Ethical Investment Processes and Outcome PDF

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

Ethical Investment Grant Michelson

Nick Wailes
Processes Sandra van der Laan
and Outcomesq Geoff Frost

ABSTRACT. There is a growing body of literature on ethical Introduction


or socially responsible investment across a range of disciplines.
This paper highlights the key themes in the field and identifies
Ethical investment has emerged in recent years as a
some of the major theoretical and practical challenges facing
both scholars and practitioners. One of these challenges is un- fashionable and increasingly popular topic in the
derstanding better the complexity of the relationship between financial services industry, particularly in the United
such investment practices and corporate behaviour. Noting that States. Estimates in that country are that about one
ethical investment is seldom characterised by agreement about in every eight investment dollars (13%) are now
what it actully constitutes, and that much of the extant research committed to ethical investment funds (Social
focuses on a narrow set of issues, the paper argues that there
are benefits associated with examining ethical investment as a Investment Forum, 2001). While of less current
process. significance in other national contexts, including the
United Kingdom and Australia, investment patterns
KEY WORDS: ethical investment, socially responsible
in both countries also point to an increasing trend of
investing, screening, funds management, corporate social
responsibility
monies being placed in ethical funds (Williams,
1999). There are a number of possible reasons for
this growth including those on both the supply side
Grant Michelson is a senior lecturer in Work and Organisational (e.g. legislative imperatives and requirements of
Studies, School of Business at the University of Sydney. Dr. funds, managers of investment funds identifying a
Michelson’s teaching and research interests include business new opportunity in the market to broaden their
ethics, industrial relations, and organisational behaviour investor base) and demand side of financial markets
(especially the moral dimension of rumour and gossip at
(e.g. the personal preferences of both individual and
work).
institutional investors revealing unequivocal support
Nick Wailes is a lecturer in Work and Organisational Studies,
School of Business at the University of Sydney. He teaches for moral considerations) (Cullis et al., 1992, p. 8).
strategic management and entrepreneurship. Dr. Wailes’s ‘‘Ethical investment’’ (the term favoured in the
research interests include the impact of enterprise resource United Kingdom) or ‘‘socially responsible invest-
planning systems on work organisation and the influence of ment’’ (the term commonly used in the United
institutional investors on corporate human resource strategies. States) is broadly defined as the integration of per-
Sandra van der Laan is a lecturer in Accounting and Business sonal values, social considerations and economic
Law, School of Business at the University of Sydney. She is factors into the investment decision. Financial return
a member of the Asia Pacific Centre for Environmental remains an important outcome but it is not the sole
Accountability (APCEA). Her research focuses on social criterion driving investments; ethical concerns are
accounting and she is currently completing a Ph.D. on socially also included. As one equities manager reported
responsible investment.
when describing the raison d’être of an ethical fund:
Geoff Frost is a senior lecturer in Accounting and Business Law,
‘‘There’s nothing wrong with making money but it’s
School of Business at the University of Sydney. He teaches
management accounting. Dr. Frost’s research interests include how you make the money that counts’’ (see Murray,
environmental reporting, the role of accountants in the envi- 2003).
ronmental management system, and the use of alternate There is an increasing body of literature which
reporting mediums by reporting entities. examines the topic of ethical investment. Until

Journal of Business Ethics 52: 1–10, 2004.


 2004 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.
2 Grant Michelson et al.

very recently, there has been relatively little attempt be to simply ‘‘feel good’’ (psychic income) or to try
to try and synthesise the different threads in and promote social change, even if this means
this work (for one exception, this journal produced a receiving a slightly lower financial return than
special issue on social investment screens – see conventional investors. In this sense, an ‘‘ethical
volume 43, number 3, March 2003). The collection penalty’’ is placed on the action of having invested
of papers presented here seeks to further advance according to one’s values (Tippet, 2001, p. 176). It
our understanding of ethical investment by explor- could be that individuals who invest in ethical causes
ing the issue in its entirety. That is, it examines are relatively wealthy and therefore able to bear a
the motives and actions of individual and institu- financial cost (Tippet and Leung, 2001). Naturally,
tional investors, discusses the various processes or this assumes that investors are aware that their
mechanisms associated with ethical investment, as- monies might perform better somewhere else.
sesses the impact of ethical investment on the Gender and education seem to play a part in
behaviour of the organisation, and evaluates the explaining the growth of socially responsible
outcomes of ethical investment for special interest investment, at least in the United States (Schueth,
groups. The purpose of this paper is to highlight 2003, p. 192). These demographic characteristics
many of the key themes in the research literature as also appear useful in profiling those more likely to
well as to identify some theoretical and practical invest in such funds in other countries. For example,
challenges for the field. ethical investors in Australia tend to be women, are
relatively young, and highly educated (Tippet and
Leung, 2001).
Who invests in socially responsible investment? However, as Dunfee (2003, p. 249) and Lewis
(2002) have recently argued, more needs to be
It might be assumed by some that those who invest known about investor psychology in the context of
in ethical or socially responsible funds do not invest socially responsible investment. McLachlan and
at all in non-ethical funds. While there will be Gardner in the second paper to this special issue
individuals for whom this claim is accurate, some engage with this need and show that key differences
research evidence reveals that it is common for between ethical and non-ethical (or conventional)
people to invest both in socially responsible and individual investors remain. These writers also cau-
more standardised or conventional funds. The tion against discounting the needs and desires of
motivations of ethical investors appear to be quite socially responsible investors in terms of the mar-
complicated in reality (Lewis, 2002; Mackenzie and keting of financial services funds. Broadening the
Lewis, 1999). There is no straightforward trade-off level of analysis to an examination of institutional
between a person’s values and their desired and ex- investors, Cox and his colleagues in the next con-
pected financial return (Lewis and Mackenzie, tribution provides further evidence for the thesis that
2000a). In other words, investors in ethical funds an organisation’s social performance influences long-
appear to spread their monies across a range of funds term investment by institutions.
with different risk-return profiles. Given this find-
ing, it is equally plausible that the better performing
ethical funds attract not just ethical investors but The processes of ethical investment
more general or conventional investors as well. This
is unsurprising as financial return is an important Part of the process of socially responsible investing
criterion for investors, regardless of the (ethical) includes the development of mechanisms which
status of the fund. inform actual and potential investors about the
Nonetheless, some investors do feel the need to involvement of organisations in activities which are
put their money to work in ways that are consistent seen either as of concern or are attractive in ethical
with their personal values, and are generally com- terms (Cullis et al., 1992). Integral to this is the
mitted to their socially responsible investments even development of social screens. Screening is the
if they perform poorly or are ethically ineffective practice of excluding or including companies from
(Webley et al., 2001). Part of their motivation might investment portfolios based on a range of social and
Ethical Investment Processes and Outcomes 3

environmental criteria. Thus, there are two major nual reports emphasising a selective range of prac-
ways of establishing whether an investment is ethi- tices appear self-serving. Perhaps the best way
cal. The first is to apply a negative screen (a ‘‘never forward is to establish uniform accounting principles
if ’’ case) whereby certain businesses are avoided, for social reporting, including the auditing of any
presumably because they are injurious to human such reports produced (see Dunfee, 2003).
health. These have generally included the com- Other studies which have sought the views of
monly listed troika ‘‘sin’’ equities of alcohol, toba- fund managers (as opposed to individual investors)
cco and gambling. The second way is to apply a reveal that the availability and accuracy of company
positive screen (an ‘‘only if ’’ case) to those firms that information is a crucial mechanism in the ethical
remain possible investment targets; in particular, investment process. A survey of 172 investment
those identified as engaging in socially responsible professionals in the U.K. found that company
practices are seen as more attractive investment information was rated ahead of other commonly
options. used screening criteria including product safety,
Precise data on the proportion of investments that environmental record and employment practices
are ethically screened are difficult to establish, due to (Schlegelmilch, 1997). Coupled with their expressed
the lack of consensus on how to define ethical desire to capture a good rate of return, this finding
investments (Schlegelmilch, 1997). Exploratory re- suggests that investment professionals could be
search reveals some variance in the criteria used by receptive to more information being provided about
ethical investment fund managers to screen firms. a firm’s social activities. Whether companies are
For some of these managers, the behaviour of firms prepared to provide more information to such
is more important than the product or service pro- investors is debateable.
vided (Stone, 2001). A best-in-class or best-in- In the paper by Hummels and Timmer, the au-
industry approach is favoured by some funds thors raise some doubts about the provision of rel-
whereby membership of an ostensibly ‘‘bad’’ evant social, ethical and environmental (SEE)
industry does not automatically disqualify a company information by three well-known multinationals
from investment by the fund. Companies within the (Nike, BP and Monsanto). However, there are signs
same industry sector are compared and ranked that the nature of shareholder engagement might be
against each other, not against those outside the changing in contemporary organisations. Hockerts
industry. The best-in-industry approach clearly and Moir claim in their paper that the investor
confirms the importance of seeking good financial relations function within a sample of predominantly
returns as ‘‘sinful’’ industries often provide above- European multinational firms are becoming more
average returns on investment (Tippet, 2001, p. sophisticated. Investor relations managers are
172). It also highlights a more proactive desire to increasingly aware of corporate social responsibility
work to improve the overall social performance of issues and the need to communicate more effectively
firms, rather than investing in companies that, on the with actual and potential investors. The companies
surface, appear to be moral entities simply because surveyed acknowledged the need for improved dis-
they are located in more ‘‘ethically acceptable’’ parts closure and reporting on social and environmental
of the economy. For example, a firm that recycles performance.
waste and paper products may rate highly on envi- We maintain that the inter-related issues of
ronmental performance, but might adopt poor transparency and disclosure are clearly important
practices in other areas such as supplier, customer considerations at the company or firm level. This is
and employee relations. The best-in-industry ap- no less relevant for the funds themselves. Investors
proach would therefore allow investment in mining need to carefully examine the prospectus to see if
companies provided that they seek to be socially the fund performance and ethical guidelines meet
responsible in terms of cleaning up after themselves their needs (Hollingworth, 1998). However, this
and adopting safe operating practices. information might not be provided or, if it is, might
An ongoing challenge for those who employ be unreliable (Hoggett and Nahan, 2002). Ethical or
various screens using a best-in-industry approach is socially responsible funds are not always forthcom-
how to judge a firm’s performance. Company an- ing about which companies (and why) are included
4 Grant Michelson et al.

in their portfolios (Tippet, 2001). As part of a ‘‘unethical’’ practice by organisations on any


commissioned report on the ethical investment dimension could be unworkable and potentially
industry in Australia, how fund managers actually exclude all firms from consideration. With the
manage the money as opposed to what they report breadth of their reach and activities, this argument is
to their investors was examined. The processes particularly relevant in the case of multinational
used by fund managers to determine which busi- firms. Such organisations are often involved with
nesses to invest in varied significantly. Of the 16 many products across many countries.
ethical funds surveyed, only four funds were re- Another issue to consider around negative screens
garded as having a high level of transparency (TEC, is the question of primary and secondary involve-
2003). Given the plausibility that each investor’s ment. While potential investors may baulk at the
idea of ethical or socially responsible investment is defence industry (armaments companies per se), they
different, the need for clear reporting procedures might be less concerned with investing in steel
about how the funds actually invest is crucial. More companies or electronics firms even though such
transparency in the practices adopted by fund firms are involved in the supply chain of weapons
managers will provide investors with more confi- production through military hardware and missile
dence in terms of ensuring their monies are invested guidance systems. To address such possibilities, some
in industries and companies consistent with their funds establish a maximum threshold figure whereby
own social priorities. certain companies are excluded only when the
Of course, there are other problematics with the proportion of sales of, say, steel or electronics to the
screening process. For example, there is no single more explicitly offensive defence industry becomes
definition of ‘‘social responsibility’’ (and therefore too high. But what is considered too high? Schepers
no consensus as to an appropriate standard) for the and Sethi (2003, p. 17) contend that the cut-off
purposes of establishing investment screens. One figure is subjective and is not uniformly applied
consequence of this is that the screening criteria across different funds. Despite the practical difficul-
employed are quite subjective (Hollingworth, 1998). ties of acquiring accurate information about the level
Not surprisingly, both similarities and differences in of involvement, indirect or secondary contribution
ethical concerns exist in different national settings, should still be part of the screening process. This
including the United Kingdom and the United will ensure ethical consistency (Schwartz, 2003, p.
States (Williams, 1999). Even within the so-called 209).
‘‘sin’’ industries there is no general consensus. While Positive screens are also not without their prob-
tobacco might be seen as morally objectionable lems. Some contend that the process of attributing
(Schwartz, 2003; Yach et al., 2001), in some coun- socially desirable and responsible practices to firms –
tries gambling is not (Schwartz, 2003). The criteria thereby increasing their attraction as investment
for defining negative screens seem simplistic targets – is subject to a wide degree of variability.
whereby the product or service, rather than its im- The example of ‘‘diversity’’ is given whereby dif-
pact, is addressed. For instance, the case of screening ferent behaviours (e.g. equal opportunity programs,
against military contracting could be rebutted where active recruitment of minorities, and discrimination
peacekeeping roles are increasingly being served by policies) are usually identified as representing
military forces. Here, more social good than social diversity within an organisation. But are these
harm might result (Schepers and Sethi, 2003, p. 19). behaviours fully representative of notions of diver-
This is not to suggest that the field is incoherent; sity? How should diversity be operationalised?
some argue there is a need to accept different ap- (Schepers and Sethi, 2003, p. 22).
proaches to social screening (e.g. Dunfee, 2003). Perhaps for all of these reasons, ethical investment
Consequently, it is claimed that investors indeed needs to be considered as much a process as a set of
know the ‘‘perfect company’’ is a fiction and that the specific aims. The identity of specific criteria might
screening or evaluation process is simply about become less important than ‘‘… the way in which
identifying better-managed businesses (Schueth, issues are identified and considered, the degree of
2003, p. 190). No more and no less. Thus, the information obtained, (and) the action that is taken
imposition by investors of a zero tolerance level of in response’’ (Taylor, 2001, p. 59).
Ethical Investment Processes and Outcomes 5

Does ethical investment pay? ward investors. Indeed, it is argued that ethical
investment will attract a financial penalty and lead to
How ethically screened investments perform in lower returns than other forms of investment. This
relation to unscreened or more conventional funds is perspective might be summarised as a ‘‘doing poorly
one of the most contentious and debated issues in the by doing good’’ argument. These reasons will now
field. There is some evidence that it does pay, while be discussed.
other evidence suggests that it does not. This section We are accustomed to the segmentation of mar-
will address the logic underlying both arguments. kets when it comes to consumer items. In terms of
Many commentators claim that ethical or socially marketing strategy, different firms compete for
responsible investing provides returns at least no advantage by attempting to distinguish their prod-
worse than standard or conventional investing (e.g. ucts and services across a number of dimensions.
Cummings, 2000). After all, socially responsible These dimensions might include price, quality,
investors are clearly not interested in considering reputation, packaging, availability and, in some
unprofitable investment options or paying a signifi- cases, social responsibility. As some authors note,
cant penalty for their ethical choices, since financial ‘‘This segmentation strategy, however, is not well
return remains an important consideration. A review accepted in capital market theory. Neo-classical
of the evidence suggests that there is merit to such economics, for example, assumes that investors care
claims (see Rivoli, 2003, p. 272). In fact, it might be about only two characteristics as they make their
the case that ethical investments do financially better investment choices: an investment’s expected risk
than more conventional forms of investment. This is and expected return’’ (Hickman et al., 1999, p. 72).
an essentially ‘‘doing well by doing good’’ argument. Conventional portfolio theory recognises that an
In the United Kingdom, ethical funds over the investor’s exposure to risk can be reduced – without
period 1986–1993 outperformed (on a risk-adjusted any reduction in return – by diversification. An
basis) non-ethical funds (Mallin et al., 1995). investment portfolio that is highly diversified is only
There are a number of reasons why ethical exposed to unavoidable economy-wide or market
investments might do better than more standard or risk. Because ethical or socially responsible invest-
conventional investment. First, it is thought that ment portfolios based on negative screens exclude
higher financial returns occur because of the adop- certain investments, they are less diversified.
tion of social screening practices. Ethical firms can Therefore, it is assumed that the exposure to risk for
act as a positive ‘‘signal’’ to investors since they ethical investment is higher than for non-ethical or
communicate to the market the types of factors traditional investment (Carswell, 2002). However,
including their focus on sustainability and manage- traditional investors can still benefit from diversifi-
ment quality that socially responsible firms are ex- cation by including ethical funds as part of their
pected to embrace (Cullis et al., 1992, p. 13). portfolio strategy. Similarly, benefits accrue to ethi-
Contained within this logic is a view that ethical cal investors who include more traditional funds as
investment operates with longer time horizons than part of their portfolios (Hickman et al., 1999). As
more conventional investment. If this is correct, the noted earlier, empirical research suggests that the
outlook for ethical investing is bright as some fund latter best characterises the behaviour of ethical
managers in Australia believe that legislative and investors (Lewis and Mackenzie, 2000a; Mackenzie
customer trends such as recycling initiatives, work- and Lewis, 1999).
place smoking bans and higher taxation on gambling It might well be argued too, that ethical funds
will continue to give emphasis to the ethical attract higher transaction costs and management fees
investing ‘‘business model’’ (Drury, 2003). Empirical due to the relatively small size of the funds, and the
research supports this optimism since the longer an need to collect specialised information data con-
ethical fund has been operating, the more likely it cerning the ethical practices of firms. On this last
will outperform more recently established funds point, managers responsible for implementing social
(Cummings, 2000). screens do indeed consult a wide range of sources of
In contrast, there are numerous reasons ex- information, and do this on a regular basis (Stone,
pounded as to why ethical investment will not re- 2001). This finding is not surprising given the lack of
6 Grant Michelson et al.

standardised social data on corporate behaviour. ther the ‘‘exit’’ response helps to change firm
Consequently, it appears that ethical fund managers behaviour towards it embracing more socially
invest considerable time and effort assessing and re- responsible practices. This will depend on what
assessing a firm’s social performance. This will impact the boycott has on the firm. Firms whose
invariably add to operating costs as some contend: share prices are more sensitive to a changing investor
‘‘Small size may mean that the ratio of management base would be thought more responsive to the
fees and expenses to total income of the funds is preferences of the ethical investor (Rivoli, 2003, p.
high’’ (Tippet, 2001, p. 174). 283).
Some also believe that the recent good perfor- Premised on shareholder or investor activism, the
mance of ethical funds is merely an artefact of the ‘‘voice’’ strategy seeks to change firm behaviour and
types of companies invested in to date. Because they might include the lobbying of shareholders and the
could have more technology companies in their process of wording and re-wording motions and
portfolios (due in part to the exclusion of other resolutions (Schepers and Sethi, 2003). Investors
companies such as those operating in the resources who use this approach tend to be institutions rather
sector such as mining), their performance has re- than individuals and there is evidence that firms have
flected short-term sectoral growth in ‘‘fashionable’’ been responsive to investor voice on social issues
industries (Hoggett and Nahan, 2002). According to (Angel and Rivoli, 1997). However, this strategy has
such critics, the bursting of the information tech- certain ‘‘costs’’, particularly those associated with
nology and dot.com bubbles is likely to impact time. Much less common among the range of
negatively on the future performance of ethical ‘‘voice’’ options is the practice of investing in firms
funds. that err in order to change them (Lewis and Mac-
kenzie, 2000b).
Nonetheless, there are a number of reasons to
Does (ethical) ownership matter? question how effective these voice strategies are
likely to be. In some ways ethical investment can be
A wider question to consider is whether ethical or regarded as a special form of institutional investment,
socially responsible investing changes corporate with ethical investment funds placing pressure on
behaviour. In general terms, investment decisions firms to either avoid certain behaviours (in the case
can provide an external influence on organisations in of a negative screen) or continue certain practices (in
terms of changing firm practices (see Solomon et al., the case of a positive screen). It is therefore worth-
2002). However, more needs to be known about while considering the findings in the broader liter-
why such changes might occur. What has been ature on institutional investment and firm strategic
employed by some scholars in the field including direction and its implications for understanding
Pietra Rivoli and Alan Lewis to answer this question ethical investment. Much of the literature on ethical
is the work of Hirschman. That is, investors can investment has assumed that once ethically invested
respond to ethical lapses in terms of both ‘‘exit’’ and funds attain a certain size, they will then be able to
‘‘voice’’ strategies (Hirschman, 1970). impact firm behaviour. This point of view ignores
The sharemarket itself clearly embodies the ‘‘exit’’ two key issues. First, it ignores the possible impact of
strategy in that investor values and convictions are the operation of financial markets on the value of
converted by the market into preference for buying ethically invested funds. In a situation where there is
and selling equities. Investors can simply choose not a class of assets which is more highly valued (like
to be associated with unethical activities by with- shares in ethical firms), this is likely to create
drawing their monies from various firms. However, incentives for financial market players to get in-
practically all socially responsible funds exclude volved in arbitrage and pairs trading. Secondly, it has
gambling. Yet as some observe with a sense of irony, been widely suggested that because of the compe-
the foundations of sharemarket investment itself in- tition between institutional investors and their need
volves a strong gambling element (Cullis et al., 1992, to show returns in the short run, institutional
p. 21). Ethical funds are not immune from this investors favour near term earnings and discount
broader philosophical criticism. It is not clear whe- future earnings (Baker and Fung, 2001). While re-
Ethical Investment Processes and Outcomes 7

search indicates that this myopia is more prevalent minority shareholders in firms. While corporate
for some classes of institutions than others (Bushee, codes have increasingly attempted to give rights to
2001; Cready, 2001), we would expect ethical minority shareholders, they still tend to favour large
investment funds to have reasons to focus on long shareholders. Furthermore managers have become
term earnings. The greater the pressures for consis- increasingly sophisticated in the ways that they
tent returns, the more likely it is that institutions, manage shareholder expectations. In this regard
including those that manage ethically invested funds, Useem (1996) demonstrates the increasing impor-
may encourage corporate strategies that maximise tance of the investor relations function in firms. The
short run share price at the expense of social, envi- papers by Hummels and Timmer, and Hockerts and
ronmental and ethical goals. Thus, ethically invested Moir in this collection, suggest that these practices
funds may actually encourage the very corporate are equally important when it comes to ethical
practices, like downsizing and underinvestment in investment.
research and development, that they are seeking to The broader literature on institutional investors
prevent. The papers by Haigh and Hazelton, and and firm behaviour therefore reveals that there is not
Sparkes and Cowton provide conflicting views a simple relationship between ownership and firm
about the role that financial markets can play in behaviour. To use the language of agency theory,
encouraging corporate social responsibility. while principals, including ethical investors, may
The literature on institutional investors and firm have more power, they are still dependent on
strategy also raise further questions about the ability managers to act as their agents. The impact of ethical
of ethical investment to affect firm performance. investment on firm behaviour is thus indeterminant.
While on the face of it increased levels of institu- That is, just because a firm takes funds from an
tional investment in the United States, and else- ethical source, this does not ensure that the firm will
where, seems to be associated with a general shift in consistently adopt an ethical stance in all of its
strategic orientation of firms towards behaviours that operations. The paper by Waring and Lewer in this
maximise shortrun share price (Lazonick and collection, which focuses on the implications of
O’Sullivan, 2000), detailed studies of managerial ethical investment for the human resource function,
response indicate that managers have much more attests to the potentially radical consequences of
freedom in the face of investor pressure than might ethical investment for key aspects of firm behaviour.
otherwise be expected. Useem (1993), for example, It also suggests that there is need to move beyond
provides evidence to suggest that managers in Uni- macro level studies to a meso level of analysis which
ted States firms have adopted a number of practices focuses on factors at the level of the firm that
that blunt the impact of investor pressure. Thus, he mediate investor pressure and which may prevent
shows that managers have proved relatively suc- ethical investment from achieving its aims.
cessful at encouraging investment from different Perhaps the most important contribution of the
types of shareholders that can act as a counter to the articles in this special issue is that they start to look
interests of institutions (see Useem, 1998). While beyond the debates about the relative financial per-
Useem’s studies focus on situations in which man- formance of ethical investment and examine what
agers have sought to limit the influence of institu- many would consider to be the more important
tions that demand short term returns, it may be the question of the extent to which ethical investment
case that managers are able to balance the impact of shapes corporate behaviour. The final two papers
ethical investors by seeking corporate funding from speak directly to this issue from the point of view of
non-ethical sources as well. Useem (1993) also ar- two interest groups that have sought to use capital
gues that while institutions may have more potential markets and shareholder activism to influence firm
influence over corporate strategy and firm behav- behaviour. The paper by Guay et al. seeks to identify
iour, in most cases this power is latent and institu- ways in which non governmental organisations can
tions are unlikely to have the resources or the employ shareholder activism more effectively. The
inclination to intervene directly in the management paper by Marens offers a sobering assessment of a
of the firm. For ethical investors this situation is even decade of financial activism on the part of United
more problematic given that they tend to be States trade unions.
8 Grant Michelson et al.

There are a number of emerging developments and disclosure of information to potential and actual
aimed at enhancing the impact of ethical investment investors.
on both corporate and societal behaviour. For cor- Some commentators have posed the question
porations, some argue that the concept of Total ‘‘what is ethical about ethical investment’’? (see
Social Impact (TSI) is a credible ratings system Schwartz, 2003; Sparkes, 2001). To describe some-
which incorporates better a firm’s impact on all its thing as ‘‘ethical’’ conveys the impression that there
stakeholders and not just its shareholders (Dillenburg is an element of altruism and self-sacrifice involved.
et al., 2003). The TSI metric scheme seeks to move A firm offering an ethical fund to investors suggests
beyond exclusionary or negative screens and actually that the firm has chosen to embrace a higher level of
modify business behaviour. These authors claim that accountability and responsibility. Therefore, it is not
corporations will respond to improvements in unusual for it to be judged more stringently (Sch-
measurement techniques; in other words, there is an wartz, 2003). But it has also been argued that socially
assumption that firm behaviour is influenced by the responsible funds ‘‘show little explicit ethical
ability to measure its outcomes. The more com- awareness, as their main objective appears to be to
prehensive these measures for key stakeholder maximise investment returns within the constrained
groups (e.g. customers, employees, owners, suppli- investment universe available to them’’ (Sparkes,
ers, competitors, communities, and the environ- 2001, p. 198). It is not surprising then that more
ment), the more effective will be the field of socially attention to the issue is needed. As some have
responsible investment. This exercise in bench- concluded ‘‘Only when the ethical investment
marking and measuring ‘‘best practice’’ ethical per- movement is ethically screened can it be deemed
formance is supported in other contexts. Spiller, for ethical’’ (Schwartz, 2003, p. 212).
example, classifies a similar model of ethical business
in New Zealand including how firms rate according
to an ethical ‘‘scorecard’’ (Spiller, 2000). Conclusion

This paper has provided an overview of current


Future challenges debates about ethical investment. It has demon-
strated the complexity of many of the issues raised by
Despite the growth in ethical or socially responsible this topic including the motives of socially respon-
investment, there are certain aspects about the field sible investors, the different types of screening pro-
which still need to be addressed. For instance, be- cesses involved, the mixed evidence concerning the
cause it is still seen as loosely or ambiguously de- financial return of ethical funds, and the links be-
fined, confusion still remains about what exactly tween ethical investment and corporate behaviour.
constitutes an ethical investment (Schepers and Se- Overall, we need to see ethical investment in its
thi, 2003; Sparkes, 2001). To date, the area has been entirety and not disaggregate its central features. We
largely self-identified by promoters. Environmental would argue that for these reasons there is consid-
issues regularly feature on the social investment erable benefit in an approach which treats ethical
‘‘radar screen’’ but there may be other areas such as investment as a process and examines all the con-
the arts and cultural industries which, hitherto, have nections and disjunctures that take place within this
not been seen as ‘‘legitimate’’ areas for socially process.
responsible investment (Williams and Sharamitaro, Taken together, the papers in this collection
2002). This oversight might be due more to its (drawn from a wide variety of disciplines and na-
aesthetic, as opposed to moral (ethical) dimension tional contexts) provide new insights into the pro-
(see Irvine, 1987). Nonetheless, the broad definition cess and outcomes of ethical investment from the
of ethical investment in the literature lends itself to decision by individuals and institutions to invest
various interpretations, including the lack of con- right through to the consequences of ethical
sensus about the issues that concern investors. This investment for special interest groups. The papers
state of affairs is not aided by the lack of transparency illustrate the breadth of research taking place in
Ethical Investment Processes and Outcomes 9

connection with ethical investment and the variety Dunfee, T. W.: 2003, ‘Social Investing: Mainstream or
of perspectives that can brought to bear on the topic. Backwater?’, Journal of Business Ethics 43(3), 247–
252.
Hickman, K. A., W. R. Teets and J. J. Kohls: 1999,
Note ‘Social Investing and Modern Portfolio Theory’,
American Business Review 17(1), 72–78.
q Hirschman, A. O.: 1970, Exit, Voice, and Loyalty (Harvard
This special issue of the Journal of Business Ethics University Press, Cambridge, US).
had its origins in a one day workshop on ethical Hoggett, J. and M. Nahan: 2002, ‘Ethical Investment –
investment financially supported by the International Deconstructing the Myth’, IPA Review 54(3), 3–6.
Centre for Research on Organisational Discourse, Hollingworth, S.: 1998, ‘Green Investing: A Growing
Strategy and Change (ICRODSC), the Accounting Concern?’, Australian CPA 68(4), 28–30.
Foundation, and the School of Business at the Irvine, W. B.: 1987, ‘The Ethics of Investing’, Journal of
University of Sydney. The best workshop papers Business Ethics 6(3), 233–242.
were submitted for consideration of publication as Lazonick, W. and M. O’Sullivan: 2000, ‘Maximising
well as a general call for papers extended to scholars Shareholder Value: A New Ideology for Corporate
outside of Australia. Governance’, Economy and Society 29(1), 13–35.
Lewis, A.: 2002, Morals, Markets and Money: Ethical, Green
and Socially Responsible Finance (Financial Times-Pre-
ntice Hall, Harlow, UK).
References Lewis, A. and C. Mackenzie: 2000a, ‘Morals, Money,
Ethical Investing and Economic Psychology’, Human
Angel, J. J. and P. Rivoli: 1997, ‘Does Ethical Investing Relations 53(2), 179–191.
Impose a Cost Upon the Firm? A Theoretical Per- Lewis, A. and C. Mackenzie: 2000b, ‘Support for
spective’, Journal of Investing 6(4), 57–61. Investor Activism among U.K. Ethical Investors’,
Baker, D. and A. Fung: 2001, ‘Collateral Damage: Do Journal of Business Ethics 24(3), 215–222.
Pension Fund Investments Hurt Workers?’ in A. Fung, Mackenzie, C. and A. Lewis: 1999, ‘Morals and Markets:
T. Hebb, and J. Rogers, (eds.), Working Capital: The The Case of Ethical Investing’, Business Ethics Quarterly
Power of Labor’s Pensions (Cornell University Press, 9(3), 439–452.
Ithaca). Mallin, C. A., B. Saadouni and R. Briston: 1995, ‘The
Bushee, B.: 2001, ‘Do Institutional Investors Prefer Near- Financial Performance of Ethical Investment Funds’,
Term Earnings over Long Run Value?’, Contemporary Journal of Business Finance and Accounting 22(4), 483–
Accounting Research 18(2), 207–242. 496.
Carswell, A.: 2002, ‘Crisis of Conscience’, Australian Murray, L.: 2003, ‘Making Money with God on your
CPA 72(3), 26–27. Side’, Australian Financial Review 6, October.
Cready, W.: 2001, ‘The Separation Theorem, Investor Rivoli, P.: 2003, ‘Making a Difference or Making a
‘Mypoia’, and Market Prices: A Discussion of ‘‘Do Statement? Finance Research and Socially Responsible
Institutional Investors Prefer Near-Term Earnings over Investment’, Business Ethics Quarterly 13(3), 271–
Long-Run Value?’’’, Contemporary Accounting Research 287.
18(2), 247–256. Schepers, D. H. and S. P. Sethi: 2003, ‘Do Socially
Cullis, J. G., A. Lewis and A. Winnett: 1992, ‘Paying to Responsible Funds Actually Deliver what they
be Good? U.K. Ethical Investments’, Kyklos 45(1), 3– Promise? Bridging the Gap Between the Promise and
23. Performance of Socially Responsible Funds’, Business
Cummings, L. A.: 2000, ‘The Financial Performance of and Society Review 108(1), 11–32.
Ethical Investment Trusts: An Australian Perspective’, Schlegelmilch, B.: 1997, ‘The Relative Importance of
Journal of Business Ethics 25(1), 79–92. Ethical and Environmental Screening: Implications for
Dillenburg, S., T. Greene and H. Erekson: 2003, the Marketing of Ethical Investment Funds’, Interna-
‘Approaching Socially Responsible Investment with a tional Journal of Bank Marketing 15(2), 48–53.
Comprehensive Ratings Scheme: Total Social Impact’, Schueth, S.: 2003, ‘Socially Responsible Investing in the
Journal of Business Ethics 43(3), 167–177. United States’, Journal of Business Ethics 43(3), 189–194.
Drury, B.: 2003, ‘Green with Envy’, Sydney Morning Schwartz, M. S.: 2003, ‘The ‘‘Ethics’’ of Ethical Invest-
Herald, 3 December. ing’, Journal of Business Ethics 43(3), 195–213.
10 Grant Michelson et al.

Social Investment Forum: 2001, Report on Socially Useem, M.: 1996, Investor Capitalism: How Money Man-
Responsible Investing Trends in the United States (available agers are Changing the Face of Corporate America (Basic
at: www.socialinvest.org). Books, New York).
Solomon, J., A. Solomon and S. Norton: 2002, ‘Socially Useem, M.: 1998, ‘Corporate Leadership in a Globalizing
Responsible Investment in the UK: Drivers and Cur- Equity Market’, Academy of Management Executive
rent Issues’, Journal of General Management 27(3), 1–13. 12(4), 43–59.
Sparkes, R.: 2001, ‘Ethical Investment: Whose Ethics, Webley, P., A. Lewis and C. Mackenzie: 2001, ‘Com-
Which Investment?’, Business Ethics: A European Re- mitment Among Ethical Investors: An Experimental
view 10(3), 194–205. Approach’, Journal of Economic Psychology 22(1), 27–
Spiller, R.: 2000, ‘Ethical Business and Investment: A 42.
Model for Business and Society’, Journal of Business Williams, C. and L. Sharamitaro: 2002, ‘Building a Model
Ethics 27(1/2), 149–160. for Culturally Responsible Investment’, Journal of Arts
Stone, B. A.: 2001, ‘Corporate Social Responsibility and Management, Law and Society 32(2), 144–
Institutional Investment’, Business and Society 40(1), 158.
112–117. Williams, S.: 1999, ‘U.K. Ethical Investment: A Coming
Taylor, R.: 2001, ‘Putting Ethics into Investment’, of Age’, Journal of Investing 8(2), 58–75.
Business Ethics: A European Review 10(1), 53–60. Yach, D., S. Brinchmann and S. Bellet: 2001, ‘Healthy
Tippet, J.: 2001, ‘Performance of Australia’s Ethical Investments and Investing in Health’, Journal of Business
Funds’, Australian Economic Review 34(2), 170–178. Ethics 33(3), 191–198.
Tippet, J. and P. Leung: 2001, ‘Defining Ethical Invest-
ment and its Demography in Australia’, Australian
Accounting Review 11(3), 44–55. Work and Organisational Studies,
Total Environment Centre (TEC): 2003, Ethical? Invest- School of Business,
ment: A Review of the Socially Responsible Investment Faculty of Economics and Business,
Industry in Australia (TEC, Sydney). University of Sydney,
Useem, M.: 1993, Executive Defense: Shareholder Power and Sydney, NSW 2006,
Corporate Reorganization (Harvard University Press, Australia
Cambridge, MA). E-mail: g.michelson@econ.usyd.edu.au

You might also like