Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 11

Auguste Comte and Modern Epistemology

Author(s): Johan Heilbron


Source: Sociological Theory, Vol. 8, No. 2 (Autumn, 1990), pp. 153-162
Published by: American Sociological Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/202202 .
Accessed: 14/11/2013 03:55

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Sociological Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Sociological Theory.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 148.61.13.133 on Thu, 14 Nov 2013 03:55:09 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
AUGUSTE COMTE AND MODERN EPISTEMOLOGY
JOHAN HEILBRON
Swedish Collegium for Advanced Study, Uppsala

Au lieu de chercher aveuglement une sterile unite scientifique, aussi oppressive que
chimerique, dans la vicieuse reduction de tous les phenomenes a un seul ordre de lois,
I'esprit humain regardera finalement les diverses classes d'evenements comme ayant
leurs lois speciales.
Auguste Comte

Among the masters of sociological thought sociologists Comte is a textbook personal-


Auguste Comte probably has the worst ity, vaguely familiar but strange and some-
reputation. "Positivism" is commonly con- what embarrassing. Sociologists, who
sidered a form of narrow-mindedness, and usually are not sure of their scientific status,
the term is used most often in a polemical do not like to be bothered with a man who
sense. If someone says, "He is a positivist" founded the religion of humanity.
or "It is a bit positivistic," there is some- Most references to Comte in academic
thing wrong, although it is not precisely discourse reproduce the established cliches.
clear what it is. During the famous Positi- When Comte is discussed in a more elab-
vismusstreit, one of the great dispute rituals orate way, apart from rather vague associa-
of German sociology, Adorno and his op- tions, there are two types of interpretation.
ponent Hans Albert each criticized the First, there are the interpretations based on
other for being a "positivist." One of the his political, social, or religious signifi-
few things they agreed on was that "posi- cance. In these cases Comte is read against
tivism" was to be rejected. That is quite the background of the ideological crisis of
typical of the status of positivism and of postrevolutionary France; his work is dis-
Auguste Comte, who is considered to be its cussed in relation to the Saint-Simonians,
founder. the rise of conservatism, or the attempts to
In philosophy Comte's attempt to de- find a worldly substitute for Catholicism.
throne metaphysics never received much The best-documented study on Comte,
sympathy, and academic philosophers Henri Gouhier's La jeunesse d'Auguste
never have really forgiven him for it. To Comte et la formation du positivisme
many of them Comte was persona non (1933-41), was inspired by such an
grata. Although his work is seldom read, it interpretation.
is widely associated with unsophisticated The second type of interpretation stresses
thinking: with empiricism, with a blind imi- a different aspect. Here Comte is seen pri-
tation of the natural sciences, and with the marily as a theorist. His earlier works are
unreflective use of quantitative methods. central; his later activities appear only in
The fact that none of these associations has sarcastic subordinate clauses. In such cases
anything to do with Comte's actual writ- Comte's originality is located in his "posi-
ings has not made any difference for his tivism" and his "sociology." Positivism is
reputation. seen as the center of his theory of knowl-
In sociology Comte does not have a edge; his sociology is regarded as an elabo-
much better name. He is a figure of some ration or application of that theory. This is
historical importance, but references to his the standard way in which Comte is pre-
work have long since disappeared from sented in academic textbooks. It is also
the debates. His writings did not become the most obvious way. Comte introduced
the object of ongoing commentary and both terms-positivism and sociology-
interpretation. They have often been edited and nothing seems more plausible than to
by followers outside academia, and there summarize his contribution according to
is no Comte scholarship comparable to that these terms.
which exists for Montesquieu and Tocque- Both interpretations, I think, are mis-
ville or for Weber and Durkheim. To most taken. The first is inaccurate because it has

This content downloaded from 148.61.13.133 on Thu, 14 Nov 2013 03:55:09 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
154 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
nothing to say about Comte's extended positivism in this sense was nothing new. In
writings about the sciences. If Comte's 1835, when he gave a lecture to the Acad-
project from the beginning was primarily emy of Sciences, he started his speech by
political or quasi-religious, it remains a saying that scientific statements need
mystery why he went to the trouble of writ- "positive verification." That was an "in-
ing numerous books and articles on recent dispensable condition" for validity and
developments in the sciences. That effort was "universally accepted" (Comte 1970a
represented an intellectual endeavor and [1835], p. 585). He expressed the same atti-
should be interpreted as such. The second tude in the Cours de philosophie positive.
interpretation does this, but this inter- Where he states that it is "useless" to insist
pretation is misleading because one can on the "principle" that distinguishes meta-
show that neither Comte's positivism nor physical from scientific knowledge. Every-
his sociology was particularly original. One one who had some knowledge of the
may add that historically they have not advanced sciences was "familiar" with this
been very significant either. That statement principle (Comte 1975 [1830], p. 26). Comte
requires some explanation. made no claim that he contributed much to
the idea of positive sciences. In his later
writings the term "positivism" assumed a
POSITIVISM AND SOCIOLOGY much broader meaning. "Positive" then
also mean "useful," "precise," and "cer-
Positivism commonly has two different tain" (Comte 1983 [1844], pp. 64-65). Such
meanings. First, it refers to a form of imita- an extension was part of positivism as a
tion of the natural sciences in the domain of world view or an ideology. That idea prob-
the human sciences. If one follows this ably was original, but I will not discuss
description, Hobbes is probably the first Comte's later work here.
positivist. Condorcet, Cabanis, and per- As to Comte's "sociology," one might
haps the early Saint-Simon were positivists, make the same comments as about his
but Comte explicitly rejected such imita- positivism. Comte invented the word, but
tions and was certainly not a positivist in the ideas to which it referred were not par-
this sense of the word. ticularly new. The law of the three stages,
Positivism also can refer more broadly to for example, which Comte regarded as the
antimetaphysical conceptions of knowl- core of his whole sociology, can be found in
edge. Here the idea is that there can be no Turgot's work. The human mind, accord-
knowledge of "first causes" or "final ing to Turgot, developed in three stages.
causes," that there is no positive knowledge At first, when people had no idea of true
of the "essence" of things, and that all such causes, they imagined that "invisible
questions must be banned from science. beings," gods, were responsible for every-
Comte is a positivist in this sense. The ques- thing that was not done by humans. Then
tion, however, is whether he contributed philosophers started to criticize these con-
much to the formulation of this concep- ceptions, but because they also lacked suffi-
tion. He invented a word for it, but it is cient knowledge of the true connections,
doubtful whether he did much more. Posi- they proposed explanations in terms of
tivism in this sense emerged parallel to "abstract entities." Scientific explanations
classical physics. Newton wished to refrain emerged only much later with the help of
from what he called "hypothetical" ques- mathematics (Turgot 1750). Comte might
tions, i.e. questions about first or final have known this text; he certainly knew
causes. That attitude became conventional Condorcet's biography of Turgot and the
in the French Academy of Sciences during Esquisse d'un tableau historique des
the eighteenth century (Hahn 1971, p. 34), progres de l'esprit humain (1794), which
and by 1800 the explicit rejection of meta- was an elaboration of Turgot's scheme.
physics was commonly accepted in French Nor can other aspects of Comte's sociology
scientific circles (Dhombres and Dhombres (the distinction between "statics" and
1989, p. 450). "dynamics" or between "spiritual" and
Comte never disputed this development. "worldly power") be seen as important
On the contrary, he himself stressed that innovations.

This content downloaded from 148.61.13.133 on Thu, 14 Nov 2013 03:55:09 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
AUGUSTE COMTE AND MODERN EPISTEMOLOGY 155
Comte undoubtedly made contributions science could be founded on some nonhis-
to both positivism and sociology. Probably torical, logical, or (in any case) universal
most important were his attempts to formu- principle. Accordingly he rejected virtually
late more systematic and more elaborate all of the existing theories. Descartes had
conceptions, but interpreting them as re- located a foundation for knowledge in an
markable breakthroughs in any sense is ahistorical subject; Leibniz had looked for
questionable. One may add that historically a logical foundation and unification of the
these contributions have not been especially sciences; all classical theories presupposed
significant either. Sociology became an that there actually was a timeless and uni-
academic discipline and logical positivism versal criterion for truth (see, for example,
developed in philosophy, but in both cases McRae 1961).
the relationship with Comte's conceptions Comte's epistemology broke with this
was almost entirely nominal. For the logical presupposition as the result of a twofold
positivists Comte hardly existed; there is operation. First of all, Comte historized the
not one such thinker for whom Comte has question: scientific knowledge was to be
been important. In fact, Comte's theory seen as a historical process. Concepts and
was opposed in many ways to the program theories change; any statement about sci-
of the logical positivists. Comte rejected the ence therefore should be a statement about
idea that there existed universal criteria by historical processes, not about universals.
which scientific statements could be distin- In comparison with the earlier contribu-
guished once and for all from nonscientific tions of Turgot and Condorcet and with the
statements. He also rejected the reduc- emerging historicism and Hegelian philoso-
tionist ideal that was so dear to the logical phy in Germany, this position was not
positivists. In sociology the situation was uncommon. More original was the second
the same. Durkheim, the sociologist who operation, whereby Comte differentiated
owed most to Comte, regarded the law of the sciences according to a theory about the
the three stages as a "historical curiosity" specific characteristics of their object. He
(Durkheim 1975 [1915]). He was no more rejected monist or reductionist theories of
strongly impressed with Comte's other science and replaced them with a differ-
sociological insights. ential theory. What science was depended
on phases and stages, but also on the spe-
cific properties of the scientific object in
COMTE'S ORIGINALITY question. It was impossible to reduce the
different sciences to one basic type.
The conclusion, then, must be either that This differential approach, first of all,
Comte was a very minor figure or that was the establishment of a fact. With the
something has been overlooked. Com- expansion and the enormous prestige of
monly the first conclusion is accepted, but science during the revolutionary period in
that, I think, is a major mistake because France, scientific differentiation accelera-
Comte's intellectual contributions cannot ted. The Academy of Sciences remained a
be reduced to his positivism and his sociol- dominant institution, but was no longer the
ogy. To do so is to fail to recognize his undisputed center of scientific work. Under
theory of the sciences; that lack of recogni- the old regime the Academy of Sciences,
tion is standard practice (for one of the very like other academies, had held a monopoly
few exceptions see Elias 1979). Whatever on judgment. A scientist's career depended
may be the significance of his positivism essentially on the support of the Academy,
and his sociology, Comte's theory of the which also controlled the possibilities of
sciences was both more original and histori- publication. One of the major effects of
cally of much greater significance. Comte the French Revolution was that the mono-
was more important as a theorist of science polistic structures (guilds and other pro-
than as a positivist or a sociologist. Very fessional corporations) were abolished.
briefly, one might say that Comte was the Universities and academies were replaced
first to have developed systematically a his- by new institutions such as the Ecole
torical and differential theory of science. Polytechnique, specialized journals arose,
Comte, in effect, broke with the idea that scientific societies were founded, and at

This content downloaded from 148.61.13.133 on Thu, 14 Nov 2013 03:55:09 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
156 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
the same time conflicts became manifest sical phenomena (light, heat, electricity,
between different groups of what soon magnetism), however, were simple enough
would be "disciplines" in the modern for adequate mathematical description.
sense. Chemists studied matter at the level of
The new regime was a more differentiated molecular "composition" and "decompo-
structure, in which the traditional "supra- sition." These processes were subject not
disciplinary control" (Stichweh 1984) was only to the laws of mechanics and physics,
weakened severely. This shift may be de- but also to what were called "chemical
scribed as the transition from the classical affinities." Biologists studied living beings,
to the modern epistemic regime. It was which were more complex than dead bodies.
accompanied by a similar change in episte- Their conduct could not be explained solely
mology (for a more detailed analysis see by physical forces and chemical affinities
Heilbron, forthcoming). Whereas theories because it depended primarily on the "or-
of science during the Enlightenment had ganization" of the body. Social phenomena
been based on the unity and invariability of were yet more complicated because human
reason, around 1800 epistemology became beings had the capacity to learn. In that
an area for competing conceptions and respect they differed from other living
divergent cognitive strategies. creatures.
In France this change led to open con- The sciences, Comte argued, formed a
flicts, especially between representatives of series of increasing complexity and decreas-
the mathematico-mechanical disciplines ing generality. The laws of mechanics and
and spokesmen for the life sciences. Each physics were fairly simple and were valid
group tended to defend a form of monism. for all natural phenomena, big or small,
Representatives of the mathematical sci- dead or alive. Chemistry was more complex
ences, such as Condorcet and Laplace, and less general. There were many physical
claimed that their models also were valid phenomena without chemical effect, but
for chemistry, biology, and even the no chemical phenomena without physical
"moral sciences." With the tools of the effects. The laws of biology were more
calculus and probability theory, mathe- complex, and were valid only for living
matization had become an important tool bodies. The laws of human societies were
in many areas. Condorcet's "social ma- still more complex and less general. Human
thematics" was only one example of this beings formed, so to speak, the smallest
trend. Representatives of the life sciences, subset of natural phenomena.
on the other hand, argued that their theo- This series of increasing complexity,
ries were in fact more general. Cabanis, for according to Comte, also explained the his-
instance, claimed that gravity was merely a torical development of the sciences. The
particular form of "affinity" or "sensibil- human mind first discovered the principles
ity" and that physics therefore was part of of the simplest objects. Knowledge of more
the more general science of physiology complex objects was acquired only after the
(Staum 1980, pp. 179-82). simpler phenomena had become known.
Against this background, Auguste Com- Chemistry became a positive science only in
te may be seen as one of the first to have the eighteenth century. Biology was in the
investigated these struggles with some de- process of becoming and science; in socio-
tachment. He rejected the generalizations logy the first steps had yet to be taken.
of the various parties and tried to specify This basic idea of a differential series of
the conditions under which certain methods the sciences was elaborated in detail in
and procedures were more effective than Comte's Cours de Philosophie Positive,
others. The result was a differential theory which appeared in six volumes between
of science, which was founded on the dis- 1830 and 1842. Comte's theory basically
tinction between different levels of com- concerned the relationships between differ-
plexity. Astronomers studied the geometry ent sciences. He recognized, of course, that
and the mechanics of celestial bodies; these the sciences had characteristics in common;
were fairly simple phenomena. Physics was he discussed this matter in the first lesson of
a more complex and less unified field that the Cours, where one finds Comte's posi-
could not be reduced to mechanics. Phy- tivism. Yet these six volumes were not

This content downloaded from 148.61.13.133 on Thu, 14 Nov 2013 03:55:09 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
AUGUSTE COMTE AND MODERN EPISTEMOLOGY 157
about what the sciences had in common. in an unexpected manner. The Ecole Poly-
Contrary to what is generally assumed, they technique was closed down, and the pupils
were not concerned with the demarcation were sent home. A conflict between the stu-
between science and metaphysics. The dents and an authoritarian tutor had been
Cours tried to explain how recent develop- the beginning of a student rebellion. In the
ments in the sciences could be interpreted in midst of this conflict 15 pupils asked the
the light of the ontological scheme that man to leave the school; among them was
Comte had developed earlier. Thus the Auguste Comte. The directors of the school
Cours de Philosophie Positive is not a thought it necessary to demonstrate their
positivist textbook, and positivism (in the firmness because they needed the support of
sense of an antimetaphysical conception of the Restoration government that had just
knowledge) is not the principal subject of come to power. They demanded that the
the book. The Cours presents essentially an government expel the 15 pupils. The gov-
elaboration of a historical and differential ernment, in turn, used the situation to close
theory of science. the whole school, which was suspected of
If this interpretation is valid, Auguste republican and Napoleonic sympathies.
Comte can be described as one of the very Comte was forced to return to Mont-
first modern epistemologists. His differ- pellier. He took some courses there at the
ential approach to scientific knowledge Faculty of Medicine, but soon Paris proved
implied a radical rejection of any claim for to be irresistible. He went back to the
scientific monopolies. It also put an end to capital, and from that time earned his living
the illusion of universal methods. This by giving private lessons in mathematics.
antireductionist form of theorizing was an Occasionally he thought of finding a better
extremely important intellectual break- job. He was employed by Saint-Simon for
through. Therefore what must be explained some months; he had a plan to go to
is not so much Comte's positivism or soci- England; he dreamed of a chair; but for 16
ology as the rise of this theory. years he continued giving his lessons. Not
until after the Revolution of July 1830 did
he begin to work as a tutor at the Ecole
THE DYNAMICS OF THE COMTEAN Polytechnique. By then, however, his theo-
PROJECT ry already was formulated; it needed only
elaboration and recognition.
Comte grew up in a period when French A closer look at these years makes it
science flourished as never before. Around possible to reconstruct the steps that
1800 Paris became the center of the scien- resulted in his theory. The first systematic
tific world. This was true for almost all outline can be found in a piece published in
fields, but especially for the mathematical 1822; thus the theory essentially had
disciplines. emerged in the six previous years. In this
At school Comte had been most impressed period Comte struggled with two problems;
by his mathematics teacher, and at the age both were linked to his exclusion from the
of 14 he began to prepare for the entrance Ecole Polytechnique.
examinations for the Ecole Polytechnique. The first problem was political; Comte
Seventy-five candidates were admitted blamed the Bourbon Restoration for his
to the prestigious school. Comte placed expulsion. His very first text is a violent
fourth; three Parisians had done better (for attack on the "terrible league of kings and
Comte's biography see Gouhier 1933-41). priests." Almost immediately afterward,
In 1814 Comte left Montpellier, his home however, Comte raised the question of a
town; after a journey of 16 days he arrived more scientific approach to politics and
in Paris to start his studies. Among his society. In early articles he clearly drew on
teachers were some of the best-known scien- Saint-Simonian arguments, but his work
tists of the time, and his first letters to differs in tone and style from the prophetic
friends show an enormous enthusiasm and declarations of his master. His views corre-
excitement. sponded to those of the liberal opposition,
Barely two years later, a crucial event but they were not merely political com-
occurred, which would change Comte's life ments. He wrote a text on tax reform which

This content downloaded from 148.61.13.133 on Thu, 14 Nov 2013 03:55:09 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
158 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
actually is an analysis of the function of In a letter, the 21-year-old Comte
taxes in industrial society. He also wrote a explained to a friend that most mathemati-
critical note about the role of liberal politi- cians were merely "calculating machines."
cians, in which he stated that it is not pos- They were preoccupied with a few very
sible to analyze and participate in politics special questions, and did not even under-
at the same time. Thus even these early stand why the methods they applied were so
political texts revealed the attitude and the effective. If they had some knowledge of
dispositions of a scientist, or in any case other sciences and other methods, they
someone who was used to reasoning in a would understand their own work better
way that was very different from Saint- and would not pretend that all scientific
Simon's. problems had a mathematical solution
The second problem that concerned (Comte 1973 [1819]). Comte had in mind
Comte was mathematics, which was the specifically the biomedical sciences. For
basis of the training at the Ecole Polytech- these disciplines, which were not taught in
nique. Most of the leading scientists in the Ecole Polytechnique, the term "bio-
France were mathematicians, and they had logy" was coined between 1800 and 1802.
been either teachers or pupils at the school. The introduction of a new term as a general
Their reputation was due largely to what designation for botany, zoology, and medi-
has been described as the "burst of mathe- cine was part of a struggle for scientific
matization" in the first quarter of the recognition. Lamarck, who introduced the
nineteenth century (Kuhn 1976). French term in France, had opposed the efforts of
scientists firmly dominated this develop- mathematical physicists in this domain and
ment, of which Laplace was the leading he strongly rejected the validity of their
figure (Fox 1974; Grattan-Guinnness 1981). approach. A similar position had been for-
Mathematics also was the science that mulated by Bichat, who belonged to the
Comte knew best. He did not doubt its sig- so-called Montpellier school. Comte refer-
nificance, but he became increasingly cri- red often to Bichat and called him the true
tical about the way in which mathematical founder of biology; in the positivist calen-
tools were used. He also was critical about dar it is Bichat rather than Galileo, Newton,
the unlimited claims that were made in the or Laplace who figures as the patron of
name of mathematics. What was needed, he modern science.
thought, was a theory of mathematics that The Montpellier version of biology is an
also would account for its limitations. Such important clue to the Comtean theory of
a theory would be useful both to scientists the sciences. According to Bichat, living
and to teachers of mathematics. Being lib- organisms differ from inorganic phenom-
erated from the routines of the school, ena because they are irregular. Therefore in
Comte felt that he perceived the imperfec- biology it is impossible to look for the same
tions of the school and of its mathematical kind of regularities as in mechanics. Math-
spirit more clearly than other people. The ematical models are inappropriate, and
book he planned on the subject, however, biology should be an independent science
was never written. He abandoned it after based on the study of "vital principles" or
writing about 80 pages because he soon dis- "vital forces" (see Canguilhem 1983, pp.
covered that a theory of mathematics would 75-80).
have to be based on the role of mathematics Comte was not an unconditional admirer
in science, and an explanation of that role of this concept. He reformulated certain
would require a theory of science rather aspects, but basically he agreed with it.
than a theory of mathematics. With the recognition of biology as a science
In 1819 Comte was convinced that he had different from physics, Comte acquired a
formulated the problem in a new way and fruitful analogy by which to redefine the
that he was reaching an interesting solu- status of social science: Social science
tion. The "learning years" were over, he would be to biology what biology was to
wrote to a friend, and to mark the transi- chemistry. This reasoning can be found
tion he changed his name from Isodore to almost literally in a note written by Comte
Auguste. in 1819. The note is titled "On the attempts

This content downloaded from 148.61.13.133 on Thu, 14 Nov 2013 03:55:09 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
AUGUSTE COMTE AND MODERN EPISTEMOLOGY 159

that have been undertaken to found the his education normally offered. From the
social science on another science" (in beginning, Comte's intention was critical;
Comte 1970b [1817], 473-82). he wanted to write a critique of mathemati-
If the analogy with biology was to be cal reason. Yet it was no less typical of his
followed, what were the specific character- project that this critique would be con-
istics of social phenomena as compared to structive. It would be based on science and
biological phenomena? The answer can be would be addressed to the very people who
found in a text about Condorcet, written in formed the object of his criticism. Comte
the same year. The progressive develop- did not recognize any reference group other
ment of civilization, or the law of progress, than these mathematically trained physi-
is the dominant force in the human world. cists at the Ecole Polytechnique and the
It was, in a way, the "vital principle" in the Academy of Sciences. He did not try to
life of human beings; according to Comte, find a position anywhere else, and he
it was to Condorcet's credit that he had maintained that biologists and sociologists
discovered it. should learn mathematics and physics
Thus Bichat's concept of biology was before starting to work on more complex
the clue to Comte's theory of the sciences. objects.
The theory of the sciences, in turn, was the Comte tried to convince his former col-
solution to the two problems with which leagues that they unjustly claimed a mono-
Comte struggled: mathematics and politics. poly on scientificity. There were other
In his epistemology they form the two ends positive sciences, in which physicists could
of the chain. learn other procedures than those to which
One may add that Comte's understand- they were accustomed. From biologists they
ing of biology also was crucial for his could learn the comparative method; from
sociology. His sociological conceptions sociologists they could learn the historical
depended strongly on biological notions, method. To think that there were math-
and his sociological vocabulary is essen- ematical methods for these sciences was to
tially a transposition of biological concepts. strive for "impossible perfection," as
Comte recognized that sociology was a dif- Comte said in his early texts. His later
ferent science from biology, and that the formulations were less diplomatic; in the
law of the three stages was the specific prin- Cours he rejected probability theory be-
ciple of human society. Yet although he cause he saw it as an instrument of mathe-
never ceased to stress this point, his notion maticians with which to dominate the other
of historical processes remained biological. sciences.
Progress was the development of order; On the other hand, Comte did not agree
dynamics, for that matter, were subordi- with the biologists' claim to independence.
nated to statics. Comte borrowed this idea Increasing complexity also meant increas-
from biology, a biology that was not evolu- ing dependency. Living beings depended on
tionist but "preformist," and in which chemical and physical processes, whereas
developments were seen as the realization of physics and chemistry did not depend on
a pre-existing entity. The appropriate biology. Biological phenomena formed a
images for this mode of thinking were specific level of reality, but this was not an
embryos and germs (Canguilhem et al. independent level. Nor was it an antago-
1985, pp. 22-25). nistic level, as Bichat had supposed. The
struggle between the forces of life and the
A CRITIQUE OF MATHEMATICAL forces of death was a vitalist myth that
REASON Comte did not accept. Instead he did much
to find concepts that could bridge the gap
Comte's theory was the outcome of a between the organic and the inorganic. His
dilemma. It was the work of a man thor- idea was that of "relatively autonomous"
oughly trained in the mathematical and sciences. Comte formulated this idea, al-
physical sciences, who had been virtually though he did not use this expression, which
expelled from the scientific community and seems to be very recent. (It is found in the
excluded from the career possibilities that work of Louis Althusser and Norbert Elias,

This content downloaded from 148.61.13.133 on Thu, 14 Nov 2013 03:55:09 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
160 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
both of whom have expressed their admira- that his project would gain recognition.
tion for Comte.) The scientists were interested only in their
It is not possible to state exactly when own specialties and in their careers, and
and how Comte discovered the work of the other intellectuals were even worse. For
biologists. Yet one could say that sooner or reasons of "mental hygiene," Comte
later he would have had to assimilate their stopped reading other work. This act sym-
work because it was the only critique of bolized his relationship with the intellectual
mathematical physics that was scientifically world. It announced a new dynamic-a
sound. There were many other forms of search for a new audience and for other
critique, but Comte was never tempted by possibilities and pleasures.
the antiscientific romanticisms of Cha- What Auguste Comte had offered was
teaubriand or by the theological resistance too critical for the scientific establishment
to science of de Maistre and de Bonald. and too scientific for men of letters and
What Saint-Simon wrote about science philosophers. In the humane sciences in
must have been like science fiction to France, half a century passed before the
Comte, and for spiritualist philosophers Comtean epistemology was taken up again.
such as Victor Cousin he had a deep
contempt. CONCLUSION
Comte adhered to a strict idea of positive
science, and his proposals were addressed Comte's theory of the sciences was a
to the established scientists. This persever- detailed elaboration of a historical and dif-
ance is linked to the fact that he had no ferential theory of science. It was opposed
resources other than his scientific abilities. to any form of cognitive absolutism; how-
Coming from a relatively humble social ever strange it may seem, Comte thought of
background, he had no economic resources. himself as a relativist. "Tout est relatif,
Being a native of Montpellier, he had very voild la seule chose absolue" was a favorite
few relatives in Paris, and he thought of maxim of the young Comte (see, for exam-
himself as incapable of moving in Parisian ple, Comte 1970b [1817]). For Comte this
circles. In this world he was condemned to "relativism" was related to the historical
"philosophical observations," as he once nature of science and to his differential
wrote in a letter in which he described his ontology of the sciences. The theory was
visit to a ball. He did not dance, and he did formulated in opposition to different forms
not like the "gens comme ilfaut." What he of absolutism, but because it presented an
had was his scientific capital, and his whole ontological scheme, it also was opposed to
strategy in the beginning was aimed at the intellectual voluntarism that spokesmen
accumulating this kind of capital in a of the literary intelligentsia propagated.
particular way. Chateaubriand and later romantics adhered
Comte's theory emerged from the ten- to the cult of the creative genius. Against
sions between a scientist and the scientific such forms of intellectual voluntarism,
establishment from which he was partially Comte's theory presented an account of the
excluded. The distance allowed him to see sciences that was formulated in terms of the
what insiders did not see and what outsiders degree of complexity and generality of their
could not see with sufficient precision. By object. Ultimately the issue is whether there
elaborating these insights he hoped to win is a need and a possibility for such a form of
back what had been taken from him, and in ontology. If this is the case, Comte's con-
fact, his first work was fairly well received. ception certainly has not lost its relevance.
In 1826 he made another move and started The difference in levels of complexity is
his course in "positive philosophy." A few a central issue in any discussion of the
prominent members of the Academy of Sci- ontological questions of science, and it
ences were present at the opening session. is a central topic again in contemporary
In 1830 the first volume of the Cours epistemology.
appeared in print; by 1838, however, Comte's historical and differential
having reached the fourth volume, Comte theory of science inaugurated an original
wrote that there was no longer any hope tradition in epistemology. This tradition

This content downloaded from 148.61.13.133 on Thu, 14 Nov 2013 03:55:09 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
AUGUSTE COMTE AND MODERN EPISTEMOLOGY 161

may be regarded as specifically French. dimensions, which are related to scientific


It started to develop at the end of the actors and to the social arrangements that
nineteenth century, when academic philo- they form, should be included in any ade-
sophers such as Boutroux began to be inter- quate theory of science. Yet there is no
ested in Comte's work. Ever since that reason why such a theory should be incom-
time, French history and philosophy of sci- patible with a historical and differential
ence have been closely intertwined. This epistemology such as Comte proposed.
historical epistemology, as it has been
called, replaced the search for logical foun-
dations with a problematic in which pro- REFERENCES
cesses of concept formation and theory
Canguilhem, Georges. 1983. Etudes d'Histoire et de
building were analyzed as historically and Philosophie des Sciences. Paris: Vrin.
regionally bound. This mode of analysis, Canguilhem, Georges, G. Lapassade, J. Piquemal,
represented by Bachelard and Canguilhem, and J. Ulmann. 1985. Du Developpement d
continued something that began with l'Evolution au XIXe Siecle. Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France.
Auguste Comte and that was opposed- Comte, Auguste. 1970a (1835). "Premier M6moire
curiously enough-to the logical positivism sur la Cosmogonie Positive." In Ecrits de Jeunesse,
which had come to dominate the Anglo- 1816-1828. Paris: Mouton.
American world. This tradition was used by . 1970b (1817). "Premier Aperqu d'un Travail
Althusser to reinterpret Marx, was renewed sur le Gouvernement Parlementaire Considere
comme Regime Transitoire." In Ecrits de Jeunesse,
by Michel Foucault and Pierre Bourdieu, 1816-1828. Paris: Mouton.
and is present in the assumptions of many 1973 (1819). "Lettre a Valat, 24-9-1819."
French works. In this respect Comte's work In Correspondance Gene'rale et Confessions.
may be said to represent a tacit reference Vol. 1. Paris: Mouton.
for quite a few leading French intellectuals. . 1975 (1830). "Cours de Philosophie Positive."
In Philosophie Premiere. Cours de Philosophie
The French reception of Kuhn's work, for Positive, Lecons 1 d 45. Pr6sentation et notes
example, which has astonished foreign par M. Serres, F. Dagognet, A. Sinaceur. Paris:
observers, can be understood only with Hermann.
reference to the Comtean tradition in the . 1983 (1844). Discours sur I'Esprit Positif.
Paris: Vrin.
sense outlined above. Dhombres, Nicole and Jean Dhombres. 1989. Nais-
If Auguste Comte is seen in this way, one sance d'un Nouveau Pouvoir: Sciences et Savants en
cannot easily overestimate his significance. France (1793-1824). Paris: Payot.
Yet this is not the whole story. In fact, Durkheim, Emile. 1975 (1915). "La Sociologie."
In Textes, Vol. 1. Paris: Editions de Minuit.
Comte's theorizing contained a fundamen-
Elias, Norbert. 1979. What Is Sociology? London:
tal shortcoming. This was not so much his Hutchinson.
"positivism" or his "internalism" as his Fox, Robert. 1974. "The Rise and Fall of Laplacian
objectivism. Comte's approach was limited Physics." Historical Studies in the Development of
to a theory about the subject matter of the the Physical Sciences 4: 89-136.
different sciences. It gave no real account Gouhier, Henri. 1933-41. La Jeunesse d'Auguste
Comte et la Formation du Positivisme. Paris: Vrin.
of the subjects of scientific work or the Grattan-Guinness, I. 1981. "Mathematical Physics in
social practices in which they are involved. France, 1800-1840." In Mathematical Perspectives:
For Comte science was an activity of Essays on Mathematics and Its Historical Develop-
ment, edited by J.W. Dauben. New York: Academic
humanity; the only way in which he could Press.
explain why certain people discover certain Hahn, Roger. 1971. The Paris Academy of Sciences,
things at a certain time was by referring to 1666-1803. Berkeley: University of California
his levels of complexity: the human mind Press.
necessarily discovered simple things before Heilbron, Johan. Forthcoming. Het Onstaan van de
more complex phenomena. That is a poor Sociologie. Een Cultuursociologische Studie. Ams-
terdam: Prometheus.
explanation for the actual development of Kuhn, Thomas. 1976. "Mathematical vs. Experi-
the sciences. By eliminating the scientists mental Traditions in the Development of Physical
from science, Comte eliminated all the Science." Journal of Interdisciplinary History 7:
1-31.
problems of interpretation and sociability, McRae, R. 1961. The Problem of the Unity of the
of hermeneutics and sociology. Recent Sciences: Bacon to Kant. Toronto: Toronto Univer-
work has made it quite clear that these sity Press.

This content downloaded from 148.61.13.133 on Thu, 14 Nov 2013 03:55:09 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
162 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

Staum, M.S. 1980. Cabanis: Enlightenment and Medi- Turgot, A.-R.-J. 1750. "On Universal History."
cal Philosophy in the French Revolution. Princeton: Pp. 161-118 In On Progress, Sociology and Eco-
Princeton University Press. nomics, edited by Ronald Meek Cambridge: Cam-
Stichweh, R. 1984. Zur Entstehung des Modernen bridge University Press.
Systems Wissenschaftlicher Disziplinen: Physik in
Deutschland 1740-1890. Frankfurtam: Suhrkamp
Verlag.

This content downloaded from 148.61.13.133 on Thu, 14 Nov 2013 03:55:09 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like