Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 4

Journal for the History of

Analytical Philosophy
David G. Stern, Brian Rogers, and Gabriel Citron,
Volume 8, Number 3 eds. Wittgenstein: Lectures, Cambridge 1930–1933:
From the Notes of G. E. Moore. Cambridge:
Editor in Chief Cambridge University Press, 2016. lxxiv + 420
Marcus Rossberg, University of Connecticut pages. $122 Hardcover. ISBN 978-1-10-8730198.
Editorial Board Reviewed by Mauro Luiz Engelmann
Annalisa Coliva, UC Irvine
Henry Jackman, York University
Frederique Janssen-Lauret, University of Manchester
Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts
Consuelo Preti, The College of New Jersey
Anthony Skelton, Western University
Mark Textor, King’s College London
Audrey Yap, University of Victoria
Richard Zach, University of Calgary

Editor for Special Issues


Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University

Review Editors
Sean Morris, Metropolitan State University of Denver
Sanford Shieh, Wesleyan University

Design and Layout


Daniel Harris, Hunter College
Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts

ISSN: 2159-0303

jhaponline.org
© 2020 Mauro Luiz Engelmann
Review: Wittgenstein: Lectures, Cambridge (for instance, Ernst Haeckel). Some biographies could have been
1930–1933: From the Notes of G. E. Moore, richer in details, especially of those figures who played a rel-
evant role in Wittgenstein’s cultural environment (for instance,
edited by David G. Stern, Brian Rogers, and Gottfried Keller and Heinrich Hertz), but the very concern over
Gabriel Citron presenting them in order to help the readers already shows the
seriousness of the edition. The appendix also contains a short
Mauro Luiz Engelmann paper by Moore on Wittgenstein’s so-called “rules of grammar”,
written for a discussion in a class taught by Wittgenstein in
February 1932, and some notes taken by John King recording
Wittgenstein’s reply to Moore. In his paper Moore criticized
This book is the result of serious and meticulous editorial work, Wittgenstein’s understanding of his peculiar notion of “rule of
and it makes available a new source of material for Wittgenstein- grammar” and the way Wittgenstein seemed to explain “ne-
studies and the history of analytical philosophy. With the atten- cessity” grounded in that notion in 1931 and 1932. Arguably,
tion to details and background information, the book introduces Moore’s critique played an important role in Wittgenstein’s sub-
a new generation of edited lectures, far superior to the ones sequent understanding of the notion. An interesting fact about
published in the past. The quality of the work reminds one of the book, explained in the introduction, is that Moore’s origi-
the edition of Wittgenstein’s diaries in James Klagge and Alfred nal notes are accessible at wittgensteinsource.org. If in doubt,
Nordmann, eds., Ludwig Wittgenstein: Public and Private Occasions the reader can check online the facsimile of the published notes,
(Rowman & Littlefeld, 2003) and of letters in Brian McGuinness, Moore’s summary notes, and the original essay on “grammar”.
ed., Wittgenstein in Cambridge: Letters and Documents 1911–1951 The reader might also find interesting Stern’s discussion of edit-
(Wiley–Blackwell, 2012). ing policies in “Reflections on Editing Moore’s Notes in Wittgen-
The editorial introduction to the book provides readers not stein: Lectures, Cambridge 1930–33” (Belgrade Philosophical Annual
familiar with the material with a clear overview. The editors ex- 30, 2017).
plain in detail the nature of Moore’s complete notes, available for The complete notes of G. E. Moore now available are partic-
the first time, their relevance, how they connect with Wittgen- ularly significant because they document part of the transition
stein’s development, and their sui generis position in relation to of Wittgenstein’s middle period, which one could call his “early
other notes of Wittgenstein’s lectures taken by some of his stu- middle period” (1929–33). Lectures from 1930 show Wittgen-
dents. The introduction also presents a comparison between the stein struggling with ideas from the Tractatus and views con-
complete notes published in the volume and the notes that Moore cerning phenomenology that he adopted after his return to phi-
had already published himself in Mind (1954–55) and in his Philo- losophy in 1929. Lectures from 1931 onwards show how he was
sophical Papers (1959) as “Wittgenstein’s Lectures in 1930–33” (the beginning to articulate the ideas of a synoptic view or repre-
lectures also appear in Philosophical Occasions 1912–1951). The sentation of “grammar” and a new method. Quite interesting,
book gives all necessary background of citations and mentioned among other things, is the centrality of the notion of “gram-
names in the lectures in informative footnotes, which are con- mar” at the time and how such a notion is meant to account
nected with an index and some biographies of historic figures for different necessary sentences, which is precisely the topic

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 3 [19]


that raises Moore’s suspicions in his paper from 1932. Thus, the for us to understand both philosophies in their context and the
appendix “Moore’s short paper on Wittgenstein on Grammar” transition from the one to the other as well.
(367–78) already mentioned is very welcome. Here, however, Concerning Philosophical Remarks, there is something possibly
one must be very careful. One cannot forget that remarks from misleading in the editorial introduction that I need to address.
the early middle period are part of a specific context, and that if The editors claim that Philosophical Remarks was used as a fel-
similar remarks appear later in Wittgenstein’s works their sense lowship dissertation in December 1930 (xxxiv). The fact is that
may change significantly. Although Wittgenstein scholars know almost all the remarks contained in it were written before the
about the importance of the notion of “context”, sometimes they middle of March 1930, but certainly none after 24 April 1930,
are prone to forget about it when dealing with Wittgenstein’s and in April or May Wittgenstein indeed handed in a typescript
own remarks appearing in different places. Notes from 1932 to Russell in order to renew a fellowship. There are letters from
and 1933 also show Wittgenstein re-evaluating the Tractatus and Russell, Moore, and Wittgenstein that attest that. However, no
presenting some its ideas in a new context. These discussions letters, remarks in manuscripts or records of any kind that show
could shed some light on interpretational disputes regarding the the existence of the “December dissertation” or that Wittgenstein
book, if properly understood. needed it for his December fellowship have been presented at this
However, more important than the discussion of aspects of the point. In fact, if he needed such a dissertation in December, and
Tractatus and some topics connected with the Philosophical Investi- records were found for that effect, it would still be surprising if
gations is that the lectures are very helpful for the understanding the hypothetical dissertation turned out to be Philosophical Re-
of two works or unfinished-works of Wittgenstein’s from the marks, since none of the remarks that Wittgenstein wrote from
early middle period itself: the Philosophical Remarks (1930) and the end of April until December 1930 appear there. So, given
the Big Typescript (1932–33). Central ideas in the context of Philo- that “Wittgenstein’s thought was changing rapidly during the
sophical Remarks such as experiential propositions understood as first half of the 1930s” (xliii), as the editors point out, it would
hypotheses, physical objects as part of language, intention, the be strange for him to leave out of the “December dissertation”
critique of Russell’s epistemology in the 1920s, are all discussed remarks written during that period.
in an illuminating way in the Lent and May terms of 1930. Also There are other reasons that make this book important. The
introduced and discussed is Wittgenstein’s philosophy in the very extensive notes were taken by Moore, who was not only
Big Typescript, where the centrality of the notion of “grammar” a great philosopher, but someone who had discussions with
is expressed by means of a calculus conception of language that Wittgenstein for many years. Besides, the book contains a sig-
limits the application of Wittgenstein’s new method of doing phi- nificant amount of new material from lectures in 1932–33, which
losophy, namely, the method whose goal is finding misleading was not included in Moore’s published notes. However, it is not
analogies and misleading trains of thought that generate philo- just a question of quantity. The complete notes are far richer
sophical problems. The application of the method and many than the notes Moore published. They preserve exactly the se-
aspects of the calculus conception of language appear in lectures quence of lectures and introduce new topics. Besides discussions
from 1931–33. Thus, if one calls Philosophical Remarks Wittgen- on philosophy of logic and mathematics, particularly interest-
stein’s “first philosophy” and the Big Typescript his “second phi- ing are discussions about Freud and Frazer, and some about
losophy” after his return, Moore’s notes are an important tool Darwin. Alice Ambrose’s Wittgenstein Lectures: Cambridge, 1932–

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 3 [20]


1935 contains some of the remarks, but with less details and in fourth meeting in February 1930, when Wittgenstein held a lec-
a rather unclear context. Moore’s notes are far more detailed. ture and discussion combined according to Lee. However, they
The discussions about Frazer during the May Term of 1933 are could have informed the reader about what was discussed on
singularly relevant, for they give us a link between the first set that occasion as well, namely, Ogden and Richards The Meaning
of remarks on Frazer from 1931 and the second set from 1936 of Meaning and, more importantly, Russell’s The Analysis of Mind.
(see “Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough” in James Klagge and This topic is important for many reasons, but the first that comes
Alfred Nordmann, eds., Philosophical Occasions: 1912–1951, 115– to mind is that it also appears as a relevant topic in Philosophical
55). Something similar must be said about discussions on reli- Remarks.
gion, ethics and aesthetics, which are far thinner in Ambrose’s Moore’s own “Wittgenstein’s Lectures in 1930–33” still re-
published notes. Those lectures are a link between the “Lecture mains relevant as well, for there one finds him struggling with
on Ethics” and the Lectures & Conversations on Aesthetics, Psy- Wittgenstein’s views and giving important inputs about some
chology, and Religious Belief from 1938 and later, edited by Cyril problems and tensions in Wittgenstein’s “grammar”. In fact,
Barrett, and the recently published (2017) Wittgenstein’s Whewell’s what one should keep in mind is that in order to appreciate
Court Lectures: Cambridge 1938–41, edited by Volker Munz and Wittgenstein’s philosophies from the early middle period, one
Bernhard Ritter. (The latter book is also part of a new gener- must consider all the material available as a whole: the previ-
ation of edited lectures.) What seems to unify all those topics ous published lectures by Lee and Ambrose, Moore’s complete
is the idea that “philosophic-scientific explanations” concerning notes, Moore’s published notes and, of course, Wittgenstein’s
religion, aesthetics, and ethics are quite limited, and that a new own manuscripts.
kind of investigation (“descriptive aesthetics”, etc.) is preferable. Independently of particular points discussed in this review,
A background unification for all those discussions, I think, is the fact is that the edition of Moore’s complete notes introduces
Wittgenstein’s dissatisfaction with modernity (see, for instance, a new, higher standard for the publication of Wittgenstein’s lec-
the “Foreword” to Philosophical Remarks). One can see that in tures. (A second edition of Lee’s and Ambrose’s notes mirrored
those lectures he is trying to unify his personal views and his in its editorial work would be very welcome.) I must recommend
“grammatical philosophy” at the time. it to anyone interested in Wittgenstein’s work and philosophical
However, one should not think that the publication of the development, but also to those interested in the history of an-
complete version of Moore’s notes makes the notes published alytical philosophy in general. The fact that Moore attended
by Desmond Lee and Alice Ambrose dispensable. They are still Wittgenstein’s lectures, took detailed notes, and challenged him
very useful for several reasons: it may be important to contrast in some ways is certainly a first rate event.
notes, some points may have escaped Moore, and the fact that
Moore was not present in all lectures and discussion sessions.
(Desmond Lee’s Wittgenstein’s Lectures Cambridge, 1930–1932, 5–6
Mauro Luiz Engelmann
and 9–10, are good examples.) In fact, the comparison with the Univesidade Federal de Minas Gerais – CNPq
notes edited by Desmond Lee points to relevant information mauroengelmann@gmail.com
missing from the new Moore notes. The editors duly inform
the reader that Moore was absent or did not take notes on the

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 3 [21]

You might also like