Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 5

r · ¥UL ~,

DIALOGUE October, 2009

The Problem of Deduction: Hume's Problem Expanded


Samuel R. Burns
University of Michigan, Ann Arbor
ABSTRACT: In his Treatise of Human Nature, David Hume argues strongly against
our intuitions about induction. In his view, the justification of induction relies upon the
principle of the uniformity of nature, a principle that we can only justify by an appeal to
induction. Thus, a non-circular justification of induction is impossible. This argument
has troubled philosophers ever since, especially philosophers interested in the philosophy
of science. One prominent solution to this problem comes from Karl Popper, who posited
a deductivist solution to the problem. In this paper, I will briefly summarize Hume's
argument as well as Popper's response to it. I will then argue that Popper's account twice
fails to solve the problem of induction: first, as A. J. Ayer pointed out, his account
appears to contain a built-in inductive assumption, and second, by shifting his discussion
from induction to deduction, Popper begs Hume's question, merely shifting from a prob-
lem of induction to a problem of deduction.

Hume's Problem idea that C-events cause E-events. We


then feel justified in making the universal
Although David Hume is credited with claim that all C-events cause E-events.'
the first influential statement of the prob- Thus, any time in the future that we
lem of induction, the word "induction" observe a C-event, we expect an E-event
never actually appears in his work. Rather, to follow.
his statement of the problem occurs within Yet we can never produce a sound
the context of his discussion of causation deductive argument for why we are justi-
(Treatise, 1.3.6; references are to book, fied in this claim. The nearest argument
part, section, and paragraph). Hume we can produce is as follows:
argues that we cannot arrive at an under- P,: In the past, we have observed C-
I
standing of the connection between cause events constantly conjoined with E-
1'1 and effect by any amount of a priori events.
scrutiny of the independent objects. For p,: In the future, nature will be uni-
example, a person who has never fomily like the past.
observed objects striking each other C: Thus, in the future, C-events will be
would have no way of predicting that a constantly conjoined with E-events.
billiard ball, when it strikes another, This argument is deductively valid.
would communicate its motion to the sec- The second premise, however (known as
ond ball. Even the most rational person the principle of the uniformity of nature),
could imagine, prior to experience, all is immediately suspect. How are we ever
sorts of possibilities: the billiard balls to demonstrate deductively that it is true?
might disappear, or they might burst into Hume argues that we can conceive of
flames, or they might simply stop moving. nature radically changing in the future so
No matter how long this experience- that everything that we have ever
deprived person examines each individual observed no longer holds (Treatise,
ball , this person could never deduce that 1.3.6.5). Billiard balls no longer commu-
the first ball will communicate its motion nicate motion but rather disappear or burst
to the second ball.' Thus, Hume claims, into flames when they collide. Objects no
we only arrive at our idea of cause and longer fall to the ground when they are
effect after experience. That is, we dropped but rather float horizontally to the
observe that an event type C is constantly ground. And so on until everything in the
conjoined with an event type E, and this universe completely fails to resemble the
constant conjunction suggests to us the past. Of course, this is not something we

26
!I'I
DIALOGUE October, 2009 .,
expect to happen; yet the mere fact that included Marxist history and Freudian I
we can see no contradiction in this imagi- psychoanalysis.'
nation shows that it cannot be deductively Popper's contemporaries, the logical II
ruled out. positivists, largely believed that verifiabil-
How then can we justify the principle ity was the mark of true science. That is, a

of the uniformity of nature? Perhaps we theory is scientific just in case it can be
will try a similar argument to that which verified by empirical evidence (Ayer
justified our expectation that C-events will "Demonstration," 337; Vickers, §3.1).
be conjoined with E-events: Popper noted that this demarcation is
P,: In the past, we have observed that faulty since most pseudo-sciences are
nature is uniform from past to future. clearly verifiable. Adherents of Marxism,
C: Therefore, in the future, nature will for example, find confirmations of their
be uniformly like the past. theory every time they "open a newspa-
This argument clearly doesn't work, per." Evidence of "class bias" is seen even
since we can conceive of nature radically in what the paper chooses to present.
changing. Thus, for this argument to work, What they cannot find, however, is a clear
we need to add one additional premise: falsifier of their theory (Popper
P,: In the future, nature will be uni- "Philosophy," 157-58). Thus, Popper
formly like the past. claims, the true demarcation between sci-
But this is exactly what we were trying ence and pseudo-science is falsifiability .
to prove. This circularity is the fundamen- A scientific theory is simply one that
tal problem of induction. "makes assertions that may clash with
observations" (Popper Conjectures, 256).
Popper's Deductivism But how does this conclusion bear upon
the problem of induction? Popper claims
Any philosopher working with the phi- that by construing science as an attempt to
losophy of science must at least attempt to falsify a hypothesis rather than an attempt
face this problem of induction, for on first to verify it, we shift our focus from the
blush, it seems that scientific enquiry is generation of the hypothesis to the process
merely a specialized form of inductive of testing. The method by which we come
reasoning. In the common conception of by our hypotheses is unimportant. We can
science, scientists observe the physical derive useful hypotheses from observation,
world, notice regularities, and derive sci- from religion, from myths and folklore;
entific laws from these regularities. This what is important is that from these
derivation is quite clearly an inductive hypotheses we draw "conclusions [ . .. J by
process. Thus, if the inductive method is means of logical deduction" (Popper
not justifiable, then scientific laws can Logic, 32). That is, we make a deductive
hardly be so. prediction (P) from our hypothesis (If) and
Of course, the simplest counterargu- look for empirical evidence that falsifies
ment to this analysis is to merely claim the prediction. If we succeed, we have fal-
that this conception of science is flawed . sified our hypothesis. If we do not, then
This is exactly the position taken by the our hypothesis "has, for the time being,
20'h -century philosopher of science Karl passed its test" (Ibid., 33). Logically, this
Popper. process of falsification takes the form of a
Like Hume, Popper does not originally simple modus tollens:
intend that his project deal with induction. H- P

~H
Rather, Popper is primarily interested in
the problem of demarcation: how "to dis-
tinguish between science and pseudo-sci-
IThis is, of course, a valid deductive
ence" ("Philosophy," 155). For Popper, argument, which contains no induction.
the true sciences included such fields as Thus, Popper claims that those who think
Einstein's physics while pseudo-science that scientific enquiry is inductive are
I
I
27
I

rt .5 • .• .. ! " •. . ...1 ,' _ .


1
. -:-, - - ,, ; . . ..

f
'

!
DIALOGUE October, 2009

merely mistaken. Indeed, all of what is be continue to be false in the future, which
commonly understood to be inductive rea- is an inductive assumption.
soning actually follows a deductive pat- Thus, Ayer concludes that the search
tern: "Induction, i.e. inference based on for a validating justification of induction
many observations, is a myth. It is neither will ultimately fail; yet he claims that this
a psychological fact, nor a fact of ordinary is hardly ground for rejecting induction as
life, nor one of scientific procedure" irrational. Induction cannot be validated
(Popper "Philosophy," 181). by any higher standard, he claims,
because induction is the standard of ratio-
Discussion nality. As he says, induction must "act as
judge in its own cause" (Ibid., 81).'
As with any prominent philosophy, The Problem of Deduction: My sec-
Popper' s account has attracted a good deal ond criticism of Popper' s account takes a
of discussion. Before getting into this dis- somewhat different approach. Let us
cussion, however, let us take a brief begin by noticing exactly what Popper's
detour into Feigl's distinction between the account is attempting to do. By shifting
two kinds of justification. focus from the process of hypothesis gen-
Validation and Vindication: Herbert eration to the process of testing, which is
, Feigl draws a distinction between two construed as a deductive process, Popper
I kinds of justification: validation and vin- has shifted our focus from induction to
1
dication. Validation is the justification of deduction. Yet Hume's problem with
a "knowledge-claim," whereas vindication induction is that it appears impossible to
is the justification of an action (Feigl, produce a non-circular validating Justifi-
674). On Feig\'s account, the principles of cation for it. It seems that the same exact
deduction and induction provide the vali- problem exists for deduction .
dation of a claim while a combination of Indeed, it is difficult even to under-
our desired end and our empirical evi- stand how a validation of deduction would
dence provides the vindication of an be set up. Clearly, if we are to produce a
action. Thus, a claim is validated if it fol- non-circular validating justification of any
lows deductive and inductive rules, claim, we cannot use that claim to set up
,,;.I: whereas an action is vindicated if it is our validation. Yet deductive logic is the
likely to succeed in reaching our desired system by which we set up all of our argu-
end. Hume's problem of induction, then, ments. If we cannot use deductive logic to
is that it is impossible to give a non-circu- prove deduction , we cannot even begin to
lar validating justification of induction. set up an argument.
Ayer's criticism: A. 1. Ayer argues Despite this difficulty, deduction pos-
against Popper's deductivist account, sesses a valuable characteristic that is
claiming that it contains a built-in induc- missing from induction: truth preserva-
tive assumption. Ayer points out that the tion. What this means is that for any set of
very idea of falsifiability presupposes the propositions with binary truth-values,
uniformity of nature, as there "would be valid deductive arguments will take true
no contradiction in holding that a hypoth- premises to true conclusions. Binary truth-
esis which had been falsified was the values are simply a valuation over the set
more likely to hold good in future cases" {T,F}, where T and F are exhaustive and
(Problem, 59). It is conceivable that falsi- mutually exclusive (Cohen, 155).5 Godel's
fication could be like an "infantile disease, proof of his Completeness Theorem
which even healthiest hypotheses could be proves truth preservation for propositional
depended on to catch" (Ibid.) Thus, it and predicate logic:
seems clear that there is no deductive jus- Note, however, that this is not a valida-
j
tification for discarding a falsified hypoth- tion of deductive logic but merely a vindi-
esis. Discarding a falsified hypothesis cation. That is, if our end is to reach true
~:;.
only makes sense if we assume that it will conclusions from true premises, then

28
DIALOGUE October, 2009

deduction appears to be a good method to identifying induction as one of the basic


use. But since Popper is interested in vali- standards of validation. then any project
dation, not vindication, it seems that the that tries to validate induction will fail. If
truth-preserving characteristic of deduc- by justification we mean validating justi- .i1
tion does not help him much. If a mere fication, Hume ' s problem of induction is J:
vindication of deduction would suffice for insoluble. But then so is the problem of
Popper, then why not simply attempt to deduction. Our highest standards of vali-
vindicate induction in the first place?' dation cannot in themselves be validated
Why spend so much time identifying without circularity. As Ayer points out, r
I
induction with deduction if the problem this is a victory for the skeptic. However. l''.
remains at the end? Even if Popper could it is not, as he claims it is, an entirely
succeed in identifying induction as a spe- "bloodless victory" (Problem, 81). For if
cial form of modus tollens (and Ayer's our best systems of logic cannot be vali-
criticism quite clearly shows that he fails dated, then even our most solid beliefs,
in this), Popper' s problem would now be most carefully reasoned arguments, and
to validate modus tollens. best-laid proofs could be entirely wrong.
i\
We still may have enough vindicating jus-
'!',
Conclusion tification to trust them in everyday life,
but we can never reach certainty. This,
This discussion has shown that then, is the victory of the skeptic: they
Popper's deductivist account of induction show us that to be a philosopher is to be
fails . That is not surprising since Popper's aware of the limitations of our reason. In
project was to find a validating justifica- short, the skeptic reminds us that an hon-
tion of induction. If Feigl is correct in est philosopher is a humble philosopher.
Ii

Notes
II,

'The example of the billiard ball is found in Hume, Enquiry, §7 .2.


' In this case, we are only concerned with cases where every instance of a C-event is followed
by an E-event and every instance of an E-event is preceded by a C-event. It is quite clear that this
is not enough for a complete account of causation since we seem quite comfortable claiming that
an event type D causes events of type F only sometimes and also that more than one type of cause
could cause some events. For our purposes, however. this more restricted version of the constant
conjunction account is all that we need.
-'This, of course. raises another problem. Marxist history and Freudian psychoanalysis were
widely accepted as science by his contemporaries, yet Popper felt that they did not deserve the
name. This became his project of demarcation. Yet if Popper already feels that these fields are not
1
science, it is unclear what his demarcation is supposed to do; his mark is already drawn. ,t
' Note that Ayer does not explicitly make use of the distinction between validation and vindica-
tion; nor does he attempt to provide a vindication of induction.
' Whether this accurately describes the behavior of truth and falsehood in the actual world is
uncertain and is, in my opinion, highly unlikely.
"The proof of this theorem is quite complicated and is not necessary for our purposes here. A 'I
brief account of the proof is contained in Cohen, 167-70,89-97.
'This project of inductive vindication is exactly what Reichenbach undertakes. i
I
Work Cited II

Ayer, A. J. "Demonstration of the Impossibility of Metaphysics," Mind 431171 (1934), 333-45.


- - -. The Problem of Knowledge. New York: Penguin, 1956.
Cohen. Daniel E. Computabilty alld Logic. In Mathematics and Irs Applications, edited by G. M.
Bell Chichester: Ellis Horwood. 1987.

29

i
i
f I
DIALOGUE October, 2009
I Herbert Feigl , "Validation and Vindication: An Analysis of the Nature and Limits of Ethical
Arguments." In Readings in Ethical Theory, edited by Wilfrid Sellars and John Hospers. New
York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1952.667-80.
Hume, David. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. 2nd edition. Indianapolis: Hackett
Publishing, 1993.
- - -. A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.
Popper, Karl R. Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. 3rd edition.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul , 1969.
- --. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Translated by Julius Freed and Lan Freed. New York:
Basic Books, 1959.
- - -. "Philosophy of Science: A Personal Report." In British Philosophy in the Mid-Century ,
1st edition, edited by Cecil Alec Mace. New York: Macmillan , 1957. 151-91.
Reichenbach, Hans. The Theory of Probahlity: An Inquiry into the Logical and Mathematical
Foundations of the Calculus of Probability, 2nd edition. Translated by Ernest H. Hutton and
Maria Reichenbach. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1949.
Vickers, John. "The Problem of Induction." In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring
2009 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2009. §3.1.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/induction-probleml#VerCon>

i'
,.
t

Ji

30

You might also like