for cross-cultural comparisons of happiness, where satisfaction is sometimes taken to involve, not just explicit global

18 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 19


Happiness Dan Haybron

judgments of life satisfaction, but also our responses to the particular This entry focuses on subjective well-being studies, since that work is
things or domains we care about. Some will hesitate to deem satisfied standardly deemed “happiness” research. But psychological research on
people who hate many of the important things in their lives, however well-being can take other forms, notably in the “eudaimonic”—commonly
satisfied they claim to be with their lives as a whole. opposed to “hedonic”—literature, which assesses a broader range of
indicators taken to represent objective human needs, such as meaning,
In a similar vein, the common practice of measuring happiness simply by personal growth, relatedness, autonomy, competence, etc.[15] (The
asking people to report explicitly on how “happy” they are is sometimes assimilation of subjective well-being to the “hedonic” realm may be
defended on the grounds that it lets people decide for themselves what misleading, since life satisfaction seems primarily to be a non-hedonic
happiness is. The reasoning again seems to presuppose, controversially, value, as noted earlier.) Other well-being instruments may not clearly fall
that self-reports of happiness employ a life satisfaction view of happiness, under either the “happiness” or eudaimonic rubrics, for instance extending
the idea being that whether you are satisfied (“happy”) will depend on subjective well-being measures by adding questions about the extent to
what you care about. Alternatively, the point might be literally to leave it which activities are seen as meaningful or worthwhile (White and Dolan
up to the respondent to decide whether ‘happy’ means hedonic state, 2009). An important question going forward is how far well-being
emotional state, life satisfaction, or something else. Thus one respondent’s research needs to incorporate indicators beyond subjective well-being.
“I’m happy” might mean “my experience is generally pleasant,” while
another’s might mean “I am satisfied with my life as a whole.” It is not 3.2 Empirical findings: overview
clear, however, that asking ambiguous questions of this sort is a useful
enterprise, since different respondents will in effect be answering different The scientific literature on happiness has grown to proportions far too
questions. large for this article to do more than briefly touch on a few highlights.[16]
Here is a sampling of oft-cited claims:
To measure happiness through self-reports, then, it may be wiser to
employ terms other than ‘happiness’ and its cognates—terms whose 1. Most people are happy
meaning is relatively well-known and fixed. In other words, researchers 2. People adapt to most changes, tending to return over time to their
should decide in advance what they want to measure—be it life happiness “set point”
satisfaction, hedonic state, emotional state, or something else—and then 3. People are prone to make serious mistakes in assessing and pursuing
ask questions that refer unambiguously to those states.[14] This stratagem happiness
may be all the more necessary in cross-cultural work, where finding 4. Material prosperity has a surprisingly modest impact on happiness
suitable translations of ‘happy’ can be daunting—particularly when the
English meaning of the term remains a matter of contention (Wierzbicka The first claim, that most people are happy, appears to be a consensus
2004). position among subjective well-being researchers (for a seminal argument,
see Diener and Diener 1996). The contention reflects three lines of
evidence: most people, in most places, report being happy; most people

20 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 21


Happiness Dan Haybron

report being satisfied with their lives; and most people experience more commonly accepted figure. Consequently many researchers have posited
positive affect than negative. On any of the major theories of happiness, that each individual has a characteristic “set point” level of happiness,
then, the evidence seems to show that most people are, indeed, happy. Yet toward which he tends to gravitate over time. Such claims have caused
this conclusion might be resisted, on a couple of grounds. First, life some consternation over whether the pursuit and promotion of happiness
satisfaction theorists might question whether self-reports of life are largely futile enterprises (Lykken and Tellegen 1996; Millgram 2000).
satisfaction suffice to establish that people are in fact satisfied with their However, the dominant view now seems to be that the early claims about
lives. Perhaps self-reports can be mistaken, say if the individual believes extreme adaptation and set points were exaggerated: while adaptation is a
herself satisfied yet shows many signs of dissatisfaction in her behavior, very real phenomenon, many factors—including disability—can have
for instance complaining about or striving to change important things in substantial, and lasting, effects on how happy people are.[18] This point
her life. Second, defenders of affect-based theories—hedonistic and was already apparent from the literature on correlates and causes of
emotional state views—might reject the notion that a bare majority of happiness, discussed below: if things like relationships and engaging work
positive affect suffices for happiness. While the traditional view among are important for happiness, then happiness is probably not simply a
hedonists has indeed been that happiness requires no more than a >1:1 matter of personality or temperament. As well, the large cross-national
ratio of positive to negative affect, this contention has received little differences in measured happiness are unlikely to be entirely an artifact of
defense and has been disputed in the recent literature. Some investigators personality variables. Note that even highly heritable traits can be strongly
have claimed that “flourishing” requires greater than a 3:1 ratio of positive susceptible to improvement. Better living conditions have raised the
to negative affect, as this ratio might represent a threshold for broadly stature of men in the Netherlands by eight inches—going from short (five
favorable psychological functioning (e.g., Larsen and Prizmic 2008). foot four) to tall (over six feet)—in the last 150 years (Fogel 2005). Yet
While the evidence for any specific ratio is highly controversial, if height is considered much more heritable than happiness, with typical
anything like this proportion were adopted as the threshold for happiness, heritability estimates ranging from .60 to over .90 (e.g., Silventoinen,
on a hedonistic or emotional state theory, then some of the evidence taken Sammalisto et al. 2003).[19]
to show that people are happy could in fact show the opposite. In any
event, the empirical claim relies heavily on nontrivial philosophical views 3.3 The sources of happiness
about the nature of happiness, illustrating one way in which philosophical
work on happiness can inform scientific research. The question of mistakes will be taken up in section 5.2. But the last claim
—that material prosperity has relatively modest impacts on happiness—
The second claim, regarding adaptation and set points, reflects well-known has lately become the subject of heated debate. For some time the standard
findings that many major life events, like being disabled in an accident or view among subjective well-being researchers was that, beyond a low
winning the lottery, appear strongly to impact happiness only for a threshold where basic needs are met, economic gains have only a small
relatively brief period, after which individuals may return to a level of impact on happiness levels. According to the well-known “Easterlin
happiness not very different from before.[17] As well, twin studies have Paradox,” for instance, wealthier people do tend to be happier within
found that subjective well-being is substantially heritable, with .50 being a

22 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 23


Happiness Dan Haybron

nations, but richer nations are little happier than less prosperous In short, the relationship between money and happiness may depend on
counterparts, and—most strikingly—economic growth has virtually no which theory of happiness we accept: on a life satisfaction view, the
impact (Easterlin 1974). In the U.S., for example, measured happiness has relationship may be strong; whereas affect-based views may yield a much
not increased significantly since at least 1947, despite massive increases in weaker connection, again above some modest threshold. Here, again,
wealth and income. In short, once you’re out of poverty, absolute levels of philosophical views about the nature and significance of happiness may
wealth and income make little difference in how happy people are. play an important role in understanding empirical results and their
practical upshot. Economic growth, for instance, has long been a top
Against these claims, some authors have argued that absolute income has a priority for governments, and findings about its impact on human well-
large impact on happiness across the income spectrum (e.g., Stevenson being may have substantial implications for policy.
and Wolfers 2008). The question continues to be much debated, but in
2010 a pair of large-scale studies using Gallup data sets, including It is important to note that studies of this nature focus on generic trends,
improved measures of life satisfaction and affect, suggested that both sides not specific cases, and there is no dispute that significant exceptions exist
may be partly right (Kahneman and Deaton 2010; Diener, Ng et al. 2010). —notably, populations that enjoy high levels of happiness amid low levels
Surveying large numbers of Americans in one case, and what is claimed to of material prosperity. Among others, a number of Latin American
be the first globally representative sample of humanity in the other, these countries, Maasai herders, Inughuit hunter-gatherers, and Amish
studies found that income does indeed correlate substantially (.44 in the communities have registered highly positive results in subjective well-
global sample), at all levels, with life satisfaction—strictly speaking, a being studies, sometimes higher than those in many affluent nations, and
“life evaluation” measure that asks respondents to rate their lives without numerous informal accounts accord with the data.[20] Such “positive
saying whether they are satisfied. Yet the correlation of household income outliers” suggest that some societies can support high levels of happiness
with the affect measures is far weaker: globally, .17 for positive affect, with extremely modest material holdings. The importance of money for
–.09 for negative affect; and in the United States, essentially zero above happiness may depend strongly on what kind of society one inhabits. An
$75,000 (though quite strong at low income levels). For more recent interesting question, particularly in light of common environmental
discussions of empirical work, see Jebb et al. 2018 along with relevant concerns, is how far the lessons of such societies can, or should, be
chapters in Diener et al. 2018 and the annual World Happiness Reports transferred to other social forms, where material attainment and happiness
from 2012 onward (Helliwell et al. 2012). Research on the complex are presently more tightly coupled. Perhaps some degree of decoupling of
money-happiness relationship resists simple characterization, but a crude happiness and money would be desirable.
summary is that the connection tends to be positive and substantial, strong
at lower income levels while modest to weak or even negative at higher So the role of money in happiness appears, at this juncture, to be a mixed
incomes, and stronger and less prone to satiation for life evaluation than bag, depending heavily on how we conceive of happiness and what range
emotional well-being metrics. But again, these are very rough of societies we are considering. What (else), then, does matter most for
generalizations that gloss over a variety of important factors and admit of happiness? There is no definitive list of the main sources of happiness in
many exceptions across both individuals and societies. the literature, partly because it is not clear how to divide them up. But the

24 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 25


Happiness Dan Haybron

following items seem generally to be accepted as among the chief be entirely an artifact of the instruments used in this study.[23] A further
correlates of happiness: supportive relationships, engagement in point of uncertainty is the causal story behind the correlations—whether
interesting and challenging activities, material and physical security, a the correlates, like psychosocial prosperity, cause happiness; whether
sense of meaning or purpose, a positive outlook, and autonomy or control. happiness causes them; whether other factors cause both; or, as is likely,
[21] Significant correlates may also include—among many others—
some combination of the three.
religion, good governance, trust, helping others, values (e.g., having non-
materialistic values), achieving goals, not being unemployed, and Such concerns duly noted, the research plausibly suggests that, on
connection with the natural environment.[22] average, material progress has some tendency to help people to better get
what they want in life, as found in the life satisfaction measures, while
An illustrative study of the correlates of happiness from a global relationships and engaging activities are more important for people’s
perspective is the Gallup World Poll study noted earlier (Diener, Ng et al. emotional lives. What this means for happiness depends on which view of
2010; see also Jebb et al. 2020). In that study, the life satisfaction measure happiness is correct.
was more strongly related to material prosperity, as noted above:
household income, along with possession of luxury conveniences and 4. The importance of happiness
satisfaction with standard of living. The affect measures, by contrast,
correlated most strongly with what the authors call “psychosocial 4.1 Doubts about the value of happiness
prosperity”: whether people reported being treated with respect in the last
day, having family and friends to count on, learning something new, doing Were you to survey public attitudes about the value of happiness, at least
what they do best, and choosing how their time was spent. in liberal Western democracies, you would likely find considerable support
for the proposition that happiness is all that really matters for human well-
What these results show depends partly on the reliability of the measures. being. Many philosophers over the ages have likewise endorsed such a
One possible source of error is that this study might exaggerate the view, typically assuming a hedonistic account of happiness. (A few, like
relationship between life satisfaction and material attainments through the Almeder 2000, have identified well-being with happiness understood as
use of a “ladder” scale for life evaluation, ladders being associated with life satisfaction.)
material aspirations. Errors might also arise through salience biases
whereby material concerns might be more easily recalled than other Most philosophers, however, have rejected hedonistic and other mental
important values, such as whether one has succeeded in having children; state accounts of well-being, and with them the idea that happiness could
or through differences in positivity biases across income levels (perhaps suffice for well-being.[24] (See the entry on well-being.) Objections to
wealthier people tend to be more “positive-responding” than poorer mental state theories of well-being tend to cluster around two sets of
individuals). Another question is whether the affect measures adequately concerns. First, it is widely believed that the non-mental conditions of our
track the various dimensions of people’s emotional lives. However, the lives matter for well-being: whether our families really love us, whether
results are roughly consonant with other research, so they are unlikely to our putative achievements are genuine, whether the things we care about

26 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 27


Happiness Dan Haybron

actually obtain. The most influential objection of this sort is Robert individual or not. Kant, for example, considered both morality and well-
Nozick’s experience machine case, wherein we are asked to imagine a being to be important but distinct elements of a good life. Yet morality
virtual reality device that can perfectly simulate any reality for its user, should be our first priority, never to be sacrificed for personal happiness.
who will think the experience is genuine (Nozick 1974). Would you plug
in to such a machine for life? Most people would not, and the case is In fact there is a broad consensus, or near-consensus, among ethical
widely taken to vitiate mental state theories of well-being. Beyond having theorists on a doctrine we might call the priority of virtue: broadly and
positive mental states, it seems to matter both that our lives go well and crudely speaking, the demands of virtue or morality trump other values in
that our state of mind is appropriately related to how things are.[25] life.[27] We ought above all to act and live well, or at least not badly or
wrongly. This view need not take the strong form of insisting that we must
A second set of objections concerns various ways in which a happy person always act as virtuously as possible, or that moral reasons always take
might nonetheless seem intuitively to be leading an impoverished or precedence. But it does mean, at least, that when being happy requires
stunted life. The most influential of these worries involves adaptation, acting badly, one’s happiness must be sacrificed. If it would be wrong to
where individuals facing oppressive circumstances scale back their leave your family, in which you are unhappy, then you must remain
expectations and find contentment in “small mercies,” as Sen put it.[26] unhappy, or find more acceptable ways to seek happiness.
Even a slave might come to internalize the values of his oppressors and be
happy, and this strikes most as an unenviable life indeed. Related worries The mainstream views in all three of the major approaches to ethical
involve people with diminished capacities (blindness, Down Syndrome), theory—consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics—agree on some
or choosing to lead narrow and cramped or simpleminded lives (e.g., form of the priority of virtue. Where these views chiefly differ is not on
counting blades of grass). Worries about impoverished lives are a prime the importance of being good, but on whether being good necessarily
motivator of Aristotelian theories of well-being, which emphasize the full benefits us. Virtue ethicists tend to answer in the affirmative, the other two
and proper exercise of our human capacities. schools in the negative. Building virtue into well-being, as Aristotelians
do, may seem to yield a more demanding ethics, and in some ways it does.
In the face of these and other objections most commentators have Yet many deontologists and consequentialists—notably Kant—advocate
concluded that neither happiness nor any other mental state can suffice for sterner, more starkly moralistic visions of the good life than Aristotle
well-being. Philosophical interest in happiness has consequently flagged, would ever have dreamt of (e.g., Singer 1972).
since its theoretical importance becomes unclear if it does not play a
starring role in our account of the good. Happiness, in short, is believed by most philosophers to be insufficient for
well-being, and still less important for the good life. These points may
Even as happiness might fail to suffice for well-being, well-being itself seem to vitiate any substantial role for happiness in ethical thought.
may be only one component of a good life, and not the most important one However, well-being itself is still regarded as a central concept in ethical
at that. Here ‘good life’ means a life that is good all things considered, thought, denoting one of the chief elements of a good life even if not the
taking account of all the values that matter in life, whether they benefit the

28 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 29


Happiness Dan Haybron

sole element. And there are reasons for thinking happiness important, both values. Shelly Kagan, for instance, has suggested that welfare hedonism
practically and theoretically, despite the worries noted above. could be correct as a theory of how well a person is doing, but not of how
well a person’s life is going, which should perhaps be regarded as a
4.2 Restoring happiness to the theory of well-being distinct value (Kagan 1992, 1994). In short, we might distinguish narrow
and wide well-being concepts. An experience machine user might be
Even if happiness does not suffice for well-being—a point that not all doing well in the narrow sense, but not the wide—she is doing well,
philosophers would accept—it might still rate a privileged spot in theories though her life is quite sad. Happiness might, then, suffice for well-being,
of well-being. This could happen in either of two ways. but only in the narrow sense. Others have made similar points, but uptake
has been limited, perhaps because distinguishing multiple concepts of
First, happiness could be a major component of a theory of well-being.
prudential value makes the already difficult job of giving a theory of well-
Objective list theories of well-being sometimes include happiness or
being much harder, as Kagan pointedly observes.[29] An interesting
related mental states such as enjoyment among the fundamental
possibility is that the locution ‘happy life’, and the corresponding well-
constituents of well-being. A more ambitious proposal, originated by L.W.
being sense of happiness, actually refers to a specific variety of well-being
Sumner, identifies well-being with authentic happiness—happiness that is
—perhaps well-being in the wide sense just suggested, or well-being taken
authentic in the sense of being both informed and autonomous (Sumner
as an ideal state, an ultimate goal of deliberation. This might explain the
1996). The root idea is that well-being involves being happy, where one’s
continued use of ‘happiness’ for the well-being notion in the philosophical
happiness is a response of one’s own (autonomous), to a life that genuinely
literature, rather than the more standard ‘wellbeing.’
is one’s own (informed). The authenticity constraint is meant to address
both experience machine-type worries and “happy slave” objections
4.3 Is happiness overrated?
relating to adaptation, where happiness may be non-autonomous,
depending on manipulation or the uncritical acceptance of oppressive The preceding section discussed ways that happiness might figure
values. Since these have been the most influential objections to mental prominently even in non-mental state theories of well-being. The question
state accounts of well-being, Sumner’s approach promises to considerably there concerned the role of happiness in theories of well-being. This is a
strengthen the position of happiness-centered approaches to well-being, different question from how important happiness is for well-being itself.
and several philosophers have developed variants or close relations of the Even a theory of well-being that includes no mention at all of happiness
authentic happiness theory (Brülde 2007, Haybron 2008a, Tiberius and can allow that happiness is nonetheless a major component or contributor
Plakias 2010, Višak 2015). The approach remains fairly new, however, so to well-being, because of its relation to the things that ultimately constitute
its long-term prospects remain unclear.[28] well-being. If you hold a desire theory of well-being, for instance, you will
very likely allow that, for most people, happiness is a central aspect of
A second strategy forsakes the project of giving a unitary theory of well-
well-being, since most people very much desire to be happy. Indeed, some
being, recognizing instead a family of two or more kinds of prudential
desire theorists have argued that the account actually yields a form of
value. Happiness could be central to, or even exhaustive of, one of those

30 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 31


Happiness Dan Haybron

hedonism, on the grounds that people ultimately desire nothing else but on the study and alleviation of unhappiness—depression, suffering,
happiness or pleasure (Sidgwick 1907 [1966], Brandt 1979, 1989). anxiety, and other conditions whose importance is uncontroversial. The
study of happiness need be no more concerned with smiles than with
Happiness may be thought important even on theories normally believed frowns.
to take a dismissive view of it. Aristotelians identify well-being with
virtuous activity, yet Aristotle plainly takes this to be a highly pleasant 5. The pursuit and promotion of happiness
condition, indeed the most pleasant kind of life there is (see, e.g., NE, Bk.
I 8; Bk. VII 13). You cannot flourish, on Aristotelian terms, without being 5.1 Normative issues
happy, and unhappiness is clearly incompatible with well-being. Even the
Stoics, who notoriously regard all but a virtuous inner state as at best The last set of questions we will examine centers on the pursuit of
indifferent, would still assign happiness a kind of importance: at the very happiness, both individual and collective. Most of the popular literature on
least, to be unhappy would be unvirtuous; and virtue itself arguably entails happiness discusses how to make oneself happier, with little attention
a kind of happiness, namely a pleasant state of tranquility. As well, given to whether this is an appropriate goal, or how various means of
happiness would likely be a preferred indifferent in most cases, to be pursuing happiness measure up from an ethical standpoint. More broadly,
chosen over unhappiness. To be sure, both Aristotelian and Stoic accounts how if at all should one pursue happiness as part of a good life?
are clear that happiness alone does not suffice for well-being, that its
significance is not what common opinion takes it to be, and that some We saw earlier that most philosophers regard happiness as secondary to
kinds of happiness can be worthless or even bad. But neither denies that morality in a good life. The individual pursuit of happiness may be subject
happiness is somehow quite important for human well-being. to nonmoral norms as well, prudence being the most obvious among them.
Prudential norms need not be as plain as “don’t shoot yourself in the foot.”
In fact it is questionable whether any major school of philosophical On Sumner’s authentic happiness view of well-being, for instance, we
thought denies outright the importance of happiness, at least on one of the stand to gain little by pursuing happiness in inauthentic ways, for instance
plausible accounts of the matter. Doubts about its significance probably through self-deception or powerful drugs like Huxley’s soma, which
owe to several factors. Some skeptics, for example, focus on relatively guarantees happiness come what may (Huxley 1932 [2005]). The view
weak conceptions of happiness, such as the idea that it is little more than raises interesting questions about the benefits of less extreme
the simple emotion of feeling happy—an idea that few hedonists or pharmaceuticals, such as the therapeutic use of antidepressants; such
emotional state theorists would accept. Or, alternatively, assuming that a medications can make life more pleasant, but many people worry whether
concern for happiness has only to do with positive states. Yet ‘happiness’ they pose a threat to authenticity, perhaps undercutting their benefits. It is
also serves as a blanket term for a domain of concern that involves both possible that such drugs involve prudential tradeoffs, promoting well-
positive and negative states, namely the kinds of mental states involved in being in some ways while undermining it in others; whether the tradeoffs
being happy or unhappy. Just as “health” care tends to focus mainly on ill are worth it will depend on how, in a given case, the balance is struck.
health, so might happiness researchers choose to focus much of their effort

32 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 33


Happiness Dan Haybron

Another possibility is that such drugs sometimes promote authenticity, if heard claim, commonly called the “paradox of hedonism,” is that the
for instance a depressive disorder prevents a person from being “himself.” pursuit of happiness is self-defeating; to be happy, don’t pursue happiness.
It is not clear how to interpret this dictum, however, so that it is both
Looking to more broadly ethical, but not yet moral, norms, it may be interesting and true. It is plainly imprudent to make happiness one’s focus
possible to act badly without acting either immorally or imprudently. at every moment, but doubtful that this has often been denied. Yet never
While Aristotle himself regarded acting badly as inherently imprudent, his considering happiness also seems an improbable strategy for becoming
catalogue of virtues is instructive, as many of them (wit, friendliness, etc.) happier. If you are choosing among several equally worthwhile
are not what we normally regard as moral virtues. Some morally occupations, and have good evidence that some of them will make you
permissible methods of pursuing happiness may nonetheless be miserable, while one of them is likely to be highly fulfilling, it would not
inappropriate because they conflict with such “ethical” virtues. They seem imprudent to take that information into account. Yet to do so just is
might, for instance, be undignified or imbecilic. to pursue happiness. The so-called paradox of hedonism is perhaps best
seen as a vague caution against focusing too much on making oneself
Outwardly virtuous conduct undertaken in the name of personal happiness
happy, not a blanket dismissal of the prospects for expressly seeking
might, if wrongly motivated, be incompatible with genuine virtue. One
happiness—and for this modest point there is good empirical evidence
might, for instance, engage in philanthropy solely to make oneself happier,
(Schooler, Ariely et al. 2003, Lyubomirsky 2007).
and indeed work hard at fine-tuning one’s assistance to maximize the
hedonic payoff. This sort of conduct would not obviously instantiate the That happiness is sometimes worth seeking does not mean we will always
virtue of compassion or kindness, and indeed might be reasonably deemed do a good job of it (Haybron 2008b). In recent decades a massive body of
contemptible. Similarly, it might be admirable, morally or otherwise, to be empirical evidence has gathered on various ways in which people seem
grateful for the good things in one’s life. Yet the virtue of gratitude might systematically prone to make mistakes in the pursuit of their interests,
be undermined by certain kinds of gratitude intervention, whereby one including happiness. Such tendencies have been suggested in several
tries to become happier by focusing on the things one is grateful for. If domains relating to the pursuit of happiness, including (with recent
expressions of gratitude become phony or purely instrumental, the sole surveys cited):
reason for giving thanks being to become happy—and not that one
actually has something to be thankful for—then the “gratitude” might 1. Assessing how happy we are, or were in the past (Haybron 2007)
cease to be admirable, and may indeed be unvirtuous.[30] 2. Predicting (“forecasting”) what will make us happy (Gilbert 2006)
3. Choosing rationally (Kahneman and Tversky 2000, Gilovitch, Griffin
5.2 Mistakes in the pursuit of happiness et al. 2002, Hsee and Hastie 2006)

A different question is what means of pursuing happiness are most A related body of literature explores the costs and benefits of (ostensibly)
effective. This is fundamentally an empirical question, but there are some making it easier to pursue happiness by increasing people’s options; it
in-principle issues that philosophical reflection might inform. One oft- turns out that having more choices might often make people less happy,

34 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 35


Happiness Dan Haybron

for instance by increasing the burdens of deliberation or the likelihood of freed to seek the good life as they see it, and beyond that the state should,
regret (Schwartz 2004). Less discussed in this context, but highly relevant, by and large, stay out of the well-being-promotion business.
is the large body of research indicating that human psychology and
behavior are remarkably prone to unconscious social and other situational This vision of the good society rests on empirical assumptions that have
influences, most infamously reported in the Milgram obedience been the subject of considerable debate. If it turns out that people
experiments (Doris 2002, 2015, Haybron 2014). Human functioning, and systematically and predictably err in the pursuit of their interests, then it
the pursuit of happiness, may be more profoundly social than many may be possible for governments to devise policies that correct for such
commentators have assumed.[31] mistakes.[33] Of course, government intervention can introduce other sorts
of mistakes, and there is some debate about whether such measures are
Taken together, this research bears heavily on two central questions in the likely to do more harm than good (e.g., Glaeser 2006).
philosophical literature: first, the broad character of human nature (e.g., in
what sense are we rational animals? How should we conceive of human But even if governments cannot effectively counteract human imprudence,
autonomy?); second, the philosophical ideals of the good society and good it may still be that people fare better in social forms that influence or even
government. constrain choices in ways that make serious mistakes less likely. (Food
culture and its impact on health may be an instructive example here.) The
5.3 The politics of happiness idea that people tend to fare best when their lives are substantially
constrained or guided by their social and physical context has recently
Just a decade ago the idea of happiness policy was something of a novelty. been dubbed contextualism; the contrary view, that people do best when
While it remains on the fringes in some locales, notably the United States, their lives are, as much as possible, determined by the individuals
in much of the world there has been a surge of interest in making themselves, is individualism (Haybron 2008b). Recent contextualists
happiness an explicit target of policy consideration. Attention has largely include communitarians and many perfectionists, though contextualism is
shifted, however, to a broader focus on well-being to reflect not just not a political doctrine and is compatible with liberalism and even
happiness but also other welfare concerns of citizens, and dozens of libertarian political morality. Contextualism about the promotion of well-
governments now incorporate well-being metrics in their national being is related to recent work in moral psychology that emphasizes the
statistics.[32] social character of human agency, such as situationism and social
intuitionism.[34]
Let’s consider the rationale for policies aimed at promoting well-being. In
political thought, the modern liberal tradition has tended to assume an Quite apart from matters of efficacy, there are moral questions about the
optimistic view of human nature and the individual’s capacities for state promotion of happiness, which has been a major subject of debate,
prudent choice. Partly for this reason, the preservation and expansion of both because of the literature on mistakes and research suggesting that the
individual freedoms, including people’s options, is widely taken to be a traditional focus of state efforts to promote well-being, economic growth,
central goal, if not the goal, of legitimate governments. People should be has a surprisingly modest impact on happiness. One concern is

36 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 37


Happiness Dan Haybron

paternalism: does happiness-based policy infringe too much on personal promoting happiness or well-being violate commonly accepted
liberty? Some fear a politics that may too closely approximate Huxley’s requirements of “liberal neutrality,” according to which policy must be
Brave New World, where the state ensures a drug-induced happiness for neutral among conceptions of the good. According to this constraint,
all (Huxley 1932 [2005]). Extant policy suggestions, however, have been governments must not promote any view of the good life, and happiness-
more modest. Efforts to steer choice, for instance in favor of retirement based policy might be argued to flout it. Worries about paternalism also
savings, may be paternalistic, but advocates argue that such policies can be surface here, the idea being that states should only focus on affording
sufficiently light-handed that no one should object to them, in some cases people the option to be happy or whatever, leaving the actual achievement
even going so far as to deem it “libertarian paternalism” (Thaler and of well-being up to the autonomous individual. As we just saw, however, it
Sunstein 2008).[35] The idea is that gentle “nudges,” like setting default is not clear how far happiness policy initiatives actually infringe on
options on hiring forms to setting aside money for retirement, interfere personal liberty or autonomy. A further worry is that, happiness isn’t
only trivially with choice, imposing little or no cost for those who wish to really, or primarily, what matters for human well-being (Nussbaum 2008).
choose differently, and would very likely be welcomed by most of those
targeted. But a major motivation for thinking happiness the wrong object of policy
is that neither happiness nor well-being are the appropriate focus of a
Also relatively light-handed, and perhaps not paternalistic at all, are state theory of justice. What justice requires of society, on this view, is not that
efforts to promote happiness directly through social policy, for instance by it make us happy; we do not have a right to be happy. Rather, justice
prioritizing unemployment over economic growth on the grounds that the demands only that each has sufficient opportunity (in the form of
former has a larger impact on happiness. Other policies might include resources or capabilities, say) to achieve a good life, or that each gets a
trying to reduce commute times, or making walkable neighborhoods and fair share of the benefits of social cooperation. However plausible such
green space a priority in urban planning, again on happiness grounds. points may be, it is not clear how far they apply to many proposals for
Some may deem such measures paternalistic insofar as they trade freedom happiness-based policy, save the strongest claims that happiness should be
(in the form of economic prosperity) for a substantive good, happiness, the sole aim of policy: many policy decisions are not primarily concerned
that people value unevenly, though it has also been argued that refusing to with questions of social justice, nor with constitutional fundamentals, the
take citizens’ values like happiness into consideration in policy focus of some theories of justice. Happiness could be a poor candidate for
deliberation on their behalf can amount to paternalism (Haybron and the “currency” of justice, yet still remain a major policy concern. Indeed,
Alexandrova 2013). the chief target of happiness policy advocates has been, not theories of
justice, but governments’ overwhelming emphasis on promoting GDP and
A related sort of objection to happiness-based policy argues that other indices of economic growth. This is not, in the main, a debate about
happiness, or even well-being, is simply the wrong object of policy, which justice, and as of yet the philosophical literature has not extensively
ought instead to focus on the promotion of resources or capabilities engaged with it.
(Rawls 1971, Nussbaum 2000, Quong 2011, Sen 2009). Several reasons
have been cited for this sort of view, one being that policies aimed at

38 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 39


Happiness Dan Haybron

However, the push for happiness-based policy is a recent development. In Angier, T., 2015, “Happiness: Overcoming the Skill Model,” International
coming years, such questions will likely receive considerably more Philosophical Quarterly, 55(1): 5–23.
attention in the philosophical literature. Angner, E., 2009, “The Politics of Happiness,” Philosophy and Happiness,
L. Bortolotti (ed.), New York: Palgrave, 1–26.
Bibliography –––, 2010, “Are subjective measures of well-being ‘direct’?” Australasian
Journal of Philosophy, 89(1): 115–130.
Adler, Matthew D., 2019, Measuring Social Welfare: An Introduction, –––, 2011, “The Evolution of Eupathics: The Historical Roots of
New York: Oxford University Press. Subjective Measures of Well-Being,” International Journal of
Adler, M. D., and M. Fleurbaey (eds.), 2015, The Oxford Handbook of Wellbeing, 1(1): 4–41.
Well-Being and Public Policy, New York: Oxford University Press. –––, 2013a, “Is it possible to measure happiness?,” European Journal for
Ahuvia, A., et al., 2015, “Happiness: An Interactionist Perspective,” Philosophy of Science, 3(2): 221–240.
International Journal of Wellbeing, 5(1): 1–18. –––, 2013b, “Is Empirical Research Relevant to Philosophical
Alexandrova, A., 2005, “Subjective Well-Being and Kahneman’s Conclusions?,” Res Philosophica, 90(3): 365–85.
‘Objective Happiness’,” Journal of Happiness Studies, 6: 301–324. –––, 2016, A Course in Behavioral Economics, second edition, London:
–––, 2008, “First-Person Reports and the Measurement of Happiness,” Palgrave.
Philosophical Psychology, 21(5): 571–583. Annas, J., 1993, The Morality of Happiness, New York: Oxford.
–––, 2017, A Philosophy for the Science of Well-Being, New York: Oxford –––, 2011, Intelligent Virtue, New York: Oxford.
University Press. Argyle, M., 1999, “Causes and Correlates of Happiness,” Well-Being: The
Alexandrova, A. and D. M. Haybron, 2012, “High Fidelity Economics,” in Foundations of Hedonic Psychology, D. Kahneman, E. Diener and N.
The Elgar Companion to Recent Economic Methodology, W. Hands Schwarz (eds.). New York: Russell Sage Foundation: 3–25.
and J. Davis (eds.). Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar. –––, 2002, The Psychology of Happiness, New York: Routledge.
–––, 2016, “Is Construct Validation Valid?,” Philosophy of Science, 83(5): Austin, A., 2015, “On Well-Being and Public Policy: Are We Capable of
1098–1109. Questioning the Hegemony of Happiness?,” Social Indicators
Almeder, R., 2000, Human Happiness and Morality, Buffalo, NY: Research, 127(1): 1–16.
Prometheus Press. Badhwar, N., 2008, “Is Realism Really Bad for You? A Realistic
Andreou, C., 2010, “A Shallow Route to Environmentally Friendly Response,” The Journal of Philosophy, 105(2): 85–107.
Happiness: Why Evidence That We Are Shallow Materialists Need –––, 2014, Well-Being: Happiness in a Worthwhile Life, New York:
Not Be Bad News for the Environment(Alist),” Ethics, Place & Oxford University Press.
Environment, 13(1): 1–10. –––, 2015, “Happiness,” in The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of
Ang, J. M. S., 2019, “Can Existentialists Be Happy? Authentic Life, Well-Being, ed. G. Fletcher, New York: Routledge, 323–35.
Authentic Happiness,” Science, Religion and Culture, 6(1): 122–129. Bagaric, M., and J. McConvill, 2005, “Goodbye Justice, Hello Happiness:

40 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 41


Happiness Dan Haybron

Welcoming Positive Psychology to the Law,” Deakin Law Review, Handbook of Well-Being, E. Diener, S. Oishi, and L. Tay (eds.), Salt
10(1): 1–26. Lake City: DEF Publishers.
Barrow, R., 1980, Happiness and Schooling, New York: St. Martin’s Biswas-Diener, R., J. Vittersø and E. Diener, 2005, “Most People are
Press. Pretty Happy, but There is Cultural Variation: The Inughuit, The
–––, 1991, Utilitarianism: A Contemporary Statement, Brookfield, VT: Amish, and The Maasai,” The Journal of Happiness Studies, 6(3):
Edward Elgar. 205–226.
Beck, B., and B. Stroop, 2015, “A Biomedical Shortcut to (Fraudulent) Blackson, T., 2009, “On Feldman’s Theory of Happiness,” Utilitas, 21(3):
Happiness? An Analysis of the Notions of Well-Being and 393–400.
Authenticity Underlying Objections to Mood Enhancement,” Well- Block, N., 1995, “On a Confusion About A Function of Consciousness,”
Being in Contemporary Society, J. H. Søraker, et al. (eds.), Berlin: Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18: 227–247.
Springer, 115–34. Bloomfield, P., 2014, The Virtues of Happiness, New York: Oxford
Becker, L. C., 2012, Habilitation, Health, and Agency, New York: Oxford University Press.
University Press. Bognar, G., 2010, “Authentic Happiness,” Utilitas, 22(3): 272–284.
Belliotti, R. A., 2004, Happiness Is Overrated, New York: Rowman & Bok, D., 2010a, The Politics of Happiness: What Government Can Learn
Littlefield. from the New Research on Well-Being, Princeton, NJ: Princeton
–––, 2013, “The Seductions of Happiness,” The Oxford Handbook of University Press.
Happiness, New York: Oxford University Press. Bok, S., 2010b, Exploring Happiness: From Aristotle to Brain Science,
Benditt, T. M., 1974, “Happiness,” Philosophical Studies, 25: 1–20. New Haven: Yale University Press.
–––, 1978, “Happiness and Satisfaction – A Rejoinder to Carson,” The Bortolotti, L. (ed.), 2009, Philosophy and Happiness, New York: Palgrave
Personalist, 59: 108–9. Macmillan.
Besser, L. L., 2014, Eudaimonic Ethics, New York: Routledge. Bosch, M. van den, and W. Bird, 2018, Oxford Textbook of Nature and
Besser-Jones, L., 2013, “The Pursuit and Nature of Happiness,” Public Health: The Role of Nature in Improving the Health of a
Philosophical Topics, 41(1): 103–21. Population, New York: Oxford University Press.
Billon, A., 2016, “Irrationality and Happiness: A (Neo-) Shopenhauerian Bramble, B., 2016, “The Experience Machine,” Philosophy Compass,
Argument for Rational Pessimism,” Journal of Ethics and Social 11(3): 136–45.
Philosophy, 11(1): 1–27. Brandt, R. B., 1959, Ethical Theory, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Bishop, M., 2012, “The Network Theory of Well-Being: An Introduction,” –––, 1979, A Theory of the Good and the Right, New York: Oxford.
The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and –––, 1989, “Fairness to Happiness,” Social Theory & Practice, 15: 33–58.
Communication, 7: 1–29. –––, 1992, Morality, Utilitarianism, and Rights, New York: Cambridge
–––, 2015, The Good Life, New York: Oxford University Press. University Press.
Biswas-Diener, R., 2018, “The Subjective Well-Being of Small Societies,” Brülde, B., 2007, “Happiness theories of the good life,” Journal of

42 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 43


Happiness Dan Haybron

Happiness Studies, 8(1): 15–49. Descriptive Adequacy,” Metaphilosophy, 43(5): 619–35.


–––, 2015, “Well-Being, Happiness and Sustainability,” Well-Being in Cavallaro, M., and G. Heffernan, 2019, “From Happiness to Blessedness:
Contemporary Society, Happiness Studies Book Series, J. H. Søraker, Husserl on Eudaimonia, Virtue, and the Best Life,” HORIZON.
et al. (eds.), Berlin: Springer, 157–76. Studies in Phenomenology, 8(2): 353–388.
Brannmark, J., 2003, “Leading lives: On happiness and narrative Chappell, T., 2013, “Eudaimonia, Happiness, and the Redemption of
meaning,” Philosophical Papers, 32(3): 321–343. Unhappiness,” Philosophical Topics, 41(1): 27–52.
Bruni, L., F. Comim, and M. Pugno (eds.), 2008, Capabilities and Charry, E. T., 2010, God and the Art of Happiness, Grand Rapids:
Happiness, New York: Oxford University Press. Eerdmans Publishing Company.
Buss, S., 2004, “The Irrationality of Unhappiness and the Paradox of Chekola, M., 2007, “Happiness, Rationality, Autonomy and the Good
Despair,” Journal of Philosophy, CI(4): 171–200. Life,” Journal of Happiness Studies, 8(1): 51–78.
Cahn, S. M. and C. Vitrano (eds.), 2008, Happiness: Classical and Christakis, N., J. Fowler, Simon, i. Schuster, P. D. Audio and L. Findaway
Contemporary Readings in Philosophy, New York: Oxford. World, 2009, Connected: The surprising power of our social
–––, 2015, Happiness and Goodness: Philosophical Reflections on Living networks and how they shape our lives, New York: Little, Brown and
Well, New York: Columbia University Press. Co.
Campbell, R., 1973, “The Pursuit Of Happiness,” Personalist, 54: 325– Clark, A., et al., 2018, The Origins of Happiness: The Science of Well-
337. Being over the Life Course, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Capaldi, C. A. et al., 2015, “Flourishing in Nature: A Review of the Cohen Kaminitz, S., forthcoming, “Looking Good or Feeling Well?
Benefits of Connecting with Nature and Its Application as a Understanding the Combinations of Well-Being Indicators Using
Wellbeing Intervention,” International Journal of Wellbeing, 5(4): 1– Insights from the Philosophy of Well-Being,” Social Indicators
16. Research, online first 12 February 2020. doi:10.1007/s11205-020-
Capuccino, C., 2013, “Happiness and Aristotle’s Definition of 02289-9
Eudaimonia,” Philosophical Topics, 41(1): 1–26. David, S., Boniwell, I., and A. Ayers (eds.), 2013, The Oxford Handbook
Carson, T. L., 1978a, “Happiness and Contentment: A Reply to Benditt,” of Happiness, New York: Oxford.
The Personalist, 59: 101–7. Davis, W., 1981a, “Pleasure and Happiness,” Philosophical Studies, 39:
–––, 1978b, “Happiness and the Good Life,” Southwestern Journal of 305–318.
Philosophy, 9: 73–88. –––, 1981b, “A Theory of Happiness,” American Philosophical Quarterly,
–––, 1979, “Happiness and the Good Life: a Rejoinder to Mele,” 18: 111–20.
Southwestern Journal of Philosophy, 10: 189–192. de Boer, J., 2014, “Scaling Happiness,” Philosophical Psychology, 27(5):
–––, 1981, “Happiness, Contentment, and the Good Life,” Pacific 703–18.
Philosophical Quarterly, 62: 378–92. De Brigard, F., 2010, “If You like It, Does It Matter If It’s Real?,”
Cashen, M, 2012, “Happiness, Eudaimonia, and The Principle of Philosophical Psychology, 23(1): 43–57.

44 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 45


Happiness Dan Haybron

de Lazari-Radek, K., and Singer, P., 2014, The Point of View of the Vittersø (ed.), Berlin: Springer, 437–52.
Universe: Sidgwick and Contemporary Ethics, New York: Oxford Dolan, P. and M. P. White, 2007, “How can measures of subjective well-
University Press. being be used to inform public policy?” Perspectives on
Den Uyl, D. and T. R. Machan, 1983, “Recent Work on the Concept of Psychological Science, 2(1): 71–85.
Happiness,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 20: 115–34. Doris, J. M., 2002, Lack of Character, New York: Cambridge University
Diener, E., 2008, “Myths in the Science of Happiness, and Directions for Press.
Future Research,” The Science of Subjective Well-Being, M. Eid and –––, 2009, “Skepticism about persons,” Philosophical Issues, 19(1): 57–
R. J. Larsen (eds.), New York: Guilford Press: 493–514. 91.
Diener, E. and R. Biswas-Diener, 2008, Happiness: unlocking the –––, 2015, Talking to Our Selves, New York: Oxford University Press.
mysteries of psychological wealth, Malden, MA: Blackwell. Easterlin, R. A., 1974, “Does Economic Growth Improve the Human
Diener, E. and C. Diener, 1996, “Most People Are Happy,” Psychological Lot?” Nations and Households in Economic Growth: Essays in
Science, 7(3): 181–185. Honor of Moses Abramovitz, P. A. David and M. W. Reder (eds.),
Diener, E., R. E. Lucas, U. Schimmack and J. F. Helliwell, 2009, Well- New York: Academic Press.
Being for Public Policy, New York: Oxford University Press. –––, 2003, “Explaining Happiness,” Proceedings of the National Academy
Diener, E., R. E. Lucas and C. N. Scollon, 2006, “Beyond the Hedonic of Sciences of the United States of America, 100(19): 11176–11183.
Treadmill: Revising the Adaptation Theory of Well-Being,” –––, 2005, “Building a Better Theory of Well-Being,” Economics and
American Psychologist, 61(4): 305–314. Happiness, L. Bruni and P. L. Porta (eds.), New York: Oxford, 29–65.
Diener, E., W. Ng, J. Harter and R. Arora, 2010, “Wealth and happiness Ebenstein, A. O., 1991, The Greatest Happiness Principle: An
across the world: Material prosperity predicts life evaluation, whereas Examination of Utilitarianism, New York: Garland.
psychosocial prosperity predicts positive feeling,” Journal of Edgeworth, F. Y., 1881, Mathematical Psychics: an Essay on the
Personality and Social Psychology, 99(1): 52–61. Application of Mathematics to the Moral Sciences, London: Kegan
Diener, E. and M. Seligman, 2004, “Beyond Money: Toward an economy Paul.
of well-being,” Psychological Science in the Public Interest, 5(1): 1– Eid, M. and R. J. Larsen (eds.), 2008, The Science of Subjective Well-
31. Being, New York: Guilford.
Diener, E. and E. M. Suh (eds.), 2000, Culture and Subjective Well-Being, Elster, J., 1983, Sour Grapes, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press. Epictetus, The Discourses as Reported by Arrian, The Manual, and
Diener, E., E. M. Suh, R. E. Lucas and H. L. Smith, 1999, “Subjective Fragments, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1925.
Well-Being: Three Decades of Progress,” Psychological Bulletin, Euler, S. S., 2019, “Psychological Universals in the Study of Happiness:
125(2): 276–302. From Social Psychology to Epicurean Philosophy,” Science, Religion
Dolan, P., and L. Kudrna, 2016, “Sentimental Hedonism: Pleasure, and Culture, 6(1): 130–37.
Purpose, and Public Policy,” Handbook of Eudaimonic Well-Being, J. Everett, D. L., 2009, Don’t sleep, there are snakes: Life and language in

46 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 47


Happiness Dan Haybron

the Amazonian jungle, New York: Random House. Frey, B. S., 2008, Happiness: A Revolution in Economics, Cambridge,
Feldman, F., 2004, Pleasure and the Good Life, New York: Oxford. MA: MIT Press.
–––, 2010, What Is This Thing Called Happiness?, New York: Oxford. Frumkin, H., 2001, “Beyond toxicity: Human health and the natural
–––, 2019, “An Improved Whole Life Satisfaction Theory of Happiness?,” environment,” American Journal of Preventive Medicine, 20(3): 234–
International Journal of Wellbeing, 9(2):1–7. 240.
Flanagan, O., 2007, The Really Hard Problem: Meaning in a Material Gilbert, D., 2006, Stumbling on Happiness, New York: Knopf.
World, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gilovitch, T., D. Griffin and D. Kahneman (eds.), 2002, Heuristics and
Flanagan, O., M. Letourneau, and W. Zhao, 2019, “Particulars of Well- Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment, New York: Cambridge
Being,” Science, Religion and Culture, 6(1): 1–5. University Press.
Fletcher, G., 2013, “A Fresh Start for the Objective-List Theory of Well- Glaeser, E. L., 2006, “Paternalism and Psychology,” University of Chicago
Being,” Utilitas, 25(2): 206–20. Law Review, 73(1): 133–156.
Fleurbaey, M., and D. Blanchet, 2013, Beyond GDP: Measuring Welfare Goldman, A. H., 2016, “Happiness is an Emotion,” The Journal of Ethics,
and Assessing Sustainability, New York: Oxford University Press. 21(1): 1–16.
Fogel, R. W., 2005, “Changes in the disparities in chronic diseases during –––, 2019, Life’s Values: Pleasure, Happiness, Well-Being, and Meaning,
the course of the 20th century,” Perspectives in biology and medicine, New York: Oxford University Press.
48(1 Supplement): S150-S165. Goldstein, I., 1973, “Happiness: The Role of Non-Hedonic Criteria in Its
Fraser, C., 2013, “Happiness in Classical Confucianism: Xúnzǐ,” E. Minar Evaluation,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 13: 523–34.
(ed.), Philosophical Topics, 41(1): 53–79. –––, 1981, “Cognitive Pleasure and Distress,” Philosophical Studies, 39:
Frederick, S. and G. Loewenstein, 1999, “Hedonic Adaptation,” Well- 15–23.
Being: The Foundations of Hedonic Psychology, D. Kahneman, E. –––, 1989, “Pleasure and Pain: Unconditional, Intrinsic Values,”
Diener and N. Schwarz (eds.), New York: Russell Sage Foundation Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 50(2): 255–276.
Press: 302–29. Goldstein, I., 2002, “Are emotions feelings? A further look at hedonic
Fredrickson, B. L., 2004, “The Broaden-and-Build Theory of Positive theories of emotions,” Consciousness and Emotion, 3(1): 21–33.
Emotions,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Graham, C., 2009, Happiness around the world: The paradox of happy
Biological Sciences, 359(1449): 1367–1377 peasants and miserable millionaires, New York: Oxford University
Fredrickson, B. L. and D. Kahneman, 1993, “Duration neglect in Press.
retrospective evaluations of affective episodes,” Journal of Graham, M., 2017, “A Fate Worse Than Death? The Well-Being of
Personality and Social Psychology, 65(1): 45–55. Patients Diagnosed as Vegetative With Covert Awareness,” Ethical
Fredrickson, B. L. and M. F. Losada, 2005, “Positive Affect and the Theory and Moral Practice, 20(5): 1–16.
Complex Dynamics of Human Flourishing,” American Psychologist, Griffin, J., 1979, “Is Unhappiness Morally More Important Than
60(7): 678–686. Happiness?” Philosophical Quarterly, 29: 47–55.

48 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 49


Happiness Dan Haybron

–––, 1986, Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Haybron, D. M., 2001, “Happiness and Pleasure,” Philosophy and
Importance, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Phenomenological Research, 62(3): 501–528.
–––, 2000, “Replies,” Well-Being and Morality, R. Crisp and B. Hooker –––, 2003, “What Do We Want from a Theory of Happiness?”
(eds.), New York: Oxford: 281–313. Metaphilosophy, 34(3): 305–329.
–––, 2007, “What Do Happiness Studies Study?” Journal of Happiness –––, 2005, “On Being Happy or Unhappy,” Philosophy and
Studies, 8(1): 139–148. Phenomenological Research, 71(2): 287–317.
Griswold, C., 1996, “Happiness, Tranquillity, and Philosophy,” Critical –––, 2007, “Do We Know How Happy We Are?” Nous, 41(3): 394–428.
Review, 10(1): 1–32. –––, 2008a, “Happiness, the Self, and Human Flourishing,” Utilitas,
Haidt, J., 2001, “The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social 20(1): 21–49.
intuitionist approach to moral judgment,” Psychological Review, –––, 2008b, The Pursuit of Unhappiness: The Elusive Psychology of Well-
108(4): 814–834. Being, New York, Oxford University Press.
Hare, R. M., 1963, Freedom and Reason, Oxford: Oxford University –––, 2011, “Central Park: Nature, Context, and Human Wellbeing,”
Press. International Journal of Wellbeing, 1(2): 235–254.
Hausman, D. M., 2010, “Hedonism and Welfare Economics,” Economics –––, 2013a, Happiness: A Very Short Introduction, New York: Oxford
and Philosophy, 26(3): 321–44. University Press.
–––, 2011, Preferences, Value, Choice, and Welfare, New York: –––, 2013b, “The Proper Pursuit of Happiness,” Res Philosophica, 90(3):
Cambridge University Press. 387–411.
Hausman, D. M. and B. Welch, 2009, “Debate: To Nudge or Not to –––, 2014, “Adventures in Assisted Living: Well-Being and Situationist
Nudge,” Journal of Political Philosophy, 18(1): 123–136. Psychology,” The Philosophy and Psychology of Character and
Hawkins, J., 2008, “Well-Being, Autonomy, and the Horizon Problem,” Happiness, N. E. Snow and F. V. Trivigno (eds.), New York:
Utilitas, 20(2): 1–27. Routledge, 1–25.
–––, 2014a, “Well-Being, Time, and Dementia,” Ethics, 124(3): 507–542. –––, 2016, “Mental State Approaches to Well-Being,” The Oxford
–––, 2014b, “Well-Being: What Matters Beyond the Mental?,” in Oxford Handbook of Well-Being and Public Policy, M. D. Adler & M.
Studies in Normative Ethics (Volume 4), M. Timmons (ed.). New Fleurbaey (eds.), New York: Oxford, 347–378.
York: Oxford University Press. Haybron, D. M., and A. Alexandrova, 2013, “Paternalism in Economics,”
–––, 2016, “The Experience Machine and the Experience Requirement,” Paternalism: Theory and Practice, C. Coons and M. Weber (eds.),
The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Well-Being, G. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 157–77.
Fletcher (ed.), New York: Routledge. Haybron, D. M., and V. Tiberius, 2015, “Well-Being Policy: What
–––, 2019, “Well-Being, The Self, and Radical Change,” Oxford Studies in Standard of Well-Being?,” Journal of the American Philosophical
Normative Ethics, Vol 9, M. Timmons (ed.), New York: Oxford Association, 1(4): 712–33.
University Press, 251. Headey, B., 2007, The Set-Point Theory of Well-Being Needs Replacing:

50 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 51


Happiness Dan Haybron

On the Brink of a Scientific Revolution?, DIW Berlin: German freedom, and rising happiness: A global perspective, 1981–2007”
Institute for Economic Research. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3(4): 264–285.
–––, 2008, “The Set-Point Theory of Well-Being: Negative Results and Inglehart, R. and H.-D. Klingemann, 2000, “Genes, Culture, Democracy,
Consequent Revisions,” Social Indicators Research, 85(3): 389–403. and Happiness,” Culture and Subjective Well-Being, E. Diener and E.
Hersch, G., 2015, “Can an Evidential Account Justify Relying on M. Suh (eds.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 165–183.
Preferences for Well-Being Policy?,” Journal of Economic Intelisano, S., Krasko, J., & Luhmann, M., 2019, “Integrating
Methodology, 22(3): 1–13. Philosophical and Psychological Accounts of Happiness and Well-
–––, 2017, “Ignoring Easterlin: Why Easterlin’s Correlation Findings Being,” Journal of Happiness Studies, 8: 1–40.
Need Not Matter to Public Policy,” Journal of Happiness Studies, Jebb, A. T., L. Tay, E. Diener, and S. Oishi, 2018, “Happiness, Income
19(8): 2225–2241. Satiation and Turning Points around the World,” Nature Human
–––, 2020, “No Theory-Free Lunches in Well-Being Policy,” The Behaviour, 2(1): 33–38.
Philosophical Quarterly, 70(278): 43–64. Joshanloo, M., 2013, “A Comparison of Western and Islamic Conceptions
Hill, S., 2007, “Haybron on Mood Propensity and Happiness,” Journal of of Happiness,” Journal of Happiness Studies, 14(6): 1857–74.
Happiness Studies, 10(2): 215–28. –––, 2014, “Eastern Conceptualizations of Happiness: Fundamental
Hindriks, F., & Douven, I., 2018, “Nozick’s experience machine: An Differences with Western Views,” Journal of Happiness Studies,
empirical study,” Philosophical Psychology, 31(2): 1–21. 15(2): 475–93.
Ho, S. M., W. Duan, and S. C. Tang, 2014, “The Psychology of Virtue and Joshanloo, M., and D. Weijers, 2019, “A Two-Dimensional Conceptual
Happiness in Western and Asian Thought,” The Philosophy and Framework for Understanding Mental Well-Being,” PLoS ONE,
Psychology of Character and Happiness, N. E. Snow and F. V. 14(3): e0214045.
Trivigno (eds.), New York: Routledge, 223–46. Kagan, S., 1992, “The Limits of Well-Being,” Social Philosophy and
Houlden, V., et al., 2018, “The Relationship between Greenspace and the Policy, 9(2): 169–89.
Mental Wellbeing of Adults: A Systematic Review,” PLOS ONE, –––, 1994, “Me and My Life,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 94:
13(9): 1–35. 309–324.
Hsee, C. K. and R. Hastie, 2006, “Decision and experience: Why don’t we Kahane, Guy, 2011, “Reasons to Feel, Reasons to Take Pills,” Enhancing
choose what makes us happy?” Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10(1): Human Capacities, J. Savulescu, R. Ter Meulen, and G. Kahane
31–37. (eds.), Oxford: John Wiley & Sons, 166–78.
Hurka, T., 2010, The Best Things in Life: A Guide to What Really Matters, Kahneman, D., 1999, “Objective Happiness,” Well-Being: The
New York: Oxford University Press. Foundations of Hedonic Psychology, D. Kahneman, E. Diener and N.
Huxley, A., 1932 [2005], Brave New World and Brave New World Schwarz (eds.), New York: Russell Sage Foundation: 3–25.
Revisited, New York: Harper Perennial Modern Classics. Kahneman, D. and A. Deaton, 2010, “High income improves evaluation of
Inglehart, R., R. Foa, C. Peterson and C. Welzel, 2008, “Development, life but not emotional well-being,” Proceedings of the National

52 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 53


Happiness Dan Haybron

Academy of Sciences, 107(38): 16489–16493. Perspective,” Journal of Happiness Studies, online first.
Kahneman, D., E. Diener and N. Schwarz (eds.), 1999, Well-Being: The Kraut, R., 1979, “Two Conceptions of Happiness,” The Philosophical
Foundations of Hedonic Psychology, New York: Russell Sage Review, 138: 167–97.
Foundation Press. –––, 2018, The Quality of Life: Aristotle Revised, New York: Oxford
Kahneman, D., B. L. Fredrickson, C. A. Schreiber and D. A. Redelmeier, University Press.
1993, “When More Pain Is Preferred to Less: Adding a Better End,” Kristjánsson, K., 2010, “Positive psychology, happiness, and virtue: The
Psychological Science, 4(6): 401–405. troublesome conceptual issues,” Review of general psychology,
Kahneman, D. and A. Tversky (eds.), 2000, Choices, Values, and Frames, 14(4): 296.
New York: Cambridge University Press. –––, 2012, “Positive Psychology and Positive Education: Old Wine in
Kauppinen, A., 2013, “Meaning and Happiness,” Philosophical Topics, New Bottles?” Educational Psychologist, 47(2): 86–105.
41(1): 161–185. –––, 2018, “The flourishing–happiness concordance thesis: Some
Kazez, J., 2007, The Weight of Things: Philosophy and the Good Life, troubling counterexamples,” The Journal of Positive Psychology,
Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. 13(6): 541–552.
Kekes, J., 1982, “Happiness,” Mind, 91: 358–76. Krueger, A., D. Kahneman, C. Fischler, D. Schkade, N. Schwarz and A.
–––, 1988, The Examined Life, Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press. Stone, 2009, “Time Use and Subjective Well-Being in France and the
–––, 1992, “Happiness,” Encyclopedia of Ethics, L. C. Becker and C. B. U.S,” Social Indicators Research,(93): 7–18.
Becker (eds.), New York: Garland: 430–435. Larsen, R. J. and Z. Prizmic, 2008, “Regulation of Emotional Well-Being:
Kellert, S. R. and E. O. Wilson (eds.), 1995, The Biophilia Hypothesis, Overcoming the Hedonic Treadmill,” The Science of Subjective Well-
Washington, D.C.: Island Press. Being, M. Eid and R. J. Larsen (eds.), New York: Guilford Press:
Kelman, M., 2005, “Hedonic Psychology and the Ambiguities of 258–289.
‘Welfare’,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 33(4): 391–412. Lauinger, W., 2015, “A Framework for Understanding Parental Well-
Kenny, A. and C. Kenny, 2006, Life, Liberty and the Pursuit of Utility, Being,” Philosophia, 43(3): 847–868.
Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic. Layard, R., 2005, Happiness: Lessons from a new science, New York:
Keyes, C. L., 2002, “The mental health continuum: From languishing to Penguin.
flourishing in life,” Journal of Health and Social Behavior, 43(2): LeBar, M., and D. Russell, 2013, “Well-Being and Eudaimonia: A Reply
207–222. to Haybron,” Aristotelian Ethics in Contemporary Perspective, 21:
Kim, R., 2020, Confucianism and the Philosophy of Well-Being, New 52.
York: Routledge. Lin, E., 2015, “How to Use the Experience Machine,” Utilitas, 28(3):
Klausen, S. H., 2015, “Happiness, Dispositions and the Self,” Journal of 314–32.
Happiness Studies, 17(3): 777–780. Loewenstein, G. and E. Haisley, 2008, “The Economist as Therapist:
–––, 2019, “Understanding Older Adults’ Wellbeing from a Philosophical Methodological Ramifications of ‘Light’ Paternalism,” The

54 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 55


Happiness Dan Haybron

Foundations of Positive and Normative Economics, A. Caplin and A. University Press.


Schotter (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press, 210–248. May, T., 2015, A Significant Life Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lucas, R. E., 2008, “Personality and Subjective Well-Being,” The Science Mayerfeld, J., 1996, “The Moral Asymmetry of Happiness and Suffering,”
of Subjective Well-Being, M. Eid and R. J. Larsen (eds.), New York: Southern Journal of Philosophy, 34: 317–338.
Guilford Press: 171–194. –––, 1999, Suffering and Moral Responsibility, New York: Oxford.
Lucas, R. E., A. E. Clark, Y. Georgellis and E. Diener, 2004a, “Re- McFall, L., 1989, Happiness, New York: Peter Lang.
Examining Adaptation and the Setpoint Model of Happiness: McMahon, D. M., 2005, Happiness: A History, New York: Atlantic
Reactions to Changes in Marital Status,” Journal of Personality and Monthly Press.
Social Psychology, 84: 527–539. McPherson, D., 2020, Virtue and Meaning: A Neo-Aristotelian
–––, 2004b, “Unemployment alters the set point for life satisfaction,” Perspective, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Psychological Science, 15(1): 8–13. Metz, T., 2014, “Gross National Happiness: A Philosophical Appraisal,”
Luhmann, M., and S. Intelisano, 2018, “Hedonic Adaptation and the Set Ethics and Social Welfare, 8(3): 218–32.
Point for Subjective Well-Being,” Handbook of Well-Being, E. Meynell, H., 1969, “Human Flourishing,” Religious Studies, 5: 147–154.
Diener, S. Oishi, and L. Tay (eds.), Salt Lake City: DEF Publishers. Millgram, E., 2000, “What’s the Use of Utility,” Philosophy and Public
Lumber, R., M. Richardson, and D. Sheffield, 2017, “Beyond Knowing Affairs, 29(2): 113–136.
Nature: Contact, Emotion, Compassion, Meaning, and Beauty Are Mitchell, P., 2018, “Adaptive Preferences, Adapted Preferences,” Mind,
Pathways to Nature Connection,” PLOS ONE, 12(5): e0177186. 127(508): 1003–25.
Luo, S., 2018, “Happiness and the Good Life: A Classical Confucian Moller, D., 2011, “Wealth, Disability, and Happiness,” Philosophy &
Perspective,” Dao, 71(2): 1–18. Public Affairs, 39(2): 177–206.
Lykken, D. and A. Tellegen, 1996, “Happiness is a stochastic Montague, R., 1967, “Happiness,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
phenomenon,” Psychological Science, 7(3): 186–9. 67: 87–102.
Lyubomirsky, S., 2007, The How of Happiness, New York: Penguin. Morris, S., 2011, “In defense of the hedonistic account of happiness,”
Lyubomirsky, S., L. King and E. Diener, 2005, “The Benefits of Frequent Philosophical Psychology, 24(2): 261 – 281.
Positive Affect: Does Happiness Lead to Success?” Psychological –––, 2015, Science and the End of Ethics, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Bulletin, 131(6): 803–855. Mulligan, K., 2016, “Happiness, Luck and Satisfaction.,” ARGUMENTA,
Lyubomirsky, S., K. M. Sheldon and D. Schkade, 2005, “Pursuing 1(2): 133–45.
Happiness: The Architecture of Sustainable Change,” Review of Mulnix, J. W., & Mulnix, M. J., 2015a, Happy Lives, Good Lives: A
General Psychology, 9(2): 111–131. Philosophical Examination, Peterborough, ON: Broadview Press.
MacLeod, A. K., 2015, “Well-Being: Objectivism, Subjectivism or ––– (eds.), 2015b, Theories of Happiness: An Anthology, Peterborough,
Sobjectivism?,” Journal of Happiness Studies, 16 1073–1089. ON: Broadview Press.
Martin, M. W., 2012, Happiness and the Good Life, New York: Oxford Murphy, M. C., 2001, Natural Law and Practical Rationality, New York:

56 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 57


Happiness Dan Haybron

Cambridge University Press. Posner, E. and C. R. Sunstein (eds.), 2010, Law and Happiness, Chicago:
Myers, D. G. and E. Diener, 1995, “Who Is Happy?” Psychological University of Chicago Press.
Science, 6(1): 10–19. Purcell, S., 2013, “Natural Goodness and the Normativity Challenge:
Nettle, D., 2005, Happiness: The Science Behind Your Smile, New York: Happiness Across Cultures,” Proceedings of the American Catholic
Oxford University Press. Philosophical Association, 87: 183–94.
Noddings, N., 2003, Happiness and Education, New York: Cambridge Quong, J., 2011, Liberalism Without Perfection, New York: Oxford
University Press. University Press.
Nozick, R., 1974, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, New York: Basic Books. Raibley, J., 2010, “Well-being and the priority of values,” Social Theory
–––, 1989, The Examined Life, New York: Simon and Schuster. and Practice, 36(4): 593–620.
Nussbaum, M. C., 2000, Women and Human Development: The –––, 2011, “Happiness is not Well-Being,” Journal of Happiness Studies,
Capabilities Approach, New York: Cambridge University Press. 13(6): 1105–1121.
–––, 2008, “Who Is the Happy Warrior? Philosophy Poses Questions to –––, 2012, “Health and Well-Being,” Philosophical Studies, 165(2): 469–
Psychology,” The Journal of Legal Studies, 37(s2): S81-S113. 89.
Oishi, S., Choi, H., Buttrick, N., et al., 2019, “The psychologically rich –––, 2013, “Values, Agency, and Welfare,” Philosophical Topics, 41(1):
life questionnaire,” Journal of Research in Personality, 81: 257–270. 187–214.
Parducci, A., 1995, Happiness, Pleasure, and Judgement: The Contextual Rawls, J., 1971, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Theory and Its Applications, Mahwah, NJ: L. Erlbaum Associates. Press.
Parfit, D., 1984, Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Raz, J., 1986, The Morality of Freedom, New York: Oxford University
Paul, L. A., 2016, Transformative Experience, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Press. –––, 2004, “The Role of Well-Being,” Philosophical Perspectives, 18(1):
Pavot, W., 2008, “The Assessment of Subjective Well-Being: Successes 269–294.
and Shortfalls,” The Science of Subjective Well-Being, M. Eid and R. Rescher, N., 1972, Welfare: The Social Issues In Philosophical
J. Larsen (eds.), New York: Guilford Press, 124–140. Perspective, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Phillips, J., L. Misenheimer and J. Knobe, 2011, “The Ordinary Concept –––, 1980, Unpopular Essays on Technological Progress, Pittsburgh:
of Happiness (and Others Like It),” Emotion Review, 71: 929–937. University of Pittsburgh Press.
Phillips, J., S. Nyholm, and S. Liao, 2014, “The Good in Happiness,” Ricard, M., 2006, Happiness: A Guide to Developing Life’s Most
Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy (Volume 1), T. Important Skill, New York: Little, Brown and Co.
Lombrozo, S. Nichols, and J. Knobe (eds.), 253–93. Roberts, R. C., 2019, “Joys: A Brief Moral and Christian Geography,”
Phillips, J., De Freitas, J., Mott, C., Gruber, J., & Knobe, J., 2017, “True Faith and Philosophy, 36(2): 195–222.
happiness: The role of morality in the folk concept of happiness,” Rodogno, R., 2014, “Happiness and Well-Being: Shifting the Focus of the
Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 146(2): 165–181. Current Debate,” South African Journal of Philosophy, 33(4): 433–

58 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 59


Happiness Dan Haybron

46. Assessment of Happiness Can Be Self-Defeating,” The Psychology of


–––, 2015, “Prudential Value or Well-Being,” Handbook of Value, T. Economic Decision, I. Brocas and J. Carillo (eds.), New York:
Brosch and D. Sander (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press, Oxford University.
287–312. Schultz, B., 2017, The Happiness Philosophers, Princeton: Princeton
Rodogno, R., Krause-Jensen, K., & Ashcroft, R. E., 2016, “‘Autism and University Press.
the good life’: a new approach to the study of well-being,” Journal of Schwartz, B., 2004, The Paradox of Choice, New York: HarperCollins.
Medical Ethics, 42(6): 401–408. Schwarz, N. and F. Strack, 1999, “Reports of Subjective Well-Being:
Ross, L. and R. E. Nisbett, 1991, The Person and the Situation: Judgmental Processes and Their Methodological Implications,” Well-
Perspectives of Social Psychology, Philadelphia: Temple University Being: The Foundations of Hedonic Psychology, D. Kahneman, E.
Press. Diener and N. Schwarz (eds.), New York: Russell Sage Foundation
Rossi, M., 2018, “Happiness, Pleasures, and Emotions,” Philosophical Press: 61–84.
Psychology, 31(6): 898–919. Schwitzgebel, E., 2008, “The Unreliability of Naive Introspection,”
Rossi, M., & Tappolet, C., 2016, “Virtue, Happiness, and Well-Being,” Philosophical Review, 117(2): 245–273.
The Monist, 99(2): 112–127. –––, 2011, Perplexities of Consciousness, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Russell, D., 2013, Happiness for Humans, New York: Oxford University Schwitzgebel, E. and R. T. Hurlburt, 2007, Describing Inner Experience?
Press. Proponent Meets Skeptic, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Ryan, R. M. and E. L. Deci, 2001, “On happiness and human potentials: A Scruton, R., 1975, Reason and Happiness. Nature and Conduct, R. S.
review of research on hedonic and eudaimonic well-being,” Annual Peters (ed.), New York: Macmillan: 139–61.
Review of Psychology, 52: 141–166. Seligman, M., 2002, Authentic Happiness, New York: Free Press.
Ryff, C. D., 1989, “Happiness is everything, or is it? Explorations on the –––, 2011, Flourish: A Visionary New Understanding of Happiness and
meaning of psychological well-being,” Journal of Personality and Well-being, New York: Simon & Schuster.
Social Psychology, 57(6): 1069–1081. Sen, A., 1987a, Commodities and Capabilities, New York: Oxford
Samson, C., 2019, “Indigenous and Western Views of Happiness: An University Press.
Essay on the Politics of Contentment,” Regimes of Happiness: –––, 1987b, On Ethics and Economics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Comparative and Historical Studies, B. Turner, J. T. Jen, and Y. –––, 2009, The Idea of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Contreras-Vejar (eds.), London: Anthem Press, 219–34. Press.
Savulescu, J., R. Ter Meulen, and G. Kahane, 2011, Enhancing Human Sidgwick, H., 1907 [1966], The Methods of Ethics, New York: Dover
Capacities, Oxford: John Wiley & Sons. Publications.
Scanlon, T., 1999, What We Owe to Each Other, Cambridge, MA: Harvard Silventoinen, K., S. Sammalisto, M. Perola, D. I. Boomsma, B. K. Cornes,
University Press. C. Davis, L. Dunkel, M. De Lange, J. R. Harris and J. V. B.
Schooler, J. W., D. Ariely and G. Loewenstein, 2003, “The Pursuit and Hjelmborg, 2003, “Heritability of adult body height: a comparative

60 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 61


Happiness Dan Haybron

study of twin cohorts in eight countries,” Twin Research, 6(5): 399– –––, 1991, “The Greatest Happiness Principle,” Utilitas, 3(1): 37–51.
408. Stenberg, J., 2019, “The All-Happy God,” Faith and Philosophy, 36(4):
Singer, P., 1972, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality,” Philosophy and 423–41.
Public Affairs, 1(3): 229–243. Stevenson, C. M., 2018, “Experience Machines, Conflicting Intuitions and
Singh, R., and A. Alexandrova, forthcoming, “Happiness Economics as the Bipartite Characterization of Well-Being,” Utilitas, 30(4): 383–
Technocracy,” Behavioural Public Policy, first online 12 Dec 2019: 98.
doi:10.17863/CAM.46854 Stevenson, B. and J. Wolfers, 2008, “Economic Growth and Subjective
Sizer, L., 2010, “Good and good for you: An affect theory of happiness,” Well-Being: Reassessing the Easterlin Paradox,” Brookings Papers
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80(1): 133–163. on Economic Activity, Spring 2008: 1–87.
Skidelsky, E., 2014, “What Can We Learn From Happiness Surveys?,” Stiglitz, J. E., J.-P. Fitoussi, and M. Durand, 2019, Measuring What
Journal of Practical Ethics, 2(2): 20–32. Counts: The Global Movement for Well-Being, New York: New
–––, 2017, “Happiness, Pleasure, and Belief,” Australasian Journal of Press.
Philosophy, 95(3): 435–446. Stiglitz, J. E., Amartya. Sen, and J.-Paul. Fitoussi, 2009, Report by the
Slote, M., 1982, “Goods and Lives,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 63: Commission on the Measurement of Economic Performance and
311–26. Social Progress, Paris: Commission on the Measurement of
–––, 1983, Goods and Virtues, New York: Oxford University Press. Economic Performance and Social Progress.
Smart, J. J. C., 1973, “An Outline of a System of Utilitarian Ethics,” Sugden, R., 2008, “Capability, Happiness, and Opportunity,” Capabilities
Utilitarianism: For and Against, J. J. C. Smart and B. Williams, New and Happiness, L. Bruni, F. Comim, and M. Pugno (eds.), New York:
York: Cambridge University Press: 3–74. Oxford University Press, 299–322.
Snow, N. E., and Trivigno, F. V., 2014, The Philosophy and Psychology of Suikkanen, J., 2011, “An Improved Whole Life Satisfaction Theory of
Character and Happiness, New York: Routledge. Happiness,” International Journal of Wellbeing, 1(1): 1–18.
Sosis, C., 2012, “Happiness: The Potential Power of Environment,” The –––, 2019. “The Advice Models of Happiness: A Response to Feldman,”
Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and International Journal of Wellbeing, 9(2), available online,
Communication, 7: 1–10. doi:10.5502/ijw.v9i2.837
–––, 2014, “Hedonic possibilities and heritability statistics,” Philosophical Sumner, L. W., 1996, Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics, New York: Oxford
Psychology, 27(5): 681–702. University Press.
Spahn, A., 2015, “Can Technology Make Us Happy?,” Well-Being in –––, 2000, “Something In Between,” Well-Being and Morality, R. Crisp
Contemporary Society, J. H. Søraker, et al. (eds.), Cham: Springer, and B. Hooker (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press, 1–19.
93–113. Tatarkiewicz, W., 1976, Analysis of Happiness, The Hague: Martinus
Sprigge, T. L. S., 1987, The Rational Foundations of Ethics, New York: Nijhoff.
Routledge and Kegan Paul. Telfer, E., 1980, Happiness, New York: St. Martin’s Press.

62 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 63


Happiness Dan Haybron

Thaler, R. H. and C. R. Sunstein, 2008, Nudge : improving decisions about Contemporary Society, J. H. Søraker, et al. (eds.), Cham: Springer,
health, wealth, and happiness, New Haven: Yale University Press. 215–31.
Thomas, D. A. L., 1968, “Happiness,” Philosophical Quarterly, 18: 97– Veenhoven, R., 1984, Conditions of Happiness, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
113. –––, 1997, “Advances in Understanding Happiness,” Revue Québécoise de
Tiberius, V., 2006, “Well-Being: Psychological Research for Psychologie, 18: 29–79.
Philosophers,” Philosophy Compass, 1: 493–505. –––, 2005, “Is Life Getting Better? How Long and Happily Do People
–––, 2008, The Reflective Life, New York: Oxford University Press. Live in Modern Society?” European Psychologist, 10(4): 330–343.
–––, 2014, Moral Psychology: A Contemporary Introduction, New York: Velleman, J. D., 1991, “Well-Being and Time,” Pacific Philosophical
Routledge Quarterly, 72(1): 48–77.
–––, 2018, Well-Being As Value Fulfillment, New York: Oxford University Verhoef, A., 2018, “Paul Ricoeur: Philosophy, Theology and Happiness,”
Press, USA. Stellenbosch Theological Journal, 4(2): 151–66.
Tiberius, V. and A. Plakias, 2010, “Well-Being,” The Moral Psychology Vitrano, C., 2010, “The subjectivity of happiness,” Journal of Value
Handbook, J. Doris, G. Harman, S. Nichols, et al. (eds.), New York: Inquiry, 44(1): 47–54.
Oxford University Press. –––, 2014, The Nature and Value of Happiness, Boulder: Westview Press.
Trout, J. D., 2005, “Paternalism and Cognitive Bias,” Law and Višak, T., 2015, “Sacrifices of Self Are Prudential Harms: A Reply to
Philosophy, 24: 393–434. Carbonell,” The Journal of Ethics, 19(2): 219–29.
–––, 2009, The Empathy Gap: Building bridges to the good life and the Vittersø, J., ed., 2016, Handbook of Eudaimonic Well-Being, Berlin:
good society, New York: Viking Press. Springer.
Trout, J. D., and S. A. Buttar, 2000, “Resurrecting ‘Death Taxes’: Von Wright, G. H., 1963, The Varieties of Goodness, London: Routledge
Inheritance, Redistribution, and the Science of Happiness,” Journal & Kegan Paul.
of Law & Politics, 16(4): 765–847. Walker, M., 2011, “Happy-People-Pills for All,” International Journal of
van der Deijl, Willem, 2016, “What Happiness Science Can Learn from Wellbeing, 1(1): 1–22.
John Stuart Mill,” International Journal of Wellbeing, 6(1): 164–79. Waterman, A. S., 1993, “Two Conceptions of Happiness: Contrasts of
–––, 2017a, “Are Measures of Well-Being Philosophically Adequate?,” Personal Expressiveness (Eudaimonia) and Hedonic Enjoyment,”
Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 47(3): 209–34. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64(4): 678–691.
–––, 2017b, The Measurement of Wellbeing in Economics: Philosophical –––, ed., 2013, The Best within Us: Positive Psychology Perspectives on
Explorations, Ph.D. Dissertation, Erasmus University Rotterdam. Eudaimonia, Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
–––, 2017c, “Which Problem of Adaptation?,” Utilitas, 29(4): 474–92. Weijers, D., 2013, “Intuitive Biases in Judgments about Thought
van der Rijt, J.-W., 2013, “Public Policy and the Conditional Value of Experiments: The Experience Machine Revisited,” Philosophical
Happiness,” Economics and Philosophy, 29(3): 381–408. Writings, 41(1): 17–31.
–––, 2015, “The Political Turn Towards Happiness,” Well-Being in –––, 2014, “Nozick’s experience machine is dead, long live the experience

64 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 65


Happiness Dan Haybron

machine!,” Philosophical Psychology, 27(4): 513–535. Academic Tools


White, M. D., 2013, “Can We—and Should We—Measure Well-Being?,”
Review of Social Economy, 71(4): 526–33. How to cite this entry.
White, M. P. and P. Dolan, 2009, “Accounting for the Richness of Daily Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP
Activities,” Psychological Science, 20(8): 1000–1008. Society.
White, N. P., 2006, A Brief History of Happiness, Oxford: Blackwell. Look up this entry topic at the Internet Philosophy Ontology
Project (InPhO).
Wierzbicka, A., 2004, “‘Happiness’ in cross-linguistic & cross-cultural
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links
perspective,” Daedalus, 133(2): 34–43.
to its database.
Williams, B., 1981, Moral Luck. Moral Luck, New York, Cambridge
University Press: 20–39.
Other Internet Resources
Wilson, J., 1968, “Happiness,” Analysis, 29: 13–21.
Wodak, D., 2019, “What If Well-Being Measurements Are Non-Linear?,” World Database of Happiness, Erasmus University of Rotterdam.
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 97(1): 29–45. Positive Psychology Center, University of Pennsylvania.
Wong, D. B., 2013, “On Learning What Happiness Is,” Philosophical The Happiness and Well-Being Project, with Suggested Readings and
Topics, 41(1): 81–101. links to Funded Research, Saint Louis University.
Wren-Lewis, S, 2013, “Well-Being as a Primary Good: Towards
Legitimate Well-Being Policy,” Philosophy & Public Policy Related Entries
Quarterly, 31(2): 2–9.
–––, 2014, “How successfully can we measure well-being through Aquinas, Saint Thomas | Aristotle | Bentham, Jeremy | character, moral:
measuring happiness?,” South African Journal of Philosophy, 33: empirical approaches | communitarianism | consequentialism | economics:
417–432. philosophy of | emotion | ethics: ancient | ethics: virtue | hedonism | Kant,
–––, 2019, The Happiness Problem: Expecting Better in an Uncertain Immanuel | liberalism | Mill, John Stuart | moral psychology: empirical
World, Chicago, IL: Policy Press. approaches | pain | paternalism | Plato | pleasure | well-being
Zamuner, E., 2013, “Happiness, Consciousness, and the Ontology of
Mind,” Philosophical Topics, 41(1): 237–54. Acknowledgments
Zhang, E. Y., 2019, “Forgetfulness and Flow: ‘Happiness’ in Zhuangzi’s
Daoism,” Science, Religion and Culture, 6(1): 77–84. For helpful comments, many thanks are due to Anna Alexandrova, Robert
Biswas-Diener, Thomas Carson, Irwin Goldstein, Richard Lucas, Jason
Raibley, Eric Schwitzgebel, Stephen Schueller, Adam Shriver, Edward
Zalta, and an anonymous referee for the SEP. Portions of Section 2 are
adapted from Haybron 2008, “Philosophy and the Science of Subjective

66 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 67


Happiness Dan Haybron

Well-Being,” in Eid and Larsen, The Science of Subjective Well-Being, and “Cross-Cultural Studies of Well-Being” assembled by Flanagan,
used with kind permission of Guilford Press. Letourneau and Zhao, including Flanagan et al. 2019, Euler 2019 and
Zhang 2019 among others; also, Joshanloo 2013, Joshanloo and Weijers
Notes to Happiness 2019, Purcell 2014, and Samson 2019. The largest body of non-Western
scholarship on happiness, usually in something like the well-being sense,
1. This article focuses on the standard division between descriptive and engages with Asian philosophy and religion; e.g., Fraser 2013, Ho et al.
evaluative senses of ‘happiness’ (see also Feldman 2010, Sumner 1996). 2014, Joshanloo 2014, Kim 2020, Luo 2018, Wong 2013, and Zhang
But that distinction may be challenged, or there might be evaluative 2019.
elements in the “psychological” sense of ‘happiness’ even if it is not
equivalent to well-being. For example, some argue that pleasure is itself 3. Possible examples of theories grounded in failures properly to
partly an evaluative kind (e.g., Goldstein 1989). Phillips et al. have argued distinguish these projects include Smart and Hare’s accounts, on which
that the folk concept of happiness is be a mix of psychological and happiness is basically about one’s mental states; but it is also partly
evaluative, drawing on a series of studies (Phillips, Misenheimer, et al. evaluative, in that (for example) we cannot properly call someone happy if
2011; Phillips et al. 2017). we find her desires, pleasures, circumstances, etc. to be repulsive or
otherwise undesirable (Hare 1963, Smart 1973; see also Nozick 1989). It
2. This claim holds only as a rough generalization, with some exceptions. is not clear what the point of such a concept would be, or what of
Chekola 2007 and Murphy 2001, for instance, appear to use ‘happiness’ as substance—rather than merely linguistic usage—is at issue between such
a descriptive term for a life that is successful from the agent’s point of theories and other accounts of ‘happiness.’ While the main philosophical
view. While there are other senses of ‘happiness’ and cognates, this article issues relate to matters of substance, it may sometimes be useful to pursue
discusses only the main philosophically significant uses of ‘happiness’ and a linguistic approach focused on the meaning of “happiness.” For
cognates; on other senses, see Davis 1981b, Goldstein 1973, Suikkanen example, in a textbook surveying philosophical theories of happiness it
2011 and Thomas 1968. Readers should note that many philosophical might be desirable to cover the full range of philosophical work under that
works do not clearly distinguish the psychological and well-being notions, rubric, leaving it open whether the literature on ‘happiness’ concerns one,
and it is not always clear how a given author employs the term. In some two, or more subject matters. A risk of that approach is that some
cases ‘happiness’ takes neither the psychological nor well-being meaning, commentators stipulate that their theories are not in competition with
and so it may be unclear how the discussion relates to broader much of the literature on “happiness,” so that it would be misleading to
philosophical debates such as those covered in this article. A further suggest that, for example, Aristotle (in English translation) and Sumner
wrinkle is that there is a growing body of non-Western and cross-cultural disagree about the nature of happiness. Any apparent disagreement is
work on happiness, and it is plausible that the philosophical landscape purely verbal.
depicted in this article will need revision if it is to accommodate the
diversity of human thinking about (or not thinking about, as the case may 4. For some recent examples of articles on the well-being sense, see
be) happiness and well-being. See, for example, a 2019 special issue on Angier 2015, Capuccino 2013, Cashen 2012, Kristjánsson 2010, 2012,

68 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 69


Happiness Dan Haybron

2018, and Vitrano 2010. Most historical work on “happiness,” at least in Almeder 2000, Kekes 1982, 1988, 1992, McFall 1989, Meynell 1969,
pre-modern philosophy, employs the well-being sense. Most empirical Scruton 1975, Tatarkiewicz 1976, Thomas 1968, Tiberius 2008, Tiberius
researchers employ the term in the psychological sense; for an apparent and Plakias 2010, Vitrano 2010. Empirical researchers often identify life
exception, see Seligman 2002, though he has lately shifted focus away satisfaction and happiness—notably, Veenhoven 1984, 1997.
from the term ‘happiness’ (Seligman 2011). For reviews of the
philosophical literature, see Badhwar 2015, Den Uyl and Machan 1983, 7. Emotional state theories seem to have become the most common view
and the chapters in Section III of David et al. 2015. Accessible in the last decade or so. Authors who appear to endorse some form of this
introductory texts include Mulnix and Mulnix 2015a. Recent anthologies approach include Badhwar 2014, Becker 2012, Besser-Jones 2013,
of the philosophical literature include Cahn and Vitrano 2008 and Mulnix Haybron 2005, 2008b, Kauppinen 2013, Klausen 2015, 2019, de Lazari-
and Mulnix 2015b. Bortolotti 2009 and Snow and Trivigno 2014 are Radek and Singer 2014, May 2015, Raibley 2011, Rodogno 2016, Rossi
edited collections of new papers. An accessible collection of papers by 2018, Rossi and Tappolet 2016, Sizer 2010, Tiberius 2018, Višak 2015,
philosophers and other researchers can be found in the Spring 2004 issue and possibly Bok 2010b. A prominent contribution from the lay literature
of Daedalus. An influential discussion of different happiness concepts, is Ricard 2006. For discussions of particular emotions and moods in the
focusing mainly on the well-being notion, is Kraut 1979. context of happiness or well-being, see Griswold 1996 on tranquility and
Roberts 2019 on joy. Because hedonistic and emotional state theories have
5. See, e.g., Blackson 2009; Brandt 1959, Brandt 1979, 1989, 1992; seldom been distinguished, some ostensibly “hedonistic” approaches to
Campbell 1973; Carson 1978a, 1978b, 1979, 1981; Davis 1981b, 1981a; happiness might more accurately be characterized as emotional state
Ebenstein 1991; Feldman 2010; Griffin 1979, 1986; Kazez 2007; views. Among empirical researchers, for instance, affect-based approaches
Mayerfeld 1996, 1999; Morris 2011; Sen 1987a; Sprigge 1987, 1991; to happiness are typically described as hedonistic, yet normally focus on
Wilson 1968; Zamuner 2013. For a recent extended defense of hedonism moods and emotions rather than (e.g.) sensory pleasures and pains.
about happiness, see Feldman 2010. Among psychologists, see e.g.
Parducci 1995 and Kahneman 1999. 8. The moniker “affect-based” is problematic given that some variants of
hedonism conceive of pleasure in non-affective terms, for instance as an
6. Variants of the life satisfaction view appear to include Barrow 1980, attitude of liking or being pleased, where this attitude need not involve
1991, Benditt 1974, 1978, Brülde 2007, Buss 2004, Campbell 1973, affect (e.g., Feldman 2004, 2010). It is possible that such theories, which
Goldman 2016, 2019, Montague 1967, Mulligan 2016, Nozick 1989, bear similarities to the life satisfaction view, should be distinguished from
Rescher 1972, 1980, Skidelsky 2017, Suikkanen 2011, Sumner 1996, more familiar varieties of hedonism.
2000, Telfer 1980, and Von Wright 1963. While Goldman and Mulligan
characterize happiness as an emotion, the relevant emotion appears to 9. On the significance of life satisfaction for well-being research, see
constitute an attitude of life satisfaction. Those making life satisfaction Alexandrova 2005, 2008, Tiberius and Plakias 2010.
central or identical to well-being, or “happiness” in the well-being sense,
appear to include (in addition to some of the aforementioned authors)

70 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 71


Happiness Dan Haybron

10. See Alexandrova 2005, 2008, Tiberius 2006, Tiberius and Plakias maintained on the webpages of the Happiness and Well-Being Project (see
2010, Suikkanen 2011. the link in the Other Internet Resources). Philosophical engagement with
empirical research on happiness has picked up considerably in recent
11. For recent discussions of measurement issues, see, e.g., Adler 2019, years, monographs including, e.g., Alexandrova 2017, Badhwar 2014,
Alexandrova 2017, Alexandrova and Haybron 2016, Angner 2008, 2009, Besser 2014, Bishop 2015, Bok 2010b, Feldman 2010, Flanagan 2007,
2010, 2011, 2013, de Boer 2014, Cohen Kaminitz forthcoming, Fleurbaey Kenny and Kenny 2006, Sumner 1996, Tiberius 2008, 2014, Wren-Lewis
and Blanchet 2013, Hausman 2010, Haybron 2016, OECD 2013, White 2019. There has also been some collaborative work on happiness between
2013, Skidelsky 2014, Stiglitz et al. 2009, van der Deijl 2016a, 2016b, philosophers and empirical researchers; for instance, Ahuvia et al. 2015,
2017, Wodak 2019, Wren-Lewis 2014. Intelisano et al. 2019, Oishi et al., and other teams funded by the
Happiness and Well-Being Project (again, see Other Internet Resources).
12. See, e.g., Krueger, Kahneman, et al. 2009.
In experimental philosophy, recent studies include Phillips et al. 2011,
13. See, e.g., Haybron 2007, Schwitzgebel and Hurlburt 2007, 2014, 2017, Robbins et al. 2018, as well as the experience machine studies
Schwitzgebel 2008, 2011, Goldstein 1981, 2002. cited below.

14. Good examples can be found in the Gallup studies discussed in section 17. For reviews of this literature, see Frederick and Loewenstein 1999,
3.3 (Kahneman and Deaton 2010; Diener, Ng, et al. 2010). These studies Lucas 2008, Luhmann and Intelisano 2018.
roughly assess both life satisfaction and emotional state, using a suite of
18. See, e.g., Diener, Lucas, et al. 2006, Lucas, Clark, et al. 2004a, 2004b,
inquiries about particular types of affect to get at the latter. Compare the
Lucas 2008, Diener 2008, Lyubomirsky, Sheldon, et al. 2005, Easterlin
World Values Survey, which uses a “happiness” question and a “life
2003, Easterlin 2005, Inglehart and Klingemann 2000, Inglehart, Foa, et
satisfaction” question (e.g., Inglehart, Foa, et al. 2008). Straightforwardly
al. 2008, Headey 2007, 2008, Luhmann and Intelisano 2018.
hedonistic measures of subjective well-being are less common, one sign
being whether physical pain is assessed, but seem to figure most 19. Heritability figures must be read with considerable caution: among
prominently in time-use studies. other things, they reflect only the amount of variation within the studied
population that can be explained by genes, roughly speaking. If your
15. For example, Ryff 1989, Waterman 1993, Ryan and Deci 2001, Keyes
subjects live in relatively homogeneous environments, heritability findings
2002, Seligman 2002, Seligman 2011. Two excellent collections of papers
will increase. Since twin studies tend not to include twins separated and
on eudaimonic psychology, including both empirical and philosophical
placed in radically different environments—say, contemporary Manhattan
contributions, are Vittersø 2016 and Waterman 2013.
versus San Bushmen, or 19th century versus contemporary Dutchmen—
16. For scholarly reviews of this literature, see David et al. 2013, Diener et they often overstate the heritability of traits relative to the full spectrum of
al. 2018a, 2018b. A more extensive list of suggested readings to get started human societies, and correspondingly understate the role of environment.
on various aspects of the literature on happiness and well-being is For philosophical discussion, see Bishop 2015, Sosis 2012, 2014.

72 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 73


Happiness Dan Haybron

20. E.g., Biswas-Diener, Vittersø, et al. 2005, Biswas-Diener 2018, 24. For recent discussion of these and other doubts about the value of
Graham 2009, Diener and Suh 2000, Inglehart and Klingemann 2000, happiness, see Belliotti 2004, 2013.
Inglehart, Foa, et al. 2008. For a striking informal account of a hunter-
gatherer society, the Pirahã, see Everett 2009. What these findings show 25. Recent years have seen lively debate about the experience machine
about well-being depends on the importance of happiness for it (see case. Some examples include Bramble 2016, Hawkins 2016, Kraut 2018,
section 4). Note that high happiness can coexist with low longevity, which Lin 2015, Stevenson 2018, and Weijers 2011. Empirical studies of lay
is clearly important on most views of well-being. For this reason, intuitions include De Brigard 2010, Hindricks and Douven 2018, Weijers
happiness measures may be unable to tell the whole story about well-being 2014.
even if we accept a mental state view of well-being. For an effort rectify
26. See, e.g., Elster 1983, Millgram 2000, Nussbaum 2000, Sen 1987b,
this limitation within happiness research, see Veenhoven 2005.
2009, van der Deijl 2017b, Mitchell 2018.
21. For useful surveys and lists, see Myers and Diener 1995, Argyle 1999,
27. The consensus ends, however, on the question of what virtue entails.
2002, Layard 2005, Bok 2010a, Diener et al. 2018, Jebb et al. 2020, and
Indeed, skeptics about (conventional) morality such as Nietzsche might
the annual World Happiness Reports starting with Helliwell et al. 2012.
hold that virtue—acting well—entails immorality, at least relative to
Philosophical discussions of the causes and correlates of happiness
conventional standards of morality (see also, e.g., the discussion of
include, e.g., Ahuvia et al. 2015, Andreou 2010, Brülde 2014, Haybron
“Gaugin” in Williams 1981, and “Admirable Immorality” in Slote 1983).
2013a, Lauinger 2015, Morris 2015, Setiya 2014, Tiberius 2017, Wren-
This is one reason to frame the view broadly, in terms of virtue, rather than
Lewis 2019.
morality. Hurka’s excellent, accessible discussion of the good life may
22. On the last, see, e.g., Kellert and Wilson 1995, Frumkin 2001, seem to reject the priority of virtue, but his treatment of virtue as a
Haybron 2011, Capaldi et al. 2015, Lumber et al. 2017, Bosch and Bird “lesser” good concerns its contribution to the sum of intrinsic value in a
2018, Houlden et al. 2018. life, not the importance of doing the right thing (Hurka 2010).

23. Importantly, this study and the Stevenson and Wolfers study use log 28. Besides authentic happiness theories, there have been a number of
income instead of raw income, which substantially accounts for the other recent proposals to incorporate happiness as one among other
stronger income-life satisfaction correlations than those found in earlier constituents of well-being, e.g., Bishop 2012, 2015, Fletcher 2013,
research. While neither metric is unambiguously superior, log income has Jayawickreme and Pawelski 2013, MacLeod 2015, Raibley 2012, 2013,
the advantage of tracking proportional differences in income: a major Rodogno 2016, Rossi and Tappolet 2016. Badhwar 2014 notably
question, for instance, is the impact of economic growth on happiness. For incorporates an emotional state conception of happiness in an Aristotelian
this purpose, the impact of, say, a five percent gain in income is more account of well-being as “happiness in an objectively worthwhile life.”
relevant than that of a $500 increase, which might represent a large gain
29. Other authors who have expressed doubts about the unity of well-
for some, small for others.
being include Griffin 2000, 2007, Raz 1986, 2004, Scanlon 1999,

74 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 75


Happiness Dan Haybron

Alexandrova 2017. 35. For worries about even this sort of paternalism, see Hausman and
Welch 2009.
30. Recent philosophical discussions of norms governing the proper
pursuit of happiness include Badhwar 2008, 2014, Beck and Stroop 2014, Copyright © 2020 by the author
Haybron 2013b, Kahane 2012, Spahn 2015, Tiberius 2008, Walker 2011. Dan Haybron

31. A sampling of other recent philosophical work on human limitations in


the pursuit of happiness includes Angner 2016, Besser 2013, Billon 2016,
Paul 2014. A comprehensive review of the empirical literature in this area
is Haybron 2008b.

32. While most policy discussion embeds happiness metrics such as life
satisfaction or emotional well-being in a broader approach that considers
other outcomes as well, there is significant support for a narrower focus on
happiness, notably in Layard 2005 and Clark et al. 2018. Good sources on
the policy debate include the World Happiness Reports published annually
since Helliwell et al. 2012, annual reports from the Global Happiness
Council from 2018 onward, resources available through the OECD,
Stiglitz et al. 2009, Stiglitz et al. 2019, Diener et al. 2009, Adler and
Fleurbaey 2015. Philosophical discussions include, among others, Adler
2019, Alexandrova 2018, Angner 2009, Austin 2015, Bagaric and
McConvill 2005, Becker 2012, Bok 2010a, Fleurbaey and Blanchet 2013,
Hausman 2010, Haybron and Alexandrova 2013, Haybron and Tiberius
2015, Hersch 2015, 2020, Kenny and Kenny 2006, Metz 2014, Moller
2011, Nussbaum 2010, Singh and Alexandrova forthcoming, Sugden
2008, Trout and Buttar 2000, van der Rijt 2015, White 2013, Wren-Lewis
2013, and other sources noted below.

33. See, e.g., Trout 2005, Loewenstein and Haisley 2008, Thaler and
Sunstein 2008, Trout 2009.

34. E.g., Ross and Nisbett 1991, Haidt 2001, Doris 2002, Doris 2009,
Doris 2015, Christakis, Fowler, et al. 2009, Haybron 2014.

76 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 Edition 77

You might also like