Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 195

Emory University

Studies in Law and Religion


THE IDEA OF
General Editor
John Witte, Jr. NATURAL RIGHTS
Studies on Natural Rights,
Number l Natural Law, and Church Law
Theology of Law and Authority in the English Reformation
Joan Lockwood O'Donovan 1150-1625
Oxford University

Number2
Political Order and the Plural Structure of Society
James W. Skillen and Rockne M. McCarthy, editors
Center for Public Justice Brian Tierney
Number3
Faith and Order: The Reconciliation of Law and Religion
Harold J. Berman
Emory University

Number4
Religious Liberty in Western Thought
Noel B. Reynolds and W. Cole Durham, Jr., editors
Brigham Young University

Numbers
The Idea of Natural Rights: Studies on
Natural Rights, Natural Law and Church Law, 1150-1625
Brian Tierney WILLIAM B. EERDMANS PUBLISHING COMPANY
Cornell University GRAND RAPIDS, MICHIGAN I CAMBRIDGE, U.K.

I
j
I
CONTENTS

() 1997 Emory University A C KNOWLEDGMENTS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . • . . . . . . . . ... ix


C ITATIONS ..... ... . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . ... . . . . . . . . . .. . . xi
First published 1997 by Scholars Press for Emory University
INTRODUCTION
This editio n published 2001 by Wm. B. Eerdmans Publis hing Co. Modem Problems and Historical Approaches . ............. .. .. . 1
255 Jeffe rson Ave. S.E., Grand Rapids, Michigan 49503 I
P.O. Box 163, Cambridge C B3 9PU U.K. PART O NE
All rights reserved Origins

Printed in the United States o f America <.."tlAPTER I


Villey, Ockham and the Origin of Individual Rights . ... . . ....... . 13
05 04 03 02 01 7654321 Clas.~ical Roman I.Aw
Individual Rights and Natural I.Aw
Aquinas and the Canonists: lus and Lex
Library of Congre!l.'I Cataloging-in-Publication Data Ockham's "Revolution"
Objections to Villey
liemey, Brian.
Alternative Approaches
The idea o f natural rights: studies on natural rights, natu ral law,
and church law, 1150-1625 I by Brian Tierney. ' ·11A t'rER II
cm. - (Emo ry Univer.;ity studies in law and religion; no. 5) <lri>;ins of Natural Rights Language:
P· li•Jo.ts ;md Contexts, 1150 - 1250 ..... ..... ........ .. .. . ....... . 43
Includes bibliograph ical references.
ISBN 0-8028-4854-'0 (paper: a lk. paper) "1111' Q11estion of Origins
1. Natural law - History. I. litle. II. Series. Sc111m~ of Modern Rights l.Anguage
K445.T54 1997 t 111rc111is tir Rights l.Anguage-Contexts

340'. 112 - d c21 97-7386 < 11111111is lir R i,~l1ts lJ1nKuaKe-Texts


C IP N,.,.,1'""' N11t 11ra/ Rixht
I 11111 l11s1<111

I ll AI' I H < III


111,.,,111 ...mcl I >ut it•!i: f\ Quar.~tifl of l-lenry of G hl'nl . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 78
/\ r•, ,_,,,,,.,.~ I lil1·111ma
c 111'111·" /111• olj .~It

-
CONTENTS
CONTENTS vii
vi

PARTTwO CHArTERX
Ockham and The Franciscans Almain, Mair, Summenhart ... .. .......... . ........ . ..... . 236
Medieval Survivals
CHAPTER IV Mair. Rights and Needs
The Beginning of the Dispute .. . ..... . .. . ................ . 93 S11mmmhart. Varieties of Dominion
From Francis to Ockham A New Age
Approaches to Ockham CHAPTER XI
CHAPTERV
Aristotle and the American Indians ......................... . 255
Languages of Rights .... .. . . . . .. . ... .... . . .... ... .... . . . 104 Vitoria. Aquinas and Natural Rights
Hervaeus Natalis. lus and Potestas Vitoria. Rights and Indians
,Marsilius of Padua. lus and Lex I.As Casns. Indians and Rights
Willillm ofOckham. Ius Poli and lus Fori CHAPTER XII
Conclusion Rights, Community, and Sovereignty ............. . . . ... . .... . 288
CHAPTER VI Vitoria. Sovereignty and Divine Right
Property, Natural Right, and the Stat.e of Nature ............. . 131 Suarez. Sovereignty and Natural Rights
Problems of First Acquisition CHAPTER XIII
Civilillns, Canonists, and Theologians Grotius. From Medieval to Modem ... . . . . .. ... . . . . ...... .... . 316
Bonagratia of Bergamo and John XXII The Question of Modernity
Ockham on Property Natural Law and Natural Riglrts
CHAPTER VII The Right to Property
William of Ockham. Rights and Some Problems Individuals, Society, and Sovereignty
of Political Thought . . . ..... ............... . ... · ........ . 170 C ONCLUSION .. . .............. .... ....................... . . 343
Origins offurisdidicn BIBLIOGRAPHY ......... . .. . .. . ................ .... ........ . 349
Varieties of Natural Law
Absolutism and Natural Rights
A Rights~Based Political Theory?
CHAPTERVllJ
Postscript .......... ... . ........... . . . . . . . .. .... .. . . .. . 195

PART THREE
From Gerson To Grotius

CHAYrERlX
Gerson. Conciliarism, Corporatism, and Individualism . . . . . . . . . 207
Individual and Community
Tuck on Gerson
Rights and Conciliarism
Rights ond Reform
lus and Dominiu.m
. . .. . .. . . •' .
•• , • ., , .,, . ,. f, •• • , . ,, •

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

The author wishes to thank the publishers for permission to reprint, in


a revised form, material that originally appeared in the following sources:
"Villey, Ockharn, and the Origin of Natural Rights," in The Weightier
Matters of the Law. Essays on I.Aw and Religion, ed. John Witte Jr. and Frank S.
Alexander (Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1988), 1-31.
"Conciliarism, Corporatism, and Individualism. The Doctrine of Sub-
jective Rights in Gerson," Cristianesimo nella storia 9 (1988): 81-110.
"Marsilius on Rights," Journal of the History of Ideas 53 (1991): 3-17.
"Natural Rights in the Thirteenth Century. A Quaestio of Henry of
Ghent," Speculum 67 (1992): 58-68.
I also want to thank Coraleen Rooney for her skill and care in prepar-
ing successive drafts of the manuscript.
., '.,,•' . -.... •'' ·-. •' ... .
.
'. ' ' ., ' ·~
' •' • ''
~'

CANON LAW CITATIONS

Decretum Decretum Gratiani (ca. 1140). The Decretum was divided


into two main sections, Distinctiones and Causae. The
Causae were subdivided into Quaestiones. Texts of the
Deeretum are cited thus: Dist. 42 c.3 refers to the third
chapter of Distinctio 42. C.12. q.1 c.2 refers to the second
chapter of Quaestio 1 in Causa 12. Two s ubsections of the
Decretum, De consecratione and De penitentia were also
divided into Distinctiones. They are cited as De cons. and
De pen.
X Decretales Gregorii Papae IX (1234). This volume is re-
ferred to by the symbol ' X' because it was commonly
known as the Liber extra, that is, the book extra to or ad-
ditional to the Decretum. It is divided into books which
are s ubdiv ided into titles. Thus X.2.12.4 refers to Book 2,
Title 12, Chapter 4 of the Gregorian Decretals.
Sext. Liber Sextus Decretalium Bonifacii Papae VIII (1293). This
work is cited in the same way as the Gregorian Decre-
tals, e.g. Sext. 5.12.3.
Clem. Constitutiones Clementi Papae V (1317). Cited in the same
way as the Decretals and Uber sextus, e.g., Clem. 5.11.1.
r:Ytrav. /. XXII Constitutiones XX Joannis Papae XXII (ca. 1325). This col·
lection was divided into Titles and Chapters but not
into separate Books.
t:xlrr111. Com. Extravaganles Communes. A collection of decretals addl'd
to the previous volumes at the end of the medieval
period to complete the Corpus iuris ca11onici. It wa!I again
dividC'd into Hooks, Titles, and Chapters.
o
, •-,

••,.•-<
• • '
..0 ., • I
0, , 1 ,

••

, . ,

INTRODUCTION:
MODERN PROBLEMS AND HISTORICAL APPROACHES

W hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created


equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain un-
alienable Rights. .. ." 1 But of course Jefferson's self-evident truths about
inalienable rights have not seemed evident to most of the human race
over most of recorded history. All civilized societies have cherished ideals
of justice and right order, but they have not normally expressed those
ideals in terms of individual natural rights-it would be hard, for in-
stance, to imagine a Confucian Hobbes or Locke. Moses gave Command-
ments to the children of Israel, not a code of rights. Plato and Aristotle saw
no need to appeal to a concept of natural rights in formulating their po-
li tical theories. Roman lawyers too were able to do without such rights in
crafting their complex legal system. In considering the origin of natural
rights theories we are faced with a historical problem, not a sort of re-
vealed truth.
When we address the problem of origins, we need also to bear in mind
some of the broader issues concerning human rights in the modem world.
Questions like these arise: Were the classical rights theorists of early mod-

I / )n·/nration c>f lndq~ndmct (1776), " We hold these truths to be self~vident, that all nwn
.uc• nt>.itc:-J l'qual, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalimable Rlghh,
lh,,t .imung I~ al? Life. Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness-That to 5t'CUI'\' the~ right~.
<;uvt•rnmc>n1~ .ir'l' in.•li1utf.'d among Men. drriving th<'ir just powers fmm !ht> con!K'nl of th••
gnV•'n""'· ·n"'' wht•O<'vc·r any Fonn ,,f C~>vt'mmt•nt l>t-<-o ml'll dftltnl<'tivt• of tht'!'f' 1•mh1, It 1..
llw l<IKhl of tlw l'ruplc• tu Alh•r nr "hollNh It 11ml lt1 ln1<tll11tr m•w ( ;ovrmmc•nt . "
2 ntE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHTS INTRODUCTION 3

em Europe merely articulating a doctrine that was implicit, if unacknowl- argument, based on a belief in the innate dignity of human persons, is
edged, in all societies? Or is the whole idea of human rights peculiarly a humane and sensible, but it could be grounded more securely on a differ-
product of Western culture? And if the idea did have a distinctively West- ent kind of historical analysis. Macintyre has deplored "the deep Jack of
ern origin can it have any relevance for other peoples? Modem historians, historical consciousness" that infects much of modem moral philosophy,
philosophers, and political scientists disagree about such matters. but he does not understand the history of the rights theories that he criti-
A UNESCO document of 1949 referred to "the antiquity and broad ac- cizes. Gewirth's philosophical argument is sophisticated. and appealing,
ceptance of the conception of the rights of man," and suggested that the but it leaves open all the questions that most concern a historian. When did
discussion of such rights goes back to the beginnings of philosophy, in the idea of natural rights find "explicit recognition and elucidation"? What
both the East and the West.2 Few historians would agree with such a broad historical context made such a development possible? How did the idea
judgment. Among contemporary philosophers, Alan Gewirth has argued come to survive once it had grown into existence? But when we tum to
that all humans, simply as conscious agents, must logically claim certain the historians for enlightenment there is again no consensus. Kenneth
rights for themselves and recognize the same rights in others, specifically Minogue has asserted that the idea of human rights is "as modem as the
rights to freedom and well-being. Gewirth also maintains that rights exist internal combustion engine." 6 Donnelly found a starting point in Locke.
in all societies even when there is no "dear or explicit recognition and An Italian writer has observed., with serene confidence, that scholars agree
elucidation" of the concept of a right.3 At the other extreme Alisdair Mac- unanimously on this one point: "The theory of natural rights is born with
Intyre, criticizing Gewirth's argument from the standpoint of Aristotelian Hobbes."7 Knud Haakonssen discussed the role of Grotius as an innovator.
moral philosophy, dismissed natural rights as mere "fictions," an unfor- Richard Tuck emphasized the contribution of Gerson. Michel Villey has
tunate invention of modem liberal individualism that we should do well maintained., in a long series of publications, that the true "father of subjec-
to discard.' Arguing from yet another point of view as a political scientist, tive rights" was the fourteenth-century Franciscan philosopher, William of
Jack Donnelly acknowledges that the doctrine of natural rights had a dis- Ockham. Evidently there is room for some further historical clarification.
tinctively Western origin in the "bourgeois revolution" of the seventeenth The historian's problem does not consist simply in determining when
and eighteenth centuries, but still maintains that the theory so engendered an idea of natural rights as such emerged. There are many ancillary issues,
has a universality that makes it generally applicable to all present-day still matters of current debate, that call for further historical investigation.
societies.5 One such issue concerns the scope of natural rights (assuming that they
The diversity of these opinions suggests that a historical account of exist at all) especially as regards "active rights" and "passive rights." All
the evolution of natural rights theories might contribute something to meaningful assertions of rights make claims on other people; but the
the modem debates. Historical inquiry cannot solve all the problems of claims can be of very different kinds. To assert an active right, a right actu-
modem philosophers and political theorists, but it might help us to ad- ally to do something-to dig in my own garden for instance, or to worship
dress them in a more informed and sophisticated fashion. Donnelly's as I please-I need demand only forbearance from others. The assertion of
a passive right, sometimes called a right of recipi.e nce or welfare right, re-
2. Human Rights: Commmls and lnttrpmation.s. A Symposium olittd by UNESCO (New
quires that others render to me some good or service--free medical care
York, 1949), 260. perhaps. Some modem scholars argue that the multiplication of social and
3. A. Gewirth, &tison and Morality (Chicago, 1978), 99. For a more recent restatement of E>Conomic rights (or so-called rights) introduces an "artificial inflation" into
these views, see Gewirth, •15 Cultural Pluralism Relevant to Moral Know ledger Social Phi· rights language that finally renders the whole concept of human rights
losophy and Policy 11(1994): 22-43. Various criticisms of Gewirth's argument are presented in vague and valueless.8 Defenders of welfare rights insist that such rights are
E. Regis, ed., Gtwirtlr's EthiCJZl Rlltio1111/ism: Critic.al Essays With a Reply by Alan GtWirth (Chi-
<it least as essential to human well-being as a mere right to be left alone to
cago, 1984).
4. A. Macintyre, Afttr Virtue. A Study in Moral Theory, 2nd ed. {Notre Dame, 1984), 70, pursue one's own interests. On the level of historical discourse, Maurice
•Natural or human rights then are fictions...." Like Macintyre, I use the terms natural
rights and human rights interchangeably. 'The tenn "human rights" is often used nowadays h. K. Minogue, "The History of the Idea of Human Rights," in~ Human Rights Rtadtr,
to indicate a lack of any necessary commitment to the philosophical and theological systems c'tl11. W. l.aqueur and B. Rubin (New York, 1979), 3-17 at 3.
formerly associated with the older term, "natural rights.• But the two concepts are essen· 7. N. Robhio, Thomas Hobbes and lht Natural Law Tradition, trans. D. Gobetti (Chicftgo,
tially the same. Human rights or natural rights are the rights that people have, not by virtue l 11'1'.\), l!'i4.
of any particular role or status in society, but by virtue of their very humanity. K. /\ Fh•w, "Th<' l\rlifici11l lnf1Atiun of Nnturnl Ri~ht~.ff Vrra l_,;r 8 (1988): 4-6. l>unm•lly
5. J. Donnelly, Uniutrsal Human Rights in Th~ry and Pracliu (lth111·ft, NY. l•JllCJ). AA 106. 1lrl1•111lc..I w1•1f"n' rightH in llnillf'rll#/ I/um"" Rixhl.•, :\I 4S.
4 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS lNTROOUCTION 5

Cranston argued that rights of recipience are a recent innovation, un- explain some early modem texts, suggests that natural rights and natural
known to the classical theorists of the seventeenth and eighteenth cen- law are not derived one from the other but that both a.re derived as correl-
turies;9 but James Tully found a "right to charity" in Locke and, earlier, in ative doctrines from the same underlying view of human personality. In
Aquinas. 10 Then Richard Tuck, at the opposite pole from Cranston, argued this way of thinking, it was assumed that natural law left to individuals a
that a doctrine of passive rights existed in medieval ;unsprudence before sphere of autonomy where the rights inherent in human nature could lic-
the idea of active rights was articulated. 11 His argument does not, how- itly be exercised.
ever, seem conclusive. The historical issue remains unresolved. Since this will be a recurring theme in the following work, and since a
The argument about active rights and passive rights grows out of derivation of natural rights from human nature may suggest some obvi-
a deeper disagreement concerning the proper relationship between indi- ous difficulties to a modem political theorist, it will perhaps be helpful to
vidual and community in a well-ordered society. Modem libertarians fear mention some of these issues at the outset and to indicate briefly why
the encroachment of state power on the core of individual autonomy that they did not arise in the same way for medieval thinkers.
they see as essential for a fully human life. Communitarian critics of rights Most obviously, many philosophers nowadays would deny that there
claims often discern in them an atomic individualism insensitive to any is any such thing as a common or universal human nature, "an essence
concept of the common good. Among historians, rights theories are often that precedes and antedates history. " 1 ~ I should explain therefore that, in
seen as an individualistic reaction against a medieval communal ethic. referring to human nature here and in subsequent discussions, I am not
D'Entreves, for instance, discussing the thought of the seventeenth cen- attributing to the authors concerned any doctrine about some abstract
tury, wrote, "The new value is that of the individual." 12 Yet Tully has ar- "essence" supposed to inhere in all humans or any particular theory of
gued that even such a classic rights theorist as Locke did not treat humans universals. Medieval rights theories were not typically derived from such
as isolated individuals but always as members of a unified community. 13 metaphysical considerations. Indeed, in the course of medieval thought,
Some of the earlier reflections on this theme are discussed in the following basically similar ideas about natural rights were propounded by phi·
chapters. losophers-Thomists, Scotists, and Ockhamists-who held very different
Yet another area of current disagreement concerns the relationship be- views on universals and essences. And in the postmedieval world doc-
tween modem rights theories and the more ancient doctrines of natural trines of rights continued to be asserted by writers who had rejected the
law and "classical natural right." Some scholars see natural rights as es- whole framework of scholastic thought. The medieval jurists, in whose
sentially extrapolations from principles always inherent in the natural law works a doctrine of natural rights first grew into existence, did not specu-
tradition. This was the position of Jacques Maritain and more recently of l,1tc about essences at all. It was enough for them-as for Locke in a later
John Finnis. Others, especially neo-Thomists like Villey in Europe, and the age-to perceive that humans displayed certain relevant characteristics,
followers of Leo Strauss in America, vehemently deny any such associ- the most important ones in this context being rationality and free will.
ation between the two areas of thought.14 Writers of this latter group see Another evident problem for historians is that, if natural rights are in~
modem rights theories as radically destructive of the earlier tradition; they lwrent in human beings as such, they must always have existed; and this
maintain that, after Ockham (or Hobbes or whoever is the chosen innova- st·ems contradicted by the lack of such rights in many societies through-
tor), rights came to form the real basis of moral discourse and natural law out the course of history. But the idea of natural rights is a moral one.
was seen as merely derivative, just a sum of individual rights. Another It does not refer to the rights that people can actually exercise in any given
approach, that we encounter in medieval sources and that might help to stKit'ly but to rights that ought to be recognized in all societies becau!*'
llwy arc necessary for the fulfillment of some basic human needs and
9. M. Cranston, Human Righls Today {London, 1962), 38. Cranston's view was criticized purposes.
by D. D. Raphad, nHuman Rights, Old and New," in Political Thmry and tlrt Rights of Man,
ed. D. D. Raphael (Bloomington, 1967), 54-67 at 62.
This may seem only to lead on to another difficulty. I am thinking now
10. J. Tully, A Discour~ on ProfXrlY (Cambridge, 1980), 132. 111 11 umc's familiar argument that we cannot derive moral statements from
11. R. Tuck, Medieval Natural Rights Theorits (Cambridge, 1979), 13. f.1dual ones. How, then, can we derive moral propositions about natural
12. A. P. D ' Entreves, Natural Law (New York, 1951), 54.
13. Di5ctlu~. 49. I'>. Rit-hard Rorty, "The Priority o f Democracy to Philosophy," in A. R. Malachowski, ro.,
14. For a review of this question see V. Black, "On Connecting Natural Rights With Na tu· lfr11.lmx fforty_Crilin1I Reiopon~ lo Phi/<1$(1phy and the Mirror of Nature (and Beyond) (Oxford,
ral Law/ Persona y DeTecho 22 (1990): 183-209. l'l'ICI). 2HI
6 THE IDEA Of NATIJRAL RIGHTS INTRODUCTION 7

rights by reflecting on the facts of human nature? Hume's argument seems Villey and Richard Tuck have made important contributions to the discus-
persuasive if we apply it only to external nature. Probably we cannot sion of medieval rights theories; but it seems to me, for reasons that will be
deduce moral principles from studying the behavior of stones and stars considered later, that the arguments they have presented are not altogether
and waterfalls. But medieval rights theories typically did not start out adequate or satisfying.16
from cosmic nature and, when medieval thinkers reflected on the nature of Some of the chapters below were originally published as separate
human beings, one fact they perceived-or thought they perceived-was articles and others were at first conceived of in the same way. (The long
that human rationality included a capacity for moral discernment; and section on the Franciscan poverty dispute was planned as a group of
from this fact it followed, for them, that humans ought to do what they separate essays to which I added a summarizing Postscript.) The published
discerned to be right. Evidently this would not satisfy a modem Humean articles have been rewritten so as to eliminate some of the repetition that
critic. And of course medieval writers did not provide an answer to inevitably occurs when an author returns to the same theme again and
Hume's argument; but this was because it did not arise for them; their way again. I hope that the reader will excuse such overlapping as remains. In
of thinking elided it. any case, it will be evident that these sections of the book were originally
Although Hume's problem did not directly concern medieval authors composed as freestanding essays. In particular, the argument in several
I have mentioned it here because it does have a relevance for a historian of chapters moves from medieval ideas to early modem ones and sometimes
medieval thought. The argument about moral statements and factual ones to contemporary rights discourse. It would be more chronologically tidy,
is often roughly paraphrased as, "You can' t get an ought from an is." I suppose, if all the modem material were presented at the end of the
Philosophers have worried endlessly about the validity of this proposition. book. But, in writing the separate articles, I wanted to illustrate the variety
But historians face a different kind of problem. We start out from an aware- of medieval source materials that we need to consider in order to under-
ness that there is an "is" standing behind every "ought"; our task is to stand adequately the origins of modem rights theories. I also wanted to
understand the "isness" within which certain kinds of "oughtness" can be show that, in medieval thought, there existed, not just some vague idea of
expected to flourish. That is to say, we are concerned to identify the his- a natural right, but many of the specific themes that we encounter in mod-
torical contexts within which certain moral values will be cherished and l'm works on rights-a distinction between natural rights and positive
certain related ideas, like the idea of natural rights, will seem appealing. I rights, rights considered as protected choices and as protected interests,
do not mean that all morality is relative; only that moral thought does not <1ctive rights and passive rights, alienable natural rights and inalienable
exist in a vacuum. In any given historical situation we can expect to find natural rights, adventitious rights, rights that were also duties.
some moral doctrines emphasized while others go unrecognized or ne- Medieval thinkers did not categorize all these different kinds of rights,
glected. The story of natural rights must, therefore, be in part a story of the argue about their relative value, and then choose some particular class
environments within which such a concept could take root and flourish; of rights to emphasize as most essential in the manner of many modem
and to make the story intelligible we need especially to remember that a rights theorists. But modem rights theorists argue in the way they do
historical environment is not constituted only by a play of contingent only because the concepts they discuss were already present, and so avail-
events at some particular time and place, but also by the whole tradition of able to them, in the tradition of discourse that the modem world inherited.
thought and language that a society inherits from its past. So, in often calling attention to parallels between medieval and modem
The studies that follow attempt to explore the early tradition of natural ideas, l was not intending just to make facile comparisons; I was hop-
rights thinking from which the doctrines of the modem world are ulti- ing to make the whole tradition of thought more intelligible. The po-
mately derived. They are presented as ventures into a terrain that has not litical culture of the seventeenth century was evidently different from
been very thoroughly explored in recent scholarship. We have a huge body that o f the thirteenth; but we cannot understand just how it was differ-
of work on present-day rights concepts-one author recently referred to a ··nt, or how it became different, unless we first learn to know what the
"welter" of such theories. There also exists an abundant literature on the ••arly modem world inherited or reappropriated from the preceding me-
classical rights doctrines of the seventeenth century; indeed it is hard to dit•val <'ra. We shall not fully understand how a culture of rights grew up
keep up with the output of the Hobbes and Locke industry alone from
year to year. But, compared with this flood of work, there has been only a
It.. ( >n Villt')' !'lt't' l>elo w, 13-42. For nilicism of Tuck st't' my luck on Rights: Soml' M<"-
thin trickle of writing on the idea of natural rights in the premodem era. •lll'v11I l'rnhh•11111." 111'.<ll".V 1if l'"lilin 1I 1111>11,'(hl 4 ( l'IKJ): 429- 41. /\nd Ill'<' l'>l'low, 217 20.
The field has not been entirely neglected of course. Scholars like Michel 1711 7.4
8 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS INTRODUCTION 9

in Western society until students of modem rights theories are willing to passed on to the modem world. Especially in the later chapters, the argu-
engage seriously with the considerable body of material that is being ment of the book is concerned both with the formalistic problem of how
made available-belatedly perhaps-by medievalists. the term ius nalurale came to be understood as meaning a natural right and
Among modem scholars, probably the most widely accepted account with the paradigmatic rights to liberty, property, and resistance to tyranny
of the origin of natural rights theories is the one presented by Michel that became central to the Western rights tradition.
Vtlley; he saw the modem idea of subjective rights as a revolutionary I hope that my chapters present an accurate account of the principal
innovation, inspired by the nominalist and voluntarist philosophy of stages in the growth of medieval natural rights theories, but I know that
William of Odcham. My book begins, therefore, with a critical study of they do not exhaust all the available material. There is room for further re-
Villey's thesis. The discussion then moves to the canonistic jurisprudence search in several areas. We need, for instance, more work on the concept
of the late twelfth century. Here, I argue, we can find an important shift of of rights in English common law, in the medieval glossators of Roman
language, a new understanding of the old term ius naturale as meaning a law, and in the late medieval jurists, both civilians and canonists. These
kind of subjective power or ability inhering in individuals, along with an latter writings often provided the immediate sources through which early
influential doctrine of permissive natural law. 1' The availability of this lan- modem authors had access to earlier medieval teachings. Apart from
guage, it is suggested, facilitated the growth of a new theory of natural studies on Aquinas and Ockham, there has been relatively little work on
rights alongside the old natural law teaching. The assimilation of the ju- the idea of rights in the writings of medieval philosophers and theolo-
rists' ideas into medieval philosophy, and their further development there, ~ians.18 Also, many sixteenth-century Spanish authors made significant
is first illustrated from the work of Henry of Ghent, who wrote interest- contributions besides the few that I have discussed. My book will serve a
ingly on the theme that every individual has a property right in his own useful purpose if it helps to stimulate more work in these fields.
person. The essays on the Franciscan poverty dispute reconsider the work
Clf Wil~ctm of Ockham in the context of the varied literature evoked by the
controversy. Ockham is presented in my work as an important figure
in the development of natural rights theories; but I argue that his char-
acteristic teachings were not derived from his nominalist and voluntarist
philosophy, but rather from a rationalist ethic applied to a body of juristic
doctrine available to him in the canon law collections that he knew well
and frequently cited. A chapter on Gerson treats the French theologian
within the context of the Conciliar movement for church reform. It dis-
cusses the coexistence in his work of an active concern for individual
rights with a profound sense of the church as a mystical body, a holistic
corporate community. The next part of the book deals with late medieval
scholastic thought where, for a time, the idea of natural rights seemed
to be losing its relevance to the real life problems of the age. Then I tum
to the impact of the European encounter with America on the growth of
natural rights theories. This chapter is also concerned with the fusion of
Thomist philosophy and juristic thought in the works of the sixteenth-
century Spanish scholastics. Their writings represent the final phase of the
medieval tradition of thought concerning natural rights and the relation-
ship between individual and community that Grotius inherited and
17. I have not included a chapter oo the rights theories of the great thirteenth-century IR. Whm this book was almost ready to go to pres.5 Dr. Annabel Brett very kindly let nw
canonists because this topk is thoroughly treated in the important a.rtide of Charles J. ....,. tht• lyJ>f'5<"ripl of her forthcoming work, liberty, Rixht 1ind Nalurt: T11t l.Jlni(uagt of lrrdi·
Reid, '1be Canonistic Contribution to the Western Rights Tradition: An Histo rical Inquiry," ''"'""' Ri,11hf,; i11 IJJlr r SC'/10/a.<lic Thouxhl. Dr. Brett pmvldes much valuable material on thl'
Boslcm Colltge l..tlw Rnriew 33 (1991): 37-92. Reid provides a detailed Hohfeldian analysis of 1·u1w1•pl of rl)lht~ In nw.lh•val phll1111ophk11l writings. I lt•r work caml' too latl• for ml' to makr
thirteenth-century rights concepts. ·"'Y 11111>111.mUal llM' nl ii, hut I h11vl' 1111.lt'C.i 11 frw 111111 mlnutt' l'l"ft'l'\'llCMI.
ONE
•,
,. •' ... ... . .
~ ·.;.
,
-· - "-> ' . ' . ,, ' . ., ' •.- ••,,

VILLEY, 0CKHAM, AND


THE ORIGIN OF INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS

I[ n a long series of studies, published over a period of forty years,


Michel Villey has made notable contributions to our understanding
• 11 !.·gal history. His thought is always interesting, sometimes idiosyncra-
1w . I !ere I want to discuss only one particular aspect of Vtlley's work, his
,,, rnunt of the origin of Western rights theories.
The concept of individual subjective rights has become central to our
I'' •I itical discourse, but we still have no adequate account of the origin and
··.11 ly development of the idea. 1 The lack of such work leaves open one of
1I1•· t "t•ntral problems of modem debate-whether the idea of human rights
1·. ·a mwthing universal, common to all societies, or whether it is a distinc-
11 v1· , wation of Western culture, which emerged at some specific, identifi-
''"'•· point in European history. Villey quoted the eminent jurist Gabriel
I ,. llr.1s as saying that the idea of subjective rights goes back all the way
'" i\.t.1m and Eve; 2 but Villey himself maintains a very different point
• 11 v ww. I le is impatient with scholars who introduce modem ideas of sub-
1.., I 1v 1· ri~hts into their studies on " Roman law, medieval law, and even in

I A h1hlingrnphy of several hundred wo rks is presented in R. Martin and J. W. Nickt•I,


i\ llll•lluKr"phy om the Nature and Foundations of Rights 1947-1977.~ Political TI1rory,,
11•11111 l'I'\ 4 D . In !!pill' of its ll'ngth, the list i~ far from complete. For in!ltance, only on!'
111111111 l'"l"•r uf Villc•y i!' lndudf'd.
J I'' /11t111ttl1H11 dr In,,,.,,_
.,.(' j11ri1fiq11r '"'~lrmr, 4th t•tf (l'ari~. 1'17~). 226.

- 1:\ .
14 TKE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS VtLLEY, 0cKHAM, AND TIIE ORIGIN OF lNDIVlDUAL RIGHTS 15

their expositions of cuneiform law. " 3 For Villey the idea of subjective rights going appraisal. Yet any scholar who wants to work in this field has to
appeared at a particular time and place and in response to a particular set come to terms with his impressive synthesis.7
of circumstances. After some hesitation in his earlier papers, he defined the In the following discussion I shall describe and criticize the various
occasion of its emergence in a group of studies published in the 1960s, and stages of Villey's argument as it developed down to the time of his de-
has since adhered to the position presented there. His argument is set out finitive work on Ockham and then, more constructively, indicate some
with clarity and force. The modern idea of subjective rights, Villey asserts, alternative approaches to the problems he has discusseci.8
is rooted in the nominalist philosophy of the fourteenth century, and it first
saw the light of day in the work of William of Ockham. Ockham inaugu-
CLASSICAL ROMAN LAW
rated a "semantic revolution" when he transformed the traditional idea of
objective natural right into a new theory of subjective natural rights. His Villey's distinction between ancient and modem thought about rights
work marked a ''Copernican moment" in the history of the science of law.4 was first developed in a series of studies on classical Roman law.9 A semi-
Villey's argument has been widely and uncritically accepted. Nowa- nal article of 1946 on the concept of ius started out from the observation
days Ockham is often regarded as the originator of modem rights theories, that some early modem jurists radically misrepresented classical jurispru-
at least among scholars who seek an origin for them before the seventeenth dence as a system of individual rights.10 The seventeenth-century lawyer
century. This is partly because of Vtlley's work, partly because some of the Feltmann, for instance, organized his presentations of Roman law around
ideas he uses were developed independently by other well-known schol- the categories of Rights in Persons, Rights in Things, and Rights to Things
ars. Villey is like Georges de Lagarde, for instance, in treating Ockham as ( jura in persona, in rebus, and ad res). 11 But, Villey points out, there is no such
a radical innovator in rights theories, and like Leo Strauss in contrasting classification in classical law. The division of law presented by Gaius was
an older Aristotelian doctrine of natural right with a newer theory of indi- into Persons, Things, and Actions. The "Things" were again divided into
vidual subjective rights-much to the advantage of the former.5 (Respond- corporeal things and incorporeal things. These latter {res incorporales) were
ing to some German jurists who proposed as a slogan Zuruck zum Kant,
Villey offered as a counter slogan Zuriick zum Aristoteles.6 ) But Villey is un- 7. Villey's ideas have been presented in many scattered articles and several works
usual in the exceptionally far-ranging studies on ancient and medieval of synthesis. Three volumes of collected essays have appeared, ~ d'histoire dt la phi-
jurisprudence which he presents as a foundation for his arguments. The losophit du droit (Paris, 1957); Sriu ~IS de philosophit du droit (Paris, 1969); CriliqUI! de hi pmsh
juridiq11t modern.t (douu autrrs essaisJ (Paris, 1969). Villey's other books (besides LA f ormation
whole body of his historical work has never been subjected to a thorough-
cited above) include Lt droil ti les droits dt l'hommt (Paris, 1983) and Philosopliit du droil 1,
Definitiorrs ti fins du droit, 3rd ed. (Paris, 1982); 2, lLs mqytns du droil, 2nd ed. (Paris, 1984).
3. "La g~ du droit subjectif chez Gillaume d 'Occam," Archroes dt philosophit dt droil 9 8. In ViHey's writings the same arguments are often reformulated with different nu-
(1964): 97-127 at 102. a nces in successive publications. I have tried to select for comment a group of works that
4. LAJonruztitm, 225, " . . . l'idtt du droit subjectif procede elle aussi du nominalisme et si illustrate the development of his thought from the 1940s to the present
explicite avec Occamu; 261, "R~volution sbnantique a elle seule riche de consequences . . . 9. Recherchts sur la lilUralure didactiqut du droil TOmllin (Paris, 1946); #Du sens de I' ex-
Nous sommes ici-meme au moment copemicien de l'histoire de la science du droit." pression jus in re en droit romain dassique" in Mel11ngts Funand dt Visscher, D, Revue in-
5. See Georges de Lagarde, LA naissanct dt I' tsprit lafque au die/in du moym agt, 5 vols. 2nd lrrnationalt dts droits dt 1'11ntiquilt 2 (1949): 417-436; HSuum jus cuique tribuens,H in Studi in
ed. (Paris, 1956-70). (The fint edition was published in six volumes, 1934-46.) Leo Strauss, 1111ore di Pidro dt Fr11ncisci, 4 vols, 2 (Milan, 1956): 361- 371.
Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1950). H. Rommen also presented Ockham as the initiator JO. " L'idtt du droit subjectif et Jes syst~mes juridiques romains," Revut historique de droit
of modem rights theories in "The Geneology of Natural Rights," Thought 29 (1954): 403-425. /ri111r11is ti tlrangtr, Series 4, 24 (1946): 201-227. The outlin.e of ViUey's views on Roman law
Villey's view on Ockham as the originator of rights theories is widely accepted in current >:iven above is based mainly on this article. It is often cited in Villey's subsequent works. His
American studies. See e.g., L. Dumont, Essays in Individualism (Chicago, 1986), 62- 66 and 1110!'>1 recent restatement of the argument is in LL droit tf lts droits, 55-:79.
Martin P. Golding. "The Concept ol Rights: A Historical Sketch" in B. Sandman ed., Biotlhics 11 . Ibid , 202. The persistence of this earlier way of thinking can be illustrated from
and Human Righls (Boston, 1978), 44-49. Golding's discussion of Ockham here was based on ·• h•><lbook of 1890. The author rendered Gaius' "De Personis" as " Equal Rights" and " De
Vtlley. Others rely on Villey at second hand by citing Golding. see e.g .. the papers by J. R. Pen· l!t•h11s" as " Unequal Rights." See E. Poste, Elements of Rtmuin Law by Qiius (Oxford, 1890),
noc.k and Kurt Baier in J. R. Pennock and J. W. Chapman eds. Human Rights: Nomos XXll w xvi. By that time though, Hmry Sumner Maine was arguing that " the Romans had not
(New York, 1981), 1-28, 201- 29. In similar fashion Isaiah Berlin cited Villey in his famo us '1ll11inl'd, or had not fully attained, to the concept of a legal Right, which seems to us elemen·
essay, "1Wo Concepts of Liberty," in Four Essirys on U11trty (Oxford, 1969); then A. [. Melden ' "' y • I Ji~"ll('rlations on Early l.11111 and Custom (New York. 1883), 365. The debate about the
cited both Berlin and Golding in his Rights in Moral Lives (Berkeley, 1988). For further refer- 11w1111lng or i11~ in Roman law goes back to the seventeenth century. Villey has an intereillng
ences see below, 118 n. SO. ,A.,.
.ft•• """Ion h1 .. urlKinl'fl tit• la nolion dl' droit !'ubje\'!if," Archiws dt phil~hit du droil 2
6. See below n. 31 . ( t•l'tl ~>4): lf•°l IK7
16 THE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHTS VILLEY, 0CKHAM, AND TiiE ORIGIN OF INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS 17

legal constructs, legal attributes inhering in external corporeal entities. portant for Villey. An owner certainly had the power to use and enjoy his
And, for the classical jurists, ius was precisely such a res incorporalis. This is own property. But this power was not a ius. Once again, for the classical
Villey's central point. To a modem jurist a right is a power; to a classical jurist, a ius was not a power but an immaterial thing. Hence it was not a
jurist a ius was a thing. Thus, to a lawyer, a fundus was not just a field, a right in our sense. In other works Villey maintained that dominium itself
plot of material land, but a field with all its legal attributes. These could in- was not a construct of law for the classical jurists, but a pre-legal reality,
clude what we might call rights-a right of usufruct for instance-and the something that Jaw limited. 16
word ius was used to describe such things in classical law (ius utendi fru- These arguments are of fundamental importance for Villey's later
endi). But the Roman lawyers did not have in mind our modem concept of work on the origin of rights theories, so they need a little further consid-
ius as a subjective right of an individual. For them ius was not a power eration. There are evident criticisms to be made. It may well be that the
over something; it was a thing itself, specifically an incorporeal thing.11 Romans had a highly developed concept of individual rights but used
Villey maintains that, although there existed at Rome practical situ- some word other than ius to express it. 17 It is also possible that Villey was
ations that we should discuss in terms of rights, the concept of an in- too narrowly selective in the texts he chose to illustrate the meaning of ius
dividual right was lacking in classical jurisprudence. He defends this itself. Cewirth, for instance, pointed out that even modem authors who
interpretation by several lines of argument. For instance, in discussing want to deny the existence of rights in Roman law find it necessary to use
urban servitudes, Gaius wrote of a ius altius tollendi. At first glance it seems the term " a right" (or "un droit") in the modem sense in explicating the
clear enough that Caius was writing about a right in the modem sense, a n•levant texts.18 Again, the separation between ius and dominium is crucial
" right of building higher." But Caius went on to mention a "ius .. . non for Villey's argument. But in classical literary Latin one could certainly
extollendi." We cannot possibly translate this as "a right of not building rder to ius and dominium as inhering in the same subject. (Livy mentioned
higher." So Caius's concept of a ius is just not congruent with our concept . 1 subordinate king who acknowledged that ius and dominium over his

of a right. 13 1.mds remained with Rome.'9 ) In legal Latin too, from the fourth century
It is the same with Ulpian's famous definition of the function of jus- onward, the two concepts were commonly confused in phrases like iure
tice-to render to each his right (suum ius cuique tribuere). Here again we dominii possidere. Ernst Levy gave many examples and observed that " the
seem at first sight to be dealing with the modem idea of inherent indi- !.1rmer strict contrast of dominium and ius in re aliena was done for. It did
vidual rights. But Villey points out that ius here has a different meaning. It 11111 survive." 20

refers to the just share, the just due, of some one within an established One might further argue that, even in Gaius himself, the concepts of
structure of social relationships, varying with each person's status and /''''"~las and dominium and ius seem to be all interwoven in a passage like
role. In this sense the word ius could imply a disadvantage to an individ- 1his:
ual. Villey observes that the ius of parricide was to be sewn up in a sack of
vipers and thrown into the Tiber.14 Again the meaning of ius is not con- Slaves are in the power (potestate) of their masters (dominorum) ... if the
ffuelly of the masters seems intolerable they are compelled to sell their
gruent with our idea of a right.
slaves ... for we ought not lo use our right (iure) badly. 21
The Romans did have a concept of mastery, power over persons or
things, expressed by the word dominium. But, Villey insists, this dominium II 1s h;ird not to see here an assertion of the subjective right of the master
was not defined as a right. A dominus, for instance, was not said to have a • ••nsisting in his power over the slave who was under his dominium .
right of usufruct in his own property. Ulpian wrote, dominus ... utendi fru-
endi jus separatum non habet. Caius also distinguished between the two
11, E.g., LA formation, 235, " La puissance absolue qu' exerce le maitre romain sur sa
concepts in the phrase, sive dominus sive is qui ius habet.15 The point is im- • 1........ ,-,. n'~t point le droit, c'est le silence, ce sont les lacunes du droit."
I'/ !'hi~ wa$ suggested by G. Pugliese, "'Res corporates', 'res incorporates' e ii problem11
12. Nl'idff du droit subjectif,N 210, 219-220. Villey persistently indicates that for him the ·11·11linllo ~'AA«'livo," Sludi in onorr di Vincmzo Arangio-Ruiz 3 (Naples, 1954): 223-60.
modem idea of a right implies a power. He does not concern himself much with the more IH Rm~m and Morality (Chicago, 1978), 372 Gewirth mentioned Jolowicz, Buckland and
elaborate classillcations of rights, like that of Hohfeld, commonly encountered in the Anglo- V1l1..y hi m~lf.
American literature. 1•1 Air urt>r nim/ifa, 45.13.15.
13. ul 'idtt du droit subjeclif, w 217. m I~ . I A'"'Y· W~I Rnman Vulgar l...llw (Philadelphia, 1951). 6.1. See also ibid., 26, 64-5.
14. usuum jus cuique tribuere," 364. 11 I'. 1t1• 7.uhwla t'd .. Thi' fn$lilulr.i of C.aiu$ 1(Odord, 1946): 17 (ln~I. 1.5'2), " In pott',.l•ll'
IS. ul.'l.th,N 21Q. " l.n nrlgi~... 17.l. vm..y ....111mrtl to 111..... 111•1• ... K111111m law ( l\' l'r 11,.. ,,.,. 1<11111 ~..rut 1tominorum. .. . Si lnlolC'r11'1>ills 11h1C'11tur domlnornm ll1l<'Ultl111 roKimhrr
111111ovrr11g•ln tn 1"1<'r wrlttng11. ""' """ ""'"' .,,.,.,1,.n• mitlr rnlm n<•ln• luw 1111110111lrlll"mu" ··
18 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS VILLEY, 0cKHAM, AND THE ORIGIN OF INOfVIUUAL RIGHTS 19
As we are so often told nowadays, all language is context-dependent.zz A of medieval texts collected in a long appendix.?$ Villey repeated here that
legal term deployed in the cultural context of ancient Rome cannot have the idea of subjective right did not exist in classical law, but he found hints
exactly the same range of meanings as the same term used nowadays of it in the law of the late Empire and a substantial development of the
(though the meanings may overlap). But one could make this same point concept in the writings of the medieval glossators.
about the language of Ockham or Hobbes or Kant, and Villey does not In this paper, Villey was mainly concerned to argue that, before the
hesitate to attribute a modem idea of rights to such authors.23 t•arly modem period, the technical term ius in re did not have the full sense
The harshest criticism that could be made of Villey's treatment of of modem property right, the droit reel of French law, a power over prop-
Roman law-it could apply also to his later discussion of Thomas l'rty enforceable against all other persons. (He mentioned that the accusa-
Aquinas-is that he selects a few suitable texts, drapes a whole theory of tive form ius ad rem could mean a subjective right, 26 but did not explore
law around them, and then refuses to take seriously any texts that do not fit in detail the intricate development of the canonistic doctrine on ius ad rem
his preferred theory. Responding to such criticisms many years after his from 1200 onward.) The author makes his technical point about ius in re,
original article appeared, Vtlley explained that, in discussing classical law, I hough to a reader more open to the idea of an earlier origin for modem
he was not concerned with literary Latin or the language in common use. It rights theories the "exceptional" texts he cites might seem more striking
would be impossible, he concedes, to prove that the concept of subjective than the ones that directly support his argument. Villey recognizes in this
right never existed at all at Rome. Villey even adds that such a negative en- paper that the medieval glossators created a new terminology. "new no-
quiry would have little interest. The point is that in classical Roman law we tions and, in particular, new words designating subjective rights." They
have a whole structure of language built around a set of concepts different tn•ated the Roman actio for instance as a subjective ius. But their analysis of
from the ones we often take for granted.24 (Although Villey does not write ri~hts was concerned mainly with the term dominium. They understood
in the jargon of modem French structuralism his whole mind-set seems to tlw word in non-classical ways, so that dominium itself came to be regarded
be structuralist. For him-as for Saussure, as for Levi-Strauss-patterns of .1s a ius. Setting out from the word dominium, Villey observes, the glos-
relationship matter more than particular instances.) Put in this way Villey's ....1tors built a "grand echafaudage logique de notions de droit subjectifs."71
position is defensible. He was indeed making a valid point all along. All this would again seem to suggest a pre-fourteenth-century origin
Roman jurists did not conceive of the legal order as essentially a structure lor modem rights theories. But Villey resists this conclusion. The glos-
of individual rights in the manner of some modem ones. .... 11ors' work, he says, was full of hesitations and contradictions and
Still, if we concede that, in some forms of discourse from classical frustrated endeavors. A coherent jurisprudence of individual rights could
times onward, the word ius could mean a right, then the case for a "se- lw aea ted only in a later epoch, in a different climate of thought. In this
mantic revolution" in the fourteenth century is apparently undermined. f'·•pl'r Villey associated the later emergence of such a jurisprudence
Indeed, in some of his earlier work Vtlley seemed to favor a more gradual, with " the cogito ergo sum of Descartes," "the psychological literature of
evolutionary approach. He often used the word glissement to indicate a th1· s<.•venteenth century," and "Jesuit spirituality."211 At one point in the
"sliding," a "shifting" in the meaning of the term ius that occurred over a 1•.1per he described medieval Roman law as marking an era of transition
period of several centuries. A paper on the medieval glossators of Roman 111 rights theories-suggesting a process of continuous development. But
law (first presented in 1947) is especially valuable for the substantial body .11 .mothe r point he asserted that the early modem jurists "broke with
111-.tury" and adopted "a new language."1'J The reason for this uneasiness
l wninws clearer in his later work.
22. "L'idtt du droit subjectif," 225, "Les Romains s'interessent si peu ~ l'idee du droit
sub;ectif qu'ils n'ont pas mbne de ternie gblerique pour l'exprimer." See also HLes origines,"
170-173.
23. One may doubt, for instance, whether any author before the twentieth century used ."• • 1.,_. "jus in re' du dro il romain classique au droil modeme, in Confermas /ailt'!' 1\
H

the word Nright" with precisely the same range of connotations that one finds in the Unittd I l11·.1r1111 rl1· /)roil Romain m 1947 (Paris, 1950), 187- 225.
N11tionl Univasiil CJedJlntion ofH1mum Rights. R. Tuck N11turlll Rights Theories: Thrir Origin 11nd ,.,, lhi.t., 20'.l.
Dn:!elopmmt (Ctmbridge. 1979), 2. also raises the issue ol language as Htheory-dependentH in J"I lhi.t .• fQR -2<Xl. On subjective right and ius in Roman law set.' also If. Coing, ··zur
considtting late Roman law but does not pursue the point in considering later texts. 1 ...... hu hh· ,,,.,. llt·griffs ·suhjdcliv<'s Rt'<'ht"" in Cuing et al.. l'<is.• Dils sul•jrklitJI' Rr.-111 11111l 1ffr
24. "Travaux reants sur les droits de l'homme," Arr:hiva de philosophre du droit 26 (1981): 11,·, /11.,. /111/'l. 1lrr t•a~111/icl1kril (Frankfurt am Milin, IQ5<J).
411- 418. ViUey presents a more nuanced discus.sion on ius in Roman law In l'hiltJIWl•ltil' du 1

droit, 1: 87-96. '" '""' . 1 10 'll.


·"' 11•111.. 704. I'll
VILLEY, 0CKHAM, AND TiiE ORIGIN OF INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS 21
20 THE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHTS

INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS AND NATURAL RIGHT esty" (invoked against "obscene" films).» But Villey is not content to criti-
cize abuses. Rather, he presents the whole modem attempt to base a
An underlying reason for Villey's reluctance to acknowledge a con- system of jurisprudence on an affirmation of individual rights as funda-
tinuity between medieval and early modem tho~ght~ even ":'h~n such mentally misguided. He describes this modem enterprise as Utopian,
continuity was suggested by his own texts, was his pnor conviction that .irbitrary and sterile. It is Utopian because the supposed absolute rights are
major shifts in legal and political ideas could.occur only after an apprC: fictions; they usually do not exist in actual law or in real life. Rights theo-
priate pattern of thought had been created m the ~p~ere of pure P1:ll- ries are arbitrary because the rights claimed are ultimately based on
losophy. For Villey metaphysics always comes ~fore 1unsprudenc~. A~JS­ subjective whim; they lead on to a debased understanding of justice as
totelian thought provided a basis for the classical doctrine of objective "nothing but a label you attach to your own subjective preferences." And
natural right; Ockham's nominalism made possible the early modem modem rights theories are sterile because they cannot form the basis of
theories of natural rights; and Kant's philosophy provided an immediate .1 coherent jurisprudence.33 The rights that people assert conflict with one
source for the subjective rights of nineteenth century jurisprudence. .mother. Juridical thought begins at the point where one considers the
Villey's attitude is summed up in an early comment oi:' ~kham; "La Ph!- situations that arise as a consequence of this reality. The task of the jurist is
losophie avait, comme ii est ordinaire, precede les 1unstes sur la v01e In establish just relationships among persons and between persons and
revolutionnaire." 30 1•roperty-not to affirm absolute rights, but to determine what is objec-
Villey explored these themes in many articles from the 1950s onward. t ivcly right. Villey does not disdain the values inherent in modem West-
There was a certain broadening of conceptual horizons in his work. The 1·rn society insofar as they reflect a concern for the human personality,
early papers on Roman law had treated ius as so~ething objective .but hut he thinks those values could be better defended, "in another, more
only as a legal quality inhering in some external entity (as usufruct m1~ht 1· ....1ct language," by an appeal to the classical tradition of natural right.34
inhere in a fund us). In his subsequent work he was more concerned with Ill' associates that tradition especially with Aristotle, with the jurispru-
ius naturale as an objective right order in relationships between persons. .1..nce of classical lawyers who took for granted Aristotelian ways of think-
Similarly, when he wrote about subjective rights (or the lack of ~em), 111.v and with the philosophy of Thomas Aquinas who remained faithful
he was at first concerned with legal rights, rights within an established lo Aristotelian principles. We need to explore a little further Villey's un-
system of human law, specifically Roman law.. In later wo.rks the e~pha­ .l1·rstanding of this tradition before we can consider his attitude to Ock-
sis was more on natural rights, rights conceived of as inherent m the h.un and later rights theorists.
human personality. In his " Abrege du droit naturel classique" (1961), A key-word for Villey is Aristotle's dikaion-the just-usually ren-
Villey wrote, "Subjective rights from their origin and still t~ay are con- ·••·n.·d into Latin as ius. Aristotle understood the term in two senses,
ceived of as natural rights."31 This emphasis helps to explain why Villey ""it her of them equivalent to the modem idea of a subjective right. He dis-
could acknowledge that the word ius could vaguely mean a right from the 1111~uished between justice as a moral virtue and justice as an objectively
time of the late Roman Empire onward and still see a radical change in the r 1ght state of affairs in a particular context, something inherent in the
fourteenth century. What was lacking before then was the full idea of sub- 11.1l11re of a situation, or "in the nature of the case," we might say. It is this
jective rights, rights inhering in the individual person as such. ....nllld meaning that especially concerns the jurist. Indeed, by defining
The "Abrege" and the first edition of I.A formation written at about 11 , Aristotle provided the foundation for a whole philosophy of law, ac-
the same time, provide a good introduction to Villey's understanding ' 11rding to Villey.35 In Aristotle's philosophy the universe was a cosmos,
of the contrast between classical natural right and modem individual
rights. These works also make clear his distaste for mode~ rights d~­ I/ lhiJ., 65. It is as well perhaps that Villey never came upon the work of Nan Berger,
trines. Vtlley objects to the subjectivism of contemporary nghts theones. '' ·~''" A I lantfl>ook for Ptople Unitn Age (Harmondsworth, 1974). There he could have found,
He reacts with understandable irony to the vague catalogues of more or 1..... t.t tu h is list o f unlikely rights, a ~right to sunshine," "to a tobacco-free job," and " to a

less worthy aspirations that are nowadays presented as lists of "human


rights"-a "right to leisure," " to work," "to culture," "to health," " to mod- 11 lhi<I., 42 - 0 , 46-47, 68-69.
... lhitl., 66.
1·-. S.•1•, l'.)I, . .. lkntham <•t le dmit nature! cl11s~iquc-," Archiurs dr 11hifo~1ph ir d11 dmit 17
30. hles origines, ~ 179. . . .
31. "Abreg~ du droit nature! classique," An:hivts dt f.h1l~h1t du dro_Jt 6 (196~:2:-n at 11'1'/'/) '11'.l ~I "' 411. l\ft..r t' llplnining l\ri!llolll''!I dl11tlnMlon, Vllll'y n•mment<•d , "Vollll qui
65. It was in this paper that Villey suggested the slogan Zuruck zum Anstntt'h•!I. lh1d .. 27. ••I t•nur 11om1 Ir to111lt•nwnl ,f' mw philt11mphit• 11t• tlmll " Vilk•y'" umlt•rfttllntllng nf d 111u1k11I
22 THE lDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS VILLEY, OcKHAM, AND rnE ORIGIN OF rNOIVIDUAl RIGHTS 23

informed by a logos which gave it order and harmony and purpose. So too According to Villey, the first, properly classical meaning was lost, or
human society could display a proper harmony and balance, a structure compromised, in the writings of the Christian Church Fathers. In translat-
of right relationships. The objective sense of ius was well expressed in En- ing and commenting on the Bible they used the term ius to mean divine
glish by John Finnis-he defined it as "what's fair."36 For Villey ius most commands, so that, for instance, the Decalogue could be called ius divinum
often means fair sharing, juste partage. or ius naturale. Then this usage was continued by the medieval canonists.
Villey insists-against both Hume and Kant in their different ways- I fence, in the first words of Gratian's Decreturn (c. 1140), we find ius natu-
that ius, what is right, can be ascertained from observation of external mle defined as the Biblical Golden Rule, "by which we are commanded to
nature.37 He cites, for instance, an argument from Aristotle and Thomas do unto others what we would have them do unto us... ." This develop-
Aquinas. We can learn from observation that human children, unlike the ment is important for our general theme concerning the origin of rights
young of many other species, need a long period of nurture and educa- theories because, in Villey's view, the classical idea of ius was undermined
tion; whence one can conclude that stable marriage between parents is a hy this Christian understanding of the term before the final (disastrous)
naturally right relationship.38 Given this approach, Villey points out, it is misinterpretation occurred in the fourteenth century, when ius came to be
not surprising that, when Aristotle or Aquinas sought to define dikaion or •q~arded as an individual power or subjective right.
ius, they did not proclaim the rights and powers of individuals. They were Villey argued that Aquinas avoided both errors-the interpretation of
concerned rather with a harmonious structure of relationships, right pro- 111s as either subjective right or prescriptive law. He thought that one of the

portion, juste partage. r.n·at ach ievements of the Dominican master was to restore for a time the
"hjcctive, classical meaning of ius (a meaning that would be lost again by
< lckham and the nominalists). Following the Roman lawyers, Aquinas de-
AQUINAS AND THE CANONISTS: IUS AND LEX l11wd ills as quod iustum est, what is just, and again as ipsarn rem iustam, the
So far we have been concerned mainly with a distinction between rust thing itself.40 For Aquinas, as for Aristotle, as for Gaius and Ulpian, ills
ius as a subjective right and ius as a system of objectively right relation- w.1.s still primarily a "thing" (rem), something existing in external nature.
ships. rn discussing Aristotle and Aquinas in La formation, Villey devel- Allt•r his primary definition Thomas gave several derivative meanings of
oped another distinction, which became of central importance in his "'" but they still did not include any subjective definition of the word. Ac-
subsequent work. This was a distinction between ius understood as an ob- ' ording to Villey no such meaning was known to him.41 Here Villey seems
jectively right relationship ("What's fair," juste partage), and ills understood tn h.we somewhat overstated his case. When Aquinas was writing unre-
as moral or legal precept, as law binding on individuals, and so equivalent tl1·dively and following the common practice of his age, he did use the
to lex.Y* word ius in a subjective sense in phrases like ius dominii (2.2ae.62.1), ius
f''";sidmdi (2.2ae.66.5), ius praelationis (2.2ae.69.1). Yet it remains true that he
.l1·vt•loped no explicit doctrine of subjective rights or natural rights. For
natural right explained in the paragraph above is found in many of his works, including I hnrnas, Villey argued, ius naturale was not a power inhering in individu-
''Les origjnes" and "Abrege." It was given a systematic presentation in lA formation, 36- 47,
.1 I·. or a body of moral precepts but a method, a way of interpreting reality,
in Philosophit du droit, l, and most recently in Le drJil •.; /cs droits.
36. John Finnis, Natural Liiw and Natural Rights (Oxford, 1980), 206. ,.,.,." .m "experimental method." 42 (Perhaps Villey had in mind the sec-
37. The influence of Kant was especiaJly emphasized (and deplored) in "Abrege." For a 111111.iry definition of ius given by Thomas, "The art by which it is known
typical comment on Hume see "Bentham et le droit nature) classique," 429. ln criticizing w h .11 is jus t.")
Villey, Finnis referred to Hume's law about the impossibility of deriving a moral proposition ·111is ll•d Villey to a further point. What is naturally right can change.
from factual observation which had, he wrote, "impressed . .. the whole modem anglo-
saxon world." In response Villey referred to".. . la Joi de Hume, si contestable et contestee, 1111 1111.is dearly insisted on a need for changes in positive human law, and
~ tout le moins sur le continent." \ "dlc·y duly <'mphasizes this. But he goes further. He holds also that, for
38. lAJormation, 126-128. I ht1111.1s, i rts 1111t11mle too could change because human beings change-·
39. Ibid ., 127: " .. . la loi morale n'est pas le droit." Among later studies see especially
"Tol'"ah-Dikaion I" and "Dikaion-Torah [(" in Critique dt la pctsl.t juridiqul' modtrnt, l'l- 50. ·Ill .. Ahr•'gcl," :ll , r('f('rring to S11mma lhrologiar, 2.2ac57.1.
The argument is summarized in Philosphit du droit, 1, 101- 112. Finni~ rnmplained that .f I 11 M . I lt·rin~ ar~ut>d that Aquinas did have a cOOC'ept of :iuhjt"Ctive rig}ll!I, " De iun-
" Villey's treatment of ius is marred by an exaggerated di~tinction betw('('ll iu~ and /a .. . •11l•1•·• ltv11 ~"'"I''" .1p11<I !'.1nctum Th11mnm," A11x1·/icu111 16 (tc139): 29~ -117. Villt•ytlt•nlt>d thi.•
which leads him to misplaced distinctions betwc-en law and mor11lltv " N.1lrnnl l.nw nnif 111 I '' ~1·111'!1<·:· 111 n I
Natural Rights, 228. ~ J •• /\l1tc'X1'." •;c1. In f.•rrm1lim1. '>II, 171• ··1,. tln1it ni1h1n•l 1•,.l 111w mc'tlu1th• 1•"1it'ri11wnlt1lr "
24 TuE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHTS VII.LEY, 0cKHAM, AND THE ORIGIN OF I N DIV IDUAL RIG HTS 25

"natura hominis mutabilis est," Thomas wrote in the Summa theologiae. over, on one occasion where Thomas equated ius and lex, it was Aristotle
Villey observes that justice is a problem which always poses itseU in new not Isidore who provided the starting point of the discussion. 46
terms and calls for new solutions as circumstances change. What is natu- It seems, then, that Villey's case for a consistent distinction between
rally right-a fair pattern of relationships-will be different in different 1/roit nat11rel and loi nature/le in Thomas cannot be sustained. In different
times and places, not the same, let us say, in a primitive agrarian society • ontexts, Thomas presented Aristotle' s doctrine of natural right and his
as in an advanced commercial one. Villey admires especially the supple- own doctrine of natural law, sometimes using the word ius to express both
ness and flexibility of Thomas's ius naturale. It is a vision open to change, lt·achings. If he had consistently used ius naturale for the first doctrine and
open to progress.u l1·r nnturalis for the second the task of modern commentators might have
Vtlley was supplying a corrective to modem neo-Thomist doctrines hl·en easier. But in fact Thomas followed the common usage of his age in
which interpret Aquinas's ius naturale too rigidly, and so far his argument which i11s and lex could sometimes be used interchangeably and some-
may seem persuasive even if it is sometimes expressed incautiously. But 111nes differentiated from one another in their more specialized meanings.
the emphasis on a mutable ius naturale led to a thicket of difficulties when < >nc has only to consult a concordance to see that Thomas used the word
Villey turned to the other meaning of ius that he discussed, the canonistic ,,,.., (not to mention naturalis) in several different senses without always ex-
understanding of ius as moral precept or divine command. The problem ,.1.1ining carefully the various meanings intended in different contexts.47
here is that Thomas (following St. Paul) certainly believed in an immutable We might expect to find this situation in such a long and far-ranging
lex naturalis, an unchanging moral law inscribed in the hearts and minds of work as the S11mma lheologiae, which drew on sources as diverse as Aris-
men. Villey had to insist therefore that, for Thomas, the meanings of ius '' •I ll·'s Ethics and Gratian's Decretum. But Villey's treatment of the relation-
and lex were quite different.44 And here the problems begin. Thomas did ·.lup between Aquinas and the canonists in their understanding of ius and
indeed distinguish between the two terms in his definition of ius at Summa In is significant for his whole argument. Especially in his more recent
theol. 2.2ae.57.1. But he followed this at once in the next article with a sen- work he has emphasized a conflict-a duel he says- between the classical
tence in which the terms seem equated with one another, and elsewhere in ·"'" Thomist concept of ius (equivalent to Aristotle's dikaion in its objective
the Summa he used them interchangeably. Villey insists, in effect, that only ·.1·11se) and the Judea-Christian concept of ius {equivalent to lex or Torah).
the first definition counts. He adds that, where there is an appearance of 111 I.Kt, however, the two concepts have coexisted in a reasonably harmo-
confusion, it is because Thomas is not using his own language to express 1111111s fashion since classical times. In Roman law ius meant not only ob-
his own thought but quoting the language of the canonists, specifically the ,,., liv e right order but also a body of legal or moral precepts, as in ius civile
terminology of Isidore of Seville incorporated in Gratian's Decretum, a ter- .1111 I i11s ~entium. Similarly the canonists emphasized the meaning of ius as
minology that reflected a "decadent syncretism between Biblical culture "'' 11-.ll precept, equivalent to lex, but they did not lack the meaning of ob-
and the language of the Roman jurists." Of course there is no trace of such 1•·1llw right order. (To anyone familiar with their work, the idea that the
an attitude in Thomas himself. He treated Isidore's texts, like other pas- • .11111nists were not interested in right order in the world will seem star-
sages of canon law, as respected authorities. (At one point, in response to t liug.) Villey complains that, in the treatise on law that forms the opening
an objection, he wrote simply, "The authority of Isidore suffices.")45 More- .,.., hon of Gratian's Decretum, there is no understanding of justice in the
• 111•·1 livc sense-as just distribution, juste partage, ius suum cuique tribuerr.
1

"3. u Abrege," n 35, #La justice, c'est un problme qui se pose sous des termes nou- 11111 this precise meaning is presented in the first paragraph of the Ordinary
veaux . . ." 50-51, N(La) vision du juste est relative, ouverte au progres.. .." Similarly l..ll • ./,,.•.. to the Decretals, a work studied in every canon law school of mc-
formation, 129-131. · ' •··v.11 Europe. "(H]aving read and understood (these decretals) we may
44. For further discussion see " Bible et philosophie greco-romaine de Saint Thomas au
droit moderne," ArchitJeS dt philosophit du droit 18 (1973): Xl-'57 and, most recently. G. Kali·
nowsld and M. Villey, "La mobilite du droit nature) chez Aristote et Thomas d ' Aquin," I r. •,,,,,,,,,,, lhro/., 1.9!i.2. Thomas argued that human law was de rived from natural l.1w
Archivrs dt pltilosoplrit d11 droit 29 (1984): 187-199. Villey might have made a better argument " " ' 11t.·11 p os.•tl .,.., an objt'Ction that natural law was invariable: "'Praete rea lex natur.w 1•111
by emphasi.iing that, for Thomas, ltx noturalis as well as ius naturale was a flexible con· • ~. 1,..,. ·•r11.t omn('!';; d icit l'nim Philosophus quod 'naturale 1us est quod ubique h.,h.•t
cept that had to be applied differently in different circumstances. See Summa tltml.• J.2ae.9S.2, •' ~"'' ''""' puh•nti.im"" (e mphasis added). The objection has no point unl~'I Thomas Will! .111·
" ... principia communia legjs naturae non eodem modo applicarl possunt omnlbu10, proptcr • m 11111p, lh11t Aristotlt>'11 iu:o meant thE' same as his own ltx. (He did not d istingui11h bt>tw1'f'11
multam varietatem rerum humanarum." 11 ... l wn womt~ In hi" n·ply tu lhl' c>hj<-rtion.)
45. For Villey on udecadent syncretism" !1tt " Benthftm t•t 11• Jmtt 111thm•I dn1111lq11l'," 429. ii •.,.,. I{ lh•M. •"<L, /111/n 'l111•mi, lirn.<. Srcl1tt II. I '1111( 11r1l1mlit1 1•rior11, 2:l vnl11. (Stuttic.nt,
Cf. Summa lhtol.• 1.94.4, " In contrarium anctoritu laldorl 1rnftldat •· l ' I ' i ; rt). 11 t;114 1 111
26 TuE IDEA OF NATIJRAI.. RIGHTS VILl..£Y, 0CKHAM, AND THE ORIGIN OF INDlvrDUAL RIGHTS 27

know how to discern between equity and iniquity, and to render to each that it was incorporated in Jacobus de Albenga's commentary on this
his own, and in this justice consists."48 collection written shortly afterward and also in the Ordinary Gloss to the
A less selective reading of the texts would show that the two meanings I >ecretals of Gregory IX (also before Thomas). The canonists did not need
of ius that Villey contrasts-treating one as truly classical, the other as In wait for Thomas to tell them that popes could legislate. For more than
a sort of Christian aberration-actually existed harmoniously, side by .1century they had been insisting on the papal ius condendi canones. What
side, in classical philosophy, in Roman law, in medieval jurisprudence, in .1dually happened is more subtle and more interesting. Thomas did not
Thomas Aquinas, and in many later natural law philosophers. Moreover, mvent a new theory of legislation. He assimilated the existing doctrine of
they could coexist in this fashion without undue strain because the two ,·ontemporary Roman and canon lawyers, and associated it with his own
meanings are complementary rather than contradictory. If we observe that lt·achings on ius naturale and lex naluralis. Then, in tum, Thomas's doctrine
it is proper for children to respect their parents, that is an example of an ob- •,f natural law began to react back on the teachings of the academic canon-
jectively right relationship (dikaion, ius). If we say, "Honor thy father and 1<.ts. (The first time I have found it mentioned in a formal canonistic com-
thy mother," that is a precept of natural law (which Gratian would also call 111mtary is in the Rosarium of Guido de Baisio from ca. 1300.) The process
ius). But we are affirming the same principle in each formulation. Both w p have to deal with is not simply one of philosophy influencing law but

meanings of ius retain the underlying sense of rightness or fairness. A 1.1ther of a constant interplay between the two disciplines. It will be useful
judge cannot establish ius (an objectively right relationship, a juste parlage) 10 keep this in mind as we tum to Ockham.

unless he has a ius (a law or moral precept) to guide his sense of what is
considered fair in such a case. We shaU have to consider later on how these I It 'KHAM ' S "REVOLUTION"
two meanings of ius relate to the third one, of particular interest to us, ius
considered as subjective right. After mentioning William of Ockham in several of his earlier papers,
Aquinas's use of canon law also raises another problem of central im- V1ll<·y gave a detailed systematic presentation of his argument that Ock-
portance for Villey's argument, the relation between philosophical and lt.1111 was the inaugurator of modem rights theories in an article first
legal thought. Villey maintained that the development of Thomas's philos- 1'11hlished in 1964.5' He began by referring again to the abuses of modem
ophy of law was a prerequisite for the justification of new legislative ••1-.hts theories. Then Villey gave two reasons for the rise of such doctrines.
activity in the church.49 Thomas envisaged a law open to change and adap- 1lw first was simple egotism, the inclination of each person to think of
tation; but Gratian's Decretum, Villey says, did not acknowledge a creative · ·v .. rything in terms of his own self-interest. But since this moral defect is a
legislative function of the ruler. After the philosophical work of Aquinas, • •11nmon human failing it does not in itself explain why the "deviation of
however, papal decretals would no longer present themselves merely as l.111.\11age" introduced by theories of individual rights has found wide ac-
judicial decisions or interpretations of a pre-existing law considered per- . ··1•t;mce among philosophers of law only since the early modem period.
manently valid, but as deliberately creative of new law. Vtlley points out Another influence was needed. And so here again Villey emphasized
that Boniface VIIl made this assertion in his Preface to the Liber Sextus, pro- ti 11· impact of Christianity-not Christian morality as such but a deformed
mulgated in 1298, a quarter century after the death of Aquinas. ,.,·rs1on of Christian ideas (idees chretiennes mais deformies).51 Christianity
But the phrase Boniface actually used to justify new legislation was .dw.1ys recognized the supreme value of the individual soul and, in the
"humane nature, novas semper deproperans edere formas, lites quoti- · lu1-.h•r, individual mysticism was cultivated as the highest form of life.
die invenire conatur...." Villey has overlooked the fact that Honorius 1 lu- mischief arose when these religious attitudes were transplanted to the
Ill closely paraphrased the same text-it is originally from the Code of .•lic·11 h·rrain of law. The Franciscan Order was the group that brought
Justinian-in the letter introducing his decretal collection of 1226,50 and ·'''""' this change and, among the Franciscans, William of Ockham wa~
· ·1·•·· 1.1lly rl•sponsible for it. "The cradle of subjective right was the Fran-
48. Villey, Critiqut, 33. Bernard.us Parmensis, Glossa ordinaria ad Dtcrtlalts, Protmium in
Dtcmalts D.Grtgorii Papae IX (Lyons, 1624), 2. "' ··1., gt'fWs<o." This article is based on material o riginally included in Villey's Cours
49. LA Jormlltion, 121, "II fallait qu' une thoologie et une philosophie nouvelles juslifi· .11,,.,..,,r 1lr l111•hilosophit d11 droit of 1963. (See Stiu tsSais, 141.) The Cours was subsequt'ntly
assent le changement de droit." See also ibid ., 133, 174 and uSaint Thomas dans l'h istoire des 1"•l•ll"l11•cl l11 IQNI ai; I .n formation dt la prnslr juridiqut modtrnt. Cours d'hisloirt dt la phil050phi'
sources," in Etuda d' histoire du droit canoniqut d~iks d Gabritl le Bras, 2 vols. (Paris, 1965) .i.. ' '""'· 1%1 l 'lbh. Om pap;t' l't'fclt'Tlret1 M'E' to the revised edition of this work publisht'd in
1:355-395. 1•1 · 'l (1 11c-.I 11hov1• 11. 2). (I hllVI' qunlC'd l.n formnli"'' in th«' following dil'C'U1<1ti.-•n whl'n II con·
SO. E. Friedberg, Quinqut compilationts 11ntiq1111t (Leipzig, 1882). 152. On th1• cnnonll'lli<-11111• 1,.'"" •IK11Ulumt phrn"4'11 nol indml1'\I in " l;t p;rn/I~•. ")
o f this language see G. Post, Studies in Mtditi1al IL!{al Tho11Rhl (l'rinl"t'ton, IW'4), ~14. 'l) ··1"Krill-...-." 11 1Y/
28 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIG HTS VILLEY, 0cKHAM, AND THE ORIGIN O F [NOIVIDUAL R IGHTS 29

ciscan Order-William of Ockham, founder of nominalism, an individual- with any philosophic precision, and so there is no basis for holding that
ist philosophy . . . enemy of the pope and convicted of heresy according to tht• term had acquired the full meaning of subjective right before the
many, may be called the father of subjective rights."SJ t1111rteenth century. The important point for Villey is that we do not
Before turning to Ockham, Villey develops in this paper some of his hnd the subjective meaning in formal academic discourse. The glossators
earlier ideas in order to contrast the newly emerging idea of subjective ••I Roman law and Thomas Aquinas drew up lists of definitions of the
right with the older, sounder doctrine. A subjective right, he says, is some- word ius but they did not include the meaning of "power" or any subjec-
thing that subiacet, that underlies or is inherent in a person. It is a quality of t 1vt> sense of the word.58 For this meaning to be defined and integrated
the subject, a faculty, a liberty, an ability to act. In a word, "subjective right 11110 a system of jurisprudence a new philosophy was needed. William of
is a power of the individual." 54 This concept he reminds us, was alien to the 1> ckham would provide it.59
thought of Aristotle or Ulpian or Aquinas. For them (in Villey' s interpreta- In approaching Ockham's thought, Villey first sketches in the dispute
tion) dikaion or ius meant primarily something objective--what is just. It ••v•·r Franciscan poverty that led to Ockham's polemical writings from the
could not mean a subjective power. Rather, right was something that lim- I l20s onward. (His work in formal Iogk and philosophy had been accom-
ited power.ss Hence the modem concept has combined two ideas that were l'lished earlier during his years at Oxford.) The Franciscans had come to
formerly distinct-right and power. It is precisely in the juncture of these ••·.ich that, in observing perfect poverty, Christ and the apostles had re-
two concepts-ius and potestas-that Villey will find Ockham most in- 111umced all property and all right of use in exterior things. But Pope John
novative; for, he asserts, the doctrine of classical natural right necessarily \ \ 11 denounced this whole position in 1323. He declared that henceforth
excluded the modem idea of subjective rights. "The notion of subjective o1 would be heresy to hold that Christ and the apostles had no right of
right is logically incompatible with classical natural right."56 11·.1· in the things they actually did use. Ockham's response to this was, for

Villey acknowledges that, in vulgar usage, even in ancient Rome, V1lll'y, " the decisive moment in the history of subjective right."60 Ockham
some people may have treated the word ius as a term defining their in- w. 1s no t a jurist by training, but he was obliged by the nature of the con-
dividual rights-after all they had their share of egotism too. But the glis- l111v<•rsy to give definitions of legal terms like dominium, ususfructus, ius
sement, the shift in meaning, became much more evident in the practical 11trntli. The distinctive quality of Ockham's definitions, Villey suggests,
life of the Middle Ages. After the downfall of Rome no work of creative ,., 1h;1t in them " the concept of right is reso lutely twisted to the meaning
jurisprudence was produced for several centuries. The Roman juridical ••I 1•0111cr. ""1 For Ockham ius meant potestas. More specifically, a right for
order was forgotten. An antijuridical attitude (conception antijuridique) 111111 was a " licit power"-"ius utendi est potestas licita utendi re extrin-
prevailed. In this juridical void people everywhere began to insist on their ...., ,, " Villey sees these definitions as striking innovations. Ockham, he
" rights"-rights of emperors against popes, rights of kings against sub- ··.iv-;. was the first to conceive of subjective right, the first to sanction the
jects, rights of this or that group or class of individuals-and they tended • 111111111ction of right and power. His language might perhaps have been
to confuse rights with actual powers.57 "">~l',•'Sted in part by some earlier glossator; but, precisely because he
Here again, as in the paper of 1947 discussed above, Villey seems to w .1·; not technically trained as a jurist, Ockham could, in good faith, carry
be proposing an early medieval origin for theories of subjective rights. But •,,.,., thc• meaning that ius was acquiring in vulgar discourse into his
his central argument is quite different. He insists that the shift in meaning l111 111.1I definitions. But above all, in Villey's view, Ockham's definitions
of the word ius was confined to vulgar usage. We cannot define with cer- ,..,.,,. dc•rived from his nominalist philosophy, and it was this philosophy
tainty what ius meant to people who themselves were not using the word 11t.11 w.1s most important for future rights theories.62 For Ockham only the
53. Ibid., 98.
54. Ibid ., 100-102. '•II ll•1e l . I07, 111. Actually Aw did give polestas as o ne meaning of i11s b ut only in rt'l,1·
55. Ibid., 104, . . . le pouvoir est au rontraire ce que le droit limite . . ." 11. " ' 1. • 11 ... p hral'(' 5 11j i11ri5 ~·e (#Origines," 271).
56. La formation, 2'2:7,
N • la notion d e droit subjectif est logiquement incompatible avec
•• '•'' r" fmmntirm , 239. Pour . . . q'il soit dtHini, integre dans un systeme de pen~· j11-
le droit naturel dassique." Similarly, " La genl!se," 103, " ... cette philosophic dite du droit • •.1 1. 11u· 11111d1•rnc>, ii nc faut pas moins que le concours d ' une philosophie .. . jt' pen!W q1w
nature! classique . . . ait ete necessairement exclusive du droit subjectif." On "droit" and • • • • • ••· t ;,,,11..11me .t'<ln :am quc d 0ttt> le toumant deci!>if."
"pouvoir," ibid ., 104. 1 ~1 '"I . t );•"tu'st•." I lJ.
57. "La genese," 110. At this point Villey dism isses the labors or lht> ~t>nt>ration~ of mr- 1.1 lhu I . 117, "Elle~ nffn•nl <'t'llt• parlil'lllMilr . .. simplt•mt•nl '-l"t' l.1 no tion dc• clroit 11' y
d ieval people who first built a Christian civili7.ation in W<>!>lc•m f.urop•· "" " le• J~plnit•m..nt h• ""*'~ .,...., •h1nu•nl ,,,,,., nu 1'-t·n~ dr• l"'.'""''ir···
d~rd<'~ntt dt> I' initiative individut'lle." ' •·' ll•hl . 1111 1111
30 THE IDEA Of NATIJltAL RIGKT'S VILLEY, OCl<HAM, ANO THE ORIGIN OF INOJVIOUAL RIGHTS 31

individual had real existence; hence there could be no juridical order that Ockham they have to be dismissed as exceptions or aberrations or mere
did not proceed from the individual will, and no conception of a supra- misunderstandings of vulgar persons who were too ignorant to attach pre-
individual social order.63 cise meanings to the terms they used in day-to-day discourse.
Villey concludes with a discussion of Ockham's Breviloqium.64 He pre- There are two main lines of objection to this whole thesis (apart from
sents it as a treatise on pure power which leaves no room for any con- the historical objection to be discussed below that rights theories did
ception of objective right. At the summit is the absolute power of God. In indeed exist before Ockham). In the first place it is not clear that theories
tum God confers powers on men, primarily a power of appropriating ex- of individual rights depend on Ockhamist philosophical premises-i!ven
ternal goods (after the Fall) and a power of instituting rulers. The ruler in the work of Ockham himself. In the second place it is not dear that the
then has the power of legislation ( potestas condendi leges). From human ideas Villey contrasts with one another-dassical objective right, Judeo-
laws come dominium, usufruct, right of use-subjective rights guaranteed Christian natural moral law, and modem subjective rights-are in fact
by state authority. The rights are all absolute. They can be exercised or inherently inconsistent with one another.
renounced at will. And there is nothing else. The subjective rights of indi- As to the first line of objection: The metaphysical " moderate realism"
viduals have filled the void left by the loss of objective natural right.65 of Aristotle and Aquinas affirmed the primary existence of individual enti-
So the argument reaches its conclusion. Ockham has achieved his "se- ties in the external world, in opposition to the Platonic theory of ideal
mantic revolution." "It is the whole philosophy professed by Ockham . . . forms. There is no reason why such a metaphysics should be incongruous
that is the mother of subjective right."66 with an emphasis on individual rights.67 Similarly, Ockham's more radical
criticism of a realist theory of universals did not exclude a concern with
right relationships between persons and between persons and things.611
OBJECTIONS TO VILLEY ( lckham's polemical works were indeed concerned precisely with such
As I have suggested in presenting the earlier stages of Villey's relationships (between empire and papacy, between rulers and subjects,
argument, each phase of it is open to objections on points of detail. Simi- lwtween persons and property).
larly, his presentation of Ockham's views might be criticized as unbal- Villey simply assumes a dependence of Ockham's legal and politi-
anced. (Ockham's emphasis on individual liberties in the Breviloqium was l'al thought on his metaphysical doctrines. " Avec une coherence par-
matched by an equal concern for the common good in other contexts.) Yet 1.iite, Occam-juriste suit la voie d 'Occam-philosophe." This relationship
Villey always has a sound and sensible point to make, even when he seems has indeed often been affirmed, especially, before Villey, by Georges de
tempted to press the point to the edge of paradox. (Some early modem ju- I .agarde; but it has also often been contested.69 Charles Zuckerman has
rists did exaggerate the importance of individual rights in Roman law; .1rgued that all modem attempts to relate medieval political theories to
Aquinas did have a flexible doctrine of ius naturale; the Franciscan disputes metaphysical doctrines involve logical errors.70 Even if this seems too in-
did focus attention on the problem of natural rights; some modem lists of t r.msigent, Zuckerman certainly shows that, as a matter of historical fact,
supposed "human rights" are indeed protracted to the point of absurdity.)
A more serious objection to his thesis concerns the whole conceptual h7. The point was made long ago by M. de Wulf, KL'lndividu et le groupe dans la sco-
framework within which it is set. Villey has devised a sort of Manicheean 1."tique du Xllle si~cle.~ Revue nfo...Scolaslique de philosophit 22 (1920): 341-357 at 348. and
universe. There is an Aristotelian thought-world, full of light and sweet I' <;illet, La pnsonnalile juridiqut rn droil ecclisillSliqut (Malines, 1927). De Wulf especially em-
ph.i.si7.cd the primacy of the individual person in Aquinas.
reason, and an Ockhamist thought-world, where all is darkness and blind
~. On Ockham ·s theory of re.l ations see e.g., G. Martin, " 1st Ockhams Relationstheori<'
will. The good theory of objective right can flourish only in the first Nt>minalismus?" Franzislcanischt Studien 32 (1950): 31-49 at 49: "Ockham s teht hier in cinem
thought-world, the bad theory of subjective rights only in the second. 1111.1110i>!llichen Zusammenhang mit Aristoteles, Thomas und DunsSrotus.N
When clear-<:ut affirmations of individual rights are found in texts before 11'1. I A formation, 224. Some of the criticisms directed against de Lagarde's work (above•
" r;) wnuld apply also to Villey's interpretation. See e.g. J. B. Morrall, #Some Not~ on
·' l<...·1·111 lntNpretation of William of Ockham's Political Philosophy," Franciscan S ludit's •1
63. Ibid., 121. t 1•14•1): :l:l5-69; W. Kolmel. Wilhelm Ockham und srin kirchenpolitischen Schriftm (Essen. 19421
64. Ibid., 123-26. ""'' .. , >.1s Natum't'ht bei Wilhelm Ockham," f'ranziskanischt Sluditn 35 (1953): 39-8.'>.
65. Ibid., 126, "Et ii n'y a rim d'aulrr. ... Les droits subfectif11 .J.-.. lnJlvu~ uni rombl~ If' 70 l '. Zuck<'rman. "The Relationship of Theories of Univi·~als to Th<'ori~ of l 'hur.-h
vick resultant de la perte du dmil ruitul't'I." I ;1w1•11111u•nl in th1• Midtlk• J\g1•!1: J\ Critiq111• of Pn•viou~ Vi1•w!1," fournal nf llrl' I li.<lory 11/ lifrn.•
M . IA farmalum, 261. 2.'iJ. , ., (111'/l)· r,711 r,<1-1
32 TuE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS VtLLEY, 0cKHAM, ANO THE OtUCIN OF I NDIVIDUAL RIGHTS 33

there is no correlation between the two spheres of thought in the positions idea of individual rights. (We can define the relationship of parents and
of many medieval thinkers. We can find Thomists and realists and nomi- • hildren in terms of an objectively right order. Or we can define it in terms
nalists at every point on the political spectrum. (For instance, Wyclif and ,,( moraJ precept-"Honor thy father and thy mother." But we could also
Hus, like Ockham, upheld the rights of Christian subjects against the pope; • IPfine the same relationship by saying that parents have a right to the re-
but they were metaphysical realists in philosophy.) There is indeed no ·.pcct of their children.)
incongruity between Ockham's philosophy and his political theory, but As for individual rights and ius naturale considered as meaning what
there is no necessary connection between them either. •·· objectively right: to affirm a right ordering of human relationships is
By the time Villey wrote on Ockham in the 1960s a substantial litera- lo imply a structure of rights and duties. In propounding a system of
ture had grown up (which Villey simply ignores) asserting that Ockham 1urisprudence one can emphasize either the objective pattern of relation-
was not radically destructive in his philosophy nor radically innovative ·.hips or the implied rights and duties of persons to one another-and then
in his political theory and, further, that there was no close connection ·•>:.1in one can focus on either the rights or the duties. The emphasis can fall
between these two spheres of his activity. John Morrall called Ockharn "an 111 different ways depending on social and economic and political circum-

interpreter and defender of the achievements of the past." Philotheus ·.1.mces and on the temperament of a particular author. (It will probably
Boehner, after a lifetime's study of Ockham's work, maintained that li.1ve little to do with his abstract metaphysics.) The resulting works may
"Ockham's political ideas ... could have been developed, so far as we can I·•· very different in tone and spirit, but the different emphases do not nec-
see, from any of the classical metaphysics of the 13th century." 71 Villey has • ··.s;i rily imply logical contradictions. Despite the assertion of Villey (and
emphasized that it was not only Ockham's own rights-theories that were ·.11nilar assertions by some disciples of Leo Strauss in America), it is just
important for the future but his whole nominalist philosophy. And yet ""'true that "the notion of subjective right is logically incompatible with
the great Spanish scholastics of the sixteenth century, the Jesuits and Do- • l.1ssical natural right."
minicans who provided the essential link between medieval rights the- It is the same with ills understood as a body of moral or legal precepts.
ories and modem ones, were not Ockhamists. Most of them considered V1ll<·y noted that some modem jurists regard rights as merely the advan-
themselves to be Thomists (though Villey, of course, sees them as at best '·•>:•-s to individuals implied by general laws, and he added that this could
111 11 <'xplain the existence of natural rights.
12 He saw a connection only in
erring disciples).
In fact, rights theories have been upheld by writers of various persua- •Ii.ti the natural law theories he associated with Ockham and the Fran-
sions, including many who defended also doctrines of objective natural ' 1·.1-.ms allowed for "permissive laws" as well as precepts or prohibitions,
right and natural law. This leads on to our second major line of objection .111d he held that rights theories grew up in this area of permissive-
to Villey' s thesis. The various senses of ius that he discusses are not con- • w s s .1·1 The idea of permissive natural law is indeed important and we
tradictory concepts. Rather they are correlative. In considering Aquinas ·.11.tll need to return to it in later discussions; but the precepts and pro-
and the canonists we suggested that the concepts of ius as objective right lul>ilions of natural law could also readily be seen as implying rights.
order and as moral or legal precept are not intrinsically incompatible with I•• s.1y that "Thou shalt not steal" is a command of natural law is to imply
one another. Now we can add that both concepts are compatible with the iii.ti others have a right to acquire property, a point that medieval jurists
• l1·,1rly grasped.74 In fact one finds natural rights regarded as correlative
71. }. B. Morrall, "Some Notes,H369; P. Boehner, "Ockham's Political Ideas" in Col/tdtd
Arlie/es on Ockham, ed. E. M . Buytaert (St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1958), 442-468 at 446. A bibli- ·: J " I .1 genese," 99.
ography of the "revisionist" work on Ockham and a sympathetic discussion of it is provided : 1 I.I' 1froil rl /es droils, 123. "En outre, ii n'est pas que des lois prkeptivts . . . ou inltrdic-
by H. Junghans, Odcham im Uchtt dtr nt11rtn Forschung (Berlin, 1968). See also J. Miethke, ,.,.... . ma is aussi des lois pmnissi~ . .. Ainsi nail le droit subjectif. .. . N

Ockluzms Wtg zur SozilllpliilosoplUt (Berlin, 1969) and H. A. Oberman, Tht Harwsl of Lalt ·.1 for some examples o r this in canonistic thought see R. Weigand, Dit Nalurrtchlslthrr
Medieval Thtology: Gabritl BitJ and Latt Mtdinlol NomilUllism (Cambridge, Mass., 1963). On ·'· • I ...~ i<lrn 11nd rHkrttisltn von lrntrius bis Accursius und von Gratian bis fohannes Ttulonicus
Ockham as a "constructive" political thinker see A. S. McGrade, Tht Polilical Thoughl of ' ""'"'" h. 1'167), 357- 59. The opposite view, that natural law and natural rights are contradic·
William of Ockham: PtrSCmQ/ 11nd Institutional Principl~ (Cambridge, 1974). For changing views •"' v •""''•'pl-;, is often found in current American literature. See e.g., Walter Berns, -rhc Con·
on the cultural signi6cance of nominalism see William J. Courtenay, "Nominalism and I .ate • lll11 lh111 ·•!'I Bill o f Rights" in How Dews tht Conslilulion S«urt Rights?, eds. R. A. Goldwin and
Medieval Religion" in Tht Pursuil of Ho/in~. eds. C. Trinkhaus and Heiko A . Oberman \V II 'itfo11nbra (Washington, 1985), 50-73 at 55. N • •• natural rights and traditional natural
(Leiden, 1974), 26- 59. An overview of contemporary views on Ockham is presented in the '""' ,., ,., In ptat it !<imply yt>I altngt•lher a('Curately, incompatible.... w Such view~ Sttm ba!l('\I
papers of the Ockham Centennial Congress held at St. Bonaventure's University, and put>- "" " 111l•l<1l1•11 ld1•11. lhat modt•m righl!< th1•orir11 nrt• d1•rlvt'd ~tlrely fn>m Hobhe11 and on
lished in Franciscan Sludits 44-% (1984-86). ~ • 11 • 1•h· t1v111rnnn· of lhC' hi11tury u f llw nm1•1-rt 11f lw1 nnllm1/r bdow 11,.. • •vrnt.-.·nlh n•nlury
THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS VILLEY, 0cKHAM, AND THE 0RicrN OF INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS 35
34

with natural law at every stage in the history of the doctrine-in the , l1·votion that grew up then. Villey appreciated the importance of Chris-
twelfth-century renaissance of law, in the eighteenth-century ~nlight~n­ 11.111ity for the growth of rights theories, and he saw too that Ockham's
ment, and still in twentieth-century discourse. A modem thinker hke ,.111losophy was not mere "cobweb of the brain" spun out of his own
Jacques Maritain, steeped in the Thomistic tradition of natural law, has de- ··11hjl'ctive consciousness but rather a reflection of the real-life circum-
fended natural rights as consistent with that tradition.75 Mo~e -~ently, ·.1.11ices of the Middle Ages.77 Yet Villey stiJI supposed that social and re-
John Finnis, arguing in the language of contemporary analytic 1unspru- l1}:111us realities could shape a new system of jurisprudence only after
dence, has also treated the concept of rights as a "valuable addition . .. to 11 w y had passed through the filter of Ockham's nominalist thought. In fact
11t1111gh-as Harold Berman most recently and notably has pointed out-
the tradition of ' natural law doctrine." 176
.1l11·.1dy by the twelfth century the writings of the canonists were per-
1111·.1ted by doctrines based on individual intention and individual will in
·•••·.1s like the law of torts, the law of contracts, the law of marriage.18 It
ALTERNATIVE APPROACHES
would seem not unreasonable to look for a concern with individual rights
Once we realize that the assertion of a rights doctrine is not neces- .1 l·.11 in such a juristic culture. Moreover, the political writings of Ock-
sarily dependent on a prior acceptance of a nomi~alist. philosop~y. and 11 .1111 himself are saturated w ith canonistic references. He could hardly
that claims for individual rights have commonly existed in a symb10hc re- .1 \·11id them. Before he ever became involved in the Franciscan poverty
lationship, one might say, with theories of objective natural right and d1·.pute, the issues had already been formulated in juridical terms by two
natural moral law rather than in opposition to them, then the whole prob- 1. •1111idable lawyers, Pope John XXIl and his Franciscan adversary, Bona-
lem of the origin of Western rights theories can be approached in ways 1:1.11 i.1 of Bergamo.
different from Villey's. In suggesting some alternative approaches I am The earlier literature of the Franciscan controversies provides another
not concerned primarily to contest Villey's understanding of Aristotelian • •• I 1hody of source material, along with the writings of the canonists, for
natural right as an ideal to which modem civilization ~hould r~turn-that 11 ... 111vestigation of medieval rights theories. Villey was correct to see the
is another whole question-but rather to argue that his c~mm1tment t~ a I ' .111ciscan Order as a "cradle" of rights doctrines even though he exagger-
particular philosophical stance has led him to present a distorted version ·••··d the importance of Ockham as an innovator.79 lf we go back to the early
of the course of medieval intellectual history. We can agree that the con- •t••\'" nf the Order, the whole Franciscan movement can be seen as a culmi-
cept of individual rights was not prominent (to ~y the le~st) in clas~i­ 11.1111111 in the religious sphere of the personalism or individualism that also
cal law and that Ockham was an important transmitter of nghts theories 111lli11•nced twelfth-century law. From the beginning, there was a special
to the modem world. But if we realize further that Ockham's own theory ~ 111.t of individualism in Francis's altitude to the world around him; he did
of rights was not a radical innovation based on a tra~sposition of his '" 11 love mankind in the abstract but particular men and women.80 Francis
novel philosophical concepts into juridical language (whic~ ~ms an un- ''"' I clown in his Rule that all the brothers were to obey their superiors, but
warranted assumption) then an obvious approach to the ongm of Western 11 wn .1dded "in everything that is not against their conscience... ." He at-
rights theories is to investigate the earlier m~ieval developme~t of those " ·" '"" ;in extraordinary group of vividly diverse personalities as his first
doctrines, especially in the sources that contnbuted to Ockham s thought h•llowt•rs. A little later, from the 1250s onward, the conflicts of mendicants
in this area. .1111 I -:c·nilars stimulated a more legalistic concern with individual rights in
A natural starting point is the " renaissance" or "revolution" of the 11 ... wri tings of Franciscan masters.
twelfth century, which saw so many new beginni~gs in Western life a~d
thought. Villey himself, as we have seen, emphasized the concern for in-
· • I" /"rm11tinn, 2..16. 266.
dividual rights in the everyday, secular life of the a~e, and many ~~ent ·n I l.1wt.I J. Bt-rman, Uiw and Rroo/ulion: Tht Formation of lht Wesltrn ugal Tradition
writers have discussed the new personalist or humanist forms of rehg10us 11 •111111111>;1•, M11ss., 19RJ).
•, , V1ll1•y ,1ls11 calls 11ttention to the voluntarism of Scotus but still finds the dccisivl'
1 . ,..,,~ tl11<111Kh m ( )(kh11m. (See, e .g .. La formal ion, 179- 189). Villey's treatment of Scolus

75. /..es droits d~ l'hommut la Joi nature/le (Paris. 1945). •• ••11lol "''l"lrt· .molll<'T pap<>r. But th<- rem11rks above 11bout the pervasivenes~ of will and
76. Natur111 Law (above n. 26), 221 . The traditional interdependence of natural law and 11111•11111111 th,11 ""'' lir11h• .1ln•111ty in 1wl'lfth-<'entury l11w llR' nolt>vant h<'n> too.
natural r ights theories was also emphasized by J. _D abin.in a cri!id~m n f Vill<'y. Sf.., " I lrnit 1111 /\• < "lw!'>l.-rtnn wrnlt•: ~ r h· iii.I not ndl n.1hm• h i~ mo llw r: ht• 1·:11ft'tt " p.ulkulrtr
subjectif et subjectivisme juridique.H Archivr.> de ph1/~h1rd11 drmt 'I ( JQM)· 17 ·.1~ .t.... ~. · ~· hi~ h n1llll"r, or ., p1ulk 11l11r N)'llrrt•W htN Nl11h'r ··
36 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS VILLEY, 0cKHAM, AND THE ORIGIN OF IN DIVIDUAL R IGHTS 37

Two streams of thought flowed together in Ockham's polemical ..;cparate from ownership, but not a right based on secular law. The friars
works. One had its source in canonistic writings, the other in the early lit- had a right t~ m~terial support by virtue of the law of mercy and by virtue
erature of the Franciscan disputes. For the rest of this chapter I would like n~ the law of JUSt1ce, he wrote (but Bonaventure meant divine justice here).
to suggest some ways in which the further investigation of these sources V11l~y has suggest~ that, in Roman law, ius utendi was essentially a legal
might advance our understanding of premodem rights theories. .1ttnbute of the thmg used; but such a position cannot be sustained in
Among the canonists one often finds the term ius used in a subjective 1f'lation to Franciscan uses of the term in the century before Ockham. The
sense long before Ockham, and also the specific association of "right" and friars and their adversaries were constantly concerned with the inner
"power'' that Vtlley emphasized as a major contribution of the Francis- mtention and inner disposition of the user. Bonaventure wrote: "They
can to the theory of rights. Sometimes too, in offering formal definitions of 11mst claim their right with humility . . . that they may be humiliated in
natural right, ius mJturale, the canonists gave a subjective sense to the term, 11·ceiving" (and it was a natural right that he was discussing).IM We have
understanding it to mean, not objective natural law but a subjective "fac- "''<'~ th~t a ~ispute exists as to whether Thomas Aquinas had any idea of
ulty," "force," or "power'' of the human personality. (These texts and other -.ubrecttve right. But what of Bonaventure? Was his concept of ius more
canonistic usages of ius in a subjective sense are discussed in detail in the -.ubje~tive than Thomas's? Any comprehensive study of medieval rights
foi!vwing chapter.) lht.'ortes would need to consider the Franciscan arguments that preceded
An extensive technical literature has grown up around the doctrines of l > ckham's work.
the twelfth-century canonists, but it is not addressed to our particular In such ~ study we should also need to discuss not only the writings
problem-the origin of rights theories and, specifically, the juristic under- 111 the Franascans themselves but also those of their adversaries among
standing of the term ius before Ockham.81 It is the same when we tum to t lw secular theologians-such writers as Henry of Ghent and Godfrey of
Franciscan history. In this area too there is a huge body of modem writ- fontaines.35 Here again there is an extensive terrain that needs to be ex-
ing on the early history of the Franciscan Order and especially on the f'lored before we can hope to make an adequate map of medieval rights
Franciscan poverty disputes.82 But most often it is only when we come to llwories. Besides denouncing the Franciscan doctrine of poverty, the secu-
Ockham that historians of rights theories seem to regard the subject as l.1r masters also attacked the papal privileges that enabled the friars to
relevant to their inquiries. In fact the mass of controversial Franciscan lit- f'lt',1ch throughout the church. Such privileges, they maintained, under-
erature written before Ockham may be relevant too. 111111ed the traditional status of bishops and priests in their dioceses and
If we had to choose one pre-eminent philosopher as the first who 1•.11 ishes. To a modem mind it is clear that the issue could have been stated
transplanted Franciscan religious concepts to the alien field of legal theory 11 tnms of the rights of subjects (bishops and priests) against their ruler
1

it might well be Bonaventure rather than Ockham (though no one has ac- I rlw pope). But could the mind of a medieval theologian (before Ockham)
cused Bonaventure of being a nominalist). Writing in 1269, Bonaventure li.1vc· conceived of the issue in those terms? Godfrey of Fontaines, writing
distinguished four forms of common ownership associated with four cate- 1
11 th(• 1280s, in fact did so. The question he posed was: "Whether a supe-

gories of rights-those derived from necessity of nature, from fraternal 11111 prelate can take away from his subjects what belongs to them by
charity, from the civil law of the world, and from ecclesiastical endow- •1r.ht. " Arguing for the superior, he pointed out that popes often did take
ments. The first two could not be renounced; the second two had to be .uv.1 ~ pow.ers of their subordinates-e.g., a chapter 's power of electing or
renounced by anyone seeking the highest form of evangelical perfection.113 11 ... n~ht (ms) that an electee had acquired. On the other side he quoted a
Bonaventure (like Ockham) claimed for the Franciscans a right of use
tt·I lhid .. :l29. Bonaventure wrote he re that the friars were entitled to receive alms, not
81. On Ocldum's use of canonistic sources see my nOckham, the Concil.i ar llleory, and ""' /
0
•11 hut ;,,,,. poli. (Odcham would later use the same distinction.) " . .. iure poli earn ex·
the Canonists, fouTMl of the History of ldus 15 (1954): 40-70 and "Natural Law and Canon
H •1·.• ' " 1'" '""'1<'I dl't>ent per modum humilitatis .. . ut ipsi humilientur recipiendo." On
Law in Ockham's Dialogus,Hin J. G. Rowe, ed., Aspects of I.Alt Mtditval Covmimmt and Soci· " " ' "'"''"" "'' ilnd his Franciscan contemporaries see especially Paolo Grossi, HUsus facti. La
tty. Essays Pmenttd t1> / . R. Landu (Toronto, 1986), 3- 24. .... ,...,.,. •h pmprie ta ntc"lla inaugurazio nC' dell' eta nuova," Quadrmi Fio~nlini I'" ta storin rlrl
8.2. M. D. Lambert, Fnmcisctm POVtrly (London, 1961} provides a convenient introduc- I'•''' "'"' !1'"''.dwn urc~rrno 1 (19n): 287-355. G rossi discussed here the Franciscan empha!'lis
tion. For a more detailed study of Ockham's involvement see M. Oamiata, Guglielmo "" 11 ... u111iv1d11al will as a w urce of subjective rights.
d'Odcluim: Puwrtit t 110ten, 2 vols. (Florence, 1978- 79). "'' I >11 thi" lit,•rnh1w S4't' ~p<"Cially Y. Congar, A spects ecd 6 iologiques de la qul'rcll\•
M

83. A110Togill pilUf'"Um in s. 8cnOW711urar . . . o,,,ra mrmill. 10 vol!I. (QuaraC'C'h i, ""1 11• 1111'thli.ml,. 1•1 ~l.n1liNs dans la s.•nind1• moitit' du XIII<' sil'd t• t•I It· d('hut du XIV1•.''
18112- 1902) 8:233-:\~ at J09. ,,.,,,,,..,rr
1 .. Im• ·• 1l1~·tm111/r rl lilli'rnirr 1111 nwvrn 6,1(1' :lb (I % 1): ;:l~ - 1 ~ I.
38 THE lDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHTS VILLEY, 0CKHAM, ANO rnE ORIGIN OF INDJVfDUAL RIGHTS 39

text of Gregory the Great, included in the Decretum, where the pope said The most full and interesting discussion of ius as a subjective right in
that he wished to maintain the rights (iura) of all other churches. Godfrey ., Franciscan source before Ockham is found in a Quaestio of John Peter
concluded that the ruler could take away the rights of subordinates only in 1 llivi. Here again ius was identified with potestas. The question Olivi
exceptional cases when such action was necessary for the common good. U l'osed was whether the possession of a ius-he mentioned specifically the
he tried to act otherwise he could be resisted. ··right of royal power" and the "right of property"-added anything real
111 the person of the right-holder.• The whole argument turned on Olivi's
... Good rulers, especially ecclesiastical ones . . . ought to rule as is fitting
in the best polity, one in which the ruler does not intend his own good .1cceptance of a doctrine common to earlier scholastic philosophers, in·
1 luding Aquinas, the divine governance of the universe through rational
but the good of his subjects, who are not slaves but free men, having the
power to oppose their ruler if he wishes to tyrannize over them.86 11.1tural law and divine positive law.

Of course, we encounter a feudal right of resistance in innumerable me- There is a certain order so absolutely fixed ... by reason of virtue and jus·
dieval documents. But here we have an academic philosopher, in formal tice that God cannot and ought not to will the opposite .. . and this order
philosophical discourse, using Aristotle's theory of government-which is commonly called the order of natural right (ordo iuris naturalis). There
Villey regarded as incompatible with subjective rights-precisely in order is another order proceeding from the command of the divine will, such
that God can will or will the opposite ... as he pleases.89
to defend the rights of ecclesiastical subjects against papal tyranny. The
same issue will recur in Ockham's work; but Godfrey was not a nominal- 1 Jlivi did not regard subjective rights as somehow contrary to this over-
ist or even a Franciscan. .... 'hing structure of natural law or natural right but as implicit in it. Rights
In discussing the problems of evangelical poverty also, the oppon- ..1 ru lership and rights of property were a part of the divine scheme of
ents of the Franciscans-just as much as the friars themselves-were led to 1l 1111gs; that was why transgression of these rights by disobedience or theft
consider questions concerning property rights. Sometimes questions arose "".1s considered a mortal sin.90 Such considerations favored the argument
in their writings on this theme about natural law and specifically about 111.1! acquiring a ius did add something real to the personality of the right-
natural rights as in these lines, also from Godfrey of Fontaines: '" •Ider. But there were arguments on the other side too. A person could sell
On account of this, that each one is bound by the law of nature to sustain 111:- rights, which meant that the purchaser received the same rights the
his life, which cannot be done without exterior goods, therefore also by ••tlwr had formerly held, and this could not be if the rights were something
the law of nature (iure naturae) each has dominion and a certain right (ius) " "''·informing the person of the first right-holder. Again, a right could not
in the common exterior goods of this world which right also cannot be I··· -;aid to inhere in the body of a right-holder or any part of it, or in the in-
renounced.tfl 1t-llt•1.:t, or in the will. And rights could be acquired or taken away without
Here the meaning of the word ius shifted from objective natural law to ·" •v n..•al change in the subject (as a seal could lose its validity without any
subjective natural right in the course of a single sentence. And, here again, 11·.11 change in the seal).91 These are only a few points from a very complex
the argument about an inalienable right to use what is needed to sustain ... hulastic discussion, but they give some idea of how much sophistication
life is one that recurred in Ockham. In considering the work of Ockham • •••1ld be brought to bear on a consideration of rights concepts before the
himself we shall need to discuss especially some of the fourteenth-century ··1111 of the thirteenth century. (Olivi eventually concluded that a right did
controversialists-both champions of the friars and their adversaries-
who wrote just before Ockham in the course of the conflict between John HH l1l<' text is edited in F. Delorme, #Question de P. J. Olivi 'Quid ponat ius vel d o-
XXII and the Franciscans; but we should bear in mind that the thought ""'"'"'' ' t•u encore ' De signis voluntariis',N Antonianum 20 (1945): 309-330. Olivi regarded
and language of these writers had been shaped in part by the literature of 1.,.. 'l"•~tiOfl about rights as analogous to the questions whether a sacrament (e.g., baptism or
the earlier disputes. .... i..... 1ion) C'Qnferred a real character on the recipient, and whether the attribution of mean-
'"I'. ... 1,1, .. 1 something real to a word or sign.
86. Les Quodlibtts onu-qwirtoru dt Godefroid dt Fontaines, ed. ). Hoffmans, Us philosopltes 11'1 I hid .• 324, '. . . est ordo sic absolute prefixus . . . ratione virtutis et iustitie, que l'~t
Bdges 5 (Louvain, 1932): 94 (Quodl. 12 q.3). •t"'" I 1lt·u~ n1m polesl nee debet oppositum eius velle . . . et hie ordo cornmuniter vocntur
ffl. Philosophes Btlges 4 (1924): 105 (Quad/. 8. q.11), Nimmo etiam propter hoc quod un· .... ,,, l11rl11 n11turalis. Alius autem est ordo sic a dominativo irnperio divine voluntalis pm·
usquisque tenetur iure naturae vitam suam sustentare, quod non contingit ni!li dt> bonis • , .. i.·11K, 11111><1 Dt•u.'1 ipsum et cius oppo,c;itum . .. pm libitu potest velle.n
exterloribus. ideo etiam iure naturae qui libel habet dominium l't quodd11m irn1 in honi11 com· 'Iii ll>i<i .• J l7.
munibus t>xt<"riurib1111 huim• munJI. rul t•tlAm iuri n•n1111tiftW nnn p<>tt'l<I lklh•." •11 ll•ld . J211
40 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS VtLLEY, 0cKHAM, ANO rnE ORIGIN OF INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS 41

add something to the person of the right-holder, but not of such a nature as ,f.-fined a guardianship as a ius, another defined it as a potestas; so again it
to change his real essence.) ····•·med that the two words could be used interchangeably. But at this
Let us tum back to the canonists for one final text. Villey observed that 1·•1int the argument took a new and interesting tum. Accursius, in the Or-
the lists of definitions of the word ius given by the Roman lawyers and by .t11111ry Gloss to the Digest, had suggested that guardianship might be called
Thomas Aquinas did not include the subjective meaning of the term as ·' .. violent power" since it could be imposed on a person against his will.
a power inhering in individuals. But around 1310, twenty years before llut Johannes would not accept that a ius could be based on violence,
Ockham wrote his first polemical works, the canonist Johannes Monachus which was normally culpable. Rather ius was a power introduced by right,
made a more ample list, ending with a mnemonic verse to help his stu- "' hy law, a iure introducta. Still not satisfied with his definition, Johannes
dents remember a score of different meanings.92 Johannes set out from a 111troduced some more verbal equivocation, this time in connection with
decretal of Nicholas UI, stating that, when an election required papal con- 11 ... word virtus as meaning either " force" or "virtue." He thought virtus
firmation, the electee had to appear at Rome "cum omnibus actis, iuribus w.1... derived from vis intus; but one common definition of ius naturale
et munimentis suis" ("with all his acts, rights, and documents"). This re~ • .1lh·d it a vis implanted in all creatures and hence, Johannes suggested, a
minded Johannes of another canonistic text, borrowed from Roman law, 1•11t11s. This innate virtus was a natural power. But, the author continued,
which affirmed that the pope had "ornnia iura in scrinio pectoris sui" ("all !\ rl imitates nature," and so the ius of the lawyers was a virtus too. But
laws in the shrine of his breast"). How could the electee bring his iura lw11· the meaning of virtus shifted, and led Johannes to his final definition.
when the pope already had all iura? The word ius was obviously being 111 ·. w as not a violent power but a "virtuous power."95
used in different senses; and this consideration launched Johannes into a l"he argument involved word-play and a sort of web of free asso-
list of all the possible meanings he could think of. There is a note of heavy- . 1.111011 of juridical ideas. It was not a philosophical argument; it had
handed playfulness in some of his definitions. He began with the entirely " "' hing to do with nominalism; still it led Johannes to a definition of ius as
non-legal meaning of ius as a rich liquid (aqua pinguis), a broth or juice, and •• ·.11hjcctive power, a "virtuous power" which was very similar to Ock-
proceeded with some word-play on mando as meaning either to eat or to l 1.1111' s "licit power" and indeed to Gewirth's modem definition, "a rightful
command. (Then he solemnly explained the pun to his students, "Mondo 1·• 1w1•r." The definition acquired a broad currency in the later Middle Ages
of the first conjugation, has two different meanings. .. .") His mnemonic i.,., .111se it was incorporated into the standard commentary on the Liber
verse began, ·.,.. /us of Johannes Andreae. Then, in the sixteenth century, Johannes An-
lus is water, ius is right, ius is called a power, 0I11·.u· was quoted in the widely-read Summa of the Dominican, Sylvester
l '1w r.1s,<1to and Sylvester, in turn, became a major source for Vitoria and
An art, a form, the rigor of law, a bond, a nature, a place ... .,,,.,.,.writers of the Spanish "second scholasticism."
and continued with many more explanations. Johannes' second definition
shows a kind of overlapping of objective and subjective right. "Ius means •t•, lhi1I. The gloss is so c ompressed and allusive as to resist literal translation, "Alio
the right and just, as when we say so-and-so has or does not have a right """ I" 11·1-:itur ilia littera ius cum dicat glossa ibidem ius et potestas, i.e . violenta potestas.
(ius)."93 Another definition identified ius with dominium . The most impor- •... f f,.., 1-:lossa videtur mala. Nam omne violentum est reprobum . . . sed accipitur (iu5)

tant discussion for us however was on the third definition, which treated ,.,.. I'"""''·''" a iure introducta. Sic dicitur quod nature virtus i.e. vis intus id est vis insita
"1 ...., •·st proprium in naturalibus ,in quibus est vis generativa . Sed trahitur a simili
ius as meaning potestas. "Tertio idem est quod potestas.. .." Johannes first ''' " '"'" 1,1tis, cum ars imitetur naturam in quantum posse!, ff de adopt. si pater, 1, in fine, et
cited in support of this a text of Gratian which claimed for the Roman _,. ·'" 11ur ius t't potestas, Le. virtus potestativa seu virtuosa potestas...."
church a right of making Jaws (ius condendi canones).94 Johannes assumed " '· Jo h,1nm-i; Andreae reproduced the definitions o f Johannes Monachus in slightly ab-
that this evidently referred to a power (potestas) of making laws. Johannes 1.,. • t.111·.t lurm in his In lilulum Dt regulis iuris novella commtnlaria (Venice, 1581 ), fol. 2v
t • •· .,., "'' _.,,.,,. 'i. 12). Cf. Sylvester Prieras, Summat Sylvestrinae {Venice, 1584), 79r. Johann<'~
next gave an example from the Roman Jaw of tutors. One text of the Digest
\ ,.. ,.,..... .uld t-d ·' significant comment in another context, In qumtum Decrrta/ium /ibrum
... .... 11.r • ••111111mtnri11 (Ve nice, 1581), fol. 151v. The text o f the Dtcrt lals {X.5.40.12) stated (quot·
92. Johannes Monachus, Glossa Aurt'R (Paris, 1535), fol. xcir, Gloss ad Snt. 1.6.16. 11.,. •~i. l 11 1t• 111 Si•villl'). "!us est a iure possidendo." Jo hannes commenled, "Non loquitur h ie
93. Ibid ., HSecWldo ius dicitur rectum seu iustum ut cum dicimus lste habct vel non l • 1.i.. ,.... •I•· iure• Jtl'nerali quod ll'gibus vd moribus constat .. . ~ sumitur pro iure quod
habet ius.H · ..,,,,...111 1•11v,11t1 inn· .1 liqua." It i.-; just lhe d istinction between i11s as genl'ral law and iu.< .,.
I"l•t\Y l r "f
94. Ibid., "Tertio idem est quocl potestas, uv q . p rima !i hiM it,, .. (i .<'. <·.2s q.I dic-1t1m I•·•••· t ll(hl th.it orw flrn.l!i in Smm•7.anJ oth..r ~vt'ntrc,,-.th · n-ntury ;iuthnl1'. On thi~ te1el !!<'<'
pl)SI c.16, whe re Gratian referred to th(' ru.~ rondmdi n rrw rrM) U
42 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGKTS

When Peter Olivi and Johannes Monachus discussed ius as subjec-


tive right, they were not casually or carelessly borrowing a usage from
vulgar discourse. Rather each was providing a detailed analysis (philo-
sophical or juridical) of a concept whose importance was fully apparent
to them. When Ockham in tum came to write on subjective rights there
was no need for him to inaugurate a "semantic revolution." A rich lan-
guage already existed in which rights theories could be articulated. The
doctrine of individual rights was not a late medieval aberration from an
earlier tradition of objective right or of natural moral law. Still less was it
a seventeenth-century invention of Grotius or Hobbes or Locke. Rather, Two
we shall argue, it was a characteristic product of the great age of crea- .,. .... ......
tive jurisprudence that, in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, established ,
,
...,,.-; .. ·-
.:-•

the foundations of the Western legal tradition. Villey is justified in calling


attention to the abuses of rights language by many modem theorists, but ORIGINS OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGE:
it is a good Thomist principle that abusus non tollit usum. The underlying TEXTS ANO CONTEXTS, 1150-1250
concept may still prove of value in our political discourse. As to the history
of the doctrine, there is still a great deal of work to be done. Villey may
not have been correct in all of his conclusions, but he certainly stated the
problem perceptively. "If all the modern juridical notions . . . bom of
the idea of subjective right still did not exist at Rome, what a vast field ~\ ;If odern histories of natural rights theories usually place the ori-
of inquiry is the investigation of their true origin!"91 .{ ~ J.lgin of such doctrines in the late medieval or early modem pe-
11.,tfs; rights theories are commonly associated with the spread of nomi-
11,1l1s1philosophy or the beginnings of an entrepreneurial economy. In this
• l 1·•1'h'r I want to suggest that the humanistic jurisprudence of the twelfth
• .... tury, especially the writings of the medieval Decretists, may provide a
hl'ft1·r starting point for investigating the origins of natural rights theories
111.111 1•ither fourteenth-century nominalism or the nascent capitalism of
11.,. •·.1rly modem world.
Iii write a full history of natural rights theories, even for the modern
1·•·1111d, would be a formidable task. Ever since the days of Hobbes and
' "' ~ .. {<tt least) the concept of individual rights has been of central im-
1''" 1.1111«' in Western thought. But also, from the seventeenth century to
11,.. l'n'sl'nt day, rights theories have been persistently attacked, and from
11 . 111 y difforent points of view. The result is paradoxical. On the level of
1

1111 11.1lional politics a professed regard for "human rights" is mandatory;


1
· •

.,.,. ·"~~m· mainly about which regimes are most cynical in purporting to
.t.-1.·11.t tht•m. But, on the level of philosophical discourse, the existence of
••·•••11 ..r or human rights is often dismissed altogether. According to Ali!-!·
,,,,,, Mdntyn.•, for instance, "there are no such rights and belief in them is
111w w11h h1•lid in witches and in unicorns."'

I /\ M,11 lnly n•, liflrr Vrrl11r, 2nd ••ti (Notn• I >,1nw, 19114). f>'·l .
97. HL'idh du droit subjectif," 226.
41
44 THE IDEA OF NATUKAL RIGHTS ORIGINS O F NATURAL R IGHTS LANGUAGE 45

As I noted earlier, a historian cannot hope to solve all the prob- 111 ·ite."6 This notion that ius naturale, "natural right," could define an area
lems that are raised in this area by modem jurists and moral phi- ••I human liberty as well as a body of restrictive law was of central impor-
losophers.2 But modem discourse about rights is often associated w~th an 1.111ce in the emergence of modem rights language.
implicit or sometimes quite explicit set of assumptions about the history Habermas and De Lagarde both drew a contrast between the modem
of rights theories. So perhaps a historical approach can contribute some- doctrine of natural rights and the thought of Thomas Aquinas, in whose
thing, at least peripherally, to the ongoing arguments. Mcintyre himself work the older tradition of natural law found a classical expression. This
asserts, mistakenly, that no language existed in which the concept of a nf.scrvation, a commonplace in much recent writing on natural law theo-
right could be expressed before about 1400.3 Leo Strauss and C. B. Mac- 1 w -;, is true enough so far as it goes; but it has led to a radical error of

Pherson and Ian Shapiro, in different ways, all base criticisms of modem 1wriodization in most modem writing on the history of natural rights.
rights theories in part on their understanding, or misunderstanding, of lnltn Finnis observed that, since there is no doctrine of subjective rights
a supposed seventeenth-century origin of those theories.• Often natural 111 Aquinas and there is such a doctrine in Suarez, a " watershed" must be
rights theories are treated as a modem aberration from an older, perhaps ..1111ated somewhere between the thirteenth century and the seventeenth.7
sounder, tradition of natural Jaw. Jurgen Habermas, for instance, has 11111 this view rests on the fallacy, widespread among modem jurists and
written of a "positivization" (Positivierung) of classical natural law in the 1•l11losophers who are not medieval specialists, that if an idea is not to be
modem era. The older tradition, he explained, laid down norms for virtu- l1111nd in Aquinas it is not really a medieval idea at all. Another expla-
ous living; the new doctrine of natural rights allowed "a neutral sphere 11.1tion is possible. It may be that a juristic, distinctively non-Aristotelian
of personal choice" in which each individual could egotistically pursue llwory of natural rights had grown up before Aquinas, that Aquinas did
his own advantage.5 ln this new way of thinking, a right was a freedom ""' t·hoose to assimilate such ideas into his Christian-Aristotelian synthe-
to act in any way that was not explicitly prohibited. Habermas referred '11'·. but that they d id enter the mainstream of Western political thought
here specifically to Hobbes. Earlier, Georges de Lagarde had made a lluuugh other channels. This is the thesis l want to explore.
similar point in discussing Ockham's rights theories; he found in Ock-
ham's philosophy of natural law "a zone of human autonomy" where,
I 11i: QUESTION OF ORIGfNS
because nothing was prohibited, all was licit, and where human freedom
could be exercised without restraint. " Ll, ou elle ne defend rien, tout est Natural rights theories seem to be a distinctively Western invention.
lt111 such theories have not been characteristic even of Western culture at
2. For the earlier bibliography see R. Martin a.n d J. W. Nickel, "Bibliography on the .11l 1imes and places. Whether the ancient Greeks had any concept of sub-
Nature and Foundations of Rights, 1947- 1977/ Political1M>ry6 (1978): 395-413. Anthologies 1•·· h v (• rights at all is debated; certainly they had no doctrine of natural
on rights which have appeared since 1977 often include some historical material. A~ong 111:lits.A(Sophocles' Antigone did not assert a God-given right; she found
them are D. Lyons, ed., Rights (Belmont, 1978); E. Kamenka and A. E. Tay, eds., Human Rights 11.-.·wlr bound by an inexorable law.) Stoic thinkers conceived of natural
(New York, 1978); B. Bandman, ed., Bi0tthics and Human Rights (Boston, 1979); W. Laqueur
and B. Rubin, eds., ~ Humm Rights Rtadu (New York, 1979); A. S. Rosenbaum, ed., Phi1oso-
1.1\v .1s an expression of divine reason pervading and ordering the whole
phy of Human Rights (Westport, 1980); J. R Pennock and J. W. Chapman, eds., Human Rights: • ..·1111os, and they envisioned a natural law inherent in humankind as one
Nomos XXll (New York, 1981). R. Martin and J. W. Nickel, hRecent Work on the Concept of ·•··1·1·1·1 of this pantheistic world-view. Diogenes Laertius held that, "our
Rights/ AlllD'ican Philosophical Quarterly 17 (1980): 165-180 provides an overview 0£ some
main trends of modem thought. ,, t ;, Je Lagarde, La nllissance de I' tsprit laiqut au dee/in du Moytn Agt, 6 vols. (Paris,
3. ltfttr Virtut, 69. I'• l·I 4h), 6:122, 157.
4. Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1950); C. B. Macpherson, Tht Politiail · I Finnis, Natural Law and Natur1ll Rights (Oxford, 1980), 206-207.
Thtory of PosstsSfve lndiuidwilism: Hobbts lo Lockt (Oxford, 1964); I. Shapiro, Tht Evolution of 11 l·nr J iff<'ring views on the ancient Greeks' concept of rights see J. W. Jones, Tht Law
Rights in Libtnil Thtory (Cambridge, 1986). In a methodological article, •Realism in the Study ... .. 1 ' ~s••' 11reory of tht Grulcs (Aalen, 1977) 191; M . Ostwald, Nomos and tltt lkginnin11s of
of the History of Ideas,• History of Political Thought 3 (1982): 535- 578, Shapiro comments, • If "''' ""'" l>rnroerncy (Oxford , 1969), 113; K. J. Dover, Crttk Popular Morality in lht Timt of Pinto
w e want to understand our own beliefs a s fully and critically as possible it is essential . . . to '""' :\ 1,,,.,,,,.(Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1974), 157. Most recently Fred Milh!r has maintai.neod
see where our beliefs come from and what functions thf'y servt' In th<- contemporary world" "•·•• " •fcl('lrine of natural rights was implicit in Aristo tle's theory o f justice. r have argul-J
(577). f agree with this approach; but it only emphH17.l'll thr llf'f"CI In jtCI our history straight. 1..-1..w (< 'h. 11) that a natural rights theory could be fonnulated in Aristotelian language; but
Shapiro !IOmetime!I writl'l' as though tM- world ~11n In tlw IW'VC'nh·•·nth n•ntury. t 1t1111i.. 1u1«h " lh<'nry came to be overtly as.wrted o nly in the medieval era. See F. Mlllt•r,
5 . J. I faberma!'I, Tht'Oryand f'racli0'. tr11n". J. Vlt•1tr1 (llo"lon, l't74). M I1,,,.,,,., / 11.'1i1'r. mul RiRltl i11 Ari~lt>llt's PoliliN (Odord, \4"J5).
46 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS 0RJGrNS OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGE 47
undivided natures are parts of the nature of the whole universe," and 1111c harmony or objective justice or natural moral law, begin to acquire

Cicero wrote of a vis innata, an innate force in humans through which they .1bo the sense of a subjective natural right? And what cultural context,
could discern the law of nature, ius naturae, that they were bound to ob- •v h;it set of contingent historical circumstances, made the shift of mearung
serve.9 But all this is far from a doctrine of individual natural rights. 1•1 •-;sible and acceptable?
It is the same with classical Roman law. Julius Paulus gave an objec- The two questions are really inseparable. Nowadays we are often
tive definition of ius as "what is right and good" and similar language 11·111inded that, when we purport to study the history of political ideas,
was used to explain the primary meaning of ius by Aquinas a thousand w1· are really concerned-or should be---wilh political language, with
years later.1° Classical jurists, like Stoic philosophers knew of a natural tlw history of political discourse. Hence our first task is to understand the
moral law, accessible to human reason, but they did not derive from it a • n11tcxt that sustains a particular style of discourse and renders it intelli-
doctrine of natural rights.11 In early Christian thought too, Paul wrote of a r.1hll•. Different modem authors dwell on different kinds of context. u Some
law written on the hearts of men; but he djd not assert that "all men are nwl;ihistorians write as though the study of language itself is enough, as
endowed by their Creator with certain inalienable rights." rliough language constitutes a magic kingdom of its own, a context suffi-
Many scholars have suggested that a doctrine of natural rights ' w11t to itself. Other critics, more sensibly 1 think, insist that we can and
was always implicit in Judeo-Christian teaching on the dignity and moral .. 1u 111ld situate language in a real world of life and action. In any case, a
autonomy of each individual human person. Such a concept of human ' li.1racteristic, recurring problem for rustorians is that patterns of discourse
personality could indeed provide a fitting basis for a theory of natu- 1wrsist in contexts different from the one that first gave rise to them.
ral rights; and, of course, it does not nowadays have to be expressed in · .., pl'rhaps we need to be reminded that "the performance of speech acts
terms of Jewish or Christian theology (though religious cultures that 11n l me rely modifies language, but leads to the creation and diffusion of
regard individuation as illusory are not likely to develop rights theories 1ww languages," that "any text may be an actor in an indefinite series of
spontaneously.) But, if a doctrine of rights has always been implicit in l111>:11istic processes," 14 that "all linguistic interpretation involves interpre-
Judeo-Christian thought, it has certainly not always been explicit. 12 Merely t.1h1>n by an audience." 15
calling attention to Judeo-Christian values does not solve the problem of Sometimes the currently favored hermeneutical approaches to intel-
origins. The rustorian's task remains-to understand the particular situ- li·· r11al history may seem merely portentous ways of stating platitudes that
ation in which an old ideal of human dignity could first find expression 1.lcl fashioned historians used to take for granted. After all, we have un-
in a new theory of natural rights. There are two basic questions to be an- ,1,·1-;tood for a long time, without benefit of advanced literary theory, that
swered. When did the phrase ius naturale, which traditionally meant cos- 11..- words of Magna Carta did not mean the same thing to a seventeenth-
' rntury parliamentarian as to the barons of 1215. And to tell a historian of
9. Diogenes Laert.ius, Lives 7, 88; Cicero, De invtntiont, 2.22.65. On Stoic concepts of 1d1·,1s tha t what he has been reading and writing all the time is really lan-
natural law in humans see M. C. Horowitz, "The Stoic Synthesis of the Idea o f Natural law t-: "·'>~t> may seem merely like telling M. Jourdain that what he has been
in Man: Four Themes, Journal of lht History ofldt!IJS 35 (1974): 3-16. For Stoic influence in tile
N
'•1'1·.1king every day is really prose. But not all the points raised by recent
Middle Ages see G. Verbeke, Tht PrtStna of Stoicism in Medieval Thought (Washington, D.C.,
1983). Some Stoic thinkers, especially the later ones, found a place for conscience and choitt
t11kll<•ctual historians are trivial and sometimes they are relevant for our
in their systems, but choice meant only a capacity to accept or reject a fate that was already 111°111iry. Dominick LaCapra defined our problem precisely, if unintention-
predetermined. Senecca wrote " fate volentem ducunt nolentem trahunt" (Ep. 107.11). ·•ll v. when he discussed "noncanonical readings of canonical texts" and
10. Digest 1.1.11. Other definitions followed, b ut they did no t include the idea of ius as
subjective right. For Aquinas see Summa thmlogiat 2.2ae.57. t . Ulpian gave a definition of ilU t I For a recent cr itical discussion of some current approaches see A. Pagdm, "Rethin.k ·
naturalt (often q uoted in medieval sources) as · what nature has taught all animals" (Dig. '"!'. •h·· I j nguistic Tum: Current Anxieties in Intellectual H istory, fournal of tht History of
ff

1.1.1.3). 1.1••, .. 4' 1 ( l'IAA): 519- 29


11. See H.L.A. Hart, " Bentham on Legal Rights," reprinted in D. Lyons, Rights, 126, H I C: . I\. Pococ k, #Thl' Concept o f Language a nd the rnilitr d'ltisloritn: Some Considt>r-
"The concept of a right, legal o r moral, is not to be found in the work of the Greek phi!Mo- . 11..,,. " " l'racti«·:· in A. Pagden, ed., The Lang11ages of Politicttl Thtory in Early -Mod"n Eu"'llt'
phers. . . . Jurists of stature have even held that . . . Ro man law never achieved. a clur t• .rn1lt111t1:•'. 19117), 19- :\R, at 29, 31. Bal7.ac put ii more simply at the beginning of Loui.q IAm-
concept of a legal right. Thus Maine w rote . . . ' the clear conception of a legal right . . . bco- h • I ..V""' ll<:•;iu livn• nc> composerait-on pa:ot m racontant la vie et les aventures d ' un mot7
longs dis tinctively to the modem wo rld'." ··~"" •lu1111· ii " n>tzu divl'r.iM imp~sions des evenements auxqut>l~ ii 11 9ervi; !K'lon It'll lieux,
12. John A. H enley. "Theology and the Basis of Human Rights," Srottish Journal of Th"'1- 11 " u' v1·1Ui' •I•·~ idtt·~ d ifftswntt>!'I.. .. " The> pa!'l."-1&t' i~ quott'd in S. Ullm11n, Srmttnlin1 (Nt>w
ogy 39 (1986): 361- 378 discusses recent literature o n Chri.~tlanity "~a bMiR for righl!'! lhrorl"". 1... ~ . l'lh~!J. 14.
H <' r\'f('rs lo " Ill<' silt•nct' of mtKh of tilt' Chri!'llian tra<filiun on the> ~uhj<'<'t '" (:lh7) I '• •.t..1plro, '" Ht•nli.!1111," t;41>.
48 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RICHTS ORIGINS OF N ATURAL RlCHlS LANGUAGE 49

emphasiz.ed the need "to pose as an explicit problem the way in which l'" wers, others more the claims. Plamenatz, in an early formulation, de-
texts are related to contexts." 16 Our texts are "canonical" in a stricter sense • I.ired that, "A right is a power which a creature ought to possess.. .. "19
than LaCapra intended and our purpose is precisely to understand how 11 1..1Feinberg defined a right rather as a "valid claim" justified by "some set
canonistic texts inherited from classical and early Christian sources were • 1 governing rules or moral principles." He distinguished sharply between
1

reinterpreted in the context of a new age. l.wors, "motivated by love or piety or mercy," and rights that could be "de-
There was plenty of room for reinterpretation. The simple-looking 111.mded, claimed, insisted upon." 20 For him a real right was a claim that
little phrase, ius naturale, is a semantic minefield. Erik Wolf once observed • ••uld actually be asserted against society as a whole or against some spe-
that the word "natural" has seventeen meanings and the word ius fifteen; ' die person.21
so, he concluded, there could be two hundred and fifty-five possible mean- A co~mon theme, in modem discourse on rights is the relationship
ings for ius naturale. But this was too modest a count. Arthur Lovejoy more "··•ween nghts and free choice. Feinberg points out that the holder of a
enterprisingly found sixty-six meanings for "natural," and the canonist Jo- ••r,ht can "choose whether or not to exercise it."22 H .L.A. Hart also empha-
hannus Monachus gave over twenty definitions of ius.17 The number of .. ,,..s freedom of action. The right holder has autonomy or "sovereignty"
possible combinations becomes mind-boggling. Fortunately we shall not 111 the relevant sphere. In the case of a promise, for instance, "If he chooses

need to consider all of them. We shall be concerned mainly with ius as '' • n·lease the promisor no one else can complain."23 According to this un-
meaning either objective law or subjective right, and with "natural" as ' 11·1standing of the term, a right defines a sphere of licit action within
meaning either a primeval state of affairs or an intrinsic permanent char- w li1ch a person is free to exercise a power or make a claim, free to act as he
acteristic of any being, as when we speak of "the nature of man." It is • liooses. Robert Louden, inveighing against an alleged modem "infatu-
the latter meaning that is more important in investigating the origins of .1t 111n" with rights, explains that " rights are permissions rather than re-
natural rights theories. ' 111in•ments. Rights tell us what the right bearer is at liberty to do, not what
1... 11111st or must not do.. . ."1 4 In the language of Habermas, rights defme
·' 1wutral sphere of personal choice."
SOURCES OF MODERN RIGHTS LANGUAGE Many modem rights theorists, including Feinberg and Hart, have
Let us begin with some examples of the language used by modem 111.uh· the point that to be the beneficiary of a duty is not necessarily the
rights theorists. (I do not want to be anachronistic, but if we are to ex- ...111u· thing as having a right, even though this is often the case. Feinberg
plore origins we need to know first what we are seeking the origins of.)
Seventy years ago, W. N. Hohfeld gave an influential taxonomy of rights as 1' 1 I. P. Plamenat2, Consenl, Fnedom and Polil1caf Obligation (Oxford, 1938), 82. Cf. T. H .
claims, liberties, powers, or immunities.18 Modem jurists and philosophers ' ......... lrt"111rts on tht Principlts of Political Obligation (London, 1941), 2Cfl. "A right is a ~r
who "take rights seriously' ' continue to emphasize such words as "free- ..1 ·" ""lo: . . . secured to an individual by the community. .. ." Similarly F. C. von Savigny,
·· ~·.1,·111 '''"" heutigm Riimischen Rtchts, 9 vols. (Berlin, 1840- 51), 1:7 " .. . d ie der ein7..eln
dom," "claims," "power," "choice." When specifically natural rights are 1·•., •., •11 J.ustehende Macht: ein Gebiet worin ihr Wille herrscht. . . ." For discussion of rights
discussed the patterns of language include words like "moral," "licit," "ra- •lu·•01 M • in Germany, see A. Vonlanthen, Zum rechlsphilosophischtn Strtil iibtr das WtStn do
tional." Natural rights are also often related to the basic needs of humans .... ,.,,, ,,..,.,, Rec/its (Zurich, 1964).
as moral agents, as in the work of Alan Gewirth. Gewirth distinguishes be- .'It I. Ft•inberg. "The Nature and Value of Rights," foumal of Valut Enquiry 4 (1970):

tween two classes of rights in the phrase, "rightful claims or powers"; • 1 1 -'"7. •11 257; " Duties, Rights, and Claims," American Ph11osophicol Quartoly 3 (1966):
I t • IH .11143.
other authors use the terms "passive rights" and "active rights" to make
.' I !'his It'd to difficulties when Feinberg considered natural rights. A starving child in a
the same distinction. Some modem rights theories emphasize more the 11 ... . 1 wurl1I country has an obvious claim to be fed, but in an impoverished society tht>w
"'·' r h1• no ont> to whom the claim can be meaningfully addressed, " Duties, Rights, and
16. D. LaCapra, "Intellectual History and Defining the Present as 'Postmodern'," in ' '""" ' ·" 142 Fd nbcrg concluded that such claims, arising from basic human needs, can and
I. Hassan and S. Hassan, eds., lnnuoation/Rmm:Nltion. Nn» Pmpectivrs on lht Hum1mitin . 1.... ,1. 1 •:•w ri~ lo rights but that lhey can be called actual rights only through an ex<'rci~ of
(Madi.son, 1983), 47-63 at 54. lin·n~." " Nature and Value," 255.
,,,..,.,, ,, .11
17. E. Wolf, Das Problem dtr N11tu~htsldtrr, 3rd ed. (Karlsruhe, 1964). A. 0 . Lovejoy 11nd .'.' ··N.tlun.» m d Valul'," 2."iO.
G. Boas, A Documnit11ry History of Primitivism 11nd Rel11t~ /dMS (Baltimore, 1935), 1:448, Jo- .' ' 111. A. f l.1rt, ~ Art' There Any Natu ral Rights?," Philosophical Rroirw 64 (1955); 175 - Jql
hanrteS Monachus, GIOSSll Aumr (Paris, 1535) 11d ~xi. 1.6.16, fol. xcir. 1be text of Johllnllft ~• llM
Monachus is discUS9ed in the preceding chapter. Jot I( I . I .0111h·n. " RiKhl~ lnfotm1tion .md ttw lmp<1v1•ri~hmmt o f Mor.ii llwory," '"'"'"''
18. W. N. Hohfeld, Fundamt'11tal l~J(ol Crmuptions (N<'w 1lllvf'n, 191'1). •o/ I 011111· lm11111v 17 ( l'lll'\)· K7 1112, .11 'I'>
so THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ORIGINS OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGE 51

referred to a general "duty of charity" which does not necessarily give rise I his "moral quality" could also be called a faculty; it could include power
to a right in any particular recipient. Hart gave an example of third-party , •vc•r oneself, meaning liberty, and powers or claims in relation to other
beneficiaries. If a promises b to confer a benefit on c, then c has no right 1"·rsons or things.
against a (though b does).25 The underlying point is that, in using the lan- Suarez and Grotius distinguished a subjective meaning of ius from
guage of subjective rights, we can make moral assertions that are not "'her connotations of the word. It was left for Hobbes to insist that the
always identical with those of moral systems concerned only with duties ·.uhjective meaning was the only proper one:
or objective justice. The distinction is significant because moral codes do The RIGHT OF NATIJRE which writers commonly call jus naturale, is the
not have to be expressed in terms of rights, and indeed they usually have liberty each man hath, to use his own power, as he will himself, for the
not been so expressed. Hart pointed out that we should not normally ' preservation of his own nature... . A LAW OF NATURE, lex naturalis, is
regard the Ten Commandments as conferring rights. He also observed that a precept or general rule found out by reason, by which a man is forbid-
natural law thinkers down to the end of the sixteenth century usually con- den to do that which is destructive of his life ... law, and right, differ as
ceived of natural duties but not of natural rights. much, as obligation and liberty. ... 28
This takes us back to the historian's problem of origins. If ade-
I .1h·r he explained that the sphere of liberty was defined by " the siJence of
quate moral systems can be articulated without any appeal to subjec-
tlw law"; where laws did not command or forbid, a person was free to act
tive rights, and normally were so articulated until quite recently, how
.1·. hl' wished. Hobbes seems to deviate from the preceding tradition, not
did rights language emerge in the first place? What is its source? Back to
1111ly in giving an exclusively subjective definition of ius, but also in ex-
a certain point in time the answer seems clear enough. The language
' 111.ling the idea of moral rightness from his definition. (For Suarez and
of twentieth-century writers echoes that of the classical natural rights the-
c .1utius ius was a moral power, a moral quality.) But later authors devel-
orists of early modem Europe. At the beginning of the seventeenth cen-
,,,,,.tf Hobbes's distinction between natural rights and natural law in ways
tury Suarez defined ius specifically in terms of the powers and claims of
111.11 restored the moral content of a natural right.
an individual. In a complex discussion of all the meanings of the word
Perhaps the most clear and coherent account of natural laws and
he wrote: 11.11ural rights in a fully developed, eighteenth-century Enlightenment
According to its strict signification ius is called a kind of moral power 1111111 of the doctrine is that given by Christian Wolff. For Wolff, law (lex)
(facultas) which anyone has concerning his own property or something 1·•• 1 rule that obliges us. Natural law, law inherent in the rational nature
due to him. So the owner of a thing is said to have a right in the thing •'' man, obliges each person to seek self-perfection. But the fulfillment of
and a workman is said to have a right to his wages. ... 26 111• •r.11 obligation requires a certain freedom of action; and, Wolff declared,
A little later (c. 1625) Grotius gave three meanings of ius. The word could I his faculty or moral power of acting is called a right (ius)." Carrying the
mean "what is just" (the preferred definition of Aquinas). Or it could ·" 1'.11mcnt further, Wolff explained that "What the law of nature obliges
mean a kind of law, and in that sense ius naturale was a "dictate of 1... 1s an end, ius gives as a means."29 He gave as an obvious example the
reason." But between these two definitions Grotius introduced another, • •r.ht to food as a means of self-preservation. Wolff also held that, besides
subjective sense of ius and this he explored in most detail: • •1111manding and prohibiting, natural law could be merely permissive,
111.lirnting behavior that was licit but not obligatory; natural rights ex-
!us is a moral quality of a person enabling one to have o r do something 1·.tt·d in this area of permissive natural law.:io One is reminded again of
justly. 77
.'II 1..-vinthnn. ed. M. Oakeshott (Oxford, 1946), 1.14, 84. Hobbes, however, was practising
25. Feinberg, "Nature and Value,H244. Hart, uNatural Rights," 180. For medieval discus- • .,.,, , nf linguistic legislation here. In normal seventeent!K-entury discourse the word ius did
sion of this question see below, 71, 74. 1 ' " "' " lhe c-xclusive sense he attributed to it, as one can gather from the texts of Suarez
. .. 0

26. ~ I~ibus 11c Dft1 ltgi.slatort, ed. L Perella, 8 vols. (Madrid, 1971~1), 1: 1.2.5, 24. • Et ..... 11 ;mti1t'l; rather the word could be used in one sense as equivalent to la, a kind of law, or
iuxta . . . strictam iuris significationem solet proprie ius vocari facultas quaedam moralis, •• • urild ht• used in a different sense to mean a subjective right. We shall find the same 'itu-
quam unusquisque habet vel circa rem suam vet ad rem sibi debitam; sic enim dominus l"l'I ''""" In nwdi<•val diSCOUl'S('.
dicitur habere ius in re et ope:rarius dicitur habere ius ad stipendium . . ." ·"' 1'1~til11ti<Jn~ j11ris nalur« l'I Jll'nlium, ed. M. Thommann in Gtsammfllt Wrrb-, Abt 2, :lb
27. ~ jurt be/Ii tt pads (Amsterdam, 1646) (reprinted Washington, D.C., 1913), 1.1.4, 2, •• •In (I hlclc•ioht•lm, I %R ll.1), 26: 1.1.46, 24. "Facultas ista, llC'U pot('lltia moral111 11gendi dicitur
H • quo sensu jus est, Qualitas moralis personae, comp<>tl'fll' 11d •liquid jui<1te habendum
••
/u• llw~l~i r r,1{11 fry11al11rtu• 11"1i, l{rl ad ji11rm. jus q11oq11r 11111 ad mrdia . ..
N

vet agendum." Ill -;.... ht•luw n. fl<;


52 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ORIGlNS OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGE 53

Habermas's "neutral sphere of personal choice" or de Lagarde's "zone of Ockham, who defined ius as "a licit power." As Villey explains things,
human autonomy." Ockham's voluntarism emphasized power rather than reason and his
By the seventeenth century, then, complex rights theories existed nominalism attributed reality to individuals rather than universals; so
in which words like "nature," "reason," "licit," "right," were interwoven his political philosophy was inevitably concerned with the powers of in-
with words like "power," "freedom," "faculty." We still need to ask: Where dividuals, which Ockham called rights.35
does this duster of ideas come from? How did these patterns of language Villey's views have been widely and often uncritically accepted. Ock-
arise? There have been many explanations, most of them concerned with ham remains by far the favorite choice as innovator among those who
the context of seventeenth century life itself. Some scholars have argued seek a pre-seventeenth-century origin for natural rights theories. But re-
that the English Levellers' claim to religious freedom was the first adapta- cently the contribution of another late medieval theologian, Jean Gerson,
tion of the old natural law tradition to defend a new doctrine of subjective has also been emphasized. Gerson did in fact give an explicit definition
natural rights.31 C. B. MacPherson discerned, behind the religious rhetoric of ius as "an immediate faculty or power pertaining to anyone according
of the age, the presuppositions of a free market economy; and he argued to right reason" and of lex as "a rule in conformity with right reason."36 So,
that these presumptions engendered a doctrine of "possessive individual- as Richard Tuck pointed out, he had already made the distinction that we
ism" in which freedom was identified with property, and natural rights encounter later in seventeenth-century works between subjective right
theories served the narrow interests of the propertied classes.32 Leo Strauss and objective law.37 We should add that Gerson also associated ius with the
called attention to the shift from final causes to efficient causes associated idea of synderesis, which he called a "superior" kind of reason, a capacity
with the Scientific Revolution. The old tradition of natural law had been for moral discernment akin to our conscience.38 So, for him, ius was pri-
concerned with human ends; in the new world of thought one had to start marily an innate power to act rightly according to reason and conscience.
from man's motives, his innate desires, which Hobbes presented as rights. This is not quite what we mean by a natural right in modem discourse. But
So rights replaced duties as the starting point for political reflection. <;erson further declared that from ius so defined it was possible to deduce,
Strauss did not regard it as a change for the better." hy a sort of mathematical reasoning, a whole theory of government and
Such views are typical of those that find the origin of modem rights property.39 He held that there were God-given rights which included lib-
theories in some aspect of the religious, economic or intellectual life of the 1·rty, "a faculty of acting or not acting," and dominion, "a right of taking
seventeenth century. Michael Oakeshott, in a seminal essay on Hobbes, inferior things for one's use and preservation."40 Gerson further associated
suggested that we need to consider the problem in a broader context; his idea of ius with the Pauline doctrine of evangelical liberty (here appar-
seventeenth-century thinkers, he suggested, were influenced not only 1·ntly following Ockham).41
by the circumstances of their own age but also by an earlier tradition of Gerson was widely quoted by later Parisian condliarists and by the
thought that they had inherited. Specifically, the skepticism and individu- Spanish scholastics of the sixteenth century. Christopher St. Germain used
alism of Hobbes were "gifts of late medieval nominalism." 34
This point of view has been worked out in most detail by Michel
JS. M. Villey, La fomiation dt la pensit juridiqut modtmt, 4th ed. (Paris, 1975), 199- 272.
Villey, whose work I have already discussed. According to Villey, the .1 6. De vita spirituali animat in r. Glorieux, ed., ftitn ~rson . Oeuvm; compl~tts, 10 vols.
modem doctrine of subjective rights emerged quite suddenly in the four- (l'.iris, 1961-73), 3:141, ")us est facultas seu potestas propinqua conveniens alicui secundum
teenth century. Its creator was the nominalist philosopher, William of •"• 1.1men rcctae rationis." The definition of lex, with a slightly different defmition of ius, is in
I ,,. 110/tslatt t cclc;iastica, Oeuvns 6 : 242, "Jus est facultas seu potestas propinqua conveniens
31. M. Roshwald argued that an ancient doctrine of natural law and a medieval empha- .1lin 1i S<'('tmdum dictamen primae justiliae . . . lex est regula conformitatem habens ad die-
sis on concrete individual rights first came together to form a theory of natural rights in the ' ·'""'" rectac rationis."
works of the LevelleTS: "'The Concept of Human Rights,H Philosophy and PhmommologiC'Jl/ Rt- 17. R. Tucic, Nat ural Rig/its Thtorits. Thtir Origin and Devtlopmtnl (Cambridge, 1979),
SMrch 19 (1958- 59): 354-379. More recently W. Garrett has suggested that medieval natural ! '• 7 ft
law served to defend the autonomy of secular government against the church; in developing 111. I >t- vita, 142. According to Gerson, man could know the universal principles of good
natural rights theories, the Levellers aimed rather to defend the religious freedom of indi· 1f111111);h t<yndn~iro and from them deduce particular rules o f action . On syndert"!iis in m•'·
viduals against the state: " Religion, Law, and the Human Condition." Sociologicnl Annlys1~ 47 ,,,..,,.,,, 11,1tural /;1w th<'Ories stt M. B. Cmwe. Thr Changing f>rofilt of lht' Nal11rn/ l.11111 (11w
(1987): 1- 34. I l.1.:111·. 1977), 12..1 -JS.
32. P~sive Individualism, 1- 4, 220-238. 1•1 llr 1•ila, 14:\.
33. Natural Right and History, 166, 180- 181. 411 llr l'iln, 14'>.
34. Introduction to l..tviathan. liii. ·I I /I,· 1•1/11. 17•1
54 THE IDEA Of NATURAL RIGHTS ORIGINS OF NATURAL R IGITTS LANGUAGE 55

his work in England. And Suarez listed the specific c~apters in whic_h canonists and to endless conflict in the sphere of real-life politics. (The text
Gerson discussed the meaning of ius as among the maJOr sources of hIS .1lso provided the starting point for one of Gerson's most detailed discus-
own treatise, De legibus. Oearly, then, Gerson was very influential. lt is not .;ions on the rights of rulers.)0 Since neither the spiritual nor temporal
so dear though that his views on rights--or those of Ockham-were also power could wholly dominate the other, medieval government never con-
highly innovative. . )~<>aled into a rigid theocratic absolutism in which rights theories could
lf we are to find an earlier origin for natural rights theones we need to never have taken root. Instead, in the vigorous, fluid, expanding society
look for patterns of language in which ius naturale meant, not only natu~l of the twelfth century, old rights were persistently asserted and new
law or cosmic harmony, but also a faculty or abil~ty or power of ~~iv1d­ 1 mes insistently demanded. A great feudal lord could enjoy simultane-

ual persons, associated with reason and moral dtSCernment, defining_an uusly all the rights enumerated in Hohfeld's modem classification-a
area of liberty where the individual was free to act as he pleased,_leadmg daim to rents and services, a power to do justice, an immunity from ex-
on to specific claims and powers of humans qua humans. I want finally to 1.-rnal jurisdiction, a liberty to, say, hunt in the neighboring forest. Cathe-
argue that this whole complex of associated ideas, this la~ce work of !an- dral canons asserted their rights against bishops. Bishops and barons de-
guage, first grew into existenc~ in the wo~ks of the ~ed1eval Decretists. l1·nded their rights against kings. Newly-founded communes sometimes
The authors we shall need to d1scuss-Rufinus and Ricardus and Huguc- I •ought their rights and sometimes fought for them. (In the twelfth century
cio and Alanus and others whose names have been forgotten-are not >~rants of rights were often made to corporate groups, but as A. L. Harding
much read nowadays except by specialists in this field. None of them h.1s pointed out, they were commonly rights of a kind that could be actu-
wrote an accessible, explicit little treatise on natural rights, which perhaps .11ly exercised only by individual persons.44) Even peasants, emigrating to
helps to explain why they are not much noticed in modem histories of the '' lt1nd new villages in the still vast expanses of forest and wasteland, could
concept. Their patterns of thought hav~ to be ~onstruct~d from scat- • l.lim enhanced liberties from lords who needed fresh supplies of labor.•~
tered, sometimes laconic glosses on a vanety of topics. There ts no on~ ~ext Medieval people first struggled for survival; then they struggled for rights.
that could find a place in the canon of " great books" on Western pohtical Of course all these rights were rights of particular persons or classes;
theory. But the Decretists' views were widely diffused in the law schools •lwy provide only a background for our inquiry into the origins of natu-
of Europe by the end of the twelfth century and, transmitted in eclectic 1.11 rights theories. But, before turning to that theme, we need to consider
works like the ordinary gloss to the Decretum and Guido de Baisio's Rosar- ··• 1111e other aspects of medieval life. It is unprofitable, perhaps, to ask

ium, they continued to influence late medieval writers, not least Ockham whether the twelfth century "discovered" the individual. I suspect that in
and Gerson. Gerson himself mentioned the opening chapters of the De- .ill cultures some persons are more self-aware than others, more given to
cretum in introducing his discussion of rights. He proposed to ~ollow_ a ...11t·ction on individual experience. But twelfth-century civilization was
different methodology, he wrote, but added, "We shall not say things dif- • ··rt<1inly marked by a new emphasis on personalism or humanism, and
42
ferent from others, though perhaps differently." •t lound expression on many levels of thought and feeling. Courtly love
l111·rature explored the joys and pains of human lovers. Religious piety
• 11llivated an intense emotional relationship between the individual Chris-
CANONISTIC RIGHTS LANGUAGE-CONTEXTS " ·"' and the person of Jesus. Peter Abelard taught that the moral value of
Let us begin with the twelfth-century world i~ which the can~nists . 111 .ict was determined entirely by individual intention. Private scrutiny

lived and taught. Medieval society was saturated with a concern for rights. • 01rnnscience, followed by private confession, became a common practirt•.
At the very highest level popes asserted rights against emperors and em- " "' h concern for human persons could easily lead on to reflection about
perors against popes. The papal claim to " rights of heav~y and earthly li11111an rights. Twelfth-century culture was also characterized by a gre<1t
empire'' (terreni simul et celestis imper~i iura), incl~ded in Gratian's Decretum llnurish ing of new centers of corporate life--communes, guilds, confra-
at Dist. 22 c.l, gave rise to extensive theoretical argument among the 1.·111ilit•s, collegiate churches, monastic houses; but we have learnt-d lo
H I >q10lr.<taf(', 236.
42. Dt uito, 143, " . . . non quidem alia dkturus quam alii, quamquam forte ali_tl'r.• H /\ I.. I larding, Hrolitical Liberty in the Middle Ag~.H Sptc11/um 55 (1980): 423 - '14:\.
Gerson did not overtly quote ca.nonistic texts as frequently as his master in theol?8Y•. P1l'rre ~ ·· ( l11 rm11i\nl Hindividuali!\m H~t't" A. Macfllrlarw, Th, OriKi"s of ["Kli~h fmli11iduoliJnt
d ' Ailly. But he was intel'\9ely interested in canon law, partly indt'ed hl'<"aU!lt' of h111 d111sat111· 11 ""' " ' 111~1·. 1'17'l) I 1luut>I wlwlh••r lh<" En~li.•h •'><pNlt'tlC•' w,,,. ''" •'~<'t'pllo"-'111" tht• aulhnr
faction with the state of the dlsciplin<' 11t the beginning of lht> fiflN•nth ('('ntury. "'"l'lt.C"'r"
}H; lt»;A OF NAT\JllAL l<t~Hrs ORIGINS OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGE 57

understand that the corporatism of the age was not antithetical to its in- ··ndeavors." 49 Tuck found in the twelfth-century glosses only an inade-
dividualism but complementary.46 •111ate theory of passive rights, apparently because the glossators of Roman
Among all the "renaissances" of the twelfth century the one most J.1w referred to dominium as a right that could be claimed or asserted
significant for us was the revival of legal studies, first the recovery of the .1gainst all other persons (but Tuck's argument grows very fuzzy at this
whole corpus of Roman law, then the reordering of the confused mass of l'oint in his work}.50
church law that had accumulated over many centuries in the Decretum of Neither Villey nor Tuck paid much attention to the treatment of ius
Gratian (c. 1140), "the first comprehensive and systematic legal treatise 111 the canonists' writings. Tuck found in their work only a collection of

in the history of the West," according to Harold Berman. The concern with • l.lim rights again, and Villey an assertion of legal or moral precepts. Both
individual intention, individual consent, individual will that character- .1uthors were interested mainly in investigating the origin of active rights,
ized twelfth-century culture spilled over into many areas of canon law. In 111.; conceived of as liberty or power, and they seem to have found little to

marriage law, by the end of the twelfth century, the simple consent of two 111tcrest them in the work of the Decretists. Tuck, for instance, suggested
parties, without any other formalities, could .constitute a valid, .sac:a- iii.it Gerson was the first to treat liberty as a right. But in fact Gratian him-
mental marriage. In contract law, a bare promise could create a b~n~mg ····lf wrote of the iura libertatis, the rights of liberty, that could never be lost
obligation-it was the intention of the promisor ~hat counted. In.cnmi~al however long a man was held in bondage.51 And the association of right
law, the degree of guilt and punishment was agam related to the mtention .111J power, ius and potestas (Ockham's "semantic revolution" according to
of the individual defendant, and this led on, as in modem legal systems, to V1llcy), was commonplace in twelfth-century canonistic discourse. The
complex considerations about negligence and. d~minished respon~ibility, 1•.1pal election decree incorporated into the Decrelum at Dist. 23 c.1 referred
areas of Jaw that we nowadays think of as mediating between the nghts of I•• "'the right of the power to elect" (ius potestatis eligere). In discussing the
individuals and the maintenance of public order.47 ·.1.1tus of bishops-elect, Huguccio wrote simply, "They have the power
Given this whole background, one might expect to find an emphasis " ' .1dministering that is the right of administering." 52 Gratian attributed
also on individual rights in the works of twelfth-century academic law- tu !he pope a right (i11s) of establishing laws (surely an active right), and
yers. vmey was reluctant to admit this. He acknowledged that, in vul~ar l I 11~uccio observed that since the pope had been given the right, therefore
medieval discourse, the word ius might be used carelessly to mean an in- lw had full power in this matter.53 lnnocent III referred to the right of elect-
dividual right, but he argued that this usage could not infect academic " ''~ .is afncultas and a glossator paraphrased his words by describing the
jurisprudence until Oc.k ham had provided a new philosophy to j~tify ••r.ht (ius} as a "free power." 54
it.ca But the evidence against his position is overwhelming. Indeed V11ley Such examples could be multiplied. Individual rights were important
himself, and Tuck too, following Villey, saw that a doctrine of subjective '" 1he canonists. They had to be protected. In the ordinary glosses to both
rights was implicit in the civilian glossators' treatment of dominion-own- ti ... Vt>cretum and the Decretals, the standard medieval commentaries on
ership, rulership, mastery-as a kind of right. ~either of th~ tw~ m~em 11 ..- lt'xts, we can read that no one was to be deprived of his right except
authors, however, seemed interested in following up the implication of
his own argument. Villey wrote dismissively that the writings of the civi- ·I' ' ~1.e 'jus in re' d u droit romain dassique au droit modeme,H in Conftrtncts faites a l'ln-
lian glossators were full of "contradictions and hesitations and frustrated ' ''"' 1t.- / Jro1t Romain (Paris, 1950), 187- 225, at 190.
·~ •. SN- below, 218 n. 32.
46. The best overview o! twelfth century culture is R. L. Benson and G. Constable, eds., " t lh'rrtt11m Gr-atiam . .. una cum glossis (Venice, 1600), C.16 q.3 dictum post c.15.
Re114issance and Rennuol in tht Twelfth Century (Cambridge, Mass., 1982). See especially the " -' I luguccio, Summa ad Dist. 23.c.1, MS Admont 7, fol. 29rb, u • • • habent poteslatem
contribution of J. F. Benton to this volume, HConsciousness of Self and Perceptions of lndi· •· h11mi,.trandi id est ius administrandi sed non habent execulionem iUius iuris in actu."
vidualityH(263- 295). For an introduction to various aspects of tweJfth-<entury individu~lism " 1 ( ·.2..o; q. t diclum post c.16; Huguccio ad Dist. 4 dictum post c.3, MS Admonl 7, fol. 6vb.
sa C. Morris, ~ DisCX11Jeryoflltt lndividual, 1050-1200 (London, 1972) and the further _hte:a· "·I llrrrl'lall's D. Grl'Korii Papat IX cum glossis (Lyons, 1614), 1.4.8 "... ius eligc ndi •h-
ture cited in the discussion between Caroline Bynum and Morris in Journal of E.ccles1as flcal i·''""' .11tiudicart> curelis, ut sic de caetero liberam habeant facultalem ... eligendi. ..."
History 31 (1980): 1- 17 and 195-206. The q uestion of co rporatism and individualism is also 11..- • ,,.,,~ 11£ tht> GI~ Ordinarill has " . . . adiudicent monachis . .. ius eligendi abbatf'm, ut
comidered here. fOl" further discussion on this see below, 208 ff. 1o1..· 11m1 h.1b<-11nt potest11tem . . . eligendi. ..." For many e llamples of iu' u!led In a !lubjectlv«'
47. The most recent full-scale treatment of these themes is H. Bennan, U1w and Rtvofu · •r• ,.,.. tu mt'an an individual right in thirtttnth-century canonistic tellls, !lee C ). Rt>id, -rltr>
tion. Tltt Formation of the Western Legal Tradition (Cambridge, Mass., 1983). • '"'""""k <"nntribulion to lh«' Wl'l'I""' Right11 Tradition: An Historical Inquiry," 1!.l!llo11 Col
'°"
t. r '"" Rr1•il'111 JJ ( IWI ): .17 - 92.
~~~9---
THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGKTS ORIGlNS OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGE 59
58

for grave cause.55 The canonists also understood dearly the difference To distinguish thus between universal natural law and varying human
between claim rights and active rights; and around 1200 they developed practices may seem to be a typical medieval tactic. The difficulties arose
a technical vocabulary to distinguish between them-the terms ius ad hecause, when Gratian sought to buttress his initial definition with canon-
rem and ius in re that were still being used by Suarez in his seventeenth- ical authorities and to pursue their implications, his argument led to a
morass of internal contradictions, or apparent contradictions. After giving
century rights theory.
All this is reasonably straightforward. In a world where rights were his opening definition, Gratian quoted in support of it some words of
constantly being asserted and demanded, the language of the jurists re- Isidore of Seville:
56
flected the realities of their age. The context serves to explain the texts. All laws are either divine or human. Divine laws stand by nature, human
The point would hardly be worth making except that it has been disputed. by usage. Fas is divine law, ius is human law. To pass through another's
But we have still not reached the heart of the problem. We have not yet ad- field is fas, it is not ius.511
dressed the question of when and how a doctrine of natural rights came to
We shall have to return to fas and ius. But to continue with Gratian's ar-
be asserted. To understand this we have to tum from the social and cul-
>~ument: He went on to present another text of Isidore which included
tural context of the canonists to the fundamental, tangled text that they
multiple descriptions of the content of natural law:
labored to expound, Gratian's Concordantia discordantium canon11m, com-
monly known as the Decretum. This text itself forms part of the context that Natural law (ius) is the law common to all peoples, in that it is every-
we need to understand if we are to interpret adequately the discourse of where held by instinct of nature, not by any enactment: as, for instance,
twelfth-century canonists. the union of man and woman, the generation and rearing of children, the
common possession of all things and the one liberty of all, the acquisition
o f those things which are taken from air and land and sea; also the return
CANONISTIC RIGHTS LANGUAGE-TEXTS of a thing deposited or money loaned, the repulsion of force by force.59

The canonists could not avoid detailed scrutiny of the term ius natu- Some difficulties may already be apparent. The texts cited in support
rale because Gratian chose to base his whole structure of jurisprudence on
1 •I Gratian's opening definition did not contain the Golden Rule that con-
an initial distinction between natural law and human usages, set out in ..11tuted natural law for Gratian himself. Moreover Isidore's natural law
w .1s not a rule enjoined by scripture, like Gratian's, but a product of in-
the first words of the Decretum:
·.1inctual behavior. And, again, Isidore's natural law included principles
The human race is ruled by two (means) namely by natural law and by ""' evidently compatible with scripture. Isidore, for instance, wrote of
usages. Natural law {ius) is what is contained in the Law and the Gospel • 11111mon property as an aspect of natural law, but scripture recognized
by which each is commanded to do to another what he wants done to I'' iv<1te possessions.
himself and forbidden to do to another what he does not want done to There are various other anomalies in the first chapters of the Decretum
himself. 57 1 111 it will be enough for our purpose to pursue the argument about prop-
1

"' ' Y· Apparently unaware of any difficulties, Gratian forged serenely


.1lw.1d. Natural law, he wrote, held primacy over all others in time and dig-
55. Glo:ss ad Dist. 56 c.7; Gloss ad X.4.13.11. 111ly for it began with the origin of rational creatures and remained always
56. Jn emphasizing contexts, I am not suggesting any kind of historical determinism.
Of course different persons respond differently to the same situation. Among the twelfth-
111111mtable. It differed from human law because, by natural law, "all things
century canonists, for instance, Huguccio and Alanus held sharply opposed views on the .11•· rnmmon to all," whereas human law had established private prop-
rights of popes and emperors. But to understand either Huguccio or Alanus we have lo
know something about the context of papal-imperial relations at the end of the twelfth ct'rl- "" 1>1.<I . I c.1. HOmnes leges aut divinae s unt, aut humanae. Oivinae natura, humanal"
tury and about the context of Decretist thought within which ~th authors w~rk~. . "'"""11" ,·on.o;tant.. . . Fas lex divina est, ius lex humana. Transire per agrum alienum fas !'!II,
57. Dist. t, dictum arrtt c.1. HHumanum genus duobus regitur, naturale v1dehcet 1ure et ftt"t ...... . ~ .. ~·

moribus. !us naturale est, quod in lege et Evangelio continetur: quo quisque iubetur alii '•'' I >isl. t c.7, ..lus naturale est commune omni um nationum eo quod ubique instinctu
facere quod sibi vult fieri et prohibetur alii inferre quod sibi noli fieret.Hlbere is now an En- '"'""'"' mm «>rl.,titulione aliqua hab<>tur, ut viri ('I feminae roniunctio. libemrum 11ucces.\i11
glish translation of the first twenty Distinction~ of the Decrtlum toget~r with the glos" ••I •·•hu .ttin, .-ommuni8 umnium ~~sio, ('t omnium una libcrtas, acquisilio rorum <JUllt'
of Johannes Teutonicus. See Gratian. Tht Trul1se of Laws With thr Ordinary C.111!<..~. '"'""· • .... 1... I•·• r.1. 1mnit1111• <"••piuntur, llt•m cl1•ptl\\i1111• n•i 11('1 comnwncfatar prnmill<' n'l'ltltutiu, vlo·
A. Thompson and J. Gordley (Washington D.C., 199:\). 1..nlln1• I '"' 111111 n•pul~ln "
60 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RJGHTS ORIGINS OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGE 61

erty.60 Finally, Gratian declared that any human law contrary to natural which example refers to which meaning. But lest the mind of some idiot
law was to be held null and void.61 The conclusion seems obvious. The be confused we shall carefully assign each one.... 61
human law instituting private property was null and void. But Gratian And he proceeded to do so. Already by 1160 Stephanus had found five
really had no intention of asserting any such doctrine. In his own day both uwanings for ius naturale and, a little later, an English canonist gave nine,
canon and civil law recognized the licitness of individual property, and 1.mging from "the order and instinct of nature" to an impenetrable meta-
Gratian simply took the fact for granted throughout the whole subsequent l'hysical definition. "Others have said that natural ius is an extrapre-
argument of the Decretum. In Causa 12, for instance, he wrote that even a 1 licamental something including both the mode of existing as essence

bishop could have private property. .md as being."64 In reading these texts one encounters a persistently re-
The implicit contradiction was never discussed by Gratian himself. ' 11rring problem. Gratian himself used the word ius consistently to desig-
But the canonists who commented on the texts of the Decretum from about n .1tc systems of objective law in the opening chapters of the Decretum-e.g.
1150 onward could see the difficulties inherent in them at least as dearly as lw considered in tum natural law, customary law, civil law, military law,
any modem reader can; and almost at once they realized that the apparent 1•uhlic law as different species of ius; but the canonists who commented on
incoherence in Gratian's thought and language arose from the fact that the l11s texts lived in a world where, in everyday discourse, the word ius com-
texts he presented used the term ius naturale in several different senses.62 rnonly meant a subjective right. Hence, in their commentaries, they would
If one could discriminate between them, the apparent difficulties might ·.hift from one meaning to the other, unreflectively it seems, and without
be resolved. As Ricardus Anglicus pointed out, there was no incoherence ..,.Ping any need for explanation, evidently confident that their meaning
if ius naturale in one meaning of the term contradicted ius naturale in w11uld be plain to contemporary readers. Thus, where Gratian discussed
some other meaning. (So private property might be contrary to natural , 11stomary law as a form of ius, the Ordinary Gloss commented that a cus-
law in one sense of the term, but in accordance with it in another sense.) 10111 was not established by repeated usage unless there was actually an
It soon became a common exegetical technique among the early Decretists 111t1•ntion to establish it, and then added, casually introducing the subjec-
to provide long lists of all the possible meanings of the term ius naturale- 1rv t' meaning of ius, that this was true even when a person acted by virtue
including, perhaps, some that no one had thought of before. Huguccio ex- ..1 his right (iure suo).65 Another example occurs at the very first chapter
plained the problem to his students near the beginning of his great Summa •• 1 lhe Decretum (Dist. l.c.l) where Isidore distinguished between divine
on the Decretum (c. 1190): 11.1tural law {/as) and human law. The natural law defined in Gratian's
Note that not all the examples of ius naturale given here refe.r to the same 11wn opening dictum as the Golden Rule was dearly a precept, a divine
meaning of ius naturale; therefore a prudent reader will carefully discern , urnmand. But fas has rather the sense of what is permissible or allow-
.1hl1• or rightful, and this meaning was suggested by Isidore's example,
60. Dist. 8 dictum ante c.l. "Nam iure naturali omnia sunt communia omnibus. .. . Iu.re ·· li.1 pass through another's field." The Ordinary Gloss, commenting on this,
vero consuetudinis vel ronstitutionis hoc meum est, illud alterius."
11-.1·d the word i11s to mean both a body of law and what was permitted
61. Dist. 8 dictum post c.l, "Quaecunque enim vel moribus recepta sunt, vel scriptis com-
prehensa, si naturali iure fuerint adversa, vana et irrita habenda sunt." loy law-what we might call a right. " It is permitted by divine law (i1m
62. Very few of the twelfth century rommentaries on the Decr"ttum have been edited. d11 i1w), nevertheless it is not a right (ius) because it is not permitted by
1

However, many particular passages relating to natural law have bee.n printed in modem I 11 unan law (iure humano)."66 For us the concepts of objective law and sub-
works. Some important texts were included in S. Kuttner's seminal Repertorium der Knnon·
istilc, 1140-1234 (Vatican City, 1937). Others were collected by 0. Lot.tin, Le droit nnturel cha 1o l. ~umma ad Disl. 1 c.6, MS Admont 7, fol. 3vb, " Et nota quod non omnia exempla iurlii
Saini Thomas tt ses prl~rs, 2nd ed. (Bruges, 1931). 'The most ample collection of texts is .... 111r.1lis hie posita referuntur ad eandem acceptionem iuris natural.is. Ergo prudenti~ lt•r -
provided by R. Weigand, D~ Naturm:hlskhre der Legisten und Dekretisten von lrnuius bis Ac· 1. •• •~ •·rit caute discemere quod exemplum ad quam acceptionem iuris naturalis r<'frra
cursius und von Cration l1is /ohannfS Teulonicus {Munich, 1967). But the authors interested in 1111 St·tl ne ydiote animus in hoc confundatur, de quolibet dilige nter as.signabimus" (Cf.

canonistic doctrines on natura.1 law have not considered the importance of their texts for w ..,,..,..,,.t, 214). Earlier. in his introductory remarks (MS Admont ? . fol. 2va). Hugucrio wrnlt•.
later theories of natural rights. Lottin observed (97), "Or, on ne voit nulle part ce demier t ' '" 1..•m• intdlectis facile erit aptare sequentia cont·raria iuris naturalis, scilicel que ad qua~
sense subjectif (du terme ius) dans la littttature du XIIe et du XDle siecle" (though his own ... , ··1•tion<.'S pl'rtincant et rereruntur." For the comment of Ricardus see Weigand, 39'.\.
texts hardly support this conclusion). In the following discussion I have taken some texts M Nal11rrtchtslrhrr, 148, 200, " Alii di>1erunt ius naturale esse q uiddam extra pl'l'tlkn·
from Weigand. Where I have used my own manuscript transcriptions and Weigand provide!! 1>u·11t11h· ha~nh'm ~imul modum exi!itendi per se ut l'll..'lt'ntiabile res et ens...
a similar transcription from another source, or a partial transcription, I have given a crO!l!I• 1.•, Cl<l!l-'I ntl lli.<I. I c.5, " . . . c tiitm si suo iun• id fai:t>n•t . .."
reference to NaturrtehtsWire. (Weigand sometimes omits phra!l('fl which !\re iiignifinmt for tol• ( ;(""""" /J1s/. 1 r . I. " . . . f;u..~t. hi t~t iun•<tivlno p..rmillitur, im1 .1uh·m non t••t. id ,.,.1
our argument.) """ p t•r m l1111ur iun• humnnn." l.111t•r 11n. wlwn I lrn11t•m1I~ w.111!<'11111 rl'f1•r to" riKhl dnlv1•1I
62 THE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHTS ORIGlNSOf NAlURAL RJGHTS LANGUAGE

jective right are clearly distinguishable, but in medieval discourse the Rufinus used the word demonstrationes to mean "descriptions," "indi-
word iu.s could oscillate easily between the two meanings. , .1tions," of behavior that was licit but not required. So in one of its mean-
It is the same when we tum to the multiple meanings of the term 111gs ius naturale referred to an area of permitted behavior where "na-
ius naturale, presented in the Decretist glosses. The everyday use of ius to ture does not command or forbid." The explanation that community of
mean a right, a rightful power, infected the language of the canonists when l'mperty belonged only to the "demonstrations" of natural law (which
they came to write of ius naturale. They occasionally gave a Stoic interpre- rnuld be changed by civil law) was widely accepted. But both parts of
tation of the term as meaning a force pervading the whole cosmos; usually tlie argument were very important, the initial subjective definition of
they included Gratian's view that ius naturale was a code of moral law m s and the following tripartite division. We shall need to consider each
revealed through scripture and also accessible to reason; but often they 111 tum.

added a subjective definition of the term that was not evidently present "Natural ius is a certain force.. . ." We do not know the precise
in Gratian's texts at all. '" •urce of this formula if there is an earlier source (though, obviously, one
A particularly influential discussion was presented by Rufinus, writ- 1·. reminded of Cicero's innata vis). But, whatever the source, the definition

ing about 1160. Like many later natural rights theorists, Rufinus first Ii.id a great success, and it was taken up and reformulated, with frequent
described a primitive condition of humankind after the Fall of Adam. Men \·.iriations of language, by many later canonists.
then were reduced almost to the status of brute beasts, but they retained Odo of Dover (c. 1170) wrote, closely following Rufinus:
just enough traces of natural right 67 to come together in order to enter into
compacts with one another and so establish the first body of law. Then More strictly, natural ius is a certain force divinely inspired in man by
Rufinus went on to offer his own definition of ius naturale. It was quite dif- which he is led to what is right and equitable.69
ferent from the original definition of Gratian that he was supposed to be
I ·c •r Simon of Bisignano:
commenting on.
Natural ius is said to be a force of the mind the superior part of the soul,
Natural ius is a certain force instilled in every human creature by nature
namely reason which is called sinderesis.70
to do good and avoid the opposite. Natural ius consists in three things,
commands, prohibitions and demonstrations. . . . It cannot be detracted
I or Sicardus:
from at all as regards the commands and prohibitions . .. but it can be as
regards the demonstrations, which nature does not command or forbid l11s is called natural . . . from human nature, that is a certain force or
but shows to be good, and this is especially so as regards the liberty of all
power naturally instiJled in man....71
and common property, for nowadays, by civil law, this slave is mine, this
field is mine. 68

........latis, prohibitionibus, demonstrationlbus. ... Detractum autem ei non est utique in


from civil law, he wrote, " ... ius de iure civile proveniens" (L«ture ad X.1.2.7). ln the same " ' ""' l;1tis vel prohibitionibus . .. sec! in demonstrationibus-que scilicet natura non vetat
passage he referred to a " . . . ius quod omnibus competit de iure naturali ... " The word """ prohibet, sed bona esse ostendit~t maxime in omnium una libertate et communi
glides from one meaning to another in a single terse phrase. I have often retained the Latin 1·• ~.~..s..~ione; nunc enim iure civili hie est servus meus, ille est ager tuus." On acquisition of
word ius in the English te.>ct above because frequently the sense cannot be rendered ade- l'"'l"'''Y and natural law, see the texts collected by Weigand, 307-361. Underlying much of
quately either by "right" or "law." ,,,.. .ir~umentation was the Roman law doctrine that, according to natural reason, dominium
67. Or " natural force." Some manuscripts have ius he.r e and some vis. Since Rufinus went ""' " .1n111irro by the first occupant of a res nullius. For further background see Janet Cole-
on at once to define ius T!lltur11le as a vis he could easily have WTitten either word. See "'""· .. l'mper1y and Poverty" in J. H . Bums, ed., Tire Camflridge History of Mtdirool Pn/itical
H. Singer, ed., Die Summa Decretorum des Magister Rufinus (Paderbom, 1902), 4, "Cum itaque ' '"'".~/11 (C ·ambridge, 1988), 607-648.
naturalis vis (ius) in homine penitus extincta non esset . . . deliberavit homo cum proximis ,,., Wt•igand, Nalurrrchtslthrt, 161. Nin tertia significatione et strictiori dicitur ius naturalt•
convenire et mutuis utilitatibus consulere .. . et rertas pactiones inire que quidem ius "'" •1111•, l11m diuinitus homini inspirata qua ad id quod iustum est et equum ducitur."
gentium appellantur." The doctrine of Rufinus is considered more fully in my " lus and I ll lhid., 17.l, "Cum autem ius natura.le dicatur esse ws mentis . . . Nobis itaqut' uidt'tur
Metonymy in Rufinus," in R. Castillo Lara, ed., Studia in honorem emintntissimi Cardinali~ 'I""'' h1!1 uaturalc est superior pars anime, ipsa uidelicet ratio, que sinderesi11 appellatur ..."
Alphonsi M. Stickler (Rome, 1992), 549·58. I'" 11th .., h•d!I idcnlifyinK iu$ nnluralt as ~ind~rtSis see Wt'igand, 177, IS7.
68. Ibid., 6-7. "Est itaque nafurale ius vis quedarn humane cl'l'atun• 11 nnlurt' lnsita ad fa . ·11 lhicl., IR4. " Nam lm1 naturall' dicilur . . . 01b humana natura, hix· t'lll qm>dam ul11 1•1
ciendum bonum cavendumque contrarium. Consi.<1lit autt'm iu11 n111h11111l.. h1 I rih1111, N<·ilin-t: I '' 1tr11t I" homlnl natmnllh•r ln11lta a.J fnch•ndum htmum t•t ult"mlum 1..'0l'\lrnrium."
64 THE IDEA OF NAllJRAL RIGHTS
ORIGINS OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGE 65
Ricardus Anglicus explained: Huguccio did not maintain a consistent distinction here between ius and
Some say that natural ius is free will ... Others say that it is charity ... lt'X; like his contemporaries he sometimes used the terms interchange-
others say that natural ius is the superior part of the soul, namely rea- .1bly.16 But he was distinguishing dearly between a subjective and an
son.... We reject none of these.n
objective sense of the term ius naturale and asserting that the subjective
·~
Richard Tuck suggested that Gerson was the first to define ius as an ability -;ense was the primary one. Moreover he was insistent about this. On Gra-
or faculty; but this language too occurs in the twelfth-century glosses. Ac- tian's view of ius naturale as what was contained in the Old Law and the
cordine; to the English Summa, In nomine: ( ;ospel, he wrote, "If audacity be granted, I will safely say that this is
Natural ius is a certain ability by which man is able to discern between improperly called ius naturale."77 Huguccio made the same point when
good and evil. and in this sense natural ius is a faculty ... and this is free he discussed the varied content of ius naturale in the text of Isidore at
wiJJ.'3 I>ist. 1 c.7. In modem discourse some of the items listed by Isidore would
So far, of course, we are not dealing with any overt theory of natural rights; h<' regarded as rules of natural law ("the return of money loaned") while
but it may already be evident that the subjective understanding of ius that others seem more like examples of natural rights ("the repulsion of force
Gerson took as the starting point of his rights theory, "a faculty or power in hy force"). Huguccio commented on this text, "The things set out here
accordance with right reason," associated with free choice and syndere- .ire not natural ius or natural iura but each is an effect of ius naturale or
sis, was no novelty of late medieval theology; it had already found ample dl'rives from it." 78 Instances of natural law or natural rights were both,
expression in the glosses on the Deere/um two centuries earlier. .iccording to Huguccio, effects of ius naturale understood in a more funda-
Many Decretists included a definition of ius naturale as a kind of sub- nwnt_al sense. In his more lenient moods, Huguccio did acknowledge
jective fo~c~ _or power inherent in human personality, along with many that rns nnturale could mean a rule of conduct, a "judgment of reason";
other defimtions. But the g.r eatest of them all, Huguccio, was unusual in hut this was a secondary, derivative meaning. For Huguccio, ius naturafe
insisting that this was the one primary and proper meaning of the term. 111 its primary sense was always an attribute of individual persons, "a force

According to his definition, "natural ius ic; cnlled reason, namely a natural nl the soul," associated with human rationality.
force of the soul. . . ." Huguccio added that, in a second sense, the te rm In reading the language of the twelfth-century canonists or Ger-
could be used to refer to the moral laws known through reason, which ·.on's later adaptations of it, one is often reminded of the Stoic doctrine of
could be summed up in the scriptural rule "Do not do to others what ·' natural law in man. But a decisive shift of meaning and emphasis oc-
you do not want done to yourself."74 All this seems conventional enough. ' urred in the twelfth century. For some of the Stoics and for Cicero there
Huguccio was apparently just following Gratian. But then the argument w .1s a force in man through which he could d iscern ius naturale, the objec-

took a sudden turn. Huguccio declared sharply that this second mean- llv<• natural law that pervaded the whole universe; but for the canonists
~g-Gratian's own meaning-expressed an improper understanding of 111~ 11nturale itself could be defined as a subjective force or faculty or power
1us naturale. We ought to say that moral precepts are effects of natural ius or • •1 ability inherent in human persons. Although such definitions do not

that they derive from natural ius rather than that they are natural ius.75 111 themselves express a doctrine of natural rights, once the term ius natu-
, ,,,,.was clearly defined in this subjective sense the argument could easily
n . Ibid., 212, HDicunt enim quidam quod ius naturale sit liberum arbitrium . .. 11111vt• in either direction, to specify natural laws that had to be obeyed or
Alii dicunt quod sit caritas . .. Alii dicunt quod ius naturale est superior pars anime, ratio
scilicet ... NuUorum sententiam reprobamus.H 11.1tural rights that could licitly be exercised; and canonistic argument
73. Kuttner, Repertorium, 202, "Quarto modo dicitur ius naturale habilitas quedam qua ·.non did move in both directions. Stoic authors, when they wrote of ius
homo statim est habilis ad discemendum inter bonum e t malum: et secundum hoc dicitur
ius naturale facultas-hoc est liberum arbitrium.u Kuttner printed parallel passages from
'lh. A!!. noted above, this was also typical of seventeenth-century usage (above n. 28).
two other related works whkh also described ius naturalt as a faculty or ability (cf. Weigand,
l\t..,....v,·r I ft>bbes's attempt at " linguistic legislation"
did not succeed. /us continued to havr
197). See Tuck, Natural Rights, 26, and my "Tuck on Rights,H 438.
74. Ms. Admont 7, fol. 2rb (Introduction), Hlus ergo naturale dicitur ratio, scilicet natu- '"''" """ming:1 as long as works on law or political theory were written in Latin. It is thr
.,,,...,. with ( ~·rs<>n. Although he distinguished between ius and ltx when giving formal defl-
ralis uis animi ex qua homo discemit inter bonum et malum ... Dicitur etiam secundo loco
"'"""~ lw ,.ftt•n uS<-d tilt' words interchangeably in other contexts.
ius naturale iudicium rationis ... et ut breuiter dicam, nolle aliis farere qtK>d tibi non uis
Tl ··u.,,1,.. si auditlia detur. dico uerbum l't'CUre, quod hoc i1L~ improprit' dicitur n11tu-
fieri ... "(cf. Weigand, 215-216).
, ,,1,. ·· (Inf 2rh)
75. u5ec1 in hac acceptione improprie dicitur ius natural<• nun •111u1lllh<'I t.tlium 4u11li.1
diximus contineri in hoc acceptione potius "it t'rft'<"hl~ iuri" nahirall• 11rl 11h r n , ,,.,..., •.,,1,11111•1 '/ H Sum""' 1111 1>i~I . I cf>, MS A<lmcmt 7, fol . Jv;t, "Nam ra •1u.• hil' ponu11111r non "'"''
ad ipsum ex iun• naturali tenl'i\tur quiio quam "it iu• '"'turAlr" (lul Jtlil s...1•1•111ttlit,..t •~I•• l'~t c•ffrt·h" lurl~ naturnlt" uc•l nh c'<I •Ir
111 • '"'htr.111' tH•I iur.1 11.tt11ri\li'1. . .
ft••·11.lll .. {11 Wr111,11111I, 71'1)
66 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ORIGINS OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGE 67

Mturale, were thinking mainly in terms of cosmic determinism; the canon- the Ordinary Gloss occurs here in the specific context of natural law and
ists were thinking more in terms of human free choice. When the con- natural right.
cept of ius 1tllturale was associated in the canonists' glosses with words Other early glossators of the Bolognese school defined natural ius
like ''power," "faculty," "free will," it was moving in a different semantic as conduct that was "licit and approved." But the dearest use of such
field of force so to speak, and took on new meanings. Stoic reflection on language to specify "a zone of human autonomy," "a neutral sphere of
ius naturale never led to a doctrine of natural rights; canonistic reflection personal choice," is found in a group of English glossators of the 1180s
did so, and quickly. who wove together in a new synthesis the idea of a permissive natu-
To carry the argument further, we need to recall the common modem ral ius, Isidore's definition of fas at the beginning of the Decretum, and
view that to have a right is to enjoy a sphere of personal liberty, a "zone Paul's words to the Corinthians, "All things are licit for me." The author
of autonomy," an area of licit choice where the right holder is free to of the Summa, In nomine, who defined ius naturale in one sense as a fac-
act as he pleases. Alongside the definitions we have considered so far ulty or ability, gave as another meaning of the term:
of ius as a subjective moral force or power inhering in individuals, we
fos natura/e . . . licit and approved, neither commanded nor forbidden
also encounter this precise understanding of ius naturale in some of the
by the Lord or by any statute, which is also called fas, as for instance to
twelfth-century glosses. The authors commonly took as a starting point
reclaim one's own or not to reclaim it, to eat something or not to eat it, to
the second part of Rufinus' definition, that we have not explored so far, put away an unfaithful wife or not to put her away . . . whence, upon
the tripartite division of natural law into commands, prohibitions, and the words of the Apostle, " All things are licit for me," Ambrose com-
demonstraliones. Often the "demonstrations" were taken to be descriptions mented, " by the law of nature" (lege nature).81
of a primeval state of affairs-the "state of nature" familiar in many later
natural law theories-which had been superseded by the later develop- (I .ater on, Gerson would declare that the word Jacultas was particularly
ment of human law and government. Alanus even wrote, "Positive law is .1ppropriate to define right in his subjective sense because [he thought)
always preferred to natural law," but he meant only natural law in this /amltas was derived from fas .)
latter sense.79 Sometimes, however, the third kind of natural ius, corre- The idea of natural right as a sphere of free choice was emphasized in an-
sponding to Rufinus' "demonstrations," was taken to be a permanently 111 her English gloss:
existing feature of the law (or right) of nature, a kind of natural ius that
defined an area of permissiveness where rights could licitly be exercised, /us nnlurale .. . licit and approved though not commanded or prohibited
rather than a body of restrictive law. by any statute, as to go through another's field or not to go, which is
The Summa, lnperatorie maiestate posed the standard problem that, called fas; to eat or not lo eat, concerning which Paul said, when he spoke
of the use of foodstuffs . . . "All things are licit for me" ; all things, he
according to Gratian's texts, private property instituted by human
said, which concern food are licit by the power of free choice and by
law seemed contrary to natural law. The author explained that natural
natural law (lege nat11ral1).82
law consisted of "precepts, prohibitions, counsels and permissions"; since
private property did not fall under the "prohibitions" of natural law its
introduction was licit. This led on to a consideration of property as a
natural right. The author noted that ius naturale was sometimes identified HI. Kuttner, Repertorium, 202, "Secundo modo dicitur iusnaturale licitum et approbatum
with ius gentium, which also permitted acquisition of property. He con- •11111<1 nee a Domino nee constitutione aliqua precepitur prohibitu.rve, quod et fas appellatur,
cluded, "The law of nature (ius nature) is called the law of nations (ius "' "'JX'lere suum vel non repetere, comedere vel non comedere, dimittere uxorem infiddem
• uh.•hilare volentem vel non dimittere.... Unde (super) illud Apostoli 'omnia mihi licenl"
gentium) because, by dictate of nature rather than by command of a statute /\mhrosius: lege nature." 1ne idea that le·x could be permissive was ancient: see Digr.ct 1.4.:l
(lex), one has his right (ius)." 80 The oscillation between ius as meaning ob- .111d I >ist 3 c.4 of the D«retum. The interest:ing twelfth-century development was the as.1oci ·
jective law and ius as meaning subjective right which we noted earlier in ........ of this principle with a doctrine or natural right.
H2 l>i~ri11cti<m~s Bamllf'rgen.<is, MS Bamberg Can 17, fol. 94ra, "lus naturale ... qu11<I
h oHum 1'llt l'I approbatum, quamuis nu Ila con!:tilutione sit preceptum nee prohibitum vf'luli
1~·• •'11.rum alienum ire vel non ire quod fas dicitur, commedere non rommcdere. dt- •1t1<>
79. Weigand, 318. ·•1•11~111111~ l'aulus cum dt• u:<u dhorum lnquewtur ut de idolatria dil<il 'omnia mihi lkf'nl.'
80. lbid., 165, urus enim nature dicitur ius gl'nlium quill tlf' nllhlfll 1lkli\nlr, 11011 tit• lc•gc• " t1111l1t ,11 ... 11 <lilt' .Ht d ll11m ('<'rtint•nl lin•nt polr~tnt,. lilwri arhilrii 1•t lf'g•· n,11ur.tli" (d. W1•I
precipiente potius habet ius suum." ........ I. 711")
68 TuE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ORIGINS OF NATURAL R.IG KTS LANGUAGE 69

This understanding of natural right, which is also found in other contem- Vitoria, however, seems to have been unaware of the earlier origin of
porary English works,33 became broadly diffused when it was incorpo- the doctrines that he had assimilated during his preceding years of study
rated into the widely read Summa of Huguccio.114 in Paris:
The association of ius naturale with Paul's text in 1 Corinthians broad-
lus therefore ... is nothing else than what is licit or what is licit by
ened the apostolic teaching on Christian exemption from Jewish cere- Jaw. . .. This is plain from Saint Thomas on 2.2ae q.57 art 1. . .. And so we
monial precepts into a more generalized doctrine of natural liberties. (The use the word when we speak. For we say, "I do not have a right (ius) of
same argument will recur in Ockhams' natural rights theory.) It was not doing this," that is, it is not licit for me; or again, "I use my right," that
that Christianity first conferred rights on its followers; rather, by not im- is, it is licit.
posing the restrictions of the Old Law it left them free to exercise their
pre-existing natural rights. ln the texts we have just quoted ius naturale Conrad (Summenhart) gives a broader definition of the word ius. ...
He says that ius is a power or faculty pertaining to anyone according to
plainly does not mean restrictive law; the term is used to mean what we
the laws-Conrad takes this definition from Gerson.87
should call a natural right-to eat what one chooses for instance. The right
of nature in these texts is what is permitted by the law of nature. Vitoria correctly ascribed the definition of ius as a facultas to Gerson
In discussing modem rights language, Hart explained that a right de- (though, as we have seen, it was not original with him). But the attribution
fines an area where the agent is free to act as he chooses, to assert a claim or of a definition of ius as a subjective right to Aquinas was quite mistaken;
not to assert it. The canonists were making the same point-for them ius Aquinas taught no such doctrine. Vitoria, steeped in a scholastic tradition
naturale could mean "to reclaim one's own or not to reclaim it." Christian lhat had been shaped by juristic as well as by theological reflection, and
Wolff wrote, "The law (lex) of nature is called preceptive which obliges us n mcemed with the new rights problems of his own age, including those
to perform certain actions; it is caJled prohibitive when it obliges us to omit .irising from the discovery of America, creatively reinterpreted St. Thomas,
certain actions; it is called permissive when it gives a right to act." We find rust as the canonists of the twelfth century, steeped in the problems and
this same doctrine expressed in very much the same language, scattered 1•reconceptions of their own society, reinterpreted the ancient texts col-
through the Decretist glosses of the twelfth century. Wolff added, "What l1·cted by Gratian. In their different ways, both Vitoria and the Decretists
we have a right (ius) to do is called 1icit'. "85 This again echoes a common were engaged in "noncanonical readings of canonical texts."
canonistic definition of ius naturale. Michel Villey, describing the doctrine
of individual rights which, he thought, could be formulated only after
Ockham, wrote that such rights implied "a quality of the subject, one of his NEED AND NATURAL RIGHT
faculties, a liberty, a possibility of acting."86 This too was affirmed by the By 1200 the canonists had created a language in which natural rights
twelfth century canonists as one of the many meanings of ius naturale. llwories could readily be expressed. Their "speech acts" did not merely
ln the period of transition from medieval to modem thought during modify existing language; they would lead on to "the creation and dif-
the sixteenth century, both definitions of ius, as a zone of human auton- f 11sion of new languages." But one might still ask whether the canon-
omy or sphere of licit conduct, and as a faculty or power of the individual, ";ls themselves defended any specific natural rights. Had they developed
were drawn together in the very influential work of Francisco Vitoria, a only a vocabulary of words or also a vocabulary of ideas that would per-
principal founder of the school of Salamanca. ·.1st in later discourse? So far we have considered only isolated definitions
83. See Kuttner, Rqlutorium, 202 and Weigand, 209. Also Ricardus Anglicus, Summa
••I ius natura/e, only paroles one might say. To answer our question we
quatstionum, MS Zwettl 162, fol. 145r. "Secundo modo licitum dicitur et approbatum nulla ·.lmuld need to consider the whole langue, the whole context of discourse,
constitutione preceptum uel prohibitum. Unde Ambrosius 'omnia mihi licent' lege nature, et
Augustinus alibi, licent que non precipiuntur nee prohibentur" (cf. Weigand, 213). 117. R. P. Vicente Beltran de Heredia, ed., Francisco dt VitoriJJ, Commentari11 a la S«Und4 y-
84. Huguccio gave the meaning licitum rl approbatum, with the usu~! refere~ to Pa~I Santo Tomns, 6 vols. (Salamanca, 1932- 52), 3:64, HJus ergo ... nihil aliud est ni•I
• 1111tl11r tft'
and Ambrose, as a possible fifth definition of ius naturak. He preferred his own pnmary defi- •lloul 11m>CI liret vel quod lege licet.... Patet hoc ex sancto lhoma supra q57 a. I ... Et ita no11
nition, discussed above. See Weigand, 217. ..1111111r illud vocabulum cum loquimur. Dicimus enim: non habeo ius faciendi hoc, id Clll oon
85. Institutionts, 22, 23, * ux naturat . .. pennissiVt, quae jus dat ad agendum," " . . . ad 1111111 lin ·t; ilt>m , jurc rnl'O utor, id esl licet, Conradus ... ponit late diffinitionem illiua nomlnm
quod agendum tantummodo jus habemus, Ucitum dicitur.n ' " ". . I licit <'rgo quod ju11 est pot~ta11 Vt'I facultas ronvcninui alicui SC'<'undum lt"gf'lt. . . .
86. " La genese du droit subjectif chez Guillaume d 'Ocram," Arclri~ de philo...,pliir du 1111111 11lf011it io 1wm <lfft>pil ( ·nnr11dm1 I'll <;,•rAont•. .. ." For 11 dt'IAlll'd con11idl'r11tlon of Vito
droit 9 (1964): 97- 127, at 101. , ,., ·~ ""'' of /\1111in1u• ,..,.. ,,..lo w. 2.i;t. 6~.
70 THE IDEA OF NATIJRAL R IGHTS ORIGINS OF NATURAL RIG HTS LA NGUAGE 71

in which the words were embedded, and the ways in which it was trans- the beneficiary of a duty is not necessarily the same thing as having a
mitted to later thinkers. If we tried to trace out all the threads that led right. Medieval canonists understood this point too. A bishop might have
from the web of medieval rights language to the fully formed natural .1 duty to grant a dispensation when circumstances warranted it, they
rights theories of the seventeenth century we should have to explore pointed out, but the petitioner did not have a right to insist on the grant.
many areas of discourse in which, by about 1300, particular rights were One of the twelfth-century Decretists, distinguishing between duties and
defended in terms of natural law. They would include rights to property, rights in a discussion on the claims of the poor, used precisely the ex-
rights of consent to government, rights of self-defense, rights of infidels, .1mple of a third-party beneficiary employed in Hart's modem argument.
marriage rights, procedural rights. (From the thirteenth century onward, "If I promise you to give something to someone else I am bound to give to
Roman and canon lawyers argued that the basic rules of legal procedure the third party and I am naturally obliged to him; nevertheless he cannot
guaranteeing a fair trial were based on the natural right of self-defense, hring suit. ..." 9 1 The rich certainly had a natural duty to succor the poor;
not merely on human enactments.) Another major theme would be the it was not so clear that the poor had a natural right that could be asserted
respective rights of individual and community within corporate groups, .1gainst the rich.
a topic long ago touched on by Maitland. Such an inquiry would re- The canonists first approached this question by asking whether a poor
mind us that the first rights theories were not derived from contempla- man in extreme need who took the goods of a rich one was guilty of the
tion of the individual isolated from his fellows-isole sur son ile comme ·;in of theft. Characteristically, they addressed the problem first by probing
Robinson 118-but from reflection on the right ordering of human relation- the inner state of mind of the agent. Theft, by definition, required the
ships in emerging societies. t.1king of something from an unwilling owner. So the poor person would
A full consideration of all these topics would go beyond the scope not be guilty of theft, Huguccio suggested, because "he believes or should
Of uUr pre~nl Ji~ USSiUll . [ \\ i ·uld JiJ P tl1f'rPtnrP In f"np•;1,fl"r J'l<:I "n 1 • •''(-
hdieve" that the owner would give him permission to take what was
ample, concerned with the most fundamental right of all, the right of self- rweded.92 Couvreur maintained that, with this argument, Huguccio "mag-
preservation, specifically the right of the poor to use the surplus property r~terially concluded from the duty of the rich to the right of the poor."93
of the rich to sustain life in cases of extreme need. In this case one can trace Uut it was still a shadowy sort of right, based only on an unprovable hy-
a dear line of argument concerning a specific natural right from the twelfth pothesis about the state of mind of the needy person. Huguccio made a
century to the seventeenth. J~rt·ater contribution with a novel argument about the relationship be-
Among the Church Fathers there was some discussion as to whether lwl-en common ownership and private property-a persistent, nagging
almsgiving was a work of justice or a work of charity; 89 but the twelfth- 1•mblem for commentators on the first distinctions of the Decretum.
century canonists had no doubt that strict justice required a rich man to So far we have considered the existence of private property in relation
share at least his superfluities with those in need. The Decretum contained '"natural law only as a sort of legal conundrum to be solved by juggling
some striking texts on this obligation: "Feed the poor. If you do not feed lhl· various senses of ius naturale. The usual explanation was that common
them you kill them." "A man who keeps more for himself than he needs is property was only a "demonstration" of natural law, a primeval state of
guilty of theft." "The use of all things that are in the world ought to be .1lf.1irs that had passed away with the introduction of human law or
common to all." "No one may call his own what is common, of which if he .1, vine positive law (as expressed in Commandments like "Thou shalt not
takes more than he needs, it is obtained by violence.... The bread that you ·.tc•al," "Thou shalt not covet thy neighbor 's house"). But there was an-
hu!d back belongs to the needy, the clothes that you store away belong to ••tlwr whole dimension to this problem for medieval moralists. "The use
the naked." 90 ••I .111 things ought to be common to all." " No one may call his own what
Such texts indicate plainly that the rich were considered to have a
duty to the poor; but, as we have seen, for modern rights theorists, to be •11 S11111mn Rnmbl'rgmsis nd D ist. 47 c.8 (Couv reur, 109), ~Nam et si stipulor tibi ml' d atu·
" ' "' X .1lii. lt.>nror quide m dare tertio et naruralitcr obligor illi. Tarrien ille non potest agt'R' '"'
88. The phrase is from J. Oabin, " Droit subjectif et subjectivisme juridique,~ Arrhi1lf's dt tll.1 \ ..
philosoph~ du droil 9 (1964): 17-35, at 20. The problem of individual and community in rt>hl· •1;> S11m111n nil C.12 q.2 c.11, MS Admo nt 7, fol. 243ra. " Ego tamen credo quod non
lion to rights theories is discussed in the chapter below on Gerson. I''"' • o•t •111is in •~Ii ca!lu, !\Cilict>t cum utitur re alteriull proptt>r urgentt'm ~itatem ...
89. For detailed discussion, with references to th<> t>ar1il'r lllt>ralun•. _,..,.. <; l ·011vrr11r, /.r~ 'I""' .1111 r n"<lit illll .tliwl crrdt>re clominu.:O '""'""°
permi:i..<1urnm .. . 'IU(l ca!lu furlum non com
pauVllS. O nt-ifs dts droits? ( Pari.\, 1%1). rntlllhu ·•
90. Dist. 116 c.21 . Dist. 4211nfl'l'. l,C. 12 11.l 1·.:Z. fl1•I 47 ,· H 0
11 I r' /~1111''.,.._· 1
11
72 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ORIGINS O F NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAG E 73

is common." These texts, attributed by Gratian to St. Clement and St. Am- to be shared with others in time of need.96 And here again, as in Hu-
brose, spo~e as if common property was a permanent feature of Christian '~uccio's initial definition of ius, the argument was based on an appeal to
society, informing it with charity and justice. There seemed an inherent 1eason, not specifically to scripture.
conflict between the ideal held up by the Fathers and the realities of me- Huguccio did not himself use this doctrine to assert a natural right
dieval life. •)f the poor to the superfluous property of the rich, but its relevance to the
Huguccio was particularly unhappy with the idea of a natural law 1-;sue was perceived almost at once. Ricardus Anglicus, again discuss-
that could simply become obsolete, with no continuing relevance to the 111g the case of a poor person in extreme need, wrote in the 1190s, "Since

social and moral problems of his own age. Such a doctrine did not fit well hy natural ius all things are common, that is to be shared in time of need,
with his own preferred definition of ius as an intrinsic, permanent force lw is not properly said to steal." 97 From this it was only a step to affirrn-
of reason or moral discem.ment in the human soul. At one point he wrote, 111g explicitly the natural right of the poor. Around 1200 Alanus held
"If you want to insist on the common explanation you may say that that the poor man did not steal because what he took was really his own
common possession of all things is from the natural law . . . that con- 111re nalurali-which could mean either "by natural right" or "by natural
sists in demonstrations."94 But Huguccio did not think this was the real l.iw." 98 About the same time another glossator suggested that the person
explanation. He preferred a new formulation of his own which he set out 111 need could "declare his right for himself." 99 Then Laurentius, followed

at the beginning of his Summa and reiterated several times in the course J.y Vincentius Hispanus, wrote that, when the poor man took what he
of the work: rn'<'ded, it was "as if he used his own right and his own thing." 100 Finally,
tht• doctrine entered the mainstream of medieval jurisprudence when
When it is said that by natural ius all things are common . . . this is I lostiensis reformulated it more sharply and included it in his very widely
the meaning. By natural ius, that is in accordance with the judgment ""'d Lectura on the Decretals. "One who suffers the need of hunger seems
of reason, all things are common, that is they are to be shared with the
to use his right rather than to plan a theft." 101 And, of course, it was a
poor in time of need. For reason naturally leads us to suppose that
11.1tural right that was being discussed.
we should keep only what is necessary and distribute what is left to
the needy.95
% . S umma ad Disl. 47 c.8, MS Admont 7. fol. 65 ra, "Quod est commune, id est tempore
"Comrnunis .. . id est communicanda." "Common . . . that is to be
"'" ''ssitatis aliis communicandum .... Et secundum hoc idem est proprium et commune,
shared." The words were endlessly repeated in later discussions. In this l''" l'ri11m quoad dominium uel potestatem dispensandi, commune quia aliis commnican-
way of thinking, private property was itself a social institution involving 0lum lt•mpore necessitatis."
obligations to others. Property could and should be private and common W. Gloss ad Comp. I, 5.265 (Couvreur, 92 n. 248), " Nam cum iure naturali omnia
at the same time; private in the sense that ownership and administration " "'' n •mmunia id est tempore necessitatis communicanda non dicitur proprie furari sed
belonged to the individuals, common in the sense that worldly goods had 1·u·111ris altissimi fungi . . . ." Rican:lus was followed by many other canonists. See Couvreur,
., .. '14.
'Ill. Gloss ad Comp. I, 5.265 (Couvreur, 161 n. 280), " . . . quod accipit suum iure naturali
.-1111 1t11r."
94. Summa ad D.1 c.7, MS Admonl 7, fol. 4ra, "Vel si vellis comm uni expositioni insistett, ' "'· App. Militnnt siquidem ad Comp. I, 5.26.5 (Couvreur, 118 n. 349), " . . . in tali articulo
dices, communis omnium posMSSio, id est quod omnia sint communia id est de iure naturali, eo I" •h ·sl sibi ius dicere sicut et creditor si videat debitorem suum a civitate fugere . . ."
scilicet quod licitum siue fas appellatur, scilicet quod ronsistil in demonstrationibus... . H 11111. Vincentius ad Comp. I, 5.26.5 (Couvreur, 102), " Hie res ista quam dicebat furari est
95. Summa (Introduction), MS Admont 7, fol. 2va, "Cum didtur iure naturali omnia sunl · " ""minis, id est communicanda in tali articulo erat, et ideo iste earn accipiendo quasi iun•
communia . .. is est sensus .. . iure naturali, id est iudicio rationis approbante omnia sunt •u1u ,~t n• ~ua utebatur.'"
communia, id est tempore necessitatis indigentibus communicanda. Naturali enim ductu 1111. lfostiensis, uctura in V /ibros Decreta/rum (Venice, 1581) ad X.5.18.3, "Unde potius
rationis approbamus nobis tanturn necessaria retinere, reliqua proximi.s indigentibus deber. • •· lo·t11r i.• qui nt'Ct'SSitatem patitur uti iure suo quam furti consilium inire." The text was lalt•r
distribuere. ... " See also 511.m ma ad Dist. 1 c.7, fol. 3ra, "Communis possessio omnium, id '" ' hulo-..1 in Johannes Andreae's In quinque Dtcrt talium Jibros novella commtnlaria (Venk<',
est rommunicatio omnium que possidemus tempore necessitatis, hoc de iure naturali quod 1•411 I.''" X. 5. IH-1. Discuss ing the rights theories of a later age, Knud Haakonssen wmtt> that.
dicitur ratio.. .."This doctrine of Huguccio, and its incorporation into the Ordinary Clo~ '" ' c;, ..1ius, "a right is not only a claim in the interest of self-preservation, but the mc>ntal
of the D«rttvm was discussed in my Medieval Poor Law (Berkeley and Lo.s Angeles, 1959). l'" w"'' (rii-;ht rc•ason) to make such a claim rationally, which means the power to judgt> oiw'"
A littl.e later Couvreur returned to the topic and printed a wealth of texts illustrating ttu- 1o w 11 1 l.1im vis·A-vis the claims of otht>rs." One find:'! thr same attitude in the nmonlst~ who•
wide diffusion of Huguccio's teaching. See I.Ls pauvm;, 91-106, 141- 154 and, for an t>Xt<'n."lvt' " ' '" "' r1c•M tht• l>t•ginning of !ht• mco<lirv.11 tr111lition that <;rolio" would inhrril. St't• M. T
selection of Huguccio's texts, 290- 296. I '" •·v .m.I IC. I l.1.tl"1n111M•n, c•tl• .• A C11/l11r1" of 1<(11111.• (( 'itmhridg<'. l'Jtl I). 2~.
74 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIG HTS ORIGINS OF NATURAL RIGHTS l.ANCUAGE 75

In modem rights language, we have seen, a right can be defined in one person.u>t Godfrey of Fontaines, a little later, was quite explicit. The right
sense as a "rightful power." This is essentially what the canonists were as- lo the necessities of life was not only a natural right but an inalienable
serting for the person in want. If he used his own efforts to take what he right:
needed from the superfluities of the rich he was acting rightfully in the
sense that he was not guilty of sin in the eyes of God. But the situation By the law of nature (iure naturae) each one has a certain right (ius) in the
common exterio r goods of this world, which right cannot be licitly re-
was not wholly satisfactory from the point of view of the person in want;
nounced.105
the secular judge would probably hang him. We need to consider therefore
whether the poor man also had a "rightful claim." If he did not want t >ckham reformulated the doctrine of the rights of the poor in extreme
to risk punishment for theft, could he only appeal to the " love or piety or need with explicit reference to the text of pseudo-Ambrose included in the
mercy" of the rich (to use Feinberg's modem language) or could he some- I Jecretum, and closely paraphrased Huguccio in discussing it:
how demand, claim, insist upon his right? Huguccio doubted that he
In another sense temporal things belong to others because they are owed
could. The problem was that none of the established forms of legal action by necessity . . . that is they are owed by right reason. And in this way
covered this kind of case. Certainly the superfluities of the rich were owed the superfluities of the rich belong to the poor. . . . So are to be under-
to the poor, Huguccio wrote, but then he added, "Many things are owed stood the words of Ambrose given at Dist. 47.106
that cannot be sought by judicial procedure, such as dignities and dis-
pensations and alms . . . but they can be sought as something due mer- l :erson wrote of a "right of nourishing the body" and repeated that all
cifully for the sake of God and piety."102 This opinion did not prevail lhings were common in case of necessity. 107 Vitoria restated the canonists'
however. Alongside the formal judicial procedures inherited from Roman h·aching but, again, mistakenly suggested that Aquinas taught a doctrine
law the canonists had developed an alternative, more simple, equitable of subjective rights. "Thomas says that all things are common in extreme
process known as "evangelical denunciation.'' By virtue of the authority rn-cessity. So if they are common I have a right to them." 108
inhering in his office as judge, a bishop could hear any complaint in- Other Spanish scholastics of the school of Salamanca continued the
volving an alleged sin and could provide a remedy without the plaintiff 11wdieval discussions about the rights of the needy and the duties of the
bringing a formal action. From about 1200 onward several canonists ar- wl'althy with endless refinements of argument.109 The right of a poor man
gued that this procedure was available to the poor person in extreme ru the surplus property of the rich still found a place in Locke's political
need. He could assert a rightful claim by an "appeal to the office of the thl'ory:
judge." The bishop could then compel an intransigent rich man to give God , the Lord and Father of all, has given no one of his children such
alms from his superfluities, by excommunication if necessary. The argu- a Property in his peculiar portion of the things of this world, but that
ment gained general currency when it was assimilated into the Ordinary
Gloss to the Decretum."13 It was, as Couvreur wrote, an elegant solution. "It 104. Summa theol. 2.2ae.66.7.
provided a judicial sanction for the rights of the poor.'' I05. J. Hoff mans, ed., Lts Q11odlibds onu-quatoru dt Godefroid dt Fontaines, Lts Philosophes
11,·('\•'S 4 (Lou vain, 1924): 105, " lmmo etiam propter hoc quod unusquisque tenetur iure natu·
These canonistic arguments about the status and claims of needy •.... vitam suam s ustent.ire .. . ideo etiam iure naturae quilibet habet dominium et quoddam
persons provide an explicit example of an early natural rights theory. Con- .. ,., in bonis communibus exterioribus huius mundi, cui etiam iuri renuntiare non potest
sidered simply as theory, the doctrine was subtle and far-ranging. As with
many supposed human rights nowadays, one can envisage serious dif- 1116. Opus nonnginta dirrum, ed. H. S. Offler, Guil/elmi de Ocklulm optra politiaz, 3 vols.
ficulties in putting the theory into practice. But, however that may be, 1/\1 .m,·h~ter, 1956- 74), 2:576, " Aliter dicuntur temporalia esse a liquorum ex debiti necessi·
,_,,,. . quia scilicet eis ex ratione recta debentur. Et isto modo superflua divitum sunt
the canonists' teaching persisted and, from the thirteenth century onward, l'·"'J't·rum .... Et sic intelligenda sunt verba Ambrosii, quae ponuntur di xlvii Sicul hii . . . ."
it was drawn into theological as well as juristic discussions. Aquinas re- 1., ..11,..r c-ontexts Ockham referred explicitly to the right of the person in need, e.g. Op<ra I :
peated that the poor person who stole in extreme need took what was • •.'. " N;im quilibet in extrema necessitate conslitutus habet ius utendi re consumptibile, :iirw
really his, but without any overt reference to a subjective right of the poor 'I"·' de· h;ic- vita migraret. ..."
I117 CH'1wrl"S, :l: 156, " . . . dicimus titulum naturalem ad quern consequitur jus nutriendi
102. Summa ad Dist. 47 c.8, MS Admont 7, £ol. 65ra, uRe vera l'is debentur, Sl'd mull• •, •• p 11~ :ik quod in eju:i nl'C'l'llsilate omnia sibi sint ad hoc communia."
debentur que tamen peti non possum ordine iudiciario ut dignitatl'!I 1•1 diAp<"nsalionl'll l'l l'I· Hiit <"11m111mlarin, :l: :WO, " • . . Sanctus Thoma:>1 dicit quod omnia !lunt communia in l' ...
emosine, sed possunt peti sicut debentur, scilict>t mi:oerk orditl'r "' intuitu til'i e•t p i,.tatiJt." 1..-111.t 11t•fl'H!lilnh•. S i 1.•rR<' ~11111 rommunla, habeo jus ad 11111."
103. GI. ord. ad Dist . 47 c-.8. On lhi9 wholl' tlUNllion l't'f' my Mr1l1.-m/ /'•"'' l,,w, :l7 :l'I .md I ll'I s...· I< I l.•11rh1K•'r. l'mhJrmr drr Cari/n~ In drr S1·h1ilr 1~111 5aln111n11ra (Fn•ihorx im Hrrh•·
Couvreut, J.r.; pa111>rr!I, 1011- 115 I\" " · l ' l'>'I)
76 THE. IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS O RIG INS O F NATIJRAL RIG HTS LANGUAGE. 77

he has given his Brother a Right lo the Surplusage of his Goods; so that
it cannot justly be denyed him when his pressing Want calls for it. 110

CONCLUSION
I.
~ I
:$.> '
{ '
Paradoxically, the closest thing we have to a "great text" on canonistic po-
litical theory is Ockham's Dialogus. 111
Carlos Fuentes wrote recently: "There is no creation without tradition;
the ' new' is an inflection of a preceding form; novelty is always a variation
on the past." It is true of course. And yet some variations are of decisive
When the canonists wrote about reason and free will and syndere- importance for the future. The semantic shifts of the twelfth century were
sis they were not offering any profoundly original reflections on the or this kind. The medieval concern for subjective rights in practical every-
grounds of human morality. They were simply deploying the familiar day life reshaped the language in which discourse about natural right was
psychological language of their own day. The novelty in their works was conducted. By around 1200 many canonists were coming to realize that the
that they used the language for a juristic purpose, to explain the varied old language of ius natllrale could be used to define both a faculty or force
meanings of ius naturale that they encountered in the texts of their great 1 if the human person and a "neutral sphere of personal choice," "a zone of

Jaw book, Gratian's Decretum. Many canonists included in their lists of human autonomy." But they did not, like some modem critics of rights
meanings a subjective one that explained ius naturale as a faculty or power theories, expect such language to justify a moral universe in which each in-
inherent in human nature. Then, from this primary meaning, various dividual would ruthlessly pursue his own advantage. Like most of the
other meanings, including natural law and natural rights, could be de- dassical rights theorists down to Locke and Wolff they envisaged a sphere
rived by a sort of metonymic association. It seems important that, from or natural rights bounded by a natural moral law. The first natural rights
the beginning, the subjective idea of natural right was not derived specifi- theories were not based on an apotheosis of simple g~ or self-serving
cally from Christian revelation or from some all-embracing natural-law q~otism; rather they derived from a view of individual human persons
theory of cosmic harmony but from an understanding of human nature .1s free, endowed with reason, capable of moral discernment, and from a
itself as rational, self-aware, and morally responsible. This understanding n msideration of the ties of justice and charity that bound individuals to
endured as the basis of many later natural rights theories, both medieval c•ne another.
and modem.
The language of the canonists persisted in later political theory,
though sometimes the original source of the language was forgotten. It
was transmitted mainly in two ways. One way was through the ency-
clopedic works of the late medieval lawyers. They were well known to
those of the sixteenth-century Spanish scholastics who were jurists as well
as theologians; and these writers in tum often influenced seventeenth·
century rights theories. When Suarez, for instance, chose to formulate
his doctrine of rights in terms of ius in re and ius ad rem he was well aware
that he was using a long-established technical vocabulary. The other main
channel of transmission was through the work of Ockham, for Ockham
relied more on earlier canonistic teachings than on his own innovative
nominalist philosophy in formulating his theories on property and pov-
erty and natural rights. He in tum influenced a whole school of late me·
dieval theologians, including Gerson. None of the canonists themselves,
we have noted, wrote an extended, coherent treatise on natural rights.

11 1. ( ln Ockham's use o f canonistk sources see my uOckham, the Conciliar Theory anti
l IO. P. Laslett, ed., John Lock . Two Trtol ises of Gowrnmmt, 2nd eJ. (Camhridg1•, 1970), 11 ... <·.monis ts," /oum al of //rt H istory of Ideas 15 (1954): 40-70. Fo r a more detailed di~u!'l.~ion
1.42, 188. But Locke a lso wro te here that the claim o f lh1• poor wall h"""'. J nn <'h<trily ralht•r ,..,. tlw cfotplt•r.1 on ( )c-kham bt"low. llw complex di~ussionB or th!' Dccrcti~ls on thr 1>ri~ln
than justice. His wo rk reflects both tht" old mt't.lil'vnl tratlili1111 11t1<l tho• rwwl'T .1ttll11tl•"" 111 " ' .c ••Khl to l'"'l"''' Y .uo• ;il!m •·11n!'littPTrd in mon• ti1•l"il in lht•11t• ··hnrh•u. St>t• 1•ttp1>t·iallv
poverty that were growing up in the s.•vt'nll't'nlh c"t•11111ry I \"/ 4'•
T
RIGHTS AND DUTIES 79

demic indu~try :'h~n he interpreted Locke's teaching that everyone has


a p~operty right m his own person as a reflection of the possessive individ-
uah.s m .o~ early ~ode?' capitalism.5 Michel Villey found an earlier origin
for md1v1dual nghts m the work of William of Ockham, but he too held
that the understanding of a right as a person's "property" in himself did
not emerge until the time of Locke.6
f have already suggested that these approaches are too limited and
that an earlier origin of modem natural rights theories is to be found in the
,. great sea o f medieval jurisprudence, especially in the canonistic writings
THREE of the late tw~lfth cen~ry. Hence, in considering the further development
.. of these doctnnes, a ma1or problem is to explain how, in different historical
. . ..
. . . . . .. .

•'
c?n~exts, later medieval writers of various philosophical persuasions as-
s1m_1l.a ted a~d adapted the language of the jurists in works of theology and
RIGHTS AND DUTIES. pohh~al ~h1losophy. In the following discussion I shall try to make a small
A QUAESTIO OF HENRY OF GHENT contnbution to this kind of inquiry by considering a text of Henry of
Ghent from the 1280s and its relationship to later natural rights theories.

A PRISONER'S DILEMMA

A modem author has observed that, in the "pre-liberal epoch" be-


fore the seventeenth century, people did not think of individuals
"as possessing inalienable rights to anything-much less life, liberty, prop-
In discussing the work of the Decretists, I emphasized the concept of
natural right as a s phere of personal autonomy, where the right-holder
~:ould a:t as ~.e chose. F? r one.modem sc~ool of thought this autonomy or
erty, or even the pursuit of happiness." 1 The statement is not true, but it is sovereignty over one s acts 1s an essential constituent of any right.7It has
excusable. There has been much less work on medieval ideas concerning t•ven ~n argu~d, on the ground of human autonomy, that a right to life
natural rights than on the classical theories of the early modem era.2 Un- must include a n~t to commit suicide.8 But this way of thinking excludes
derstandably, therefore, some modem scholars see the seventeenth- .1 whole cla~s of nghts that were prominent in medieval and early modem
century rights theories as a radical departure from ancient and medieval ll1ought-~1gh~s that were a lso duties, and that could, accordingly, be re-
ways of thought; 3 they are content to explain the ideas of Hobbes and )~~rded as ma~1en:ble rig~ts. Of these, the prime example is the right of
Locke and Pufendorf by reference to some aspect of the intellectual, politi- :-it lf-prese~ahon; a nd this was the theme that Henry of Ghent took up in
cal, or economic life of the seventeenth century itself.4 C. B. MacPherson, lhc Qunestto that I want to discuss.
for instance, emphasizing economic factors, inaugurated a minor aca-
5. C:· B. Ma~P~rson, The Political Theory of P~ive Individualism (Oxford, 1962), J. "It•
l. A. W. Saxonhouse, Womtn in tht History of Political Thought. llncitnl Grttce to Machia- J'< ~Sf':';s1ve quality is found in_its conception of the individual as essentially I.h e proprieto r nf
~l/i (New Yo rk, 1985), 7. lus c•wn person. · · . The relation of ownership ... was read back into the nature of the indi·
vu\ual.h
2. By contrast there is a huge body of writing on other aspects of medieval constitutional
thought-<ounsel and consent, representation, the rule of law, resistance theories, church- fl. M . Villey, LA formation dt la ptnsit juridiqut modtrnt , 4th ed. (Paris, 1975), 22..'i -262·
state relations-and it is widely understood that medieval thought in those areas provided a " t.·m. U droit fl Ir.; droils (Paris, 1983), 147. .
"foundation" for early modem political theory. This is we ll brought out in the far-ranging 7. See e .g . H. I.. A . Hart, Are There Any Natural Rin'-ts?" Philosophical Rtv il"w M (lq'l<;)·
N
17'i 'II . 6'' . .
s urvey of Q. Skinner, Tht Fouruloticms of Modtrn Polilia1l Thought, 2 vols. (Cambridge, 1978).
3. See, e.g., L Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1950), 16S- 166. 11. 11. J. McCln1<key. NThe Right to Ufe.'' Mind 84 (1975): 403- 425.
4. Good bibliographies are provided by A. Carcia, Thom11~ I fobl>t'~: RiblilJKrnphit lntm111·
1
' · '11••:
canoni~ls of cour~ condf'mnl"<.I suid<lr and l'('('ognized a nalural right of "<'If ·
lio1111lt dt 1620 a 1986 (Ca~, 1986) and J. S. Yolton 1uul f W Yollun, /01111 l 1lf'kt . A Reftrtnrt l'n·,..·r~.ltH>n - a right to the nl'C~•iti••11 of life• 11ml d rixht to defend om-If if allackc'< I 11111
Cuidt (BMton, 1985). For CUl'Nfll lltt-r"turr....,. "/1rr I 1~ A' Nr11.lrilrltr 1 •ml .. llullootln Hobb<>llNlu llwy dJ"'<'ll"-'lt'<I ~u.-h qu1-stion11 In h •rn1H " ' •ixht" 1o1llwr than dulirs. An rmphlll'il' on tllt' duty
An.,,ltin dt Phllc~lhlt (1914~ ). " ' "''" pn....•rv.1111111 .1n111t• out c•f ..11,.. -a.. "" 1111• "' "' " '"' ....... d'1im lhat lht'f hn<I n•nourwc.,f ,,11
.1.,.i.1..
'/H
80 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGlITS RIGHTS AND DUTIES 81

The immediate problem to be considered then is this: Is there an not pursue the point. 17 Discussing an analogous case, he wrote that a mili-
inalienable right to life, that is a right of self-preservation that cannot be re- tary officer could justly send a soldier to almost certain death.18 But,
nounced and that can be exercised in all circumstances? And, specifically, according to his earlier argument, the soldier could not have alienated
does a criminal who has been justly condemned to death have a right, or his right of self-preservation. It would seem that two sets of rights existed
even a duty, to preserve himself by escaping if he can? Or does he have an relating to the same person. G. D. Glenn, who discussed this case in con-
obligation to accept his just punishment? It is another kind of "prisoner's sidering Locke's teaching on suicide, concluded that, "A Lockean gov-
dilemma." ernment has a right to order a citizen to virtually certain death, and a
The problem is as old as Socrates, and it found a place in the dis- citizen has a right to avoid death at all costs." 19
cussions of seventeenth-century rights theorists. Locke was ambivalent on Hobbes was more explicit and unequivocal in considering the right of
the issue. He wrote, famously, that every man had a property in his own a condemned criminal. He too held that a man had a kind of property in
person and that property could be defined as "Life, Liberty, and Estate." 10 his own Life and an obligation as well as a right to preserve it.20 No law
Humans had a natural right to preserve themselves and a corresponding could oblige a man to abandon his own preservation; hence if a starving
right to "Meat and Drink" and other basic necessities of life. 11 But, because man took food "by force or stealth" he was to be excused.21A government
man was God' s creature, he had no right to destroy his own life. Rather had indeed a right of punishing, but a criminal had a right to defend his
he was "bound to preserve himself."11 Moreover, since he did not have ab- own life.22 A covenant not to defend a man's own body was void; that
solute power over his own life he could not concede an absolute power was why "they lead criminals to execution, and prison, with armed men."
over himself to anyone else.13 (Locke sometimes used the words "power" If the sovereign commanded a criminal to kill himself or to abstain from
and " right" indifferently in the manner that Villey traced back to Ock- the food needed to sustain life, then even though the criminal was justly
ham.14) Even if a man sold himself to a master, which he could do under condemned, "yet hath that man the liberty to disobey.''ll In the De Gue
Jewish law, it was "only to drudgery not to slavery."15 But Locke also wrote Hobbes explained that the "vindicative" or penal provisions of the law

\ in this same context that a criminal could "forfeit" his life and liberty. An
unjust aggressor forfeited his life to the injured party; the latter could lic-
itly kill him or hold him as a slave; the relationship between them was " the
were addressed only to the magistrate; they obliged the magistrate to
impose a penalty but did not oblige the criminal to accept it.24 Here again
we have a pattern of correlative rights. The sovereign had a right to impose
state of war continued." Clearly the captor had a right over his captive. a death sentence; the criminal had a right to preserve his life.
But, given that there existed a "Fundamental, Sacred and unalterable law Pufendorf reached a similar conclusion. In his view the sovereign
of Self-Preservation," 16 did the captive also have a right to escape? Locke did possessed a power over the bodies and lives of subjects that was called
10. P. Laslett, ed., /ohn Lockt. Two Trtatisr.; of Government (Cambridge, 1967), 2.27, 305; 17. He wrote only that, if the captive found his servitude too harsh, he had the power to
2.87, 341. hring about his own death by resisting his master. But what if he resisted successfully?
11. Ibid., 2.25, 303. Throughout this passage Locke seems to be responding directly to Grotius. Grotius held that,
12. Ibid., 2.6, 289. It may seem incongruous that the duty of self-preservation should l><'Cause a person could enslave himself. therefore a whole people could hand itselr over to 11n
have been associated with ownership of one's own person. 1n civil law a holder of dominium .1hsolutjst government. But he also d iscussed explicitly the question that Locke avoided and
was at liberty t.o destroy or alienate his own property. But the law d efined liberty itself as a lwld that pnsoners enslaved after participating in an unjust war did indeed retain a right to
freedom to act as one pleased "unless prohibited by force or laww(Inst. 1.3.1). Similarly the •·S<·;ipc (Dt j11re be/Ii, 1.3.8 and 3.7.6).
right of ownership was limited by law. ln the later definition of Bartolus, domirrium was "a IR. lbid .. 2.139, 380.
right of disposing o f a corporeal thing completely unless prohibited by law.w And of course, 19. G. D. Glenn. "Inalienable Rights and Locke's Argument for Limited Government: P<>-
for all medieval and early modem thinkers, self-destruction was prohibited by d ivine and l11 ical Implications of a Right to Suicide,w/ournal of Politics 46 (1984): 80-10!? at 98.
natural law. 20. T. Hobbes, Leviathan, 2.30, 223, "Of things held in propriety, those that are deart".'lt
13. Ibid., 2.23, 302, " No body can give more Power than he has himself; and he that •• • .1 man are his own life and limbs. ..."; 1.14, 84. NA Law of Nature, ltx natrm11is, is a prt'·
cannot take away his own Life cannot give another power over it." At 2.168, 398, Lockt' • •·pl . .. by which a man is forbidden to do that, which is destructive of his life .. . and to
wrote that it was "out of a Man's power so to submit himself to a nother a.-; tn give him a lih· • 1111i1 that hy which he thinks it may best be preserved." (Page references are to Oake9hott'io
erty to destroy him.w ... 1&1 ic>n .)
14. Evidently a man had the d' / 11dC1 powt'r tu la kr hl1' own lift• I •>1·kc· m<"ant that he had n lhid., 227. 197.
no rightful power, no right, to do so. Jl. lhid ., 2.211, 202.
15. Ibid., 2.24, :io.1. J:I lhid .• 1.14, 111 - '12.
It.. Jhld., 2. 1411, .114~. / '1 11. w,,m•11<l<'r, c•tl.• Dr Cil.11'. Thr f.rrJlli<ilr Vrr~imr (Oxford, lqf\J), 14.7, 1n; 14.21, 1112.
82 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS RIGHTS AND DunES 83

a "right of life and death." 25 (Here again "power" and " right" were used and the peculiar conception of a right as a kind of property in a person and
indifferently). But Pufendorf also maintaine~ that men _hav~ a natural at the same time as a kind of power. Also there was the rather complex
right " to do everything that will lead to their prese~ahon m so far as notion of correlative rights in the body of a criminal. (The magistrate has
the right of others is not i..""tjured."26 This self-preservation was, moreover, one sort of right, the criminal another.) Finally, the argument was set in a
a duty commanded by the law of nature; a man had _n o right ~o ~estroy broader framework of discourse where self-preservation was conceived of
himself.Z7 Pufendorf considered in considerable detail how this nght of as both a right and a duty and was taken to imply a natural right to acquire
self-preservation could be exercised in cases of extr~me necessity. If a the basic means of life, especially food, if necessary " by force or stealth."
man were starving, for instance, "immediate necessity may be 1:"e~ by
taking (food] through force or stealth.''28 As for the cond_emned cnmmal,
OWNERSHIP OF SELF
Pufendorf held that the magistrate had a power over his body that was
akin to a property right. "The body and property of a sinner is no ~ess in Let us turn to our medieval author. Henry of Ghent was one of the
the power of a magistrate for crimes than is the property of a debtor m that most illustrious masters of the University of Paris in the latter part of the
of a creditor for his debts."29 (Elsewhere, discussing property in general he thirteenth century. He was an eclectic philosopher, usually categorized as
defined it as a right in the " substance" of a thing and explained that t~e an Au~ustinian or Neoplatonist. In another role he was the outstanding
same thing could belong to different persons in different ways-for in- champion of the secular masters of Paris and the French bishops against
stance one might own the property, another lease it.)30 But, althou~h.the the encroachments of the new orders of friars, Franciscans and Domini-
magistrate had a right to condemn a criminal to d_e ath and the cnmmal cans, and against the more extreme claims of the contemporary popes. In
could not claim that an injury had been done to him when he was pun- this ~ap~city h~ was one of the founders of what later became theological
ished, still this did not mean that he was obligated to accept the punish- -,r Galhcamsm. Like other great scholastic masters he had far-ranging in-
32
ment.J• Rather he could seek to avoid it "by denial, hiding or flight.'' ~ terests.34 He wrote, for instance, on issues of economic theory and on the
Quoting Hobbes, Pufendorf repeated that the penal clauses of_the law .. thorny ecclesiological problem of the relationship between scripture and
were addressed only to the magistrate. They commanded t~e mag1.s trate to church tradition. Some of his writings also touched on problems of politi-
hang a thief; they did not command the thief to ~o voluntanly to his death. cal theory.3s
So it was no sin in the thief if he were not hung; 1t was rather that the mag- In his Quodlibet 9, probably written in 1289, at a time when he was
istrate had neglected his duty to the state.3.l . . ~ieeply inv~lved _in defending the rights of the French bishops, Henry
The problem of the condemned criminal is, as we have sa~d, a~ ar:c1ent introduced mto his text a group of questions about superiors and subordi-
one. Pufendorf indeed quoted the case of Socrates from Plato ~ Cnto m the ll<ltes. Quaestio 26 is the one that concerns us-"Whether one condemned
course of his discussion. What seems distinctively modern m the argu- to death can licitly flee." His first argument was rather similar to one of
ments we have summarized is the emphasis on the rights of individuals, 1'u fendorf's.

25. S. Pufendorf, Dt jurr naturot ti gtntium libri octo (Amsterdam, 1688), 8.~ ~· 791, "Com· J4. TheTC' is a substantial literature on each separate aspect of Henry's thought but no
petit quoque summo imperio civili potestas in corpus ac vi lam, ut et bona c1v1um ex causa w·nNal work o f synthesis. For an overview of his life and writings see R. Macken et al, cd!I.,
delicti; quae presse solet vocari jus vitae et necis." I lr11riri de Candat'O opera omnia, 28 vols. (Leuven, 1979-94), 5: vii-xxviii.
26. Ibid ., 2.2.3, 108. :15 . Henry's political theories were discussed by G . de Lagarde, I.A naissana de l'tspril
27. Ibid., 2.4.16, 176; 2.63, 205. . ''"'I"'" 011 dk lin du moytn iige, 5 vols., 2nd ed. (Paris, 1956-70) 2: 161- 213 and M. Wilks, Thi'
28. Ibid., 2.6.6, 305, Hsi summa urgeat necessitas ... extra ordine~ ad~atur mag~stra ­ l'11•hlr111 of Sovtrtignty in the I.Aler Middle Agts (Cambridge, 1963). Another o f Henry's themes
tus, aut ubi tempus id non fert, vi aut danculum erepta re urgens necess~tas d1spella_tu~ The lf1.1t 1-lC'<'ame a topic of seventeenth-century political theory has attracted some int<'rt':'I,
reference to an extraordinarv ap('f'ill tn the magistrate echoes the medieval cano_:i1sllc doc- 11
.11111•ly his lr<'atmcnt of pottstas absoluta and poltslos ordinota. Henry was apparently thl" first
trine that t~ u1 ""'"J wulJ ' i.11:rl·•n· t!1c uffac uf Iii.: juJgc: Utt the.~ .iwvt<, 14.
0
1•l11lnsopher to apply this theological distinction to the power of human rulers (aftl"r a !'limi·
29. Ibid., 8.3.5, 798-99. l.11 .,,..,~·· by th .. canonist Hostiensis). On this !i<'t' J. Marrone, HThe Absolut<' and Ordaill<'J
30. Ibid., 4.4.1, 363. I'1 •w1·n• ,,f the l'opt-: An Unroitcd Text of I lt·nry of< ;rn-n1," Mtdion111( Studirs :16 ( 1974): 7 22;
31. Ibid., 8.3.5, 798. W I <"ourh•nray, .,lw Dfalectic of Di vim•< lmnl1>1•h•n1·1··· in Cownant and Cau511fill( i11 Mrdinral
32. Ibid., 8.3.4, 795. . I ''""Jiii (I Am.Son, IQl\4); f . 0Aklt•y, "I"'~'"""'" l'ulillr•I 11.,.,,1,~y: Th<' Ah!'lolutr a~tl ( lnlln11ry
33. Ibid., 8.3.4, 796. HErgo non peccat in eo fur, si non !111-"l'''"'lltur. ,,.,1 maKl~trntus. <1111 l"uw1•1'1 ol 1111' Kin.-:· 11•1111111/ 11/ l/rr llbh11v H/ J.fr,,, /•J (l'lfill) 12:1 4f1 t1nd ldrm, C>mn f1~•lr11o·I'.
pmficuam reipublicac animadversionE'm intt'1Tllisit." I,,,,..,,,,,,,_,,,.,,
I 1,,,,., (lth111"11. Ny 1•1,..1
84 THE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIG HTS RIGHTS AND 0UTIES 85

The body of one condemned belongs more to the judge than some other the judge had the power of capturing, holding and killing it; but the crimi-
temporal thing; but it is not licit for the condemned man to take away nal had the power of using his body so as to preserve its life, so Jong as he
any other thing from the judge; therefore it is not licit for him to take did not injure another. This was not only equitable (fas) but licit (licilum)
away his body. ...36 b_ecause it w_a s permitted by the law of nature, and not only licit but a right
(ws) a~cordmg to the law of nature, and not only was there a right but

J
But this did not settle the question. Henry explained that several persons ~.

could have power over the same thing in different ways. For instance one .i somehmes a necessity of exercising the right. 41 If, for instance, food was
could have property, another use. And if the criminal did not flee when '
withheld from the criminal and he could acquire it by stealth, he had the
he could he seemed to bring about his own death which no one could lic- power and right and necessity of doing so. (Here and in the subsequent
itly do.l7 The rest of the Quaestio was an etaborate inquiry into the differ- " discussion the terms ius and potestas were used interchangeably as in the
ent kinds of rights that the judge and the criminal possessed in the body modem authors we considered). In taking the food he needed, the crimi-
of the criminal. nal would not injure another because in case of necessity all things became
The author was especially concerned with rights in cases of extreme common.' 2 This was another doctrine from the Ordinary Gloss to the Decre-
tu_m; it became a commonplace in later works of moral theology and was
necessity. He began with some juristic distinctions taken from the first Dis-
tinctio of Gratian's Decretum. There were four things to be considered, he
.
6 sh.11 remembered by the seventeenth-century rights theorists.c
wrote, in defining the powers that different persons could have over the The conclusion was that the criminal had an overriding right to pre-
same thing-fas, licitum, ius, necessitas.31 Fas was natural equity, licitum was serve his life. The right of the judge over the body of the condemned
what the law permitted, ius was the equity that gave a claim to something, person did not exclude a corresponding right in the criminal. Just as the
what we might call a claim right, necessitas was the occasion or opportune- judge had a right to hold and kill the criminal, so the latter had an equal,
ness of using something belonging to another.39 Quoting the Ordinary Gloss indeed greater right to escape if he could. The right of the condemned
to the Decretum Henry noted here that, when a person was compelled by -~
person was greater because the judge was not compelled by such neces-
hunger, "necessity excuses theft." 40 Each term in the series was of broader sity to hold and kill the criminal as he was to preserve his own life. If he
scope then the preceding one, so the last term, necessitas included all the were left unbound, with the door of his gaol open, he ought to escape; not
others. to do so would be equivalent to suicide.44
Equipped with these distinctions Henry turned back to the rights of
the judge and the condemned person. As regards the body of the criminal, 41. Ibid., ~, " Diro ergo ad p roposilum quod super corpus damnati ad mo rtem poles·
tatem habet 1udex saecularis capiendi, detinendi et occidendi. Habel autem et ipscm<'I
36. Macken, ed., Htnrici dt Candavo optra omnia, 13:307. "Corpus damnati mortis est J amna.tus q~oad animam potestatem super idem corpus utendi eo ad vitae suae in corpor<'
maius quid {iudicis) quam alia res temporalis. Sed non licet damnato iudici subtrahere n 1slod1am, m qua cons istit eius perfectio sine iniuria alterius. Et hoc non sol um aequitatt>
quamcumque aliam rem. Ergo nee licitum est ei subtrahere illi corpus suum." Macken omit· naturae quae fas est circa rem alienam, sed quae licitum est. Et non solum licitum tamquam
ted the word iudicis in his edited text but listed several manuscripts that include it. The word ·' lcge naturae indultum in aliquale alterius praeiudicium, sed quae ius est serundum leg<'m
is ~1<;1' m the tdilio princtps of Paris, 1518. It seems essential to the meaning of the passage. n.l!urae. Et non solum ius, sed in casu necessitas exsequendi ius suum.#
~- Ibid., 3117, HCum iste abeundo vitam suam posset salvare, remanendo occasionem oc· 42. Ibid., 308, "Ut s i oporteret captivum talem mo ri fame nisi acciperet clam contra vnl·
cidendi se darel Quod nulli licet." 11nlatem custodis sui panem eius, in hoc ha bet potestatem et ius atque necessitat<'m ul<'ndi
38. Ibid., 307, "Di.c endum quod plures habere potestatem super eandem rem diversis re· • urpore ad panem capiendum et vescendum. Et fit hoc sine laesione alterius, q uia necessil;u•
spectibus non est inconveniens, ut quod u.nus habeat in eam proprietatem et aIius us~m.... 1.u-il commune quod erat proprium, ut iuste occupanl'i concedatur."
Sunt autem quattuor per ordinem se habentia, secundum quae super eandem rem d1versas 4:l. GI. ad Dt cons. Dist. S c 26, " Et est ratio quia in necessitate o mnia debt>nt essc com mu
potestates diversi habere possunt diversimode, quae sunt: fas, licitum, ius, necessitas, et in- ""' ... <'I maxime cibaria ut ff ad leq. Rhod. d e iac. 1.2 (Digtst, 14.2.2)." Gro tius rept'all-<l lhh
cluditur semper prius in posteriori." dodrin<' with a re fe rence to the same text o ( the Digest (Dt jurr ~Iii, 2.2.6). Pufmdo rf q1mh'<t
39. Ibid., 307- 308, HFas est aequitas naturalis qua quis potest uti re alterius absqur •h•· opinion of G rotius but did not accept it (Ck ju r~ nnlura~. 2.6.6, 208).
damno et incommodo illius. Ut enim dicitur Decretorum dist. I, par. "Omn~ l~g~:· Ntransirc 44. Ibid .. JOll- 309, "Sic dico in proposito quod iudex no n tantum iuris habl'I ""I''''
per agrum alienum fas est, id est aequum .. .. Licitum est quod a lege indul~m est .... _'u!I
N • "'I'"~ damnati, quin l'I ip!i(>m<'I damn,1111!< similitt>r S<'<'u ndum animam habt-t. Q uantum
est aequitas quae dat actionem rem vendicandi ... ~itll!I r!ll opportumla~ ulen.d1 re ••11i111 h.1 0t' I ill<' iuri~ in d t>tinl'ndo t•t , ..·d dc•t1•lo , lilnlumdcm Pl plus hahet isll' In 11ht•1111d o
aliena .. . ." See the Ordin11ry Cl°" lo Di!lf. I c.1, " 1"11!1 t'lll, ill f'llt llf'<JUUm • . • Item 1ure d1vlno • 11111 pnh•ril, c•t vitam cu~todil'lldo. c•I ••II""' p l11.~ uni• h .11...1. q uia iuJrll ncm tnnln nrn'tlllilitl••
licitum est romedere uvas in •Km altrrlm1 . . tam<'t1 11011 ""' 11111. 1<1 '"'' Im• nun dat civill•m • " '"l" 'llitur t•um llt•lin••n• .t11I '""·id <'rt'. •11111111;> 11r1 •"••ildh' p n 1ph•r i11lll11rn nwlum rnorll.•
actlonem." • ''"'l"'llil11r •l.1mn11t u" •11111cl lllM pruvhl1111I. ' "' "'"""' rt I"'• l••1·U11114•m !C\111111 l11 1·urpon• 11mlt
40. H,. dlt•d th<' glt>M tu/~ nm~ . I JM 'It Jto, " N"' """""" 1111111111·~• """t ,, lurh• .. l.11, •1111,1. •I i11hcN· 11011 pruvhlt•tl'I •I 1 ~ •••1• 1 h1Yl't1h•• l•M11111 c•I h•111p11.., 111 Mi fmlc• 1·nl'I • lnr
86 THE IDEA O F NATURAL RIGHTS RfCHTS ANO DUTIES 87

Having reached his conclusion, Henry, in typical scholastic fashion, criminal closely then the latter could and should escape. The judge had
gave a detailed response to the contrary argument that he had placed at no right "in the substance of the body" of the criminal; the right that he
the beginning of the Quaesti~e body of the criminal belonged to the did have he lost by failing to exercise it. The escape did not injure the right
judge; therefore he could not licitly take it away. Henry replied that the of another: rather it was imputed to the negligence of the judge.48
criminal could take away anything necessary to sustain life, just as he I It is not surprising that Henry of Ghent should have chosen to discuss
could take another's bread in case of necessity, provided that he did not I the moral rights and duties of a condemned criminal. Aquinas had already
violate the right of the judge. But how could he escape without doing ;j considered the same problem, and it became a fairly common topic of
this? To carry the argument further, the author returned here to his initial scholastic debate. But Aquinas, in typical fashion, discussed the question
distinction between property and use, the different modes in which the entirely in terms of objective moral law without exploring the subjective
same thing could belong to different persons. One could have a "power" rights of the judge and the criminal.49 Henry of Ghent based his whole ar-
or "right" over something in two ways, Henry explained, either as re- gument on an elucidation of the individual rights of each party. Starting
gards property in the "substance" of the thing or as regards use, the ex- out from some canonistic definitions and doctrines, he created a kind of
ercising of some act concerning it. The judge did not have the first power rights language that was neither Thomist nor Ockhamist, nor indeed, as
or right of property over the body of the condemned man any more than the argument progressed, like that of any preceding canonist, but that was
over his soul; he had only the second right of using the criminal's body in oddly similar to the language of early modem rights theorists. Henry's ar-
the ways already described (capturing, imprisoning and killing him).45 gument was not identical with that of any of the seventeenth-century
Only the criminal himself had a property right in his own body or, as
Henry put it, "only the soul under God has property in the substance of
the body."t6
ti
f
"~
writers we considered (just as their discussions were not identical with
one another); but it contains many of the same elements of discourse that
characterized the later works. In Henry's Quaestio we find an emphasis on
individual rights, specifically the natural rights to preserve life and to ac-
It is interesting that Henry used the word proprietas. Often in medieval
and early modern discourse one reads that a person had dominium over :;'""" quire the necessities of life; self-preservation treated as both a right and
himself. But there was an ambiguity in the term. Dominium could refer to a duty; the idea that a person has a kind of property right in himself;
property, but it could also mean control or mastery of one's behavior as in the equating of a right with a licit power; and an elaborate inquiry, more
our phrase "self mastery." Aquinas used the term in this sense when he explicit and detailed than those of the seventeenth-century authors them-
wrote of mens' dominion of their acts, dominium suorum achtum.47 Henry selves, into the correlative rights of judge and criminal.
avoided the common term dominium here and specifically referred to pro- Henry's Quaestio was not forgotten. Just after 1500 Jacques Almain
prietas, a property right. Continuing his argument, he asserted that one took up the question of the condemned criminal in his commentary on
was bound (tenetur) to use this right in order to preserve one's life- Ockham's Octo quaestiones. Almain belonged to the nominalist school of
but, again, without injuring the judge. The argument ended with a final thought that was dominant at Paris around 1500 and, as Francis Oakley
twist. If the judge kept the criminal in firm custody, chained and locked in has pointed out, he was a figure of major importance in the transmission of
gaol, then the criminal would indeed injure the judge's right by trying to l<lte medieval conciliarist thought to early modem political theorists.50 But
break loose. But if the judge omitted to exercise his right of confining the in this case he relied, not on Ockham or on conciliarists like Pierre d 'Ailly
who were influenced by Ockham, but on the earlier work of Henry o(
vinculis et ostia essent aperta, nee adesset impedimentum abeundi et per hoc vitam sal- 48. Quaestio, 309, "Quod custodiret in praeiudicium et iniuriam iudicis, si, cum existell'I
vandi, sui ipsius homicida esset, non providendo sibi sicut deberel. w n •rpus in vinculis aul in firm a ta custodia, ut, abiret, vincula disrumperet aut carcerem.. . .N;
45. Ibid., 309, " Ad cuius intellectum sciendum est quod supra rem aliquam dupliciter Ibid., 310, NSi tamen iudex damnatum dimittat in carcere sine vinculis et negligil firman•
haberi potest potestas sive ius: una quo ad proprietatem in substan!ia rei, alia quoad usum rnrc:erem in quo est damnatus, et sic omittit eicercere circa ipsum ius quod habuit, qui.. nN
in actione aliqua exercenda circa rem. Primam potestatem aut ius nullatenus habet iudex ' "·d dit nee detinet, absque omni iniuria iudicis, qui nullum ius h.abet in substantiam ror
saecularis super corpus damnati plus quam super animam illius, sed secundam tantum, p n ri,;, potest corpus suum abducere.... Per hoc enim amittit ille ius suum quia . .. non
quae consistit in tribus, scilicet in corpus capiendo, in vinculando sive incarcerando, et in •"'«"ffl'ndo ius suum, anima exet«'nll' quod potuit et debuit, a iure suo alienatur, hoc llt'gll ·
occidendo.'' Krntinl' sune impute!."
46. Ibid., 309. "Potestatem autem quoad proprietatt>m in sub~tantia C'orpori.~ sola anima 4'1. Summa thtt>l~iat, 2.211t•. 611.4
habet sub Deo, et tenetur ius suum in hoc cll:lltod ire absqul' iniurin nltt-riw1." _r.c1. fl. O<lklry, " Nntm111l l ."w, ll1t• ( "11rp11• My•llr·um. nml <:on!IC'nl In Condlinr ll-u111Khl
47. Summll thtologiat, 1.2ae.1.2. '" •m lohn ul l',.rl!l !11 Mnlhl"" l IA1111h1•. ·· . .,,,. ulmn '1<1 ( l'Jtll ): 7116 lllU .
88 THE lDEA OF NATIJRAL R IGHTS RIGHTS AND DUTIES 89

Ghent. Almain paraphrased Henry's argument at length and reached a nality in this area has sometimes been exaggerated. On the other hand, the
similar conclusion. "It seems to me that if it is licit for him to flee he is twelfth-century Decretists made original and significant contributions to
bound to do so, because by natural law he is bound to preserve the life of the shaping of Western rights language. Then Henry of Ghent made his
his body." 51 Almain also discussed more briefly a treatment of the problem own distinctive contribution as we have seen.53
by Robert Holcot, a fourteenth century English Franciscan. Holcot was one A continuous chain of texts connects the idea of dominion of self with
of the friars in whom Beryl Smalley discerned "dassicizing" tendencies, the seventeenth-century doctrines. There are relevant comments, for in-
and his argument about the condemned criminal provides another ex- stance, in Olivi, Gerson, Summenhart, Vitoria, Suarez, and Grotius. Some-
ample of this approach. He made no reference to the prisoner's rights but times dominimn was taken in Aquinas's sense of self-mastery; sometimes
emphasized instead the public welfare, the good of the respublica. Hokot the idea of property persisted, especially in discussions on whether a man
argued that punishment was not inflicted for the good of the criminal but could sell himself into slavery._ It is a story that has never been adequately
for the good of the republic, which in tum resulted from the goodness of written. Medievalists sometimes complain that their work is "margJnal-
single persons. If, then, the criminal resolved to reform, to abstain from ized," not sufficiently regarded by scholars working in other fields of
vice in future, even to give his life for the republic if necessary, it would be research.54 But in this particular area, the history of natural rights theories,
licit and meritorious for him to save himself. This was because more good '• perhaps it is we medievalists who are at fault. We cannot reasonably claim
might come to the republic through his survival than through his death; it that our work is neglected when there is still so much for us to do.
was possible that more people would be restrained from crime by the ex-
ample of his virtuous life than by his undergoing punishment.52 Almain
thus offered two approaches to the prisoner's dilemma, one a humanist ar-
gument based on classical republicanism, the other a scholastic argument
I
!'. ·
·~ !

based on individual natural rights. Interestingly, it was the scholastic ar-


gument that persisted in seventeenth-century discussions of the problem.
The language of subjective natural rights has become a central, charac-
teristic theme of Western political discourse. It is important to know when
and how the duster of ideas it conveys grew into existence, what historical
contexts made their articulation possible and their survival likely. A glance
at Henry of Ghent's Quaestio suggests that seventeenth-century rights
language cannot be adequately understood simply as a response to the
contingencies of the early modem era. Rather, it was an adaptation to new
circumstances of a much older tradition of discourse. The key concepts
of the seventeenth·century rights theorists often had medieval origins.
But, in tracing out those origins it is not enough to look at Aquinas and
Ockham. Aquinas had no theory of natural rights, and Ockham's origi-

51. f. Almain, Expositio circa decisiones Magistri Guilfdmi Occam in L. E. du Pin, ed., Jo·
hannes Gnsonii opera omnia, 5 vols. (Antwerp, 1706), 3: col. 1103. Almain' s contemporary at
Paris, John Mair, also disrossed the problem of the condemned criminal but without explicit
reference to Henry of Ghent and w ithout the same emphasis on individual rights. See his /11
quartum Sententiarum quaestiones (Paris, 1519), Dis/. 15 q . 22, fol. cxxiir.
52. R. Holcot, In qual uor Jibros Sentenliarum quaestiones {Lyons, 151 R), 3.1 (no pagination), 'l1. I l<'n ry also d iscussed tlw di~tin.:tion h1•tween a, right and the object o( the' riKht in hi~
"Lex enim nunquid precipit hominem occidi nisi propter bonum reipuhlic:l" .. . fat aul<'m Uw>fililirt 12 q. 21 , C'd cit.. 16: 1119. <)11 thi~ ,..,.. f. V1•raja, IL origirri della rontro!lf'rsia ttV1111xm1 s11/
possibilc in casu quod ista fugiens m<'lion>tur pt>r vitam d 1><·r nwrila qm• ro!<I fadt>I • flll l raltn di .-rn."'1 rir/ XIII !<l'COlc• (R11mr, l'Ui(I)
plusquam per m ortC'm illatam corrigen>tur, t>I t~l po!i.'iibik• quod phm".'1 c·nrri~,mlur t>t ,1 mal••- 'l4. I. l'a th·· rson, ..On lht- MuKln l'••lr11oolt•t111..111. lnHlil' lfi~tory. and Mt'<lit•val S1Udl4•11,"
ficiis retrahanlur per vit,, m !luam 'l'"'m pt•r J111pplki11m 111111111 l'.•K•' 111111111·11~11 Alhl lk d ho" ·;,.,., u/u,,. b~ j 1•r10). H7 11114 I m111lr 111111 h llw """ "' n1mpl11lnt In " I fi••rnn-hy, <·urnM•nt, 11nol
fort'rc>, vid,•lkt•I d.-.-linart• mnr!t•m ro·r 11111,11111 "inr i11i11rl~ f•t11\lllll .. lho· Wt"!<l..rn Tr,,.Htiun." l'oilllto1I I""" II I "I II''"'/) t•lf•,,.,7
FOUR

THE BEGINNING OF TI-IE DISPUTE

n 1321 Pope John XXJI initiated a debate over evangelical poverty that
[
soon led to a bitter dispute between the pope and the leaders of the
r ranciscan Order.' Rather improbably, the murky theological problems
involved in this controversy gave rise to intricate debates on topics that
would later become central issues of Western political theory; and this is
•-specially true as regards the theory of rights. No participant in the con-
1roversy set out deliberately to compose a treatise on natural rights; but, in
lhe course of the arguments that arose, all kinds of such rights came under
discussion-the right to acquire property, rights to establish governments
.md to limit their powers, natural rights as distinguished from civil rights,
.1lienable natural rights and inalienable natural rights, natural rights that
were also duties, and what would later be called adventitious rights.
In the years around 1300 the understanding of ius as a subjective fac-
ulty, formulated earlier in canonistic jurisprudence, was becoming fairly
widespread. The texts of Peter Olivi, Johannes Monachus, and Henry of
( ;hent that we have already considered suggest a growing awareness of
the richness and complexity inherent in the concept of subjective right;1

I. There is a very large literature on the Franciscan disputes. M. D. Lambert proviJt•11 "
dt•;ir o utline in Franciscan Povrrty. Thr Doc:lnn" oflht Absolutt Powrty of Chri~I and thl' Ap>.lllr.•
111 Jhr f'ranriscan Ordtr, 1110-132.1 (London, 1% I). On tht" o utbreak of the controvcT11y undrr
fuhn XX ll, with C'Klensive furthf'r blhllogr•phy, ~A . Trtb11rmol, Paupt-rla~ Clrri!;li ti DP"f'lcili•
111111 • .l.'idrnll' frnnrt!l<'Qrl(I i n dl""llNC/cmr r 1.171 r.l/fJ Cttonw. 1 ~19(1).
2 Aht1VI', :w 41 . 7H- H'I.

IJ '
94 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS THE BEGINNING OF iHE DlsPUTE 95
but it was the Franciscan dispute that first drew this concept into the although the Franciscans possessed no property from which they could
center of a major public debate, a controversy involving a reigning pope live, still they were not tempting divine providence because, by the "law of
and some of the leading inteJJects of the age. The intricate details of the heaven" (iure poli), they were permitted, like everyone else, to take what
dispute need not concern us; but, to understand the arguments concern- they needed to sustain life in case of extreme necessity.4 Finally, in what
ing rights that grew out of it, we need to review briefly the course of the proved to be the most controversial passage of all, Nicholas explained in
controversy. Exiit that the Franciscan way of life as he had defined it was also the way
of Christ and the apostles:
FROM FRANCIS TO 0cKHAM This is a way of religious life pure and immaculate before God
the Father . .. handed on by his Son to the apostles by word and ex-
Soon after Francis of Assissi died, disputes arose in his Order about
ample ... inspired in blessed Francis and his followers by the Holy
the way in which the Rule he had composed was to be observed. In 1231 Spirit. . ..5
Pope Gregory IX issued a clarification. The pope declared that, in accor-
dance with the intention of their founder, the Franciscans should own Exiit became a sort of Magna Carta for the Franciscans. It both confirmed
nothing, individually or in common, but should have only the use of the their Rule and equated their practices with the evangelical way of life
things that they needed. In 1245 Pope Innocent IV made this arrangement taught by Christ himself.
more practicable by taking all the goods of the Order into the ownership of In 1321 Pope John XXII, for reasons that remain obscure, decided to
the Roman church. From then onward the pope acted as a sort of trustee. challenge the Franciscan doctrine of apostolic poverty (though he always
The Franciscans used the property conceded to them by benefactors, but claimed to be merely "interpreting" the decree of Nicholas Ill).6 The pope
they did not legally own anything. Still, disputes persisted, and in 1279 opened his attack by inviting theologians and canonists to debate publicly
Pope Nicholas III promulgated the bulJ Exiit, which gave a more precise the question, "Whether it is heretical to assert that Christ and the apostles
and very legalistic definition of Franciscan poverty, using the technical had nothing singly or in common"; and, to facilitate the debate, he revoked
terms proprietas, possessio, ususfructus, ius utendi, and simplex us11sJacti: Nicholas Ill's decree forbidding discussion of Exiit. The Franciscans, as-
In temporal things we have to consider especially property, possession,
sembled in a general chapter at Perugia under their minister-general,
usufruct, right of use and simple factual use, and the life of mortals re- Michael of Cesena, issued a public encyclical declaring that the issue had
quires the last as a necessity, but it can do without the others. 3 been settled once and for all in Exiit and strongly implying that John XXII
had no power to change the ruling of his predecessor in such a matter.7
The Franciscans, according to the pope, had given up everything except John regarded the encyclical as insolent in form and erroneous in content.
"simple factual use." The language of the bull was taken over largely from In January 1323 he moved decisively against the Franciscans by issuing
the Apologia pauper-um of St. Bonaventure. But, while Bonaventure had the bull, Ad conditorem.1 On the level of practical administration he under-
referred to property, possession, usufruct and simple use of fact, it was mined the Franciscan position by relinquishing papal ownership of the
Nicholas Ill himself who introduced the phrase " right of using," and so
ensured that the concept of a right would become of major importance 4. Ibid .• " .. . nee ipsis fratribus iure poli in extremae necessitatis articulo ad providen·
in the subsequent disputes. Pope Nicholas himself had no such intention
of course. Precisely in order to exclude any future controversy he com-
manded that no glosses should be written on his decretal. (The text still
l•
(
<lum sustentationi naturae via, omnibus extrema necessitate detentis concessa, praecluditur,
n1m ab omni lege extrema necessitas sit exempta.n
5. Col. 1110, " haec est apud Deum et Patrem munda et immaculata religio . .. pt"r eiui<
lolium exemplariter et verbaliter apostolis tradita . . . deinde IX'' Spiritum Sanctum be11t11
stands, bare of commentary, in many early glossed editions of the Corpus Francisco el eum sequentibus inspirata.. . ."
iuris canonici.) 6. Modem theories about John X:XU's motivation are discussed by T. Turley, HJohn XXll
Other phrases used by Nicholas III in Exiit also gave rise to later dis- .md th<' Franciscans: A Reappraisal," in Popts, Teachtrs, and Canon I.Aw in thr Middlt A,11~. rd!I

sensions, especially a passing reference to the ius poli. The pope wrote that, r R. Sw('t!fley and S. Chodorow (Ithaca, NY, 1989), 74-88. Some of the respon1<'!1 to lht· pc>p<·
w 1•re printed in F. Tocco, La quistiont drlla povrrltl ntl StCO/o XIV (Naples, 1910).
7. Thi~ a!lp«t of the contmv1•r11y i~ di!lt't1!1!k'<i in my O rigins of Pa1111/ /1rf11/lif1ih111.
3. E. Friedberg. ed., Lim st:clus in Corpus iuris canonici, 2 (Leipzig, 1879), Stxl. 5.7.3, 11 '>0 IJfi(). 2nd l-d. (l..eiden, 19Rq)_
col. 1113, " Nam cum in rebus temporalibus sit considerare praecipuum proprietatC'm, p~­
sessionem, usum fructum, ius utendi, et simplicem facti usum, C't ultimo tanqui'lm l'W('~~ario
,.,,,.,,r
II E. rriNtl"<·~· l'd .• r.xtrlllltl!(flnf,.,. /I , ,•.,,,,,. x XU in Cntpou 1uris 1·t1111,,,in. 2 (I A·lp7IK.
11rl'I)· r:1 rrm• 14 1, 1'nl" 121'1 2'-1 1'111"111111... '"'"'''' ""'"'" ••tllltun ~ l.1nn•nt. ftfflll~l.l(llttlro
egeat, licet primis carere possit vita mortalia . . . ." f,./11111111.• XX /I (V.ilkrtu l 'Uy, 111" I)
96 TuE l DEA OF NATUltAL RIGHTS TuE BEG INNl NC OF T HE D ISPUTE 97

Order's goods. He also presented a theoretical case against their claim to John who calls himself Pope John XXll." The pope replied in the bull, Quia
have renounced all ownership and right of use. Reviving an old argument vir reprobus. Ockham entered the fra y with his Opus nonJJginta dierum, a
that had been used against the Franciscans by earlier critics of the Order, very detailed, word by word commentary on the pope's bull.
the pope maintained that there could be no separation of use from owner-
ship in things that were consumed in the act of using them. According to
the law, a right of use permitted one to use something "saving the sub- APPROA CH ES TO 0CKH A M
stance of the thing." So there could be no such right when the substance The Franciscan controversy has often been seen as a source of later
was destroyed by use-as when one ate a piece of bread for instance. Only rights theories if only because it stimulated the polemical writings of
an owner could licitly destroy his own property. It would be absurd, the William of Ockham, the " father" of subjective rights according to Miche l
pope asserted, to suppose that Nicholas Ill had intended to reserve for the ViJley. 10 Yet Ockham himself remains something of an enigma. For Georges
Roman see the ownership of such things as "an egg, a piece of cheese, or a d e Lagarde the venerabilis inceptor was "an awakener of the modem world";
loaf of bread," while assigning only the use of them to the Franciscans. for John Morrall he was "an interpreter and defender of the achievements
Moreover, the pope argued, even as regards nonconsumable things, there of the past.''11 In spite of all the work of the past few decades no consensus
could be no licit use without a right of using. To use something without a has emerged concerning Ockham's early philosophical and theological
right to use it was simply to act unjustly. doctrines or concerning his later writings on political theory. Nor is there
The Franciscans reacted to the pope's decision with dismay and indig- an y agreement about the relationship between these different spheres of
nation. Their proctor at the papal curia, Bonagratia of Bergamo, protested his thought; this too remains problematic.
against it so strongly that the pope punished his presumption with a There are several different ways of addressing Ockham's work-
year's imprisonment. Finally, in November 1323, the pope gave his de- scveral different contexts within which we need to consider it-if we are
cision on the underlying theological issue of evangelical poverty. In a sol- to evaluate adequately h is contribution to the growth of Western ideas
emn dogmatic decree, Cum inter nonnullos, he declared that henceforth it about natural rights. One common approach to Ockham takes the last
would be heretical to maintain that Jesus Christ and the apostles did not problem mentioned above as its starting point. According to this view,
"have" anything, individually or in common, or that they had no "right of Ockham's political ideas can best be explained by placing them in the con-
using" the things that they actually did have or no right of selling, giving, text of his volunta rist and nominalist philosophy. Advocates of this meth-
or exchanging them.9 odolog y, prominent among them de Lagarde, Villey and, more recently.
nus seems a flat condemnation of the Franciscan doctrine of apostolic Michel Bastit, usually find Ockham' s work to have been radically inno·
poverty, but for several years the leaders of the Order tried to argue, with va tive and essentially destructive. The Franciscan's "corrosive criticisms,"
various verbal equivocations, that the pope's decrees could be reconciled lhese au thors assert, both subverted medieval institutions and, in th«:>
with Exiit and with their own Perugia encyclical. Among the Franciscans world of thought, fragmented an earlier scholastic synthesis. Ockham' s
at Avignon was the brilliantly innovative theologian, William of Ockham, nominalism, it is maintained, led on to "social atomism" and h is volun-
who had been summoned from England to the papal curia and there tarism to a positivistic conception of law as mere command.
accused of various unorthodoxies unconnected with the poverty dispute. Another group of scholars-including critics of de Lagarde and Villey
At some point a superior, probably Michael of Cesena, commanded Ock- like Morrall and Kolmel-argue that Ockham's political and ecclesiologi·
ham to study the pope' s decretals. Ockham became convinced, slowly m l writings have no necessary connection with h is early specu lativl'
and reluctantly as he later wrote, that the pope was teaching heresy. philosophy; they maintain that the political ideas were derived or could
Michael of Cesena was coming to the same conclusion. Finally, after an have been derived from more traditional sources.12 These authors usually
angry confrontation w ith John XXII in 1329, Michael fled from Avignon
accompanied by William of Ockham and Bonagratia of Bergamo. The IO. M. Villey, LA formation dt lo pm5b juridiqut modrrnt, 4th ed. (Paris, 1975), 226.
three dissidents took refuge at the court of the emperor, Lewis of Bavaria, 11. G. d t:' Lagarde, LA nnis.<;anrr dr ,.,.,.,,,;, lniq11r au dlclin du moytn 4ge, 5 vol11. (1'11riJI.
who was engaged in a political dispute of his own with the pope. From I 'l'i'1- 6.'\), 5:.'\37. This i11 a l'\"Vi1wd v1•r!\ion or 11 work orig inally publi~ht>d in ~ix v11l11rnM1
ll'.tri!\, 1'H 4- 4"). J. B. Moru ll, "Somr N 11tr" on 11 R1,-..nt Interpretation of Willhu n nf Od..·
there Michael issued a series of manifestos indicting ns a twrctic " the Lord
1..un·~ rolltki\I Ph ilo!!o rhy," frtt111·/•r1111Sll11fl,. 11 ( 1•14•11 l:l~ 6'1 at ."169.
12 lt>i1t .. W. Klllm l'I, " I )111" N11turn-t hi lwl W lllw hn vo n l kkham," l'rur11 i~l1mi"' llf' Srml1rn
9. Exlrov. 14.4, ml11. 12'N< lO. 1•, ( 1'1'>1 )· 1'l -14'>, tti.•m . Willtt'f111,..,,, I ~ Ah.!H1 111111 orltr lhdrt•111~ 1/ill~rl1rt1 Srhrlflm ( E.,,...n , 1% 1)
98 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS THE BEGINNING OF THE DISPUTE 99

see Ockham' s work as moderate and constructive. Neither line of argu- This seems a coherent argument. But there is another whole side to
ment has provided altogether satisfactory answers to the questions that Ockham's thought that has been emphasized by several recent schol-
will most concern us. How did Ockham come to formulate a doctrine of ars. Marilyn Adams has referred to Ockham's moral theory as "notorious
natural rights? And what, if anything, was innovative in his teaching but widely misunderstood";17 and John Kilcullen concluded a recent d is-
about them? Villey and de Lagarde wrote extensively, but, it seems to me, cussion by observing simply, "It seems that Ockham's moral theory is
not convincingly about Ockham's rights theories; their critics have not fo- not voluntarist." 18 In fact, Ockham left a complex web of texts from which
cussed particularly on the Franciscan's thought about rights but more on modem scholars have extracted a variety of theories. Certainly Ockham
other aspects of his political theory.13 emphasized both divine omnipotence and human free will. But he also
The problem of understanding the relationship between the different insisted that human reason could provide a reliable and necessary guide
areas of Ockham's thought is complicated by continuing disagreements to moral conduct. Ockharn maintained that only a voluntary act could
about the kind of moral theory that the venerabilis inceptor developed in be morally right or wrong; but he held that, precisely because the will
his early theological and philosophical works before he turned to writing was free to choose either good or evil, something we know from experi-
on ecclesiology and political thought. Those who see Ockham as a radical ence, the will needed a directing rule other than itself.19 This rule was
voluntarist emphasize his teaching on the absolute freedom and infinite right reason. Ockham declared over and over again that any virtuous act
will of God. Reacting against a strain of Aristotelian necessitarianism that had to be elicited by the will "in conformity with the dictate of reason.''20
had appeared in medieval philosophy, Ockham insisted that the divine Moreover, the exercise of right reason did not involve merely the for-
will was entirely unconstrained. In God there was no distinction between mation of moral statements; it included also the act of assenting to such
will and intellect. Whatever God willed to do was done justly and well. propositions as a source of moral obligation.21 Evidently, for Oc.k ham as for
And nothing that God willed in regard to creatures was willed necessar- other scholastic philosophers and for the earlier canonists who had de-
ily.14 So the whole universe that God had made, including the universe fined ius naturale as a "force of reason" in man, the term right reason did
of moral values, was contingent. By his absolute power God could create not mean merely ratiocination (or " reckoning" as Hobbes would put it).
some other universe of values in which it might be virtuous to steal or lie Nor was reason, as in some later voluntarist theories, merely instrumental,
or commit adultery.15 In the world of human affairs, it is argued, this led on a "slave of the passions," guiding us to the attainment of the end that the
to a doctrine of law as simply the command of a legislator and of rights as
17. M. M. Adams, #The Structure of Ockham's Moral Theory," FranclSCQn Studies 46
mere assertions of individual wills. Since the moral principles that guided
( 1986): 1-34 at 1. Adams quoted the view of Helm together with half a dozen similar remarks
human conduct were commands of an inscrutable God, who could change
from other authors.
them ?twill, they could be known only through God's revealed word and 18. J. Kilcullen, "Natural Law and Will in Ockham," History of Philosophy Ytarbook 1
not through any natural law accessible to human reason.16 (1993)· 1-25 at 25.
19. OTh, 6 :375, " . . . solus actus voluntatis est bonus vel malus moraliter"; 8:410 uma vol·
untas quae potest . . . indifferenter bene agere et male . . . indiget aliqua regula diri~te
13. For a moderate discussion of Ockham's rights theory in relation to his nominalist phi- .ilia a se"; 9:88, "Potest tamen evidenter cognosc:i per experentiam . .. quod quantum-
losophy see A. S. McGrade, "Ockham and the Birth of Individual Rights," in 8 . Tierney and rnmque ratio dictet aliquid, potest tamen voluntas hoc velle vel non velle vel nolle." Tht'
P.. Linehan, eds., Authority and Puwer. Studies on Mtdiroal Low and Gowrnmmt PrtSmttd to works I found especially useful for the following discussion, besides those of Adams and Kil-
Walttr Ullm11nn (Cambridge, 1980), 149-65. McGrade pointed to •affinities" between Ock- " "llen already cited, include: L. Freppert. Tht Basis of Mor1ility According to William of Ockham
ham's nominalism and his political concepts without asserting that the latter views were (Chicago, 1988); O. W. Clark, "Voluntarism and Rationalism in the Ethics of Ockham," Fran·
necessarily derived from the former ones. ,·iscan S tudies 31 (1971): 72-87; idtm, "Wil.l iam of Ockham on Right Reason," Sptculum 48
14. Guillrlmi dt Ockhom "P"a plrilosophiai tt theologica, eel. G. Gal et al., 17 vols. (St. ( 1973): 13-36; K. McDonnel, " Does William of Ockham Have a 1l1eory of Natural Law7"
Bonaventure, NY, 1967-88). Opn-a thrologictl 4 :664, " . . . nulla penitus est distinctio inter es- l"rauciscan Studi~ 34 (1974): 383- 92.
sentiam et voluntatem nee inter voluntatem et intellectum...."; 3:478, " . . . co ipso quod 20. OTh, 6:422, " . .. de ratione virtutis perfectae et actus eius est quod elidatur <'<>n-
ipse (Deus) vult, bene et iuste factum est"; 9:589, "Quidquid Deus agit ad extra, rontingenter lunnitcr rationi rectae ... .H; 8:362, "nullus actus est virtuosus nisi sit conformls l't'Ctllf"
agit et non necessario...." 1.11i1•ni . ...- ; R:409, - . . . actus recte t>lidatur a voluntale necessario ~uirilur 111iqua ""'-"'"
15. OTh, 5:352, " . . . odium, furari, adulterari et similia . . . etiam meritorie possunt fieri r.1ti11 in intellectu ....-; 8:410, Hll(ln poh'ltl C'!'llM' rt'Ctu" et virtuoeus nisi habtoal ratiolle'm
a viatore si caderent s ub praecepto divino, sicut nunc opposita cadunt sub praecepta.• rt"(·fnm "; 9:177. 11w l<'fm umoral" R'frr11 tu "11t'llhu" 11uhll'<"ti!t poteitati volunlatiS lll'CUndum
16. P. Helm, ed., "Introduction," in Divint Commands and Morality (Oxford , 1951), 3, 11o1l11rnlc• 1lkh1men rntionl11...."
"Ockham could consistently only regard ethics as a matter of ~p«ial divine revelallon In 21 OTh. f.:42'.l, •• . .. 111·tu" clkt11111ll 1111..Urt·lu• 11011 ""' forrnalltt'f rnmplt'xum, M'<I ,.,.,
scripture or elsewhere, and not as a matter of natural law rfiM'l'ntrtf lhmuKh rea~11111r «•m- n 1·ti 11111•,...nllc•mli v1•I cll.111W"11llf"n1ll 1·11111pl.,_11 111111 l11111111ot111 El f"w: Ulo 11C'l11 lllllM'ntlrrnll Jtl'lll'f
science." nlur pru1lrnlln, 11011 t111ll'1t1 ,.. f11rn 1111tl11111' 1111111•1•"1 ••
100 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS THE BEGINNING OF THE OISPUn: 101

will desired. Rather, the Franciscan philosopher was using right reason in out that the topics Ockham discussed in his political works were all di-
a typically scholastic sense to mean a "directing rule" of conduct.22 As re- rectly or indirectly related to juristic problems. He argued therefore that, to
gards the source of this rule's authority, Ockham held it to be a self-evident understand Ockham's distinctive contributions, we need to enter the "ju-
principle of morality (per se nota) that the will ought to act in conformity ristic thought world" of the Middle Ages. Gagner emphasized Ockham's
with reason. 23 From such self-evident principles (of which there were rnnstant reliance on the texts of Gratian's Decretum even, paradoxically,
many according to Ockham), and from experience, it was possible to build when the Franciscan was arguing that a theologian was better equipped
up a "nonpositive moral science . . . that directs human acts apart from than a canonist to discuss the points in dispute between the friars and the
any command of a superior." 24 All this seems far removed from a radical pope. Gagner also discussed another of Ockham's comments that helps to
voluntarism. t•xplain this persistent reliance of a theologian on the texts of canon law.
Yet Ockham also held that, behind right reason, stood divine com- At one point in the Dialogus, when he was about to discuss the rights of
mand as an ultimate norm of morality.25 Modem scholars have found it the Roman empire, Ockham's Master explained that, for a thorough treat-
difficult to reconcile Ockham's various pronouncements. One of them ment of the subject, he would need an extensive library that would include
concluded that "Ockham has no ethical 'system'."26 At least it is evident hooks on theology and moral philosophy and a variety of histories. But
that there are both rationalist and voluntarist elements in his moral theory. in fact, the Master complained, he had access only to the Bible, the Dec-
Stephen McGrade even referred to "the rationalism of Ockham's volun- rdum , and the five books of the Decretals. 29 The vast majority of Ockham's
tarism."27 The point for us is that, when one approaches Ockham's work rl•ferences are indeed to these sources or to the ordinary glosses on them
by considering the relationship between his early speculative writings that commonly accompanied the text.
and his later polemical works, it is necessary to consider, not only whether De Lagarde also called attention to Ockham's use of canonistic sources,
there was any significant relationship between the two areas of thought, r ven though he placed more emphasis on the Franciscan master's nomi-
but also, if that proves to be the case, what elements of his earlier thought 11.1list philosophy in interpreting his political works. The French scholar
were most relevant for the later writings. 1·ven took the trouble to count the citations in one book of the Dialogus.
A different approach to the venerabilis inceptor was suggested by Sten I le found three references to Thomas Aquinas, twelve to church fathers,
Gagner in an article on Ockham's concept of dominium.28 Gagner pointed sixty-five to scripture, and three hundred and thirteen references to canon
l.iw.30 As de Lagarde wrote, Ockham "installed himself in the labyrinth of
22. The common scholastic understanding of recto ratio as the practical wisdom that
the Decretum and its glosses" 31 in order to examine afresh the basic prin-
should guide our conduct was rooted in Arislot.le's Ethics. The phrase took on new shades of «iples of ecclesiology; but de Lagarde also referred to Ockham's "insidi-
meaning when it was associated with the medieval conscirntia and syndertSis. ous subtlety and respectful impertinence." He thought that the display of
23. OTh. 9:177, H • •• multa s unt principia per se nota in morali philosophia; puta quod 1-.m onistic learning served to mask Ockham's true intentions; the Francis-
voluntas debet se conformare rectae rationi, omne malum vituperabile est fugiendum et ,-,,n was really subverting the tradition that he purported to expound.32
huiusmodi.N This, however, is by no means self-evident. When we seek to locate
24. Ibid., HScientia moralis non positiva est illa quae sine omni praecepto superioris di·
rigit actus humanos; sicut principia per se nota vel nota per experientiam sic dirigunt. ..." c >ckham's thought in the world of canonistic jurisprudence that provides
Later on Suarel. saw Ockham as the fountainhead of a voluntarist tradition that based all 1 •ne obvious context for evaluating it, we need to keep other possibilities in

morality simply on the will of God. He contrasted this view with another late medieval doc· mind. Above all we need to ask whether Ockham really was a radically in-
trine holding that the moral principles discerned by human reason would be valid even novative critic of existing juristic ideas when he shaped his own doctrine
if there were no God- an argument famously restated by Grotius. Jt may be that both the
of natural rights. Was he imposing novel meanings on the texts he cited?
later positions were extrapolations (perhaps distortions) derived from diffe rent aspects of
Ockham's work. c lr simply selecting from existing interpretations the ones most suited to
25. Ibid., 8:411, n • • • voluntatem d ivinam volentem talem elicere actum conformiter his purpose? We cannot know whetherOckham was a revolutionary with·
rectae ralioni •
H 1•11t some familiarity with the pre-existing canonistic orthodoxies.
26. Clark, "Ockham on Right Reason," 35.
27. A. S. McCrade, Tht Politico/ Thought of William ofOclclram (Cambridge, 1974), 195. Mc· 7'I l>ialuxus in M. Goldasl, l'd., M"'11111"hi11 S. Rtlmani imJKrii, 2 (Frankfurt, 1614): :lW. CJ~7
Grade's work is especially valuable because the author gives due weight to the rationalist " ' K70_
side of Ockham's moral thought. :lll IA 11ni!<!ian.-r, 4 (1%2), .'\2.
28. S. Gagn~r, "Vorbemerk\Jngen zum Thema 'Dominium' bc•i Ockh..m," Mi~crl/anrn ,,,,.. I I. I .a 1111i!1.wr111·r , ~ ( l'lt..1), 2\W
diatvalia 9 (1974): 293-327. 1:• tJI llfll~llll'I', '\ ( 1%.1). 12to
102 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS THE BEGrNNrNC OF THE DISPUTE 103

A further problem here is that we know very little about when and structure of the corpus of canon law with its major commentaries. It seems
how Ockham came to study the canon law, or about how extensive a to me likely that, when Ockham began to study the problems of poverty
knowledge he acquired of canonistic literature. H . S. Offler, who knew and property at Avignon, he acquired a fairly extensive knowledge of can-
Ockham's texts so well, saw this as "a problem awaiting further investiga- onistic commentaries on the dozen or so texts of the Decretum that were of
tion";33 but there seems to be no definitive evidence that would lead to a central importance in the dispute and that later he worked from memory
solution. Often Ockham used arguments that seem to echo some early De- or possibly from a dossier of notes. In any case, if Ockham really did in-
cretist teaching but without any direct reference to a source or any certain tend to build a doctrine of rights on canonistic foundations, he would not
evidence that he had actually used the relevant text. Ockham certainly have needed any vast juristic erudition. Huguccio, together with the ordi-
knew at least the Ordinary Gloss to the Decretum of Johannes Tentonicus nary glosses to the Decretum and the Decretals, could have provided all the
and relied heavily upon it. One has the impression that the Franciscan sources he needed. And often the arguments of his adversary, Pope John
often had this work open in front of him as he hunted out arguments to XXII, who was a professional canonist, would have pointed Ockham
refute his adversaries; but his use of even this source is not always appar- toward the texts he most needed to study. Ockham was not striving to
ent. Quite frequently Ockham gave specific references to the Ordinary l·onstruct a political theory or a system of ecclesiology in a vacuum. He
Gloss, but occasionally he quoted it without mentioning his source; and was engaged in a furious dispute with the pope. His own positions were
sometimes it is helpful to know the source in order to understand the point shaped in response to the arguments, often juridical arguments, of the
that Ockham was making.34 Because of various similarities of thought l'nemies he sought to vanquish.36
and language I think that, apart from the Ordinary Gloss, Ockham must at This can remind us of a final context in which Ockham's work has to
least have known the work of Huguccio, perhaps through some intermedi- he considered, the context of the Franciscan dispute itself. Much that Ock-
ary source. One such work that Ockham could have used was Guido de ham wrote was drawn from a common stock of Franciscan arguments; a
Baisio's Rosarium, a vast compilation of glosses on the Decretum that rein- 100 exclusive emphasis on Ockham's personal role can distort our under-
troduced much early half-forgotten Decretist scholarship to the world of standing of the whole affair. Other participants in the dispute, Ockham's
the early fourteenth century.lS .uJversaries as weJI as his allies, were also important in developing the con-
It remains true though that Ockham was a theologian, not a profes- l·cpt of subjective rights. The Dominican theologian, Hervaeus Natalis,
sional canonist; probably he never acquired a firm grasp of the whole wrote interestingly about property rights; so did the Franciscan canonist,
Bonagratia of Bergamo; so did Marsilius of Padua; and so too of course did
33. H. S. Oftler, "The 'InOuenct" of Ockham's Political Thinking: the First Century," in Pope John XXII himself. (When, centuries later, Suarez and Grotius wanted
D~ Gtgmtoarl Ockhoms, eds. W. Vossenklilil and R. Schonberger (Weinheim, 1990), 338-65 at l o discuss the o rigin of private property they did not choose to quote
359 n.56. l >ckham; but they both cited the decretals of John XXU.) I am not suggest·
34. Ockham's use of canonisbc sources is discussed in more detail in my articles, ing that Ockham's own contribution was inconsiderable. On the contrary,
"Ockham, the Conciliar Theory, and the Canonists," Journal of lht History of Ideas 15 (1954):
lhc Franciscan master should always be seen as a figure of major signifi-
40-70 and " Natural Law and Canon Law in Ockham's Dialogus," in J. G. Rowe, ed., Aspects of
Latt Mtdimtl G<nltrnmnit 11nd Socirly. Essllys Presmttd to/. R. lander (Toronto, 1986), 3-24. The c.mce in the history of rights theories; but we cannot grasp the nature of his
discussion in the text above is based mainly on these two papers. rnntribution unless it is set against the background of these other writings.
35. Guido's work was certainly known at Avignon in the 1320s. The Rostlrium was used by There are then, several contexts within which Ockham's work can ht•
the canonist Z-enzellinus de Cassanis in his commentary on Cum inter (John XXU"s dogmatic •·valuated. To understand adequately his ideas on natural rights we m•cd
decree on evangelical poverty). Relying on an earlier gloss of the canonist Alanus, which he
lo keep in mind especially the three I have mentioned above-the conkxt
quoted from the Rosarium, Z-enzellinus wrote that the pope could create a new article of faith.
This tmqualified assertion proved unacceptable to John's curial advisers, and Zenze!linus was •,r Ockham's own earlier theological writings, the context of his canonistic
required to rewrite his gloss in a more discreet fashion. Ockham can hardly have been un· ·;nurces, and the immediate context of the dispute over Franciscan povcrly.
aware of the dispute. It touched the heart of the Franciscan case and occurred at Avignon
while he was resident there. Oclcham referred to the view of Alanus in his Dialogus (1.1 .14,
421) but without explicit reference to his source. H he did trouble to look up the disputed text
in the ROS11rium he would have found there an ample array of Decrcti11t gl<>lli!t'S on the issues :lt•. Jn OriJ(it1.~ I 01rgul'CI that Cldthnm w111 11'\I hy hi~ ronflkt with John XXll In propo11n1I
that came to dominate his later work. I noted a d<JM> Vl'rbn I para IIt'I bctw('('O Ockham 's Brnril · 11ll11w1'<l 01nd incoh<'n•nt t't•ck~loln"y llut I waa 1·nrn·1·m.-.l then- o nly with his t ..A.-hlnK on
oquium and the ROMrium In "Ockham, thl' Conciliar looiry, 1111<.t tlw l'11nnnl"tt1:• 45 . On th<- llw lnfolllhility of tlw popt• Ancl th" Mo11111111111111 h I •lo not lhlnl thnl lh" i<11mr n ltld " " ' "I'
dll'lputl' Involving :t..t"nzcolllnu•llf'«' my clrlx111- "' l'111ial /11f11/ll/>llll11, 1•14 •I'\, 27.tl plh·io "l'rd lk11lly tu l lo·kh"rn·- tl1<111Khl ••~ 1111 11ah1111l 1l11ht,.
LANCUAC ES OF RIGHTS 105

ownership and all rights. For the purposes of our inquiry the important
point about these arguments is that they led Hervaeus to make frequent
use of words like ius, dominium, potestas, and proprietas. He often associated
the concepts of right and ownership in the phrase ius et dominium, which
he used over and over again almost as if it were a single hyphenated vo-
cable. He also frequently associated the concepts of right and power.
To appreciate the significance of this we need to recall the widely ac-
cepted view of Michel Villey that William of Ockham was the first phi-
losopher to understand the word ius in the sense of a subjective right
FIVE and, further, that the semantic breakthrough came precisely when Ock-
ham "resolutely twisted" the idea of "right" to the meaning of "power"
,
.........
•,,• • • . ..#_ . , . , ,. , . '
in phrases like "A right is a licit power" (ius est Ucita potestas).1 In fact,
the understanding of a right as a power was common in juristic thought
LANGUAGES OF RIGHTS long before Ockham. But Villey maintained that a new philosophy was
needed to justify such scattered usages before they could form the basis
of a new jurisprudence. In his view, Ockham provided the necessary
philosophical foundation; his nominalism was the "mother" of subjective
right. And this meant further that the modem concept of individual rights
J[ n the foll~w~gdiscussion I want to prescin~
as far as possible from was derived from a philosophy radically inconsistent with the teaching
the technicalities of the argument about FranctSCan poverty in order to of Aquinas. In modem discourse, Villey noted, a right means "the power
concentrate on a rather formalistic but important theme-the various defi- itself, a quality of the subject, the dominium which he has over things."
nitions of ius that emerged in the course of the dispute and, especially, the But such a definition was impossible within a Thomistic framework of
understanding of ius as a subjective power. This is a typical case where thought. For Villey the idea of subjective natural rights was logically
we can understand Ockham's distinctive contribution only by considering incompatible with the objective "classical natural right" that we find in
first the arguments presented by some of the other major participants in Aristotle and Aquinas.3
the controversy. Especially relevant are the views of two sharply opposed Now Hervaeus Natalis was a faithful Thomist, an ardent defender
thinkers, Hervaeus Natalis and MarsiJius of Padua. of Aquinas's philosophical doctrines against their various critics, a man
"~lowing with enthusiasm for Thomas," according to a modem account.•
But, writing some ten years before Ockham entered the controversy over
HERVAEUS NATALIS, Ius AND P OTESTA S l'vangelical poverty, Hervaeus persistently used the same language about
One of the most influential responses elicited by John XXIl's invitation "right" and "power" that we find in Ockham, the language that is sup-
to debate the issue of evangelical poverty came from the master-general of posed to be the Franciscan master's distinctive contribution to the growth
the Dominican Order, Hervaeus Natalis.1 In his treatise, De paupertate, Her- of rights theories.
\ "ilCU!; formul.itcd two urgumcnts th.it I ha,·c ai1~dU} mt!tttionc<l Hl con The relevant part of Hervaeus's treatise was concerned with the queN-
sidering John XXIl's case against the Franciscans-licit use of things that tion, "Whether right and ownership in temporal things can be separa ted
were consumed in use (like foodstuffs) could not be separated from own- I m m use o f them." To address this question the Dominican first explained
ership; and there could be no licit use of any thing else without a right of tlw meanings of ownership (dominium), right (ius) and property (proprir-
use. Since the actual use of things was necessary to sustain life it followed l11s ). According to Hervaeus each of these words co nveyed the meaning of
that Franciscans and the apostles before them, couJd not have rejected all
2. M. Villt>y, l.11 /ormalron dt> la pt'n.• lr j1iri1liq1u moclt'rnr, 4th ed. (Paris, lcr75), 225 -262, ""
l''"dn11y 247 4q _On Vill<'y'!! vll"WI',..... nhove", ( n . I
1. J. G . Sikes, ed., HHervaeus Natalis: De paupertate Christi et apostolo rum," A rcliivrs 1 I /lid., 227, NF.n tout CH . .. IC' 1ln11t ••tl.,...·111 rtd lnKhJut•mmt lncomp111lbh• 11vc•.- l1• clmll
d 'hisloirt doclrilflllt ti lilUrairt du moym ~gr 12- 13 (1937- 38): 209- iq7. ""'""'! d111U1itllH' •
4 1: I l<o••t1111'h, 1'11rl11 '/"h" rr1ld11· .~. h1~il (I 1t1l•111111r, 1UM), 117, •111u llllK M11rlln l :r11hnumn
- 104 -
106 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGES OF RIGHTS 107

a power to use or alienate a thing.5 But there were different shades of vaeus, however, argued that the slave and the monk and the son did have
emphasis. Dominium referred more to the power itself, ius more to the Jicit- a right since the master and the monastery and the father had an obligation
ness of the power, and proprietas indicated that the thing in which a righ t to provide them with the necessities of Jife. 10 In this way of thinking, rights
was held was one's own, not belonging to someone else. Hervaeus also and obligations were correlative; to assert that a person had an obligation
noted here a distinction between a factual power and a lawful power. to someone implied that the latter had a right. The situation was different,
(The Franciscans claimed to retain only a "factual use" of things.} De facto Hervaeus conceded, when a permission to use something was held purely
a person could use something licitly or illicitly; but licit use required a at the will of the owner; but even then the user had a right of use so long
lawful power. The power to use licitly, Hervaeus noted, meant a "power as as the permission was in force. Further on, Hervaeus explained that those
of right" or "the right itself." 6 who lived on alms did not lack a right in the things they used; it was
The argument then turned to the various ways of holding "right just that they held the right by the grace and liberality of someone else. A
and ownership" (ius et dominium). Here Hervaeus distinguished between subproblem concerned the owner's right to revoke a permission he had
the principal owner of a thing and one wh0 had a right in it. A person who granted. In the case of a thing consumed in use it seemed that the owner 's
leased a house, for instance, owned a right to use the house; he had a kind right and power to do so endured until the thing was actually used and so
of dominion therefore as regards the right, though he did not own the ceased to exist: At the end of the argument, however, Hervaeus explained
house itself.7 The idea that one could have dominion over a right had been that this was to envisage an absurd situation. A person who gave to an-
developed earlier by civil lawyers and Hervaeus was making the same other the right to use a piece of bread really gave him the ownership of it
point.' This seems to be the starting point of the argument about whether without retaining any right for himself. On the face of it, Hervaeus wrote,
every ius implied some kind of dominium that Richard Tuck pursued in its it was ridiculous to suppose that a person would give someone bread to
later stages.9 t•at while retaining the right to snatch it away from his teeth. In consum-
Hervaeus went on to consider another problem that was often de- ;ibles, he concluded, licit use could not be separated from ownership."
scribed by later participants in the poverty dispute. The Franciscans often Such rather arcane reflections became staple themes in the later litera-
argued that a person who made use of things solely by permission of ture of the Franciscan dispute, and Hervaeus continued to pursue them in
someone else-which was their own position so they claimed~ould use . 1 complex and repetitive fashion. For us, however, the main point is not

without having any actual right of use even as regards consumables. A the substance of his argument about Franciscan poverty but the fact that,
slave, for instance, used the property of his master, including the food he in the course of it, he persistently, almost obsessively, kept on defining a
ate, without ever having a right to it. And it was the same with a monk in right as a power and specifically a licit power. "Potestas licite utendi idem
relation to his monastery or a filiusfamiliae in relation to his father. Her- 1·st quod ipsum ius," Hervaeus wrote.'2 Here are some more examples
(with emphasis added). "By concession of the owner one has a licit power
5. ~ pauputall!, 235-36, "Quantum ad primum, sciendum quod ista no m ina, 'do- of using and this we call a right"; "ownership, right and property all imply
minium', ' ius', et ' proprietas', idem dicunt in re. Nichil enim aliud dicunt quam habere
.1 110wer. ... "; "a right is, as has been said, a licit power of using . ...";"to
potestatem in aliqua re per quam possit licite re aliqua uti vet rem aliquam alienare.. .."
6. ll1id., 236,
ff• posse licite dicit pos,'K' iuri.<i !<ivt> ir,mm in~ "
••
have a right in that use is to have a power of licitly using.... ";"to have a
7. ~ paupt!rlall!, 236 .J~ . 111>wer of licitly using is to have a right"; "a power of licitly using is called a
8. Digtstum novum (Venice, 1598), gloss ad Dig. 42.5.8, col. 660, "Contintlur: quantum ad l.1wful power or a right."13
ius, cuius dominus recte dici potest." The same doctrine was expressed by Bartolus on Cod. When Ockham in tum defined a right as a licit power a few year~
4.19.4, " . . . quicurnque habet aliquod ius dominium illius iuris d icitur habere." On the teach-
ing of Sartolus see the important a.rtide of H . Coing. " Zur Eigentumslehre des Sartolus,"
l.1h' r he was not introducing into the debate some novel concept drawn
Ztilschrift dl!r Savigny-Stiftungfar Rtrhlsgeschichlt!. RiimiscM Abteilung 70 ( 1953): 348-71. Simi-
larly in canon Jaw the right in a benefice could be treated as a form of duminium. On this see Ill. Dr po11perlalr, 238. "Talis cui concessus esset talis usus haberet iu!I in rP 11ihi <'On
C. Gross, Das Recht an der Pfriindl! (Graz, 1887), 186-87. , '""!'" _. quia m onasterium, paterfamilia.~ et dominus obligantur monacho, filiofomiliAA rt
9. ln the 1330s the argument was taken up by ano ther Dominican, Jo hn of Naples, who '"'' vo .td nt'C"eS.<;ari11 vit11e."
wrote in response to Ockham. See his Qulll!Slionts variat Parisi is disputalat {Naples 1618), 359. 11 . Ibid., 242. " l'rimil enim (rontc- vitlrlur dni11ihile quod aliquis conc~al alkul p1'nf>m
" ... habens licitum usum alicuius rei habet necessario eiusdem rei dominium, salkm secun- ,ul n 1mt'<l<'ndum ct retint'lll flih( hu1lli>tolr"IM'llllt1!1• 1l..ntih11A <'illll . . . in l111i USU pm l ..mpt>,...
dum quid, seu partiale. .. . " Much later, around 1500, tilt- i!l,.UE' was debatE'd l>E'lwttn lhE' 11011 :oot•p.tr••hir mm" licitus 11domlnln111 f1' ••
Dominican, Sylvester Prieras, ;md tilt' Franci!K"an. Ang<' lo dt• Cl;iv;u;io. On their vk•w:c ~'t' my 17 ll•itf .• 741
"Tuck on Rights: Some Mt'di.-val l'roblt·m~... / fi.t litr.lf "( 1'11/iti."DI 11mu.11ht t> {l'IH'.1)· 4'.N 41 1\111! 11. ll1ul .• 2:1'\,
h • ol«' 1'tlll4"PPhH,., 1luml11I '"I hl\l'<'I 11lhJt11t<l /~t~~r lldtum 11tr111ft 11111 n•, rl
II('(' be-low. 24'.I 45. ..... VUt'l\lllll• ,,,~ .. . ) ~. .. , .....1 11111101 1l1•111l11h1111. ,,,. v..1 pn•p• l•ltUI ...., ......., ,~.,,..,.
108 THE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHTS LANGUAGES OF RIGHTS 109

from his nominalist philosophy. On the contrary, Ockham himself noted often been discussed; but Marsilius has not usuaUy been regarded as an
at one point that the understanding of ius as a Heit power was a position important figure in the history of rights theories. He did, however, also
that had earlier been adopted by his adversaries. It seems quite probable make a significant contribution in this area of thought.
that he took his "nominaJist" definition directly from Hervaeus, the faith- In the early modem period, when the idea of natural rights was
ful Thomist. 14 moving to the center of political discourse, various writers not only took it
Hervaeus did not invoke any metaphysical premises in the course for granted that the word i11s could be used in a subjective sense to mean a
of his discussion on rights; his argument grew out of the context of the dis- right; they also thought it necessary to discriminate carefully between this
pute itself. The Franciscans could hardly deny that they exercised a licit meaning and the other senses of the word. The scrupulous analysis of the
P:°wer wh~ .t hey used external goods; and if a right were defined pre- varied meanings of ius, that we find for instance in Suarez and Grotius, has
cisely as a bot power they could not reasonably claim to have given up 11ften been seen as a significant step in the development of Western rights
aU "right of using." This was the argument that Hervaeus suggested and rheories at the beginning of the seventeenth century.15 But, as usual, therl'
that Ockham later on set out to refute. But, although Hervaeus saw no were medieval precedents for the early modem formulations. When W<'
need to appeal overtly to Thomist metaphysics in constructing his argu- 1ry to trace them back to their origin we find an explicit distinction bl'-
ment, he was certainly not intending to go against the principles of the lween the subjective and objective meanings of ius in Driedo and De Soto,
revered master whose doctrines he defended so vigorously throughout the .md still earlier in Conrad Summenhart who wrote just before 1500.16
course of his career. Indeed, at the time when he wrote the De paupertate, Summenhart mentioned Gerson as a source of his defmition of ius but
Hervaeus was actively engaged in promoting the cause of Thomas's can- I his particular distinction between ius as objective law and ius as subjectiVl'
onization at the papal curia. When I discussed Vtlley's work earlier I sug- right is not in Gerson (or in Ockham}. Its first overt formulation seems to
gested that, although Thomas himself did not choose to develop a doctrine have been in the Defensor pacis of Marsilius of Padua. Summenhart wrote:
of subjective rights, there was nothing in his work that necessarily ex- lus is taken in two ways. In one sense it is the same as law (/ex) as when
cluded such a concept. One can add now that the principles of Thomist we say that the precepts of God are ius divinum and the statutes of em-
philosophy and the idea of subjective rights were not only theoretically perors are ius civile ... In another se.nse ius is taken to be the same as a
compossible; they actuaUyroexisted in the work of Hervaeus Natalis. More- power as when we say a father has a right (ius) as regards his son, or a
over this was not just a rare aberration. The combination of a professed king as regards his subjects and men have a right (ius) in their things and
Thomism with an acceptance of a rights language derived ultimately from possessions. . .. 17
medieval jurisprudence was characteristic of the greatest thinkers of the
Marsilius presented a similar distinction. He explained that, according to
Spanish "second scholasticism," whose works provide the principal link
•me meaning of the word, ius meant divine or human law; but in anothc•r
between medieval and modem rights theories. Hervaeus Natalis was an
-;t•nse it referred to a kind of subjective power.
early exponent of a position that later came to be widely accepted.
Thus in one sen se ius is the same as lex, divine or human ... . In a second
MARSIUUS OF PADUA. Ius AND LEX way ius refers to any voluntary human act, power, o r habit ... in con-
formity with ius taken in the first sense....18
Marsilius of Padua is a very well known figure in the history of politi-
cal thought. His role as the most radical critic of the Avignon papacy has 15. The views o f Suarez and Grotius are discussed belo w in Chapter 12 and Chapl<'r \'.\
16. See A . Folgado, Evolud6n historica dtl conetpto dtl dutdto subjtclivo (Madrid, 1%0).
tmr . .. .N; 240.ff• • •ius est, ut dictum est, potestas licite utendi aliquo re•.. .H; 240, f f• • •
'"'· 1n, t96.
habere ius in ipso usu est habere potestatmr licite utendi...."; 240, ".. . habere pottStatmt licite 17. ~ ronlrartibus /icitis alq11t illicilis (Venice, 1580), 1.l,1, " ... jus capitur duplicilt•r. llnn
utendi est habere ius. . ..•; 241, N • potestQS licite utendi dicat potestatem iuris sive ipsum
• • """'" id<'m ~t quod lex. quo modo accipitur cum dicimus praecepta DPi t"s..'W' jull d ivinum ••I
ill$...•"' • u11.'ltit11tiones imperatorum esse jus civile ... Alio modo a ccipitur jus ut id<'m <"Ill q111Mt
14. Opus non11gint11 diuvm in H . S. Offler, ed., Guillelmi dt Ockham opu11 politie11, 3 vols. 1•nlt·~t;,~. quo mo do accipitur cum dkitur patrem habere jus in filium, rcgem in ~uhJi1t111. 1•1
{Manchesttt, 1956-74), 2:559, " . .. iste impugnatus (i.e . John XX:IJ] ponit hie ius utendi es.'K' l u11nim~ hab<-r<' ju~ in rebu~ et p<l!\!lf'ftJ1ionih1111 "ui~. . .."
licentiam utendi seu licitam potestatem utendi. .. ." There j_, no reason to doubt that John 111. R. Scholl~ ed., Mnrsilii dr Pad1111 l "'f~n11or l'u.-i~ (1lano ver, 1933), 2.12.6, 2t.ff. "'Sk IKll"'
XXll understood a right to be a licit power, but the pope did not actually use the phrase. On "'""111<l11m imam 11ignifkadunt•m lu.• ltlrm r~I 111111tl l1·- d ivinll vet h11m11nA . .. ·· 2.12 .111, 'ltt'J'.
the other hand Hervaeus Natalis used it repeatedly. When Ockham was commanded to ··111dt11r J111lrm iu • Nt't·tm1ln mncl11 1lr 11111111 1111111111111 "' 111. puh'~t11h•, Vf'I h11hllu n111ft1r
study the issue of Fra.nc:i9can poverty he could hardly h•vl' ovrrloolcl'd the w o rk of Hi•r· mlh•r 11111 .l1et11 !M'nmclum p rlor"m 11111111111111 lu111•111 •• llwn• IJ1 l4t1 •·-r1111cli'tl vrulnn 111 thr
vaeus, the principal Oom.i nican oppont'nt of the Prancl"'•n J><•ltlu11 11,.1 1frh11ltl1111 "' I 12 I. 1tt4 llu•w lt•d11 "'" 111•1 tt•••~ l 1111 l1•l11ll hrl11w
110 THE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHTS LANGUAGE'S OF RIGHTS 111

Such a text may remind us again that we need to consider other par- pacis omitted these chapters as "contaynynge no matter moche neces-
ticipants in the Franciscan dispute besides Ockham when we investi- sarye," and Marsilius's modem editor, Previt~on, called them "an
gate the history of rights language. But the present situation seems to be excrescence." 22 In 1970 Jeanine Quillet noted that no modem commentator
that scholars who are interested in Marsilius are not interested in rights. had provided an analysis of these "long and important chapters" and that
And scholars who are interested in rights are not interested in Marsilius.19 they had generally been regarded as irrelevant to the main theme of the
Perhaps this is because the work of Marsilius does not fit in well with the work.23 Quillet herself did not associate Marsilius's discussion here with
common modem view that theories of subjective rights are essentially the growth of later rights theories, but she did show how it fitted into
a sort of by-product of late medieval nominalism. Marsilius was not an the whole pattern of his argument. Marsilius was concerned to deny all
extreme nominaJist but an Aristotelian; and modem neo-Aristotelians are temporal power to the pope and clergy. Much of his argument was di-
often hostile to ethical or political doctrines based on subjective rights. rected against the claims of the hierarchy to temporal jurisdiction; here he
Again, Marsilius is often regarded as a corporatist or "holistic" thinker pursued a complementary theme by arguing against clerical claims to
who constantly emphasized the claims of the corporate community, the temporal wealth. Marsilius argued that the practice of perfect poverty
universitas civium rather than those of its individual members. But the involved the renunciation of all rights to property, that Christ and the
structure of medieval corporations, both in juristic theory and in the day- apostles had practiced such poverty, and that it would be fitting for the
to-day life of guilds and communes was not simply " holistic"; rather it dergy of his own day to follow their example. Marsilius was pursuing his
was marked by constant tension and interplay between the claims of indi- own agenda, different from that of contemporary Franciscan controver-
viduals and those of the corporate whole. Medieval lawyers described a sialists, but the whole pattern of his argument here was shaped by the
corporation as a fiction of the law precisely because they attributed actual dispute over evangelical poverty launched by Pope John XXIl.
reality only to the individual persons who composed it.211 Marsilius ac- Briefly summarized, the argument about rights ran like this. First of
knowledged the same point when he noted that the political community .111, Marsilius declared, it was necessary to discuss the meanings of the
was made up of persons who were "many in actuality and formally sepa- word ius because this word was needed to explain the other terms used in
rate from one another. . .." 21 the controversy over evangelical poverty.24 Next he gave his first definition
Another reason, perhaps the main one, why Marsilius's treatment of of ius. " Ius then in one of its meanings refers to law."25 Then Marsilius ex-
rights and dominion has not attracted much attention from modem histo- plained further that "each law is a command or prohibition or permission
rians of rights theories is that the relevant argumentation is contained in a of acts that occur under the control of the human mind."26 The notion of
group of chapters dealing with the convoluted problems of Franciscan permissive law that Marsilius introduced here was not original with
poverty. They seem at first like an obscure eddy, outside the mainstream him-it is found in Roman and canon law sources-but Marsilius's appro-
of the political theory that has interested most modem students of Mar-
silius. John Marshall, in his sixteenth-century translation of the Defensor 22 C. W. Previt~on, The Defmscr Pads ofM#rsilius ofPadWI (Cambridge, 1928), xx, 222.
23. ). Quillet, La phr1osophie politiqut de Marsile dt Padout (Paris, 1970), 203. Among the•
more recent studies several do include discussions of Marsilius's views on apostolic poverty.
19. Most arguments about Marsilius tum on other questions-what the sources of his S1.•e P. di Vona, I principi dtl Defrnsor Pads (Naples, 1974); I<. E. Spiecs, "The Eccleslastk11I
thought were, and whether he favored absolutist or limited government, oligarchy or l'overty Theory of Marsilius of Padua. Sources and Signific.ance, n pmsirro polrlico 10 ( )977):
H

democracy. Such issues are discussed in C. Condren, nDemocracy and the Defensor Pads: 'i -21; M. Damiata, " Funzione e concetto della povertl evangelica in Marsilio da Padova,"
On the English Language Tradition of Marsilian Interpretation,n II pmsirro politico 13 (1980): Mrdi«VO 6 (1980): 411-30. But these authors are not interested in Marsilius' leaching nn
301- 316. Further extensive bibliography on Marsilius is included in Carlo Dokini, Crisi di 1ights. Further literature is given in Conal Condren, #Rhetoric, Historiography and Political
poltri t politologia in crisi (Bologna, 1988) and in the works cited in n.23 below. ll1t'Ory: Some Aspects of the Poverty Controversy Reconsidered, /ount11I of R~ligious Hi~l"ry
H

20. See P. Michaud-Quantin, Uniuersilas. Expressions du mouvrmtnl communa11taire dans Ir 1:1(1984), 15-34. See also G . de Lagarde, La n11iss1ma dt l'tspril laiqutau dklin du moym d,1(1',
moyen-8gt latin (Paris, 1970), 206-211. And see below, 212. '•vol~., 2nd ed. (Paris, 1956- 70), 3:329-357.
21. Defrnsor pticis, 1.17.11, 119, On Marsilian individualism see A. Gewirth, Mnrsili11s of 24. Veftnsor pocis, 2.12.3,264.
Padua. Tht Defmder of the Peact, 2 vols. (New York, 1951-1956), 2: 91 , 121, 218. In discussing 2_<;. Ibid .• nlus igil\Jr in una sui 11ignifkatione dicitur de lege... -H Mar.dllull l't'frrml
the above text, Gewirth discerned in Marsilius "a transition . . . from nominalism to real- lu•n• to his earlier definition of lr:r at I . tcl.4, " ... ordinacio . .. habft\s roactivam potendam,
ism." It would be more true to say that his work simply n'ON't<'d th<' mmmon view of lilt' I.I 4~t. de cuiu.~ obst>rvad~ datur pn-t'C'J'lllm, qund qul11 rogitur obetrva,.. ... lex 1'111. H

age on corporation structure. In his introduction to the r>tfr11,..•r t :.•wirth P<'n.'"t'ptivl'ly calll'<l 26. 2.12.:l, 26.';,
H • •• utraqu«' 1..- r•I l'"""'l' lum v..i pmhlblclo aut pt"l'mh111lu • •·tuum
a ttention to " the distinrtion t>t•twet>n 'o!>i<'t·tiV4'' 11mt 'H11l•]<'<·tlv1•' 1l>thl ·· In Mnr1dli11M. S«>t> Mar '1'1l prnv1•nl"' 1mnt natl ah lm1,.rl11 m1111ll1 lnm1a1.., " l "f. I lij(nl 1.4.3 aru.t lJ11t :11·.4 of lhr
siliu.<fl/ f'adun, 2:1oxv. 1i.-, rr-l1m1 Arnf ,..... al•ovr. tt7
112 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS

priation of the idea represents a new departure in his thought. Earlier he


had maintained that Jaw, in its proper sense, was a command or prohibi-
' r.
LANGUAGES OF R IGHTS

right,' when he wants or makes use of something in conformity with ius


in the first sense." Then Marsilius added," And this is what we previously
113

tion of the ruler backed by coercive sanctions. Now, he explained that called 'licit'."JO A right then (ius in the second sense) specified an area of
permissive law was "an ordinance of the legislator obliging no one to licit conduct allowed by law or a rightful claim to some external good. (In
punishment." 21 For Marsilius, then, permissive law did not compel or pro- thus treating ius in its subjective sense as either an immanent power or a
hibit any human action; rather it defined an area of free choice where claim Marsilius was deploying two concepts that would often be distin-
the individual could licitly follow his own will. The word "licit," Marsilius guished in later writings as active and passive rights, or rights of action
explained here, applied to any act done in accordance with the law (in- and rights of recipience.)
cluding permissive law). Later on in the argument permissive law would Marsilius next undertook to define dominium, ownership, and the re-
be important as a source of the subjective rights both to acquire property lationship between ius and dominium. In its stri.ct sense, he wrote, domini11m
and to renounce it. meant a principal power of laying claim to something acquired in accor-
Before turning to that topic, Marsilius had one further distinction dance with law and of excluding others from it. This power was called
to make about ius understood as meaning law-the common division of the "right" of some person because it conformed to ius taken in the first
ius into ius naturale and ius civile, natural law and civil law. Marsilius did ". sense.3 1 Here again there was the association of power and right that
not find this distinction very useful. The word "natural" was used equivo- we have already noticed in Hervaeus Natalis. For Marsilius the power of
cally, he pointed out, to mean either those parts of human law that were holding or ownership was necessarily associated with the will of the
common to alJ nations or alternatively the dictates of right reason that owner. Dominion was nothing but "the actual or habitual will to have the
came under divine law. 28 The impJication was that "natural law" as a sepa- lawfully acquired thing."" To provide for the case of an infant who could
rate category, was superfluous; all the content of natural law was included legally acquire property, Marsilius acknowledged that there did not have
either in positive human law or positive divine law. Like some later posi- to be a positive will to acquire; but a negative will excluded ownership. No
tivists, Marsilius went on to develop a theory of rights, including moral one could acquire dominium against his will.33
rights-rights that were morally justified but not enforceable before a For Marsilius, then, dominium was a power of laying claim to some-
human court-without appealing to a doctrine of natural law. He was not thing in accordance with the law. But he had already defined a right (ius in
a~uir.6, however, that all rights were just favors conceded by a human
legislator; the notion of positive divine law was essential to his argument. I
Turning now to the second, subjective meaning of ius, Marsilius gave 30. Ibid., "Secundum hanc quidem significacionem soliti sumus dicere: hoc ius alirni11s
r~~. cum rem aliquam iuri primo modo dicto conformiter vult aut tractat." Marsilius al~o
the definition quoted above. "In a second way ius refers to any voluntary
human act, power or habit . .. in conformity with i11s taken in the first
sense. .. . " That is, a subjective right was a voluntary act, power or habit 'i'
II
!
gave. very brie fly, two further meanings of ius-as the sentence of a judge or as "an act o r
habit of particular justice." He did oot, however, refer to these definitions in the su~urn1
discussion.
in conformity with objective law. Such a right could be immanent in the 31. 2.12. 13, 2.7 0, "(Dominium) significat stricte sumptum potestatem principalem vl'!tdi-
person of the right-holder or it could be "transient," related to some exter- ,·andi rem aliquam quesitam iure dicto secundum prim.um modum . . . volentis eciam
nemini alteri licere rem illam contractare absque . . . expresso consensu .. . que siquidt•m
nal object; and then it could refer to a thing itself or something pertaining

I
ius a licuius dicitur, quon.iam iuri primo modo dicto ronformis.. .."
to the thing like use, usufruct, acquisition, retention, exchange. 29 In this 32. Ibid., " Hee autem potestas nil aliud est quam actuale aut habituale velle sic hat....mli
sense of the word Marsilius explained, we often say, '"This is someone's n-m iure quesilam.... " This was a common theme of earlier Franciscan writing. Stt c;nlft.11,
.. Usus facti" (above 37 n . 84). And see now Brett, Uberty, Right and N11turt.
33. In a final comment on dominium, Marsilius wrote that the word could rell'r to hum.111
27. 2.12.4, 266, "Sunt autem alie quedam ordinaciones non obligantes ad penam ut will or freedom itself. In this sense dominium belonged to man alone among all C1tht-r n•'"
actum liberalitatis exercere vel omittere.... Et talia proprie dicuntur lege permissa ... per- t11r1~. This kind of domini11m was inalil'll<!ble, and witho ut it there could he no cc>ntn•I 111
missum vero proprie dicitur ordinacio legistatoris ad penam neminem obligans." n h•m .tl goods (2.12.16, 271 ; 2.13.9, 2111. The argument that every kind of rightful ownniohip
28. 2.12.7-8, 268-269. w.ts r<M•tl'd in man's rational control uf hi~ own far ulties, presentl'CI l'arlicr by Aquin11!'I, wn"
29. 2.12.10, 269, " Dicitur autem ius secundo modo de omni humano actu, potestate vd ,1,•vd o pt'<I furlhl'r in later right" ll11•11ri•'\'C (in 1l1~·u!l1ion..~ about alil'nation t•f Tight" ancl lhr
habito acquisito, imperato, interiori vel exteriori, tam immarwnh• quam lran,w unte in rl"m pos_<;il"tll' t>xisl1•0Cl' of Tight" in 11nlmo1I• 1m1l l11fnnt1t And ln!'lllnt' pl.'n;on..~); but Mar.dllua 1lkl not
aliquam exteriorem, aul in rei aliquid, puta u~um ilUt u11ufrur turn, nr.1111~1.-iorwm, dt•lc•n-
111.•lll' 11111«h of it tlf' ri•frrrf'll to lhr 11111111111•111 ll1 l'""''h111 ''" "',1lmu!ll M'lf-c'Vl1ftonl." Still, hl11
ciont'm llt'U con:'lervadonl'm aut rommutacionl'm, 1•1 r..11,1w• "1111111.. <"o nlormih•r iuri dklo
11U"nti1111 of"·'"'' l'<'r""''" 111111111111111 uv111 '11• 11w11 .,.1f ,f1 N'• '"'Kii''"' "n lnKr"lnt'tl ln<llvhlu"I
"t'l"Undum priol"l'm !'li~niri1·1Kiorwm •·
1.i11 .11 tlw rout 111 hi• th1111Khl
114 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGES OF RIGHTS 115

the second sense) more broadly as any power in conformity with law. He understood as a legal power equivalent to dominium .38 Later Marsilius ex-
therefore logically explained that ownership was a kind of right. "Owner- plained that a man vowed to perfect poverty might catch a fish in the sea
ship (dominium) is called a right (ius) of someone. .. .34 Later he explained and eat it without ever acquiring dominion over it if he did not wish to
that, although ownership implied a licit power or right, not every licit own the fish or to assert a legal claim to it against others.39
power or right implied ownership. /us and dominium were not identical In practical day-to-day life there could be licit use without any right of
terms; rather dominium was only one species of ius.35 ownership when a person acted with the consent of the real owner. Here
Titis distinction was important when Marsilius turned to the problems again the will to acquire ownership was decisive. Even if a donor intended
of evangelical poverty. We need not follow all the detail of his argument .· to transfer ownership as well as use the recipient would not acquire own-
here. He wanted primarily to maintain that, although all licit use had to be ership if he did not wish to do so. Anyone was permitted by law to use
in conformity with ius (in both senses of the term), this did not necessarily without owning something belonging to another, even to the extent of con-
imply that the user had a right of ownership even in consumables or any suming it, if the express consent of the owner intervened.40
right that could be asserted before a human court. For Marsilius, owner- Having shown that complete renunciation of all property right was
ship and use were conceptually separable. One could renounce the one legally and practically possible, Marsilius went on to argue that Christ and
and retain the other. For instance, one could renounce all ownership of ~
the apostles had indeed made such a renunciation. And so he reached his
external goods by a religious vow of poverty; but one could not take a desired conclusion, that it would be fitting for ministers of the Gospel in

I
licit vow to renounce all use of things. This was because to do so would his own day to live in the same fashion and for the church to be stripped of
be tantamount to suicide, which was forbidden by the positive divine all its wealth.
law, "Thou shalt not kill."36 The fundamental right of self-preservation was Since we are interested in Marsilius's argument primarily as it re-
also a divinely imposed duty and so inalienable. lates to the history of rights theories, the most interesting aspect of it is not
On a strictly legal level too there could be use separated from owner- ' the conclusion about the disendowment of the church but the definitions
ship. The argument here relied on the points about permissive law and and distinctions developed along the way. Much of the discourse dealing
about human will as a source of dominion that Marsilius had discussed specifically with evangelical poverty was not peculiar to Marsilius; like
earlier. Clearly the law permitted a person to acquire property in various Ockham he drew on a common stock of Franciscan arguments. But to base
ways-through a gift say, or through his own labor in hunting or fishing or the whole discussion on a formal distinction between ius as objective law
some other work. The owner then had a lawful power of using the thing and ius as subjective right and then to sustain the distinction consistently
acquired and also of claiming it against others. But the law permitted re- through the whole course of the ensuing argument-this does seem origi-
nunciation of rights as well as their acquisition. "Anyone can licitly re- nal with Marsilius. Fourteenth-century jurists understood of course that
nounce a right intwduced on his own behalf for, according to divine and the word i11s was polysemous-we have mentioned earlier the two dozen
human law, a benefit is not conferred on one who is unwilling." (Here definitions of Johannes Monachus-and they knew it could have the two
the meaning of ius shifted from a power to a "benefit.") 31 Since ownership principal meanings we have been discussing. But they did not distinguish
and use were in principle separable a person could renounce the power sharply between them as did Marsilius and many other rights theorists
of ownership (the power of laying claim to a thing and excluding others .lfter him. Often, in juristic discourse, the word drifts from one meaning to
from it) while retaining the power of use (simple use of fact). This simple the other in a single sentence without any apparent confusion of thought
use could be considered a kind of "ius in the second sense" since it was
licit, permitted by law. But it was not a "right of using" if that term were 33. Ibid .•# ••• potest licite renunciare patestate vendicandi ... non renunciata poll'Sf,\I<'
u tt'ndi ... qui siquidem patestas cadit sub iure dicto iuxta secundam eius significarionrm. El
vncari solet ab aliquibus simplex facti usus sine iure ulendi; per ius utendi sumentibu!I J o·
34. Ibid., •;us aJicuius dicitur, quoniam iuri primo modo dicto conformis....• nlinium. .. .u
35. 2.13.10, 282. :N . 2.14.20. :l 19.
36. 2.13.5, '179, • Talis abdicacio est prohibita lege divina eo quod species quedam est 40 2 IJ.8, 280; 2.14.20, J20, Marsilius ;i~t11•rl thus: if a f'l'™'" with only a right of us.• .11·
homicidii." 111.11ly n m suml"J somt>thing belonging lo J1nm••ono• cl~· w ith thl' own<'r' s m n!O('f•I, hP 1lld nnl
37. 2.13.3, "Ul, " ... quilibet aptus licite patest renunciare iuri pn:i llC' intmducto, quoniam .1n111irt• 1lomi11i11m or illicitly dt'J'riYC' th.- 11w1wr nl 1lonrrniu111. Thi• owner could 1mly inh•nt1 h•
beneficium non confertur invito, 5eCUndum ~l"f1l humanam lllCJllC' 1livin11m.n M.usiliu" 11(!<(1 n ·t.1in d11n11ni11111 of n thinK !1<1 lonK llM It t'd•lr.C Who•u ii c'c"'"'"i tn t•xi.'11, t•vlilo•ntiy nu o rw Willi
referred to "the benefit ofa right" 1112. 12.IS, 271. ,,,.,,,,,,.,,
116 THE IDEA O F NATURAL RIGHTS
~
.I
I
LANGUAGES OF RIGHTS 117

but also without any explanation to the reader. Thus, even when he was plicit a distinction between two meanings of ius that many subsequent
ostensibly distinguishing between the various meanings of ius, Johannes rights theorists would also want to emphasize.
Monachus could write, "Ius . . . accipitur . . . pro potestate a iure intro- If we could "unpack" all the implications of Marsilius's dense lan-
ducta" which we should have to render into English as, " A right . . . is guage-it would take a longer discussion than is possible here-we
taken . .. for a power introduced by law."41 Similarly Bonagratia of Ber- should find within it many strands of thought that were woven into later
gamo, a canonist by training, declared that a person could renounce "omni rights theories. The idea of self-preservation as both a right and a divinely
iure privato, quod a.licui competat ex humano iure," "any private right ordained duty and so an inalienable right, which had been explored earlier
that belongs to one by human law." When Marsilius, writing a couple of by Henry of Ghent, recurred prominently in the classical natural rights
years later, wanted to make the same point he carefully used ius for the in- theories of the seventeenth century. The distinction between ius under-
dividual's right and leges for the laws that defined it (and when Marsilius stood in a subjective sense or an objective sense remained important for
did use ius to mean law he carefully wrote "ius in the first sense").42 Per- Suarez and Grotius; and the delineation of the relationship between the
haps just because he was not a lawyer, Marsilius found it necessary to spell two meanings still persists as a characteristic feature of some contempo-
out for himself a distinction that was implied in the legal texts but so taken rary forms of discourse on rights. Thus Jean Dabin wrote that, in the
for granted that it had not seemed to call for any analysis. Yet it was es- language commonly used nowadays, " droit subjectif" is opposed to "droit
sential for the distinction to be made if a coherent tradition of discourse objectif." He explained that, "Le droit objectif en ce sens, designe le regle
concerning subjective rights was to grow up. And it was Marsilius who de droit (Recht im objektiven Sinne), tandis que le droit subjectif, (Recht
first insisted on the point. im subjektiven Sin11e) signifie une certaine prerogative etablie ou reconnue
Presumably medieval lawyers knew when they meant "law" and par le droit objectif au profit d'un individu...." 45 This was the distinction
when they meant " right" in using the word ius, though there are occa- that Marsilius repeatedly emphasized. Late medieval voluntarism, "the
sional ambiguities in their texts for a modem reader. One has the impres- displacement of Reason in favor in will," 46 is often seen as a source of
sion that sometimes an author was not making any careful discrimination seventeenth-century rights theories and Ockham is commonly regarded
in his own mind, but perhaps implying both meanings at once. Marsilius, as the fountainhead of this tradition; but in this area of thought Marsilius
however, always discriminated meticulously, and when he intended both was more voluntarist than Ockham. For Marsilius everything depended
r
meanings he said so, often in rather tortuous prose. For example: :.0 on the will to assert or renounce a right. Ockham's corresponding argu-
ment that there could be licit use without legal rights relied more on a con-
It is apparent from these statements that not all power that is licit or de
iure, in the first or second sense (of ius) or both, over a temporal thing or
over its use is ownership, although, on the other hand, all licit ownership
(in the three legal senses already mentioned) of a thing or its use or both
li,., cept of natural rights associated with rational natural law. Marsilius would
have agreed with Jeremy Bentham that, "From real law come real rights"
and that such rights could be derived only from positive human law or
is a licit or rightful power.43 ': positive divine law, from the will of a legislator.47 (But of course rights
theorists who believed in real natural law, could also defend a doctrine of
De Lagarde found such "mental algebra" merely tiresome and it certainly real natural rights.)
makes for a tedious literary style; 44 but Marsilius was laboring to make ex- In emphasizing permissive law as a locus of rights, Marsilius was
contjnuing a line of argument that the Decretists had developed earlil•r
and that would persist until the time of Christian Wolff and beyond. The•
41. CIOSSll aumi ad Sat. (Paris, 1535), ad 1.6.16, fol. xci (see above, 40).
understanding of a right as an area of autonomy defined by law which
42. Bonagratia de Bergamo, Tractatus d~ paupatat~ Christi tt apostolol'llm, ed. L Oliger in
Ardtivum Frandscanum historicum 22 (1929): 292-335, 487-511at503, "Cerium est autem quod we find in Marsilius, an area where the will of the rightholder prevailt..>d,
omni iuri privato, quod alicui competat ex humano iure, potest quis renunciare.... " Cf. Mar- still characterized the school of Savigny in the nineteenth century. Hut
sili us 2.12.15, "Potest enim quilibet renunciare licite iuri pro se introducto secundum Marsilius also treated a right as a "benefit" protected by law, an altcmatiVI'
humanas leges . . .N

43. 2.13.10, 282, HEx hiis itaque apparere potest quod non omnis rei tempnrilli~ ilUI eiu_q
usus potestas licita seu de iure primo aut secondo modo dlrto vd lllroc1111.•, sit J ominium, 45. J. f)abin, I.I' dmit .cuh/«11/ (1'1ulJ1, 111'\2). 2.
quamuis econveno dominium omne licitum !t4'<'11m1um l11m 1lkh•N In.,. """'"" lt·~nlc.,. . . _11it 41>. M kh.,<'I 011kMlholl. lntro1ludl1111 tu /.,-11111ll1r111 (l lkfnnl. 1946), llll.
pot<'~l<'lll lidtil !l('U d<' iun- i.1m dklo.'" <17. '" l\n11n·hin1l llnll••·h•,.,'' lu I lt11w1t1111, 1•11 • .,.,,,. W11rh r1( ''""'!I Rmlhnm. 11 vol~. (E1ll11
44 I a 11ni .<.' illl ll'I" dr l"r:<pril lnt.111,. .l · 50 hurKh. IK41). ·1. 4H<I '\J'f l\I '\11
118 THE IDEA OF NATU RAL RIGHTS LANGUAG ES O F RIGHTS 119

approach emphasized by Ihering and his school. Marsilius was, in effect, After reading the careful distinctions of Marsilius it seems natural to
conflating two theories of rights which are nowadays called the "will" or ask how scrupulously Ockham distinguished between the subjective and
"choice" theory and the "interest" theory.48 The two doctrines are com- objective senses of ius. The answer is at first sight rather surprising.
monly traced back, respectively, to Kant and to the Utilitarians; but they Ockham never considered the question; he never gave it a thought_ In the
obviously have deeper roots in Western thought. 49 Op11s nonaginta dierum (henceforth OND), his first response to John XXII,
and in his later writings, Ockham would shift from one meaning of ius
to the other as his argument required without ever explaining or appar-
WILLIAM OF OCKHAM. /us POLI AND IUS FOR! ently noticing that he was using the word equivocally. He would write
A glance at the work of Hervaeus Natalis and Marsilius is enough casually, for instance, "habet ius utendi ex iure naturali," which seems
to suggest a need for some reconsideration of Ockham's role in the de- to mean ". . . he has a right of using from natural law."51 Again, when
velopment of rights theories. Although it is no longer so fashionable to Ockham discussed the way of life of the apostles, he wrote, "utebantur li-
regard the whole of Ockham's political theory as a novel structure based centia iuris naturalis seu iure naturali ... ," which one could render as,
on his nominalist philosophy, the Franciscan is still rather commonly "they used a license of natural law or a natural right . . ." 52 Another typi-
regarded as an innovator who first imposed a new subjective meaning cal example occurred when Ockham discussed a key text of Augustine on
on the word ius. John Finnis for instance mentioned " the novel definition the origin of property in human law. Ockham wrote:
of ius developed by Ockham." Similarly Dario Composta referred to a Verum est quod loquitur de iure agendi cum dicit: Quo iure defendis villas
" transformation of the concept of right in Ockham," and Louis Dumont, ecclesiae? Et etiam loquitur de iure possidendi . .. quia ius civile etiam
after characterizing the English Franciscan as " the systematic expounder dominia rerum introduxit.53
of nominalism," called him also "the founding father of the 'subjective
theory' of right." Dumont further saw Ockham as a voluntarist for whom Clearly the ius agendi and the ius possidendi are rights, while ius civile refers
law was simply " the expression of the 'power' or 'will' of the legislator."50 to civil law, and Augustine's Quo iure could be rendered in English a!I
The truth seems to be rather different. Ockham took over his subjective either, "By what right .. . ?" or "By what law .. . ?" Marsilius would
definition of ius from the earlier literature of the poverty dispute or from have carefully explained how ius was to be understood at each occurrence
respectable canonistic sources; and, we shall see, he persistently empha- o f the word. Ockham, on the other hand, simply juxtaposed the different
sized right reason rather than mere power as the criteria of just law and as meanings without any clarification. Even when Ockham deliberately S('t
the basis of natural rights. out in the Dialogus to distinguish three different meanings of the term i11~
naturale, he still did not call attention to the subjective and objective senSt's
of i11s, but again shifted from one meaning to the other without any expla-
48. On a similar conflation of the "choice" and " interest" theories in Ockham, see below, nation to the the reader. 54
189.
Usually it is not very rewarding for a historian to ask questions of a
49. Although there are many apparent echoes of Marsilius' tho ught and language in
later works it is not always easy to trace his direct influence. One difficulty is that Catholic text that the author had no intention of addressing; but sometimes thc>
authors usually referred to Marsilius by name only whm they inte nded to criticize him; .lUthor's unarticulated, taken-for-granted assumptions are as significant
when they wanted to borrow his ideas they preferred not to mention such a questionable ns his overt arguments. Ockham's assumptions about the subjective and
source. Some good examples of this are given by P. Sigmund. -me Influence of Marsilius on ohjective meanings of ius were the entirely conventional ones of the pn•-
Fifleenth-Cmtury Conciliarism, ~ Journal of tht H isl ory of ldtns, 23 (1962): 393-402. For refer-
ences to Marsilius in Suarez and Grotius see G. Piaia, Marsilio de Padova ntlla riforma t nelln
I n ·ding juristic tradition.55 Like Bonagratia of Bergamo and earlier canon·
j
contrariforma (Padua, 1977). 222-225, 261-268.
50. J. Finnis, Natural Law and Nalural Rights (Oxford, 1980), 228; D. Composla, " II concetlo
di diritto nell' umanesimo giuridico di Francesco de Vito ria 0 .P.," in C. Soria, ed., / diritli detr
uomo t la pact nd ptnsiero di Francesco de Vitoria t Bartolomi de Las Casas (Milan, 1988), 276;
i 5 1. Opus 11onaJli11tn ditrum in Opera politico, vols. 1- 2, 562 lhere after O NO!.
c;z. oNn,:.m .
<;J <>NO, 6f.7.
L Dumont, Essays on lndividwdism (Chicago, 1986), 63-65. All three authors rt'ft•rred to Villey <;4 /)i111'ix11~, J 2.J.6 On lhi~ lt••I ~.,. t..•luw. 175ff.
as the source of their views. G. Samuel, also relying on Villey in hi11 Jisc11s.'iion of rights, 55. Tlw unrc•flt'<"livl' ~hl(t Imm lh•· nh~···t ivr to thl' ~uhjf'<"livl' m1•aning 111 iu,· wll•
refe rred to a " nominalist revolution." See his "Epistemology, rror;igamln .m.t Roman l.<1w: , ommon in juri:otic cli:on>11rN,. I ti1 thl• •rr K1111t Nllrr, uzur Fr,1gr d~ ~11b~·kti11t·~ Rrd1tr:< In
Some Refll'Clions on the History <•f thr Suhj('(·livr Righi." /1111111111 ••f''ii'.'''
llr<tm v Ill ( l'IR'I): ol1•1 111llh•l,1lt.•rlklw11 R•.,·ht•wl•...11•• h ..ft."' In I 11,.h•r M0'1lln1~ "' 111 , ''''"·· fr~t!<.-lrrifl /dr llfl
161 . •q .111 74.
""""' I 1111x r (S t11llK111 I, 1'1'11>, 1•11 Jll4 N1111 oil•• 11•••·•1 ''"I"'' l11tly " l'""~"K,. 11l l lc10tl••t10l11 In
r111 T11E Inf.A OF NATURAL RIGHTS l.ANG UAGF.S OF RIGHTS 121

ists Ockham knew that the word could be used in both senses; but to him using, without defining what kind of right. This seems to have been
the fact was self-evident and entirely unproblematic; it did not call for merely a debating point because later on in Quia vir reprobus John argued
any e~t~nded comment or scrutiny. We should perhaps not find this too that the apostles did in fact own things for which they could sue in court."'
surpnsmg..The English word "right" also has many meanings, but, in Still, Ockham felt obliged to prove over and over again that John had
everyday dtSCourse, it does not occur to us that we need to specify which always held this position and had intended to assert it in Cum inter. And
particula~ m~aning of the word is intended each time we use it. Normally the argument he presented made it necessary for him to distinguish for-
~e meanmg tS conveyed by the context. This is the kind of usage we find mally between natural rights and positive rights.
m Ockham and in many earlier writers. It would not call for any comment Ockham's argument ran like this. John XXII claimed to be interprC't-
except that Ockham has so often been re6arded as the author who first sin- ing Nicholas Ill's decree on Franciscan poverty, Exiit, and to be discussing
gled out and elucidated the subjective meaning of ius, and defined this the right of use as it had been understood by his predecessor.59 But, when
meaning in terms of a new philosophical vocabulary. There really is no Nicholas wrote of the ius utendi that the Franciscans had renounced, hl'
such argument in Ockham's work When he did use ius in the sense of a did not refer to a natural right (for he considered that the friars retained a
right he explained the term by referring to the standard canonistic com- natural right in case of extreme need). Therefore Nicholas used ius utendi
mentaries that were available to him, the ordinary glosses to the Decretum to mean a positive legal right; and, accordingly, when John XXII used
and the Decretals.56 the same term, he too must have referred to a positive legal right. In Ock-
Although Ockham was not interested in the formal distinction be- ham's words:
tween ius as Jaw and ius as subjective right that Marsilius presented, he
Every right or using is either a natural right or a positive right. . ..
emphasized another distinction that Marsilius had never really explored. (Nicholas) did not take right of using for a natural right. Therefore he
The Paduan master did not develop any theory of natural law or of rights took right or using for a positive right.60
related to natural law; he was interested only in positive rights. For Ock- -
ham, on the other hand, the distinction between positive rights and natu- The term that Nicholas III actually used in defending the friars' right
ral rights was aU-important. .' in cases of extreme necessity was ius poli, the law of heaven or right of
One reason why Ockham emphasized this distinction more than his heaven, a phrase taken from a letter of Augustine included in the Deere
predecessors arose out of a technical point of contention with John XXII. tum. Because Nicholas happened to employ this term instead of the more
Ockha.m thought it necessary to prove that the pope really had attributed common ius naturale, Ockham in tum often used the same expression.
to Christ and the apostles a legal right, enforceable in the civil courts, when Ockham's purpose all the time was to argue that the Franciscans did
he wrote that they retained a ius utendi, a right of using. This is most prob- not have any legal right to the things they actually used. So, after explicat-
ably what John had meant all along, and this is how the Franciscans had ing the terminology of Exiit, he continued to elaborate his distinction
always understood him.57 But in the bull Quia vir reprobus John pointed out bC'tween positive rights and natural rights. A positive right of using wa~
that~ in his dogmatic decree Cum inter, he had not explicitly asserted that simply a licit power as regards some external thing, he wrote. It was es-
Chri~t and ~e apostles held any positive legal right, or specifically a right tablished by statute or human agreement; the holder of such a right ought
to bnng suit: he had declared only that they had a ius utendi, a right of not to be deprived of it without fault or reasonable cause; if he were so dt·-
prived he could sue for his right in court. This was a legalistic definition
his Summa Rurto (Lyons, 1537) on X.1.9, fol. 26va. For another similar usage in Hostiensis see of a right, supported by references to the ordinary glosses of the Vrm·
his Commmtllrill lld Dtcrttll/es (Venice, 1581) ad X.1.2.7, fol. 9ra. Here the author referred to a
"ius quod omnibus rompetit de iure naturali" and a " ius de iure civili proveniens." ~- Q11i1111ir uprob11s in C. Eubel, ed., B11/111r111m Franciscan11m 5 (1898): 432, 446. llw wht1lo•
56. OND, 559. See below n . 61. At the beginning of the OND Ockham defined nine terms 1.. xt of Quill vir "Probus is included in Ockham's ONO. I have given refcrenc-~ to th1• t•dilluu
prominent in the povet1y dispute including usus iuris and ius 11trndi. But even here it did not 111 tht' 81lllari11m because this includes also the manifesto o f Michael of Ce~n" lo whkh llw

occur to him to distinguish between ill5 as objective law and as subjective right. Instead, we pope was ~ponding.
find. the ~s~al unreflecting transition from one meaning to the other in a phrase like " in - 59. In Q111n t•ir reprob11s, col. 4211, John wrote, HDicimus ergo, quod dr.·n•talis Ail '""'''
veruatur tn 1ure . .. quod omnis servitus est ius utendi.. .. (303).
#
torrm de usu l.'t uli loquilur, :<irnt t!C'C"rt'tnli!I F.:riil loqut-1:-iatur. ...
#

57. In Cum into John referred to a right of 9elling, donating, or ~xc-hanging, which rer- 60. ONIJ, ~'ih. "()mil(' C'nim tu~ uh•mli 1'111 ius n.lluralt• aul iu!I pol'itivum . . . 1'f•n1ml11111
tainly seems to imply civil ownenhip. Indeed, if John ditl not lnl1•n•t ..11 Along to maintain Nk holilum f ri\trM Minon"' ... h11t ...111 '"' 11tr111ll n1tl11r.1lt.', cum d k i11 iJl!<i.< 111rt' I'" " "'I provl
that the holding of legal rights was compatible wilh "P"'"tnlk rovrrly II 1,. h1mt lo !U.'C' why .lt•t11l11m ~11,.h•111.1ti11n l n11hmll' vlArn 11011 <'••r /'"'"' '""""' rrKo non 11n·iplt h1" uh'mll 1•ru lur,.
the dispute should h1vt' ari!M'n nt all. 1111lur.1'i Sumil '''K" lu• 11trmll 1•ro Im" l''"'lll\111 "
122 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGES OF RIGHTS 123

tum and the Decretals.61 It described the kind of right that the Franciscans ment outlined above is a good example of his distinctive approach. The
claimed to have renounced. On the other hand, Ockham asserted, there difference between ius naturale and ius positivum understood as natural Law
was a natural right of using that was common to all and that was derived, and positive law, was well known, taken for granted by jurists and theolo-
not from human law, but "from nature." This right could never be re- gians, and some of the canonists had seen that the term ius naturale could
nounced since the actual use of things was necessary to sustain life.62 have a subjective meaning. But no one before Od<ham had discriminated
When Ockham applied this distinction specifically to the problem so carefully between ius positivum and ius naturale when the word ius was
of Franciscan poverty he noted that the natural right of using things had taken in a subjective sense to mean a right. Moreover, Ockham persistently
been limited by the law that instituted private property. One could nor- appealed to this distinction in the course of his argument against the pope.
mally use things belonging to another only in case of extreme need. So far And so the concept of a natural right-not novel in itself-came to be
this was the old doctrine of the canonists; but Ockham added a refinement drawn out of the realm of juristic discourse into the center of a major theo-
of his own. He argued that the underlying natural right also came into logical debate.
play when one used something by license of an owner. The permission - Ockham did not devote any one section of the OND to a systema-
.:
of the owner did not confer any new right on the licensee; it merely re- tic analysis of the idea of a natural right. He was commenting word by
moved the restrictions of human law that normally impeded the exercise word on John XXII's bull, Quin vir reprobus rather than formulating his
uf d nafurat right.' And thfa wa!: rrPd""'Y thf' rnc:itinn ('f Uic frJnd~\.dllS own position independently, and this led him to make the same points

I
l

according to Ockham. "They have no positive right," he wrote, "but they over and over again in scattered contexts, with minor changes of wording,
do have a right, namely a natural right." 64 in a contorted, sometimes mind-numbing sequence of propositions and
Our concern is not so much with the substance or persuasiveness of definitions.66 Such material is not easy to summarize. Still it is possible
Ockham's argument for Franciscan poverty as with the ways in which he 1 to trace out a few strands of thought that can help us to understand Ock-
developed the concept of natural rights in shaping his case.65 The argu- ham's ways of using the language of natural rights. The following ex-
amples are taken from a dense thicket of argument included in one section
61. ONO, 559, nGrca primum dicunt quod ius utendi est duplex. Quoddam enim est ius ·' of the OND (chapters 62-65), where Ockham was primarily concerned to
utendi naturale; aliud est ius utendi positivum ... quod ex constitutione aliqua vel humana refute the pope's assertion that all just use required a right of using.
pactione habetur; et de isto iure utendi dictum est prius in capitulo secundo. Unde istud ius The first argument that I want to consider illustrates further the points
utendi non est aliud quam quaedam licita potestas exercendi actum aliquem circa rem tern·
poralem extrinsecam, qua quis sine culpa et absque causa rationabili privari non debet
already mentioned-Ockham's persistent interest in distinguishing be-
invitus, et si privatus fuerit, privantem iniuste potent in iudicio convenire... . Nullus autem tween positive and natu.r al rights and his indifference to the distinction
sine culpa et absque causa rationabili debet suo iure privari, ut notat glossa, Extra de consti· between the subjective and objective meanings of ius that has sometimes
lulio111"bus, c. ii, et Extra, dt to, qui cognovil consanguinmm u:coris suat, c. ultimo, et di. xxii, c. been regarded as a characteristic feature of his work. This phase of the ar-
Renovonles, et ex sac:ris canonibus colligitur evidenter....n Ock.ham referred here to the Or- gument also illustrates how both parties in the controversy manipulated
dinary Gloss on X.1.2.2, X.4.13.11, and Dist. 22 c.6. There is a similar definition at ONO 302 but
without the canonistic references. Sometimes Ockham overtly cited his sources. Sometimes - - -- --- --
he did not trouble to do so. Order consisted of reaJ individual persons. He had in mind the canonistic corporation the(1ry
62. ONO, 559, nlus utendi naturale commune est omnibus hominibus, quia ex natura, that treated a corporation as a "fictitious personn or a »fiction of the lawn preci3ely becau!M'
non aJiqua constitutione s uperveniente, habetur." ONO, 556, "... iure autem naturali non only the individual members were true persons. One might think that a nominali~t coultl
potest carere vita mortalium, quia tali iuri nullus renuntiare potest." The statement was re- have accepted this doctrine happily enough. But Ockham wanted only to di!\putt' t•vc·ry
peated several times, e.g. at ONO, 561, 562, 564, 5Tl, 519. word of the pope's decretal in every possible way.
63. OND 578. See below, n. 81. 66. E.g. at ONO, 575, Ockham argued that John XXII intended to refer to a positive', ll'g•I
64. ONO, 561, Nfratres minores, in rebus quibus utuntur, non habeant aliquod ius posi· right, a right to sue in court, when he used the term ius 11ttndi. Then he re(erttd bad< to
tivum, habent tamen a.liquod ius in eis, scilicet ius naturale.n Chapters 2, 6, 31, 32, 37, 42, 55, 58 and 60, where he had made the same point ovrr ;m,I nv..r
65. After the above argu~nt Ockham interpolated a discussion of a quite different ,,gain. II is a typical example of the repetitive and d iscursive style o f the ONTJ. An M .•<•d
issue. John xxn mentioned here that, when previous popes had conceded the use o( things .1tion between a right and a capacity to tiring suit (i11s and aclio) was noted in the' Ordi1111rv
to the Franciscan Order, they must have intended to concede a right of USl' bt-cause the Order 1 ;/~< to the Dt-crrtum at the Yl"ry bt>ii;inning of tht" work, Vi~t. l c.l !1.V. Fa~ rt>I, " ltc•m lurr
as such was not a real person but only "imaginary." l\n al>strMI entity could not actually u!K' tlivino lid tum rsl cnmt'drl't' uvH In "M'° 11ltl'rh111 ... !Wd licct !lit aequum lurt' <llvh1<1, lt11t1f't1
things but it cou.ld acquire a legal right. CKkham rrplfrd lh11t llw <lnlt•r wa" not im.lginary non l~t iu.!'I, id e!!I im• non dat dvllrm 111·tl11n..m l lhl M\lm aliquld mlhl prodr11t rt llhl non
but consisted of true person~. Thi~ !l('('m" to bt• onr nf th.. vt•ry "'"' lnlruHion~ of lli·kh111n'11 111 1t·••I, 1\C'<lllllm 1·~t . 111 m lhl 11011 prohlhC'•, Ito"I l111t lhl ·1l1•fld 111.'· <"lt'kh11m •11m1r.t lh1• 111•1
nominali.• I philosophy into hi" pt1lt•111ln1I wrlll11K~ llul lnlm )\I( II w"" 11111 d1•11yl11K 111111 llw word" 111 (IN/>. 'iHI , hut wllho11l 1<1f.,11111" lo hi•""'"'"
124 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGES Of RIGHTS 125

an underlying structure of canonistic jurisprudence to develop their own fully. No one doubted that. The pope's point was that a license specifically
rights theories. conferred a right and that without a right there could be no just use.
The question at issue was the one just mentioned, Pope John's in- But in order to make this point John had to impose an unusual mean-
sistence that there could be no licit use without a right of using. By the ~ I
ing on his text. There existed a long tradition of canonistic commentary
time Ockham joined in the dispute the pope's argument had advanced on Isidore's definition and, until the time of John XXII, the word ius was
somewhat beyond its original formulation. From the outset, John had always understood in an objective sense as referring to law, specifically the
maintained that anyone who used without a right used unjustly, but in civil law.69 The point the canonists always wanted to make was that al-
Quia vir reprobus he drew into the discussion for the first time a text of
canon law from the title, On the Signification of Words, in the Gregorian De- J though. according to their text, a justly possessed thing was possessed in
conformity with the law, the converse did not always hold. Not everything
cretafs to support his argument. The pope was arguing here that a license i;-. possessed in accordance with civil law was possessed justly. They had in
to use did in fact confer a right on the licensee: mind the example of prescription, acquisition of property by long pos-
. .. If anyone concedes a license to anyone, the latter has a right of session. In Roman law uninterrupted possession was enough to confer
using .. . if he says that he uses justly it foJlows as a consequence that ownership, but church teaching required that the possessor should also act
he uses by a right because what is done justly is done by a right. See De- in good faith throughout, not knowingly excluding someone with a better
cretals, On the Signification of Words, c. /us dictum est and C.14 q.4 c. Quid claim. Hence one who acted in bad faith would possess legally (iure} but
dicam.67 not justly (iuste). This was the interpretation that Ockham could read in the
Since the Gregorian Decreta/s contained a title On the Signification of Ordinary Gloss to the Decretals. "He possesses by law who prescribes in bad
faith, but not justly."70
Words, and since the word ius was one of those whose signification was ex-
During the first part of the fourteenth century the great canonist Jo-
plained there, one might expect to have at hand a definitive, clearcut
hannes Andreae introduced a new interpretation of the text He wrote:
statement of the primary or strict meaning of the word ius for medieval ju-
rists. {Perhaps Suarez had this text in mind when he wrote that "in its strict Isidore does not speak here of the general ius which is established in I.aw
signification" ius meant a moral power.) But unfortunately the text of the and customs ... But he takes it for the right that belongs to a private
Decretals, taken from Isidore of Seville, was ambiguous. It ran like this: person in some thing.71
lus dictum est a iure possidendo. Hoc enim iure possidetur quod iuste; The gloss of Johannes marked a turning point in the understanding of
hoc iuste quod bene. . ..68 the primary signification of the word ius, as it was formally defined in
That is: canon law. Later medieval canonists like Zabarella and Panormitanus con-
tinued to discriminate between the subjective and objective meanings of
lus is so-called from possessing by (virtue of) a right. For that is pos-
the word and to emphasize the subjective one. l do not think, though, that
sessed by a right that is possessed justly; that justly that (is possessed)
well... . John XXII or his adversaries knew Johannes' gloss when the pope wrote
his own comment.n More probably John took an ambiguous text that had
This is how John XXII understood the text. But it could just as well mean:
lus is so-called from possessing (in accordance with) the law. For that is J· I
69. For a discussion of the origins of X.5.40.12 in Isidore of Seville and Augustine, and for
possessed by law that is possessed justly. .. . l l'.trlier commentaries on the text see my " /us dictum esl a iurt possidtndo: Law and Rights In
1 llrcrtl11/es 5.40.12," in D. Wood, ed., Church and Sovereignty. c. 590-1915: Essays in Honour•'/
This is not just a verbal quibble. The point is that the second understand- Michael W ilks (Oxford, 1991), 457- 466. The early commentators did not raise the i!l..,ue thal
ing of the text would not have supported the pope's position. John XXll just possession might be derived either from divine law OT human law, but the point w1111
was not arguing simply that a person who used with a license used law- m11de by Zenzellinus de Cassanis in his gloss on John XXll's dogmatic decrtt Cum inlt"r """
r111/fo~ s .v. Non i11stf/. 7..en1.ellinus wa!I a major adversary of the Franciscan party, mc-nliurwtl
hy namP in Michael of c-na'!! mi'lnif<~tc• of 1:129. Perhaps taking a hint from hi~ oppt>11l'nl,
67. Quia uir reprobus, 433, " . . . si enim aliquis Jicentiam roncedat alicui . . . constat, quod
( k kh11m billlt.>d his argumc>nl on ii 1'1mll.,r '"""'""lion.
iictp ,h;thrf UJ~ uh~ndi . c;.j fl rr~I '1Un1i in&,, .. uhlffr. , , .. p •ffll• f•'I t 'ttl1·,••i flft•11 ..;, •1"•l\f t~t turtt.
711. l>t"m·tnlr~ IJ. C.rt"gorii IX mm ,l(l•••Jfl• (I.yon.•, 1h24), rnl. 1937.
quia, quid iuste fit, et iure fit {extra de verborum signifkatiorw cap. /us 1lidum rs/, XIV q.4 cap.
7 1. Irr 1111irrlum 1l«rtl11U11111 lll•run1,,,,,,..1(,,11•111111ml11rin (Vt•nin•, 1.581), fol. l!'lvb.
Quid dicnm)." The canonistic reft'n'·T\Cr.l iire It• X.'>.40.12 ft tu I C".14 •t 4 " 11 (of tlw I >t-,·,,.111111).
611. X..'i.40.12. n luh"'""... h<'!I"" worJ.11111 "" hi• • 111111111•111,., v 1111111ml IJ 11 l>ut ttltl not n •mplrtr It
1111111 I 'l \H, 11i1l<' V•'itr" "'"'' l11h11 'I( ltll l..11P1 I l ) llht 1•11 rfl'""'•" II "' l'"""Jhlr, howrv.-r. lh"t lhr
126 THE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHTS LANGUAGES OF RIGHTS 127

previously been understood as referring to objective law and read it as a Jori); they could just as well be based on a natural right (ius poli}.75 In this
statement about subjective right simply because that was the reading he way, by applying his Augustinian distinction taken from the Decretum to
needed to support his argument. }. John XXll's text from the Decreta/s, Ockham was able to circumvent the
If Ockham had wanted to present a distinction between the subjective pope's position.
and objective meanings of ius, the pope's text would have provided a per- In the course of his convoluted chapter devoted to refuting John's ar-

I'1
fect opportunity. Ockham could have pointed out that John had departed gument, Ockham went on to present a detailed analysis of the terms ius
from the standard interpretation of the Ordinary Gloss and improperly Jori and i11s poli that he had first introduced as a sort of tactical maneuver.
introduced the notion of a subjective right into the text he cited. But, al- His handling of these two concepts provides another theme that exempli-
though Ockharn usually liked to tease out every conceivable objection to fies Ockham's typical ways of arguing about rights. Here again we are
every single word of John XXII's decretal, he did not choose to pursue this reminded of the ambiguous use of the word ius in Ockham's discourse. We
argument. He simply accepted the pope's understanding of ius as meaning also encounter another intrinsic feature of his thought, an emphasis on
a right in this context. Ockham did indeed write that John was using right reason as the basis of both natural law and natural rights.
words sophistically and equivocally, and that it was necessary to distin- As Ockham's discussion proceeded, he took ius fori to mean a posi-
guish between the different senses of the word ius;73 but his own defini- tive right (or law) and ius poli to mean a natural right (or law),76 shifting
tions had nothing to do with subjective and objective meanings. Instead he -.: between the objective and subjective senses of the phrases as the course
turned back to his preferred distinction between natural right and positive
right.
... this noun ius is sometimes taken for the law of the court (ius Jori),
sometimes for the law of heaven (ius po/1). This distinction is taken from
I
!

,-J i•
I
of his argument required. When Augustine wrote of ius Jori and ius poli. he
clearly used the word ius to mean law-either human positive law or natu-
ral moral law.n Ockham's position was at first the same. After introducing
Augustine's text, he wanted to provide some further canonical authority
for discriminating between positive law and natural law. The first Distinc-
the words of Augustine On the Life of Clerics, which are included in the
tinal chapter of C. 17 q .4 (of the Decretum).74 tions of Gratian's Decretum dealt with just this issue; they distinguished
between ius naturale and various other kinds of ius such as the ius civile or
In referring to a ius poli Ockham was reverting to the language that i11s co11s11et11dinis, all the time clearly using ius to mean law-natural law,
Nicholas III had used in Exiit. This apparently led him to the text of Au- civil law, or the law of custom and so on. Also the Ordinary Gloss suggested
gustine in the Decretum that included the original distinction between here that the word "custom" might be used loosely to mean all human law.
ius poli and ius Jori. And since there were these two kinds of ius, Ockham Ockham took this as the basis for his own first definition of ius Jori.
argued, John's text from the Decretals ("what is done justly is done by
lus fori refers to the justice established by a compact or by some explicit
right") did not prove that all just acts required a positive legal right (ius
human or divine decree; whence ius Jori can be called the law of custom,
taking the word custom in a broad sense. And it is said of this law in
text quoted above was known from an earlier recension of Johannes' work. See the Introduc- f Dist. 6, "The law of custom had its beginning after natural law.. .. "78
tion of Stephan Kuttner to the modem reprint of Johannes' work (Turin, 1963). The texts of
Johannes Andreae, ZabareUa, and Panormitanus are discussed in Hlus dictum ~I a iurt .. ." 75. ONO, 579. "Quin q11od iuste fit. fit et iure. Verum est quod fit iure poli vel iure fori; scd
(above n. 69). non opportet quod semper fiat iure fori."
73. OND, 573. 76. See e.g. OND, 578, "Omne ius ... vel est naturale et poli vet est ius posilivum t•t
74. OND, 573, referring to C .17.q.4 c.43. Oclcham's sharp distinction between human fori."
positive law and natural moraJ law has so.metime.. been seen as an example of how his skep- 77. Augustine's text referred to a bishop who was morally obljged to make restitution
tical, voluntarisl approach subverted the harmonious synthesis of Aquinas, who held that though not compelled to do so by civil law. The Ordinary Gloss to the D«retals indudt'J a
human law must be in accord with natural law and found law and justice in the intrinsic mnemo nic verse that identified ius poli with the natural law defined in the first w ord" of< ;r.,
nature of things. See, e.g. M. Bastit, Naissllnct dt la loi modmtt (Paris, 1990), 257-63. But tiam's D«.rtlum. See gloss ad X.1.1.1. s .v. Ordi11atissimam, "Quod tibi vis fieri mihi fat·, qw1tl
Ockham was merely reformulating here the standard interpretation of the Dtcmals rext, non tibi noli I Sic potest in terris vivt>n- iun- poli, dist. 1 in princ."
XS.40.12, that he could read in the Ordiltllry Gloss. A little further on (579) he wrote Hqui iul'f' 78. ONO, ~73, " . . . ius fori voc11t11r iu,.turn, ·~und "" pactionc ~u orJinationt' humimn
poli possidet bme possidet" with a reference to the words Hhoc iu.1te quod bme" o f X.5.40.12. v"I Jivina t>xplidti\ cc•n.!ttitnitur; umlr "' 111~ furl iu~ ,·.,nslJt•tuJinis, lu11.e .!<Utnptn vno\huln
These particular words were not included in John XXll's Quill vir rrpmb11s. F.vidently Ockham " 'Oll.!tlH'tudini.!t·. p<>l<'ril itppdlnrl. Ft dr i~to lttn- olkltm In olt'n!'li'4. 11. vi; 111.< ,,..m n111s11t'l111l1
looked up the D«rrtab tcd, with iii. glOM, for himM'IL uis I~"' ' 1111turulrm lr,°'t'IJI t'Wrtf!um 1111/ttl "
128 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS LANGUAGES O F RIGHTS 129

As for ius poli, the Ordinary Gloss to the Decretum defined this term, and when he had a little earlier defined the term as meaning something quite
also ius naturale, as meaning natural equity.'19 Again Ockham took over the different, natural equity or natural law. Ockham did not explain why
juristic definition and expanded on it, though this time without any ex- he had presented, in different contexts, two quite different definitions
plicit .reference to his source: of natural right or how, if at all, the two meanings were related to one an-
lus poli means natural equity which is consonant with right reason with- other. But, as I have already noted, this should not surprise us too much.
out any human or purely positive divine decree ... this law is some- The dual sense of ius was taken for granted in the sources that Ockham
times called natural law....80 used, and he took it for granted too. In presenting his definition he showed
no awareness that to distinguish between the objective and subjective

;:.
So far there is no ambiguity; ius Jori and ius poli mean positive law senses of the word ius might be a matter of considerable significance. One
;
and natural law. But in the subsequent discussion the meaning of ius poli might indeed think it anachronistic to look for any such awareness in a
shifted to a subjective sense. Discussing again the question whether a li- .,
-' I
I
writer of the early fourteenth century, working long before the developed
cense necessarily conferred a right, Ockham wrote, ~I i rights theories of a later age, except that Marsilius of Padua and Johannes
·;I Andreae, both contemporaries of Ockham, did see the importance of the
Every right (ius) is either divine or human, and if human it is either natu- It '
ral and heavenly (po/1) or positive and legal (/ori).81 distinction and so helped to initiate a new tradition of interpretation.
Ockham was making a different contribution to the debate. For him
And so the argument moved on to another set of definitions: ius poli could be taken to mean either natural law or a natural right "conso-
lus poli is nothing other than a power conformed to right reason without nant with right reason." In the definitions we have considered, Ockham
any compact; ius Jori is a power from some compact, sometimes concor- did not derive the notion of natural rights from natural law or vice-versa;
dant with right reason and sometimes discordant. 82 . '
_.;I
both concepts were derived from an underlying assertion of human ration-
~ ality. This was the central theme of Ockham's theory of natural rights.
In these last definitions Augustine's "law of heaven" and "law of the The same concern is evident in yet another line of argument devel-
court" have been transmuted into subjective powers or rights. The change J_
oped by Ockham to dispute John XX:Il's asse~on ~t anyone who u~
of meaning seems to have been introduced quite nonreflectively. Still,
without a legal right used unjustly. Here the d1scuss1on turned on a persis-
it is a little disconcerting that Ockham, the master logician, could casu-
tent interplay between the concepts of justice, right reason, and natural
ally write here that ius poli meant "nothing other than" a subjective power
rights. As so often in the ONO, the argument was presented in a rather d~­
fuse fashion but, ifOckham's various comments are put together, the chain
79. Gloss ad C.17 q.4 c.43 s.v. Non iure poli, "i.e. quad am natu.rali aequitate"; ad Dist. 1 c.8 of reasoning runs like this. To understand how an action can be called
s .v. Ius naluralt, "Tertio modo dicitur instinctus naturae ex ratione proveniens et ius ex tali "just" we must consider the concept of justice itself. The word can refer to
natura proveniens dicitur naturalis aequitas." . a particular virtue distinct from other virtues, or it can refer to the legal jus-
80. OND, 574, Nlus autum poli vocatur aequitas naturalis quae absque omni ordinatione
tice that ordains acts to the common good; but, according to Thomas
humana et etiam divina pure positiva est consona rationi rectae . . . hoc ius aliquando vo-
catur ius naturale.. .. Aliquando vocatur ius divinum; quia multa sunt consona rationi Aquinas, there is a third meaning, according to which any licit act can be
111
rectae acceptae ex illis, quae sunt nobis divinitus revelata quae non sunt consona rationi pure called just because such acts are good and "consonant with true reason."
naturaJi. ..." Ockham was arguing here that some divine law was known by right reason 1f we take justice in this third sense then indeed it is possible to act justly
reflecting on revealed truth. As an example he mentioned a pastor preaching the gospel. without any positive right (though not without right reason).84 And,
Right reason could establish that he should be supported by h is flock, but only because it
was known by revelation that the gospel was true. "The ~tial distinction was between law
that could be ascertained by reason and law that rested on a purely positive command, 83. OND, 557. "Ad cuius evidentiam est sciendum quod nomen 'iustitiae' triplici arcipl
whether human or divine. potcst. Uno modo accipitur pro quadam virtute partkulari. . .. Secundo accipitur iu111ill11 pn•
81 . OND, 578, NOmne ius vel est divinum vet humanum, et si humanum, vel est naturale quadam virtute generaIi quae vocatur iustitia legalis.... Tertio accipitur iustltia pm 11rhltn
et poli, vel est ius positivum et fori." Ockham was clearly using ius here to mean a right. He ordinatione actus ad rationem... . F.t i111iu11 opinionis fuit Thomas ... et isto modo omni"
argued that a revocable license did not confer a natural right. for that preexi~ted, and it did actus licitus est iustus, quia t'lll honw• t•I vt•rar consonus rationi.N Ockham must h11vr •'II
not conler a positive right because it gave no power to sue in court. ~·yl'<l quoting AquinaJll, whom [ohn XXll h111I n-t't'11tly c11noni7,ed, in hie own r11u11t•. ·nlC'
82. OND, 579, Nlus autem poli non est aliud quam poll"l'l•'" n•nlormi11 r,\lioni n.•dal' lhrN>·fuld dl'rinllion or ju~tkt" Willl "'1"'"'"'' 411 (>NI'· !°t(Tf>, 577.
absque pactione; ius fori ~t pol!'!ltas ex pactimll' ,1ll111111mlo n1nlo1111I "'"""i n·d.lt'. l'I ,,1; K4. ONI >. ~17. " ... "''" •du• 111111• """ ...1 l11lu• h111 •rtl ht~hu•; l'l t11m1•n Kim• iun•, 'I"" vAlrl
quando discordnnti." 1111i• in imlldo lill1tM•'. 11e•1l 11ot1 •h1., '"' 111 111llt•ot> ••
130 THE IDEA OF NATURAL R ICITTS
~
I
!
Ockham continued, this was indeed the situation of one who used by
virtue of a license. Such a person had no legal right but he used justly be-
cause he used in a manner consonant with right reason; the right he
exercised was a ius poli not a ius Jori, a natural right not a positive right.as
Ockham's argument might be restated like this. Any act in accordance
with right reason is just; a natural right is a power consonant with right
reason; so the exercise of a natural right is a just act even in the absence of
a positive right. ln this way Ockham succeeded in grafting his own doc-
trine of natural rights on to Aquinas's theory of justice.

S IX
CONCLUSION

We need finally to review the different approaches to the language


of rights in the authors we have considered. To sum up then: Hervaeus
Natalis, a Th.omist, emphasized especially the idea of ius as a licit power; PROPERTY, NATURAL RIGHT, AND THE
it was he, if anyone, who "resolutely twisted the idea of right to the mean- STATE OF NATURE
ing of power." Ockham was content to take over this language from his
adversaries. Marsilius of Padua, an Aristotelian, distinguished carefully
between the subjective and objective meanings of ius. Ockham showed no
interest in this distinction and never overtly called attention to it; he used
the word in both senses but did not formally distinguish between them.
Ockham's own contribution to natural rights theory consisted, not in some
new nominalist and voluntarist definition of ius, but in a new emphasis on
nature and reason as sources of subjective rights, and in a carefully s us-
T he social context in which the Franciscans lived and worked wa.s
shaped by the economic strivings of an age that had already experi-
enced a "commercial revolution" (in the phrase of Robert Lopez). In the
more urbanized parts of Europe, a feudal regime of mutual obligations
tained distinction between natural rights and positive rights. was giving way to a system of more sharply defined property righ~. And
the Franciscans were men of the cities. They were deeply engaged with the
mercantile culture whose values they had renounced; as confessors and
moral theologians the friars had to consider all the problems of economic
morality associated with the acquisition an~ right use of wealth .. When
their own position was challenged the Francisc~s were well quah~ed to
undertake searching inquiries into the foundations of property rights.
And, since property became a paradigmatic right in later Western thought,
their arguments merit some detailed consideration.

PROBLEMS OF FIRST A CQUISITION


The Franciscans maintained that they had renounced all rights to
property, e ven in the things that were consumed in use. Their advcrsilry,
Pope John XXII, insis ted that such a claim was both unlawful and unn'a-
sonablc. As th<' debate protiff'rnh>tl it num• to involve a group of probh•m11
85. ON O, 577. "Si autem accipiatur ' iulltl'' lf'tliu mo.In, ~k <lln ml 11uod ulitur iu~lt· n•, that had t•arli<•r bt>cn dii«'U!'sc•tl hy dvll 1m1I c.·.mun lilwycrs and thilt would
cuius ha bet liC't'ntiam ulrnd i; quin ulilu r n mfnrrnlle'r r111innl , ..,., ..,. f;t to''"' 1·u11n'<l11nl •111011
liltt'r pc•rsist as topit'/4 11( t'rt1lr11I lmpt11l;m1·1· in ttw writing1' of tlw ~rt·nl
ulitur iun•, non ' l11i1lrm iun• fnrl, ~t lur" I'"" "
I \I
132 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PROPERTY, NATURAL RIGHT, ANO THc STATE Of NATURE 133

natural rights theorists of the seventeenth century-in the works of own person. Some have argued for a right to property based on a prior
Grotius and Pufendorf and Locke. The fourteenth-century discussions right to liberty. Many have argued in various ways from human nature,
provided a bridge-or one of the bridges-between these two areas of human needs or human aspirations. 3 Jn considering some fourteenth-
discourse. century approaches to such problems we shall be dealing with issues of
Questions like these arose. What kind of property (if any) existed in a perennial significance in Western thought.
state of nature? Was Adam at first the sole proprietor of the world? How Ideas concerning the origin of property have often been associated
could a right to individual property arise from an earlier condition of with a second important topic that we shall need to consider, another
common ownership? Was such a right derived from natural law or from theme that arose during the Franciscan dispute and that persisted in
human convention? If from human convention, was the act of institution a seventeenth-century discourse on natural rights. I mean the play of ideas
pre-political agreement or the decree of an established government? And if inherent in the frequent appeals, in both epochs, to a primeval state of
property was instituted by government, did rulers have absolute power nature as a starting point for arguments about the right ordering of society.
over the goods of their subjects? This kind of argument was made possible by the ambiguities inherent in
The problem of first acquisition has been a persistent focus of con- our word "nature." Philosophers and jurists have found many meanings
troversy in discussions on the basis of property rights. Evidently a person for the word, but two of them seem specially important in the growth of
can acquire physical possession of unoccupied land by settling on it; but political theory. "Natural" can refer to a primeval state of affairs before the
why should the first occupant have a right to exclude others, to impose institution of any human laws or customs or conventions; or the word can
on others a moral or legal obligation to accept his right of ownership? As refer to the intrinsic, permanent characteristics of human beings as self-
Robert Filmer pointed out in criticizing Grotius, if at one time all things aware, moral, rational creatures. Many thinkers have taken the natural
were common, then it would seem that the person who first seized a part law or natural rights derived from the second concept of nature as a basis
of the common property as his own was simply acting as a robber. The act for defining permanent norms of human conduct. But difficulties could
of acquisition could be legitimate if it were based on a preexisting agree- arise in natural law theories-and indeed they kept on arising-if the two
ment of the whole community but, as Filmer again pointed out, it would meanings were confused, so that the primitive condition of things, since
be "a rare felicity" if all the people in the world had simultaneously con- it was "natural," was also regarded as permanently nonnative. Medieval
sented to such an arrangement. 1 Locke's labor theory of property was an jurists often saw the need to distinguish between the different meanings.•
attempt to answer Filmer's argument, but it soon proved vulnerable to So too did some early modem theorists. Pufendorf, for instance, called at-
multiple objections. Most obviously, a man's labor does not create the land tention to "the ambiguity of the word nature" when he criticized Hobbes's
on which he works. If he "mixes his labor" with the land, why should unflattering portrayal of natural man. Pufendorf pointed out that, if W('
we say that he acquires the land? Why not just say that he loses his labor? treat the primordial as natural, it is as though we were to say that, since
Or that he is entitled only to the direct fruit of his labor, the crop that he babies are born without the faculty of speech, it is unnatural for them later
raises? Such problems continue to perplex modem political theorists. One to learn to talk.5 On the other hand, Pufendorf noted, if we understand tht•
of them has observed simply that "no adequate theory of initial acquisition
exists."2 Among modem writers who have tried to formulate such a 3. The following are a few of the recent works that criticize Locke's theory of pmperty in
theory, some have concluded that private ownership is a social construct; various ways and set out alternative positions-they include libertarian. communitarian, utili-
on this view a right to property can exist only when the relevant commu- tarian, Straussian and feminist arguments: J. 0 . Grunebaum, Private Owntrship (New York.
nity has instituted rules concerning acquisition and exchange. Others have 1957); L E. Lomasky, Persons. Rights, and tht Moral Community (Oxford, 1987); T. Machan, /11-
dh•iduals and Their Rights (LaSalle, 1989); T. Pangle, The Spirit of Modtrn Rrp11blica11ism {Chi-
asserted a natural right to property by developing the argument put for- cago, 1988); C. Pateman, Tht St:rua/ Ccmlrnc/ (Stanford, 1988); D. B. Rasmu~n and I>. J. D1•n
ward by Henry of Ghent in the thirteenth century, and emphasized by Uyl. Li~rty 1111d Naturt. An Arislottlian Deftnst of Libmll Ordtr {LaSalle, 1991); A.. Ry;m. Pm1>rrtv
Locke in the seventeenth, that every individual has a property right in his (Minneapoli-;, 1987); J. J. Thomson, Thi' Rt'alm of Rixhts (Cambridge, Mass.• IQq(j); J. W Wnl
tlmn, Thr Ri!(hl to Proptrly (Oxford, 1~).
1. Robe.rt Filme!', Patriarcha md Olhtr Writings, ed. j . r. Sommerville (Cambridge, 1991), 4. S!'e e .R tht' O rdinary Gfc>$.< lo tlw I >r1·rrt11m 111/ ni~t. 1 c.8 s.v. /us 11al11r11r, " A.I inh·ll1K<'"·
23f. For an overview of property origins in early modem p<>lillcal lh<•u!iihl, S<oe N. Luhmann,
0

tiilm istomm nola <JlHXI n.1t11r" mulllll 111ntll1< tlldlur." lh1• nulhor. Joh1mnt'!I T.-ulonku,., wrnl
MAm Anfang war kein Unrecht,~ in idem, Gr"ll!t<"hnfl~•lr11/d11r 111111 Sm11wtik, 4 vol~. (Frank· o n lo givt• four 11w;1 nln1<1<.
furt, 1980-95) 3:11- 64. ~. S l'ufc•mln rf. I Ir /111r u11lui11r rt xr11l111111 11111 • ,,, lo. ' " ' ( · 11. ( >hlfotlwr "'"' W A (lid
2. J. Gray, Ubm1'1~m (Mlnrw11pol1A, l<JM), 1~1 f.11lwr. 2 vnl1< (< hfnrd. 1'114), ') /l it uo/11111111 . J l It•. Jiii
134 THE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHTS PROPERTY, NATIJRAL RIGITT, ANO THE STATE O F NATURE 135

law of nature as "that which is in conformity with rational nature," such a primitive church were established by a divine founder, it seems n:aS?n-
natural law can allow for growth and change in time.6 It does not have to !I
.• I
able enough that believers in all ages should have looked back on this first
be ahistorical. Since it is derived from rational reflection on changing ordering of things as an ideal to be preserved or, if necessary, recovered.
human conditions, it can accommodate some kinds of historical develop- But the image of the early church was inconstant and malleable; it proved
ment, including the transition from primitive community to private variable enough to sustain a wide range of movements of protest and
ownership of property.7 reform, as well as conservative defenses of existing institutions. People
The attempt to derive natural rights and natural Jaw from human poured their own ideals, born of the contingencies of their own times, into
reason may be a worthwhile enterprise; an appeal to simple primitivism the disputed texts of scripture that they quoted at one another.
seems at first sight merely naive. And yet this latter approach appears to All this is especially true of the Franciscan controversialists of the four-
satisfy some deep instinctive tendency of the human mind. Tribal peoples teenth century. In Franciscan writings a very distinctive vision of the early
dream of a remote and magical epoch when god-like ancestors estab- church coexisted with idiosyncratic theories concerning the right to prop-
lished the norms of their present-day societies. Classical authors wrote of erty and with appeals to a primordial state of nature that were intended to
a golden age when men lived together happily and shared all things in justify the existing practices of the Franciscan Order. William of Ockham
common. Christians had their Garden of Eden. Sophisticated poJiticaJ had interesting things to say about all these questions. But, as usual, it is
thinkers in the seventeenth century appealed often to more or less imagi- impossible to understand Ockham's distinctive contribution unless it is set
nary ancient constitutions. Eighteenth-century imaginations played with against a broad background of earlier reflection on the question at issue
the idea of noble savagery. Even in twentieth-century juristic discourse, and also in the immediate context of the Franciscan controversy.
one eminent author has thought it necessary to remind us that we should
not think of natural rights as "spectral attributes worn by primitive men
like amuJets." 8 THE BACKGROUND: CIVILIANS, C ANONISTS, AND THEO LOGIANS
In spite of the confusions that arise if we simply equate the primordial .•

with the natural, we can perhaps learn one lesson from considering the ! ~ Civilians
attitudes of primitive societies. The problems about property that are cen- The idea that a right to property derives from first occupancy is
tral to our Western tradition of political thought are not universal human rooted in Roman law.9 The ancient jurists made a distinction-sometimes
problems. Among primitive peoples we can find almost every conceivable carefully preserved and sometimes neglected by early modem rights
variety of property distribution; but the peoples concerned do not vex theorists-between things that were owned by a community and things
their minds with conflicting theories about how their customs came to that had no owner.10 These latter were referred to as res nullius or in lxm;s
exist or on what grounds they can be justified. A modem anthropologist nullius. Ownership (dominium) was acquired by first occupation of a res
might point out that each such system is a result of unconscious patterning nullius. 11 At the time when the classical jurists were writing, this kind of ac·
in response to conditions of soil and climate and other physical realities; to quisition applied only to a small range of objects; the laws mentioned such
the peoples concerned, however, their customs seem natural in the sense things as gems picked up on the seashore and wild game, "tak~ by land,
of being part of the natural order of things, accepted unreflectively as one sea, or air." But Nerva Filius, a jurist of the first century, explained that
accepts the changing of the seasons or the rising of the sun in the east. It
follows that a major problem, often overlooked, in considering theories
about the origin of property, is to determine just when the issue began to 9. The relevant Roman law texts are conveniently assembled, with a good commentary,
in R. W. and A. J. Carlyle, A History of Mtdiroal Political TMory in IM Wts!, 6 vols. (Edinburgh,
be seen as problematical
1903- 36), 1:33-54.
The appeal to a remote past in Christian thought has often focused on IO. Pufondorf built his theory of property around this distinction, using tht- tPrmll Npo...1-
the Garden of Eden or, more practically it might seem, on the example of tive community" and Hnegative communityHto describe the two situations. GmtiiL" movrd
the early church. Since Christians believed that the institutions of the from the idea of rrs nul/iu~ in hl!I nrly work to a doctrine of common o wnf'rllhip In tlw
v, ;urt btlli. Locke's usaKf' w11" 11mblg1101111. Modem llCholars still a~ue about hl11 rf'nl po·
l!ition. For a dillCull~lon o f thl"· ,..... /\.. M11p11<7.ynJ1ki, Nolurt ond PCJhlrrs (lthac11, NY, 1'>147),
6. Ibid., 2.3.13, 226. IH0- 186.
7 . Ibid., 2.2.22, 225. 11. I Ji,( . J .H 2, "1.)1111c«l11111 n11htrall 1uu1 • 01111111111111, """' n mnlum, •111111•,l11m 11nlvrultnlh1,
It. R. Dworkin, TakinR Ril(hts .'>t'rim1.<1v (C 1m1hrldK'"
0

M11a~ . 1•rn1. 1·111


'I'"''''''"" 111111111"· l'h·r••I"'' •111.11111111111 ••
136 THE IDEA OF NAn.JRAl RIGHTS PROPERTY, NATURAL RIGHT, ANO THE STAT£ OF NATURE 137

all ownership had at first originated in this kind of natural possession and too was an institution of the ius gentium understood in the same sense." A
that the existing rules were just relics of this initial state of affairs.12 continuation of this line of argument, only hinted at in the texts of Roman
The doctrine of res nullius does mitigate some of the difficulties inher- law, would explain private property as conventional, a creation of human
ent in theories of first acquisition. A person who takes something that has law that supervened on an earlier state of nature. This approach perhaps
no owner cannot be called a robber. And it does seem intuitively reason- reflects Seneca's vision of a primordial golden age when all things were
able that, for instance, a man who catches a fish in the open sea has a right held in common.
to claim it as his own. It is not so obvious that the one who first occupies a Long before the lawyers wrote, Greek philosophers had invented, or
tract of land acquires a right ipso facto to exclude others from it; but, unde- discerned, a distinction between nature and convention. The Roman ju-
terred by such considerations, the Roman lawyers referred to acquisition rists were aware of the distinction, but they applied it inconsistently; they
by first occupancy as "natural" and "rational." Gaius, for instance, wrote, did not offer a single coherent theory of property, but rather provided a
"what belongs to no one is conceded to the occupier by natural reason." 13 sort of quarry from which later writers could hew out a variety of theories.
Gaius also related the institution of property to the ius gentium, the law Some of their texts suggested that private property existed by nature,
of nations, but he made no distinction between this law and the law of others that it was instituted by convention. The lawyers were practical
nature. For Gaius the ius gentium was "what natural reason has established men; they do not seem to have been much perturbed by the theoretical dis-
among all peoples." 1• It was common to all humanity and coeval with the sonance in their sources; there was no extensive debate on the matter of
human race. ~ According to this view the institution of private property
1 which we have any record. Later on, the Byzantine compilers of Justinian's
was primeval, natural, and rational. Corpus iuris included the texts of Ulpian on natural law along with those of
Another tradition of Roman law, however, distinguished sharply be- Gaius, either not noticing or not caring that the texts were inconsistent
tween natural law and ius gentium. Ulpian offered a tripartite division that with one another.19 Evidently the ancient jurists were simply not interested
discriminated between natural law, the law of nations, and civil law. Natu- in the problems that later seemed of such central importance: why should
ral law was "what nature has taught all animals." This law was common first occupancy confer ownership? How could a right to exclude others
to humans and other animals; it included such things as the procreation from common property be justified? In classical writings the beginning of
and rearing of offspring. lus gentium pertained only to humans and was private property-whether under the ius naturale or the ius gentium-was
common to the whole human race. Civil law was the specific law of the still treated as something unproblematical. For jurists the origin of prop-
Roman people. 16 Ulpian maintained that, according to natural law, every- erty was a fact to be recorded; for poets and mythmakers it was a story to
one was born free and that servitude was instituted by the ius gentium. 17 be told; no one saw the emergence of property as a problem that needed
Another text of the Digest, from Hermogenianus, suggested that property to be solved.

12. Dig. 41.2.1. " Oominiumque rerum ex naturali possessione coepisse Nerva filius ail Cnnonists
ejusque rei vestigium remanere in his, quae terra mari caeloque capiuntur, nam haec proti-
nus eorum fiunt, qui prim• possessionem eorum adprehenderint." See Dig. 1.8.3, "Item When we turn to the medieval canonists we find a quite different situ-
lapilli, gemmae ceteraeque, quae in litore invenimus jure naturali nostra statim f'iunt." ation. As I noted earlier, in discussing the various meanings of ills nnt11rn/1•
13. Dig. 41.1.3, "Quod enim nulliusest id ratione naturali occupanti ronceditur...." in Decretist writings, the canonists did indeed encounter a major problem
14. Dig. 1.1.9, "Quod vero naturalis ratio inter omnes homines constituit ... vocatur ius when they sought to explain the origin of private property. And, once thl•
gentium"; Dig. 41.1 .1, "Quarundam rerum dominium nanciscimur jure gentium, quod ra·
tione naturali inter omnes homines peraeque servatur. . .."
15. A paraphrase of Gaius included in the Institutes of Justinian explicitly identified i11s Ill. D('{· 1 I 5, " Ex hoc iure gentium introducta bella, discretae gentl'l!, ~n11 con<lit ... 110·
natural~ and ius gmtium. Inst. 2.1.11, "Quarundam enim rerum dominium nanciscimur iure minia d i:o;t\ncta, agris termini positi ...."
naturali, quod sicut diximus appellatur ius gentium, quarundam ex iure civili . . . pa lam t'SI 111. Medieval Roman lawyers continut"d both lines of argument sugg~t<.'d l:iy tlw• d;1""'
autem vetustius esse ius naturale, quod cum ipso genere humano rerum natura pmclidit." c.~I jurists, sometimes empha!li7.ing 11 conv<'ntional, sometimes a natural origin of proprrty
16. Dig. 1.1.1.4, " ... privatum ius tripertitum est: collectum e-st ex naturalihus p ral.'Crpti.' For S<•mt• illu!!lrative texts l'('(' R. Wt-ig11ml, l>ir Naturrrchtslrhrr drr Lrxistrrt und l>rkrrti11tr11
au! gentium aut civilibus. !us naturale est, quod n11h1ra omni11 animalia dncuit... .lus g<"n· ""' lmrn11s #Ii!< 1krnr5ius u11d tlOrt c;ratum /11~ /1-./ui1111~ "lr11larticus (Munkh, 1%7), It'\ '12. In tltll
tium est quo genies humanae utuntur...." n1~'iinK tht• ,·11nuni.•llo I hAvr R'll.-.l prhwl1•Ally on WriKt1ml'io C'xcelll'nt roll1'C1lon ol trxl,.. I'm
17. Dix. I. t .4, "Manuml11sh111t'!I <jllll<llll' iuri" l(t'nlium 1111111 . , 11111 hm• 1Mh1r,11i ""''"'" I tuxu.-do ;I 1111<0 .,,...ti trnn•nlpth'I•~ ll'tlm Mo /\1lm1111I. Stilt"hllillotllf'lr. 7 Thr n•t11llnK" "'" ,,..
lit>.-rl nil~('n•nl ur. ,-,,~irni.11l v ~lil(hl ly <llll1•r1•11t ln•m thn..• nf Wrlg~11·I
w
ii
138 TuE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PROPERTY, NATURAL RlGHT, ANO lliE STATE OF NATURE 139

existence of property was seen as problematical, a large body of relevant


II Huguccio preferred a different solution. He held that community of
argumentation quickly emerged, some of it destined to persist for cen- ! property really was a permanently valid precept of natural law but only in
turies in works of law and political theory. the special sense that goods owned by individuals had to be shared with
The difficulties arose because the sources that Gratian assembled often others in time of need. On this view property was individual as regards
seemed to conflict with one another, and, unlike the Byzantine compilers, ownership but common as regards use (at least in case of necessity).23 Here
the medieval Decretists were very much concerned to harmonize all the again the argument for property did not rely on an appeal to a primordial
varied elements of discourse that they had inherited from many ages of state of affairs; instead Huguccio based his doctrine on an understanding
the church's past. (Gratian's own title for his work was A Concord of Discor- of ius naturale as a force of reason inherent in humans, and on the judge-
dant Canons.) Moreover some of the patristic texts included in the Decretum ment of reason concerning use of temporal goods.24 For both Rufinus and
seemed unfriendly to the whole idea of private property. St. Ambrose, Huguccio, primitive communism was not an ideal to be restored but only
for instance, wrote, "No one may call his own what is common, of which, the starting point of a historical process through which private property
if a man takes more than he needs, it is obtained by violence." Finally, had emerged.
the comments of Gratian himself on natural law served only to confuse The distinction of Rufinus between the commands and demonstra-
the issue further. Gratian wrote that, by the law of nature, "all things are tions of natural law showed how property could be licit, but it did not
common to all," and that private property was introduced by custom or explain how it had come to exist in the first place. As l noted in an earlier
legal enactment; but he added at once that human laws contrary to natural ·; discussion of his views, Rufinus himself provided an explanation that an-
law were "vain and void."20 It could seem, then, that the laws instituting ticipated a theme of some later natural rights theories. He envisaged the
private property were invalid. But Gratian had no intention of asserting emergence of an ordered, lawful society from an anarchic state of nature
this apparently evident conclusion of his own argument. Nor did any of through the making of human compacts. After the Fall of Adam, Rufi nus
his commentators want to affirm that primitive communism provided a wrote, humans lived for a time almost like brute beasts; but the sparks of
permanent basis for human institutions. wisdom and justice that still persisted in them led them to deliberate to-
A major breakthrough came with Rufi.nus' distinction between two gether and to enter into compacts with one another. Thus they established
kinds of natural law-<:ommands and "demonstrations." The commands the first body of law, including law regulating property rights. The argu-
(precepts and prohibitions) defined basic rules of morality that were ment envisaged a division of property by human agreement but in a
indeed immutable. (Rufinus gave as examples, "Thou shalt love the Lord pre-political society.
thy God" and "Thou shalt not kill.") But the "demonstrations" of natural Much of the canonists' further discussion of this question centered
law were merely descriptive of an original equitable condition of things around two texts of the Decretum that would also be frequently cited in the
that could be altered and had been altered by the introduction of human later Franciscan dispute. The first (Quo iure) was a genuine passage from
laws; and having all things in common was a "demonstration" of this sort, Augustine, the second (Dilectissimis) a text of pseudo-Isidore attributed to
not a precept.21 Other canonists referred to this kind of law as primeval or the first Pope Clement. Gratian quoted Quo iure to support his own view
permissive. It was primordial but not normative; it had no permanent that private property was introduced by human custom or statute. In the
binding force.22 words of Augustine:
20. Dist. 8 antt r .1, "Nam iure naturali omnia sunt rommunia omnibus.. .. lure vero con- We find divine law in scripture, human law in the ordinances of kings.
suetudinis veJ constitutionis hoc meum est, iUud alterius." Dist. 8 post c.1, "Quaecunque By which does each possess what he possesses? Is it not by human
enim vel monbus recepta sunt, vel scriptis comprehensa, si naturali iuri fuerint adversa, law? .. . God made rich and poor from one clay and the one earth pro-
vana et irrita habenda sunt."
21. Dit Summa D«rttorum des Magist" Rufinus, ed. H. Singer (Paderbom, 1902), 6- 7. 5tt 23. MS Admont 7, fol. 2 va, Prwmium, "Vel potius cum dicitur iure naturali omnia ~uni
above, 62. communia non excluditur pmprium, nee dicitur commune contra proprium, ~l i~ t·~t
22. See l.aurentius, #De iure naturali primeuo, vel de naturali equitate quibus derogatur S<>nsus, iure naturali id ('SI iudicio rRlinni~ 11pprobante, omnia sunt co mmunia, id t'lll ll'm-
per ius humanum ... ."; Summa Parisiensis, " . .. ius naturale quod fuit in principio, !ICiliCt>t pore nccessitatis indigl'ntibu4 rnmmunknml11 ..... (Wl'igand, 329).
primaeva institutio rerum. . .. n; Summa Monactnsi5, H • iut' naturall' consl~tit in preceptis et
• •
24. MS /\dmont 7, fol. J vn. '" '/IM I "7 M v ( ·ommunis omr1i11m pos5'ssio, " ... id t'l\t com·
protubitionibus consiliis el permlssionibu~. Verum l'111 q11od dl'n~nhir it1rt' naturali in . . . muni<"atio omnium q11r 1'4•J1hlr11111• '""'I'""" 11...·,.'"1111 11~. hoc· de ro iure n.1hm1li qmxl 1lldt11r
permissionibu..et ronsilils. . .." (Wt'lg1m•I. 26#1, l!>.' i, IM) r.1tio Vt'I ilutklum rnllnnl• .. (Wrl.11n1I. I 10) c ,,, thlft Yll'W of I h•Kllfflo ...... nhovr, n
lf. .
140 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PROPERTY, NATURAL RIGHT, AND TtlE STATE OF NATURE 141

vides for poor and rich alike. But by human law we say, "This estate is this view, the holding of property eventually became legitimate, in spite of
mine. This house is mine. This slave is mine." 25 its violent origin, through customs and laws accepted by common consent.30
This seems a straightforward assertion that the origin of property was Another widely accepted solution explained that the words per iniqui-
conventional, a result of positive human law. But Huguccio found a prob- tatem (through iniquity) could be taken to mean propter iniquitatem (on
Jem here. He gave a cross-reference to the other key text, Dilectissimis, and account of iniquity). It was not that the first acquisition of property was
pointed out that there property was said to originate "through iniquity."26 iniquitous in itself but that the institution of property had been made
According to Difectissimis: necessary by iniquity, that is to say by the primal sin of Adam and the
corruption of human nature that followed from it. "By natural law, that is
The use of all things that are in the world ought to be common to all. But by the approval of reason, all things are common, that is they would be
through iniquity one claimed this as his own and another that. 27 common if there had been no sin," wrote Huguccio.31 But covetousness
The author of Difectissimis went on to mention Plato's vision of an ideal and avarice had made private ownership necessary. In good Augustinian
community where all things were shared in common, a reference that fashion some authors presented the institution of property as a partial
evoked much curious questioning among the canonists as to whether remedy for sin and others, including Huguccio, as a penalty for sin.32 This
women were among the things to be shared. 23 The text of Dilectissimis interpretation of Dilectissimis emphasized a temporal dimension in the
itself continued more soberly by recalling the example of the early Chris- discussion of property; there was a specific era-before the sin of Adam-
tian community at JerusaJem. when all things were common, and then a subsequent age when private
property was instituted.
!'Ji who owned houses or fields sold them and brought the proceeds In discussing Dilectissimis the canonists were addressing the perennial
with whatever else they had and laid them at the feet of the apostles .. .
problem of first acquisition. How could the initial appropriation from an
and they were divided among individuals according to need.29
original common stock be justified? On this there were almost as many
The reference to a common "use" of things was congenial to Franciscan shades of opinion as there were commentators on Gratian. Different texts
writers who wanted to maintain that there could be use without owner- of the Decretum suggested different solutions; but there were some com-
ship. However, this issue became prominent only later on at the time of monly recurring arguments, most of which can be illustrated from the
the poverty dispute. The Decretists focussed more on the words "through .. work of Huguccio. In considering the views of this outstanding Decretist
iniquity." Their problem was to explain how the institution of property we should bear in mind his teaching that the primary meaning of the term
could be legitimate if its origin was iniquitous. ius naturafe referred to a force of reason and moral discernment innate in
The simplest explanation of Dilectissimis acknowledged that the first humans, and that other meanings-natural law or natural right-were
act of private appropriation was indeed unjust; the first person who seized derived from this basic one.
for himself what had been common to all was an aggressor and a robber. Gratian himself opted for a conventional origin of property in human
This culprit was commonly identified with Nimrod, the "mighty hunter" custom or legislation; but some of his texts suggested an origin in divine
of Genesis 10, who was often portrayed in medieval writing as a tyrant. On law or natural law. Huguccio explored both lines of argument. Gratian

25. Dist. 8 c.1, HDivinum ius in scripturis habemus, humanum ius in legibus regum. 30. On Nimrod as tyrant and first property owner see the texts in Weigand, 337-339, <'·K·
Unde quisque possidet quod possidet? Nonne iure humano? ... Pauperes et divites Deus de Ricard us Anglicus, " Nembroth eo ipso quod propria possidebat peccauit ... Hodie uero pm-
uno limo fectt et pauperes et divites una terra supportat. lure tamen humano dicitur, haec pria habere est licitum, non tantum consuetudine set constitutione que communi con1R•n1<11
villa mea est, haec domus mea, hie servus meus est N
utcntium est confinnata ... . H

26. MS Admont 7, fol. 10 va, ad Dist. 8 c.1 s.v. lurr ergo human um, cum ius humanum
H • ••
31. MS Admont 7, fol. 2 va, Proeririum, HVel iure naturali, id est iud icio rationi1< ap-
sit ius, ergo non per iniquitatem.. Set contrarium dicitur xii q.i c.ii. pmbante omnia sunt, id est esscnt, communia nisi esset peccatum .. . .N; fol . Hlra, nrl /1i~t . H
N
: !
27. C.12 q.l c.2, "Communis enim usus omnium quae sunt in hoc mundo omnibus esse c. I s. v. "'" t'f'f(O humanum, "_ . . Vel iniquitas ibi dicitur peccatum et proprie primi h1>mlnl.• ul
homirubus debuit. Sed per iniquitatem alius hoc suum esse dixit et a Ii us illud." sil i;cnsus ' per' id est 'p ropt<'r' inlquit.1l<'m. ..." (Weigand , 327, 341 ).
28. See S. Kuttner, "Gratian and Plato, in Church arid C.m>f'rrimmt ;,, thr Middlt AKr.<,
N
32. Alanus, ad L)isr. H c.l 11.v. l11rr, " . . pn>pler iniqu itatem .. . id est pn'J'll"r l'ltlt•111J11111
ed. C.N.L. Brooke et al. (Cambridge, 1976), 93-1 llt ini4uittltem ... _" (Wei~nm\, :l41). l 111K111-..·lo. MS A1lmont 7, fol. 10rA, nd Oii;f. H c.l 11.v. lurt
29. C.12 q.l c.l. "Omnes autem qui domos Vf'I ilK""' pc>81ild<'h1ml v1•1i..t1-hant t'<l!'t, ('I pn-ti11 .-rg" /11mrnr111nr. H . niNI 1•nlm h11111111,..n·u!M'I 11111111" l'l'l.•<'nt communla ... !'M'I pn'f'h•r pt"t·
_ •

£'Orum et reliqua!I res qu~ ha~nt dft•rM>.111, po11rnlr11 11nlr l"" "'M 111><>11!11lnnm1 . . 1·1 di· rntum infli<-tmn 1•111 hommlol 111 ltt'"""' 111 "II •1•1l11·1tu" aJ halwmlum proprlum .. "
vidroantur .!linguli~ prout c111<1111•"I'""
rr-111 " (W1·i~rtn1I. :1-lO)
142 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PROPERTY, NATURAL RIGHT, AND THE STATE OF NAnJRE 143

clearly stated that by natural law all things were common, but the first approve common property "if there had been no sin"; but here, evidently
words of the Decretum identified natural law with the divine law of scrip- thinking of the actual condition of sinful humanity, he wrote that the
ture. Commenting on this Huguccio pointed out that scriptural texts natural law of reason favored individual acquisition. On the word acqui-
provided many examples of licit private property. God said to Adam, " In sitio, he wrote, "This is from the natural law that is said to be licit and
the sweat of your brow you shaU eat your bread." Also, we know from just and from reason and the judg:ment of reason, for reason dictates that
scripture that Cain and Abel had individual possessions because Cajn what belongs to no one (in nullius bonis) is conceded to the occupier.''37 In
made an offering from his fruits and Abel from his lambs. And the com- another context Huguccio suggested that what anyone acquired by his
mandment forbidding theft dearly indicated that it was lawful to own own care and labor became his own property.38
property.33 Later on Pope John XXIJ took up these same scriptural texts Even with a concept of permissive law there was still a problem in de-
and used them to buttress his case against the Franciscans. fending a natural law origin of private property. Isidore wrote that natural
The Decretist argument for an origin of property in rational natural law was based on "instinct of nature," not on any legal enactment; but
law was based on the Roman law theory of first acquisition, incorporated Gratian asserted quite explicitly that property came to exist by custom and
into the Decretum in a text taken from Isidore of Seville. Isidore wrote that enacted law; and the text of Augustine that he cited, Quo iure seemed
natural law existed everywhere by instinct of nature not by any legal en- clearly to support his position. When Huguccio came to consider this, he
actment and then continued: first repeated his argument about permissive law and then explained that,
Tus naturale . . . as, for instance, the union of men and women, the pro- although property could exist by natural law, only human Jaw defined
creation and rearing of children, the common possession of all things, adequately the various modes of possessing-such things as purchase, ex-
the same liberty of all, the acquisition of what is taken by air, land, or change, inheritance, prescription. Another canonist wrote that property
sea....34 was established by natural law and approved by civil law.39 A little later,
the great jurist-pope Innocent IV, writing about 1250, provided a decisive
The canonists often noted that, in this text, natural law was said to include treatment of this question. He wrote that property (dominium) was a right
both common possession and individual acquisition. This suggested to according to the natural law of reason; civil law provided only the forms of
Huguccio an objection that would recur in many later theories of property. action through which property claims were pursued in court. Hence, he
"If I wanted to snatch what was common so that I alone should have it I wrote, governments should not arbitrarily deprive their citizens of prop-
would commit theft."35 Huguccio responded by introducing the concept of erty; a law in violation of a natural right was not valid unless some just
permissive natural law, the Roman law category of res nullius, and his own cause intervened. A rescript could take away some form of action de riVl-d
understanding of ius naturale as reason or the judgement of reason. from civil law but could not deny justice altogether since this would bl•
All things were common by natural law, he wrote, but "by permission contrary to a natural right. (Or contrary to natural law; throughout thi~
not by precept." Natural law did not command that all things should be passage of Innocent the meaning of ius naturale shifts between "natural
common or that some things should be private; rather it permitted either law" and "a natural right"; sometimes the phrase could have either mean-
arrangement.36 Elsewhere, as we saw, Huguccio wrote that reason would ing, or both.)40

33. MS Admont 7, fol. 3ra, ad Dist. 1 c.l, .. Nam iure divino etiam in veteri lege aliquid 37. MS Admont 7, fol. 4ra, ad Dist. 1 c.7, NHoc de iure naturati quod dicitur licitum 11ivl"
erat proprium. Nonne a deo dictum est 'in labore uultus tui uesceris pane tuo'? Nonne Abel fas el de ratione e t iudicium rationis. Dictat enim ratio ut quod in nullius bonis est occup1mli
obtulit de suis agnis et Cain de suis frugibus . .. Item nonne furtum tune prohibitum erat, conceditur" (Weigand, 352. Weigand reads hominis for bonis).
nee fit furtum nisi rei aliene in proprie" (Weigand, 358). 38. MS Admont 7, fol. lOra, ad Dist. 8 c. l , N • acquisitum per laborem et sollkitutlirwm
••

34. Dist. 1 c.7, .. lus naturale est commune omnium nationum, eo quod ubique instinctu dic itur es!'e meum" (Weigand, 347).
naturae n on ronstitutione aliqua habetur ut viri et feminae coniunctio, liberorum succes.~io 39. MS Admont 7, fol . lOra, ad Dist. 8 c.1, "Non !amen ostenditur eo (I.e. iun- ""lunoll)
et educatio, rommunis omnium possessio, et omnium una libertas, acquisitio rorum quaf' •1uahter aliquid pn>prium possidt>atur sicut ostenditur iure humano, ut t>mptiOnt'. tlonA·
coelo, terra, marique capiuntur ..... lionl', rnmmutationc, legato, 11ucct'S...ione, pn'S<'riptione et huiusmodi. .....; Sumrn11 Animal ~r
35. MS Admont 7, fol. lOra, ad Dist. I c.7, ... . . si uellem 11urripere ut ll<llus haberem quod •11fl.<tantia, ad l>i5/. I c.7, "Set hoc- ,fidm11J1 t'!l!Ot' .t1• iure ciuilc per approb11tiom•m, i11rb1 Vt'nl
esset commune furtum commiterem." rmlurali:i J'l'f in:itituliorwm" (Wrlj(ftl\41, 11\4)
36. MS Admont 7, fol. 4ra, 11d Dist. I c.7, " I)(> iun> nalur•li alii111ld t•:il nlt'um ('I aliquid 40. <'mt1rnt'nl11ria l11r11-'t'l1/I/ ·""I"'' llflr.o. 'l""''I"" dt'1' rrlnlium (Fr11nlcfurt, I !'i70), 011 X. 1.2.7,
est tuum, :!let de permJ:i~lone, non dP prf't'••pln, <!Iii/I hll< <llVlll\111\ llllllHl<l<Ull pwd pit omnln lnl 4v. l\rgulnR thnt " d ty K••Vrrtlllll'lll 11111!.t hnl Id... II" 1111l>t<'c·t11' pmpC'rly uhltrully, lrmn
<'SS<' n1mmuni11 vrl 1111<11111 ''"'"'' prupd11. 11t•t 1wrmittit 1111111111 "'"" • '11t11111mft1 1·t 11li1111n ''"!«'
pniprll\... " ( W1ojl(11111I, .' l'IJ)
, 1•11! wnolt•, "Sup••r t1•h11.o 1•t1111n l•h~1111 111 hn• "'"""'"'"""I'"""""'· nun 1111.. 1tll\h1tum r!OM'I In
1,.,.,.1.,1w111 lml1t .. 111•1h11t rl <'hi• hula 'I"'"' • 1l 11lh111"111 "I'"''"'· vrl 11<1111trlt11r cir httl' "'''"'""
144 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PROPERTY, NATURAL R IGITT, ANO THE SrA1'E OF NATURE 145

Innocent also argued, in a very influential passage, that all peoples, ers of thought an author presented often referred to different historical
even infidels, had a right to acquire property and to form their own gov- epochs.
ernments. He wrote that God subjected all things to the dominion of man Embedded in the texts of the Decretum, and occasionally stated explic-
as a rational creature. At first all was held in common, but property was itly, there was an historical account of how human government emerged
introduced by occupation of things in bonis nullius or by agreements like after an origina) age of prelapsarian innocence. After the Fall of Adam,
that between Abraham and Lot Innocent added an explanation, lacking in men lived for a time as scattered individuals guided only by natural law.
Roman law, of why first occupancy created an obligation in others to re- According to Gratian this lasted until people began "to gather as one and
spect the right of the first possessor. It was because of the natural law that live together" in the time of Cain who first built a city (Gen. 4.17). Then
Gratian had set out in the first words of the Decretum-the scriptural rule there came an age of customary law until. finally, actual legislation began
that we should not do to others what we do not want done to ourselves.41 in the time of Moses.42
Innocent's view remained influential but it was quickJy challenged by Jn the evolution of property a similar development occurred. First
Hostiensis, the greatest canonist of the next generation. He held that, after there was an age of innocence and community; then, after the sin of Adam,
the coming of Christ, rightful dominion could exist only in the Christian a time ante occ11pationem as one canonist put it, when the world lay open for
church. The argument about the rights of infidels continued all through appropriation.43 Individual properties could then be acqu~red in acc.or-

..
the medieval era and took on a new life in the sixteenth century in the dance with the rational natural law that granted ownership to the first
.
Spanish debates about the rights of American Indians. ~
occupant of a res nullius, and in accordance with the needs of fallen hu~a~
So far we have seen that, in different scattered passages, the De- nature. (Here the Christian doctrine of the Fall was grafted on to the ongt-
cretists attributed the origin of property to the divine law of scripture, to nal Roman law theory of first acquisition.) Specific divisions of property
natural law, or to human law. Commenting on this, Rudolph Weigand ob- were made by human compacts like that between Abraham and Lot
served that, not only did the canonists often differ from one another but recorded in Scripture and occasionally, by direct divine grants. Finally,
that sometimes the same author seemed to contradict himself in different property rights came to be defined and regulated by the growth of custom
contexts. It is true that canon law, even more than Roman law, provided and the laws of kings. For a systematic thinker like Huguccio, underlying
an armory of texts that could be used to support a wide variety of later • this whole process was ius naturale understood as human reason, "a natu-
...'i
opinions-including those of Pope John XXII and William of Ockham. ral force of the soul," that gave rise to different perceptions of what was
But, although Decretist commentary was rich and varied, much of the naturally right in different historical circumstances.
apparent incoherence disappears when we realize that the different lay-

ut sunt dominia, obligationes et huiusmodi. Et non datur a iure civili vel ab imperatore ut ac· Tiieologians
tiones ... Et d ico non valere legem vel rescriptum in praeiudicium naturalis iuris nisi iusta
causa interveniat .. . Sed et tune, ut quidam dicunt, licet sustineatur quod auferat actionem, Theologians as well as lawyers wrote extensively about the origin of
tamen quin reddat iustitiam auferre non potest, cum esset contra ius naturale.... De iure property in the thirteenth century. I am treating them somewhat cursorily
autem naturali dixi dominia ad aliquem pertinere, id est de iure gentium, quod dicitur nafu. here because, rather surprisingly, the theological material was not much

rale quia ratione inductum est.• insti de reb. divisi. § Singulorum (lnsl. 2.1.11) .. . quod eliam used by Ockham or his adversaries in the Franciscan dispute. Ockh~~
dicitur naturale ius quia apud omnes generaliter est.ff On this text see K. Pennington, Tht did occasionally quote Aquinas when he could find a text of the Domm1-
Princt lfrUI tlrt 1.Aw (Berkeley, 1993), 149-51, 222- 23. Innocent was following the Roman law
tradition of Caius that identified ius naturalt with ius gmtium. The argument that a right can master that happened to suit his own argument; but, in discussing our
acquired by natural law could not be violated was repeated by Hostiens.is and Johannes specific problem, the origin of individual ownership, both sides rclit•d
Andreae commenting on this same text of the Decrttals.
41. Commtnlaria ad X.3..33.8, fol. 429vb-430ra, "Deus haec universa subiecit dominio ri\· 42. Gralian, dictum antt Dist. 7 c.l The text of Dist. 7 c. I also referred to lht> fumulin11
tionalis creaturae .. . et haec a principio seculi fuit communis quousque usibus priorum ldwgivers ol the Egyptians, Grttk.1, and Romans. H05tiensis gave a similar his torical 11n~•unl
parentum introductum est quod aliqui aliqua el a Iii alia sibi appropriant ... quia naturale est of the dt>velopmcnt of Jaw in Summa l>omini Hrnric-us Cardino/is Hostirnsis (l.yon11, l'iJ7),
res communes negligi ... et fuerunt a principio cuiu!l<'Unqllt" qui (l("cupavit, q uia in nullius l'Tfll"mium, fol. 2va. Rufinu!I too cl1'!W'rlh<-.I how the first humans, reduced almo:o1t In ttw con
bonis erant nisi Dei .. . sed ab aliis occupatum OC't'Upl'n' ™"' lkcbat quia ficl>at contra k>gem dition of animals aftt>r lilt- l'.1111, 11•111hM'<l 111111 1•no11Kh 11parks of ju~lice and undt•r.olandinK lo
naturae, qua quilibet inditum est ut alii ll(m fadat ljll<lll 11ihl non vult flt•ri." On lnnoct>nt's n1mt• lt>jtf'lh1•r and cn•alr 11 h<"IV of l.11w (Sunrm11, 4)
argummt and tM crilicism ol tl08tirru1lll ,..... ,. Muhtu..n, l'•'I""'· l.11rc'Y"" 1111111,,fiolrl~ H'hiJ,,.wl· 4J Sin1 nlu~. "Omnl11 ..uni &'011111111111" ' ""' 11111111 ~h. Id ••ftl n•mmunitt'r omnll111" l'"h-111
phia, 1979),6- 17. .mtr '"·1·11p11li111w111" (Wrl"'""''· 1]111
146 THE [DEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PROPERTY, NATURAL RIGHT, AND THE STATE OF NATURE 147

almost entirely on texts drawn from the Deere/um and the Bible, together ture:48 Duns Scotus, however, citing the canons Quo iure and Dilectissimis,
with their ordinary glosses. maintained that individual ownership was not introduced by natural
In several scattered contexts, Thomas Aquinas presented an influential law or divine law but by positive human law, established either by the pa-
though not altogether coherent theory of property. For Thomas natural ternal authority of Adam or by the po1itical authority of an elected ruler.49
law was essentially a law of reason, "nothing other than the participation Bonaventure and other Franciscans often emphasized that ownership
of the rational creature in the eternal law."44 But, when he came to explain could not be acquired without a will to own. As Richard of Conington
the text of Isidore stating that by natural law all things were common, wrote, "No one has dominion without desire and will." It was precisely
Thomas argued that natural law could have a different meaning, as refer- this will to dominate that the friars claimed to have renounced.50
ring to a primitive condition of mankind. "We might say that for man to be On the eve of the Franciscan poverty dispute two rival theories of
naked is of the natural law." According to this understanding of the term, property were presented by the Augustinian, Giles of Rome, and the Do-
private property was not introduced by natural law but by human artifice. minican, John of Paris. Giles combined a historical account of the origin of
It was an addition to natural law devised by human reason for the benefit property with a theocratic doctrine of papal overlordship. He argued that
of human Hfe.45 private ownership came to exist through a series of conventions and com-
. i
In another context Aquinas wrote of a "natural dominion" that be- pacts beginning with the sons of Adam, renewed by the sons of Noah,
longed to humans because of their faculty of reason "in which the image of and then repeated many times as the human population increased. But
God consists." He also wrote that it was by virtue of human free will, Giles also held that, since God was the lord of all, and the pope was God's
through which a man was master of his own acts, that he could be master vicar on earth, all licit dominion-including both property and ruling
of external things also.46 Aquinas explained that private property was authority-was held ultimately from the pope. There could be no right-
an acceptable and necessary way of exercising man's natural dominion ful property or rightful government outside the church.st These argu-
because common property was easily neglected and could give rise to ments drew a quick response from John of Paris. He maintained that
confusion and discord. It was fitting, therefore, that external goods should "individuals as individuals have right and power and true dominion."
be held by individuals as regards "the power of acquiring and administer- They acquired this right, not from any ruler, either pope or king, but by
ing things"; but, as regards use, they ought to be treated as common in the .
.(
their own "skill, labor, and industry." The pope was only an administrator v
sense that they were to be shared with those in need. This argument re- of property that belonged to the church, the king only a judge who could
stated the doctrine that the canonists had elaborated earlier, and, indeed, settle disputes about lay possessions. Neither was the source of the indi-
Thomas's words here read like a paraphrase of Huguccio.47 Thomas never vidual's right to property.52
concerned himself directly with how the first acquisition of private prop- By around 1300 a considerable body of theological argument existed
erty from a common stock could have come about licitly, and he never 11. about the origin of property, but no consensus had emerged. Aquinas
wrote specifically about a "right" (ius) to property.
Among Franciscan writings, the Summa of Alexander of Hales main- 48. Altxnndri dt Halts .. . Summa thLOlogie11, 4 vols. (Quaracchi, 1930-48), 4:348. Alexander
based his argument here on the canonistic doctrine concerning the precepts and "demon-
tained that natural law prescribed common property in the state of strations" of natural law.
innocence and private ownership in the state of corrupted human na- 49. Opus Oxo11itnst, 4.15.2 in /oannis Duns Scoli ... opera omnia, ed. L. Vives, 26 vol11.
(Paris, 1891-95), 18: 265, 270-71. Scotus did not accept the canonists' doctrine of permlMlvr
44. Summa thtologiot, 1.2.ae.91.2. natural law. He held that community of property was at first a precept of natural law. but
45. Ibid., l.2ae.945. that this precept was revoked by God after Adam's sin.
46. Ibid., 2.2ae.66.l ; NDe perlectione spiritualis vitae# in <J,Nra omnia iussu l..Lonis XIII 50. On this aspect of Franciscan thought see especially Paolo Grossi, "Usus far ti. l.n
P.M., 48 vols. (Rome, 1882-1971), 41:79. no7.ione di pmprietl nella inaugurazione dell' eti nuova," Qiuidtnri Fiortntini P" In slorin dtl
47. Thomas wrote that external goods could be considered in two ways, H • unum
••
pmsirro gruridiro modtrno 1 (1972): 287-355. The emphasis on will and intention wu not.
est potestas procurandi et dispensandi et quantum ad hoc lkitum est quod homo pro- however, just a product of Franciscan voluntarism. It was rooted in Roman law. St'f', «'·I'·
pria possidet . .. sed ut communes, ut scilicet de facili aliquis eos communicet in necessitate Vixrst 41.2.3.6, "If you are on a pil'Ct' of land and you lose the will to pos~ it, you lmnwJI
aliorum. " Cf. Huguccio ad Dist. 47 c.8, s.v. Quod ~I, MS Admont 7, fol. 65ra, " . . . proprium att>ly reasc to ptis!'ll'8s it."
quoad dominium vel potestatem dispensandi, commune quia aliis communicandum tem- !il . R. S<-hol1.• ~i.. /\l')litliu' Ron111m1~ I>.- ,.. ., .,,.,./,1.~lln1 111•lrsl11lr (Weimar, 1929), 11- J:\, 70 7'i,
pore necessitatis." Of course Aquinas also knew Aristotle's recomm.,nd11tion or privalt• IO:l · 111.
property and common use in Politics 2 .5.6-8; but the only tt'xl ho• 1·ho,.1• tn dh• h..n• w11,. l 'i2. E lll1•lrn~tri 11, '°'' , /11li111111r'• Uull/1111 '""' /'11rl• 1lll<'r l.llni,11lrrl1r 111111 ,,a,.-rlirlrr ( ;fl4"•/t
Timothy6.17. (StullKMI. l'lf,111. 'Ito •17
148 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PROPERTY, NATURAL RIGllT, AND THE STATE O F NATIJRE 149

treated individual ownership as something artificial, an addition to natu- plify this way of reasoning. Each of them envisaged an age of primal in-
ral law devised by reason; but he gave no historical account of how the nocence when there was no sin, no false consciousness as we might say
division of things had actually come about. Giles of Rome provided a nowadays, no alienation of man from himself or his world. The conduct
historical explanation but, rather incongruously, subordinated it to a theo- of life in this age of authenticity established a norm for future human be-
cratic ideology. John of Paris argued that property was acquired by labor havior. Bonagratia's Franciscan dream world was entirely without prop-
without addressing, or even apparently envisaging, the central objection to erty; in Pope John's imaginary Eden private ownership was a dominant
such a theory. (How could an individual's labor give him exclusive rights fact of life.
to what had been common property?) Duns Scotus required that there be At first glance, it is not evident why a fourteenth-century Franciscan
a ruling authority before property could be instituted, but he left undeter- dispute should give rise to such speculations about earlier ages of human
mined whether the original institution was by the paternal authority of history. But, in fact, the habit of mind I have suggested, an inclination to
Adam or the political authority of an established government-and dif- see the remote past through a prism of present-day concerns, was a char-
ferent consequences could follow from the two alternatives. acteristic feature of Franciscan thought. There is an irony in the way the
The Franciscan dispute of the early fourteenth century led to a recon- situation developed. Contemporaries of Francis saw him as a saint who
sideration of the whole question. Two especially interesting contributions imitated perfectly the life of Christ. But gradually a curious reversal came
to the debate came from the Franciscan spokesman, Bonagratia of Ber- about. The Franciscan way of practising poverty, it was assumed, showed
gamo, and from Pope John XXII himself. Their opposing views, both how Christ and the apostles must have lived. Francis himself taught best
marked by an odd kind of primitivism, shaped the immediate context by example. His own way of living an evangelical life was to obey all the
within which William of Ockham eventually took up these questions. precepts and counsels of the gospel in a very literal and simple and down-
to-earth fashion. (When, for instance, Francis remembered the text "Take
no thought for the morrow," he told his brothers not to soak beans
BoNAGRATIA OF BERGAMO AND JOHN XXII overnight in order to prepare them for eating the next day.) Francis had no
Bonagratia and John XXII were both trained canonists and both ar- interest in legal niceties and indeed he had difficulty in composing a Rule
gued from canonistic texts, but each of them presented an idiosyncratic at all. But, after his death, the Franciscan way of life came to be defined
argument about property in a primordial state of nature that moved out- with elaborate technicalities drawn from civil and canon law, culminating
side the framework of earlier juristic thought. Instead of pursuing the in the multiple distinctions of the decretal £xiit. Then all this thirteenth-
kind of historical argument that we can find in the Decretist texts, each en- century legal terminology was projected back on the life of Christ. The
visaged a primeval condition of things that provided permanent ideal Franciscans came to believe wholeheartedly that Christ and the apostll's,
norms for their own society. Bonagratia presented his views in a Trncta- like good Franciscans, had renounced all "property, possession, usufruct
tus de paupertate, written in the early stages of the Franciscan controversy and right of use," retaining for themselves only a "simple use of fact."
when John XXII initially invited a debate on evangelical poverty.53 At first This was how Bonagratia of Bergamo argued in his first approach to
John ignored Bonagratia's arguments about the original state of nature the problem of poverty. Bonagratia set out to prove that Jesus and his first
but, when they were repeated in a later manifesto of Michael of Cesena, followers had nothing "as regards property or lordship or right of bringing
the pope responded to them in Quia vir reprobus, the decretal that Ockham suit." His underlying purpose of course was to prove that the Franciscan
in tum commented on. way of life that embodied these same principles was truly evangelical.
There is always a danger of circularity in arguments that seek to But he did not begin, as one might expect, by arguing from scriptun·
derive norms for an existing society from a supposed primeval condition that the apostles possessed nothing, and then showing how the Francis-
of humankind. Typically an author projects prejudices derived from reac- cans faithfully followed their example. His argument moved in the oppo-
tions to his own culture on to an imaginary state of nature and then uses ~ite direction; the example of Francis, as understood by his Order, shnwt•(t
the state of nature he has invented to justify the prejudices he set out with what the teaching and practk<' of Christ must have been. Bonagratia was
in the first place. Bonagratia and John XXII both, in different ways, exem- n·rtain that the pov<'rly of Francis could not have been diffl'rt'nt fmm
llw poverty <'Xt•mplifil•tl In tlw lift• u( (. 'hrist. This was pn.wl•d, lw main·
53. L. Oliger, " Fr. Bonagrati;a de Bergamo t•I e lu1' Trac-t11tu" dt• Chrl<'lll <'I npo!ilnlorum lilim•d, not only hy llu• ho1l11rNN 1111111' 11nh1t's lift', hut nlsn, mirnculnrncly, hy
paupt•r1ah•," Ar1·/1i1ium frt1111"i~.-nn11m hisllorinmr 22 ( JQ2Q)· 7111 :ni;. 4117 'i 11 . tlw sti~m,\lil, till' wo11111t" 111 l 'lu Int th11t 11p1w.m•d on his body. M11r1•11vc•r,
150 THE IDEA OF NATl.JRAL R IGHTS PROPERTY, NAnJRAL RIGHT, AND THE STATE OF NATURE 151

Pope Gregory IX, followed by several other popes, had explained that he had no ownership of anything singly or in common, but only simple
Fran~ underst~ apostolic poverty to mean the renunciation of all prop- use of fact. "58
erty, singly and m common.54 It followed that Christ and the apostles had Bonagratia's most detailed discussion of these questions came when
renounced everything, singly and in common. "If blessed Francis vowed he addressed an argument commonly raised by the Franciscans' adver-
~nd pro~ to observe the gospel, living without property singly or saries. There could be no complete renunciation of all ownership, they
m common, It follows that such was the teaching and rule of the gospel asserted, because, as regards consumables, ownership was inseparable
and consequently that Christ had nothing, singly or in common. " SS After a from u se. To refute this assertion Bonagratia turned again to the age of in-
long quotation from Exiit, Bonagratia added that, since Francis had not nocence. His own argument had two stages. First he showed that use of
only practised poverty but also taken a vow of poverty, the apostles must fact was mandated by natural law, then that there was no property (though
have taken a vow of poverty too. there was use of fact) before the sin of Adam.
Bonagratia was not content with this level of argument. His further Bonagratia argued like this. It was a precept of natural law that every
step was to restate the story of primal innocence in the Garden of Eden in person should seek to preserve his own life; but this required the use of
terms of the Franciscan teaching on poverty; then he defended Franciscan consumable things like food and clothing; therefore the use of consum-
poverty as a return to the state of innocence he had imagined. Here again ables was a precept of natural law. Moreover this precept was inherent
an aspect of Francis's own personality and behavior provided a starting in natural law understood in many senses of the term-Bonagratia men-
point for a later growth of Franciscan theorizing, or fantasizing. Francis's tioned, with appropriate juristic citations, the law that began with the
exceptional attitude to the natural world, his love and compassion for all origin of humankind, the law that was observed everywhere by instinct
creatures, and his extraordinary power to control birds and animals are of nature, and the law that nature taught all animals. These natural laws
well attested in the first lives of the saint.56 Commenting on this, Bonaven- (iura naturalia) could not be rejected or changed in any way. 59 But proper-
ture wrote that Francis had "pictured anew the state of innocence." Before ties and possessions and usufructs and right of using were all rights
Bonagratia intervened this had been just an engaging theme of Franciscan introduced by human law, and all such rights could be renounced volun-
piety. Bonagratia turned it into a technical argument for the doctrine of tarily.60 Jn the age of innocence, Bonagratia continued, the use o f consum-
apostolic poverty that was peculiar to the Franciscan Order. In the state of ables was also a precept of natural law understood in yet another sense, as
innocence, he wrote, there had been no division of property. And Christ divine command, for God had told Adam to eat the fruit of all the trees
had come to renew this state of innocence in all who wished to follow him except one.6 1 But-and this was the crux of the Franciscan's case-ther<'
perfectly-that is, the apostles and, later, Francis and the Franciscans.57 In was no property in the age of innocence.62
a later passage, Bonagratia described this primordial state of innocence Bonagratia illustrated his argument throughout with an array of
that Christ had reestablished in the precise language that the Franciscans .- dozens of citations to civil and canon law but the two essential texts were
used to define their own way of life. "If Christ held the state of innocence the ones I have already discussed in considering the work of the De-

58. Ibid., 497, "Set in statu innocentie fuissent homines sine dominiis distinctis. fikut
54: ~id., 329, NPrimo ex eo, quod fere omnes romani pontifires qui fuerunt a tempore
patet VIII di. c. l (Quo iurt). lgitur si Christus tenuit statum innocentie, non habuit d ominium
Franaso . . . confinnaverunt regulam et vitam beati Francisci, que est sanctum evan-
d istinctum in speciale vel in communi alicuius rei, set solum simplici fact i usum rerum."
~lium observare in altissima paupertate, scilicet in non habendo aliquid nee in speciale nee
m comune, tanquam regulam et vitam evangelicam a Christo doctam.. .. Quern etiam 59. Ibid., 503, " Praeterea usus facti rerum necessarium ad s ubstentationem nature t'!lt d t•
statum ... Christus .. . miraculose confinnavit, cum ipsum beatum Franciscum tanquam iure naturali ... Et ideo nee per legem nee per renuntiationem sive abdicationem nee ali<Jll"
suum specialem sectatorem suorum sacrorum vulnerum stigmatibus insignavit. ... H
modo tolli vel mutari potest. w
55. Ibid., 330, "Sequitur quod si beatus Franciscus vovit et promisit evangelium vivendo 60. Ibid., HProprietates vero et possessiones et dominia rerum sunt a iure humano. VIII
sine proprio in specia)i et in communi, quod talis fuit doctrina et regula evangelii et per ron- di,.t. Quo i11rt'. .. . Cerium est autem quod omni iuri privato, quod a\icui compo:•t..1 " "
sequens quod Christus non habuit in speciali nee in communi.H humano iure, pot<'St quis rt'nuntial"l'. . . ."
56. See John Oakley, "John XXII and Franciscan Innocence, Fr11ncisam Stud~ 46 (1986):
ff
61. rbid., 504, '"Quod ault>m usu"' n.•rum, a limento rum cadat sub preccpto lt:Ki• m1111n·
217- 226. 1>.111'1 ... in "'tatu sciliet>t innoct'f1tic•. lli.•11.~ d('(jit d uo precepta ho mini: unum d(• c·unmM'
57. TTact11tus, 489, "Et ipse Christus venerit . .. ad omnem materiam !IOllicitudinis dc•ndo, St>cundarium dC' non cornm1.. h•111lo.
temporalium perfecte eum sequi volentibus amputand11m C'I 1111 ~lfttum inn<K'"t'TltlaC' r«'no- 62. Ibid., _i;()fi, '"St•t nullu~ 1mtr I"" ,·11111111 h"hUL"-"''' tfominium C'.1n1m n•nim, •!Ill' 11•11 n•n
vandum." ~111n11ntur ··
152 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PROrERTY, NATURAL RIGHT, AND THE STATE OF NATURE 153

cretists, Dilectissimis and Quo iure. Bonagratia quoted both of them again in fact presents us with a state of innocence in which there was a duty to
at this point in his argument. According to Dilectissimis, he noted, the obey the precept of natural law commanding self-preservation but, so far
use of all things ought to be common to all; it was "through iniquity" that as he tells us, no corresponding natural rights. He made no mention of a
individual property had come to exist. And, according to Quo iure, prop- natural law based on human reason that might justify private property or
erty was introduced by human law.63 So before the sin of Adam there was of rights related to such a law. Bonagratia referred to the idea of subjective
no meum and tuum, no "mine" and "yours." It follow.ed that, in the age of rights only in connection with human laws and then only to argue that
innocence, there was use of consumables in accordance with natural law, such rights could be freely renounced.
but no property; Adam never really owned the fruit that he ate. One When Bonagratia described the state of innocence he was imposing
might argue that the original condition of things was irrelevant for future new Franciscan interpretations on the old texts that he quoted. The idea
ages, Bonagratia noted, because the state of innocence did not last long; that all things were common in an original state of nature was widespread
but, he replied, it could have lasted. Adam had it in him not to sin, and in earlier writing; and Dilectissimis did indeed refer specifically to common
if he had not sinned the common use of all things without any property use. But none of the many canonists who commented on the text had in-
would have persisted everywhere among all people at all times.64 It was terpreted it as meaning that the fruit Adam ate did not become his own, or
clear then that the apostles and the Franciscans (who had returned to the that he had no right of use or usufruct in the things that he actually did
state of innocence according to Bonagratia's earlier argument) could Jive use. These were distinctively Franciscan ideas. Similarly, no one except
in this fashion, renouncing all ownership, even of consumables, and re- Franciscan apologists maintained that the apostles had owned no property
taining only a simple use of fact without any right of use or usufruct.65 in common; the relevant texts in the Acts of the Apostles seemed to state
Bonagratia's argument has not received all the attention it deserves in the opposite view quite clearly. Finally Bonagratia's idea that the apostles
modem histories of natural law and natural rights. The best account of it, a and then the Franciscans had returned to a state of prelapsarian innocence
detailed and perceptive appraisal, was given by Giovanni Tarello,66 but he was highly unusual. Bonagratia's view that the primeval state of inno-
was misled at one point by Bonagratia's use of the term iura naturalia, cence was a normative condition to which humans could and should
where the Franciscan referred to the various kinds of natural law. Tarello return was a new and potentially subversive doctrine.
thought that Bonagratia had introduced a subjective meaning of ius into The Franciscan spokesman concluded his argument by pointing out
his argument here and that he was presenting a novel doctrine of inalien- that, if indeed use could not be separated from ownership in consum-
able natural rights. But this is a misreading of the text. Bonagratia used the ables, it would follow that Christ and the apostJes had owned property
plural form, iura naturalia, because he was quoting, word for word, from a not only in common but also individually since they consumed things as
passage of the Institutes that he cited, and in that context (and in Bonagra- individuals; but such a conclusion was obviously heretical and absurd ac-
tia's own context) the words referred plainly to natural laws.67 Bonagratia cording to Bonagratia. When Michael of Cesena repeated the charge of
heresy and the argument from the state of innocence in his manifesto of
63. Ibid., 504, "Certum est quod stante iure nature, nullus potest dicere de aliqua re: hoc
1328, Pope John XXII took up the challenge and showed himself entirely
est meum hoc est tuum. Hee enim duo pronomina meum et tuum, ut dicit beatus Oemens. willing to embrace as Catholic truth the "heretical absurdities" that his ad-
sunt ex iniquitate ... introducta ... Xll q.1 c. diltctissimis, et Augustinus ... VIII dist. c. quo versaries condemned.
iurt... ." There were plenty of arguments within the existing armory of law
64. Ibid., "Potuit enim prim us homo non peccare et sic usus omni um rerum semper fuis· and theology that could have been used against the dissident Franciscans;
set in omnibus hominibus...."
65. Ibid., 505, " Patel igitur ex predictos quod apostoli et fratres Minores in speciali et in
but, when John XXII made his final response to them in Quia vir repro-
communi potuerunt a se abdicare dominium et proprietatem ... et ... tantummodo usum bus, he chose to strike out on a different and original path of his own. His
facti simplicem retinere"; 508, "Quia simplex facti usus utentibus n.ichil iuris prebet. ac qui adversaries maintained that the apostles had returned to the primeval
habet usumfructum, habet ius in re...." state of innocence. Pope John did not choose to challenge this dubious
66. Giovanni Tarello, " Profili giuridici della questione delta poverti\ nt'I Franrescanesimo
assertion; he just invented a different state of innocence to suit his own
prima di Ock.ham," Univtrsitit dtgli studi di Cen01Hl. Ann11li dtll11 far<>lllJ di xiuri~priulmlll 3
(1964): 338- 448. ....:;· argument.
67. Traclatus, 503, ".. . naturalia iura, qur l\ru~l 1mmrio l""".. I'"' l'l'rvilnl11r, 1livina •1undilm
providmtiil cons tituta m•mpn firm., "''!Ill' lmm11t11l•llln p,.rmn111•11t ln~tll . 1lt• iun• nnlu · •. 1.2. 11 . ~· ·r;m·llo. 421> JO Kr-1..n lnM tu llw """'I. ul Vlll"V· ·ri\n-llo 11t1Kgr11t..d th111 ll1H1"M'"""
rali , I.I, drnl firwm Yl'rl> Ml m1t11rt1ll<I •• llo11n.,,rnll11 w1,. ' l"''""K 111,.rnlly hrll' Imm /11.<I. :" rntlwr thom ( kkh11m fhol l11tm1h1t .,,1 11 •ul•f<•• tlv11 nw11nh11( of th.- wnnl /uo
154 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RrG HTS PROPERTY, NATURAL RIGHT, AN D TifE STATE Of NATURE 155

Bonagratia and Michael of Cesena appealed to Dilectissimis to prove pattern at the very beginning of things in an ideal state of nature was not
that at first there was only a simple factual use of things without any indi- common possession but individual property. This was John's original con-
vidual or common ownership. John replied that Dilectissimis itself implied tribution to the debate. It went counter to the whole tenor of the canonistic
a state of common ownership even before Adam and Eve had sinned. The tradition that he had inherited.
Decretist text explained that, after division was made, one man could call John developed his argument extensively in a final discussion toward
this his own and another that. But, John argued, if the division produced the end of Quia vir reprobus. Here he addressed the central question that we
individual ownership, then what was divided must originally have been have been considering. How did private property come to exist in the first
owned in common. lt was not simple use of fact that was divided but place? Or, as the pope put it, "By what law was the right of property or
common property. 66 ownership introduced?" The pope's adversary-John always referred to
This was a fresh way of arguing about Dilectissimis, but the underlying Michael of Cesena simply as "the heretic"-argued that property was an
assertion that there had been common ownership in the original state of institution of human law and he quoted Quo iure to prove the point. But,
nature was familiar enough. The next step in John's argument was more the pope argued, the heretic was wrong; property was really established by
unconventional. Although Adam and Eve had owned things in common, divine law. Quo iure itself stated that, "We have divine law in scripture,
he asserted, there was a still earlier stage of things when Adam alone human law in the laws of kings." But in scripture we can read that property
owned as a single individual. God said to Adam, "Have dominion over existed before there were any laws of kings or even any kings.n John next
the fishes of the sea and the birds of the air and all living creatures.. .." repeated his assertion that, in the original state of innocence, Adam at first
(Genesis 1.28). And if Adam had dominion he was a domin11s, a master had sole dominion of temporal things; 73 but now he carried the argument
or owner.69 There was an equivocation here, as Ockham would point out, further. The pope was concerned all along to prove that the suum-<>ne's
between two meanings of the word dominium, and John XXIJ, as a pro- own-existed by divine law before there was any human legislation. He
fessional jurist, can hardly have been unaware of it; but the pope was therefore maintained that, after first instituting property in the age of in-
interested only in refuting the Franciscan claim that there had been no nocence, God reinstituted it again and again. After the Fall, God said to
property in a state of innocence so he persistently used dominium in a uni- Adam, " In the sweat of your brow you shall eat your bread." So Adam
vocal sense to mean individual ownership. The text of Genesis that John could call his bread suum, his own; and this was before there were any
first cited did not make it clear that God's words conferring dominion kings. Abel made an offering to God from his flock, so he too had property.
were spoken to Adam alone before Eve was created, so the pope reinforced Noah also could call something his own, for he had a vineyard. Later God
1
them with a reference to Ecclesiasticus 17.1-5, where we read, "God cre- ; made specific grants to Abraham and Isaac and to the children of Israel
ated man of the earth . . . and he had dominion over beasts and fowls. He through Moses. It followed that private property existed "in the state of in-
created of him a helpmate like to himself. .. .' "]O For Pope John, this dearly nocence and after the Fall of our first parents and before the Flood and after
indicated that Adam had dominion before the creation of Eve; but this the Flood"-and all this before there were any laws of kings.7•
meant that Adam was at first the sole owner of the world, for there were Moreover, John argued, property could only have originated in divine
no other persons to share it with him. There could be no common owner- law. God was the lord of all temporal things by right of a creator bt•-
ship when only one person existed.71 What God had established as a cause he made the world out of nothing and by right of a maker becausl'
he shaped creatures out of his own material; so dominion of things could
68. Bullarium Francisamum 5: 417-IS, " Haec autem divisio facta fuit eius rei, cuius prius be conceded to humans only by a divine grant The pope concluded:
erat communio; divisio autem facta est rerom et non usus simplicis facti, ut patet, quia alius
dicebat hoc esse suum et alius aliud .. . sequitur, quod ante divisionem quoad rerum do-
minia communio erat." n . fbid .• 440. .... . ius enim divinum est, quod in scripturis divinis habemus. ut k•gitur
69. Ibid., 422, " f.t dominamin i . .. Ex quibus evidenter apparel, primas parentes . . . dcr VIII di . cap. Quo iure . . . In scripturis autem divinis habemus, quod, antequam ' "II.'""
n·11.t11n,
minium in statu innocentiae habuissent, Et si quaeritur utrum illud dominium proprium immo etiam antequam regcs es.<;('flt, rt'S aliquae a!icuius erant: ergo iure di vino .lliquL~ di<1•r..
fuerit vel commune, videtur ... quod ante fonnationem Evae dominium temporalium i\dae puteral, aliquid suum CS.'!(>."
proprium fuit non commune." .. 73. Ibid .• " Die-it c>rgo, qu01I d1•min.1tw1 ftU'rit; ex quo sequitur quod dominium h~
70. Ibid., 423, " ... cum de solo Adam dkitur. <Jtmd <iomin.llw1 ··~t lw.•ti11rurn 1•1 volatil·
ium, sequitur quod t>I solus dominus foil .. . •
71. Jhid., 422, "Commune quidc•m C'~llC" " " " , ......... 'Ulll ....... I"" h•111por•· mo h1t•r i1 o•t
r<"!lpt"<"tt• unius . . . nihll did «nmmmH• pnHll "
1 huil ... ...
74. ll>iol., "'Ex 1 1uihu~ 1111mlh11R
t1r~um primo r11m I"'"'"'""' "'
n·y,11m .tll•111t.I ••!<!«' •m1m ··
I'""'' •I""'' 11li1111i!I l't in !ll.1l11 inntll' <•nlhw ,., 1•0111
~11h• 111111 .. 111111 rt pu~t di111vl11m •lin•n• potrr"I "h1r lur,.
156 TuE IDEA O F NATURAL RIGHTS PROPERTY, NAT\JRAL RIGHT, ANO TI1E STATE OF NATURE 157

Dominion of temporal things was not introduced by primeval natural of course that property could also be owned by specific communities.
la"". understood as the law common to all animals . . . nor by the law of There was community of property for a time after Eve was created; the
nations, nor by the law of kings or emperors, but by God who was and is primitive Christian community at Jerusalem owned property in common;
the lord of those things.75
and the church over which john presided included innumerable property-
John still had to account for the words of Quo iure which stated ex- owning corporations. But individual ownership was the norm, the initial
plicitly that property was introduced by human law. He explained, as condition from which later forms of property were derived. Adam had
lnnoc~t IV had done.earlier, that human law established only the forms property before he shared ownership with Eve. The apostles and disciples
of action through which property claims could be pursued in court. Or had private possessions before they contributed their individual proper-
perhaps, John suggested-and here he was stretching his argument rather ties to the common pool. Things had to be possessed individually before
far-perhaps Augustine had never really meant what he wrote, but was common property could be created.
m~rely pu_tting forward his argument as a debating point in disputing The differences between Bonagratia and John XXII are evident. Bona-
with heretics.76 gratia believed that ius dominii, right of ownership, was derived from
Jotu:' finally turned to the central issue of the theological dispute over human law and that it could be renounced. The pope maintained that the
e~~gelical ~verty-whether Christ and the apostles owned anything, in- right to property was introduced by divine law and was inalienable (since
dividually or m common. In keeping with the whole preceding argument, all use of consumables involved ownership). But there are also significant
~e adopted th~ position most offensive to the Franciscans by asserting that, resemblances between the positions of the two adversaries. Both of them
~ ~e evangelical ~ay of life, there was not only common property but in- set out from a primeval condition of things, an original state of nature initi-
d1v1dual ownership. As God, Christ held universal dominion from all ated by God's first dealings with Adam. And, of course, each imagined a
~temity and as man from the moment of his conception. During his state o f nature consistent with his own position in the fourteenth-century
hfe on earth Christ also acquired particular things through the normal dispute. Both writers emphasized positive divine law and positive human
proc~ of purchase or gift. Jesus lived in a poor and humble fashion law; neither based his argument on a natural law discerned by human
m this world, not because he lacked dominion, but because he refused to reason and conscience. In this regard their arguments represent an im-
accept the revenues that were due to him. He was like a king of France poverishment of the tradition of discourse about natural law and natural
who, after traveling abroad, returned to his own country incognito and rights that had been growing up among jurists and theologians for morE.'
chose to live as a mendicant.77 than a century past. A major achievement of Ockham was to restore the
The apostles too owned property for which they could sue in court. idea of a rational natural law to the center of the argument about the origin
After the death of Christ, the disciples in the gentile churches continued to of property.
own private property. The apostles and disciples at Jerusalem did indeed
establish a community of goods, but what they shared was common own- 0CKHAM ON PROPERTY
ership, not just use of fact as the Franciscans maintained. Also, as John
had earlier explained, when portions of food were assigned to the needy A noted writer on religious experience in the modem world, Simone
members of the community, each became the owner of his own portion.78 Weil, maintained that "private property is a vital need of the soul.,,.,., Pope
Th~ugh ~e ~~ole course of ~ohn's argument there was a persistent john XXII would probably have agreed; he certainly held that property
emphasIS on md1v1dual ownership as a normal and rightful pattern of was a vital need of the body. Ockham thought otherwise. His wholt•
human conduct going back to the very beginning of the human race and to purpose in attacking John XXU was to uphold the thesis that Christ and
the state of affairs that God had established then. The pope acknowledged the apostles had renounced all property "individually and in common,"
retaining for themselves only "simple use of fact," and that, accordingly,
75. Ibid., 441. On Locke's argument from God as maker see J. Tully, A Discou~ on Prop- the Franciscans were following a truly e vangelical way of life by adopting
erty (Cambridge, 1980), 36-38. the same rules of conduct.
76. Ibid., #Quo iurt . .. loquitur enim de iure agendi in iudicio, cuius formulas civil<' ius
et n on aliud introduxit ... Vel potest d ici, quod AuRu"tinu~ ho<.· clk ...bnt rum h11l'rc>licis dis·
putando, non quod hoc pro Vl'ritate t<'fWWI. . ·· ' 7<1. S. Mil<.-s, <.'ti., Sittrrmr Wril 1\11 1\1111111/oxv (l.ontlon, 191!6), IJ5. But Wc•il ,\Ilk>wruh'. In
.inolh<'r conIt»<I, .. Rixht" h1w<' 1111 clh<'< I • • ttlll<'• llnn wilh lov<.' .. . th<.' nnlion ur rl1thlii I•
77. Ibid., 442- 43.
.1lic•n h• 1111' <1>ri,.li1111 in~plr11lh111 I ''"' •"""'•I l11111K""' SI l'ranc-h1 of A""l"I l"llo.ln~ 111>11111
78. Ibid., 44'.l - 47, 414.
rl1thl" .. (I{\)
158 THE IDEA OF NATURAL R IGHTS PROPERTY, NATURAL RIGHT, AND THE STATE OF NATURE 159

From the beginning of the controversy, the theological issue had been ence to the dominion of Adam did not prove that Eve was actually created
complicated by John XXII's juristic argument that there could be no use of later. Often, Ockham noted, the order of scriptural narrative does not con-
consumables without ownership. This implied that the right to property form to the chronological order of events.81
had always existed and could never be renounced. (1f to eat things is to Ockham's next argument was more subtle. Even if we grant that
uwn them, lllt!ll must alwdy~ ~ uw11el~.) Uu1lJ~l..ilia argucJ thal lite hdu- Adam received dominion before the formation of Eve, he wrote, it would
ciscans had returned to an original state of innocence when use without not follow from this that he acquired such dominion for himself as a single
ownership existed. John responded with his argument about Adam's sole individual. His dominion was granted "for himself and the wife to be
dominion. Both Bonagratia and John treated the life of Adam before the formed from him and for all their progeny." 111 (This was the same reply
Fall as exemplifying a paradigmatic pattern of conduct that humans of that Locke would make to Filmer's revived Adamite theory in a later age.)
their own age could emulate. The result of all this was that, when Ockham As for John XXII's argument that there could be no common dominion
took up the argument, he could defend the Franciscan teaching on evan- when there was no plurality of persons, Ockham quoted the canonistic
gelical poverty only by undertaking a far-ranging discussion of property text (going back to Huguccio) that communis could mean communican~a
in relation to divine law, human law, natural law, and natural rights. His ("common, that is to be shared"). Adam's dominion was common in thls
intention it seems, was to refute John XXII while avoiding some of the ec- sense, because whatever was given to him was given to be shared with
centricities that had crept into the Franciscan position since the work of Eve.83 Ockham also introduced here the legal doctrine that the rights of
Bonagratia. To do this, he needed to disprove john's assertion that Adam a corporation could persist in a single member. If all the monks in a
at first held individual property as sole owner of the world and that later, monastery died save one, then de facto he would hold the property of the
after the creation of Eve, Adam and Eve owned property in common. A community, and so too would the first monk in a newly founded monas-
Franciscan apologist was reluctant to concede that either individual prop- tery. But in neither case did the individual monk have exclusive owner-
erty or common ownership was of direct divine institution. Then Ockham ship. Rather, he held on behalf of a monastic community; as soon as other
had to show how a right to acquire property could have arisen, how the monks joined him they too would share by right in the property that
right could be renounced, and finally how the existing division of prop- belonged to the corporate whole.84
erty had come about in the course of human history. Earlier in the dispute Ockham was apparently fond of the argument about a solitary monk
discussion of these questions had turned on a few crucial texts of the De- functioning as a k ind of corporation sole, and he returned to it later in the
cretum and Ockham also had to rely primarily on them. But these texts Opus nonaginta dierum (OND) and again in the Breviloquium.85 But the anal-
had been exhaustively discussed by an earlier generation of canonists. So ogy he drew was not an exact one. A community of monks held property
Ockham did not produce an entirely new theory of property; rather he in common; Ockham wanted to argue that Adam and Eve had no property
adapted from the earlier tradition, or perhaps reinvented, the interpreta- at all, either individual or common, in the state of innocence o r immedi-
tions that best suited his own Franciscan argument. ately after the first sin.
In addressing John XXIJ's assertion that Adam was at first the indi- In discussing this issue Ockham presented his most decisive argu-
vidual owner of the whole world, Ockham deployed two lines of ar- ments against John XXII's depiction of the state of innocence. John argued
gument. The simpler one maintained that the key words of God, "Have that Dilectissimis equated the state of the apostles with the state of inno-
dominion . .." were not spoken to Adam alone but to Adam and Eve cence; but, according to the pope, the apostles held property in common
together; so whatever dominion was conveyed by them was held by and so, correspondingly, Adam and Eve before the Fall also had all thi~gs
the two in common. (Later Ockham would argue that this dominion was in common "as regards dominion of property." Ockham responded with
not a property right.) The word Dominamini was a plural form, Ockham two lines of argument, an analysis of the different meanings of the word,
noted. Moreover, it was part of a blessing that began with the words "In- dominium and a denial that the apostles, or anyone else, had ever returned
crease and multiply." And Adam could not have multiplied the human
race all by himself without a wife to help; so the words of the blessing 81. OND, 490.
must have been spoken to Eve as well.80 As for the tt>xt of Ecclcsiasticus on 82. OND, 488, " ... illud d11mlnl11m nnn fuil llibi datum p rose sola, !It'd pm !It' t'I mulirrr
which John relied, the fact that Eve was first mt•ntiorn•<i only t1ft('r a l'C'fer- formand<1 dl' i~l al" pni 1m111lh11• pn•trrl" ron mtl1•m."
HJ. ONf>, 411'1, ~ . •. 1•1 l1IC'u " """"'""lull, ho1· ""' <'c>mmunicandum."
114. ONfl, 4147.
llO. Opus nonn.~intn tfir rnm re lN! lJ, 4H7 llr.. llNI>. 4HQ, f•hl , lltt"l'll1~/llll1Pfl, I I'\
160 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PRO PERTY, NATURAL R IGHT, AND THE STATE OF NATURE 161

to a state of innocence. In a series of definitions at the beginning of the and Eve. Only the use of them was separate; most probably they would
OND Ockham had pointed out that dominium could mean (among other not have wanted to own their tunics individually. And even if they did
things) a power of ruling or a power of owning.86 Now he insisted that the own the garments that God gave them as private possessions, Ockham
dominion given to Adam and Eve was not a property right but "a rational persisted, they had earlier made for themselves girdles of fig leaves; so the
power of ruling and governing." When God said "Have dominion over first institut1on of property would still have been by human initiative.92
the fishes of the sea and the birds of the air," he was conferring a "perfect Ockham's argument grows a little crotchety here, but the Franciscan was
power" to rule all living creatures. They were under Adam's sway; they determined to refute by all possible means the assertion of John XXII thal
had no power to resist him or do violence to him.87 But, Ockham noted, private property was first instituted by God's own command and to deny
scripture never referred to property when discussing the dominion of our the kind of sanctification of property implied by this teaching.
first parents.a! The principal error of John XXll was to suppose that the do- According to Ockham's account, instead of endowing Adam and Eve
minion granted to them was the same as the ownership of worldly goods with property, God gave them a power of using certain things when he as-
that came to exist later. The pope was also wrong in supposing that Dilec- signed to them herbs and fruit-bearing trees for their food.93 But this "licit
tissimis referred to common ownership in the period before the Fall.89 In power of using"-that Ockham elsewhere referred to as an inalienable
fact, although Adam and Eve had a kind of common dominion (a power of natural right 94-was not a right of ownership.95 Ockham also held that
ruling) they had no common property: the power of using was different from the original dominion God con-
ferred on Adam and Eve through which they could rule other creatures.
Although it may be conceded in one sense that our first parents had do-
minion of temporal things in the state of innocence, it is not conceded
This was proved by the example of the animals. They too were given a
that they had property in temporal things because this word "dominion" power of using things as food but they were not granted any dominion.
has meanings that "property" does not have.90 Also, the power of using things always persisted among humans, even
though the original dominion was lost by sin.96
If God did not institute property in the form of common ownership, This last point can serve to introduce another major theme that Ock-
still less, according to Ockham, did he confer individual possessions on ham developed in his response to the pope's depiction of the original
Adam and Eve, even after the Fall. John XXII argued t.h at God made an age of innocence. Ockham not only criticized the details of John's ar-
individual grant to Adam when he said "In the sweat of your brow you gument; he also rejected the whole underlying supposition that the pri-
shall eat your bread." But it was highly improbable, Ockham argued, that mordial state of affairs was normative for all time. Since Ockham believed
Adam would have wanted to own his bread separately from Eve, given that he could demonstrate from scripture and from a correct interpretation
the bond of marriage and the love and concord that existed between of Difeclissimis that no property existed in the state of innocence he might
them.91 It was the same with the "tunics of skins" that God gave to Adam have been content to accept this supposition as Bonagratia had accepted
it. But in fact Ockham chose to attack this part of the pope's argument too.
86. ONO, 305-308.
The Franciscan champion had set himself the task of responding, word
87. ONO, 432, " ... dominium omnium temporalium datum primis parentibus fuit potes-
tas rationabiliter regendi et gubemandi temporalia absque eorum resistentia violentia . ..
for word and blow by blow, to every argument put forward in Quia vir
talis perfecta potestas regendi et disponendi temporalia fuit dominium, quod datum fuit reprobus; so he too had to write at length about Adam and Eve and the age
primis parentibus." of innocence. But Ockham did not argue that the apostles or the Francis-
88. OND, 436, " ... nee unquam de proprietate loquitur scriptura, cum loquitur de domi-
nio primorum parentum ante peccatum.* Oclcham here ilJustrated the meaning of domin- 92. ONO, 657, " Ergo si pelliciae et res aliae fuerunt divisae inter eos quuad dominium.
ium as a power to rule from another scriptural text. When w e read in Proverbs 16.32, " Isle sequitur quod perizomata fuerunt divisa inter eos quoad dominium; et non ex speci,,li pr;w·
dominatur animo suo,* it does not mean that a man owns his spirit but that he rules his cepto divino, sed vo luntate humana.·
spirit. Ockham did not use the argument that an individual had a property right in his 93 OND. 432, "Praeter istud autem dominium fuit data ipsis et animantihus h•rr,11·
own person, presumably because he wanted lo argue that the Franciscans had no pmpt>rty pol~t.ls ut<'ndi quibusdam rebus detPrminalis.. .. "
right at all. 94. OND. 562, " . .. iuri utt'ndi naturnli nulli rt'nuntiart' liC<'t." Simil<lr expn'"!li1i1m!O ill :t\4,
89. John XXll's interpretation of Dileclissimis was di5CUSSE'd in d<'lail ill OND, 436- 40, ssn. 561 , 564. sn.
492-94. 45. C>NTJ, 4112-·9:\. <'k·khnm "~pl11i11r.,l l11•1t• lh.ll tlw only point of pur!!ulng the• 11rg11ntNll
~- OND, 485. Tile same argument occurs at 4..16- 37, 4112, 4"4. .11><mt l\di'lm irnd 1-:vr wA.• to •lmw th"t ..,...,. nt 111<'1" 1'11111<1 t'l<ii<t without c•wm•ri•hip.
'11 . ONO, 656, "Stanlt' Mlim .1 mon• 1•l 1~11wor.ti.1 inlrr lpio.••. noon v i.l1•t11r 1t1101l 1trh1..-nml •lfl (IN/ I, 41:1. "' . 111,, J'" l•••lot•, 111,.11.11 '" '""' "I .1.,mtnl11m .. 1't'M1111lr Uln domlntn, 111111
aliqua r.ttiom• movt•rl ad Jlvh\,,111l11m h•111pornli11 inlt'f "" 'I"'""'•l11mh1l11m """ pmrri· .,.,.,,wit llllllll• f'""°"'''" nh•mll 11111"1111111•11h·~l 11'11111 ,, lult .,111~ 11nlmnllh11• 111111•110 non
1•"1h•n>." s,.,. 111110 CIN/> hhil lull •l 11h11n iluml11111111 ••
162 THE IDEA OF NATURAi RIGHTS PROPERTY, N ATURAL RIGHT, AND THE STATE OF NATURE 163

cans had returned to the prelapsarian state of humankind. Both John XXII ing on Dilectissimis, John XXII argued that, since the first division of things
and Bonagratia in their djfferent ways maintained this position. Ockham produced individual ownerships, what was divided must earlier have
differed from both of them. Understandably though, he did not mention been common property. Ockham responded by introducing the juristic
the view of his Franciscan confrere, but preferred to concentrate his attack concept of res nullius. After their first sin, Adam and Eve still did not own
on the pope. any property individually or in common; but, Ockham argued, they did
John XXII was arguing frivolously and using words equivocally, then have a power of appropriating things because ''what belongs to no
Od<llam complained, when he argued from Dilectissimis that the apostles one is conceded to the occupier." This power of acquiring "what is taken
had exercised the same kind of dominion that Adam did in a state of inno- by land, sea or air" was not a form of common ownership because, if it had
cence.97 Dilectissimis did not "equiparate" the state of the apostles with the been, the consent of the community would have been required for any act
original state of innocence as John maintained; it only "compared" them. of acquisition. 100
The kind of dominion that God instituted in the beginning had nothing to Ockham perhaps had in mind here the kind of problems about first ac-
do with existing rights to property; it was a once and for all phenomenon, quisition that would be discussed in detail by later natural rights theorists.
never repeated in the history of humankind.911 The dominion of Adam was But his immediate purpose was to defend the view that neither common
different from any dominion subsequently established among humans. ownership nor individual ownership was instituted by divine command.
The apostles did not recover this dominion or return to the state of primor- One must always remember that the Franciscans claimed to have given up
dial innocence, for the natural defects of human nature were not repaired all property "individually and in common." However tortuous Ockham's
in them, and they were not given any supernatural power to command arguments became this was always the position he was seeking to defend.
all living creatures.99 For Ockharn there had been no going back to the He emphasized therefore that a situation where the whole world was in
primeval condition of humankind. bonis nullius could not properly be described as a state of common owner-
If either of the varieties of primitivism presented by Bonagratia and ship. This was the same argument that Pufendorf would make centuries
John XXII had prevailed, argument about the right to property would have later when he distinguished between "negative community" and "positive
been drawn into a sort of scriptural cul-de-sac. Everything would depend community" in a state of nature. Ockham, of course, was pursuing a dif-
upon which idiosyncratic interpretation of Genesis an author chose to ferent agenda; but the sharp distinction that he introduced here between a
adopt. This kind of argument did indeed persist. Even in the seventeenth power to appropriate and an actual right of ownership was central to some
century Filmer and Selden were still using variations of it. Ockham chose of the later rights theories.
to pursue a different and more promising course. Having proved to his Ockham went on to argue that, even if we do call the power of appro-
own satisfaction that private property did not originate in divine law, priating a kind of common dominion, using the term in a loose sense, still
Ockham still had to explain how it actually had come to exist. Here the this power did not exist in the state of innocence.101 This led on to a further
argument took a paradoxical tum. John XXII and Bonagratia were both
trained canonists, but it was Ockham, a philosopher and theologian, who
JOO. OND, 434-35, "Nam nulli possunt inter se dividere aliqua bona q uood dislin<·t,1
returned to the well-worn categories of juristic thought and to the kind of dominia, nisi prius habeant dominium commune in dividendis ... Ad hoc dicunt illli
historical explanation that we can find in the Decretum and its glosses in impugnatores quod primi parentes post peccatum non habuerunt do minium commu1w
order to account for the development of property. As we saw, in comment- omnium temporalium proprie loquendo de dominio, sed habebant potestatem appropriancli
s ibi et etiam acquirendi commune dominium; quia quae in nullius bonis sunt, ocrup.1nti
conceduntur. Et ideo ilia potestas non fuit proprie dominium commune: sicut nee mo.lo
97. OND, 431, " . .. non solum eronee, sed etiam cavi!lose et sub vocum multiplicitate potestas appropriandi seu acquirendi ilia, quae caelo, terra marique capiuntur, no n rsl pm·
procedit. . .. "; 434, " Dominium ergo quod fuit apostolorum ... non fuit tale dominium, prie dominium commune, quia si esset proprie commune d ominium, nullus dd>t'n•! ~il>i
quale fuit dominium primorum parentum." appropriare aliqua ipsorum absque communila tis consensu." Ockham wa~ apparently quol
98. ONO, 436, "... Clemens comparat et non aequiparat ... Quia nunquam aliqui mor- ing here from Dist. I c.7 of the D«rtlum which referred to things !a ken ~by air, land, amt,...., ..
tales habuerunt tale dominium temporalium, quale habuerunt primi parentes in statu .1nd from the O rdinary GIO!>..( hert• which cited the Roman law doctrine of res nulliu.<. For olh..r
innocentiae"; 493, "Dominium autem quod habuerunt primi parenles in slatu innocentiae. rdercnces tn goods in boni~ 11111/iu.< l't't' (>NP, :n'.l, 4'.lR.
est totaJiter alterius rationis ab isto do minio... ." i l IOI . ONV, 4'.l.'i, " El itlt•u "'' mnninn rnnn...t.1tur quod ista polN1!11s appmprinndi lull
99. OND, 434, " . .. natura in eis quantum ad defectu.~ llillumh•K full m ltlimt• rt•parata .. .
(dominium) supematurale non fuit ill illl~ . . . ••rgo non h.-h1ll'mn! t"I,. <lomlnlum q uoit'
habuenmt pri ml parentt'l'."
."'
l ('ommnnt' dominium. tlinml l~!I h11p111(1"1l11w" 'I""'' I.lit' ilominium non fult'.•rl In !!lnlu in
n1)(·1•11li.w, ~i primi l"1rr11t.... 11n11111•1 1~•1M·111 . •tnltt lhi 11nr1 fui~M·I p<•h'!ll•,~ o1pprnprl.uidl ·· S.-.-
.11-.14:1~. 4'0
164 TuE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PROP£RTY, NATIJRAL R IGHT, AND THE STATE OF NAnJRE 165

question that John XXIT had already raised. Where then did this power of troducing a concept of "suppositious" natural law that came into play
acquiring property come from? According to the pope it came directly after property had been introduced and of natural rights associated with
from God. Ockham on the other hand emphasized human agency; his this law that could be renounced voluntarily, but that could also be as-
answer was that the power of appropriating came from human nature serted against the claims of an absolutist ruler.
in its fallen condition and from human reason. Among sinful men a "dic- At a later point in the OND, Ockham acknowledged that private prop-
tate of reason" indicated that it was expedient for persons to appropri- erty was introduced through human laws ''by command or permission of
ate things for themselves unless, Ockham added, anyone had volun- God." 106 And presumably the original power of acquisition that existed
tarily deprived himself of this power (as the Franciscans claimed to have before property was instituted must have come from God, at least as a per-
done).10'Z Later on, commenting on the Ordinary Gloss to Dilectissimis, Ock- mission that had not been granted before. The idea of a permissive law
ham noted that the introduction of property was in accordance with the seems implicit in Ockham's argument; but he did not choose to explore
natural equity that existed among fallen humanity.103 this theme. When Ockham returned to the point in the Breviloquium he was
There is perhaps some equivocation in Ockham's language here. willing to acknowledge a divine origin of the right to acquire property; but
Although the power to appropriate was a "dictate of reason" and in accord in the OND it suited his purpose better to emphasize Gratian's straight-
with natural equity, Ockham did not call this power a natural right or a forward view that property had its origin in human law or custom to-
product of natural law. Yet, in other parts of the OND, he defined a natural gether with the text of Quo iure, that supported this opinion. As.a .Francis-
right precisely as a power consonant with right reason and natural law as can apologist Ockham wanted to argue for a merely hum~ o?gm of th.e
equity in accord with right reason.104 The logic of the language suggests right to property so that he could effectively defend the friar s renunci-
that the acquisition of property was a natural right in accord with natural ation of the right.
law. But Ockham seems to have avoided this conclusion. With his eyes Accordingly, in refuting John XXJI's interpretation of Quo iure, Ock-
fixed always on the problem of Franciscan poverty he wanted above all to ham persistently emphasized voluntary human agreements as the source
distinguish between a power of appropriation that could be relinquished of particular property rights. Arguing from Quo iure's assertion that "We
voluntarily and a natural right of using things that could never be re- have divine law in scripture," the pope had given various examples of pri-
nounced: vate ownership in biblical texts and concluded from them that property
It is licit to renounce property and the power of appropriating but no one
was established by divine law. But Ockham responded with another text
may renounce the natural right of using. 1~ from the Decrelum. "Natural law is contained in the law (of the Old Testa-
ment) and the gospel but not everything in the law and the gospel is
To have called the power of appropriating also a natural right would natural law." •07 It was the same with divine law, Ockham argued. Many
merely have confused the argument. In Ockham's later work, when he texts of scripture referring to ownership were not precepts of divine or
moved to broader issues of political theory, he modified his stance by in- natural law but simply accounts of transactions among humans. Cain and
Abel, for instance, made the first division of property by mutual agree-
102. OND, 435, " Et si quaeratur unde ergo habuerunt primi parentes talem potestatem ment, not by divine command. Later on similar divisions were madt>
appropriandi res temporales, quam non habuerunt ante peccatum, dicunt isti quod ha- by the sons of Noah and by Abraham and Lot. But this was all done by
buerunt illam potestatem ex natura corrupta. Quia ex dictamine rationis naturalis con- human will and human regulation.108 Also, Jacob and other patriarchs ac-
vincitur quod expedit posse peccantibus quod etiam habeant potestatem appropriandi sib i, quired great possessions by their own labor and industry, and so did many
nisi aliqui eorum eadem potestate sponte se privent, ita quod nullus debet in principio cogi
talem potestatem dimittere."
103. ONO, 669. The gloss to Di1ectissimis suggested that property could have been intro- 106. OND. 664, " Ergo n11//11s rn de ill11r11m dominio nisi de trolunt11tt Ori, potuit (lrdi1111rr:
duced through "a custom of the law of nations contrary to natural equity." Ockham Verum est quod omnia fiunt de voluntate Dei iubente vel permittente... . For the rnlhn <llf-
H

explained that such a custom would be contrary to the natural equity that existed in a state ferent treatment of this question in the Brroiloquium and for the concept of "suppo.'lili111111..
of innocence and to the natural equity that would have existed if men had always lived ac- natural law, see below, 172-7.\, 178 - 79.
cording to reason, but it was not contrary to the natural equity that actually exisl<'d among
men prone to dissension and wrongdoing. The argument here lK't!ms to •mlicipate OckMm's . 107. OND. 661, citing ni~UI I""'' c 1.
Ill!\. ONO, 661, •· . .. Al>rnh11m ,., l.olh pmpri01 01uctoritate. ut habt'lur <;c-n1•11l11 xiii.
well-known discussion of three types of natural law in Di11/~11s, :l.2.:l.6. St"'t' bt'low, 177. re~lorn>!! intc>r ~l' divi11i11114• vhll"nlur"; ft'l7 , •· mullnrum wrum dl~tlocta domlnllt t•I d lvl'n1b1
104. O NO, 574, 579. ~above•, 128. ff'mpnrlh1t'I fut•runl lntwcl11d11 I l1H· 1•11t..1 "l"'rlt• 111• cllvl~lnnt• h1( IR lntrr 11111111 flllorum

J
105. ONO, .562. NtH• <jtl•lt" .l lvl:do v11l1111t.. 1r l'I 111111111•1111111• hwn111111 lull ln<"tn.H
166 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PROPERTY, NATURAL RIGHT, AND TiiE STATE Of NATURE 167

pagans mentioned in scripture.109 The texts quoted by John XXII proved in this way Ockham drew the whole discussion about the origin of prop-
only that some grants of property had been made directly by God, some- erty away from the idea of a state of nature understood as a primeval
thing that everyone conceded; they did not prove that property was first condition of things in order to emphasize instead the permanent nature of
instituted by divine command. Moreover, since the preaching of the human beings as creatures endowed with reason and free will
gospel, no such divine grants had been made; in Ockham's day all prop- Ockham's arguments may remind us of the earlier canonistic com-
erty existed by human law. 110 There remained the problem that, whereas mentaries on Quo iure and Dilectissimis that also emphasized reason and
Quo iure attributed the origin of property to the laws of kings, John xxn rational choice. Ockham did not reproduce consistently the view of any
had given many examples of property existing before there were any kings particular Decretist; but much of his argument was in accord with main-
and had concluded that only the forms of legal action were instituted by stream canonistic thought. For the Decretists as for Ockham, the use of all
human law, not property itself. Ockham had no interest in defending a things was at first shared in common. But, as Rufinus pointed out, this
specifically royal origin of private property. He wanted only to prove that state of affairs was not normative for the future; according to various com-
the origin was not divine. And indeed his many references to early pacts mentators on Dilectissimis, it had passed away after Adam's primal sin.
among individuals suggest that, for him, the origin was conventional but After the Fall there was a time when the whole world was res nullius, open
pre-political. to occupation. In these circumstances the "judgment of reason" (Huguc-
Ockham argued, therefore, that in Quo iure Augustine was refer- cio) or the "dictate of reason" (Ockham) indicated that individual property
ring only to the circumstances of his own day when laws were indeed could be acquired. The actual division of things came about through an ac-
commonly made by kings. In earlier times, Ockham noted, there had been cumulation of agreements and customs and laws.
many human laws that were not royal enactments. According to a text One can consider the arguments of the OND as a step in the evolution
of Isidore in the Decretum any people could make laws for itself, and of Ockham's own political thought or, in a broader context, as a contri-
many had done so. 111 The Romans, for instance, held property by human bution to the overall development of theories on property and natural
law before they had kings. Again, many lesser rulers apart from kings- rights.•u When we read Ockham after studying earlier canonistic texts on
dukes, counts, barons, and other secular princes-<ould establish individ- the origin of property there is sometimes a feeling of deja vu. If we turn
ual properties and had done so at various times. finally to the classical natural rights theories of the seventeenth century we
Summing up his argument on the origin of property, Ockham distin- can experience a sense of "deja vu all over again." Filmer turned back to
guished three epochs of human history. There was a time before sin when the first chapters of Gratian's Decretum in criticizing Grotius's theory of
our first parents had no property but a power of using things; then there natural law.114 Grotius himself, in his early work De jure praedne, cited the
was a middle time after sin but before the division of things when they decretals of Nicholas Ill and John XXII on Franciscan poverty; then he
had a power of appropriation; and finally a time after division was made observed that the common "use of fact" that existed at the beginning of
when individual possessions came to exist.112 In Ockham's view property the human race could not properly be called dominium.115 This was a crucial
emerged during this third epoch in a historical process that involved a distinction for Ockham too. Grotius went on to argue that, as regards
long series of voluntary arrangements among humans--compacts, cus- consumables, "a certain kind of ownership is inseparable from use," and
toms, the laws that peoples made for themselves, and finally the laws of made this the starting point of his first theory of property. Selden and thm
kings and other rulers. But the foundation that made the whole process Filmer reintroduced the theory of Adam's sole dominion. Pufendorf and
legitimate was natural equity and the "dictate of reason" indicating that
private property was a fitting arrangement for fallen humanity. By arguing
113. Janet Coleman has emphasized, quite properly, the continuing influence of ( l{-k
ham's older contemporary, John of Paris, in this area. But John offered only a brief rnmnwnl
109. OND, 659, "Iacob etiam per laborem suam et industriam multa acquisivit . . . c>t d<' on the o rigin of the right to property; Ockham discussed the issue in inlrkall" d1"t11ll. S.-.•
paganis multis posset per scripturam copiose probari." J. Cole m an, "Dominium in Thirteenth and Fo urteenth-Century Politica l Th(111p;ht 111111 lb
110. OND, 657. Sc-vt>ntrenth-Century H <'ir.i: John of l'.uis and Locke," Politico/ Studi~ 33 (19HS): 7J IClll.
111. OND, 661, citing Dist. 1 c~8. 114. ). I~ Sorrwrvillt•, rel , 1'11triairlu1111111 Ollirr Writings (Cambridge, 1991), 2l'N.
112. OND, 439, NEt ita fuit triplex te mpus : scilicet ante pt>cc.1t11m ... post pt>cc.1tum 1•t 11 ~. R.V.I >. M.1p;o ffl11, lnm• , "/11r frrf'1l11m n{ ll1r St'ns (Nrw York, 1q16), 22-24 <:roliu~ r'
ante d ivisionem rerum; et in ilia tempore habul'runt pot~lntt•m <livlth•ndi ••I apprnpri;mc\i plairwJ that formrrly .i..,,,111/um 111"11111 " •• t;i1 ·11l111~ tum iniust.1 utC'ndi rt' t'tm11nu11I, 1111r111
sibi res . .. Tertium te mpus foil poiit tlivi~ionem n•rum. ••I tum· llH...lwrunt 1lu1nlnin proprl.1
q11alii1 nunc :<uni mun~lannn.un . "
u~11111 Sdml.1Nlid~ vl1n1111 r•I '"'ti""" Im 1.-· lwllh .i r1'11•n•11n• lo Nkholn~ Ill'•/. rnl), hut In
h i" uw111"1y, h1• ,·,.11U1111rol, lhP w1111l 11•l1•111'<I 111 pt lVAlr propnty
168 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS PROPEIITY, NAlllRAL RIGHT, AND THE STATE OF NATIJRE 169

Locke undertook to refute it, and in doing so deployed some of the same In Ockham's later writings his interest shifted from the technical
arguments that Ockham had used earlier. Pufendorf expressed a hearty problems of Franciscan poverty to the broader political issues involved in
contempt for aU medieval thought; yet he constructed a theory of property the struggle between John XXll and Lewis of Bavaria; but some ways of
remarkably Jike that of the fourteenth-century Franciscan. Pufendorf could arguing that first appeared in the OND persisted in the later works. In
almost have been quoting Ockharn when he wrote, "the right of Adam to particular, the idea of natural rights, deployed in the OND only to defend
things was different from that dominion which is now established among a natural right of using the things necessary to sustain life, proved capable
men," or, "brute creatures use and consume things ... although no domin- of significant extension when it was applied to wider problems of ecclesi-
ion is recognized among them," or, "the fact that right reason suggested ology and political thought.
the introduction of separate dominions does not prevent them from going
back to a human pact," or, "God himself conferred . . . only .. . the power of
taking and possessing ... For the power to acquire some right and the
right itself . .. are different things." 116
I do not suppose that any of these seventeenth-century authors had
plowed his way through the Opus nonaginta dierum (though Suarez, who
was a common source for early modem writers on political theory, per-
haps had). There had been a long process of transmission through the
theological and juristic writings of the late medieval period and especially
through the Spanish scholastics of the sixteenth century. The important
point in any case is not the occasional verbal similarities but the continued
preoccupation with the same set of problems. AU the great natural rights
theorists assumed that God had at first granted the whole world to the
human race in common. They did not seek a return to this primordial
situation. (Proudhon indeed criticized Grotius for not doing so. 117 ) Their
problem rather was to explain and justify the fact of individuation. The
persistent engagement of seventeenth-century writers with this issue has
sometimes been seen as a major shift away from medieval attitudes
toward modem ones. In a classic old article on the development of prop-
erty Richard McKeon wrote that discussion in the Middle Ages "turned
exclusively about the problem of use"; then he contrasted this approach
with that of Grotius and his successors for whom the dominant concern
became "the problem of acquisition." McKeon found in this transition "the
most striking mark of the modem period of the discussion." 118 But his
argument is only partly true. Medieval writers were certainly concerned
about the right use of property. But the problem of first acquisition had
already surfaced in the twelfth century among canonists faced by the
tangled texts of Gratian's Decretum, and it became an issue of central im-
portance in the fourteenth-century Franciscan dispute.

116. S. Pufendorf, ~ju~ nat11rae ti genti11m lilTri octo, trans., C. H. Oldfather and W. A.
Oldfather (Oxford, 1934), 4.4.3, 535; 4 .4.4, 536; 4.4.4, 537; 4.4 .10, 548.
117. D. R. Kelley and B. G. Smith, eds., What ls Property? (Cambridge, 1994), 45.
118. R. McKeon, 'The Development of the Concept of Propt>rty in Political Philosophy,~
Ethics 48 (1938); '1.9'1- 366 at 344.
- - - -- - ·-· ---- - ·--------
Ocl<HAM: RIGHTS AND SOME PROBLEMS OF POUTICAL THOUGHT 171

rights theory concerned the origins of jurisdiction and the limits of ruling
authority. The discussion of both issues led Ockham to further reflections
on property rights in relation to human government.

ORIGINS OF JURISDICTION

Ever since Augustine, the existence of private property and of coer-


cive government had been seen as interrelated aspects of the human con-
dition; both represented departures from an original idyllic state of affairs
and both were occasioned by original sin. In medieval arguments about
§EVEN the right to property, this way of thinking was often exemplified in dis-
cussions on the origin of dominion (dominium). Medieval authors com-
monly assumed that dominion was a right. They wrote freely of a ius do-
minii (though this was an unclassical usage). Moreover they used the word
OCKHAM: RIGHTS AND SOME PROBLEMS dominium to mean both jurisdiction and ownership-a right to rule and a
OF POLITICAL THOUGHT right to own. So discussions on the origin of dominium typically t.r eated
both rights as powers that sprang from a common source, either directly
from God or from the pope, or from natural law, or from human law.
We find the usual juxtaposition of arguments about the right to in-
stitute a government and the right to acquire property also in Ockham.

W hen Ockham wrote the Opus nonaginta dierum (OND), he was


wholly preoccupied with the problems of Fr~nciscan pover~y: In
his later works he turned to broader issues of ecdes1ology a~d political
theory. For instance, Ockham wrote extensively, almost obsess1v~ly, about
De Lagarde indeed suggested that Ockham explained the origin of gov-
ernment by "purely and simply" transposing his earlier theory of property
to this new subject matter.• But this seems an oversimplification. Ock-
ham had different ends in view when he discussed the two themes. When
the problem of papal heresy; and he was also much concerned wit~ d~fin­ Ockham developed his first theory of property in the OND he was inter-
ing the right relationship between spiritual and temporal power. His views ested only in defending the doctrine of Franciscan poverty; this caused
on these questions were not radically novel. Al~eady before 1200.~re­ him to reject the idea that property was instituted directly by God. When
tists like Huguccio had written in intricate detail abou~ the d~os1tion of he wrote on the origin of government he was concerned primarily to argue
a heretical or criminal pope and had presented a dualist doctnne of em- that the emperor did not receive his power from the pope, but rather "from
pire and papacy that was substantially similar to Ockham's. Then, _aro~d God through the people." It suited this argument to assert that the power
1300 similar ideas had been expressed in the work of John of Pans-hke of the people to institute a ruler was conferred by a direct divine grant. In
Ockham a theologian writing on what we should call political theory. drawing parallels between the right to acquire property and the right to in-
These aspects of Ockham's thought are well known, _and I .have ~ade stitute government Ockham therefore had to adapt, perhaps compromi~.
no attempt to consider them once again in the following discussion. I his first theory of property to make it fit the new argument. Ockham'11
want only to review some key passages in which t~e conc~pt ~fa natural handling of this theme shows how his political thinking was sometimes
ri ht, first presented in the OND, was taken up a~am, applied m new con- shaped more by merely tactical considerations than by any underlying
te~ts, and assigned a role of central importance i~ a complex structure of metaphysical principles. It is also interesting because, in pursuing his nr·
political thought. Here again it will be helpful, 1~ order to unde_rstand gument, Ockham was led to reflect again on the role of human reason in
Ockham's distinctive contribution, to compare his arguments with the discerning God's purposes for humankind.
canonistic sources on which he often relied. As Stephen McCrade note~,
1. 5<>e Grorges de l.agardt', 1.n 1111/"""",.,.,,,. I" r.</Jril lalquea11 dklin du mc1yrt1"·fl"· 5 vol..., 2nd
ham's conn•ption of ri~hts, Wt.> m •t•d to h. L'ar. m
to und erstand fully Ock · .. .. ed. (Paris, 1956- 70), 5:2141. w. SIUmt'r ...w tlw lll<"<>ry or pm~rty In !ht• flm•illllJlliltm ""II ..i.u1
mind "the important lc•gal Jinwnsion" of his pnht1l·i\I wntm~s._ In thc·st> fi<-.1 linn or what W"!\ aln•" ''Y lmplh 111111111• I INI I ~;.... hi" l ' ri-mltm1 ""'' ,.,,,,.,.,.., (SIKnlllrlnK""·
lat<'r work.~ thl' prindpnl nmh•xls in whkh <kkh111n 1l1•v1•l11p1•1l Im; 11ahm1l

J
19117). 2211 2'1.

1711
172 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS 0cKHAM: RIG HTS AND 5oME PROBLEMS OF POLITICAL THOUGHT 173

Odcham's engagement with these issues is especially clear in the Brev- "both by right of creation and by right of conservation."5 As to when God
iloquium.2 He was concerned there to re~ute _the argument of_h~gh ~apalist made this special grant, Ockham found it mentioned, "at least by implica-
theologians like Giles of Rome, who mamtamed that all dom1mum, includ- tion," in the text of Ecclesiasticus where God gave power to Adam. ("And
ing licit jurisdiction and right of ownership, _w as derived from the po~ he gave him power over the things which are on earth" {Eccl. 17.3).) In the
and that, accordingly, it could not be held outside the church. As part of his OND Ockham had vigorously denied that God's original grant to Adam
response, Ockham asserted that "true ownership and true temporal juris- conferred any property individually or in common, or any power to ap-
diction" could exist even among infidels.3 To deny that infidels possessed propriate. But now he called on Aristotelian terminology to support a
rights led to all sorts of anomalies, he pointed out. A Christian would not different interpretation. After quoting the text of Ecclesiasticus he added at
be able to inherit any goods or rights that came ultimately from an infidel once, "That is, he gave him the power . . . that right reason declares to be
ancestor, for the ancestor had no rights to begin with. An infidel who necessary, expedient, fit, or useful, not only for living, but for living well.""
became a Christian would have no rights for he had none beforehand. Un- And right reason showed that, after sin, the power to appropriate things
baptized children of Christian parents could have no rights. Infidels would was something necessary and useful to the human race for living well.7
have no rights over their own children. All this was absurd, Ockham Ockham added, turning now to the main theme of the Breviloquium, that
insisted.• Then, to complete his argument, he went on to explain that the for a similar reason God had conferred on mankind directly "without
right to acquire property and the right to institute government were both any human ministry or cooperation," the power to establish rulers with
conferred on the whole human race (including infidels) in God's original temporal jurisdiction.8 The phrase, "without any human ministry," was
grant to Adam. presumably introduced to exclude the idea that temporal jurisdiction was
In the OND, Ockham had argued that the power to acquire property derived from the pope.
came from "nature," that is corrupt human nature, and from a "dictate of In the next stage of this argument Ockham asserted {without any
reason." Now he asserted that this power was instituted by divine law scriptural authority) that the twofold power to appropriate things and to
"through a special grant from God." He supported this assertion by re- institute rulers was conferred by God on the whole human race in the form
peating (though not deliberately one supposes) an argument that John of a precept, not just as something permitted. To safeguard the Francis-
XXU had used against the Franciscans, namely that human property must cans' claim that they could renounce the power of appropriating he added
have been derived originally from God, since all things belonged to him that the command was valid " for all time but not at all times." It obliged
strictly only in case of necessity. So the two-fold power could be renounced
2. I have used the edition of the Breviloquium in R. Scholz., Wilhelm von Ockham als po/iii· except in a situation of necessity.9 But in the OND Ockham had persistently
scher DtnW und stin Breuiloquium de principalu lyratmico (Stuttgart, 1944). 'There is an excellent
translation by John Kilcullen, A Short Discourst on Tyrannical Govnnment (Cambridge, 1992). 5. Ibid., 3.7, 126, " (stud autem dominium commune Ioli generi humano cum potestate
3. Breviloqui11m, 2.4, 118, " . .. apud infideles est verum dominium temporalium rerum et tali appropriandi temporalia foil introductum ex iure divino, quia eit speciali rollatione l>t•i,
vera iurisdiclio temporalis." Oclmam was here repeating a view classically formulat~ by cuius erant et sunt omnia tam iure creationis, quam iure conservationis. .. ."
Pope Innocent IV in his commentary on the Decrtfals (X.3 .34.8). Ockham, however, did not 6. Ibid ..• 3.7, 127, "De potestate vero appropriandi res temporales habetur saltem im-
know this text of Innocent and attributed to the pope a view opposite to the one he actually plicite &:di. 17, ubi sic legitur. .. . Et dtdil ti potestatmr «1r11m que s11nt s11,- luram, id est dedit
held. It is a good example of Ockham's limited familiarity w ith the literature of canon law. He ei potestatem pro se et posteris suis disponendi de terrenis, que ratio recta dictaverit t>sllt"
knew some texts very well and cited them o ften, but he was not acquainted with the whole necessaria, expedientia, decentia vel utilia non solum ad vivendum, sect etiam ad lx-1w
range of commentaries on the Dtcretals as a professional jurist would have been. Ockham vivendum."
relied for his knowledge of Innocent IV on Eger cui lenia, a letter issued on behalf of the pope 7. Ibid., 3.7, 127, " Potestas autem appropriandi res temporales ... est inter n«eSs11riil e t
during his struggle with Frederick ll. This letter declared that "outside the church ... there is utilia humano generi ad bene vivere computanda post pecratum .... ldeo enim Aristotelt'l'.
no power ordained b y God." Modem scholars have d oubted whe~ lnnoce.n t actu~lly w~e ut habetur 2. Politirorum, reprobavit politiam sive ordinationem Platonis ponmtis civit11h•m
Egtr cui leniR. If he did, then he changed his mind when he recons1d~red the i.ssu~ d1s~ass1on· esse melius o rd inatam, in qua omnia essent communia, quam illam in qua es.9t"nt prnprl11."
ately in the Dtcrtfa/s commentary. Ockham paraphrased Egercui ln11a in the Brrorloqmunr and 8. Ibid., 3.7, 128. "Potestas ergo appropriandi res temporales pel"S(lne et iwrsoni~ aut col·
quoted it directly in the Octo quaesliones, with several references to Innocent IV b y ~ame. 5tt legio data est a Oro humano g<'n<'ri; et propter rationem consimilt>m data <'lit a Dro .1h:o.1m·
H. S. Offler, ed., Octo quaestiones dt poltslate papar in Guilltlmi dt' Ot·klrnm ••1>rr11 pnl1l1ca, 3 v1>t~. ministeri1> et cooprratiun•• hum.m11 poh•sta!I instituendi rectores habenl<'!' iurl~lklloflt"m
(Manchester, 1956-74), l:l.2, 19; 1.10, 42; 1.13, 56; 2.13, 92; S.4, 157. 0n thi~ whol(•qlK':'llion,.l;('t' l<'mporalem, quia iuri~llt11u h•m1"1r,1liM •~t tie num('ro illorum, qU<' ~unt nt"<"t'M.-irla <'t utlllA
A. Melloni, " William of Ockham':i Critiqut> of lnnon•nl IV," fr11111·1:<1'1111 Sl111li~ 4h (111116): ad h<>nl' 1'! polilit"t• vlvrrr "
161-203. II lhi.1 ., 1 A. 12K, " l>upt... 1•uh••l•• r11·1lto 111. ,..·llin•t nprrurrhmcli n •11 trmp••r11lr111•t 111
4. lliid.. J " · 122 24 stihll'rnli rt'\"h•n·11 h11l•1lt11111111•111 h11l1;•111t·•. ''"'" r•I 11 t>... 1 lmml'lllAlr nun t1mt11m ll1h•llh11•.

..
174 TKE IDEA OF N ATIJRAL RIGHTS 0cKHAM : RIGHTS AND SoME PROBLEMS Of P OLITICAL THOUGHT 175

asserted, without any such qualification, that the right to appropriate command; it was rather that reason showed us what God must have in-
could be renounced altogether, and in that work he maintained that, even tended all along. There was no thought here of an inscrutable deity who
in a case of extreme necessity, one could use things without appropriating might arbitrarily wiJJ anything. Ockham was confident that, in this uni-
them, without acquiring any property right.10 That was indeed how the verse that God had actually chosen to create, right reason reflecting on
Franciscans claimed to live. human needs, could discern God's plan for the human race.
At this point Ockham seems to have lost his original focus on the issue
of evangelical poverty. He hedged and fudged arguments important to the
VARIETIES OF NATURAL LAW A ND NATURAL RIG HTS
Franciscan case that had been clearly enunciated in the OND. But it was
only by doing this that he was able to transpose ideas developed in con- Ockham's most detailed analysis of natural law and natural rights
sidering the origin of property to explain the source of imperial power. The came in a passage of the Dialog11s that again was concerned with the ac-
parallelism of the arguments about go~e~ent and pro~rty t~en ~ed on quisition of property and, more particularly, with the establishment of
to another interesting point. In the Brev1loqu1um Ockham still maintained a temporal jurisdiction. Ockham had often insisted that the natural right
distinction between the right to appropriate (a direct grant from God), and to acquire property could be renounced; in the Dialogus he also asked
the actual ownership of property (normally established by human law). whether a people couJd renounce the natural right to institute a ruler.
Then, continuing the same line of argument, he went on to distinguish His way of addressing the issue was to present a complex discussion
similarly between the power to establish jurisdiction and jurisdiction of three kinds of ius naturale, including a sort o f conditional natural law or
itself.II It was a significant step. Ockham was making here the distinction natural right. The importance of the text has been widely recognized, and
between "constituent power" (the right to establish a ruler), and the actual it has often been discussed by modem scholars. De Lagarde, for instance,
right to rule that would persist as an important theme of early modern associated the idea of a conditional natural law with a sort of moral "no
political discourse.12 • • • man's land," where autonomous human will prevailed. 13 McGrade, on the
Ockharn's style of argument in these passages 1s as interesting as other hand, found here an insistence that "actions be rational rather than
his particular conclusions. We saw that, in interpreting the text of Ecdesi- arbitrary or authoritarian."•• The text has other interesting aspects. It illus-
asticus on the power that God gave to Adam, Ockham appealed to right trates again Ockham's relation to the juristic sources that were often in the
reason. If humans were to "live and live well" they needed both a power to background of his arguments; we also find again a tacit shift from an argu-
acquire property and a power to institute governments. Right reason ment about natural law to one about natural rights; and, finally, the course
therefore showed that these rights were included, "at least by implication" o f Ockham's argument led him to discuss in some detail the idea of an
in God's initial grant to Adam. Ockham's argument here was not that God alienable natural right, one that could be renounced at the will of the right-
had revealed his will in a clear divine precept (as in the Ten Command- holder.
ments for instance) and that reason required us to obey God's revealed In the relevant chapters of the Dialogus Ockham approached the theme
of natural law and natural rights in a circuitous way. His underlying pur-
sed etiam infidelibus sic, quod cadit s ub precepto et inter pure mo ralia computatur. propter pose was to prove that an emperor might have the right to appoint a pope.·,
quod omnes obligat tam fideles, quam etiam infideles. . . . Qui.a eni~ ista perti~ent a~ pre- and he found two texts of the Decretum asserting that Pope Adrian I had
ceptum affirmativum, quod obligat semper, non pro semper, 1~eo mfide~ a~ ista ~icut et granted this right to Charlemagne and Pope Leo Vlll to Emperor Otto I."
fideles non pro omni tempore obligantur, sed solummodo in art1culo n~1tatis. Et rune.est, To show how such a transaction could have come about Ockham wa nted
quod predicte duplid potestati renuntiare possunt tam fideles, quam m fideles extra arhcu-
to argue that the Roman people, who had the original right to elect a popt•,
lum necessitatis et utilitatis, que necessitati debeat cmnparari.#
10. OND, OP 1: 322, #Nam quilibet in extrema necessitate ronstitutus habet ius utendi re
usu con,.11mpbbili . . . et tamen dominium talis rei propter hoc non acquirit . . . slante neces- 13. La noissanct, 6 vol.s., 1st ed. (Paris, 1934-46). 6:122, 1~6.
sitot~. iste habuit ius utendi veste absque dominia et proprietate." 14. Poliliral Tirought, 110.
11. BmriIOtJuium, 3.9, 129, "Cum appareat ex predictis, quod aliqua distinctio est inte r do- 15. Dia/~11s C'd. M . Gnldasl in M onarrhia S . Romani imptrii, 3 vols. (Frankforl. lti14),
minium proprium et potestatem appropriandi res temporales, el similiter inter potestatem 2:3.2 3.3, 9 17. Ori th" ~rants of Atl rian I and Leo Vlll that Ockham citt'd, S<'t' Disl. t..1 c.22 ""''
instituendi iurisdictionem et iurisdictionem- ..." r .2.1. Ockha m ~houltl hAvr nolrtl. if lw w ;iintf'<l lo aSS('rl a dortrin1• strictly roniciiitrnl with
12. Ori this theme in George l.a w!IOn ;md John L.oclct> - I. l'rimklln, /olin /,1-.ckl" and thr thilt o f the Bm•iloq11111m, thAI ,, ... I"~'"'" wo•n• ho und to l'Xt•rci~ ltwir right o f r1...·11011 In ...,~.·
Theory of Sawreignly (Cambridgr, llflR). f'Or mt'dl.-v11I burkKnmntl iwt• my l<rlf!(i1111. IJ111•. mrtf of n<'('C'!l~ily. 11111 ht• dlil n11t t~lw thl• p11h1l l11 tlu· tt-•t of ttw l>rarr~11~ wht•n• lw W4• 1'1H1<'1•m...1
11u- Growth ofCorr~tilutmn11I 11K•11xl11 (( -., mbri1lg,·. l'IR2). only wilh the• pt-.•plr'• ' "'"""' "hllllv 111 " '"""'" ,. 1l1e·lr rlKhl
176 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RJGHTS OCKHAM: RtCHTS AND SoME PROBLEMS OF PotmCAL THOUGHT 177

could renounce their right in favor of the pope himself, and that the pope !ems posed by Gratian's texts in a sort of excursus from the main line of his
in tum could confer the right on an emperor. But at this point the Student argument. Since the text has sometimes been seen as destructive of tradi-
in the Dialogus raised an objection. It seemed that the Roman people had tional ideas on natural law it will be useful, in analyzing it, to consider
no right to elect the pope either by divine law or human law. The Master whether Ockham did in fact depart radically from earlier canonistic treat-
replied that they did have such a right by divine law if divine law were ex- ments of the relevant passages of the Decretum.21 Let us consider the three
tended to include alJ natural law.16 kinds of natural law in tum.
At this point in the discussion Ockham veered off into his minitreatise Natural Law I. This was defined as a law " in conformity with a natural
on the different varieties of natural law and associated natural rights. reason that never fails." Two examples were given from the Decalogue:
Much of the material presented seems superfluous in relation to the point "Thou shalt not commit adultery" and "Thou shalt not lie." This law was
he was intending to make. The core of the argument could have been pre- immutable and invariable and not subject to dispensation.22 There seems
sented in half a dozen lines. According to divine and natural law, any no problem with this definition. The texts of Gratian that Ockham cited
people had the right to choose its own ruler. 17 The pope was the ruler of here declared that natural Jaw "began with the origin of the rational crea-
the Roman people. Therefore they had the right to elect him. As for the re- ture," that it was immutable, and that it was exemplified in the moral pre-
nunciation of this right it would have sufficed to quote the Ordinary Gloss cepts of scripture. Guido de Baisio, whom I mentioned earlier as a possible
to the Decretals, "Licitum est cuilibet renunciare iuri suo." (" It is licit for source for Ockham, quoted a similar text from Hugucdo in his Rosarium.23
anyone to renounce his right." 18) But, instead of just making these simple Natural Law II. Ockham's formulation seems at first more original
points, Ockham embarked on an extended, apparently redundant treat- here. The second kind of natural law is the law observed by those "who
ment of natural law in general. H. S. Offler, the editor of Ockham's text, use only natural equity without any human law or custom." This was the
suggested an explanation for this when he wrote that Ockham's discus- law that existed "in the state of nature as first instituted." It would still be
sion was "conditioned, if not motivated" by the difficulties inherent in observed "if men lived according to natural reason or divine law." But this
Gratian's account of natural law.19 I think Ockham's argument was prob- law was not immutable like Natural Law I. After the Fall, on account of
ably both conditioned and motivated by these difficulties. Almost all the human iniquity, it had been changed by human laws and customs. For in-
early commentators on the Decretum had noticed that the words ius natu- stance, according to this second kind of natural law, all things were
rale were used in several different senses in the opening Distinctions of common and all persons were free; but human law had introduced private
Gratian' s work and had sought to bring order out of the apparent chaos by property and servitude.24 The idea of a mutable natural law has seemed
categorizing, in different ways, the various meanings of the term. The
comment of Huguccio is typical: "Note that not all the examples of ius 21 . In presenting his three modes of natural law Ockham cited the following passages of
naturale given here refer to the same meaning of ius naturale . . . but lest the Dtcrdum: Dist. 1c7, Dist. 1 c.8, Dist. 5 dictum anle c.1, Dis/. 6 dictum post c.3, Dis/. 8 dictum
the mind of some idiot be confused we shall carefully define each one."20 post c.1. Dist. 9 didum ante c.l , Dist. 28 c.16, Dist. 6.1 c.12, C.12 q.1 c.2, Cl2 q.1 c.68.
Ockham often had occasion to refer to the relevant passages of the Decre- 22. Offler, "Three Modes," 212-3. "Uno enim modo dicitur ius naturale illud, quod <'l!I
conforme rationi naturali, que in nullo casu fallit, sicut est 'n.o n mechaberis,' 'non mentieri~'
tum, and he too did not suffer idiots gladly. In the Difllogus he seems to et huisusmodi ... ius naturale primo modo est immutabile et invariabile ac indispen~bill',
have taken up the challenge and provided his own solution to the prob- di. v, § Nunc autem et di vi, § Hiis itaqut rtsp0ndd11r."
23. Guido de Baisio, Rosari11m decrrtorum (Strasbourg. 1473) {np) ad Dis/. 1 antr c. l , "lu~
16. Several texts in the opening chapters of the Drcrd11m seemed to identify divine law naturale est d ivinum ius scilicet quod continetur in lege mosaica et evangelica ... ad u qur
with natural law. See Dist. 1, c.1, "Divinae (leges) natura ... constant." GI. ord. ad Dist. 1, c.7, iure divino continentur naturalis racio etiam sine extrinsica excitatione ducit e t impcllit l't~
n • •• omne ius divinum dicitur na turale ius.tt Dist. 6, dictum post c.3, "Jn lege et in evangelio cundum Hu." On Guido's work as a possible source for Ockham see above, 102 n. 35.
naturaJe ius continetur...." 24. Offler, "Three Modes, 212-3, "A liter d icitur ius naturale, quod servandum est ab illi'I,
tt

17. Ockham several times stated this principle. See e.g., 81'evifoquium 4.10, 161, " A Deo qui sola equitate nalurali absque omni consuetudine el constitutione humana utuntur ... NI
enim et a natura ha.b ent om.nes mortales, qui nascuntur liberi ... quod sponte possunt sibi homines viverent secundum ra tionem naturalem... . lsto modo et non primo modo t'K lun•
rectorem preficere." naturali omnia sunt communin, quia in ~tatu nature institute omnia fuls~nt communin, c-1 "i
18. GI. ord ad X .1.95 and X.3.31.23. post la~um om~ lwmlnc'ft !'<'nrndum ratlonem vivert'nt, omni• deb<'renl""""' rommunl• "'
19. H. S. Offler, "The Three Modes of Natural law in Odtham: A R,•vis ion of the Text," nic'hil pmprium; proprlt•tn11 o•nlm pruph•r ln1t1111t11trm f'i!I lrn1ucte, iril, q . I, c. Dilt'Cll"inii.•, l'l
Fr11nciscan Studies 37 {1977): 207-218 at 21 l. l1le text o f Dialaxu.4:u _
1.t. in (:old•"" i.• dt>ft'<'tiv<'. ponitur in dt'<'n•llA di.I, '" lu• ""''""''· n un tll1·1t tiunci Nt'CunJum lu11 n11turnlt:' 1•111 n•mmrmi•
In the following notes I havt' ust"d the- com.>Clt'd veniion RiVMl l>y ( lfOt'r t l ltlo•r 111"" dis.'tL~M'1.t
here variom• modc-m approat·hfoft ft> I >in/11~11~ J.2.J .I\.
.1 "m11ium t"'''- "5-''" fl""'"""",.,.., l1l..-1t11• hu" 1111l11r.11i orn11M1humlnc-11 111mt lil'<'rl rt t11mr11
..,,vi,••
'I"''•"'" 1111111111 •1110.1 1111• n11lur111lr 11110 mt1tl1111•'t"'l'h• vu

~
allq11l i11 n• tt"ntlum fhmt
20. Surr1mn 111/ />i.<I. I. c h . MS /\111110111 7. lol :l vh. 1 _,hu lo n un <'•I l1111n11l,.hll•. 11111110 llo •I 1 n11h "' '""' "'"'"'' '"· 111 hon- 11111 n111tr,.1l11m ••
178 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS Ocl<HAM: RIGHTS AND 5oME PROBLEMS OF POLITICAL THOUGHT 179

disturbing to some critics, but here again Ockham was following a suppositione)."29 This conditional natural law was derived from rational
common line of Decretist argument. His distinction between Natural responses to contingent situations. Supposing that property has been in-
Law I and Natural Law II corresponds closely to the distinction introduced troduced by human law, then evident reason concludes that money lent
by Rufinus, one of the first commentators on the Decretum, between pre- should be repaid. Supposing that someone has been violently attacked
cepts and prohibitions of natural law on the one hand and "demonstra- (which is against natural law in the first two senses) then evident reason
tions" on the other. The precepts and prohibitions were immutable. But shows that it is licit for a person to repel force with force. 30 A kind of
the "demonstrations" were merely descriptive of a state of affairs that natural law, a law of reason, can therefore be discovered in the relevant
was good and equitable but subject to change by human initiative, "espe- provisions of human law concerning repayment of debts and self-defense.
cially as regards the liberty of all and common property," Rufinus wrote, Some critics have seen in this concept of a conditional natural law, de-
"for nowadays this slave is mine, that field is yours by civil law.":zs This ar- pendent on previous human usages, a dangerous novelty, different from
gument of Rufinus was also included in the Rosarium of Guido de Baisio, any previous understanding of ius naturale. But in fact one of the early
again in a formulation of Huguccio.26 commentators on the Decretum, Alanus, had proposed a very similar doc-
Kolmel found a significant innovation in that Ockham associated trine to explain some other words of Isidore included in the text at Dist. 1
two different kinds of natural law with the condition of humanity before c.7 that Ockham cited. Isidore wrote here that both common possession
and after the Fall. This doctrine, he wrote, was not to be found in Thomas and "the acquisition of what is taken by air, land, and sea" pertained to
Aquinas or Duns Scotus.27 But it is to be found quite commonly in the natural law. To explain the apparent contradiction, Alanus wrote, in a
Decretist literature, and Ockham supported his argument with some rele- phrase similar to Ockham 's, that in one of its various meanings the term
vant texts of the Decretum. Also, the canonists' teaching concerning the two ius naturale could mean "whatever is naturally equitable in the law of na-
types of natural law, before the Fall and after, had been assimilated into the tions or civil law or canon law."31 Moreover, he introduced here a concept
Franciscan Summa of Alexander of Hales in mid-thirteenth century, and, of "relative" natural law (ius respectiuum) that was essentially the same as
once again, the relevant text was included in the Rosarium.~
Natural Law Ill. Ockham's third kind of natural law is the most in-
teresting one. His argument was suggested by a text of Isidore of Se-
ville, included in the Decretum at Dist. 1 c.7. Here Isidore mentioned "the
l
t
Ockham's ius naturale ex suppositione.» "Simple (natural law) shows some-

29. Offler, "Three Modes," 213, #Tertio modo dicitur ius naturale illud, quod ex iul"l'
gentium vel alio aut ex aliquo facto divino vel humano evidenti ratione rolligitur, nisi dc

j
ronsensu illorum, quorum interest, contrarium statuatur. Quod poterit vocari ius naturale
common possession of all things" and also "the return of a thing deposited
ex suppositione. ... "
or of money loaned" as pertaining to natural law. But the repayment of a 30. Ibid., "Quia, supposito quod res et pecunie sint appropriate iure gentium vel aliquo
loan presupposes the existence of private property. In explaining Natural iure humano, evidenti ratione colligitur quod res deposita et pecunia commodata debl'nt
Law II, Ockham had just declared that property was instituted by human f
§, restitui, nisi ex causa per ilium vel illos, cuius vel quorum interest, contrarium ordinl'tm.
law. Now he had to explain a text that derived both common possession Similiter, supposito quod aliquis violentiam de facto iniuriose inferat alteri-<1uod non est dl'
iure naturali, sed contra ius naturale-t>videnti ratione colligitur quod licet per vim violm·
and private property from natural Jaw. To do this, Ockham introduced
tiam talem repellere.#
his Natural Law III. "Jn a third way, natural law is said to be what can be 31. Alanus, Pr0tmium in Weigand, Die Naturrtehtslthrr (above, 137, n. 19), 228, " Vndr
gathered by evident reason from the law of nations or some other law or quicquid est equum naturaliter uel in iure genii um uel ciuili uel canonico, sub iure naturali
from some act, divine or human, unless the contrary is established by cont\netur."
those concerned, and this can be called natural law by supposition (ex 32. Ibid ., "Item sciendum (est) quod (et) est ius naturale simplex et respectiuum. SimplNt
quod sine precedenti positione iuris pos1tiui demonstrat aliquid equum esse q~ale. est i~tU<I .
'deum diligere', 'omnia esse communia'. Respectiuum est quod demonstrat ahqmd t'C)uum
25. Rufinus, Summll dtcrrtorum, ed. H. Singer (Paderbom, 1902), ad Dist. 1 antt c.I, 6- 7. habito respectu ad precedens ius positiuum, quale est hoc 'adquisitio corum que Cl'lo' t<I<".,
On Rufinus see above, 62. nisi enim apponatur prius aliquem hominem habere propr"ium, non erit istud equu~ '• ff·
26. Rosarium ad Dist. 1 antt c.1, NEt hoc (ius naturale) consistit in tribus, scilicet in precep- quisitio' etc." In hi.~ comment on Dist. 1 c.1 (Weigand, 229 n . 48), Alanus u~ a l'h~htly
tis, prohibitionibus et demonstratiorjbus. Precipit quod prodest ut 'dilige deum tuum', different terminoh>F;y. distin~uishing relative natural law horn Habs<llull'" natural l01w. " I k·
proh.i bet quod ledit ut 'non furaberis', demonstrat quod convenit et expedit ~cilic'et omnia iure <'!'RO naturali ah!<olnto ·~t omnia ~o;e rommunia, de respectiuo iure natur11ll l'l't 11liq11rn1
esserommunia etomnium esseunam libertatem . . . secundum Hu." agnrm e!l..'lt' alil'num." l l.·kh1m111!1<'\I tlw lilnguage of absolute and condlllom1\ natural l•w 111
V. W. Kolmel, "Das Naturrecht bei Wilheim Ockham," Frnnli~k1111i,..·lw .<;1111l1m :l.<; ( 195..1): Dinli•}/llS :l2. 1.IO. <;uhlot. H7H, " l'r•rc·••plum autem naturall' quoddam t'lll 11h11olul11m . .
39-85at 49. Quo1hl.1m mah·m """ r•t ,.,,.. ,111111111 ••"''um 11li.1111• nmditlutw, m11c.llrk11tlonr, vrl 111,...-lflt'~
28. Rm:arium ad Di.•t. 1 C'.7, rderrinK spt'<·ifin11ly to l\h•••uulrr of 11111"" 1;11111., • In hl11 /'nlf'ml11n1. Al<11111• ,.,.., , ..1..~l 1111otlll'f iN01tr lhnt w1111t.I I"• lmp111t<111t In lntrr

\
l
180 'THE I O£A OF NATURAL RIGHTS 0CKHAM: RIGHTS ANO SoME PROBLEMS OF POLITICAL THOUGHT 181

thing to be equitable without any preceding enactment of positive Jaw . if a man refrained from exacting a debt or from defending himself when
relative (natural law) shows something to be equitable having regard to a attacked he was not repealing the natural law concerning payment of
previous positive Jaw." Thus the "acquisition" mentioned by Isidore could debts or self-defense. He was waiving the exercise of a right that he held
pertain to natural law only because it had previously been enacted that an in accordance with that law. From this point onward in Ockham's argu-
individual could hold property. ment, the word ius was used indifferently to refer to a natural right or to
These passages of Alanus and Ockham are especially interesting as natural law; and, just as in the ONO, Ockham did not think it necessary to
early formulations of the concept of "adventitious'' rights that, much later, alert his readers to the shifts in meaning. Often the word glides from one
would become prominent in the work of theorists like Pufendorf and meaning to the other in the course of a single phrase as when Ockham
Burlamaqui Pufendorf discussed the rights and obligations existing in an wrote that " the Romans have the right (ius) of electing from d ivine law
"adventitious state" that arose "by virtue of some human deed."33 Burla- (iure) or natural law (iure)." Subsequently the word ius was repeatedly
maqui held that the right to property was not derived from "primitive" used to mean a right in phrases like ius eligendi (right of electing), cedere
natural law; it was introduced adventitiously by human initiative; but, iuri suo (to cede one's right), transferre ius suum in alium (to transfer one's
once instituted, the right was protected by a "secondary" natural law right to another), ius instituendi electores (right of instituting electors).37 We
which "supposes some human act or establishment." 34 This is precisely must remember that the whole point of Ockham's involved discussion
what Ockham meant when he wrote of a natural law from supposition, was to prove that the Roman people had a right to elect their rulers that
and what Alanus had suggested with his distinction between "simple" was associated with a certain kind of natural faw.
and "relative" natural law. In spite of Ockham's concern here with rights, de Lagarde went too
It is impossible to know whether Ockham had ever come upon the far when he wrote that, for the Franciscan, natural law was "only a sum of
text of Alanus. Conceivably, he did know it and reworked it for his own natural rights," without any underlying permanent principle of rational
purpose; more probably he reconstructed the same line of argument by equity.38 Ockham was really concerned with both natural law and natural
reflecting on the same passage of the Decretum. In either case we are deal- rights. He wanted primarily to define a kind of natural law that could be
ing with a way of understanding the idea of natural law that was implicit associated with an alienable natural right; but he was careful to explain
in Gratian' s texts and that had been perceived to be implicit more than a that each of the three modes of natural law that he described was rooted
century before Ockham wrote. There is no need to appeal to "Ockhamist in "an instinct of nature, that is, of natural reason," 39 a phrase no doubt
epistemology" or to "a nominalist conception of law" in order to explain suggested by the Ordinary Gloss to Dist. 1 c.7 of the Decretum which gave
this part of Ockham's argument.35 as one d efinition of natural law, "an instinct of nature proceeding from
We still, however, have to consider the most distinctive feature of reason." 40
Ockham's discussion, his "obscure and ambiguous" words, "unless the Having established the principle of alienability by referring to a prop-
contrary is established by those concemed."36 This does seem to introduce erty right (the right to recover something loaned that could be waived),
a new kind of natural law, unstable, changeable according to the wiJI of Ockham moved on to consider the issues that had really inspired the
the people involved. But, the point is that Ockham's argument was shift- whole argument, the right of the Roman people to elect their bishop and
ing here from natural law to natural rights. He wrote, for instance, that the possibility of their renouncing this right. The right to elect, Ockham \
debts had to be repaid unless the interested parties decided otherwise. But, wrote, was related to the third kind of natural Jaw. For, supposing that a
ruler was to be appointed, then it could be gathered by evident reason
natural law theori~whether the perception of what is just itself imposed an obligation or
whether a positive command was also needed. Alan us favored the latter view. "Vnde si nil
that those over whom he was to rule should have the right of electing
aliud prohiberet, contra naturalem equitatem facere non esset peccatum. Prohiberet tamen
quod iniquum est ius positiuum quod nos ligat et precipit equum.M 37. omer. HThree Modes," 216- 18.
33. Pufendorf, Dr iurt naturae, 1.1 .7, 8; 33.4.3, 381. 38. N11i~snnct, 5 (1963): 118, " Pour Ockham le droit naturE-1 qu·it s'agit dt> sauvc•g.mlN t~I
34. J. J. Burlamaqui, Tht Principles of N alural 1..aw, trans. T. Nugent (Cambridge, Mass., un droit s ubjectif individuel . . . l'essentic l du droil nature! - . . n 'est q' unc 50mmt• <It• droit"
1807), 2.4.24. Cf. Grotius, Dr iurr bt/li, 1.1.10, "Thus ownership .. . was instituted by the will naturels H

of man; but, once instituted, the law of nature indicates that it is wrong for me to ta ke your 39. Offler, 'Three Mo<l~." 11~. I !..re•< J.·khnm wt•nt thmuKh all thn't' kind!'I of n.1hm1l l;1w
property against your will.N and :;howo'tl how t'illii kinof w•• known "hy i n~llnd of natun·. th;it L'I of n11hm1I n •11... m ·· ( " in
35. These phra!leS a re from df' ~giude, Nni~sattf,. h ( 11J4t.): l';fl, 1f>7 !'1linc.1u llillllr(', h1>c- l'!'l n11h1r11I• 11U11nh•" )
36. ~Lagarde, N11a""""'" !I ( l'Hi.l): 114. "( ·,"' molic ... M>nt t>t>11nu• ••I itmhl1tt1~ ", 11 7, 40 (a...... ''"''"' I •. 7, " lr rli11 "''"''' .... lhu (Ill• 11ottur.1lc•) in•lilll'lllN ""It""''"' rt11lu111·
'I"'
••. .. <"t>lle c•xplk allon p.M'ncfn . rnllrn1rll1• t>J......,.. le• heHI M'tl" Ir p lu• 1•\'ltl1•11I J•f.l \V f'l1U •l 1"
182 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RICKTS ()cKHAM: RIGHTS AND SOME PROBLEMS OF POU11CAL THoUCKT
183

him. As for alienation of the right, Ockham argued that when the people emment. If they did so they would have instituted an absolutist re~me.
conferred on a ruler the right of making laws they also conferred the right Liberal theorists therefore argued that individuals retained some nghts
to choose future rulers or to designate the electors. These are not strik- even after a government had been constituted. In ~e later de~ates ~ufen­
ingly novel ideas. The idea that licit rulership was conferred by consent dorf's argument leaned more to absolutism, Locke s more to liberalism.
of the community to be ruled was fairly commonplace at the beginning In the centuries before Ockham, medieval jurists had argued endlessly,
of the fourteenth century. Ockham's Dominican contemporary, Hervaeus without ever reaching a consensus, about whether the Roman people
J Natalis, an adversary of the Franciscans, also presented a well worked-out alienated its rights in creating an emperor (the "translatio~ theory") or
theory of government based on election and consent. So too, of course, merely conceded to the ruler the exercise of rights that remamed with the
did Marsilius of Padua. Again, all jurists knew the t~t of Roman law as- people (the "concession theory"). From the twelfth century onward, me~
serting that the people had created an emperor by conferring their own dieval jurists also debated the question whether the emperor's role as
authority on him, and Hostiensis had further suggested that the people's dominus mundi (lord of the world) gave him absolute power as the actual
right to elect was derived from "the common law . .. by which any college owner of his subjects' property.41 Ockham's insistence in the ONO that the
elects a ruler for itself ... or from natural reason from which law derives." actual division of property among individuals was first made by huma~
As for renunciation, it was a common medieval practice, as Ockham law-often by the laws of emperors and kings-could have ~avored this
noted, for an electoral body to transfer the right of electing to one or a few conclusion. But his arguments that the original right to acquire property
persons whose decision they were bound to accept. But the whole title, De pertained to natural and divine law, and _that priva~ p~perty was pro-
renuntiatione, in the Decretals dealt with rights derived from positive canon tected by another kind of natural law once it had been instituted by human
law; there was no discussion of the alienation of natural rights. The new consent, left the way open for a defense of property rights in civil society.
feature in Ockham's work is t at e whole argument about the institu- This was the position that Ockham adopted. . .
tion of a ruler and the alienation of the right to elect was set in the context Ockham has sometimes been called an absolutist because he did not
of a discussion on natural law and natural rights. We may also note that, argue for any regular participation of the people in govem~ent or for per-
in the Dialogus, Ockham's argument for the right of any community to manently established representative institutions to restrain th~ power of
choose a ruler was based on a natural law discerned by reason, rather emperors or kings. But, as regards the persistence of _natura_l nghts after
than on the direct divine precept emphasized in the Breviloquium. But, in the institution of government, his thought was clearly m the _h~ral or con-
the course of the argument we have just outlined, Ockham also held that stitutionalist tradition. For him the power of rulers was bmtted by the
all the principles of all three modes of natural law were implicit in divine rights of their subjects. Ockham did not hold that the emperor was a mere
scripture even though they were not explicitly stated there.41 Again, it agent whom the people could remove at will (though he ~uld be d~posed.
seems, reason shows us what God intends when his will is not made for heresy or serious crime).43 Once elected the rule~ had nghts of his own,
explicit. but the people had rights too, includin~ propertr nghts.. .
Ockham was especially interested m defending the nghts of the C::hn~-
tian faithful against the absolutist claims of ~e pap~cy, bu! at on~ pomt m
ABSOLUTISM AND NATURAL RIGHTS the Dialogus the Student raised the same issue m relatt~n to impen~l .powcr.
ln the later development of thought on natural rights, discussions Did the emperor have the same plenitude of power m temporahties that
about alienation of rights became intricately linked with arguments about the pope had (according to some) in spiritual affairs? Could he make law~
the proper limits of ruling authority. The idea of natural rights could be
used to defend either absolutist or liberal theories of government; the out- 42. The debate goes back to a legendary dispute between the twelfth-ce~tury dvi1111n•
come of the ar ument turned on the theory of alienability that an author Marti nus and Bulgarus. According to a popular story, the emperor Fn:der1dc. ttnrb•m"'""
adopted. The question at issue was w e rs of a community once asked Martinus and Bulgarus whether he was truly lord of the world (domrnu' n11md1)
Martinus replied simply th11t hl' wa~ indeed lord. Bulgarus explained carefully th11t the' ~m
could or actually did alienate all their rights in the act of constituting a gov- peror was a supremt• rult•r hut not tlw rtctual owner (dominus) of hi!l subj«ls' pmpt•rty. n1r
!!mpcror theR'upon K"vr hi• h <lfll<" tu M"rtln1111. Bulgaru.~ ob§erved with a rut'ful pun'""' hr
41. OfAer, art. al., 216, N • in scripturis divinis sunt qut>Jnm n~ulc gt'fl('rall>s, ex
• • hnd !laid wh•I wn" ln•I (t'lfUll~). hut M•rtl1111• got the hoDe (tquum). f(lr 11 rt'Ct'lll dl11e111111lon
quibus . . . colligi potest omnc im1 n.itumk- <'I primo ct !IC<"undo 1•1 h•rtlo """I" clktum, lin•t '*'''
K. t't•nnlnKhm, Tltl' 1'11111,. 11n1I II" I 1rn1 ( llc•rli.rlry, l'llY.l), I!'\- IQ.
in eis non inveniatur <'Xplicilt>." ·4:\ llu111l11111111in1. 4 I.I. t r1'1 "''
184 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ()CKHAM: RIGHTS AND SOME PROBLEMS Of POLmCAL THOUGHT 185

for his own private advantage or only for the common utility? There al- that Ockham had heTe set a limit, not merely to the power of the ruler, but
ready existed a large body of thought in earlier works of jurisprudence " to the power of the State itself."•5 We should add that Ockham's method-
and political philosophy about the proper limits to a ruler's authority; ology here is significant as well as his conclusion. A discussion about
but Ockham succeeded in adding a new argument of his own here. The the relationship between a community and its individual members might
people could not confer absolute power on an emperor, he wrote, because well have been presented in terms of nominalist philosophy; but in fact
the people itself did not possess such a power over its own individual Ockham chose to base his argument on a technicality of canonistic corpo-
members; and the people could not confer more power than it actually ration law.
possessed. When Ockham turned to the issue that really interested him, the
To prove this point, Ockham turned to a rather improbable source, a limitation of papal power, he faced a rather different problem. In the Brev-
text of canonistic corporation law dealing with a long-ago dispute in the iloquium he maintained that an emperor' s power came to him from God
church of Troyes. The cathedral chapter there was divided into a majority through the people. But it was derived from God only as a remote cause or
of resident canons and a minority of nonresident ones. According to the in the sense that, once elected, an emperor recognized no superior except
custom of the church they all received the same stipends. But in the early God. 46 The crucial point was that the people could not confer any power
years of the thirteenth century the majority attempted a financial coup. on a ruler that was not already inherent in the commuruty. The situation
They appropriated for the common fund of the chapter some vineyards at- was different with the pope. Here Christ himself had directly instituted the
tached to the prebends of the nonresident minority. The case was appealed power of the papal office in his commission to Peter, and each new pontiff
to Pope Innocent Ill, and he voided the arrangement. The pope argued, succeeded to this divinely ordained authority. The cardinals did not them-
in effect, that members of a minority in a corporate community could selves possess the divine power of the papacy and could not confer it
not be deprived of their individual rights by a vote of the majority. The on anyone. Ockham exp?ained in the Brevifoquium that they merely desig-
Ordinary Gloss, pursuing the matter further, argued that a majority vote nated a candidate who, when he accepted the papal office, received his
could prevail only in certain necessary actions-the author mentioned power to rule the church directly from God.47 Yet Ockham also argued in
elections and alienations-while in all other cases unanimous consent was the Breviloquium that a pope's power was limited by the rights of his sub-
required. This was the argument that Ockham seized upon. The Roman jects just as an emperor's was. In Ockham's view, where the pope was
people could command its members only in matters necessary for the concerned, God did not choose to bestow absolute power; where the em-
community; in other cases an individual member would not have to obey peror was concerned, the people had no absolute power to bestow.
unless he so wished. It followed that the power of the emperor, which One could make a good case for regarding the Breviloquium as the
was derived from the community, was simjlarly limited.44 first essentially rights-based treatise on political theory. In the Prologue
Ockham presented this argument in a few terse lines, without any to this work Ockham wrote that the abuse of papal power was "opposed
particular emphasis, but Gierke long ago saw its importance. He wrote to the rights and liberties granted by God and nature," and he attacked
-----.. those who "not content with their own rights . . . reach out for the rights
44. Diafogus, 3.2.2.27, 923, "Item, imperator non habet maiorem potestatem in tern·
of others." 411 Ockham followed this up by deploying a series of canonis-
poralibus, quam habuit populus, cum imperator habeat potestatem suam a populo, vt tic texts in which earlier popes had themselves affirmed the principl<'
allegatum est supra. quia populus plus iurisdictionis aut potestatis non potuit transferre in that a supreme pontiff should n ot invade the rights of the faithful but
imperatorem, quam habuit. Sed populus nunquam habuit talem potestatis plenitudinem, vt should seek to preserve them. Pope Innocent Ill, usually no favorit<> of
possit praecipere cuilibet de populo omne iJlud, quod non est conIra ius diuinum aut contra
ius naturale; quia non poterat praecipere illa, quae non eranl de necessitate facienda, teste
Glossa, extra de constitutione, cum omnis, secundum quam in talibus, quae (non) de necessitate 45. O . Gierke, Pnl1t1cnl TheoritS uf the Middle Age, trans. F. W. Maitland (Camhridgt•, 1'1110),
facienda nihil potest fieri nisi omnes consentiant. Ergo si popuJus praecipit aliquid alicui 179 n. 27-l
de populo, quod non est de necessitate faciendum, non tenetur iUud facere, nisi velit, restat 46. Rrtt•i/oq11ium, 4.8, 15..1. u • • • quamvi-; primo institutum fuerit a Oco p<'r hominc'11 .
igitur, quod imperator non habet talem potestatis plenitudinem." The decretal cum omnis tamen postquam imperium r<'r onlinilli1•m•m humanum institutum est, lmpt•mto r 0 111111111
(correctly Cum omnes) (X.l.2.6) referred to the case of the church o f Troyes discussed above. habl't rt'gularitf'r !\upt•riorl'm In h•mpo rdlil•11,., ni~i ~olum l'Num."
The O rdinary Gloss here commented, s.v. Constitut11m, "Si vero sint plul"l'S ut rolll'gium, dis · 47. llm•rl11q11i11m. 4.'1, 11\1
tingue, si aliqua facienda sunt ex necessitate, ut alil'nationes, f'lf'•:tionl':" .-t similia, J0111fficit 41\. llrrrtilitquium, l'rulc•K11~. 111, ·· hulhu• C'l lllwrlalihu~ a IJ\•o rl 11 n11hm1 v1>t>h1 <011
quod maior pars facit . ... In alii!I qual' ex 1WCt>Ssil11lf' non fiunt, •1•111li" o•r1ml '"'·'· 1111.w i!!li c·c·~"i" .ulvi•r.in_. ", " 'I"' l''''t''ll• 111111111~ """ c'n11trnl11 11.t 11111•1111. t11m tllvln" •111"111
facit"bant. nihil polt•st fit>ri, nisi ""'"'"' .-unsc•nli.mt "
'"'"'' "''' "'""''- "''"'"'.,'" 11011 l'" v""' uni "
186 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS OcKllAM: RJGtn'S AND SoME PR0 8l.f.MS Of PoLmCAL THOUCKT 187

Ockham, wrote that he did not intend to disturb the rights of the king of from the regular exercise of the jurisdiction that the pope received from
France. Gregory the Great disclaimed any intention of diminishing the God.s3
rights of his brother-bishops. Also Gregory IX, in the Proemium to the De- Ockham's favorite way of proving this was to argue that the evangeli·
cretals, his authoritative codification of church law, quoted the civilian cal liberty proclaimed in scripture limited papal power by safeguarding
dictum that the law should "render to each his right." 49 And, from the the natural and civil rights of the pope's subjects. The argument from
point of view of the subjects, Ockham added, "To neglect common rights evangelical liberty was first introduced in the Contra Benedictum, then de-
is a vice."50 veloped at length in the An princeps, and repeated in several other works.~
Later on in the Breviloql1ium, and in other discussions scattered In the Breviloquium Ockham noted that the papalists took their stand on
throughout his political writings, Ockham achieved a new kind of syn- the words of Christ to Peter, "Whatsoever you shall bind on earth .. ." to·
thesis by weaving together the idea of the natural rights inherent in all gether with the further comment of Innocent III on these words, "Except-
persons with the specifically Christian concept of evangelical liberty and ing nothing when he said 'Whatsoever'." But, on the contrary, Ockham
with the canonistic understanding of a right as something that could not maintained, it was an established principle of canon law that general ex-
be taken away without fault or cause. The idea that ius nalurale could be pressions were to be understood with appropriate exceptions; and so it
associated with evangelical liberty, understood as a sphere of personal au- was in this case.ss Christian law was a law of liberty, indeed, "a law of per-
tonomy, had been suggested by some of the early Decretists; 51 but Ock- fect liberty" according to the Epistle of James. Paul too wrote of "the free-
ham carried the argument further by relating the concepts of natural rights dom that we have in Christ Jesus" and declared that "Where the spirit
and gospel freedom in a way that set limits to the God-given power of a of the Lord is, there is liberty."56 But, if the pope could command anything
supreme pontiff. not contrary to divine and natural law, then Christian law would be a
Ockham addressed the is.5ue of papal authority by asking whether the law of most horrid servitude. All Christians would be made slaves of the
pope had such a plenitude of power from God in spiritual and temporal supreme pontiff, for to command anything not forbidden by divine and
affairs that he could do anything not contrary to the immutable principles natural law was precisely the kind of power that a master held over his
of divine and natural law. Even the extreme papalists recognized that slaves.57 In the An princeps, Ockham wrote that, given this kind of pleni-
these laws set limits to the authority of a pope; but Ockham's point was tude of power, the pope could depose kings and princes from their offic~
that they were not the only limits. One could envisage many papal com- and deprive all clerics and layfolk of their goods and rights-and all this
mands whose fulfillment would not involve any offense against divine or without fault or cause.56 Such assertions were absurd, Ockham wrote; they
natural law but that would still be unjust because they violated the rights were contrary to the liberty of evangelical law, heretical, pernicious, dan-
of others without fault or cause. The papalist view that Ockham was at- gerous to everyone.S9 The proper limits to papal power were set by tht•
tacking-though truly it would be hard to find a papalist who envisaged
in detail all the claims that Ockham mentioned-held that, although the
53. Ibid., 2.4, 59, "Et ideo si in contravenientem ferret sentent.iam, ipsa sententia l'SIK'I
pope might sin in issuing unjust decrees, still he had the power to act as
nulla tamquam a non suo iudice lata.. . .H
he chose, and there was an obligation on the subjects to obey. A papal 54. Ockham returned to this th.e me repeatedly in his later works. The principal phll'l"fl
decree could be unjust but still valid.52 Ockham maintained that such de- where he discussed evangelical liberty and natural rights as restraints on papal power nn•
crees were not binding because they were simply ultra vires, excluded Bmriloq11i11m, 2.3- 4, 56-9 and 2.17-18, 90-95; An princq15, OP 1: 2, 233-5; Odo qWJr.;tiont'fi, <JI'
I: 1.6, 29-30; Dia/ogus, 3.1.1. 5-8, 776-80; Ck imfNratorum ti pontificum poltSllllt, ed. R. &hob
49. Ibid., 1.3, 44, citing X.2.1.13, Dist. 99 c5, X. P~mium. in Unbekannlt kirc:htnpolitischt StrtiJschrifrtn llUS du ail Ludwig des Bayun (1327- 13.54), 2 VOIN.
SO. Ibid., 1.4, 45, ". . . negligere iura communia est vitium. .. .H
(Rome, 1914), 2:1- 9, 456-66.
51. See above, 66- 68. 55. Breviloq111um, 2.2, 55; 2.14, 82.
52. Bmliloquium, 2.1, 54, " ... nonnulli tenent quod papa sic ha bet a Christo plenitudinem 56. Ibid., 2.3, 56- 7, citing James 1.25; Cal. 2.4; 2 Cor. 3.17.
potestatis, ut omnia tam in temporalibus, quam in spiritualibus possit de iure, que nee iuri 57. Ibid ., 2.3, 57-8.
naturali nee legi divine repugnant in tanturn. quod, quamvis quedam talia de facto precipi· 58. An prinu~, OP I: 2.2'.\2; Oct11 qw1rsti1ms, 0 1' 1: l .6, 29; VialoX11~. :l.1.1.6, 77t>; /)t inrr t i
endo vel faciendo peccaret mortaliler, tamen facta tenerent et sibi essel obediendum de porrl. pol., I, 456.
necessitate salutis." By natural law here Ockham plainly meant the first of the three kind'! o f 59. Arr princ·t~, 01' I: 2, 212, " 1'1_.1 "l"K" pi!pa. si hahrn•I talt>m plM1ituJlrwm p<ltMOl8tlN,
natural law described in the Di11logus. He made hi'! intention dear in the An 1irinc~. OP 1: !lint• n 1lp11t•t11rnw11w l"8UM l"t'M"' rl prl11< lpn ,... dllo11d1··rit"o.'ll1•1l11koro11nlvrrau111lr d lKnlh1I
1, 229, where he described his advl'rsaries a!I holding lh11t lht> p<>J'<' Wftll ll<mml only "'p<•r it111N aui" dC'prnwrr ip.. 1111111r 1•11\lul' 0111111'111• rrl•u~ aui~ rt lurlt>u" . . 'I""" Aha111<ll,.11lrn•
tegem divinam v<'I ius nalur"lr imm11t11bil1• 1•1 lndi10p<·n.~hllt•." It>""'·
:iunl 1•1 tlhrrl"ll rv1111Krlh·411,. 'I"".,••• 1tlvlnl• .. rlphrrh• h11!i.-hrr, tlrrtl)tllllllft m11n1f.-.1..
188 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS 0CKHAM: RIGHTS AND SOME PROBLEMS OF PoLmCAL THoUCHT 189

liberties and temporal rights of emperors, kings, princes and other per- The phrase iura et libertates that Ockham commonly used is often
sons, rights that came to them from natural law or the law of nations or found in medieval charters and other documents without any clear differ-
civil law. Without cause and without fauJt the pope ought not to disturb entiation of meaning between the two terms; but Ockham does, sometimes
these rights of others.60 His power did not extend to anything severely at least, seem to have had a distinction in mind. In the An princeps Ock-
prejudicial to "the temporal rights and liberties conceded by God and ham several times qualified the word iura with the adjective temporalia.64
nature."6' When he wrote of iura here, the rights he had especially in mind seem
There were difficulties in this argument that Ockham could foresee. to have been those inhering in temporal offices and properties, rights of
When he took up the same theme in the Dialogus he had the Student protest possession. But libertates could mean something different. When Ockham
that the scriptural texts on evangelical liberty referred only to freedom introduced the theme of supererogatory works in the Breviloquium, he
from sin or from the demands of the Mosaic law. The Master, however, wrote that not only must rights be respected but also "the liberties granted
explained that Christian liberty would be meaningless if the pope were to mortals by God and nature."6.S Ockham often used "liberty" convention-
empowered to impose even heavier burdens on the faithful than the Old ally to contrast with servitude as in the phrase "the natural liberty by
Law did on the Jews. The Student further objected that the argument from which men are naturally free and not slaves"; 66 but when discussing works
evangelical liberty seemed to exclude all servitude in Christian societies. of supererogation he had in mind a further meaning, liberty as defining a
The Master replied that servitude could be introduced by human law; his core of spiritual autonomy inherent in the human person, granted "by God
point was that the law of Christ itself did not enslave anyone.62 and nature," a freedom of choice in responding to divine love and divine
In the An princeps Ockham was principally concerned with temporal demands. Supererogatory works, like entering a monastery or vowing to
rights. In other works he emphasized equally the spiritual liberties of fast on bread and water, belonged in a realm of moral freedom, outside the
Christians, especially as regards works of supererogation. Such things as scope of government concern.
taking a vow of virginity, fasting on bread and water, or renouncing all of Modem writers have argued about whether a right is to be defined
one's property were certainly not contrary to divine or natural law. They as essentially a "protected interest" or a "protected choice." Ockham in-
were indeed works of Christian perfection. Yet the pope could not regu- cluded both concepts in the phrase iura et libertates. The temporal iura can
larly command such things because, once again, to do so would be con- best be understood as interests; the libertates related to areas of free moral
trary to the liberty of gospel law.63 choice.67
Although there is so much emphasis on individual rights in Ockham's
Quare non solum est falswn papam habere huiusmodi plenitudinem potestatis, sed etiam political works, he was not presenting a theory of social atomism. His de-
est haereticum, pemiciosum et pe.riculosum mortalibus universis." fense of rights was always balanced by a concern for the common good or
tiO. Ibid., 244, "Quemadmodum igitur a praedicta generalitate, qua dicitur: Quodcunque common utility (Ockham used the terms indifferently). Ockham expressed
ligaveris, etc. excipi debent illa . .. quae essent in notabile et enorme detrimentum et dis· this concern in several ways. He cited the familiar Aristotelian view that a
pendium ltbertatum et iurium temporalium imperatorum, regum, principum et aliorum
laicorum et etiam dericorum, quae eis iure naturali, gentium vel civili ante vel post institu- - --- - -- - - - -
tionem legis evangelkae competebant. Ad illa enim potestas papalis regulariter mini me se pane et aqua, saltem extra necessitatem extremam, iniungere, et cuilibet pro sue arbitrio vol-
extendit, cum absque causa et sine cuJpa iura turbare non debeat aliorum, Extra, de iudiciis, untatis abdicationem proprietatis omnium rerum indicere. Quare posse! de iure maioribuA
Novit." The decretal Nwil was the one in which Innocent JU wrote that he did not intend to oneribus premere christianos, quam unquam fuerint oppressi ludei, quod libertati t>van-
"disturb" the rights of the king of France. The principle that a right could not be taken away gelice legis obviat manifeste.•
wii:.Jut fault or cause, often repeated by Ockha.m, was stated in the Ordinary Gloss to X.1 .2..2. 64. An princeps, OP 1: 6, 250 Niura legitima temporalia"; "salvis iuribus temporalibu!l 1111h
s.v. Culpa caret, cited in the ONO, OP 2: 61, 559. The phrase "sine culpa vet sine causa" was ditorum el libertates"; 251, " iun"bus temporaJibus ac libertatibus."
used by Hostiensis in his commentary on X.1.2.2. 65. Brroi/oq11ium, 2.17, 90- 91, "Nee solum iura i.mperatorum, regum et aliorum .. . Alll\I
61 . An princeps, OP 1: 6, 251, " ... per legationem generalem papa non habeat potestatem excipienda, sed etiam liber1ates a Deo et a natura concesse mortetlis excipi dcbcmt...."
reslringendi vel tollendi libertates fideliu.m roncessas a Deo et natura." 66. An princeps, OP I: 6, 24R, " ... libertas naturalis, qua homines naturalitet" 11unt Ul>t'rl rl
62. Dialogus, 3.1.1, 6- 7, 777-779. non servi. ..."
63. Bmriloquium, 2.17, 91-3, " Hee est enim libertas evangelice legis, quod observatoribus 67. The distinction l>t•lw1't't1 rlKl•IM '1!< chokes o r right!'I a!l inteorl'!'l!l, intmc.lun'tl by
eius sine culpa eorum extra articulum urgentis necessitatis et ma.nifestc utilitatis, ip!!is in- ninelttnlh·Ct'nlury c:.-rn1t11n lttrt•I•, '" 1dmll1u It> tht' mod~m di~tlnction bf'twttn 11rtlvl' anti
vitis, nichil precipue grave, quod s upererogationi11 e11t, v(') non I'll! cir iurr nalurali nt'c de pa.~!liv•• riRhl" but nol •1111t.. llw .,.,..., 111r 111·•1 pnlr of alleornaliv~s refcr11 mun> tu lhl' j111lllfl
iure divino expresso, potest imponl virtulc ciulldrm lt>gi11.... SI rnlm l'"I'" in huhmnodi 0
rnlion of riKht", thr ..,, 011Al 1111 .,.., In lht!h • 11111<•111 A " pmlf't1t•<I d\Cll«' m•y rrlrr lu • p11MIYr

haberet pot~tah'm conc:kndi k•Kt'tl obliKaloria11 1·hri!ltl11ni11 lnvlll!1, J>t-·t •111rm.-11111<111•• d1rii1· riKhl, r K·· lh1· rll(hl 11111'•111t11111l 1•t11v1111111t 11l t111M•t 11r wt11lvl' II. A "'pmtrdrd lnlfn'•t" mny rrfr1
Uanum "''R''n° lnvll11m lntratt rrliKi"'"'"' 1111nnw111111111r, rl 1·111 vo•llf'I h•h111t1111111111lh111111n 111 1111111 -· •lvt• 1ll(hl, 1• K, llH11l.hl 111Yllltt1111 whum w .. 1 ""'""'
-
1'l(l THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS OcKHAM: RICITT'S ANO SOME PROBLEMS Of POUTICAL THoUGHT 191

just government existed for the common good, not for the private advan- that the pope's authority extended to everything necessary to uphold th('
tage of the ruler.68 He also found a text of the Decretum asserting that Jaws faith and the common good "saving the rights and liberties of others
should be instituted "for the common utility of the citizens."69 From scrip- granted to them by God and nature.'172 •
ture he quoted the text "The kings of the gentiles lord it over them. Not so This is not the whole of Ockham' s argument. In the passage JUSt
you ...."(Luke 22.25-6) to prove that the papal office was one of service quoted, and in other contexts, the Franciscan wrote that on occasion (casu-
to the community not one of domination. Similarly, in arguing against an aliter), in case of extreme necessity or very g.reat utility, the pope could
imperial plenitude of power he wrote that the emperor could act only for interfere with the temporal rights of rulers and other persons in order to
~he co~~n ~tility.70 In using such language Ockham was not propound- defend the church against some extreme peril.73 It was the same with
mg a utilitanan theory of government in opposition to a rights-based works of supererogation. The pope could not normally impose such tasks,
theory in the manner of some later utilitarians. Rather he maintained that but there could be exceptions in a case of "necessity or utility tantamount
the.co~on utili~ nor:mally required rulers to respect the natural rights of to necessity.'174 On occasion (in casu) the pope did have the power to im-
their subJects. Christ dtd not want the pope to rule for his own advantage, pose a task such as fasting on bread and water for some necess~ry pur-
Ockham wrote, but for the common utility. Then he added, "And therefore pose, for instance to punish a crime (though, as Ockham noted, if such a
the supreme pontiff does not have power from Christ to despoil others of task were carried out under compulsion, it would not really be a work of
their liberties, rights and goods by his arbitrary will.'171 Elsewhere he wrote supererogation).75 It seems that, for Ockham, common utility prevailed
over private rights in the last resort. But this is still not quite the end of
68. Brroifoquium, 2.5, 60, " Nam principatus apostolicus seu papalis non minus institu- his argument. Ockham was not content to leave it to the pope alone to
~s est propter communem utilitatem fidelium, quam principatus secularis temperatus et decide what powers he could exercise even in case of necessity. The first
iustus propter utilitatem subiectorum; qui tamen propter utilitatem subclitorum institutus infallible rule in such matters, he wrote, was "scripture and right rea-
est secundum mundi sapientem in Politkis" (referring to Aristotle, Politics, 3.6). See also son." So, if the pope erred in defining his own power, all those who knew
An princqJS, OP 1: 2, 233, n • • • non in periculum sed ad utilitatem fidelium receperunt a
Domino potestatem. .. . n, 240, " ... a Deo mediante populo, qui accepit potestatem a Deo
from scripture and necessary reason that he erred were bound to rebuke
praeficiendi sibi regem propter bonum commune"; Octo quaestiontS, OP 1: 8.5, 197, "Quia
natura optimi modi monarchiae regalis . .. in hoc consistit, quod est institutus propter bonum
co_mmune subiectorum et non propter utilitatem, honorem et gloriam principantis . .. "; n . Ibid., 245, " . .. data fuit sibi a Christo potestas in hiis, quae bono communi profici-
D1alogus, 3.2.2.20, 918, " .. . nee imperator potest eis hoc praecipere absque utilitate boni unt, salvo in temporalibus iure aliorum... ."; Brtvi!oquium, 2.20, 99, " ... potestas pa-
~munis. . .." These are just a few typical examples. Ockham referred to government in- palis . .. se extendit ad omnia que necessaria sunt pro regimine populi christiani . . . 53lvis
s~1tuted for the common good or common utility in dozens of places, scattered throughout iuribus et libertatibus aliorum eis concessis a Deo et a natura."
his later works. But, in spite of this emphasis on the common good, Ockham did not have 73. An princtps, OP, 1: 5, 244, " Ad quae tamen casualiter, puta in casu summae utilitatls
a very positive view of the functions of government. In the Octo qUlltstionrs he wrote that a vel vicinae aut extremae necessitatis vel propinquae, rationabile sit ut se possit extendtrl',
ruler was instituted "principalissime ... ut corrigat et puniat delinquentes" (3.9, 110). quatenus communitati fidelium in omnibus necessariis per Christum provisum erat, nl' l'X ·
69. Brroiloquium, 25, 60. "Amplius leges civiles pro nullo privato rommodo, sed pro bono tremo exponatur periculo propter ignorantiam, ignaviam, impotentiam, pusillanimitatt'm,
comm uni debent institui, dist. 4. Erit auttm." Dist. 4 c.2, of the Decrttum stated, "Lex erit hon- quamcunque libidinem vel malitiam quorumcunque."
esta, iusta ... nullo privato commodo, sed pro commune civium utilitate conscripta.n 74. Ibid ., 7, 252, "Qui etiam casualiter tam in spirituaJibus aliis, quae scilicet regularitrr
Ockham quoted the text again in An princqJS, OP 1: 2, 233 and Dialogus 3.2.2.27, 923. supererogationis sunt et in quibus fideles reguJariter licite possunt quod volunt fare,., q1111m
70. ~imp. d pont. pot., 6, 462. After quoting Luke 22, Ockham continued," . .. id est in temporalibus, quandam habet plenitudinem potestatis: ut scilicet in casu, quo n«t'S.W t'!ll
n~- debet~ eis p rincipari propter utilitatem vestram temporalem vel gloriam, sed propter talia fieri et nemo est, ad quern talia spectent, qui de ipsis d iligentiam habeat congruentrm,
utihtatem 1psorum, ut vere a serviendo et ministrando, idest procurando utilitatem vobis ipse habeat potestatem de talibus disponendi.... "; ~imp. d ponl. pol., 5,_459, "Supere"'K"
subiectorum, vere servi et ministri did valeatis eorum, et vester principatus non dominativus, toria etiam excipi debent, que licet papa etiam christi.anis valet suadere, sine culpa tamrn 1•1
sed ministrativus debeat nuncupari." For a typical te.xt on imperial power see Dialog11s, absque causa rationabili el manifesta, scilicet extra casum nccessitatis et utilitati11, qur 1'4'<'1,.
3.2.2.27, 912, u • • • sed limitata est potestas, ut quo ad liberos sibi subiectos et res eorum sitati valeat comparar;, nulli chrisliano, qui ad huiusmodi ~ullatenus ~ lp:nim oh~1K11v lt .
solummodo ilia potest, quae prosunt ad communem utilitatem"; 3.2.2.28, 924, n • • • quod videtur sub d istricti<>nc pf'l'('l'pti iniunK''"'· . .... There is a similar reservation m1wrrn111K tllf'
placet principi, scilicet imperatori, rationabile et iuste propter bonum commune legis habet case of n('("('S.o;ity o r utility n1mparahh• to nt'<'1'!<llity in Rrroilllq11iu111, 2.17, 91 11nd Orio 'I""""
vigorem." lim1r:<, OI' I: l.7r1S.
71. An princtps, OP 1: 5, 244, "No n enim Christus voluit omnes homincs servituti sum mi ~- I>ial"f(u~. :l.2 .1.7, •,;\!\, " •(111"111lh(lll• fnd .tl 41(1q11hl. •)mld t'l'I :oupt•rrn'l(atlonh<. nulh
pontificis subiugare nee vult i.p sum praeesse aliis propter propriam, ;oaf proptt>r communt"m p11tc~t rr"1'C'ipc'l1" nl~l In 1·••111111•11•111 .. _, ,,.. llt'<'t'NOlllll.. fnrlrnclum. "' tum· non ....,.... rrp
utilitatem. Et ideo non habet pontifex summu~ 11 Oiri:oto pol«':"tAll'm pro""""' nrhllrlo volun· 111,ul ~uprn•rt>j1,ntlo11ia, ....1 ""' 11H•1h11n ah 111 1•1111•trr n 1lp11m pt,.,...,
4111<'111 P'""'·lprh'
tatis spoliandi alios llb<-rtatihu~. i11rih1111. t•I n•hu• .. . .·· ll'hlllllll' In p1111r rl "'I""· v11l l11f1 "'" 1111111,ulrl 111111 vrl .. 1111111<1 l111l11a1tul<ll "
192 1HE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS CX:KHAM: RIGHTS AND SoME PROBLEMS OF POLITICAL THOUGHT 193

him.76 After repeating that in case of necessity the pope's power could supererogation. It was commonly understood that they should be under-
exten~ to temporal affairs and matters that were regularly works of super- taken voluntarily and Ockham could, quite appropriately, cite the Ordi-
erogation, Ockham summed up by noting that, in such circumstances, "IJ nary Gloss to the Decretum when he wanted to make the same point."1
his decree is just and useful others are bound to obey; if it is unjust and The new feature of Ockham's work was that all these conventional as-
useless others are bound to resist."71 Ockham's argument has been seen as sertions were set in a framework of discourse about natural rights, the
an "exaltation of human will" creating a disjunction between the general rights granted to humankind "by God and nature." Ockham's persistent
and rational character of law and the decisions of individual wills resisting emphasis on natural rights as setting limits to a ruler's power has no clear
it.71 But this was not what Ockham was arguing. For him, scripture and precedent in earlier writings.82 But, of course, it had a considerable futul"l'
~ght reason, not naked will, de.f ined both the power of the pope and the in later rights theories.
nghts of the faithful. The gap in Ockham's theory is the absence of any in-
stitutional machinery to mediate between ruler and community in case of A RIGHTS-BASED POLITICAL THEORY?
dispute. In the end the decision to obey or resist is left to the individual
conscience-but to a conscience informed by reason and scripture. Should we say then in the end that Ockham created, perhaps for
There is nothing especially radical or novel about the particular limits the first time, an ecclesiology and political theory founded on the concept
to papal power that Ockham wanted to establish. The doctrine that the of natural rights? It depends on how we define a rights-based theory.
pope did not normally intervene in temporal affairs but could do so casu- Some modem scholars have set rather exacting criteria. L. W. Sumner, for
aliter, in exceptional circumstances, was rooted in a decretal of Innocent III instance, has argued that such a theory must define natural rights as free-
that had attracted a considerable body of canonistic commentary.79 Every- doms (choice rights), and treat such rights "and nothing else" as morally
one agreed that government was instituted for the common good, and basic.83 Sumner acknowledges a little ingenuously, that his definition ex-
probably no one would have denied that the papal office was one of min- cludes all the major rights theories of the early modem period . And one
istry or service to the church. After all, the official title of the pope was may indeed doubt whether any current rights theory would satisfy his
"Servant of the servants of God," and the Ordinary Gloss to the Decretals, criteria. Nowadays, even the most extreme libertarian proponents of indi·
commenting on these words, recalled the scriptural admonition, "Who is vidual natural rights will usually defend those rights by appealing to more
greater among you, let him be your minister."80 So too with works of basic moral arguments about human personality.84 There seems to be a sort
of Godel's theorem that applies to legal and political systems of thought,
including those that emphasize rights; they all depend on some premise
76. An princ:eps, OP 1: 6, 251. "Sed quaeret aliquis, si non est specialiter et in particu-
lari expressum in quibus casibus habeat potestatem . .. ad quern pertinet explicare et de-
drawn from outside the system itself. This is what we find in Ockham. He
terminare in quibus casibus papa habeat potestatem, et in quibus non habeat potestatem? de rived both natural rights and natural law from "right reason," from an
Huie respondetur quod prima regula et infallibilis in huiusmodi est scriptura sacra et ratio underlying view of human persons as rational, free, and morally respon-
recta.. .. Si tam.en papa contra veritatem in huiusmodi determinare praesumpserit, sibi nul- sible. It is the same attitude we found also in earlier canonistic treatments
latenus est credendum; sed illi, qui per scripturas sacras et rationern necessariam sciunt of ius naturale.
ipsum errare, loco et tempore opportunis, allis circumstantiis debitis observatis, eum repro-
bare tenentur. . .." Following a suggestion of Ronald Dworkin, Sumner also pointed out
77. Ibid., 252, " ... cuius dispositioni, si iusta et utilis fuerit, am obedire lenentur; si that a true rights-based theory must be distinguished from theorit.>S tha t
autem iniusta fuerit et inutilis, alii sibi resistere obHgantur."
78. M Bastit, N11iSS1met de IA loi modnnt (Paris, 1990), 303. 81. Breviloquium, 2.17, 91, citing the gloss ad C.32 q .1 c.13.
79. In the dec:retal Per VCttrllbiftm (X.4.13.17) Innocent UI declared that, although he 82. There are many discussions of limitations to a ruler 's power by divint' and na turnl
did not normally exercise temporal jurisdiction outside the papal states, he could do so on law bul only scattered references to individual natural rights in this conteict. E.g.• tht• dvillnn
occasion (CllSVll/iter). " .. . certis causis inspectis, temporalem iurisdictionem casualiter exer- jurist Odofrcdus wrote tha t the emperor could not arbilrarily deprive suhjcct~ of th1•ir l'" 'I'
cemus." Odcham quoted these words in 81Tt1iloquium, 2.15, 86. The canonists commonly t•rty "because natural righls art" immutabll•." 5l'e his Pratltclionrs i11 . • • l>("l~lw11 ""'''""
glossed the decretal by presenting long lists of the specific cases in which the pope could (Lyons, 1552), fol. 1q3 ra, "Sl'd """In h11<· qul'~linnf' didmm quod illud quod cnmpc•til mihl
intervene in temporal cases. Oclcham, as noted above, took a different approach. Jn t.h e Dill- naturali ratione cl equitalt•, ut 1.lnml11h1111 rl"i n11... ... non pol<'!lt to lll'll', q11i11 l11r11 n11llm\ll11
logus, after referring to the pope's extraordinary power in case of necessity, he wrote, Hit is not ~uni imm1,.,ili11: ·
easy to explain all the cases individually in which he can do the abovl' m~ntiont'd things o r R1. 1.. W. Sumtw•r, Tl1t M ,,r.i/ fou,,,l1ll lm1 it/ H1.11l,I.• fl >•fnnl, l'IK7). Hit.- IOK.
any of them, and perhaps it is not possibl~ to giv~ 11 univl'r11&l fl•"rhln)t n>n<...,rninK tlwm . . ." H4 s...... K T I< M111fo111. """'"" "'""'" ""'' " " ""'" l .ilN"rlll'.• (<"hk11x1•. 1'>7~). 24H
(DUllOKUS, 3.1.1.16, 786). "Tl"llll' mur11l 1•ol11t 111 vt.. w lrnm whh h h111t11111 tlKhl• ur 1h•rlvC'<l I" murt' l•11"l• lh"" lt11m1m
!Ml. G lo!lll ad X f'n>f''1ti11m" v Strm1• 1l11ht• ..
194 THE IDEA OF NATURAL R IGHTS

are based on duties or on goals (i.e., utilitarian or other "consequentiaHst"


doctrines). There are evident differences between the various approaches;
but perhaps we ought not to draw the lines of distinction between them
too sharply. In making a moral or political decision a reasonable person
will often consider all three factors. And it seems a matter of common
sense that, depending on the circumstances, sometimes one consideration
will prevail, sometimes another. The rights involved may be trivial and the
goal of paramount importance-or vice-versa. Sometimes there may be a
duty to relinquish rights and sometimes a just ground for asserting them.
This is the kind of argument that we find in Ockham. He often asserted the EIGHT
rights of individuals but also maintained that political society had a goal,
, .:., : .:" :" '·:,, .:-.: t :. :, '
the common good or common utility.85 Usually a person's natural and civil
rights could be invoked against attempted abuses of a ruler's power; but
occasionally, in cases of urgent necessity, the requirements of the common POSTSCRIPT
good might prevail over the rights of an individual.
Such considerations may persuade us that Ockham did not create
a "pure" rights-based theory. Perhaps no one has ever done so. But Ock-
ham's writings on ecclesiology and political thought were certainly per-
vaded by a real concern for what we now call human rights, rights granted lf n the preceding chapters I have been trying to place Ockharn in a t~adi­
to the whole human race "by God and nature." Ockham wrote of alienable JL tion of thought that led from medieval jurisprudence to modem nghts
natural rights and of at least one inalienable natural right, the right of self- theories. But, to understand how Ockham could come to play a major role
preservation. We can find in his work suppositious natural rights that in a process of historical developm~nt tha~ he him_sel~, in~tably,.was en-
depended on the enactment of some preceding human law; also active tirely unaware of, we need primanly to s1t:uate h~ in his own time and 1
rights and passive rights; rights considered as "protected choices" and as place and in his own world of thought. In mtroduong Ockham s work, I
"protected interests," rights related to human liberty and to human wel- suggested that we need to consider it in three contexts-the context of t~c
fare. Ockharn did not set out to construct a systematic body of thought real-life struggles in which he became engaged, the context of Ockham s
about natural rights and he did not opt for the distinctive solutions that own earlier reflections on philosophy and moral theology,.and the conte~t
would later be embodied in some particular modem rights theory. Instead, of the canonistic sources on which he so often relied. It will be helpful, m
like the juristic works that he cited, he presented elements of thought that conclusion, to consider each of these themes in tum.
would be used to sustain a variety of later theories. The first context need not detain us long. Everyone agrees that Ock-
ham's involvement in the ecclesiological and political issues that dom i·
nated the last twenty years of his life came about fortuitously. His early
writings display no interest in such themes. There is no reason to suppMt'
that he would ever have given his mind to them if he had not happened to
be in Avignon on other business when the conflict ~tween John_ XXll anci
Michael of Cesena broke out. We need to add that it was not simply tht•
fact of the conflict and Michael's flight to the protection of the emperor thn I
shaped the content of Ockham's polemical writings, but also the fim• dt•tnll
85. Ockham provided a fine p iece of "consequentialist" rhetoric when he deplored the o f the issues involvt'd . To follow the argument of the OND we need to lw
evil results of papal absolutism, Dt imp. et pont. pot., 7, 461, "The churches are afflicted with
acquainted with all tht• twb1tH nnd turn~ of the earlier exchanges hctwt'l'n
unbearable burdens, indeed reduced to servitude against the evangelical liberty divinely
and humanly granted, licit oaths are relaxed, s ubjects of pri~ an- IOO!led fmm f('alty and John XXll and th<' Mkhn1•llP1t l'rnndM<"am1. To under.;tand what Wi\11 Jh•·
due service, the bonds of human !IOCiety are di11ruptc>d ... thf' (lf'Oplt< dt'!llmy1'<I . . tl•'!tlru<"- tinctiv<' in rkkhnm '1t tl11111~hl "huul rl~hlH wt• nt.'t•d lo be famlllnr with tlw
tion and confu.'llon rel~. clth'f' ""' huml'<l ... imd all an- 1•1tp<1"MI to . llvrrM pc·rll1< •·
Jiii\
196 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS POSTSCRIPT 197

views of various other participants in the poverty dispute. To see the point enough to be a scholastic philosopher in the first place was quite capable of
of some of the later political writings on papal-imperial relations we associating any preferred set of metaphysical premises with any chosen
would need to know about such things as the Anglo-imperial alliance of political stance. Ockham's theory of rights was compatible with his nomi-
1337, the Declaration of Rense issued by the German princes in 1338, the nalist philosophy, but it was also compatible with any philosophy that
iar.;-~nal decree Licet iuris promulgated in the same year, and the Tyrolese acknowledged-as all Christian philosophers did- the existence and
marriage dispute of 1342. These are obvious points. But, given the current value of individual human persons.
fashion for discussing political theories as though they were simply ex- Ockham's supposed voluntarism might seem to provide a more ob-
emplifications of different languages of discourse, it may be worthwhile vious link between his philosophy and hls political theory. Even if meta-
to mention them. As Ian Shapiro has pointed out, we cannot understand physica1subtleties have no necessary connection with political ideas, we
political ideas merely by a formalistic study of "matrices of language.''1 cannot say the same about theories of human psychology and human be-
To become meaningful the language has to be situated in the real world of havior. Understandably, therefore, Bastit especially emphasized Ockham's
the writer. voluntarism in his treatment of this issue. But unfortunately, while an em-
Still, the matrices of language are important. A person can think or phasis on Ockham's nominalism is merely lacking in explanatory force in
write only in the languages available to him, languages that will typi- relation to his political thought, an emphasis on his voluntarism can lead
cally include not only a vocabulary of words but a vocabulary of taken- to radical misjudgments concerning it. Bastit suggested that the ideas
for-granted assumptions. And a major problem in coming to terms with Ockham developed in reflecting on the omnipotence of God served later to
Ockham, as I noted at the outset, is to decide whether the language of exalt the power of the emperor.4 In this interpretation, Ockham conceiv<'d
nominalism and voluntarism associated with his early work can help us of political authority simply as "power, that is to say will." His treatment
to understand his later thought on ecclesiology and political theory in- of individual rights and liberties also reflected "an exaltation of the human
cluding, especially, his teaching on natural rights. The older interpretation will." Bastit deployed a similar argument to explain Ockham's teaching on
of writers like de Lagarde and Villey, asserting a close interdependence the intrinsic nature of law. Since all existing reality is contingent on the will
between the two areas of thought, has recently been restated in an uncom- of God, which might change, there can be no law rooted in the inherent
promising fashion by Michel Bastit. But it still offers difficulties. Among nature of things. Law is detached from any essential end. Its definition, for
writers who support this position we can read over and over again that, on Ockham, no longer includes justice as an essential criterion. "(ljhe whole
the level of political discourse, Ockham's nominalism led to "social atom- being of law consists in its being willed by the legislator." 5
ism." (De Lagarde expressed the same thought with a welcome change of But all this is only a kind of imaginary extrapolation of what Ockham
terminology when he referred to the " individualist microbe" that Ockham might have written if he had set out to base a political theory on an anal-
introduced into medieval thought.}1 But a word like "atomism" does not ogy with his theology of the absolute power of God. Ockham had no such
adequately convey Ockham' s persistent concern for the common good. intention . For him the divine will and human wills were incommensu-
Moreover, no necessary link between nominalism and political theory was rable. In God there was no distinction between will and intellect; alt that
asserted in Ockham's work; and, among medieval authors generally, there God willed was just and right. A human will, on the other hand, could
seems to be no correlation between a writer's theory of universals and choose good or evil, and so needed to be guided by reason.6 Ockham'!'I
his political orientation. Ockham and Wyclif were both radical critics of teaching on God's absolute power was simply irrelevant to the argument!'I
the fourteenth-century papacy and defenders of the secular power, but he developed in his political writings. What conceivable purpose could
Ockham was a nominalist and WycliJ was a realist. Many more examples have been served, in the context of those works, by Ockham asserting that,
of such incongruities were given by Charles Zuckerman in a penetrating
article on this theme.3 It seems that any medieval author who was clever 4. Naissance dt la /oi modt'rnt (Pari~. 1990), 243, H • •• les doctrines philrn1ophitJu•·• .-1
lh~ologiques, penstts ... pour t'xalt!'r la lout puissance de Dieu . . . vont pouvnlr 11e·rvlr lr/'Jo
1. I. Shapiro, #Realism in the Study of the History of ldeas,n History of Politic11/ Thought 3 ..rficact>mc nl a exaltl'r II' rouvolr .1.. 1·..mpc-rt•u r contre It' pape. • • •H; 303, HOckh11m rl•t<"t• In
(1982): 535- 78. , ·1ml<'tilahll'mrnl 1°1.'S.'14.' ll<"t' .It• 111 lo l tli11\A J.• 1lc'd!<i1m volont.a irt'. CC'lll' volonlil l'l'l, 1m him '"'llr
2. L4 n11iSS11nu de /'esprit l11i"q11e 1111 dtclin du moyen dgr, 5 vols . 2nd ed. (Paris, 1956-70), tit> Dil'u, ou t'l'lk- d1• J'f'mpt'n'llr . -
5:334. ~. lh i1l.. 300, 302, 103
3. C. Zuckt'rman, "Tut' Rt'lationship of llwori<'!I of U nivC'rll11l1< lo llu><iril'1' o f Chur<h h . ll1•1'lll i•o1tKhl h • 1low11pl11v I lo ~h11111 "• 1 111111111tll•m hv "'KulnK 1h11t, fnr th•• l'r1uwtiw·•n.
Govt'Tllmmt: A C riliqut' of l'n•v io11!4 ViC'w!<." /c>urnnl "' thr /IM11n1 "/ I.Im~ :\<; ( 11171)· 'l7Q <;QO. thn1• w11" 110 11•111 111flf'lt!llnt t..twt'f'i. " ' "''"" 111111 will SM• lhl•I . 2~2 - . 111 r11hoon. tl11n• 111
198 Tm IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS POSTSCRll"T 199

through his absolute power, God could have created some other uni- In spite of all these difficulties we may still expect to find some mean-
verse of moral values? In some other universe Pope John XXll might have ingful relationship between Ockham's early views on moral ~eory a~~
been right alJ along and the Franciscans wrong. Ockham wanted only to his later political thought. As I once wrote, in reading Ockha.m s work, ~t
prove that the pope was wrong in this present universe that God had ac- is one mind we have to deal with not two." And if we set aside the nom:-
tuaUy made. nalism and voluntarism that seem to have little relevance fo~ Ockh~m s
Interpretations of Ockham as an extreme voluntarist sometimes at- ideas on natural law and natural rights, and tum instead to his teac~mgs
tribute to him views precisely the opposite of those that he actually held.7 on " non-positive moral science," where he emphasized reason as a d1rec~~
It was Ockham's high papalist adversaries who wanted to make their ing norm for the will, there is indeed a perfect coherence between his
ruler a sort of God on earth whose every volition could create law. It was earlier and later thought. . .
they who maintained that an unjust command of a pope created valid law, Whenever Ockham discussed natural law or natural nghts he persi~-
imposing an obligation to obey, even if the pope sinned in issuing such tently appealed to right reason as the ground of his argument. Ockham did
a decree. Ockham attacked this position over and over again; as we saw, not, as has been suggested, abandon the idea of a ra~onal natura_t law ~y
he held that such decrees were void because ultra vires. If Ockham had emphasizing arbitrary divine commands and then fill the resultmg void
wanted to create a voluntarist theory of law there were plenty of suitable with a body of natural rights based on individual wills. 11 Inst~ad~ whether
texts in the works available to him. He could read in the Ordinary Gloss to he defined natural right (ius polr) in a subjectiv~ sense or an,?bJeCh~~ sense,
the Decretals, "In the things (the pope) wills, his will stands for reason .. . in either case his definition was grounded on nght reason. lus polr is no~h­
nor is there anyone who shall say to him, 'why do you act thus?"'8 Under- ing other than a power conformed to right rea~n. : .." And then ag~1~'.
standably, in view of his opinion of the popes who were his contempo- "lus poli means natural equity ... consonant with nght reason . . . this is
raries, Ockham did not embrace this point of view. In the Dialogus Ockham sometimes called natural law... .''12 ForOckham a natural right was not an
did have the Student quote another famous voluntarist text of Roman and assertion of naked will but a power conformed to reason. Similarly, when
canon law, "What has pleased the emperor has the force of law"; but the Ockham gave his more complex, multi-layered definition of natural law
Master explained that this really meant "What the emperor wills rationally in the Dialogus, each of the three modes ~e desa?bed was derived from
and justly and for the common good . ..."9 Ockham did not believe that reason as it was exercised in different contingent arcumstances. .
will was the only criterion of valid law. His own view is perhaps con- Ockham deployed the argument from reason at ~very level of ~1.s
veyed in a text of the Decretum that he cited several times with approval, discourse. Applied to the intricate details of the Francisca~ poverty dis-
"Law shall be worthy, just, possible, in accord with nature . . . necessary, pute, it showed that the friars could )ustly use, by natural nght, property
useful, clear . . . enacted for the common utility of the citizens."10 belonging to others because they used in a manne~ ~onformed to ~ason:
On a broader scale, Ockham's teaching on the ongm of property 1~ t~l
pensee occamlenne, n'est pas un realit~ distincte de la volonte... .n Referring to reason and OND seems a precise exemplification of his rat~onal moral theory. A. d1e·
will again, Bastit wrote, " mais chez Occam ii n'y a pas de di.ffemce de l' une a l'autreN(2n).
But this is an oversimplification. Ockham held that reason and will were not separately ex-
tate of reason" showed that individual properties ought to be estabhsht>J
isting realities because they were both activities of the same rational soul. But they were among sinful humans; a series of voluntary acts then impl_e~entcd ~e~­
distinct activities. Hence Ockham could write that reason directed the will "as something son's directive. On the highest level, the criterion f~~ determ1~10g t~c hcil·
other than itsell" (OTh, 8: 410). ness of a pope's command was "necessary reason al?ng with scnptun•.
7. Sometimes the misunderstandings arise because of errors in the transmission of All medieval and early modem thinkers who considered these qtws·
Ockham' s texts. According to Goldast and the tdilio princeps of 1494, Ockham wrote in the
D11dog11s of Nmoralia quae nulla possunt ratione muniri," ..moral principles that can be de-
tions realized that both reason and will were necessary for_the ~ndud
fended by no reason" (1.1.8, 405). This has been seen as a striking example of Ockham's o f h uman a ffa 1·rs.n
, but if we have to divide them into ratmnahsls· ;md I
voluntarism in moral theory. But a check of the manuscripts indicates that what Ockham ac- voluntarists according to their emphases, Ockham clearly belongs m 1 w
tually wrote was, Nmoralia quae nulla possunt ratione mutari." Ockham was referring to rationalist camp.
immut.lble moral principles, not irrational ones. On this text see my article, " Natural law
and Canon Law in Ockham's Dililops" (above, 102.• n. 34).
8. Gloss lld X.1.7.3. On this text see K. Pennington, Popt and Bishops. Tht Papal Monarchy I I. M. Villt•y. I .11 {c•rmalum cir /11 1.,.,..,.,. j11111l1q11r m cHl,.ml'. 4th t'tl. (l'1ul1<, 1'175), 21tll::·1...,.
in the Tult.lfth and Thirtmrth Ctnl11riG (Philadelphia, 1984), 117- 25. olrnil:< ""hj<"<tif~ clr11 lnillvhlu11 0111 romhl" Ir 1•11lr 1Ni11ll"nt 1lf' In J"C'flr tlu 1lrnll n"l11rrl.
9. Dililog11s, 3.2.2. 26-28, 923- 24.
10. Dist. 4 c.3. On the words "acrnrJlng to n11t11n-" thr ( lrtlina')I I ;1•.,.,. 1·unmw111t•<I, "that
12 <JNI II,,. 2 (11\, '"14 .,., . .
n . l'nr .,;, r-i-..llt1t1I tll•• 11..-i." 1ul u•11•n1111wl will In 11u-.l11•v11l j11rl"l'r111lr111 r,..... I· ( 111
i8, natural ~•11on.N for ()ckh11m'• """of tl'M' trxl,..... nhovr, IQCI n f•'' r,..'. I 11111•1ma .111111tcl/111, J vul• CMll1111 l'lf•J Ml. J 141 1'"
POSTSCRIYT
201
200 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS

Modem arguments that invoke the absolute will of an arbitrary and almost entirely on texts from scripture and canon law. And s~~etimes he
inscrutable deity as a necessary background for understanding Ockham's used canon law to show what scripture must have meant. ThJS 15 the final
teaching on law and rights seem to overlook the friar's commitment as a context within which we need to consider Ockham's work.
Christian and a Franciscan. Ockham not only believed that God, in his in- Ockham's later writings are saturated with canonistic citations. T_he
finite goodness, had chosen to create the universe we live in; he also knew fact has often been noticed; but it has commonly been assumed that with
from scripture that God loved the world he had made. 14 So Ockham never a sort of devilish ingenuity (or "insidious subtlety" in the phrase of de La-
doubted that, in this world made by a loving God, the divine will willed garde), Ockham used the canonistic texts only as a sort of ornamental
the good of humankind. He also believed that God had endowed humans facade to hide his real purpose, which was to construct a new language of
with a faculty of reason through which they could discern that good. It politics radically subversive of the canonists' own doctrines. But this view
has been argued that, in Ockham's way of thinking, since natural law was is mistaken. It reflects an unawareness of the abundance and variety of
in the end nothing but a particular manifestation of God's will, humans earlier canonistic thought on the questions Ockham discussed. Ockham
could not find in themselves the means to attain a natural end. •s But did not set out to construct some novel theory of his own invention about
Ockham did see such a natural end for humans-to live and to live weU- papal-imperial relations or evangelical poverty or about natural rights and
and he maintained that reason could discern this end and the means to natural law. On the contrary he wanted to show that he could appeal to
attain it. Moreover, he was serenely confident that the end perceived by the traditional law of the church to defend his own views against oppos-
reason and the necessary means to the end were in accord with God's ing ones that he regarded as harmful innovations. He did not intend _to
will. Reason showed, for instance, that humans required certain rights if subvert the foundations of canonistic jurisprudence; he wanted to build
they were to live and live well; so Ockham could take it for granted that on them.
God had given those rights to Adam and his progeny.16 Ockham was certainly at odds with the canonists of his own age
What God might have done differently-what kind of other world who were among the foremost supporters of papal absolutism. But the
he might have created or might create by virtue of his absolute power texts and glosses of the Decretum that he cited could support-~nd ~ad
and infinite reason-never came into question in Ockham's political writ- supported and would in future support-a varie~ o~ oth~r eccles1olog1es.
ings. We sometimes assume too readily that the fine-spun speculations Gratian had drawn his texts from every age of Christian history, and many
of philosophers and theologians about the manner of coexistence of reason of them did not reflect the extreme papalism that later became fashionable
and will in God were transferred wholesale to the authors' more mun- among the curial canonists. Moreover, Gratian p~ted his_texts in a dia·
dane reflections on law and politics. In fact this seems seldom to have been tectical form; each time he wanted to prove some point he first presented
the case. all the authorities that could be adduced for the opposing point of view.
Although the rational side of Ockham's early moral theory coheres This meant that, from the beginning, the Decretum was open to a wide va-
well with his view on law and rights one could not simply deduce the riety of interpretations.
later views from the earlier ones. An appeal to right reason can be, and I do not think that a student in the great law school of Bologna around
has been, used to support any number of different political theories. To 1200 would have found anything alien or perverse in Ockham's way of
understand the actual content of Ockham's work we therefore have to handling Decretist texts. He would already have been expo~ to many
consider- along with the real conflicts in which he became involved- and various interpretations of Gratian's work. Among the eminent mils·
the soun:es that he drew upon in framing his arguments. Much of what ters whose views he would have encountered some were staunch dt•·
Ockham wrote on ecclesiology and political theory could have been sup- fenders of papal absolutism, others favored more the imperial cauS(', and
ported with arguments drawn from earlier scholastic philosophers who still others defended the rights of national kings against the tempurnl
had criticized the more extreme claims of the papacy-John of Paris, for in- claims of both pope and emperor. Some thought that a . pope ~maid . lw
stance, or Henry of Ghent or Godfrey of Fontaines. But in fact, presumably deposed only for heresy, others maintained that any notonom1 cnme K;\Vt'
because of the limited resources available to him, Ockham based his case grounds for deposition, while still others held that no human trlhunnl
could depose a pope thouKh lw mlKht nutom~tically forfeit hiit office..'. hy
!wcoming a hl•ft'tk. AmonK lhr KloriHt•s of this p<'nod we can nli«l fmd
14. John 3 .16, •God so lo ved the world that he gave his only lx1(ollrn N<>n•• • : ·
15. NaisS11n~ dr la loi, ~2. mnny lldinitinm1 of lw• 11nl11mlr 11111h•r,.tood inn 1mbjl'l:tivl' lll'lll44' '"' 1\ forn•
16. Bm1iloquium, 3 .17, 127. Sc..- 11h<w.-, 17.l. or fonilty ,11011k·i11h•1I with 1-r1uu111, 1t111I '"' 1•mhry11nk tlodrlm• of nrtlurnl
203
POSTSCRIPT
202 THE I DEA OF N ATURAL R IGHTS

hen Ockham started out from a canonistic text or a series of odthem,


rights. It was pointed out long ago that, in formulating his views on papal ··ven w . m to us more like early m ern
heresy and related questions of ecclesiology, Ockham could find ample tlic outcome of his argument ~ay ~ . d Ockham took the
.. h J"ke medieval 1unspru ence.
support in these early glosses on the Decretum.17 We can add now that this i•nhhcal theory t an 1 H . mmuni·s 1• e communicanda
· od ed by uguccio co , ··
seems to be true also of his teaching on natural rights and natural law. The ,·,1nonistic phras~ mtr beuch d ") and u~d it as an argument against
Decretists had explored many pathways of thought that Ockham would ("common, that ts to s are ' that recurs in Locke. He
later retrace. /\dam's sole ownership of the wo;\d~=t~~;~:miniscent of Pufendorf's,
We do not know how much of the early Decretist literature Ockham built a coherent theory of proper y,D H defended the natural
became acquainted with during his study at Avignon of the poverty ques- .1round some scattered texts of the ecre1um: . e mbinin in
tion. Sometimes, it seems, he worked out for himself a line of argument ri~hts of subjects agai~~ the claims ~f ty_ra~tc~t~~~:~p~ral idea~ of
that some earlier canonist had explored, without being aware of his pre- .1 new way the canomshc concept o a ng Wtbsc doctrine of canon-
. 1 l"berty Ockham could even take an o ure
decessor's work. But often he found suitable arguments ready at hand in o·v~ngehca t . I. d tum it into an important principle of political
works that he certainly knew and often cited. The core ideas around ishc corporat~on aw. a~e was not embarking on a semantic revolution; he
which Ockham built his doctrine of natural rights and natural law are lhought. B_u t, mall th::~ablished tradition of juristic discourse in new an~i
genuine canonistic ones, not Ockhamist innovations or distortions. His was car,~mg aoynsanMaitland once wrote that, in its infancy, political ph1-
basic understanding of a right as something that a person could not be de- mteres mg w · I d " Ockham
prived of "without fault or cause" was taken directly from the ordinary losophy is apt to look li~e sub\~mated jurisprudence. n rea mg ,
glosses to the Decretum and the Decretals. His three modes of natural law we can see the sublimation taking place.
were all anchored in the texts of the Decretum. Ockham's teaching on the
natural right to use another's property in case of necessity was a standard
canonistic doctrine. His insistence that humans were by nature free and
not slaves reflected an ancient Stoic teaching, but Ockham again found his
authority for it in a text of the Decretum and its gloss.
Having said all this, we need finally to emphasize that Ockham was
not just a passive transmitter of earlier juristic ideas. He was not inter-
ested in pursuing the sort of legal archeology, the disinterring of old texts
for their own sake, that we find in a work like Guido de Baisio's Rosarium,
one of his possible sources. Instead, Ockham sought out the texts he
needed to serve his own purposes and deployed them creatively. Having
reappropriated or reinvented some earlier canonistic understandings of
ius naturale he went on to apply them to the problems of his own day; in
the precess they took on some new meanings and revealed new implica-
tions. The old texts also acquired a new significance from the fact that
Ockham was addressing an audience different from that of the Decretists,
not just a narrow circle of professional canonists but the whole intellectual
world of the Christian West. The language of rights continued to be used
in the works of late medieval jurists but, after Ockham, it increasingly in-
habited the realms of philosophy and political theory.
There was no "semantic revolution" (Villey) or "Copernican revolu-
tion'' (Bastit) in Ockham' s political works, but we can certainly find some
interesting evolutions of thought and language going on there. Sometimes,

17. See my article, #Ockham, tlw C onclliar Tht•o r y, im d ti"' C1111nni1t~." /111m 111/ fl/ lhf' Iii.<
tory of ldns 15 (1954): 40-70.
NINE

GERSON. CONCILIARISM, CORPORATISM,


AND INDIVIDUALISM

A fter the death of William of Ockham in 1347 the Franciscan war of


propaganda against the popes of Avignon died away. By the end
of the fourteenth century only a few scattered bands of Fraticelli defended
the doctrine of evangelical poverty that Pope John XXII had condemned.
But by then the church was tom apart by a still more grievous dispute, the
<;reat Schism that broke out in 1378. For nearly forty years, two and then
three would-be pontiffs contended for the throne of St. Peter. This intoler-
.1ble situation gave rise to the conciliar movement of church reform. When
.111 attempts at compromise and arbitration had failed, the conciliarists,
drawing on earlier currents of juristic thought, asserted that ultimate au-
thority in the church inhered in the whole Christian community, conceived
of as a corporate entity, a universitas .fidelium, and that a general council,
representing the universal church, was of greater authority than any pope.
Eventually a council did assemble. It removed all three claimants to thC'
papal throne by deposition or forced resignation and then elected a nl'w
pope who came to be universally recognized.
For us, an important aspect of the whole affair is that one of the prin-
d pal conciliar theorists, Jean Gerson, was also an important figure in tht•
d1·vi>lopmcnt of natural rights theories. This suggests two intt>rrt•lnh•d
probll•ms for investigation. flow nm WC' explain the coexistcnn• of corpo·
rntist conciliar and inJividunlisl ri~hts lht•ories in Gcrstm's work? Ami
what C'irn1mstann•s, wh.tl hh1l11rknl nmlt•xt, 11.J to his concrrn with nntu -
r.11 ri>~hls?
)II'/
208 THE IDEA OF N ATURAL RIGHTS
G ERSON. C ONCIU ARISM, C ORPORATISM, AND INDIVIDUALISM 209
INDIVIDUAL AND COMMUNITY
often regard Gerson as a typical exponent of this viewpoint. But scholars
. Duri~g the Romantic movement of the nineteenth century, many interested in other aspects of late medieval political thought have recently
wn_ters re1ected. the "atomistic," rationalistic, natural rights theories of the presented Gerson as a pioneer in the creation of an individualist theory of
Enhg~tenm~nt 1~ order to emphasize the values inherent in the group-life natural rights.6
of vanous h1stoncal communities. Since then, scholars in several fields- Both points of view seem defensible. Certainly, conciliar thinkers often
historians, anthropologists, sociologists-have emphasized the contrast argued from the holistic concept of the church as a mystical body, adapting
~tween a "h?lis_ti~" or _or~anic approach to the understanding of soci- the scriptural doctrine to their own purposes by reformulating it in juridi-
eties and an md1v1duahstic approach. (For medievalists the vast work cal or political language. A canonist like Zabarella would use the term
~f Gi~rke, devo~ed .essentially to an elaborate investigation of this distinc- corpus mysticum to describe, not only the universal church, but also lesser
tion, 1s o.f especial 1~portanc~.) 1 More recently, Louis Dumont, in setting corporative associations within the church like that of bishop-and-chapter.
the m~1eval e~pene~.ce ~gamst a broader anthropological background, Then he would apply the technical rules governing the affairs of such
has defined hohsm as an ideology that valorizes the social whole and ne- lesser corporations to explicate the constitutional structure of the whole
gle~ts or su~rdinat~ t~e.individual," and individualism as "an ideology church. Among recent authors, Eric Meuthen has observed that, with-
which valonzes the md1v1dual ... and neglects or subordinates the social out this background of corporatism, late medieval conciliarisrn would bt>
2
whole<' The ideology of individualism, so described, is usually seen as "unthinkable"; Antony Black noted that "ecclesiastical holism remained
the basis of modem natural rights theories. Indeed, a common criticism of a standard weapon in the conciliarist armoury"; and Joseph Wohlmuth
such ~heories, one that comes from both ends of the political spectrum, left specifically contrasted conciliar corporatism with modem individualism.
and nght, asserts that they exalt the isolated, autonomous individual at the He maintained that, because of its corporatist foundation, the conciliar
expense of t~e ~hole c~rnmunity. In a famous passage, Marx wrote that movement never developed "an ecclesial individual-right that could yield
the bourgeois nght to liberty was "not based on the association of man a catalogue of basic rights in the modem sense."7
~it~ man ~ut on their separation"; it was "the right of the restricted in- Moreover, among the conciliarists, Gerson is noteworthy for his frl·-
d1v1dual withdrawn into himself." 3 In similar fashion, but from a conser- quent, fervid appeals to the holistic doctrine of the mystical body. In the•
~ative point of view, Leo Strauss complained that, in seventeenth-century words of John Morrall, this was "the theme around which all Gerson-
nghts theories, "the individual, the ego, had become the center and origin ian ecclesiology rotates." Andre Combes especially emphasized Gerson's
of the moral world."4 use of the Pauline metaphor in his Propositio facta coram Anglicis. Thew
If, now, we approach modern scholarship on conciliarism with such Gerson declared, "No one doubts that the church flees and abhors its
criticisms in i:nind we quickly encounter a problem or paradox, an appar- own division since it is a mystical body according to the reasoning of tlw
ent anomaly m recent work on the conciliar movement. s Modem scholars Apostle in Ephesians 4 and l Corinthians 12 and Romans 12...." Gerson
usually see conciliarism as a form of holistic, corporatist ideology, and they illso spoke in this address of the "seed of the Holy Spirit having power to

. 1. 0 . von Gierke, Das drotsche Ge110SMnschaftsreclrt, 4 vols. (Berlin, 1868- 1914). After
6. Standard w orks on Gerson are J. B. Mo rrall, Gerson and lht Grl'At Schism (MancMh'r.
Gierke (and H~el o~ course) one thinks of Durkheim, Weber, Troeltsch, T0nnies, and Popper.
1%0); G. H . M. Posthumus Meyjes, Jtan GtrSOn. zijn kerkpolilik en ecclrsiol~rt {'s-Cr.wmh" K"·
For all of them, m d1Jferenl ways, the distinction between holism and individualism was of
central importance. 1963); A. Combes, la thiologie mystique dt Gerson, 2 vols. (Rome, 1963- 64).
7. E. Ml.'u then, Das Basler Konzil., 19. A. Black, "Society and the Individual from tllr
~· L. Dumont, Essays on Individualism. Modern Ideology in Anthropologrcal Perspective
Middle Ages lo Rousseau: Philosophy, Jurisprudence and Constitutional Thcory.h tfot"'l( 11/
(Ch1cag_o , 1986). Dumoot follo ws Michel ViJJey in seeing Ockham's philosophic no m inalism
as a main source of modem individualism. /'ofilicnl Thouxht I (1980): H6-66 at 156. J. Wohlmulh, " Konzili.aris.mus und Vrrfo,.,.inK dn
Kircht'," Corrcifium 19 (1 983): 522-526 at 524, " ... kann nichl gesagl werdl'n , dit• 1<.0111.ill•n•
3. Karl Mane, "Zur Judenfrage" in /(Qr( Marx Friedrich Engels Gtsamtausgabr, Abt. I, '29
vols. (Berlin, 1975- 90), 2:157- 58. llt•wc>gung h<1be ein ckklesialeo; lndividualn'Chl entwickelt, das i.m heutigt' n Sinn rinc•n f("t"
l" K von Crundrcchtl'n ergeben ko nntr n ."' In my own t>arly wo rk, Fmmdatian.<11/ lhf <·,,,,, 111111
4. Leo Strauss, Natur11I Right and History (Chicago, 1953), 248.
f11nm1 (Camhridgc. 1955), I al"'' 1'mptw1i1t'li tht• rnrporalist foundation11 of c:undliM llwmy
5:. The best. mod.e~ account of th~ c~nciliar movenwnl as a wholr i:< C . l\ll><'ri~o. Clrif!'a with particular n •ferNll't' h> 7.111h1m •lla arnl 1·.1rl11•r .-.m11ni11tic lt'arning11. For a Olt>n' n-o-nt 111"
conolral'!'. ldentrtd t s1gnificato dd ~nc1l111rismo (Brescia, 1981 ). For a lt'Vicw o f curn-nt probll'mc;
··11-;..,inn S.'<' my Rdi,'(imr. I 11111. 11111/ lft( <: 11111•1/r 11{ <·1111stit11lional Tlmuxht (<:amhrMKr, 1'1111) II.
see E. .Meuthen, Das Bas/tr Konzrl als Furscl11mJl5pro/llt'm drr r11roplli<r11t'll ( ;,.,.,·liii·lttr. R/r,•ini.<c:h·
Wt'Stfol1sclrr Akndnm1r dt'r W1S!<r11schn[lm v.,,t,,,xr c;174 (( )pladi•n. 1'IH'>} K""" gr1wr11I !ih11ly 011 mr1llrv11l n•1111 •r.,tl11n n •nn•pl-" 111 I'. Mld11u11.l ~Q11antln , llm1.-r~rl1I•
r 'I'""""'''"' 1111 1r111111.-111f11I 111111m11111111l1lflr 111111• It 1111•11<'11 II,'(•" lalin (1'1ul", 1'17111
210 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RJCHTS GERSON . CONOUARISM, CORPORATISM, AN D INDIVIDUALISM 211

form and reform the whole body of the church," of the "life-giving power knowledgeable about canon Jaw.12 His originality consists in his ways of
by which the mystical body of the church can unify and unite itself," of the handling the earlier traditions of thought and applying them to the new
"life giving blood diffused through the whole body of the church." 8 One problems of his own day.
could hardly imagine more explicit organic imagery. Gerson did not apparently intend to convey any difference of doc-
Yet a convincing case can also be made for Gerson as an early pro- trine by the slight change of wording in his definition of ius. Rather, he
ponent of a doctrine of individual rights. Richard Tuck found the first explained that, in God, "right reason" and "primal justice" were synony-
"fully-fledged" rights theory in his work. Michel Villey referred to Gerson mous. The important point for us is that Gerson gave a clearly subjective
as a significant influence on later rights theorists. Reinhold Schwarz, again definition of ius.'3 and also presented a distinction between lex and ius that
referring to subjective rights, wrote that the concept of ius that appeared we more commonly associate with seventeenth-century natural rights
only obscurely in Ockham was first defined by Gerson. Quentin Skinner, theorists. For Gerson lex was objective law; ius was a subjective power or
in his book on Parly mC'ffrm ppJitical thnnght, ~lsn rlisc11ssPci thE> contri- right inhering in individual persons.
bution of ~1M111 Lu Lhc dl!\.du!Jlllt!lll uf W1::::.l1::w ti~l 1~ lht:ories.': Gerson, then, seems to have defended simultaneously a holistic con-
These modem views are based mainly on two very similar defmitions cept of the church and an individualistic doctrine of subjective rights. This
of the word ius that Gerson presented in the treatises De vita spirituali is the problem we have to explore further. The first, fundamental point
animae (1402) and De potestate ecdesiastica (1416). In the first work, he wrote, to be made in addressing it is that, if this tension in Gerson's thought pre-
/us is an immediate faculty or power pertaining to anyone according to sents a paradox, it is not a paradox peculiar to Gerson. Rather it inhered
the dictate of right reason.10 in the whole Judeo-Christian religious tradition that he inherited. In his
Propositio fnctn coram Anglicis Gerson introduced his holistic imagery of the
The later definition declared, mystical body by commenting on Hosea 1.11, "The children of Judah and
/us is an immediate faculty or power pertaining to anyone according to the children of Israel shall be gathered together." The Old Testament is
the dictate of primal justice. . . . indeed the story of a community, a people of God; but the God of the Old
Lex is a rule in conformity with right reason.11
Testament spoke often to specific persons and addressed his word to his
people through particular chosen individuals. The Bible is full of free in-
Gerson's language is not new in itself. As 1 noted in an earlier chapter, dividuals responding (or not responding) to God's word. What could b<.•
we can find examples of ius naturale defined as a "faculty," "power," or more individualistic than an Old Testament prophet? In the New Testa-
"force" in twelfth-century canonistic writings. We may also be reminded ment too Jesus touched the hearts of individual persons and summoned
of Ockham's definition of ius poli as "a power conformed to right reason." individuals to follow him, but he also called on Israel to perfect a new
And the definition of law as a dictate of reason is standard Thomist doc- community of holiness. The specific epistles of Paul that Gerson cited
trine. Gerson was familiar with the teachings of Ockham and Aquinas; when he used the imagery of the mystical body are also full of moral ex-
and, although he was not a professional canonist, he was interested in and hortation directed, sometimes by name, to individual members of thl'
nascent Christian communities that Paul addressed. Paul especially em-
phasized the ultimate responsibility of each individual for his own eternal
8. Morrall, Gnscn, 67. Combes, Thiologit mystiq1a, 204-5. For the texts o f Gerson see
destiny. In Romans we read, not only, "We are one body in Christ," but also,
P. Glorieux ed., /tan Cason: OtuVTts compWts, 10 vols. (Paris, 1960- 73), 6: 126- 127, 131.
9. R. Tuck, Natllral Rights Tht0rits. Their Origin and !Xwlopmmt (Cambridge, 1979), 25;
12. Cerson's inte rest in canon law is d iscussed in L. B. Pascoe, /t an Gtrson: f'rincil'lr:< ••I
M. Valley, lAJomualion th 111 pmstt jllridiqut modtmt, 4th ed. (Paris, 1975), 267, 365; R. Schwarz,
Ch11rch Rtfornr (Leiden, 1973) and F. Oakley "Gerson and d ' Ailly: an Admo n itio n," St1t•1·11l11m
#Circa naturam iuris subiectivi,n Ptriodica dt re morali canoniCJl lilllrgial 69 (1980): 191- 200 at
40 (1965): 74-83.
191-2; Q . Skinner, TM Foundations ofModern PolitU:al Thollght, 2 vols. (Cambridge, 1978), 2: 117.
13. G!'rson was not, ho wevl'r, who lly consistent in using the word i11s in thr ,.uhj1't·tlv1·
10. Otirore:s, 3: 141, jus est facultas seu potestas propinqua conveniens alicui secundum
sense ht> had defined . Some times lhl' word S<'<'ms lo have rathl'r lhl' nh jl'Ciiv1• 1m•.mit1K 111
dictamen rectae rationis.ff Gerson repeated this definition almost exactly in his DtfiniliontS
id qrtnd i11M11m rst that w1• fir11I in lllpi.m .tml A1111inils . St'\• l'.g., ( °;('r.'l<m ·" 1lt•finiti1111 o f /"
ltrminOTMm tht0/ogiae moralis, Otuures, 9: 134, "Jus est facultas seu potestas rompetens alicui
ris.lictic•, "d k itur ju ri!ldklio "1n1ll11• 111•11 poh'sla!> pmpinqu;i tlin •ndi vt•I '"'nll'nlinn1li Ju•
secundum dictamen rectae rationis."
in altt•mm t•tiilm invilum'" (< lrrlf!rr... '' 211>) A1111i11 ( ;,.r,.on n•f1•rn•d lo lht' pn'<"l'f'l!t of lhl'
11. Otuvrts, 6: 242, "Jus est facultas seu potestas propinqua c:onvc·nil'n!I illicui !ICCundum
I >.·1·n l11~1H' .u1 ;11.• '"'t11111lr (1 lrur•tr• 1 14/) It wu11l1I: l111v1• h1-.•11mun• 1"c11111l"h'lll Im· him In
dictamen primae ju!ltitiae. Porro dictamt'tl hoc lex dicilur, 1111111 lrx not WK11l11 n1nformilillem
l111v1• w ri ttf'n lri 1P11l11111fu 111•11• I"'" ' u11l1I 111111 h1111.ln·.I• ol ~11.-lt """II"" ,.,.,,11,•rt•ol tl1101111h
habens ad dictam~ rt.'Clile r11tlonl~. "
l ;11 r!i'n n '" w urlt.-.
212 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS GERSON. CONCIUARISM, CORPORATISM, AND INDIVIDUALISM 213

"Each one of us will render an account of himself before God. " 14 There can of corporate solidarity when confronting outsiders, but also an intense
be no more holistic image of society than the medieval vision of the church awareness of individual rights when particular claims within the group
as a mystical body; and no more starkly individualistic view of human were in question. 16 A modem author has observed that, without a concern
destiny than the medieval vision of the Last Judgment, when each soul for individual persons, "families disintegrate, congregations do not con-
would stand alone, naked and trembling, before the divine judge. gregate nor colleges continue collegiate." Medieval people seem to have
Of course no society can be entirely holistic or entirely individual- known this intuitively. It is useless to write about "medieval corporatism"
11
istic. It is usually a question of degree, of deciding which value is con- without understanding the structure of a medieval corporation.
sidered "paramount," as Dumont wrote. Normally, we expect to find one Long ago, Frederic Maitland, in discussing the relationship between
value subordinated to the other. The unusual feature of medieval Christian the theology of the mystical body and the medieval theory of corpora-
thought is that both values-the value of individual persons and the value tions, wrote, "The corporation aggregate was almost resolved into a mere
of Christian community-were asserted with equal passion. Moreover this collection of corporations sole."18 Other classic works have explored the
attitude pervaded medieval life on many levels of theory and practice. interplay between individualist and communal ethics in Christian social
On the level of theological discourse, the whole developing doctrine of thought. 19 To understand fully the growth of rights theories in the late
Purgatory and indulgences reflected both an intense concern for the wel- medieval period one has to bear in mind, not only the obvious facts of me-
fare of individual souls and a sure conviction that the merits of the whole dieval life-the obsessive concern of many persons and groups to maintain
body of the Church could help to succor them. Zabarella moved directly their "rights and liberties"-but also the pervasive influence of Chri!l-
from an account of the church as a mystical body to a defense of papal tian attitudes to individual and community at every level of thought and
indulgences. Gerson, arguing in the other direction, pointed out that the action.20
prayer of an individual mystic aided the whole body of the church, "not
just one or two but the whole mystical body. " 15 16. Jn adjudicating a dispute within the cathedral chapter of Troyes. Innocent Ill laid
On a legal level we find in medieval corporation law a peculiar em- down that the chapter could not deprive a minority of its own members of their tradition,11
phasis on the defense of individual rights within corporate groups. It rights (and Ockham tried to base a general principle of political theory on this legal lf'Chni·
is now well understood that earlier canonistic doctrines influenced the cality). See above, 184.
conciliarists' teachings on the corporate structure of the church; but we 17. The whole medieval " fiction theory" of corporations was based on a d enial of what
Gierke called " the real personality of the group" and on an acknowledgme.n t that only indi-
need also to consider the relevance of the corporation law that the canon- vidual persons had real existence. Gerson, a theologian, did not formally study the canon
ists developed for later rights theories. In a typical medieval ecclesiastical law of corporations . But he served as Dean of the collegiate church of Saint-Donatien and
corporation, say the bishop-and-chapter of a cathedral church, some rights Chancellor of the University of Paris. A familiarity with the behavior of individual'> in ror·
(e.g., the right to alienate church property) belonged to the whole corpo- porate groups was part of everyday life for a medieval churchman. .
rate entity, bishop and cathedral chapter acting together. But there were 18. F. Pollock and F. W. Maitland, The History of English Law, 2 vols., 2nd ed. (CambndKe.
\898). 1: 5'Jl. E. Kantorowicz, 'TM King's Two Bodies. A Study in Mtditval Political T11nilll)(!f
also two spheres of "right-subjectivity" in the corporation. The bishop had (Princeton, 1957) has many examples of the term corpus mysticum used in a legal or po liticnl
certain rights of his own and the chapter as a corporate entity had rights ~ense. On this~ also F. Oakley, "Natural Law, the Corpus Mysticum, and Consent in Con
too. Then, beyond this, each individual member of the chapter had his ciliar Thought." Speculum 56 (1981 ): 786-810. Gerson wrote of rights within a my~tkal body
own particular rights, typically a right to revenues from a prebend at- not o nly with reference to the church but also in discussing the French state. See h1..~ Vitvit " ''•
tached to his canonry, and sometimes rights associated with an office that Oeuvres, 7: 1156. Great cruelties arose in a "corps mistique se les partiez sont divi!IC7. l'I ~··
p<."rsecutent l' une l' autre ... car naturelment tout chose deffent son droyt el reboule fail p01r
he held in the cathedral church. These were individual rights in the sense
I.lit, violence par violence; vim vi repellere licet." .
that an individual could sue for them, but they were not private rights; 19. For a gene ral account of the whole problem and discussion o f the earhl'r lilNo1tu1 ..
they were rights held by individuals as members of a corporate commu- w e A. Black, Guilds nnd Civil St:1ciely in European Political Thought from tht Th1t"lftl1 Cmlury '"
nity. The members of such a community could display a very strong sense thl' Present (Ithaca , NY. 1984).
20. Modern di!ICussion~ on indlvidu.1ls and community in the Middl.- Agt•M h1w1• olt..n
fonis.wd on Aquina!I. ~ M. ,t.• Wulr. "" I .'lmtlvt.lu 1•1 It• Kroupe dan~ la M"'t>la!!liqm• 1111 XIII"
14. Romans, 12.5, 14.12. "il'dt•, Rn•ur nn>!«·c•ln~tiqur 1lr 11l1ll11"''l'l11r 21 ( 111211): J41 ·-J r>7; F- I A"wi11, "l >rx1U1k Tt•nJrnd..,.
ff

15. J. LeCoff. La naissana du PurKaloirt (Pari,., IQlll); :t.ao11wlln, S11pt"r '/11i11q11,. /if.ris dr- in Mo-<lil•vnl l'11litk.1I Th1111Khl."" """"" "' l'1•llllnll Sdr111 r Rt1•ir1C1 :l2 ( 111~): R49 7t>. I T t\11d1
CTttalium commmtnriQ (VmlCC', lt102), nil X5.l\. \ 7; ( :1•r.ion, I >r l!rn•l••.11111 11111sllnr, In t lrm•r•·s. lli.tllll, " f\ ·11u1111iMh•· t ;i,...,111 y 1111 thr 1'1 hu 11'1" "' t lw l'n•••mhwnn• of " l "n11m11111 <;, ,. ..1 :·
:l: 291. Mrofotrr~rl .'ilwl1.-• •; ( 1114 I) I JI n'\ Ao1111t111• 1ho1111~11lohril 1..•1w....11 n "'unity nl unl,.1 " (ft• In""
214 THE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHiS GF.RSON. CONCIUARISM, CORPORATISM, AND INOIVIDUAUSM 215

This background may help us to understand the apparent paradox t "hristian tradition.22 Michel Villey sees rights theories as derived from
from which we set out, the combination of corporatist and individualist <"hristian morality, but as an aberration, a deformed variety of Christian
language in Gerson's work. There is, after all, nothing so unusual about it. thought (idees chrniennes mais deformees).n But another who!~ ~hool of
But we still have a further problem to consider. Why did Gerson come to be 1hinkers, represented most eloquently perhaps by Jacques Mantam, sees a
so concerned about individual rights in the first place? Judeo-Christian •tuctrine of individual rights as always implicit in the Christian emphasis
teaching has indeed always recognized the value of individual persons • m the dignity of human personality.
but this recognition has not always Jed on to a doctrine of subjective in- If this last point of view is to be defended, the key word must surely be
dividual rights. Robert Cover has recently pointed out, for instance, that .. implicit." Perhaps there was always a possibility that Christian teaching
Judaic law has always been able to uphold the worth and dignity of human , 111 the inherent value of each individual person could be reformulated as a
personality without asserting a doctrine of human rights by emphasiz- , loctrine of subjective natural rights. But, certainly, through most of Chris-
ing the alternative concept of mitzvah, duty or precept.21 There are aspects 1ian history, the possibility was not realized. The idea seems foreign to the
of Christian teaching too that may seem hostile to any growth of rights the- 1radition of Eastern Orthodoxy, for instance. There was no Creek Gerson
ories. Christian ethics seem to demand the abandonment of rights rather or Grotius or Locke. In the medieval West, from the twelfth century to the
than their assertion. " If a man strike you on one cheek, turn to him the fifteenth, we can find writers who used early Christian texts to support an
other." The ethos of all the great medieval religious orders was based on 1·rnerging doctrine of natural rights; but their understanding (or misun-
abnegation of rights by the members. (Francis of Assisi, although he was derstanding) of the texts was a new one, shaped by the circumstances of
such a strikingly original individual himself, once said that a perfectly obe- rhc>ir own age. Let us go back for a moment to the writings of Paul on the
dient friar should be like a corpse, moved only at the will of a superior.) dlurch as the body of Christ. Paul described the unity of the church in two
Moreover, Christian fervor could easily lead to the suppression of rights- ways. Sometimes he stressed differentiation of function. "The body is not
or what we should consider rights-where religious dissidents were con- nne member but many-the eye cannot say to the hand, 'I do not need
cerned. In the conciliar period, one has only to remember Hus at Con- your help'."24 Jn other places Paul emphasized the equality of all Chris-
stance. Even a thinker like Gerson, who wrote eloquently on "evangelical tians in their freedom from the Old Law and unity with Christ, "There
liberty," could not conceive of anything like a modern right to religious 1s neither Jew nor Creek, neither slave nor freeman . . . ." All Christians
freedom. were free "with the freedom wherewith Christ has made us free.'-15 Pre-
It is not surprising then that one finds considerable disagreement sumably in neither case was Paul intending to propose anything like a
among modem scholars who have tried to relate the Judea-Christian re- modem doctrine of rights. But Gerson, writing in a different historical con-
ligious tradition to the growth of Western rights theories. Sometimes the h'xt, assumed that the Pauline texts provided support for his own rights
relationship is seen as one of opposition. One school of thought holds theories. The point is that the emergence of a theory of natural rights _is
that all modem rights theories are rooted in the "atheistic" philosophy of ,, contingent phenomenon. It does not arise in all cultures nor even m
Hobbes and hence regards them as incompatible with the whole preceding .111 Christian cultures. The task of a historian working in this area is to
make the growth of such theories intelligible by explaining the conting<>nl
organized group) and a "unity by composition or connection" (as in an actual o rganic body). circumstances in which they could emerge and survive. Modern rights
On the church as a mystical body he noted that this description referred to "a l't'semblance . . . dodrines can give rise to all kinds of moral and philosophical problems.
not an exact correspondence or identity" (Summa tlrtol. 3 .8 .1 ad 3). Aquinas' d istinctio n is dis- U11t the questions a historian has to answer are rather d ifferent on('s.
cussed with specific reference to conciliar thought by A. Black, Council and Commune. Tire
Conciliar Mourment and tire Fifteenth-Century Heritage (London, 1979), 138-143. In a diffen-nt
area, much recent work has been concerned with the new religious individualism or per- 22. In America this view has been emphasized mainly in the work of ~c-holar~ infltH'f\C"l'<I
sonalism of the twelfth century and its relationship to the corporative movements of that hy 1.N> Straus.~. $('(> e .g., W. ik'ms in This World 6 (198.1): 98, "(T)he very idt'a of nahm1I right~
age. For a discussio n see the papers of C. W. Bynum, " Did the Twelfth Century Discover "inrnmpatibl<' wilh Chri~ti;m doctrinr.... " Bt'm~· argument wa~ developed fu.rth<-r.in h ll'
the Jndividualr and C. Morris, " Individualism in Twelfth-Century Religion. Some Furthl'r 111 />r(rr1.« of /i1"'ml [)rm(l("rary (Chicago, 111144). It w.1~ cont~trd by H . Jaffa. Att1t'nran < 011M'r
Reflections," Journal of Ecclesiastical History 31 (1980): 1- 17, 195- 206. For an t'XC<'llt.'llt o vcrvit-w r'fllism a11d lht' Amrrira11 f m111di11,!( (l>urhnm, N< ·, 111144)
see A. Black, "The lndi\•idual and Society" in T/11• CnmhridKt' lti51or_v of Mrolir1wl 1'0 /it1rnl 2:\. M . Vil11•y, " I .1 g1•nl'M• tl111lmlt •11hjrr lll o+.1•1 ( :uil11111mt• d 'C lc"cO'm," Arfhi1~ dr 1ol1il1""'
Thought. ed. J. H . Rum!I (CambridgP, 19811}. ~-<>Cln. 1•l11r rlu olmil 9 ( 1llM)· W 127 "t '17
21 . R. Cover. "'Obligalion: A )t•wi~h furi~prudt•1wr of Son11l 1 lrtl,•1." fmir 11nl of I •111•n11ol l«-
14 I <·orh1lhl""' 11 14, 71
lixiun 5 ( I 9R7): 65 - 74.
I'• l ;"1"11""~ I } It 'I I
216 THE [OEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS GERSON. CONCILIARISM, CORPORATISM, ANO INOIVIDUAUSM 217

He will want to know what contexts, what contingent developments intrinsic nature of the relationship between God's sovereignty and man's
made the assertion of rights theories seem necessary or practicable or use- sovereignty. Specifically, according to Tuck, Gerson saw the relationship
ful in certain times and places (and not in others). In earlier chapters I between God and man "as a reciprocal one between equals." It is hard to
have discussed the twelfth-century context of juridical humanism and the imagine any thought that was further from Gerson's mind. Rather, he in-
fourteenth-century context of Franciscan poverty disputes. But why was sisted that every gift of God to man was made, not ex debito, but from
Gerson so concerned with individual rights? What context can we define God's unconstrained freedom and generosity.28 Tuck imagined that, for
that would make his rights theories intelligible? Gerson, the relationship between God and man "generated rights on bot'1
The modem authors who have discussed these questions have sug- sides." But Gerson wrote that there could be no "quid pro quo" in man's
gested two kinds of answers. For Michel Villey the context of late medieval dealings with God. Tuck even argued that "men have rights against God
nominalism was all-important. Villey regarded William of Ockham as the as a result of God's promise to them" and quoted Gerson's phrase, "the
radical innovator who first "deformed" Christian teaching into a theory of humble have been given a right to all things." But Gerson treated this right
individual rights; and he thought that Gerson was important in the history of the humble, which he elsewhere called a i11s evangelicum or ius charitntis,
of rights theories mainly as a transmitter of Ockhamist doctrine. There are as a gift from God, not a right against God. In the immediately preced-
two difficulties in this explanation. As I have already argued, Ockham's ing passage Gerson wrote of man's need to know his own "nothingness"
rights theories were not really dependent on his nominalist philosophy. before God.29
And Gerson was not a nominalist so far as the theory of universals was
concerned. Gerson was an eclectic in his philosophy. One can find ex-
TUCK ON GERSON
amples of Ockhamist influence in his work but also frequent use of neo-
Platonic and Aristotelian ideas. 26 Gerson raised the problem of universals Although Tuck's account of Gerson's theology is not persuasive, his
in a specifically ecclesiological context when he asked whether potestas ec- work requires some further consideration before we can explore the work
clesUistica was a "real universal"; and he gave an answer entirely in accord of the French conciliarist in more detail. Among modem writers, Tuck is
with Aristotelian or Thomist moderate realism. "All priests share in the the one who has laid most emphasis on Gerson's innovating role in dis-
priesthood, all bishops in the episcopate...."As Morrall observed, "there cussions concerning natural rights. Tuck even wrote that Gerson "really
is no trace of Ockharnism in Gerson's approach here."21 invented the theory." Moreover, what is at stake here is not just a dispute
Richard Tuck presented a different approach to Gerson's rights theo- flbout theological technicalities but a whole way of placing Gerson in the
ries. He emphasized, not Gerson's metaphysics, but rather his moral developing tradition of thought about subjective rights.
theology. This seems a more promising line of argument; but Tuck made Tuck's understanding of Gerson's moral theology was apparently in-
nc-n~cuse of his own suggestion by presenting an impossible account fluenced by a desire to relate Gerson's doctrines to a modem debate about
of Gerson's theological ideas. In Tuck's view, Gerson saw ius as an active the nature of "active" and "passive" rights. Tuck explained that, "To havf:'
power involving a sort of "sovereignty" in relation to the object of the ius. a passive right is to have a right to be given or allowed something by
Further, he argued, in Gerson's thought, such rights were derived from the someone else, while to have an active right is to have the right to do soml'·
thing oneself." He also noted that the holder of an active right could tw
26. On Gerson's neo-Platonism see A. Combes, /tan Gnson, commmlaleur dionysie11 (Paris, said to exercise a kind of "sovereignty" over the relevant part of his moral
1940). world.xi Tuck suggested that rights theories before Gerson were gent'rally
27. Dt poleslale ecclesi11slic11, CXuvres 6: 222-3, "Si vero vellet aliquis curiosus inquirere
qualiter habet fie.r i talis abstTactio potestatis ecdesiasticae, remittimus ad metaphysicam . . . concerned with passive rights. Gerson's great contribution was to providt•
Omnes enim sacerdotes conveniunt in sacerdotio, omnes episcopi in episropatu... _,,(Cf.
Morrall, Gerson, 104). Gerson also declined to a.nswer another question raised by nominalist 211 Tuck Natural Ri111tts JO. Gerson, & 11v1rs. 3: 148, " ... non l'>< dl'bito r igori!'I !<4~1 <'k Ill•
theology, whether will or reason was prior in God. CXuvrrs, 3: 141, " Videtur igitur positio esse ,.,,1Ji~sima <'; dignilnlis.~im; rond~<'n!iionr .11.11 donal ionl' cre11tori11 .. . ip~· umnium IMh.-1
magis catholica et expeclita si dicamus neutrum esse prius alte.ro." In other contexts Gerson .,.,lus plrnarium dominium <'I r!l."4'oli.1lt• ..
wrote extensively about the ,,affective" and "intellective# approaches to religious life. Often 2'1. Nat11rnl Ri,11/its, JO. <:C-r~on, ( >.-111•r,..... '.\. 147, " Et ... umnia qmw dilmus <'itlc-rn ..1111 tlr
Gerson emphasized will, the affective approach; but, in his di5CUSSion!I on i11s, reason 9ttm~ ~110 .•• ili'I proprir clnrr nrtJlllmu• •tuhl I''" •tm• . •· <>rrwrr.o, ~: 17. " I In< 11110 mu.lo 1tnh 1111
especially important. E.g., immediately after the definition of ius in Dr 1•il1111piritu11li 1111irr1ar, he mli rmit,lli~ proprl.w, immo 11lhllrlh1tl• 11111.111 '"· 1td c "•:nilit•m·m pr;u'lff•nliiw 1Uvl11lt..tl" Im
wrote, "ltaque totalis <'I finali!I resolulin malt•ri.w """'' w 11tl tfkl11nwn rt'l"l•U' r'11ioni,. lt'fml- 1111•11JM<' IH•rr-r... It ·•
natur" (~uvres, :\:141). ICI N r'1urn/ ~1.11/rl•. I•
218 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIG HTS GERSON. CONCIUARlSM, CORPORATISM, AND lNDIVIDUAUS.~ 219

a theological rationale for an active rights theory, which Tuck sees as para- for instance an argument of Sylvester Mazzolini da Prierio, a theologian of
digmatic for the modern concept of a right. Hence, in discussing later the early sixteenth century, who maintained that every iu_s i~plied a ~ind
developments of thought, Tuck referred to active rights theories as "Ger- of dominium or mastery since a right-holder could assert his nght by bnng-
sonian" and passive rights theories as "anti-Gersonian." i ng suit. Tuck sees this as an argument for active rights against the passive
But this argument is not really sustainable. It was a great merit of rights theory of the jurists. But in fact Sylvester was arguing here specifi-
Tuck's work that he called attention to the jurisprudence of the twelfth and cally for passive rights, as Tuck originally defined the term-namely the
thirteenth centuries as a possible source of later rights theories; but he mis- right of a son to receive sustenance from his father and the right of par-
understood the relevant texts and so produced only a confused account of ishioners to receive sacraments from their priests.33 And, of course, when
the subsequent development. For Tuck, all the rights envisaged by the ju- lhe jurists discussed such claim rights, they too envisaged their asser-
rists were claim rights or passive rights. The medieval church, he points tion though legal action. For the canonists, to have a right meant typic~lly
out, was much concerned with the claims of the needy, so the canonists to have an actio, a capacity to bring suit. Discussing the act of walking
naturally developed a theory of rights as claims. But, as we saw in an ear- across another's field, Johannes Teutonicus wrote in the Ordinary Gloss
lier discussion, the right of the poor in canon law was not merely passive; 10 the Decretunr, "It is just by divine law but it is not a right, that is, the
in case of necessity they had an active right to take what they needed. The lnw does not give a civil action." 34 If a claim that can be asserted in court is
canonists also recognized many other active rights. The ius episcopale, for ;m active right the canonists were among the foremost protagonists of such
instance, the complex of rights exercised by a bishop, included a right of rights.
preaching (ius praedicandi), a right of administering (ius administrandi), a To dwell on these technical points might seem mere quibbling, except
right of judging (ius iudicandi). Canon law was full of active rights; it is that Tuck goes on to present the history of late medieval rights theories as
misleading to suggest otherwise. ,, contest between "Gersonians," who insisted that all rights were active,
It is equally misleading to see Gerson as hostile to the idea of pas- and others who defended a theory of passive rights. His account has been
sive rights. In discussing the rights of a parish priest he mentioned in widely accepted as an accurate presentation of late medieval thought on
one sentence a right of preaching (ius praedicandi) and a right of receiv- rights, and seldom criticized. But really no such argument as Tuck en-
ing tithes (ius insuper . .. decimas recipiendi). The first is an active right visaged existed in the medieval sources. Everyone who discussed these
according to Tuck's definition, the second a passive right. Elsewhere, matters, including those who adopted Gerson's definition of ius, acknowl-
Gerson mentioned other rights of recipience; it never occurred to him l'dged the existence of both active and passive rights, rights of action and
that a right to receive something or to claim something was not a real rights of recipience.35 The texts that Tuck adduces do not support the con-
right.31
Tuck is able to sustain his argument only by a persistent equivocation 33. Natural Rights, 5. Tuck emphasizes a late medieval dispute between scho lars whu
in the use of terms. When he wants to argue for the absence of active rights wanted to equate ius with dominiilm and others who insisted on a distinction betwttn lh1•
two terms. He sees the former group as protagonists of an active rights theory. But the dis·
in the jurists every claim right becomes a passive right; but when he wants pule, a le ft-over relic of the Franciscan poverty controversy, really had nothing to do with
to argue for an absence of passive rights in Gerson and his followers, every .1etive and passive rights as Tuck uses the terms. See below, 243- 45.
claim right that can be asserted in court becomes an active right because it 34. Gloss ad Dist. l c.1.
is something that "its possessor could control himself.''32 Tuck discusses, J5. Fernando Perez, for instance, wrote (1557) Hlus prout est facultas moralis . . . ad utm·
.tum re aliqua l'tl ad obtintndam illam, quo pacto solemus cticere aliquam habere ius in w wl
.1d rt'm, sic definitur: Est potestas seu moralis facultas legitima ad aliquid. lta Gerson'" (cni·
31. The two classes or rights correspond roughly to the medieval categories, ius in re, and phasis added). (Cited by Schwarz, HCirca naturam iuris subiectivi.•H 192.) Q. Skimwr nlritt
ius ad rem, developed by the canonists from ca. 1200 onward. Gerson's De conlr11ctib115 (Oeu- KdVl' a distorted ac:count of Cerson's teaching by attributing to h im too narrow a dt'flnitiu11
vr~, 9: 385-421) includes much discussion of claim rights. 11
f ius. f uundC1/i011s, 2:117, ~Gerson .. . equates the possession of a right or ius over RnyrhlnK
32. At the outset in Naturlll Rights, 5, Tuck distinguishes sharply between iris as meaning with thl' power or pottslas to di."J'OS<' of it frt'E'ly." But this is Skinl\t•r'i< d<'flnltion, 1101
dominium, an active right with nimplications of control and mastery," and ius as "simply a <:t·rson':o;. Fc>r Gerson iu.< was a bn>ad c:l\ll'ROT}' which could includ<' a right of do111ini11111 (with
claim on other people, u a passive right. But at ibid., 15, where he discusses the work of lhe till' row<'r to ~ti.~poS<' of !!om1•thlng fn.,·lyl !lul whkh 011~1 indud1•d v.uioui'l olht•r rt.14ht11, t' K··
early glossators, dominium becomes a passive right because it was "a claim to total control lht' iu< l'rardirn111l1. Skinm•r o·onlhlllt'•I. "'So II follow" tl1o11 no nih•r mny ht' Mi.t tn h11vr Ally
against all the world." Then at ibid., 17 dominium lum.<1 back into an aclivc right again; but riKhl" ov••r ,1 n•mmonw<'nlth. . ." 11111 I ;..t•on 111011! •'t'rl11l11ly ht'ltl thnl n1l<'r" 11'1<1 rlKhl11 I lo•
here claim rights are also treated "s ac:tivc righl!'I. It is hard h> tlis..·••m .my t•olwn'flt argumt>nl wmh" lor ln"l"n.-.• lh;1l I lAvhl oll•I 111111 ...., hi• 111• hi 1r,111111 whrn ht• rommlllrol lhr Aln nl 1\11111
running through thl"""' page'!I. lt•oy S.••• !>l'low 11 7r;
220 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS GERSON. CONCIUARISM, CORPORATISM, AND INDIVIDUALISM 221

dusions he draws from them. They are mistranslated or misunderstood by definition of ius was included in his major conciliar treatise, the De potestate
being taken out of context. ecclesiastica as well as in his earHer theological work. One might go further
Tuck, for instance, presents Luis Molina as a sort of belated Gersonian and suggest that the context of medieval conciliarism is the truly signifi-
who launched an "explicit attack" on the idea of passive rights. He quotes cant one, the context that makes Gerson's theory of rights intelligible. This
the following passage: is the position that I want to argue for the rest of this chapter.
The objectives of the conciliar movement, as they were eventu.ally
lus ... divisimus in ius in re et in ius ad rem. Altero modo dicitur
aliquis habere ius ad aliquid, non quod sit ei aliquid debitum, sed quod
formulated at the Council of Constance were threefold-to end the schism,
facultatem habeat ad aliquid. ... to reform the church in head and members, and to defend the Catholic
faith (specifically against the errors of Wyclif and Hus). These were the
Tuck translates this as, "We divide ius into ius in re and ius ad rem. When areas in which the decree Haec sancta, promulgated at the Council of Con-
we say in this second way that someone has a ius to something we do not stance, claimed supreme authority for a general council. Gerson pu~sued
mean that anything is owed to him but that he has a facultas to it. ..." these aims throughout his public life. His distinctive doctrine of individual
Thus he assumes that Molina was reinterpreting the passive ius ad rem, a rights grew out of his strivings to achieve them. .
claim right, as a sort of active right.36 But, when Molina wrote Alfero modo, Let us begin with the first objective, since Gerson's doctnne concern-
his meaning was not, "In this second way. ..." but " In another way one is ing the supremacy of a council over the contending popes of the schism
said to have a right. . .." And he went on to describe a third kind of right, may seem the best example of his corporatist, holistic view of the church.
the right of an owner in his own property, that he distinguished from the From about 1408, Ger'30n became convinced that the only way to end the
jurists' ius in re and ius ad rem. Later in this same passage he argued that a schism was the via concilii, "the way of a council"; and his tum to strict
claim to receive something gratuitously, from another person's benevo- conciliarism was indeed signalled by the rich display of the imagery of the
lence, could also be called a right, a ius accipiendi.17 If one emphasized such mystical body in his address to the English envoys of that _year. Yet, _a s we
passages one could present Molina as an extreme defender of passive have noticed, Gerson's subjective doctrine of rights was included m the
rights. But really he was not arguing about the issue raised by Tuck at all. conciliar treatise De potestateecclesiastica, composed several years after this
In order to understand Gerson's very real role in the development of address (and after the enactment of Haec sancta at Constance). The place-
rights theories we need therefore to forget the imaginary dispute about ment of the definition of ius in this work may seem odd at first glance-it is
active and passive rights, and tum back to the medieval texts themselves. presented in Consideratio 13 as a sort of appendix tacked on at the en~ of
the argument. There also seems to be a kind of disjunction in the full title
RIGHTS AND CONCILIARISM of the treatise, Tractatus de potestate ecclesiastica et de origine juris et legum "A
Treatise on Ecclesiastical Power and on the Origin of Right and of Laws." It
If we cannot explain Gerson's rights theory adequately in terms of late appears at first as though two unconnected treatises have been transcribed
medieval nominalism, nor exclusively in terms of his moral theology, nor one after the other and given a common title. This difficulty is resolved
as a defense of active rights against passive rights, we are still left with the when we notice that Consideratio 12, immediately preceding the formal
problem of explaining how he came to formulate his characteristic doc- dt>finition o f ius, is devoted entirely to a discussion of iura-the rights of
trines. Neither Villey nor Tuck emphasized Gerson's involvement with the popes, kings, bishops and lesser prelates in the conduct of church affai':5.
conciliar movement of his own day as a way of understanding his rights After all this, it was entirely appropriate that Gerson should explam
theory. Tuck, indeed, dismissed conciliar thought as irrelevant. Any theory his own understanding of the term ius (and cognate terms like iustitia, lex,
of rights, he noted was potentially individualistic. Hence, he argued, such il11111i11i11m) in the concluding Consideratio 13.
a theory "played very little part in the communitarian, conciliar case.. .. "Jll But, s till, why the emphasis on individual iura at all in a treatis<'
This observation is in accord with much modem wo rk on conciliarism; •ll'votf><l t'Ssentially to defending th<' corporate authority of a general coun-
but it seems to me open to.question. It is not only that Gerson's influential ci I? 'lhE> answer lies partly in Ct•rstm's n'liance on an earlier body oft'<>
dt•siological doctrine that had ~rown up in his alma mater, .the l!nivt>rsi_ty
36. Natural Rights, 53.
37 Ludovici Molin~ D~ justitia d j1m•, 5 vols. (Col0j1,n<'. 1759), I : 15 It>. Mnhn" <it•fint'<I j11.<
111 1'<1ris. Wht>n C.<'rson tliKt·u"Mt'tl the- rul" uf hh~ho~ and pm.•sts m C11,.s11I
here as a ufacultas aliquid fadrndi ~iv1• ohtln<'mli. . .. " ,.,.11/io 12 of thP I >r 1mlr11l11lr hr hn1I l'I rll"h 1nttllllon uf tlwolo~y to drnw nn;
38. Na/urn/ Ri!{ht~. :l<I. hut it w.1s a tlwoloKY thnt l11ul •'lll1'hl'l11l1••1I lht• tmllvlchml riKhls ol t•.u-h
222 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIG HTS GERSON. CONCIUARISM, CORPORATISM, AND INDIVIDUALISM 223

prelate in his own locality rather than collegial authority in the universal of this kind. Gerson was implicitly responding to them when he declared
church. Ever since the 1250s, secular masters of the university had been in the De potestate that the authority of a general council would be annulled
concerned to defend the autonomy of local prelates against the claims of if the supreme pontiff sought to usurp for himself all the rights of inferior
mendicant friars who, relying on papal privileges, came to preach and prelates.•2 ••
hear confessions in their churches. Walter Ullmann perhaps oversimplified Gerson would probably in any case have appealed to the familiar
when he described fifteenth-century conciliarism as "a resuscitation of the episcopalist arguments in formulating his own conciliar doctrine; but, as
old episcopalist theory"; 39 but traditional episcopalism certainly did play a it happened, the whole ancient quarrel between mendicants and seculars
significant part in the conciliar argument that Gerson presented. And, in had erupted once again at the University of Paris just a few years before
its earlier forms, medieval episcopalism was more like a theory of individ- the Council of Constance.43 It was in the context of this earlier dispute that
ual feudal immunities than like a theory of corporate representation. Gerson propounded the doctrine concerning the rights of inferior prelates
In the course of the earlier debates, the more extreme spokesmen for which he would later deploy as a part of his conciliar theory.
the friars (beginning with the Franciscan, Thomas of York, in 1256) argued Jn 1408 a Franciscan friar, Jean de Gorrell, reasserted the mendicant
that all ecclesiastical jurisdiction inhered in the pope. Since bishops and daims against the secular clergy, and Gerson formulated a reply on behalf
priests possessed only a subordinate authority, derived from the papacy, of the university's faculty of theology (January 1409}. It declared that par-
they had no licit reason for resisting the intrusion of the friars, whose ish priests (curati) were originally instituted by Christ and that by virtue
work was also authorized by the popes. The episcopalists (led at first by of their state they held a right of preaching, a right of hearing confessions,
the redoubtable Guillaume de St. Amour) replied that, although Christ .i right of administering sacraments, a right of giving burial, a right of

had indeed instituted a papal office in Peter, he had also conferred au- receiving tithes.44 But the friars appealed to the pope and Alexander V ~a
thority on the twelve apostles (whose successors were the bishops) and on Franciscan himself) rejected the university's positions in the bull Regnans m
the seventy-two disciples (whose successors were the parish priests). The cxcelsis (October 1409). Gerson and the theological faculty again protested.
pope, Guillaume argued, had no power to disturb the general state of the In an implied rebuke to the pope they declared that an act of theft did not
church as Christ had established it. Since the original dispute concerned consist only in taking gold and silver but also in usurping the rights and
the claim of mendicant friars to enter parishes without permission of the dignities of others.4s The emphasis on rights was stiJl stronger in a sermon
local priest, the subsequent debate emphasized the status of the individual that Gerson preached in French at about the same time. Here he used the
priest in his parish as much as that of the bishop in his diocese.40 This vernacular word droit over and over again in its modem sense of a sub-
would eventually influence Gerson's teaching on the structure of a general jt·ctive right. Gerson spoke of the priest's "droit de preschier," "droit de
council. confessions ouyr," "droyt de recevoir dismes." He even offered French ver-
The secular-mendicant quarrel had little to do with conciliarism at sions of his earlier Latin definition of ius as a faculty or power, referring to
first; but, when conciliar doctrines were put forward by critics of the ;\priest's "droit ou faculte" and to "cette puissance ou ce droit."46
papacy like John of Paris early in the fourteenth century, papal supporters We can now tum back to the use of such concepts in Gerson's mature
soon realized that the arguments developed in the earlier dispute pro- conciliar theory. Consideratio 12 of the De potestate ecclesiasticn introduced
vided an effective response to them. A century before Gerson, Hervaeus the question of rights in the church with a discussion of the pope's jurn tcr-
Natalis had observed that a pope's relation to his bishops was like that of a rr·11i simul et coelestis imperii ("rights of earthly and heavenly empire"), "
king to his stewards or bailiffs. A king, surrounded by his servants, had no phrase from Gratian's Deere/um that had attracted extensive canonistk
more authority than a king alone; so too a council of prelates could add
nothing to the authority of a pope (since any power they had was derived 42. Orm•".~· 6: u Auctoritas itaque nulla erit si solus s ummus pontifox omni;, v1•1il in·
from him). 41 Any persuasive conciliar theory had to deal with arguments '"'"'rum l'Cdl'siasticorum usurparc inslitutio n<'S, jura, status, gradus ~I orficia.- Elst•wlwn•
c ;,•rsun n -spondeJ dir<'('tly to tilt' .1rgum1•nl Jh.11 infrrior pn>lat~ WPl't' like ..bailiffs.. (C >t-1w1r•
39. W. Ullmann, A History of Political Thought. Tht Middlt Ages (Hannondsworlh, 1970), I?'')
223. 41 f >.·ur•rr.;, to:.1 0-11priwi1l1'll11 ··,111.••11·1 ·· on thi~ ,li•pult'.
40. An excdlent guide to the whole controversy is provided by Y. Congar, Aspt>ets eccl~
H
'14 ( lt-111•r1-s. 10·1.l .
siologiques de la querelle entre mendiants et s«ulien dans l<t !le('(mdl' mollie du XIII<' 11il'c"lt' 4<; ""'"''""· Jll·'.UI, " N,.. 111r rnlm 1.. 111111111110•1" lmh1111 ··~I in .111111 vt•I .1r11••nlo, •·~I 1•1 h1
et le debut du XNe," ArchivtS d'histoirt dorlrin11/ut li1tlr11i" d11 m".' lm llJl' 27 (I %1)· 15 IS I.
41. Hervaeull Natalis, Dr i11ri~icli1111r, rd. I _ ltllcll (Munkh. l'J'i'I), 2H, .i .c
"""I'"''""'' ,1t11111t.1ti... J11rl• . 11f111 II v1•l h 1111111I• .. 11..111 ··
•It• 1 >1·111 •11·'· 7 ••PW 'IPl'l
224 THE lOEA OF NATURAl RIGHTS G ERSON. CONCILIARJSM, CORl'ORATISM, AND INO!VlDUALISM 225

commentary ever since the twelfth century.47 Gerson began his discussion world-view the prelates gathered together at a council could not_ express
with a consideration of the temporal claims of the papacy;.a but the more 1he collegial authority of the whole church unless each had some inherent
important part of the argument from our point of view dealt with the au- .1uthority of his own to bring to the assembly.
thority of the pope in relation to other "dignities" and "offices" within the But there still remains a question of why Gerson chose to defend that
church. Some "adulators," Gerson noted, claimed for the pope an absolute .1uthority so emphatically and repeatedly in terms of rights, iura. He could
plenitude of power in this sphere at least. Against this, Gerson asserted Ii.we used other language. The autonomy of lesser prelates was often de-
that papal power was given for the "edification" of the church. Referring h'nded by referring to their status or rank or dignity or hon_or or ~ffic~, and
again to Paul's image of the church as one body, he wrote that it was < ;erson himself sometimes used such terms. The emphastS on 1ura m the
wrong for the pope as head to usurp against nature "the duties of all the 1>c potestate ecclesiastica and in the declaration of 1409 is perhaps explained
other members ... if all is eye or head, where is the foot, where is the i.y the fact that Gerson had already developed a sophistical~ concept
hand?" Here Gerson spoke of duties (officia) but soon, as the argument pro- , ,f i11s in his earlier writing, and found it well adapted for use m the _later
gressed, the duties turned into rights.49 In order to prevent abuses of papal ,·ontroversies. Moreover, the earlier theory was a broader one. The rights
power, Gerson wanted to establish that a general council possessed an that we have seen Gerson defending so far were typically medieval ones,
authority greater than that of the pope. Accordingly, he explained that a 11ghts pertaining to a particular status or offic~; and _the s~ift .from this
council included "every hierarchical status of the whole Catholic church" !..ind of right to a concept of subjective natural nghts, •"!'enng mall per-
and that the two essential such hierarchical ranks were those of bishops ..ons is often seen as an essential difference between medieval and modem
and those of priests with care of souls. Then, to defend the inherent au- tho~ght. But, in Gerson's work, the argument m~ved in the_~pposite_ di-
thority of these prelates in a council, he deployed the rights language that 11-ction; the specific rights claimed for prelates in the co_nahar treatises
he had formulated earlier in the university declaration of 1409: .ire only particular instances of a more general concept ~f n~~s d~vel~ped
111 his earlier theological writing, especially the De vita spintuah ammae.
In support of this is the decision of the sacred faculty of theology of
1 lcnce, to understand the foundation of Gerson's theory of subjective
Paris. . .. The lord priests are minor prelates in the church .. . to whom
belong, by reason of their status, a right (i11s) of preaching, a right of hear- 11~hts, we need to tum back to this earlier work.
ing confessions, a right of administering sacraments, a right of giving
burial, a right also of receiving tithes and other parochial rights (iura). 50 l( IG HTS AND REFORM
It was immediately after this lengthy adumbration of iura that Gerson The opening chapters of the De vita spirituali animlle introduce us to the
moved on to his formal definition of ius in Consideratio 13. Because of the ..1-cond main theme of the conciliar movement, reform of the church. When
whole tradition of ecclesiology that he had inherited, it seemed to Gerson , nnciliarists wrote about "the reform of the church in head and members"
necessary to defend the rights of individual bishops and parish priests, they were usually thinking mostly about the reform of the he_a d-:-and
precisely in order to assert the supremacy of a general council. The con- <;erson certainly shared this concern. In the De potestate eccles1astrca ~e
trast between organic and individualistic views of society that modem , umplained about the excessive centralization of power in th~ papal cuna,
authors emphasize seems never to have occurred to him. In Gerson's the endless lawsuits that were carried on there, the exaction of taxes,
tlw conferral of countless minor benefices by the pope, "and innumerable
47. ~uvres, 6:236. For the canonists' views see A. Stickler, Nlmperator vicarius papae, H .,1 milar things."51 But in the earlier treatise, De vita spirituali animae, Gerson
Mittrilungtn des lnslituts for Oesterrrichischt Ceschichtsforschung 62 (1954): 165- 212. was mo re concerned with the reform of individual members of the chur(·h,
48. Here Gerson used an argument from John of Paris (which he probably knew through with the renewal of spiritual life in the souls of Christians who had to
Pierre d 'Ailly). Truth occupied a middle ground between Hdetractors" and "aduJators" of the
papacy. ..tru~~le for salvation in a still unreformed church. .. . .
49. Oeuvres, 6:239. Gerson referred to individual rights in the mystical body in a different In Lectio 1 of the De vita, Gerson observed that the spmtual life mfuSt•d
way in the Tractatus dt unitatt tcclesiat, written in January 1409 at the same time that he was mto the soul at baptism could bt• lost by mortal sin and recovl'fc-<l by Im·
preparing the University's statement on the Jean de Gorrell affair. After referring to tilt- church
as a corpus mysticum, he wrote, NE! quaedam vera seu praetensa jura possunl dt'St'ri . ... Hoc r; 1. ( H-ur1rr.1. 6; 224, 219. On (;..noon "" nolormrr ,..... l '11Mu•'. /ron Gt~m amt S. 01.m1'f1I.
nimirum dicta! naturae lex ut pars quaelibet pro suo to lo llalvando ~lt'l t•I t>xponat" (( >t111•rt:" ·· nu· lJnlvt•,-,.lly .m,t lhl' Clnm·h. l'•ll.. 11•• uf H,.fnrm In Jr1m <:.Onion: Mtdit1"1lin rt /1111111ml-
6:137- 138). GeTSOn had in mind here lilt- abdic,.tit>n or d l'J>tlfllllun u f lhr rlval J"'f"'~ - ' " " · ru•w ,...rlr:o, I ( 1'1711): 111 11to l 111 lhr .. 1111'• l'" wrt II • n•urw 11111•11 ..,.., "''"' ( >tnwn l, tl11m1•
50. Orourts. 6: 242 (emphMiM n1ldt'<I) "1""11111/1• (I ••hlrn. l'lt1'1)
226 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS GERSON. CONCILIARISM, CORPORATISM, AND lNOIVlOUALISM 227

mility and penance. As we have seen, Gerson did not suppose that there Gerson' s first response to the problem was to introduce his argu~ent
could be any actual obligation of God to man or any contractual relation- ninceming evangelical liberty, a theme that had already been emphasized
ship between them as between equals. Gerson did not suppose that any hy Ockham and that would be taken up later by Luther. Christ's law was
person couJd actually deserve saving grace (gratia gratum faciens) by his .1 law of liberty according to St. Paul; Christians were freed from ~he
own unaided efforts; he condemned that view as Pelagian heresy.52 Grace bondage of the Old Covenant. ~et, even in the early c~urch, Augustin~
was always a free gift of God. But Gerson trusted in God's goodness. He had found it necessary to complain about the growth of severe burdens.
shared the belief of many late medieval theologians that God would not "Oh wise Augustine, what would you say of our times?". Ge,~son asked.
in fact choose to withhold grace from anyone who was striving to do rhc incredible variety of human regulations had become hke snares and
his best, " to do what was in him." It was an intensely personalistic, indi- 11ds," through which a person could hardly make his way ~rely."'
vidualistic view of each soul's responsibility before God. Although no one A major theme, pursued through the later chapters of t~e treatise, ":as
could actually merit divine grace, any person, doing the best he could, ac- 10 distinguish between the divine and natural law essential for salvation
cording to the strength he actually had, could "dispose" or "prepare" his .md the merely human rules whose transgression did not usually involv<>
soul for the reception of spiritual life by striving to obey God's laws.53 All mortal sin.
moral righteousness of the will, Gerson wrote, resulted from conformity But, in order to pursue this theme, Gerson thought it necessary to
to divine law.S4 ...upplement his treatment of Christian Hber:tf ~y introdu~ing the concept
Pursuing his argument further, Gerson asked, at the beginning of the of individual subjective rights. At the begmnmg of Lectro 3 he decla~ed
second Lectio, what was the nature of the law whose transgression took that, in order to continue with his argument, step by step, he needed f1~t
away the divine life of the soul. His answer was in part merely conven- In consider some related material. This "related material" turns out to
tional. Humans were bound l.Jy divine tdw, dircdlf 1cvc.llt"U l>} God, anJ hl· precisely the topic of our inquiry. " Hane materia est quid sit jus.. -~"
by the precepts of natural moral law, discernible by human reason. But ( :crson responded with the definition we have already quo_ted : "lr~s is
there was a further difficulty, and, in discussing it, Gerson was led to for- .m immediate faculty or power pertaining to anyone according to nght
mulate first his idiosyncratic doctrine of Christian liberty, an adaptation of icason."57 Right reason inhered primarily and ess~ntially in G<>?, ~e ex-
Pauline teaching to the ecclesiological circumstances of his own times, and plained, so in a sense all the creatures of God en1oyed a certa1_n 1us by
then a more general definition of subjective rights. The difficulty trou- virtue of the very fact that they had being and goodness from him. Here
bling Gerson was his perception that the divine law, essential to the life ( :crson wrote, strikingly, "The sun has a right to shine ... the swallow has
of the soul, had become overlaid by a mass of human tradition. The poor, .1 right to build its nest." So too man, although a sinner, had a right to

bewildered Christian, seeking to obey the pure law of God, found him- many things, like the rest of fallen nature.58 •
self bound on pain of sin by a vast accumulation of additional regula- In his definition of a right as a faculty or power, Gerson did not refer
tions. lt was hardly possible to enumerate them all. They came from ...pecifically to a natural right, but this further argument indicates that lw
canons of popes and local councils, rules of religious orders, regulations of was concerned with the rights that inhered in all creatures by reason of
universities, colleges and churches, edicts of emperors and princes. In the their very nature. The extension of natural rights to irrational creaturt>S
beginning Adam had had only one law to obey, Gerson wrote, and yet was perhaps a dubious move, and it was criticized by later writers who ac-
he fell. How could a Christian of Gerson's own day hope to avoid trans- ··•·pted Gerson's primary definition of ;us. But Gerson understood dt•arly
gression?s5
"'" Oriwrrs. 3:129, "O sapiens Augustine quid noslra tempestate_d ixisscs ubi ... _inrn•.11
l•1li" t'St varirtas t'I dissona multiplicitas onerum .. . inter quas velut mteT laqut'n'i an1111o1nu11
52. Ot-uvrts, 3: 116. ,., li..:.intia retia vix quis piam securus et indeprehensus incesserit." See_I.... rai!Cor, ~L-iw ~ml
53. ~uvrts, 3:114-5, 117-a, " ... peccatrix anima nitendo facere quod in se esl, se disponit h •.mgdic;,I Libt>rty in tht> Thought o f Jean Gerson," Proceedings of tht' S1:rlh l~trrnalHma.I < "''
ad vitam." On the background of this doctrine see H. A. Oberman. Tht llarwst of Medirool _..,,..,,of Mrilinvi/ Canon I.aw (Citti\ drl Vatkano, 19115), 351- 6\ . As PaKOl' p oints out, <.rr.!11111
Theology (Cambridge, Mass., 1963), especially at 131 - 34, 205-206, and, morl' rrcrntly, C. D. c11,.." not mt>ntion Ockham in di....:·w,.~ing rvnngl'liral lih<>rty (though hl> did ttf<'r to Odr.h11111
Brown, Pastor and Laity in lht Theology offt11n Gerson (Cambridge, 1987). ,.1...•wht·n· in th1• lk 11il11 ~11irilu11/i11111111r).
54. Oeuvres, 3:124. "Omnis rectitudo moralis ipsius voluntalis result11t t'X ronformi t.1tl' c,7 ( )f•ur•rts, :l:141. St-.• .ib<1v1• n Ill
ejus .. . ad divinam legem et ejus reclam rationcm...." 'ill 1 lruc•m<. :l 142. " 111 hum 1111Ml11m, urlum jll" hAl,.•l 1\ll inOm•mh1111. ,..,1 Atl \llu111ln1111

55. ~uvrts, 3:129, "Quod si Adnm vir tnlis t' I 111nlu•. unit-um •ll1<dplln.w pr.wn•ptum .tum hlrumlu 11.t nhllflc•11nclu111 'lie """"'""""'I"... • 111ur lu• h11hrt'"ImullA •Intl rt
I'""'"
habt>ns in illo curruil, nos inlt-r innunlt'r.1hili.1 1p1.11i1t-r r vn1 t.•nu1..r .1hnc• I r<"AhHA•' "~'"''" ""'" 1lr11•llc ,,. .. -
GERSON. CONCtLIARlSM, C ORPORATISM, ANO INOIVIOUAUSM 229
228 THE [DE.A OF NATURAL RtGITT'S

that humans enjoyed natural rights in a different way from the rest of cre- But Gerson meant more than this by ius. After his original definition
ated beings. He wrote that humans shared the gift of divine reason in a ,,f the term, the argument in Lectio 3 took a new tum, a sort of digressio~
unique way, by participation (participative). Human reason in its highest from the main theme of the treatise as a whole. This next step of Gerson s
form (synderesis) couJd discern universal principles of good, and, from .1rgument was concerned with the idea of ius considered in relation to
these, could derive more particular rules of conduct. The basic command- ~overnment and property, the familiar themes of so many later natural
ments of God, divinely revealed in the Decalogue, were also accessible to rights theories. And this phase of the argument leads us finally to the
human reason as natural law.59 Thus, man could live in conformity with third major concern of the conciliar movement, the defense of the true
God's law by exercising his inherent ius, a faculty or power in accordance fai th, particularly against the errors of Wyclif which were eventually con-
with reason. demned (along with their later Hussite variations) at the Council of
The relevance of this argument to the preceding discussion should be Constance.6 • Gerson was perhaps reminded of this complex of problems
apparent. It was the whole vision, set out in Lectio 2, of striving human by the actual terms of the definition of ius as a "faculty or ~ow~r'' ~hat had
souls seeking to renew their spiritual life in a church which set "snares" for 1~rown out of his earlier argument. After formally defining 1us m th~
them, which crushed their Christian liberty with "servile burdens," that terms he wrote that this same faculty or power could also be called a tit11-
led Gerson to his definition of ius as subjective right at the beginning l11s iuris, a lawful title or entitlement, 62 and he added, as we have seen,
of Lectio 3. For the individual Christian to reform himseli, to renew "the that man retained a right to many things although a sinner. But the whole
spiritual life of the souJ," he had to follow divine and natural law (lex); difficulty with Wyclif's teaching in this area was that he d enied ~o a s~nn~r
but in order to do this he needed an innate power or faculty by which he .my rightful title to d ominion. Gerson evidently felt that, at this pomt m
could discern this law and fulfil it (ius). This way of correlating lex and ius his argument, he could not ignore a problem implicit in his own treatment
persisted in Western rights theories for many centuries. It was finally of ius as a faculty that was not forfeited by sin.
expressed, most simply and clearly perhaps by Christian Wolff, "The law The issue of right and dominion had grown out of the old disputes
of nature (lex) obliges man to perfect himself . . . ius is called a faculty or over Franciscan poverty. Richard FitzRalph, invited by Pope Clement VI in
moral power of acting . . . ius provides the means for what lex prescribes as 1150 to reconsider these questions, developed a theory of dominion based
an end."60 This was Gerson's view too. For Gerson the first natural right on divine grace. Since God was lord of all things, he argued, only men who
was a right of the soul to strive for its own perfection by acting in accor- 1•njoyed God's favor could exercise licit authority on earth. This was not so
dance with God's law-which, in its central moral precepts, was known to shocking in itself. There were scriptural and Augustinian texts that co~ld
human reason as the law of nature. be add uced in support of such a position; and Giles of Rome had earlier
h;ised a whole papalist ecclesiology on similar arguments. But, in the gen-
1•ration after FitzRalph, his conclusions were developed in a radically
Ius AND OoMINlON
.mtinomian fashion by John Wyclif. Wyclif argued that, since the rulers of
So far Gerson's theory of rights is a sort of Christian psychology, the church were evidently corrupt, they had forfeited all their rights as
related to the second objective of the conciliar movement, the reform of prdates. They could exercise no licit dominion-rulership or ownershi~
the church in head and members-especially in the members. Gerson was over the church or its property. Accordingly he urged the secular power m
concerned with the innate "right" or power or faculty or liberty of the in- England to embark on a radical policy of d isendowing the church."-'
dividual soul to reform itself, to strive for its own salvation even in a
worldly, legalistic church.
h J. C..crson did not mention Wycli( specifically in the D~ 11i ta spiriluali animal'. I le rl'f<"rml
59. ~lltl1l!$, 3:142, n!Jeinde, sicut dicta ratio participative in creaturis rationabilis dividi ""'Yto FitzRalph, - dominus Armachanus" (145) and to "qu~am e;1t doctorib ull ~n.Klkam•
solet a doctoribus in portionem superiorem et inferiorem sic s unt ejus dictamina multiplicia; , .1 lung<' dl'lt>rius quosdam ex haereticis ... ." (15 1). Perhaps an 1402 he knew Wychf ll vl.. ws
quaedam sunt circa universalia principia . . . alia s unt dictamina circa condusiones ex I •y n•pu te but had n<>I actually studil'tl h is writing.... In latN work.., C".erllOn rt'ft>rl't'd lo Wydll
eisdem principiis deducibi!es. Ex primo officio nominatur ipsa ratio synderesis . . . nulla est loy nnme. (Fur references!'!('(' (N'ur•m<, Hl:M4.)
veritas ita naturaliter cognita quin in superiori lumine superinfuso divinitus possit agnosci. r.2 " . . . haK po~la!' !K'U (an1ltltll 11lll••r t lluh11• j11rll• vornrt'lur-" (0..111•rr.<, '.I: 142). F.IPl<'wl"•n•
Hoc liquido constat in decem praeceptis. . . . Cf. 135 u •• • lex vera naturali!I innititur dicta·
N l ;..,-,.on rrf1•rn:'tl tn a pril'llf'll right of ,....·rtvlnK11th,...'"' A " ju• rt tltulum" (C N'urrrr.i, 41"'.l I)
mini ra lion.is.
N ti\ f\K""'' nutlin.• of thr 1trv.l11pmrnl l n11n l'lltl<alph In Wydlf (with muct.·r~1 llkrah1rr
60. C. Wolff, Jn,tilutionts juris nalurnl' l'I Km lium NI., M. Timmmnnn Inc ;r,.,,mmrllr Wl'rkl', "" tlwir t<'1'•·hh1K•l I• 11mvlil1•1I hy I I 1 I law•1111. ''Hh h11ttl l 11l 1H11lph ""'' 011' 1·11111 h•C' nl h
Abt. 2, 36 vols . (Hild~hl'lm, 1%8 K'.l). 2f.:2.1 24. ( ·,.11lury l'o v,.rly ( "n11lruvr1•lr• ," /111m111I 1t/ I " lr•llf•ll111/ ll l•fl•IV :14 (1'1111) 'll'i 44
230 TuE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS GERSON. CONCIUARISM, CORPORATISM, ANO INotVlDUALISM 231

There were elements in Wyclif's thought that might have appealed to cording to the rules of evangelical right" and a human dominion "accord-
a conciliarist. An acceptance of the idea that a bad pope automatically ing to the rules of human right").68 This power of dominion was a gift
ceased to be a pope at aJI could have provided a simple solution to some freely bestowed by God, in the first place on Adam. "Natural dominion is
of the outstanding problems of the Great Schism. There was even a re- a gift of God by which a creature has the right (ius) immediately from God
spectable canonistic tradition that could have been used to support such to take inferior things for his use and preservation." Dominion, then, was
an approach. But Gerson saw that Wyclif's argument, if pressed to its logi- one form of right, and it was related to the basic end of self-preservation.
cal conclusion, would lead to mere anarchy. If only those prelates who Jn Adam this natural right included the power over the birds of the air and
enjoyed God's grace could possess licit dominion, and granted that there the fishes of the sea described in Genesis, and it also included the power of
was no sure way of knowing the status of any individual soul before God, liberty.69 The crucial point is that, for Gerson, this natural right of domin-
then there could be no certain authority in the church.64 ion was not wholly lost by Adam's fall "No one is such a sinner as to have
Gerson's concern with this theme, a central issue of the conciliar no dominion that can be called natural." 70 Gerson had argued earlier, as
epoch, dominated the next phase of his argument, where he attempted to we saw, that all creatures possessed some kind of ius by the very fact that
derive a whole theory of government and property from his initial defini- God conferred existence on them; now he added that if man had lost all
tion of ius. his God-given natural right after the Fall he would have been simply an-
Now it remains to show how, from ius so defined . . . there arise polities
nihilated.71 God continued to bestow his gifts freely even on sinful man.
and many jurisdictions and various dominations, kingdoms, and ruler- Human liberty, he noted, persisted even after the Fall. And toward the
ships.65 <.• nd of his discussion, Gerson also defended the persistence of a kind of in-
.1lienable natural right to use the things essential for self-preservation. A
After a brief reference to the opening chapters of the Decretum, Gerson friar might renounce all civil ownership, singly and in common, but he
wrote modestly that he would say things "not other than others but would always retain a "natural title" to the necessities of life, a ius nutriendi
perhaps otherwise." His discussion, he explained, would solve the dif- rnrpus, since, in case of necessity, all things were common.n
ficulties that perturbed many people-whether an unjust person could After the Fall, other forms of dominion were instituted. Civil or
justly hold dominion and whether a person who fell into mortal sin im- human dominion, based on human law, included coercive rulership and
mediately lost dominion, and how members of religious orders retained private property.73 Licit dominion of this sort existed even among infidels.
or did :lot retain dominion over common goods. After the Redemption there was also a kind of evangelical dominion, a
It is interesting that Gerson, like many later natural rights theorists, n>mmon right of all Christians to all things, in accordance with the words
took ius as a primary category of thought from which other legal and of Paul, "having nothing yet possessing all,'' 14 a right that was founded in
political relationships could be derived. (He even claimed, again like the
rights theorists of later ages, to be arguing in a mathematical manner, to 08. Ibid., Gerson applied the same threefold classification (divine, natural, and human)
be constructing a sort of juridical geometry.66) We need not pursue a11 the .1L...1 to politia and jurisdiclionts.
intricate details of his arguments. Gerson distinguished three types of do- 69. Oeuvres, 3:145, HErit igitur naturale dominium donum Dei quo creature jus habet im·
minion and, of these, the concept of natural dominion was most important "''"liate a Deo assumere res alias inferiores in sui usum et conservati.o nem... . Hoc modo
l1.1huit Adam dominium super volucres coeli et pisces marls ... Ad hoc d o minium Spl'<'lan•
for his rights theories. "Natural dominion," Gerson wrote, "is an immedi- poh~t dominium libertatis. . . .~
ate power of taking things .. . into one's power and use according to the 70. Otuvres, 3:146, " ... null us erit ita peccator quin habeat al.iquod dominium quoJ Jtd
rules of natural right.''67(Similarly there was an evangelical dominion "ac- 1•11h•rit naturale . . . habet saltem domi nium libertatis in actu vel habitu."
7 1. Ot'11vm;, 3:150. After repeating that God did n ot withdraw all his gifts from a !linnt-r,
64. Oeuvres, 6:212. After mentioning the condemnation of Wyclif. Gerson expla.ined, • .rrson added "alioquin flueret in nihilum."
"Cur ita? Ne hierachus ordo potestatis ecdesiasticae maneat instabilis, vagus et incertus cum 72. (),.11v rl'S, 3 :156, " . . . d icimus titulum naturalem ad quern coruiequitur ju.~ n11trh'mll
nemo sciat an amore vel odio dignus sit. ... # '11ri•11s sic quod in tjus necessitate omnia !libi !lint ad hoc communia." On the carllt-r dt•vt-1
65. Ot-uurts, 3:143, hNunc superest ostendere qualiter ex jure sic descripto multiplices, • •1•mt•nt nr this doctrine !iee abovt•, 72- 7).
saltem secundum rationem, oriuntur politiae et multiplit l'S jurisdictiones l'I divl'rsae domi-
0
·1.1. R11tht-r JiMppointingly, wh1'f1 ( :rn1on rrli-1 tlw IM~ o f ht>W a right to lndlvidnnl
nationes regna vel imperia...." l'" 'f"' rly nmld .iris.• fmm 111111riich111l "l"lr of 111111111"1111w111•r.ihlp. 11n irnporlnnt 11<.•111• in vul
66. Ibid., Gerson compared his argument to that o f a " K('Omtotl'r vl'I arithnwlirns." """ ••.uli1•r 11111! IA!t•r rlicht11 thC'urh.,., lw w1111.. ahnply thr11I hr wouhl pM11 11v1•r thl11 mr11tlrr "fur
67. Ot-uvrts, 3:144, " Dominium m1turalt• t'!lt potf"!'hli< propim1u11 "-' "unu•mli " '" ;ili;i11 Vt•I lr.u 111tlrgn-io~in)t111111nud1. " ( lt-111•tr·• . I l'lf1 'I'/
ut a lias in sui f:acultatrm vel u11um i<t'<'IUl•lum n~ul"" j11ri1111l\h1t111i" " ·1-1 ( '""'"'" :1 14(1 7
232 THE IDEA Of NATIJRAL RIGHTS G ERSON. C ONCIU ARISM, CORPORATISM, AND INDrVlDUALISM 233

charity and lost by sin. It might seem for a moment that Gerson was fall- phasized again the individual right of self-defense in order to support the
ing into Wydif's error here; but the whole point is that, for Gerson, loss right of the whole church or a general council to resist an err~g pope. On~
of evangelical dominion did not imply the loss of natural dominion or can see the development of the argument dearly in the treatise, De aufer1-
human dominion (that is power or property held in accordance with l1ilitate sponsi (1409), "Since it would be licit for one single person to repel
human law). A right of human dominion could be forfeited by voluntary force with force in case of violence attempted by a true pope against life
alienation or by judicial sentence, but, Gerson insisted, it was not lost or chastity . . . why in a similar case should it not be so permitted to the
simply because the holder fell into sin. David did not lose his right of whole church?" 79 Once again, it was because individuals possessed rights
kingship when he committed adultery. It was the same with a sinful that the corporate associations they formed could exercise licit authority.
pope.75 "No hidden heresy, no mental simony, no hidden crime takes away To recapitulate: at every point in the development of his rights th.eo-
civil dominion, whether canonical and spiritual or legal and temporal." 76 ries, Gerson was motivated by his desire to achieve the central obJec-
H subjects cou1d desert their superiors at will, without waiting for a de- tives of the conciliar movement. His teaching concerning a natural right
finitive sentence on them, all government would be reduced to miserable of dominion was developed to refute the Wyclifite error condemned at
confusion.n Constance. His influential definition of ius as a faculty or power of the in-
An unjust ruler could be deprived of his "title" to rule only after judg- dividual soul, was developed in response to the conciliarists' demand for
ment and condemnation, and Gerson held that the whole church or a reform. Finally, Gerson's theory of conciliar supremacy itself rested in part
general council was competent to pass sentence on a pope. But, since no on his defense of a divinely ordained right pertaining to individual pre-
council was in prospect when he wrote the De vita spirituali animae, Gerson lates in the church and in part on his assertion of an individual natural
suggested in this work an alternative course of action based on his doc- right of self-defense inhering in all persons.
trine of natural rights. It will serve to lead us back to our original point of Joseph Wohlmuth was no doubt technically correct when he wrote
inquiry-the relationship between the theories of subjective rights devel- that conciliarism did not lead to a catalog of human rights in the modem
oped in Gerson's earlier theological writings and the corporatist concept of sense. Probably no one before the twentieth century ever conceived of
a general council presented in his mature conciliar treatises. To be sure, quite such an extensive catalog as we find in a document like the United
Gerson argued, an evil ruler did not simply cease to be a ruler. A pope who Nations Declaration on Human Rights. But Gerson's achievement should
committed arson or rape was still a pope. But nothing prohibited the in- not be underestimated. In pursuing the aims of a whole generation of
jured individuals from exercising a natural right of self-defense against church reformers, he formulated a theory of individual subjective rights
such depredations. No human law could take away this natural right, that included a natural right of each person to fulfil God's law, a natural
wrote Gerson. It was based on the title of natural existence conferred by right to liberty, a natural right to self-defense, a natural right to the neces-
God himself.71 Similarly every polity had a natural right to preserve itself sities of life. Moreover these doctrines were not forgotten. Transmitted by
in being just like an individual person. Later, when Gerson became firmly writers like Almain and De Soto and Vitoria and Suarez they entered th('
committed to the via concilii as the only way of ending the schism, he em- mainstream of early modem thought on natural rights and so influenced
80
the whole subsequent development of Western political theory.
75. Oeuvr~. 3:146, "Propterea manifestum est quod absque charitate potest tale do-
These comments on Gerson lead on to two concluding suggestions.
minium retineri; quoniam non in ea sed in alio dono fundatus est suus titulus. .. . " 150, The first concerns the conciliar context of Gerson's work. Perhaps th(•
" Numquid David perd.idit jus in regno quia adulterii crimine pollutus est? Numquid apud
infideles ... nuUus omnino juste politizat? Absit . . . non perditur eorum jus regulariter
absque peccatis manifestis ... quae stare nequeunt cum debito usu talis dominii in republica, 79. ~11vrts, 3:300. "Quoniam uni singulari personae fas esset in casu violl'TltiaE" atll'n
et dumper sententiam definitivam talia esse monstrata sun! et damnata.H t.tlat• per p apam verum contra castitatem suam vel vitam vim vi repell~ .. . cur !limilitl'r in
76. Oeuur~. 3:150, "Exhinc perpenditur quod nullus h.aeresis occulta, nulla simonia men· ,·.tsu non licl'al idem Ioli Ecclesiae pm dE"fe n.<Jione s ue l'I vio lentiae attentala«' caula n ·pn·"
talis, nullum denique crimen occultum tollit dominium civile, sive illud sit canonicum el 'iune.#o
spirituaJe dominium, sive regale et temporale.H 1111. An l'mphas i!I on community n11 w1•1l "" <m imlivi~ual right:t.p<'nt:i!ltl'd «'Vt'O In 1....·kr .
77. Onlvr?S, 3:151, " .. . quis non videat protinus omnia d o minia fore mi~ra rnnfu~ionl' S.-.•, <'.g., J. Tully, I\ Di~ctllr5" ctn l'n'l'"''Y /,../111 r.-ir 111111111~ A•fl'l'rl<41rr~ (C11mbrklgE", l<nlll), II ,
turbanda ?" ···nm~ a fund;imrntal 11!11111mptlon ul I A•d•r'• 1•ullll..•l thnught I.• , c:ontrary tu com m un m l•
78. ~uvres, 3:152, " ... humana con.~titutio jn!I hoc natural.. lullrrr nnn pu luit; fundatur 1 m.tl'r~tamling11. nut " ' '"'"' tn•11 •• 1111 IM•I•-'•" ' h1tllvhl1111I 1>111, n1lht•r, lo ll't'AI him In hi•
enim in tilulo naturali~ t'- i~ll•ntlnl' communlnilnt'" I><'<• lp~I .-n•nt11r111• rnllrn111ll ,,.1 'I"''"' ""rlnw• ro•l"ll""" wllh otlwr mrn 11ml with I ;,,.1 ·· <l'I . ··1... ·t.r'• t1n.,ly11I• 11lw11y• pn'!l111•fHllM'-
titulum COll..'l<'qUitur ju~ Jrfr11<kn•ll ,... ..t 1111-1" rrprll••tufl, hn·· ,.,, vi m VI n'l"'llc•n• ·· 111rn •>rl(Allllr<l lnh• • 1111111"'11011111111111ty •·
GERSON. CONCIUARISM, CORPORATISM, AND INDIVIDUALISM 235
234 THE IDEA Of NATURAL RIGHTS

whole body of conciliar literature should be reevaluated in relation to This suggests another more general, perhaps more significant con-
the Western rights tradjtion. There has been abundant work in the past clusion. The contrast between holism and individualism, with which
thirty years dealing with the influence of conciliar ideas on secular politi- we began, may after all distort rather than enhance our understanding of
cal theory,81 but this particular theme has not been much explored. Yet the history of Western rights theories. If we want to seek out the origins
Gerson was certainly not alone in his concern for individual rights. Pierre of a doctrine of natural rights we must learn to understand a medieval
d' AilJy, before Gerson, was interested in the same problems of dominion, religious tradition and a medieval society where the values of individual-
rights and grace that we have considered in the De vita spirituali animae, ism and of community were equally cherished. Holist and individualist
and Jacques Almain returned to these questions in a later age of conciliar doctrines can be forced to extremes where they seem mutually exclusive.
thought. An emphasis on the rights of individual prelates against the pope But they do not have to be so forced. Gerson wanted to reform the whole
was common in conciliarist literature. Dietrich of Niem wrote, "If the church as a corporate community in order to enhance the spiritual life of
rights of each indjvidual bishop are not preserved, what happens than that each individual Christian; and he believed that, to pursue freely " the
the ecclesiastical order is confounded?" spiritual life of the soul," each individual needed to be endowed with cer-
No one, at this date, would want to minimize the extensive influence tain inalienable rights.
of canonistic ideas on conciliar theories generally (Francis Oakley has re-
cently reemphasized the pervasiveness of this influence).82 But earlier
writers on this topic considered mainly the canonists' juridical exposition
of the holistic conception of the church. Jn considering our particular
theme of natural rights and conciliarism, it is important to keep in mind
especially the earlier canonistic teachings on rights, the transmission and
adaptation of canonistic concepts in the work of Ockham, and the com-
plexities of canonistic corporation theory. Earlier canonists wrote exten-
sively on ius considered as an individual right; it would be interesting to
see how much of this persisted in the works of such canonist-conciliarists
as ZabareUa and Panormitanus. Certainly both great jurists distinguished
carefuUy between the objective and subjective senses of the word ius, be-
tween ius as objective law and ius as subjective right.13 Nicholas of Cues
too was a canonist by training though we remember him now more as a
great theologian and philosopher. Nicholas is normally thought of as an
extremely holistic thinker; de Lagarde once called his conciliar theory a
"swan song" of corporatism. But Nicholas also wrote of "the equal natural
rights common to all men." 84

81. On this see especiaUy the collected articles of Francis Oakley, Natural Law, Concil-
illrism and Consnit in tht Late Middle Ages (London, 1984).
82. Natural Law, 796- 797.
83. Zabarella, CommtnlarUI on X.5.40.12. "lsidorus in hoc capitulo non loquitur de iure
generali quod ieglous vel moribus constat. .. . Seel accipit ius pro iure quod competit privato
in aliqua re...." He was discussing a phrase or Isidore incorporated into the Decrrtals, " lus
dictum est a iure possidendo." The commentary of Panormitanus on the same text was incor-
porated as an addition to the GIOSS4 Ordinmia in D«retales D. Grtgorii Popat IX cum glossis . . .
ad exnnplar Romanum difigtnkr recognita (Lyons, 1614) (ad X.5.40.12}, "Diffinitur hie ius, non
prout est generate nomen, sed prout applicatur ad certam rem quando d idtur: habro ius in
tali re." On earlier interpretations of Isidore's text see above, 124- 25. in I."cir;.i 1111io;alio111llf/~•rnllllf' d11 "'''.II""" l!(t ~ /11 /fn olr r t\m·rm Rf!(lnlt' (I A1\IY.1ln. I'J:l7), :l
!l'I 411 !12
84. Dt concordantia catholica in Nirofni de Cusa "Pf"' 11mnia, I'd. <;. K11ll1•n, t"I 111 .• Iii vol~ . NII ho1,1,. rdi•rro•ol lo lhr " . 1·11mm11111•111 "11111lum hn111t1111111 .1r.11141lrm u.11ivll4lll'm r l " ''
(Hamburg, 19)2- 95). 14:348. C.. dt' l.agnrdl', "l11dlvidu11ll11ml' ••I m rpurutlNmo• om moyc•n "K" 1111nlt.1 n•1l11rnll11 h1r11
ALMAIN, MAIR., SUMM'ENHART 237

sion of Ockharn's Octo quaestiones, emphasized the fundamental right of


self-preservation. He wrote that God had made man with a "natural right
or power" of acquiring the necessities of life and also of resisting aggres-
sion, even to the extent of killing the aggressor if necessary. He also wrote
that, by natural law, every-<>ne was obliged to preserve his own being, so
~
that self-preservation was both a right and a duty, and so an inalienable
.<
right. 2 Here Almain was restating a medieval argument that persisted as a

TEN
i• central theme of the major seventeenth-<:entury rights theories.
The writers of this period commonly distinguished between paternal

•.
power and the authority of a civil ruler which, they maintained, was de-
i1
:_'
rived from consent of the people.3 Almain noted that a community could
not grant to a ruler a power which it did not itself possess; so he argued
~ l
that coercive power, including the power of life and death, inhered natu-
ALMAIN, MAIR, SUMMENHART rally in a political community. This power did not come from any external

I
source, "unless it is said to be from God."• And just as an individual could
cut off a gangrenous limb to save the whole body, so too the community
could cut off by death anyone who threatened its existence. This under-
lying power of the community was the source of a ruler's jurisdiction. Re-
~

T he years around 1500 are commonly seen as a watershed in Euro-


pean history, an era of new departures in many areas of life and
thought. Copernicus was born in 1473 and Michelangelo in 1475; Colum-
ferring to an earlier opinion of Durandus of Saint Po~in, A1main argued
that the authority of a king did not come from God directly, but only in the

bus crossed the Atlantic in 1492; Machiavelli wrote The Prince in 1512;
Mair,H History of Political Thoughl 2 (1981): 31- 61 ; Q. Skinner, Tht Foundations of Modtrrr Po-
Luther posted his ninety-five theses in 1517. In the sphere of politics this
litical Thought, 2 vols. (Cambridge, 1978), 2:43-47, 119-123. On Summenhart see H. Ott, • zur
was an age of "new monarchies," of more effective, centralized govern- Wirtsc.h aftsethik des Konrad Summenhart,H V-wttljahrschrifl fiir Sozial-urrd Wirtschafls·
ments in various regions of Europe. Our problem is to understand how a geschichtt 53 (1966): 1-26.
peculiar doctrine of natural rights that had grown up in medieval ju- 2. Dt aulhoritnlt tcclesiat ti condliomm gmtralium in foannis ~rsonii opera omnia, td.
risprudence and was then nurtured by an obscure squabble about Fran- E. du Pin, 5 vols. (Antwerp, 1706) 2: col. 977, HDeus, naturae author, hominem condidit cum
naturali Jure, seu potestate, ea quae suae sustentationi ac conservatione necessaria sunt
ciscan poverty, and by the conciliar movement for church reform, could
sumendi - .. super quo Jure fundatur potestas eum, qui injuste aggreditur, interimendi, sl
survive into the new age and persist as a major strand in Western political . I
servetur moderamen inculpatae tutelae... ."; idem, Quaestio resumpliva in du Pin 2: col. 961,
theory. There was nothing inevitable about it. In some works of the early "Dominium naturale, quod homini convenit ex dono Dei, simpliciter est inabdicabile .. ..
sixteenth century the medieval doctrine of natural rights seems to persist Huie d ominio, nullum Jus humanum derogare potest, cum Jure inferiori non abrogetur Ju~
only as a tired survival from an age that was passing away. superius."
3. In the background of this argument was the Roman Jaw doctrine, repeated by tht-
canonists, that the popu/11s had origin ally conferred its own authority on the emperor. On pa-
MEDIEVAL SURVIVALS ternal and political power see John Mair, Jn Quart um Snrtmt:iarum quatSliontS uti/issimat ( Parl'I,
ln the first years of the sixteenth century, the ideas of Ockham and 1519), fol. Cllv, H •• • potestas enim patema patris ad !ilium est de Jege naturae .. . . Alia est
Gerson about the limits to papal authority and about the natural rights of potestas politica, et ilia convenit homini ex rorum consensu super quos habet talem potl't'·
tatem . . . . " Similarly, Conrad Summt>nharl, DI' rontrart11rus licilis rt illicit is (Venino, I 5M), JS.
individuals were still alive in the University of Paris; they were transmit-
4. Qwustio rrsumpliva, col. 964, "S.'<·umlo, 1111ppontndum est, quod in illa Communll11h•
ted in the works of theologians like Jacques Almain and John Mair, and in Jurt' naturali esl pott5ta!I qual'd11m, 'I"" lld ll' 111011, quorum v ita est in perturballnn<'m f'ltu,
the writing of Conrad Summenhart, who studied at Paris before moving pnlt!il a corpo n- pr~ndrl"I', rtl11m fl"' 111or1rfh; rl l11ttttl cfrducitur 11 pri(lri l'X rationc-11anr ll
to a chair at Tubingen.1 Jacques Almain, who wroh' an l'Xlcnsive discus- Tn m a11. 2.2.q.6S Arlk ulo I ... t"lllll ( ·umn11111llo •lrl l' 1l11d pl aul"torllatrm ocrldt'fldi, 11eoqultur
•11101.1 1'!11 priu." in Co111m1111i111lr, "' non•- ol11lh ""' • 11j1111n 111111111• 1dlf'riui1, 11l11i dkt1l11r f lc•I: "'K"
1. On Alma in and M11ir 8f't' J 11. llurn•. I 11rrl•lrl/•. ~'"·'<'"'1• 11111/ l'm1•irr 11rr ltlm ••/ Mmmr.-h_y
In ••11 ' '"' 11111 potr11lu n111ur11ll• •um'"" l'111r1rplum, Nu" 1~·,·1.1,... , Exo•1. .,. l:l 1111 .tr Jur..
1400 f ,' j]fi (C ldnrtl, l<Nl), 1'.\11 14'1, hlo•m . " l'r•llllH'"llrlll• rl ••1•/111111 11w l'olllknl hl••M of Jnhn
n11l11ritl1•, llflli 11h f'(f , ...I fllll llllhmllll lllhjlll• I 11•11• Ol•o fj'l'lf'hll ••
238 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS AlMAIN, MAIR, SUMMENHART 239

sense that God endowed humans with right reason through which they Mair echoed Ockham's argument that Christian law was a law of liberty
could discern the need to establish a governing authority. Moreover, Al- and that, if a ruler held plenitude of power over his subjects' persons and
main insisted here, relying on a text of the Decretum, a people did not property, they would be in a more servile state than the Jews living under
alienate its own jurisdiction when it instituted a ruler; rather the ruler held Mosaic law. Almain stated the same argument with a direct reference to
only a ministerial position as a delegate of the community. Just like an in- Od~ham.3
dividual, a political community possessed an inalienable right to preserve These late medieval scholastics thus preserved a whole tradition of
itself in being; hence it could depose a ruler who abused his authority.s On thought about natural rights, property and government that had flowed
this view a community was always greater than the ruler it instituted, the from the jurists through Ockham to Gerson; but, as Francis Oakley tact-
populus g:reater than the emperor, a general council greater than a pope. fully observed, their own thinking was "somewhat less than outstanding
Mair and Almain and Summenhart all discussed the emergence of for its originality." When we turn to their further refinements of thought
private property from an original state Clf common possessio~. They were about rights problems we may have a sense of a tradition that was in
especially concerned to argue, against FitzRalph and Wychf, that own- decline, perhaps becoming moribund. Too often the authors seem more in-
ership of property d~d not depend upon being in a state_of grace_. ~e­ terested in pursuing endless scholastic subtleties than in applying the old
tracing earlier pathways of thought in considerable detail they dt~~n­ tradition they had inherited to the newly emerging problems of their age.
guished between an age of primal innocence and the subsequent ~ondthon
of humanity after Adam's sin. All the standard arguments against com-
MAIR. RIGHTS AND NEEDS
mon ownership among sinful humans were repeated, including ~~istotl~'s
criticism of Plato's ideal republic. The Parisian masters saw no difficulty m Let us consider for instance Mair's approach to the problems of
assimilating Aristotle's position to the Christian myth of the Fall; the <?reek poverty and almsgiving. During the medieval period the canonists had
philosopher was evidently writing about the state of fallen men, Mau ob- worked out a body of law that acknowledged a natural right of the poor to
served, because he knew no other. Summenhart held that natural law and the necessities of life and that regulated the administration of poor relief
natural reason inclined sinful humanity to acquire individual property, through a network of ecclesiastical institutions. But, at the beginning of the
but he insisted that the actual division was made by human volition, by sixteenth century, Europe faced new problems of poverty and an inten-

I
positive human law.6 Property could have been instituted by paternal au- sification of old ones. Attitudes to the poor were growing harsher at this
thority, he wrote, or by the political authority of a ruler, o~ by the c~mmon time. To many people it seemed that the best way to eliminate poverty was
consent of those concerned without any dictate of a supenor authonty. The to punish the poor; more constructively, secular authorities in many parts
question whether property was instituted only aft~r governments were es- of Europe began to establish systems of public poor relief. In 1526, the
tablished or in a prepolitical condition of humankind had not yet become i humanist Juan Luis Vives wrote a pathbreaking book, De sulroentiont pau-
an urgent issue. It still seemed easy to argue that, even if private posse:- perum, advocating such measures.
sions were instituted by civil law, rulers were not the actual owners of their This was the situation when John Mair, a few years before Vives, took
subjects' goods, able to make use of them at will.7 In making this point up the problems of the destitute poor. He first presented the standard ar-
gument that, in accordance with natural and divine law, all were obliged
s. Ibid., " Nulla Communitas perfecta hanc potestatem a se abdicare pot~I•. sicul n~ to give to those in extreme need.9 Then he presented a host of subsidiary
singularis homo potestatem quam habet ad se conservandum in ~ . .. domm1um Juns-
dictionis Principum est solum ministe ri.a le in ordinem ad C~~umtatem.. · · .Non polest
questions concerning the relief of poverty. These are some of the issues that
renuncia.re Communitas potestati quam habet super suum Pnnapem ab ea constitutum, qua Mair thought worth pursuing. Does a rich man who gives to the needy
scilicet polestate eum (si non in aedificalionem, sed ad deslructionom regal) deponere i:'°t:-'.I·
cum talis polestas sit naturalis: et istius sententiae es t glossa. 23 q:3: Can. Ostendrl, ub1 d1c1t: II. Ma ir, De poltslalt papal' in ltmpornfib1t.• in Grrwnii Opt'rO 2: col. 1151; i\lmain, F.x~ili<•
"Populus habet Jurisdictionem, licet dicat Lex, quod eam tr~nstuht m lmper~torem. N~~ ;~ n rca drcisiones MnRi5lrr Gui/It/mi <>cn1m, ibht., m l. I010, "Ergo ex instituti()fl(' divina, Papa non
civitas, vel populus non haberet Jurisdictionem, quare pumn>tur propter dehctum Jud1c1s. habet supr<'mam Potestal<'m r>omlnll In 11h1K11li" homnibu..' et rebus ip:1<>rum: imo dkrR'
There is a similar argument in Almain's Dr a11llmril11lr rcr/t'!liM. nw n·ference to Durand us of uppo~ itum , ut dicit Ocn1m, t'RI m11ll11m l111rrrth .. Ir l'1 pt•miri<>S<1m . _ . not1mdum quot!
St. Pou~ain is included there at col. 971t I J' l Christiann. ~11 J'X S111orrmnt l .1t>r1 "'""· l'Tlll"' 11•1lf' In nnlinr ntl Vl'lt•ram Lrgrm, pllllt•l lnt'tihl.
6. Mair, Quarlum Srnlrnlinrum ( l ." il'I), fol. l 'v; S ummrnhn r t , / >r 11111lmrl11111s. :I!\, :w 1 2~...
7. As Mair ob!lervl'tl, a klnK 1lhl not own hi• l.lnK•lllm In thr w"y thnt ",..·h••litr nw1w.I hi~ 11. / ..11111r.• Mnmr 111 '1Ullfl1m1 S l'lllt11ll111m1111·-111. I 'llr11. 1111 h•-.11 v, "(Jullll..-1 nm1 ...i..trn•
book~. Qunrlum $ mtm,111111m (l'lllJ), fol ( llh." '"' 111111 " " ' " ' ' llA 111..·rum .tumi11111111 in 111••-.trc•mA l\l'l'l'JIAlt•lll' '""""" 1114 11111•1• llll 1tlll •••I lt1 P•hr111111"'' r"J1lh1tt' . ti...· •~ •nd11.111111 ...1
n"K"" 111 •'K" In hlhll11 1nr11 " rvhl••11,. l11 l11rr r11•l11t" rt <llYllM• '
240 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS Al.MAIN, MAIR, SUMMEN HART 241

poor give what is really already theirs? And if so, how can he really be said that this was an understanding of dominion different from that of ordinary
to give alms? Would it not be better for me to give to a less needy person speech. From a realist point of view, one could regard dominion as a rela-
than to one in extreme need, since the former would be obliged, out of tionship between a person and a thing; but this explanation was also
gratitude, to pray for me, while the latter, receiving only what was due to ;. inadequate because, for a nominalist, such a relationship has no real ex-
him, would not be so obliged? What if there were a thousand rich men and istence. Mair argued that it was just as difficult, or more so, to explain
only one poor one? Would they all be obliged to give? If I am required as a dominion in realist terms as in nominalist ones, and, without resolving the
penance to give alms should I give to a less needy person rather than to j! issue, con.eluded that it was better not to raise metaphysical difficulties
one in extreme need? (If I give to the latter, it seems that I have not per- about such matters but to discuss them in the language appropriate to the
formed a penance at all since I was obliged to give to him anyway.) If all 1! subject matter.12
things are common in case of necessity does it not follow that the poorer a Mair's argument really leads to the unpromising conclusion that
man becomes the richer he is, since everything is open for him to take? If rights language cannot be justified on either nominalist or realist premises.
four men are in extreme need and I have sufficient resources to save only I have not seen it discussed by any of the modem authors who insist that
one of them from death, am I obliged to save any of them? It would seem the idea of individual rights was derived directly from late medieval nomi-
not. I am not specifically obliged to save A or B or C or D, so it seems that I nalism. But, a little later on, De Soto, defending his own doctrine of rights,
am obliged to no one. If a person not in extreme need steals a cheese and dismissed Mair's nominalist position as barbarous in language and absurd
then is deprived of all his other goods, does the cheese become his own? in content. Who, he asked, would want to hear that ownership of a horse
May he eat it? And what if the original owner falls into extreme need was either the horse itself or the rider of the horse?13
before the other person does? Or afterward? Or at the same time?10 Some of Mair's other discussions of rights problems were presented
All this is standard theological casuistry. The questions are ingenious. merely as teasing unsolved conundrums. For instance: I and a companion
The point is that they do not address any of the urgent problems that faced go into a forest; my companion has a loaf of bread sufficient to feed only
European society at the beginning of the sixteenth century. Only at one one person; it is set down between us. Can I take his bread? It seems not
point in this extended argument did Mair touch on a real social problem. since it belongs to him by a two-fold right, by positive Jaw since he owns
He wrote that it would be licit for a ruler to prohibit mendicancy so long the bread, and by natural law which concedes to him the use of the bread
as he made other provision for the impotent poor.11 This was a timely when necessary. But, on the other hand, I am more bound to preserve
comment, and it has been noticed in some modem histories of poor relief; myself than him, which seems equal to a positive right; and the right
but it was only one passing observation in a long discussion devoted of nature applies to both of us; and the loaf is not actually in his posses-
almost wholly to abstract theoretical issues of the kind I have outlined. In sion. So I can take the bread, at least to preserve my life. No law forbids me
discussing the problems of poverty, Mair seems to have been much more to do so, and my natural right extinguishes his natural right. But, Mair
interested in sophismata of his own invention than in the social issues of concluded, "The opposite is also probable." 14 Medieval philosophers, like
his age. Moreover, in all his intricate argumentation, the concern to protect
the actual rights of the poor, evident in earlier canonistic writing, has 12. Quarlum Stnltnliamm (1519), XCIXv-Cr, "Nominates insectando d icere oportebit
almost disappeared. quod dominium rei vel est res ipsa vel rem ipsam possidens . . . conclusio inferenda ex illi.~
Mair gave answers to all the questions on poverty mentioned above; praemissis hanc infert, usus est proprietas"; Clllv, " ... diximus quod dominium rei esl usus
but sometimes he presented hypothetical problems about rights with- vC'I ius ipsius rei metaphysice loquendo: quomodo illud sit verum, cum usuarius habeat ius in
out any dear solution. He explored, for instance, a metaphysical difficulty rr, similiter fructuarius et !amen non habet illius rei dominium secundum vulgo loquentes?
Respondetur: sf'quendo principia realium in metaphysica, dicendum esset quod ius funda-
concerning the right of ownership (dominium). For a nominalist, dominion nwntaliter est res possessa. Formalitf'r autl.'m est habitudo et relatio ipsius pos.~identis ad wm
had to be something real, and this must be either the owner of a thing or pcKo;es.o;am. Sed no minates 5eCtando rt h"~ n•lation<"' nrg<1ndo s ive reales sivf' rationi" alitrr
the thing owned. According to Mair this implied that to have the use of a d kl.'ndum e!'t quod non o por1l't innlti in hi" m.1tc•riL• diffir ultatibus talibus, ~ loqui "t-cun·
thing or a right in it was the same as having dominion; but he conceded durn m11tNiam subit'<'lllm. N.Hn '""'I'"" dtll11"1l1• 1°•1 nlh,.. imrno 11111110 diffkiliu" applk .ir(•
malcri,im J f' qua k>quimur "''i" pu..lllnn lhu" 'I"""' 11umln,.lll:>11N. . . ."
t:l. Oomingo de Solo, />t' i11otll/11 fl l urr C ""''"n"'" "· I t;'"oti). 4 1. 1. 2KO, " Hot· v1•nrmlnnwn
10. Mair discussed all t~ qut'l<lion• In hi" U1111rlun1 '>mtmlru111111 (l'itlQ), fol. luxii fol. .ulmntwrt· non pr.wtt·rlt..>, 111 phll11•1111'hl •'""' ""I l•1., l1111 u lllM ·1i•m1ini,.t11rum lc><111111l1111rN
boO<V. l'<'IJl•I~ c•nlm 1111.tin' f1•r1tl 1l11111h1l11t11 tt1111l t'••I' ""' r111111111 vrl r1111itl'nt "
I\. lhid .. fol. hooclll v 14 Llt1111h1111S.-11lrnll1m1111 11'1111). "' Vllv
242 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS Al.MAIN, MAIR, SUMMENHART 243

modem ones who indulge in "thought experiments," were no doubt try- As I noted earlier, Marsilius of Padua had presented a similar distinction.
ing to clarify real issues by the imaginary situation~ that they concocted; Summenhart gave it a new currency. From this time onward a distinction
but an unfriendly critic might see an argument hke the one above_ as between the "subjective" and "objective" meanings of ius became a char-
merely an example of the kind of scholastic quibbling that t~e huma~1sts acteristic feature of early modem rights language. Summenhart next went
would soon try to laugh out of existence. It was the sort of thing that Vives on to provide a more detailed definition. He explained that a right (ius in
liked to make fun of. And Erasmus was studying at the College de Mon- the second sense) was to be understood as a relationship founded in the
taigue in Paris in 1495, when Mair was also_a student there. . person of the right-holder and extending to the thing in which he had a
John Mair was a master of formal logic. He has been descnbed as a right, and to his actions in regard to it.18
major figure in a "glorious flowering" of logical studies at the end of the In his next argument Summenhart set out to defend the view that the
Middle Ages.15 But when he turned to practical problems of rights and words ius and dominium, right and ownership, meant essentiaJly the same
duties his logical virtuosity seems to have been more hindrance than help. thing. Everyone agreed that dominium was a right; Summenhart wanted to
argue further that every right was a kind of dominium. This issue seems to
have been a legacy from the old Franciscan poverty dispute that took on a
SUMMENHART. RIG HTS AND OOMINION
new life after Summenhart revived it. Marsilius of Padua had explained
One might make the same critidsm of Mair's younger con~empor~ry, that, although ownership was a right, not every right implied ownership.
Conrad Summenhart, though it must be acknowledged that, m the first Hervaeus Natalis and Bartolus had made the further point that a right-
pages of his major work, Summenhart provided an_ exceptio~ally careful holder could be said to have dominion over his right though not always
and perceptive theoretical analysis of the concepts inherent m the wo_rds over the property to which the right pertained . Summenhart now wanted
ius and dominium. Summenhart began his influential book, De contmct1bus to argue for a closer identification of ius and dominium. He acknowledged
16
licitis et illicitis by quoting Gerson's definitions of these two terms. For that, if dominium were taken in a narrow juristic sense, there were various
Gerson, ius was an immediate power or faculty pertaining to anyone ac- rights, like use and usufruct, that did not constitute ownership. Also, taken
cording to the dictate of right reason (or according to the dictat~ of original in a strict sense, dominium implied some kind of mastery or superiority;
justice). Dominium was an immediate power or faculty of taking external but an inferior could have a right against a superior, a son against a father,
things under one's control for licit use according to rights and laws ra- a wife against a husband. So again to have a right was not the same as
tionally instituted. Summenhart first asked whether these were sound having dominium. (lbis argument had been presented a little earlier in
definitions and eventually concluded that they were. He gave the reader a the popular Summa Angelica of the Franciscan, Angelo de Clavasio.) But,
foretaste of his scholastic methodology by explaining that the answer to Summenhart continued, dismissing these objections, he was not accepting
his apparently simple question would consist of four suppositions and six dominium in such a strict sense; there was a broad sense of the word in
conclusions with one corollary. which ius and dominium were indeed interchangeable. His "proof" of this
The first supposition presented an important two-fold definition of was based on a standard definition of the crime of theft-"to take an-
the word ius, a definition that is not found in Gerson: other's thing against the will of the owner (dominus)."
Jus is taken in two ways. In one sense it is the same as law (lex), as when Whoever has a right in any thing can be called the dominus of that thing;
we say that the precepts of God are divine law (ius divinum) an~ t~e therefore his right can be called dominium ... for if someone has a right in
statutes of emperors are civil law (ius civile) . ... In another sense ms 1s .• a thing and the thing is taken or snatched away against his will then the
taken to be the same as a power as when we say a father has a right as re-
gards his son or a king as regards his subjects, and men have a righ~ over
thejr things and possessions and sometimes also over persons as m the las, quo modo accipitur, cum dicimw• pnln.•m habere ius in filium, rcgem in sull<liht!l, &.
case of slaves... .17 homines habere ius in rt'bu~ & p<>J01HC'P1.~ionlhm1 !iUi.•. &. e liam in pcrsonis aliquando, pula ln
sc.. ruis. .. . ~~
1

15. A . Broadie, ThtCirdtoflohn Mair(Oxford, 191\!i), 2"6. 18. Ibid .• HEt diff<'ninl illiw 11<'0-..ptlutlC'• 1111111 Im• ,...,·11ncln modo <.>st reh1tio M.'U lmtiitu<ln
16. Summenhart, Dt rontractilm~. ) . llll' work W.111 find ruhhiih<-.1 in 15(10. lundata in illo, qui didlur h11l•l'1' ht•, Ao lo1111tn"I'" In n•m, in quam, vt'I In q1111 h11~t ht'
17 Dr contraclibus, t, · rrim11 ll11ppo111tl11: '"'' 0·11pll111 1l11pll• lh•r. Vno mo..lo p mut ld<·m est, '·"''l"''m ;,d tt·rminum l'l'rnohmt A. 1111111111111""'· 'I"""' llfllN•I r•wn·t•n• In ttilt•m n•m, v1•l dn·11
quod j<'X, quo modo ac-d pitur, n1111 oll1 lm11•. 1""'' ' r1•tr1 I lrl ..-· lu" 1ll11ln11m, & nnuolilutiont'!I '""" 11111•1""'" ml t11·rm11111m 1•11111111111111111 ··,.."11.r·
• I hi• I• tlu· 1l1>1"1rhw ul rl.iht• llu111 M111lr
imJ'<'r;ito nim c'l\.'tt' iu" duill", v••l lr11l"''''"'" .,,'I""''!'""'"
Altu "''"'''"' drllur h 1• vi 1.to•m , • o-rilh"l11•1I
244 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ALMAIN, MAIR, SUMMENHART 245

taker would be said to have committed theft, and if so he has taken mainly in exploring all the possible implications of the terminology that he
another 's thing against the will of the owner. This follows from the defi- found in Gerson's definitions, the starting point of his argument. But once
nition of theft. And so the one who had a right in the thing could in a he had raised again this issue about ius and dominium it continued to be
sense be caJJed the dominus of the thing.19 discussed by other scholars, among them Mair, Sylvester Prieras, Vitoria,
As Richard Tuck observed, this is "a pretty bad argument." The thief stole De Soto, and Molina. Sylvester Prieras defended a version of Summen-
the thing from its rightful owner. If he stole anything from the right- hart's position,22 but the later scholastics more commonly rejected it and
~turned to the older point of view that a right-holder had dominion only
holder it was his right in the thing. The argument proves, if it proves
anything, that the right-holder was the owner of his right, not of the thing m the sense that he owned the right itself.23 Jn this form the argument lived
to which the right pertained. A little later, Mair pointed this out in refor- on in seventeenth-century discourse.24
mulating Summenhart's argument. Summenhart himself seems to have Summenhart's careful analysis of Gerson's definitions sometimes
half-grasped the point when he repeated his argument at a later stage of led to more interesting results. When Gerson wrote of a right as a "faculty
his work. There he wrote that a person with a right of use was "in a sense or power" associated with reason and synderesis he seems to have under-
the owner of the thing or of the use of the thing." 20 stood ius as a power of the soul, an ability to act justly in accordance
It is hard to understand what Summenhart's purpose was in intro- with reason and conscience. Earlier, we noticed that the medieval canon-
ducing and defending such a dubious position. One might think that he ists used very similar language in defining ius naturale. But Gerson, and the
was trying to frame a logical argument that would explain the current doc- canonists too, assumed by a sort of metonymic association, that the ius they
trine concerning a vassal's right in his fief. (The vassal was said to have a so defined also meant a power to have or do something. Summenhart,
kind of dominion-" utile dominion" as opposed to the "direct dominion" I think, was the first to comment directly on this point. Referring to Aris-
of the overlord.) But this was not Summenhart's point. He acknowledged totle's De anima he wrote that a force (potentia) or power (potestas) of the
that there could be use or usufruct without any legal dominion, either soul could be understood in two ways; first as a reality that elicited actions,
"utile" or "direct"; but he still argued that these rights implied a kind and in this sense the potentia was something absolute and not a relation-
of dominion in his broad sense of the term.21 Tuck suggested that Sum- ship; or it could be understood as a disposition (habitudo) founded in this
menhart was arguing here for an active rights theory against a theory of ~rimary reality. Understood like this, the potentia of the soul was a disposi-

passive rights or claim rights, but (as noted below) this does not seem to tion toward some external object and to the actions it could produce con-
have been his purpose either. cerning the object. In this sense the potentia was a relationship. And this
Clearly, Summenhart's need to pose the issue of ius and dorninium is how we are to understand Gerson's meaning, Summenhart argued.
arose from his concern as a moral theologian with the problem of theft. When Gerson wrote of a faculty or power he was not referring to an abso-
It was important for him to establish that there could be theft of rights lute reality of the soul, but to a disposition toward some external thing.2,
as well as of material things. But it was already well established that a 22.. Sylvester Prieras, Summa~ Sylvestrina~ (Venice, 1584), fol. 215r. Prieras argued that, i(
right-holder could be considered the owner of his right and could not be the word dominium were taken to mean potentio, a usage he found in Aquinas, then every right
deprived of it "without fault or cause" (as the canonists often noted). Sum- implied a kind o( dominium. Prieras also held that a son did have a kind of superiority over hi~
menhart's further argument seems only to complicate the issue unnec- father in that he cou ld bring a legal action against h im.
essarily. One is left with the impression that Summenhart was interested 23. Mair restated this position in criticizing Summenhart's argument. Q11art11m Snilrn·
tiorum (1519), fol. Clllv usuarius habet dominium usus et usufructarius habet dominlum
H • • •

usufructus.... " Mair used the terms #imperfect dominion# and #perfect d o minion# to di.1tin -
19. Ibid., u5ec1 ita stride hie non accipiemus. Quod autem possit ita large accipi, vt conuer- g11ish bt>tween a right of use and actual ownership.
tatur cum iure probo: quia quicunque habet ius in aliqua re, potest did dominus illius rei: 24. The idea that a person's rights form a part o f h is "property" is pervasive in l..ockt•. A
igitur iUud ius poterit did dominium. Consequentia nota, antecedens probatur: quia qui- "'"''"" hilt diffol"l'nl re<1ding of tht' n'lation,.hip l>t'twrt'n i115 and dominium in Summt'nhtirt 1~
cunque habet ius in re: si ei surriperetur, vel subtraheretur, res ilia eo inuito, surripiens 1•rt'S<'n1t-.I in Bn:'tt, Ubrr-ty, Rixlit n11d Nt1t11rr
diceretur furtum commisisse, & si sic, ergo !'lurripien.• conlrt'C°l.1uit rem <1lienam inuito 2~ I >r Cm1trnr li1'11.<, 2, " Polrnti,,, !0<•11 I"'" '"'''" iuurn111' ,·,1pilur dupliciter. Vnu m o.Jo"'''"'
domino: tenet consequentia per diffinitiollf'm furti. F.t ~r <:t>nlW<lllt't\~ illt•, qui habuit ius in ca 1i.1li1t•r s.•u fu nd11m1•nl11lih•r pm rr111ll11I" 1111111111•• rlidt111.t .1du11m, quom<>do potmli11 "'llm11r
re, poterat aliquo modo dici domi111111 illlu" l't'I.°" l'nr tlw dvll 1.,w Jl'finition of tht•ft S('C inst. 1·"1 n -s .1!is<1l11t;l, & non n•l11ll..- •1111111111111 1rl11llu 11"111••1 ••11tlt.1• l'lk iti1111. Alio m0tfo fnrm,,111 ..1
4.1.6, HFurtum autem fit . .. nun 'l"I" .u..11•111 n-111 l11vll11 il11mlno n111tn.,·t11t.H I. prn J'<'r ~· ~iKnifknh1, & Rh° NII htd•lhulu "nl111"1• l1111tlnti\ In tnll n•nlitrllr, q11 11m h:ihltml lnrm
20. OrC11ntr11.-li/m.c, 2"1 1..,1.,.1 .mlmn n.t 1•hh•1·t111n o\ 111 l11• 11111•l111 ll•llt1• 11 "" t II•" o l •I,.. 111111. & """ l'<tlf'ntlfl ,.,., rrl11t111 •·
2 1 lhlti . I,·• dvllltrt h>1111•111l11. 11lh111I• 11..1...1 h1• ht u• .. 11o11101, 111 """"' 111 11h•1hlt1n•1.111. 'i11111111<•11h1trl w01" lwn· 1•11•,llll ""'"'· ht 1111111•1 • "1111lto•1 1..i.11111, n ~'""'""''Yul rnrllrr nq~ 11
v1•l 11"11fr111·t11111 11111hllllPll111111 h11l"'I tl11111t11t11111 tlllu• trl. Ur• 1lhn turn IU~ 111111• " 11w11lflllt111 on lh•· ll11•ury 11f th.. -.1111 111 ~tl•lutl" •I Ir,,,.,,,,,,
THE IDEA OF NATURAi. RIGHTS Al.MAIN, MAIR, SUMMENHART 247
246
Summenhart thus understood a right as a power that gave rise to a re- If the penalties were to be called rights at all it was in a "material" sense;
lationship between a person and the object of the right. they referred to the subject matter in regard to which the king's right was
Summenhart next considered the significance of the two words, po- exercised.28 In similar fashion the tithes and offerings that a parish priest
testas and facultas, in Gerson's definition of a right. A simple power, received were sometimes called his right.29
potestas, could be exercised licitly or illicitly; but a faculty-since the word A similar argument applied to the demons' right to punish the
was derived from /as-always implied a licit action. Summenhart con- damned. The demons' capacity to receive their own p unishment was not a
cluded, moreover, that Gerson's final words, "according to original jus- right; but their power to inflict punishment was a just right conferred on
tice," also served to limit the meaning of potestas to a power that could only them by God. Summenhart added that the demons did not exercise their
be exercised licitly. The right associated with such a power was "what we right licitly because they acted out of hatred for the human race. So too,
can do by right or licitly," "a power of li~tly d.oing som~thin~.'~ an executioner had a right to kill a crim inal handed over to him, but he
When he considered the word propmqua m Gerson s defimt10n, Sum- abused his right if he acted out of hatred or avarice. Summenhart here
menhart emphasized that a right must be a power "at hand," available for was drawing a distinction that has interested some modem rights theo-
exercise. Thus a sinner had a power to merit beatitude by e ventually re- rists between the possession of a right and its licit exercise.30
penting for his sins, but this power was not a right because it could not be In a final discussion on this theme Summenhart returned to his
exercised in the sinner's existing condition. So too "the least star" had the argument that the terms ius and dominium in Gerson's definitions were
potential to give out as much light as ~e s~, bu~ t~s could come about interchangeable. Gerson defined dominion as a power of taking things
only if God so ordained; so it was not a nght inhenng m t~e star. The wor~ (potestas ... assumendi res) for one's use. But, Summenhart asserted, this
potentia could mean a force or power but, in metaphysical language, it power was already implied by the words potestas and facultas that Gerson
could also mean a mere capacity to receive or be acted upo~, a sort of .re- used in defining a right, so again ius and dominium had essentially the
ceptivity. Summenhart's point was that a right could not be JUSt a passive same meaning, for the words potestas and facuftas could not refer to a mere
potency of this kind. GerS<m's choice of the words Jacultas and potestas, he passive potency. The right they defined was rather a power to act in regard
argued, could only refer to potentia in the active sense of the w~rd. •
11
to something. Or a right was a disposition of the right-holder in relation
The next phase of Summenhart's argument was a long d1gress1on on to some thing, that could be expressed only by some action regarding it.
this theme provoked by some further words of Gerson. Not ev.erything in Thus a father 's right was a right to act in correcting and directing his
accordance with right reason was a right, Gerson noted. For instance, to son. Anyone's right in his house was a right to perform acts like entering
receive a punishment, like the pains inflicted on the damned, could not be or leaving it. A person had as much right or dominion over a thing as he
called a right. But then Gerson added that, nevertheless, this underst~d­ had freedom of action concerning it.3 1 Summenhart finally noted that a
ing of a right was not altogether alien to scripture. As an exam~le he c1~ed
I Kings 8 which used the phrase ius regis ("right of the king") m referrm~ 28. Ibid., 3, "Secundo, quia dato, quod ibi posset acc:ipi ius a liter, quam pro iure supra dl'·
s<ripto · !amen no n oportet accipi quo ad multa ibi posita pro pena futu ra fili is lsra<.>I a suo
to various afflictions that were to be visited on the Jewish people by thetr rege: sed posse! accipi ibi materialite r pro materia, circa quam ip sius iuris sup ra descripti,
king. Also, Gerson added, the demons had a right to punish the damned. quae materia est terminus ilius relationis, scilice t iuris descripti: unde acciperetur pro rebu.~.
Summenhart objected to the suggestion that a right could ever be con- in quas quis habet ius, vel pro adionibus, quas exercere potest circa res aliquas ille, qui dicitur
sidered a mere passive capacity to receive punishment; so he. argue~ !hat habere ius s upra d escriplum circa tales res."
Gerson had misconstrued the scriptural text he cited. The ius regrs m 1 29. Ibid., " ... te mporalia stipendia que plebanus praetextu beneficii s u i (quod est speci<'S
iuris supra d escripti) simil iter & acceptiones illae, quibus accipit talia temporalia stipendia, 111
Kings 8 d id not refer to a right of the people to ac~e~t pena lties but to the mo rtuaria, oblationes & fructus d ecimalcs praetextu iuris, illa (inquam) & illae vocantur ali·
king's faculty or power to take their good~ for.h~s hc1t m;~._H was ~ere­ •1uando iura sua parochialia."
fore a power wholly in accord with Gerson s ongmal defimhon of a nght. 30. Ibid .• " . . . sicut lictor, vel spicul11to r hi!l>c•I ius ot·ddendi reum sibi lradilum, licl'I on-i
.i..ndl> abutatur iure s uo : si <.>x illMritia t•xt·n-rt illu.t oflid um, vl'I ex odio."
26. Ibid., " ... facultas enim ut a fas d<.>rivatur, connotat licite . . . quod d e iul"l' !l<.'U quod JI . lhiJ., 4, " Nam pol<'Sl.ts, vt'I f11rnll11N. •111111• J'ollilur 111.·o ~t'nt•ris in descriptionibus prllt'·
lidte possumus ... potestas autem :teeundum clktnml'fl prim<W iu~titiae alicui convcniens ~t •lie-tis, dl•n ot.il p oll'nti.tm nun p11J<11i1111111 ....i p111h1" h11l1t•nh•m Pit' in rillion<.> agt•ndi, & 1wr
potestas lidte agendi aliquid." . . . . nul.'14.'•lllt'I\~ im1 !'rit p11h•i1111~ p niJ'lll•)ll" "'' "Mr111l11111 11h11111.1 m ill.un n•m, v1•l In 11111 n • N11m
v.Ibid., uNam faculta1uilgnUici1I pol<'nll"m Adlw ,... hAh•·nh'lth'm. 1.t•. polt•nltam ah~m.I t>rttt'M' i1L• ••11q1..- .tominl11111 l'AI h"l•llt11l11 tllhl•. 111 111111 r•I 1111 n•m ill11111, In •11111m, v1•l In ' I"" 1111

agmdl circa allquld. Slmlillrr rl pc•lr•ltt~. "' prof'rlr •·ttpltttur, NIK11lfk1il Mntum pt h •1111.1m
1
lit•tu r t. hA•'<· h tthl h1<l11 11011 lrrmlu ..1111 1ul 11111111 1<•111 111• 1 ~•·• umlum ttlltl'"'"' ... -111111. v1•I
actlvt' lM' h11t>t-11h•m." 1tdh>n1•111. •11111111 h11l1t•11• h u• v"l 1l11111l11h1111 h11l ... 11•" ' ' ' " " ' '" 111.. 111. v1•l l11111.. rr l'"·mpl11m. " '"
248 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIG HTS ALMAIN, M AIR, SUMMENHART 249

person could be said to have a right in regard to himself, a right of liberty ignate a liberty, a freedom of action; but Summenhart's application of the
understood as a power to act as one wished within the limits of the law. He same terms, ius and dominium, to both irrational and rational creatures per-
added the usual reservation that this liberty did not include a right to petuated a confusion concerning the proper meaning of these words that
injure or abuse one's own body.32 later thinkers, beginning with Vitoria, had to address. Summenhart's argu-
Summenhart's argument therefore yields a complex understanding ment here was a sort of aberration from the mainstream of thought that
of a right as a faculty or power that implies a relation to some external eventually led on to modem theories of natural rights.
object, specifically a freedom to act on it in some way. Similarly a right over Summenhart was evidently presenting a theory of active rights. But
one's own person was a liberty to direct one's own actions. In a subsidiary here again we need to distinguish his own meaning from a common
sense ius could refer to the right-holder 's actual exercise of his right or, in modem understanding of the term. Summenhart was not arguing about
a "material" sense, to the object of the right. This is clearly a doctrine of active rights as opposed to passive rights in the manner of modem schol-
subjective right conceived of primarily as a liberty, a freedom of action in ars like David Lyons or Richard Tuck (who took over Lyons' terminology).
relation to other persons or things. Further on, however, Summenhart ap- These modern authors are concerned to distinguish active rights from
parently contradicted his own argument when he assumed (following passive rights when the latter are understood as claim rights or rights of
Gerson) that the words ius and dominium could be applied also to inani- recipience. Fo r Lyons a passive right is a "legitimate claim" that a person
mate creation and to irrational animals, creatures that acted out of neces- "can press or waive as he chooses."34 Summenhart (like medieval authors
sity, not through free choice. "The heavenly bodies have the right of exer- generally) fully acknowledged the existence of such claim rights. In the
cising various actions," he wrote. "Also the subcelestfal bodies have many passages we have considered he discussed the right of a king to receive
dominia and rights.. .. " Irrational animals too had a kind of "general do- revenues from his people and of a priest to receive tithes from his parish.
minion," consisting in their right to take the food they needed to preserve Elsewhere he often used the phrase ius percipiendi to indicate a right of re-
life. To Summenhart himself, no doubt, the argument seemed entirely co- cipience.JS Summenhart wanted only to argue that a right could not be a
herent, for he went on to distinguish sharply between this kind of right sort of empty receptivity, a mere passive capacity to receive something
and the right inhering in humans. "The dominion that pertains to rational without any legitimate claim to it. Again, it is hard to see why Summen-
creatures is something different," he noted.11 Only in humans did ius des- hart thought it necessary to make such an argument at such length; no-
body, so far as I know, had defended the opposing point of view that a
right was a mere passive potentia.
vel d ominium, quod habet pater in filium, est ius in £ilium secundum quod pater potest ex-
Nonetheless, Summenhart's argument so far can be considered a
ercere actum correctionis in filium, & actum directionis circa eundem. Et ius, quod ha bet quis
in domo sua, est ius secundum quod tale potest exercere illos actus in domo, scilicet ingredi, valuable contribution to the elucidation of the concept of a right-a little
egredi, & res suas inferre. Vnde tantum quisque habet iuris, vel dominii in aliquam rem: abstract perhaps, not always entirely persuasive-but still sophisticated
quantum actionis licet sibi exercere circa rem.· and interesting. However, Summenhart's analysis d id not stop here. The
32 Ibid., 4-5, · similiter Hbertas est quedam species iuris, & illud ius habet liber in seip- definitions and distinctions we have considered so far were only the start-
sum scilicet agendi quod libet. Vnde difinitur ius in instituti, de iure personarum. §.1. Est
naturalis facultas eius, quod cu.i que facere libet, nisi quod ui aut iure prohibetur. Et sic liber
.
·:~
ing points of a more intricate argument; there were many, many more of
habet ius s uper suam persona m, quamuis non sit dominus membrorum suorum ad ea ab- .- them still to come. And, as the discussion moved on to deeper and deeper
scindendum, aut ad alium abusum, de quo dicetur in quaestio 74." Jn Quaestio 74 (ibid., levels of complexity, it seems to become more and more remote from any
335- 341) Summenhart asked in what way a person was dominus of his own body. Specifically real problems of the late medieval world.
he asked whether a man could sell himself into lifelong servitude. He conceded that this was
legally possible; but, like Locke, he seems to have been thinking of "dru~gery not slavery." 34. D. Lyons, "The Correlativity o( Rights and Duties," N ous 4 (1970): 45- 55 at 49. ~
Summenhart compared the case of a ma n selling himself into servitude with that of the mas- Richard Tuck, Natural Righls Throrirs. Their Origins and Dcvtlopmrnt (Cambridge, 1979), 5 . If
ters of his own university-they were seeking a permanent stipend from the unive rsit y in WC' look for a modem analogue, Summenhart'~ aMlysi,oi, wilh its e mphasis on the status of th«>

return for an undertaking not to I.e ach elsewhere (ibid., 339). Sum men hart acknowlroged that right-holder, the rela tion o( the ril(ht-holllf'r tu lhl' c>hit'<I o ( the right, and the bundle o f e n-
there could be involuntary #despotic# slavery but he associated it with puni~hm<'nt for crime litl(•ment!I included in the righl, might rC'mh1<I 11M of 1lw righl~ theory of Johan Van dt'r Vyvn
or for participating in a.n unjust wu. S."t• his articl<·. "lnc Dodrirw of l'rtv.,lr I Aw Right..," In S. A. Stmu!'ll ed.. lluldixung/ibund~I rirr
33. Ibid ., 23, "Corpora enim l't·~ti11 h11l>c•nl iu,. v.iri.t." .1<'lio11M1 l'Xt' IX"l'lidi. .. . Corpor.:i W J\ . fnu,,,.rl (llurhan, 1111111), 2111 24f\
etiam subcclestia habenl mult11 tlominin ••I hir" l'I 1111hn"ll" lrmti11n,1lia, quonim K"rwralt• 1'>. l'or ;,,, prrl"i11irmli ,..., ..,.,,...·1111ly I•••'"''"' 111'11•. 1)1 :to. ~1111mwnh,1rt 11IM1 nrKlll'tl ho•n•
dominium t'~I iu~ 1u..-ipk·11tll r10t•11111 ....,,. vll11r • """"' vnlll<'m Altud 1•1<1 tlnmlni11111 •111tx l lhftl to 1•vf'ry ri11hl llwro• W4•" 1111 '""I"'"'""" 1ol •llic11lln11 • I II\) .,n,t 11>11vrf1M'ly lhlll "" nllll~a
nmvl>nil .-rt•11h1rn1• ralk>r111lt ·· llnn (ha""'' l'<'~M•n) imp II"' I" 1lj11hl 111111rn1tlw1ICI1111
THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ALMAlN, MAIR, SUMMENHART 251
250

Summenhart continued to present his argument in the form of an nine divisions of divine dominion.) Moreover, "this mode of dividing
exhaustive scholastic analysis of Gerson's terminology. Having suggested ought to show how the first four species of the first mode of dividing could
that the terms ius and dominium might be interchangeable, he next in- be reduced to the first member of the third mode-which it fails to do.".34
quired about the different kinds of dominion and the rights associated Then at last Summenhart gives us his own answer to the problem he
with them by taking up various classifications that Gerson had proposed has raised. There are, it turns out, no fewer than twenty-three kinds of do-
and asking whether any of them provided an adequate set of definitions. minion with associated rights; and, except for the last two, each of them is
The first classification offered a six-fold division of dominion into beatific a subdivision of one member of the preceding division.)9 I am presenting
dominion, original dominion, gratuitous dominion, evangelical dominion, here only the barest outline of an argument that traced out many obscure
canonical dominion, and political dominion. Summenhart considered each pathways of medieval thought. Summenhart succeeded, for instance, in
in tum. He pointed out, for instance, that beatific dominion, the dominion presenting Aristotelian physics in the language of natural rights. (Every
of the saints in heaven, included a right of their glorified bodies to pass element had a right to its own place in the universe.«>) And he was very
through common gross matter without resistance and to occupy the sa~e interested in the rights of demons. Were they a form of legitimate domin-
space as ordinary matter, even though it was.na~ural for a body to rest.st ion or not? As we work our way through the twenty-three distinctions
the occupation of its place by another body. Tius nght could be called a gift and subdistinctions we may seem at times to be wandering in a medieval
of subtlety. Also included in beatific dominion was a right that some_of labyrinth; but we assume that all this material must be mastered if we are
the saints possessed to cure particular diseases, or to control the behavior to understand the substance of Summenhart's treatise that is to follow. At
of fire and water. After these preliminaries Summenhart gave his own the twenty-first d istinction, however, we are casually told that the whole
definition of beatific dominion: " It is a dominion immediately from God of the subsequent work is to deal with only one kind of dominion, namely
belonging to the blessed by reason of their beatitude a~co~ding to the_la":s civil dominion.41 We suddenJy realize that nearly all the material we have
of glory or beatitude, justly belonging to many and mahen~ble wh~l~ m toiled through so far is irrelevant to what is to come, the discussion of
beatitude."36 Next he commented in detail on each term of his deftmhon. various problems concerning licit and illicit contracts in civil law that will
Then he went on to consider in a similarly exhaustive fashion all the other constitute the body of Summenhart's work. The rights of the glorified
branches of Gerson's six-fold classification in twelve columns of closely saints and of the demons and of irrational creatures, and in fact nearly all
packed argumentation. . the rights that Summenhart has discussed so far, have no bearing on such
In the next Quaestio, however, Summenhart tells us, m effect, that matters. The labyrinth leads nowhere.
all this was for nought. Gerson's classification was inadequate for six When we read Ockham on rights and dominion his arguments often
reasons. It dealt only with the dominion of creatures, not with that of the grow intricate; but we sense behind all the intricacies a passionate will of
creator; among creatures it dealt only with rational creatures, not irr~tional the Franciscan to defend the doctrine of his Order and to bring down the
ones; among rational creatures it dealt only with humans, not w1th de-
mons; among humans, it failed to deal with natural dominion. Also ~is JS. Ibid.. 22, " . .. quomodo deberent rrouci quatuor primae species primi m odo dividendi
division did not include the dominion implied by the power to work mir- .,d ml'mbrum primum huius tertii modo, quod non tacit."
37
acles or the dominion granted by Mosaic law. :w. Ibid ., 23. " Primo, quartus modus dividendi ronti net 23 divisiones. quarum sempt"r
Gerson's second classification presented a three-fold division-do- posterior est subdivisio unius membri praecedentis divisionis demptis duabus ultimis divi-
siunibus."
minion based on the title of sanctifying grace, on the title of supernatural
40 lliid., " Corpora e nim celestia habent ius varias actiones exercendi ... et quodlibct E"k•-
grace freely given, or on the title of som~ purely natural ':lualification like nwntum habet ius occupandi certum locum in uni verso . . ."
election or succession. Summenhart again carefully examined the terms of 41 Ibid., 25, "Et quia de solo civilc dominio <>st nobi.~ ad pmpositum in hoc trac tatu, ideo
the classification and again found them inadequate. It was the same with 1ll11J cnn~uentl'r subdivid<'fldum N<t." <lnr m i~ht h<- r<'mindcd here of thE' numerous ddini·
Gerson's final classification, a straightforward division of dominion into I 1111L~ of 111.< givl'n much l'arli<'r liy tlw 1·,1111111i.•l loht1111u•" Mona.·hus (<1bove, 4H). ffut Johannt':'I"

three kinds: divine, natural and human. The fir.;t krm ought to have been pnrpc>St• wai; difft>rent. 1 le w.1~n>1w••nwcl 111 provt.I•• "l"·dh« d t.1lioni; to illustralt• tll(• difft•r·
""' 11s.1J1,1"S of lht• word 111.< in R11111tt11'""''11110111< 11l (11tl•f •llu li•m"t•. I lis m<'aninK" W<'n" t>llt'!I
divided in many ways, Summrnhart cnrnplaint•tL (He went on to suggest th,11 .1 pr.11"1ic,1I jurisl miKhl 1•1wo1111h•1 1111111' • n111 I• nl l11w ~; 1111111u·nh.1 rt 'i; arJ1.11m1•nl wa" mnn•
' l""·11l,1llv1· 1h•1h•fint'tl ''"""' lwl'l1ly • h1•I• ul 111111111111111 /~•hit"• tlU' •lnmlnl1111 of dvll 11rnl
36. lJr ro11I rad ilms. S. • ·"'"" l,1w Still."'"' 1·u11M ""Y uf lu h1t1111t•• M """ ' huo ""' 1h,.1 Iii• tt11111mr11l 111,.rl.r<I tlu• t•rnl

:l7 llii·I.. 1q point nl "'"" ~ 11ut ..1 • .111u11l•th "'"'IV•I-, 1111 " "" O'Yf'I II h••l 1", 1111 y II 1rny l11rtl1<•r
252 THE IDEA OF NATURAL R IGHTS Al.MAIN, MAIR., SUMMENHART 253

pope who had attacked it. Summenhart seems to multiply comple_x~ties wanted to serve, at the courts of the great rulers of the age. There is no
merely for the sake of complexity. We understand now that the wntings talk of natural rights in Machiavelli's Prince or in Thomas More's Utopia.
of late medieval theologians and canonists were not so sterile as the hu- In considering the survival of natural rights theories we need always to
manists liked to suppose; these writers made significant contributions remember that it is perfectly possible to construct coherent systems of po-
to economic thought in their discussions on the morality of commercial litical thought without appealing to such ideas, and that, indeed, in any
transactions. The substance of Summenhart's treatise was indeed a useful universal history of political doctrines, theories grounded on rights would
summation of such material that was highly regarded by his contempo- appear as exceptions rather than as a norm.
raries. But still, twenty-three kinds of dominion! It is too much. Machiavelli and More were contemporaries of Summenhart and Mair.
A connoisseur of late scholastic writing might admire the architecture The university masters, surviving representatives of a medieval scholas-
of Summenhart's argument. But it is like the architecture of a late gothi_c tic tradition, seem out of place, in some ways out of touch with reality,
church, filled with intricate craftsmanship and fretted stonework, admi- in the new world of thought and action that was growing into existence.
rable in itself perhaps, but marking the end of a tradition. After a French The "silver-age" conciliarism of Mair and Almain, lacking the real zeal for
flamboyant cathedral there was nowhere further to go with that style of church reform that had given life to the work of Gerson and his contem~
building. And after Summenhart's twenty-three divisions of domini~n raries, was becoming irrelevant to all that was most vital in the life of the
there was nowhere further to go with that style of argument. No one did church in the sixteenth century. When new movements of Catholic reform
try to go beyond Summenhart' s twenty-three distinctions. Instead, half grew up they sprang from different sources. As for natural rights, we
a century later, De Soto deplored his predecessor's "gratuitous" multi- encounter a considerable body of technical argumentation about ius and
plication of terms.ti It was time for a new paradigm; ~~d, of c~urse, a. new dominium in the writings of around 1500; but too often it seems to degen-
paradigm was at hand in the literary culture and political phdosoph1es_of e rate into a mere scholastic wordplay that was drifting away from any
the Renaissance humanists. To them, the writings of the late scholastics constructive engagement with contemporary issues. Unlike the writing of
seemed barbarous, clumsy, and empty of meaning. Ockham and Gerson on rights it does not seem addressed to any particular
purpose. A humanist contemporary of Summenhart and Mair might have
seen the whole tradition of natural rights as just a murky stream of me-
ANEW AGE dieval thought that had finally petered out in the sands of a barren scho-
There was no certainty that medieval rights theories, embedded as lasticism.
they were in scholastic treatises, would survive in these new circum- Things turned out differently of course. The events that shaped the
stances; for a time such theories seemed out of touch with both the po- actual course of history in the sixteenth century, especially the Protestant
litical realities and the intellectual culture of the age. In the era of the new Reformation and the European encounter with America, ensured that this
monarchies, people everywhere reacted against the disorders of the ea~ly would be so. Silver-age conciliarism had a significant after-life in secular
fifteenth century-schism in the church, civil strife in several of the maJor constitutional thought, particularly in the works of Protestant resistance
kingdoms, a destructive war between England and France-and showed theorists.c And the discussion of natural rights, the theme that particularly
themselves willing to lend their support, even to pay heavy taxes, to any concerns us, was revivified in the Spanish debates that followed the dis-
ruler who could establish some degree of peace and orderly living. There covery of America. Quite suddenly, the late scholastic musings about
was much talk then of "the overmighty subject'' and less concern about the rights and dominion became relevant to problems of worldwide signifi-
dangers of absolutism. People complained more about "lack of gover-
nance" than about lack of rights. 4J. On this theme see F. Oakley, " On the Road from Constance to 1688: The l'olil ica l
In the intellectual sphere, the emerging humanist culture was al~ not Though• or John Major and Grorgr Buchan01n, fomrnal of British Studies 1 (1962): 1-:l 1; i.lt•m .
H

receptive to the idea of natural rights. Humanist authors emphasized " Figgis, Co nstanCt', and the Uivin1.,. of l'Ari.~... Amrrrm 11 Historical Review 75 (1%9): :lnt; llh.
above all the duty to uphold the common good; many of them served, or lne Protestant wformt'rs' •·mrh11Ni~ 011 "'"""'' olt•pr.ivity wa!< not at fir:<t c1m1lud vt• to ,.
"row th of natural rights tlworl..,. 11111 thr hAr•h ··~····r h·no ··.,. of tlw w.,r!' of Rdiginn .mtl 111 lhr
English Civil War !'ti11111la1c.. 1llrKt1111r11I• fur rrllKh•n• tnlrr.1!1011 and t•vc•nt11111ly l1'll tn lhl' 111·
42. IX iustilid d iurt, 4.2.1, 2116. Pl• Soto n•tnnw<I h• II l'C'lnllvc•ly ~im plc divl~ion of domin- knuwl..<lgm1•nt of frn-.ln111c•l 1..llKlnn """ """" "' ''Kht l >11 thl• ,..... my " Rc·llxl1111" IOxht": /\t1
ion into three l<lnd11, natu.-.1. Jlvinc'. 111111 h111111rn, with 11i.. 1111tc•r 1llvl1lt•1l lnlo tlominlon from I li~l ork.•l l't·r~pc-.·lh11•," hi I With•""''' Y10 11 l•1 Vyvt'I . . ..... l<r/1.11l1111N ""'"'"' 1<1.-<'' ' ill c:f11l'fll
civil law imd from c·nnnn l11w. l'1'"f"'•·l11'<': Rr/1.'<"'"·' l'rr•1,..,·111¥• ii ~111111•1 hi l!l'J'll. I'/ 4'1
254 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS

cance that would persist into the modem era. Can the domination of other
peoples by Western colonialists be justified in any way? What are the
rights of "backward" indigenous peoples? Are any of them natural slaves?
Are some human beings non-persons? Does everyone have a natural right
to liberty? to property? to sell-government?
Since Innocent IV wrote his classic text in mid-thirteenth century it
had often been maintained that infidels had legitimate rights; however,
the infidels that canonists and theologians chiefly had in mind were Mus-
lims, people as advanced in civilization as themselves. But naked savages,
idol worshippers given to human sacrifice and cannibalism-for that was ELEVEN
how American Indians were often described to European audiences-
could they have rights too? Could there be truly human rights, rights that
inhered in every kind of human being?
For a first answer we might take a final glance at John Mair. One of ARISTOTLE AND THE AMERICAN INDIANS
his texts illustrates a theme that has been much discussed by modem an-
thropologists and occasionally by historians-the disinclination of many
peoples to enslave their own members, those belonging to an in-group,
while feeling no such compunction as regards outsiders. 44 Mair acknowl-

I
edged, in conventional fashion, that slavery could be a legitimate institu-
tion since it was recognized in Roman and Jewish law. A person could sell
himself into slavery, or be enslaved as a punishment for crime or for taking
A ccording to one modern account, the greater part of Spanish
political thought in the first half of the sixteenth century was
inspired by disputes concerning the American lndies. 1 This may seem
part in an unjust war. But then Mair added a little paean to human liberty. an overstatement when we consider the broad range of political writings
It was abhorrent, he wrote, that human beings, rational creatures whom from the authors of the "second scholasticism"; but, in fact, even when the
God had commanded to look on heaven and raise their faces to the stars, sixteenth-century writers were discussing such familiar medieval themes
should be sold like cattle. And he praised the custom of his native Britain as the temporal power of the pope, the universal authority of the emperor,
where such servitude was no longer practiced.45 or the right of resistance to tyranny, the case of the American Indians was
That is one side of Mair's argument. But when he commented, in an- often present in their minds. Agostino Iannarone has pointed out how,
other context, on the natives in the newly discovered Indies, he simply before Vitoria wrote specifically on the Indies, observations on the rights of
wrote that Aristotle's theory of natural slavery was now proved by expe- infidels in general or the Indians in particular were often introduced into
rience: his earlier works on a variety of different topics.2
. .. hence, the first to conquer them justly rules over them because they are < Apart from many such casual allusions there is also of course a very
"' extensive body of writing concerned directly with the situation in Spanish
slaves by nature. As the Philosopher says ... it is clear that some men are
slaves by nature and others free by nature ... and it is just that one should America, ranging from Las Casas' passionate polemics on behalf of the In-
be a slave and another free, and fitting that one should obey and another dians, through Sept.ilveda's rhetorical, neo-Aristotelian defense of natural
command by the innate authority through which he is a master. Ac- slavery, to the formal academic reflections of Vitoria, cool and judicious
cordingly, the Philosopher says ... that Greeks should be masters over in tone, but evidently inspired by a troubled conscience. (In a letter of 1534
barbarians because by nature barbarians and slaves are the same.46 Vitoria wrote that his blood ran cold when he heard accounts of the Span-
It was the starting point of a great debate. iards' behavior in Peru ..l) There is also il huge body of modem Jiteratur<• on

44. See D. Ellis, HEurop<>an.q and th<' RI!'(• and F.111 ul J\frk;in Sl;ivc-ry: J\n lnh•rpn·talion," I. J\. I'. Mo nahan, /"mm l'rr11m111I I lullr• ·1111mrrl• l'rr"<•1111/ R~'{hls (Montreal. 19'14). 1411
Amtrican Historical Rnrinu9R (199'.l): IJQQ 1421. 2 "G~flf'Sis dd pt•n11hun,.11lu 11110111•1 '"' l'r•m l•m •Ir Viloria.ff in I.. Pf'rl'l\11 11mt J. M
1'1\rn: l'n·mlt'!I, t"<lit.• /'m111;.,11 ,,, VIImin H,/,, tit•,,, Im/I• (Mn1lriil, 1%7), XXXI XI .I.
4!'. Quart um Srntr11ti11rum ( l~I'>). <"llv
46. 111 ,..~·11n.l11111 Sr11lrnllu1mtt1/Udt..li1•11r• (1'•11 I•, I'• I'I). lul t ·1 XXV llr 1 lhi1I., 117
256 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ARISTOTLE AND TiiE AMERICAN INDIANS 257

the sixteenth-century debate-one recent discussion referred to "the thou- at Paris Vitoria helped to edit a part of Thomas's Summa theologiae and,
sand and one" current articles on Vitoria and Las Casas.4 at Salamanca, he used the Summa-instead of the traditional Sentences of
Out of all this rich material I want to abstract only a few lines of argu- Peter Lombard-as the basic text for his courses on theology.
ment that directly concern the concept of natural rights.5 This may seem There is no consensus in modem writing about Vitoria's teaching
to offer only a thin and bloodless approach to a great "struggle for jus- on natural rights. In the past, much of the argument was conducted by
tice"6 during the Spanish conquests, but there is some justification for such Catholic neo-Thomists, but even among them there was no agreement.
a procedure. In the end, all the writings on behalf of the Indians did little Some maintained that Vitoria and his followers, as faithful Thomists, did
or nothing to ameliorate their plight. The battles that were sometimes won not teach a doctrine of subjective natural r ights but adhered faithfully
in the debating halls of Salamanca and Madrid were nearly always lost to the objective sense of ius defined by Aquinas. Philippe Andre-Vincent,
among the hard realities of life in Mexico and Peru. As a sixteenth-century for instance, insisted that Vitoria never conceived of ius as "an ensemble of
Spanish historian wrote, "Great disputes took place among famous jurists, individual powers or subjective rights."9 Others maintain that Vitoria and
canonists, and theologians ... yet no good came to the land or the Indi- various subsequent authors of the "second scholasticism" did indeed
ans."7 But, if the Spanish debates did nothing for the hapless Indians, they teach a doctrine of subjective rights, but only because they allowed their
did significantly affect the development of Western political theory, and professed Thomism to be corrupted by nominalist and voluntarist currents
this is especially true when we consider the theme of natural rights. In the of thought. This was the view, for instance, of Michel Villey; he wrote
following discussion of Vitoria's work, I want to concentrate on two main that Vitoria "betrayed" the teaching of Aquinas when he attributed sub-
topics: Vitoria's treatment of the texts of Aquinas concerning right and jective rights to the American Indians.10 Writers of both these schools of
justice, and his reflections in the Relectio de lndis on the kinds of creatures- thought typically regard the modem doctrine of individual rights as a
human and other-that could or could not be bearers of rights. Vitoria's lamentable aberration from an older, sounder tradition represented by
arguments about sovereignty, the state, and individual rights will be con- Aquinas. Within the Thomist camp there is, however, yet another position.
sidered in a later chapter. Influenced, perhaps, by the fact that in modem times the Catholic Church
has come to favor the doctrine of human rights, some scholars maintain
VITORIA, AQUINAS, AND NATURAL RIGHTS that this doctrine was already implicit in the work of Aquinas and that
the Spanish masters remained faithful to his teachings in presenting their
Francisco de Vitoria, a principal founder of the sixteenth-<:entury own rights theories. Teofila Urdanoz, the editor of Vitoria' s Relectiones,
school of Salamanca, studied at Paris from 1511 to 1523. He could have wrote that Vitoria derived from Thomas the idea of "imprescriptible moral
heard there the lectures of Mair and Almain, followers of the via moderna prerogatives or fundamental rights." 11 (Urdanoz referred to Vitoria's " fi-
initiated by William of Ockham. H e knew and admired the work of Con- delity" to the teachings of Aquinas: Villey wrote of Vitoria's " treason"
rad Summenhart, who generally preferred the teachings of Duns Scotus. to those same principles.) Even among the modem authors who write
But his own master was Pierre Crockaert, a Dominican Thomist.3 While without any evident ideological commitment, there is still no agreement.
4. V. Abril Castell6, " Vitoria-las Casas, confrontadon y proyeccion," in C. Soria. ed .. I Richard Tuck wrote that the Spanish Dominicans emphasized the objective
diritti dell' uomot IJ1 pace ntl ptnsiero di Francisco de Vitorin t Bartolomtde las Casas (Milan. 1988). .sense of i11s. Daniel Deckers severely criticized his argument, pointing to a
The essays in this volume provide the best introduction, with abundant bibliography. to strong doctrine of subjective rights in Vitoria.12 Then, most recently, Anna-
the writings of Vitoria an d las Casas. The earlier work of Venancio Carro, La teologia t i los ilel Brett h as criticized Deckers for overemphasizing the "modernity" of
tt61ogos-juristas esp;iiloles antt la conquisla de Amirica, 2 vols. (Madrid, 1944) is still valuable,
Vitoria's teaching.
though marked by a certain nationalist bias.
5. For overviews of Vitoria's thought see B. Hamilton. Political Thought in Sixttrnlh· To address these issues in a sensible fashion we need to start out from
Century SJ1"in (Oxford. 1%3) and J. A. Fernandez-Santamaria, Thi' Stnll', War nnd Prnu. two evident facts. Aquinas did not teach any doctrine of subjective natural
Spanish Political Thought in the Renaissana 1516-1559 (Cambridgt>, 1977). rights; and Vitoria certainly did not intt'nd any treason to the thought of
6. The phrase is taken from L Hanke, Thi' Spa11i~h StruxKI" for f11Micr in 111' Co11q11r~t c>f
America (Boston, 1%5). See also Hankt>'s /\ rr~torlr· nnrl thr Amrrimu lmlin11s (Chica~n. 1959).
(I borrowed this title too as a hl'ilding for tlw pn-11t•nl 1·l"'l''"r.) q I'. Anti re' Vinn•nt, />nut,,,.~ luolff"ll• rt 1lt'1orl1•1•1or11rr11I ,.,, l\111n1qur lntinr (l'itrl"· 1'171 ). 'i'i
7. G. Fem.§ndez dt> Ovit'<iu y V.1lc lc'~. ' I"""" ' In I I IAnk•·. All M•r11lm,/ is C>11,- (I >.·Kall>. 111. M . Villt•y. In /1orn111tl1111cir 111 Jlfll•N /11tl1l l1/llf" t111~/,-11rr, 4th r,f (l'Mil', 1117'1). :itl2. :'6-S tot..
Ill .• 1974). to. I I r I lnl1111111 in l'N..n11 l'll1N l'1~111 l1J•. I''"'''""' 1lr Vllc11111. XI.VII
8. R. Villc~lada. IA 1111h•rt•l1l111I ofr l'crt t• 1/11,.11111· t1•• r•l111/1,,. ,t,· I 10111< , ., " ,t,. Viloor "'· Ill' 17 11l><·•k..1' . 1;,-lf1l1llJtlrll 111111 lf11hl tin, h1o1... 1.,/1 l1111.. 1,, llnt,.,0111'11u11.' l ,,,., 1;,-1rd1
(1.t;(ll l !ilJJ (l<omc•. l'l"IH) 11..!rll•lrhrr ,t,.. ' "''"
1., '"'' Vll1111r1I11111 1'14111 (1'1"ll1111 K. 111111 l. tr~>. 111I
258 THE IDEA O F NATURAL RIG HTS A RISTOTLE AND THE AM ERICAN INOIANS 259

the greatest master of his Order. It may also be useful to bear in mind that restitution, according to Aquinas, was "to reinstate a person in the posses-
Thomism and nominalism are not the only possible sources of sixteenth- sion or dominion of his thing." But theologians had come to realize that a
century rights theories; there also existed a whole background of me- person could be d eprived of a right (ius) as well as of a material thing and
dieval jurisprudence-and the Spanish masters are commonly known as could claim restitution of the right. Moreover, according to the common
theologian-jurists. opinion of theologians and jurists, dominion-ownership-was itself a
When Aquinas explained the meaning of ius in objective language as right. 17 "There is no dominion that is not founded in a right," Vitoria
"the just thing itself" or "the object of justice," he did not give a simple uni- wrote. 18 Vitoria's problem, then, was that he could not discuss restitution
vocal defmition; instead he noted that words are often twisted away from adequately without considering the concept of ius as subjective right; but
their original significations to take on other, related meanings. Thus, he ex- the definitions that he had earlier accepted from Aquinas did not appar-
plained, the word ius was also used to mean the art of jurisprudence, or the ently include any such concept.
place where justice was administered, or the decision of a judge.13 Aquinas Vitoria responded with a sort of verbal jugglery. He first derived a sub-
must have known perfectly well that, in the everyday discourse of his own jective meaning of ius from Aquinas's objective definitions; then he asso-
time, the word ius could also mean a subjective right and that, in contem- ciated his new understanding of Aquinas with Summenhart's Gersonian
porary jurisprudence, a right was sometimes defined as a faculty or power. definition of ius as a faculty or power. Vitoria began by quoting Aquinas's
He seems deliberately to have excluded these meanings. It is the same at phrase, " law . .. is the ground of right" (lex . .. est ratio iuris). Vitoria took
various other points in the Summa theologiae. Aquinas acknowledged that this to mean that "ius is what is licit by law."19 Aquinas had not actually
violence could lawfully be resisted but he did not refer specifically to a written this, but Vitoria pointed out that he did at one point equate i11s
right l)f self-defense. He took from canon law the teaching that property with iustum ("the just").20 This seems to be precisely the objective defini-
was common in the sense that it was to be shared with those in need, but tion that Villey and his school insist on. But, Vitoria continued, Aristotle
he did not ask whether the poor had a natural right to the means of subsis- had defined "the just" as what the laws allowed; and so he reached his
tence.14 From Roman law Aquinas accepted Ulpian's dictum that "Natural conclusion, still claiming to interpret Aquinas.
law is what nature has taught all animals," but he did not ask whether
He (Aquinas) says therefore that right is that which is licit in accordance
animals have corresponding natural rights.15 To a modem reader it might with the laws. And so we use the word when we speak. For we say,
seem that, at all these points, some further discussion expressed in the " J have not the right of doing this," that is, it is not licit for me; or again,
language of rights could usefully complement Aquinas's arguments. "I use my right," that is, it is licit. 21
Vitoria already perceived this. Although I think the Spanish master's
engagement with natural rights theory was always related to an underly- But this is not what Aquinas meant at all. Aquinas argued that law indi-
ing concern about the problems of the Indies, his first detailed definitions cates what is objectively right. Vitoria took him to mean that law defines
of ius as a subjective right arose out of other specific issues that he en- an area of subjective rights. Vitoria was relying here on a concept of per-
countered in commenting on Aquinas. When Vitoria discussed the first missive law that he introduced into his argument explicitly a little further
part of Aquinas's treatise De iustitia in the Summa theologiae he was content on. He was treating a right as a kind of license to act within the framework
to accept the definition of ius as "the object of justice" or "what is just," of law; for Vitoria permissive law defined an area of free choice where a
together with the related meanings of the word that Aquinas had listed.16 person was not commanded or forbidden to act in a certain way but could
But when, further on in the treatise on justice, Vitoria came to discuss say, "I use my right."
the Quaestio, De restitutione, he presented a different doctrine of subjective
17. Aquinas h imself used the phrase rus ditminii when discussing l'('Sfitution th<1ugh
rights, though still daiming to derive it from the text of Aquinas. The un- the usage is not in accord w ith hi,. earlier definitions o r ius. See Summa thtof~inr, 2.2at•.£.2. I,
derlying reason for this move was that Aquinas's own definitions of ius - ... secundum jus dominii, ab uno po:<!Cunl ad alium dt-venirt>. -
were inadequate for discussing the moral theology of restitution. To make IR. Ibid., 2.2ae.£.2. I, M , •• ... nullum •·•I 1lmni11111m quot! non fundt'lur in jun.·.·
l'I. /)r j uslilil1. 2.2at•.62. I, 64. "'Ju,. '"'K" •••I 11110.! t•sl lidtum po r lt~ell. r011t•t hut· •·~
Summa thmlogiae, 2 ..2ae.57.l .
13. o;.1nclo Thoma supril 457, " -' Ml ..., 111hh1111. uhl cit. II 'I""'' h"< non l'jl;t p m pril' j11H. i<t'<I ..,.,
14.
Ibid., 2.2ae.64.7, 2.2ae.66.2. r.1lio juris, i.t e!<t, illml r.11h111t• • 11111• 11ll11111ol •••I llo1111111 ··
15.
Ibid ., 2.2ae.57.3. 211. lhi<l. • ... d ldl 'I"'"' lt1• rl J11ol11111 tol1•111 011111. l r~lr Ar l•loh•l1• .'i l"ll111·11rum; rt J11,.h1m
De ju~lilia, ed. V. ~ltrAn it.. I ll'rrtll11 h11"111111 l•n• olr v;r,.,,,, l ·,,,,,,,,,.,,,,,,;,t• 11 la Srrnm/11
16. i1111tl i1!1•m • ·~I •flll MI lq\lh11• ll1t•I *''II" fll• """"' lol1•111 •••I. hi c••I t]lt11tl lt•)llhu~ llc<'I ..
S«undardr Santo 1oma..4, 6 vol11 (S..l11m101111, I'll) 'IJ). I J 7nr '\7 I, 4
71 '""'
260 THE ID£A OF NATlJRAl RIGHTS ARISTOTLE AND THE AMERICAN INDIANS 261

From this point, it seemed an easy step to the definition of ius as a sub- Vitoria's reliance on both Aquinas's teaching on justice and Gerson's
jective faculty. So far, Vitoria wrote, he had given only a "nominal" defi- doctrine of rights (as transmitted by Summenhart), has naturally attracted
nition of ius;n to explain the reality behind the word he next turned to a the attention of modem scholars. The Spanish master's way of handling
definition that he found in the "noble treatise" of Conrad Summenhart: these texts is at the heart of the dispute among modem Thomists that
"He says then, that ius is a power or faculty pertaining to anyone in accor- I have already mentioned. Daniel Deckers, who has provided the best
dance with the law.'123 In fact, Vitoria had slightly misquoted Summenhart and fullest account of Vitoria's thought, also sees the confrontation of the
here. Summenhart, following Gerson, had written of a power or faculty two sources as a decisive step in the evolution of a modem doctrine of
"in accordance with right reason" or "in accordance with primal justice." rights. Deckers quoted in this context the work of the sociologist, Niklas
Vitoria altered the wording, presumably in order to maintain a continuity, Luhmann who, in the course of a far-ranging article on subjective rights,
or apparent continuity, with the preceding argu~ent in ~hich he had emphasized the understanding of ius as facuf fas in the work of the Spanish
derived from Aquinas and Aristotle the conclusion that rus referred to scholastics. Luhmann thought that their definition possessed an inherent
behavior that was licit "in accordance with the laws." Vitoria added that
24
·I dynamism; it focussed attention on human freedom and on individual ca-
the word potestas (power) was often used in scripture to mean a right, pabilities and responsibilities; it raised new questions in legal theory about
and summed up his argument in a crisp sentence, "Whoever has a faculty the grounds and limits of human behavior.27 Deckers himself went on to
in accordance with the laws has a right." 25 argue that two different semantic structures existed in Vitoria's work-
Vitoria next turned to an issue raised by Summenhart-whether ius an Aristotelian-Thomist semantic of ius as objective justice and, alongside
and dominium meant essentially the same thing. Vitoria noted that, in its this, the subjective definition of ius asJacultas derived from Summenhart.
strict sense, dominion referred to a certain superiority or eminence, as Deckers saw this as a "fundamental dichotomy.'' He thought that Vitoria
when we say that a ruler has dominion over his subjects. This kind of do- kept the two definitions apart in his thought, that he established no mean-
minion was not equivalent to ius, for an inferior could have a right a~ainst ingful connections between them and showed no awareness of the latent
a superior even though he had no dominion over him, a so_n _against a conflict inherent in his definitions. Following Luhmann, Deckers also con-
father for instance. In another proper sense of the word, domrnrum could sidered the subjective definition of ius as facuftas to be indicative of a fun-
mean ownership of property and again this was not equivalent to ius, for a damental restructuring of legal thought. It was based on a "changed legal
person could have a right in a piece of property, such as use or usufruct, consciousness," he wrote; and this in tum was a result of the economic,
without being the actual owner of it. Finally, Vitoria discus~ ~ummen­ political, social and religious revolutions that had already begun in Vi-
hart's argument that, in a very broad sense of the_ word, domrnrum c~uld toria's day. 211
be equated with ius, because a person who depnved another of _a nght There are two criticisms to be made of these arguments. Vitoria's defi-
was said to be guilty of theft. Vitoria held that ~his was an _a~us1ve use nition of ius as facultas was not new; and the two semantic structures in
of language, but conceded that the two words-ru~ and ~omrrrru~-:wer~ his work were not really isolated from one another. No one would want to
often used indifferently in moral theology.26 In d1scussmg restitution it deny that important changes in political and religious life were taking
did not matter whether a person had been deprived of ownership or place in Vitoria's lifetime; but to see his subjective definition of ius as a
some other property right; in each case there was an injury that called for reflection of a new juristic consciousness brought into being by those
reparation. changes is to overlook the fact that the understanding of ius as a faculty or
power had existed in legal literature for centuries before Vitoria wrote. WC'
first encountered the complex of arguments used by Vitoria-ius under-
22. ~ justiti11, 2.2ae,62.l , 64, HSed ista est diffinitio quid nominis tan~m iUi~ vocabuli.ff
He means I assume. that the definition of Aquinas that he had been d tSCussmg was con-
stood as "what is licit by Jaw," or as a faculty, or as an area of free choice
cerned pa;ticularly with the etymology of lhe word jus, specifically with the rdation be- nllowed by permissive natural law-in the works of the twelfth-century
tween jus and justitia.
23. Ibid.. HDicit ergo quod jus est potestu Vf'I facultas conv~nicns alicui secundum leges.ff 27. N. 1.uhmann, Gesell5ehafh~lr11Al11r 111111 .'Vma11/i~ . Stmlirn wr WisYns..<0iiol~ir drr "''"'
24. A critic from Villey's camp would poinl 0111 thO\t th1• Vul)l.alt• biblt> d1x.~ llflen use lht> ,.,,,,.,, l.rsr/l~dmfl vols. (Frank furl. l'IH I), 1 'Ito
w ord poltslQs but does not equalf' it wllh iu~. 21!. lk'<"kt•r:o1. GrrrrhliRlril, IM ''"· IHH •JI s.,.. lhi.I . lf'4 " ... ilk• funJamt'fltnle U11111tnik
25. Ibid.• 6..'i, "QuicumqUt' ~" h1thrl f1t.-ullnh•m ,....·1111<111111 lt•)l.t.,;. h 1thl'I jrn• •• t11rit•n111K '"'" R«'chlit al~ Er)l.rhnl• l'h11•• vt1r•111t..11..11 1<.., ht11l>1•w11Mlrln 11n!l 1111.,; wlt'llt'rum
26. Ibid., 67, "Vt"nim nil 1111ud ..,., 11h1111lv" '"'" "' • •'t•llll. 11011 lnnwn iii• 1p1ln '"' iuwpt• .11" 1'111)1.<' llkonnm b1<:h1•r, pol1t1..·h.,1. •1u1t11lt11 111111 1t•ll)l.lll...1 I lmwlil11111)1.t'll .r.11 Vllnrl11' • Zrll
ulamur in nmlrrln mur1tll, 111111• II ( ·.,......tu• ·· ht•n•ll" In voll1·11 K"''K '"' ..
262 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ARISJOTI.E AND Tii E AMERICAN INDIANS 263

Decretists. Thirteenth-century jurists, especially the canonists, had also thought.31 So Vitoria's early handling of this theme may have a certain con-
defined ius as a faculty or power. As Charles Reid wrote, "The canonistic temporary relevance.
rights vocabulary, like our own, is a rich one. Ubertas, potestas, Jacultas, _im- We can further illustra te Vitoria's way of arguing by turning back to
munitas, dominium, iustitia, interesse and actio can all in the appropnate the commentary on the Summa theologiae and considering his discussion on
circumstances, be translated as 'right'." 29 the origin of property rights. Relying on Aquinas, and here arguing
Gerhard Otto has pointed out that, although Vitoria probably knew against Summenhart, Vitoria first maintained that irrational creatures
only a few major treatises of the canonists at first hand, he was strongly could have no rights.32 (The argument was repeated in Vitoria's Relectio de
influenced by canonical material that had already been assimilated into lndis, and I discuss it below in that context.) Vitoria next argued that God
the theological sources that he used.30 In this case the understanding of ius in fact gave "right and dominion" over all created being to humankind.))
as a power or faculty had been drawn into works of theology and politi- He proved this from scripture, citing Psalm 7.8 ("You have subjected all
cal theory in the Franciscan dispute of the fourteenth century and subse- under his feet") and Genesis 1.26- 28 ("Have dominion over the fishes of
quently transmitted by such writers as Gerson, Almain, and Summenhart. the sea and the birds of the air... ."); but Vitoria at once added that the
Vitoria, then, was not using a new language of rights; he was deploying an same point could also be proved by reason. Citing Aristotle, he explained
old language in a new context. . that all things existed for an end; but humankind was the end for which all
In an earlier discussion I wrote that Vitoria's reliance on a scholastic other things were made; therefore man was the lord of all. Again, Aristotle
tradition that had been shaped by jurists as well as theologians led him to had shown that, in the whole universe, the less perfect beings existed for
some creative reinterpretations when he considered the texts of Aquinas. the sake of the more perfect ones; but man was more perfect than all other
One can add that the confrontation with Aquinas also led to some substan- creatures; therefore he had "right and dominion" over all.34 There followed
tial modifications of Summenhart's positions in Vitoria's work-especially an argument from natural law. It pertained to natural law that man should
as regards the possible bearers of rights. That is why one can say that the conserve himself in being; but he could not do so without using other crea-
two semantic structures he called upon were not wholly isolated from tures; therefore he had a right to use them.15 Moreover dominion of things
one another in his work. Aquinas's phrase, " law is the ground of right," did not belong only to the human race as a community; rather each indi-
provided for Vitoria a bridge between them. Ha~ing fi_rst interpr~ted­ vidual person was owner of everything, so that he could use or abuse it at
or misinterpreted-Aquinas's language here as 1mplymg a doctrine of will. This sounds almost Hobbesian, but Vitoria added, "provided that he
subjective rights, Vitoria could readily go on to present Summenhart's does not harm other people or himself."36 The Spanish thinker was still
definition as a necessary complement, adding depth and substance to conceiving of natural rights as existing within a framework of natural law.
Aquinas's merely "nominal" definition. Vitoria ~as certainly present~ng Vitoria next asked how the division of goods into private properties
here a doctrine that Aquinas himself had not envisaged; but I do not thmk had come about. After quoting the text Quo iure (Dist. 8 c.l) from Gratian's
that he need be seen as contradicting or betraying the master he admired Deere/um, he responded that it was from human law. But this raised an·
so much. We might say rather that he was carrying further the proce:s of other difficulty. If natural law makes one the owner of all things and this
metonymic association used by Aquinas himself when he added vanous
derivative meanings of ius to his own primary definition. :n . T. Machan, Human Rights and Human Ubulits (Chicago, 1975); 0 . B. RasmuSSt'n and
In his further discussions on ius and dominium Vitoria persistently I>. J. Den Uyl, Uberty and Nnturt. An Aristotelian Defense of Liberal Ordtr (La Salle, 1991 ); E I>.
used Aristotelian and Thomist arguments, interwoven with ones from Miller, Nature. Justice and Rig/rt in Aristot/e·s Politics (Oxford, 1995).
32. Dt j11stitin, 2.2ae.62.1. 69-71.
Summenhart, to support a doctrine of individual rights. The possibility
33. Ibid., 71, "Et sic jus et dominium omnium dedit hominibus_ H

of using Aristotelian language to defend some form of natural rights :l4. Ibid ., 72, ... . . homo est omnibu!I p<>rfoctior: ergo omnia alia o rd inantur pmptc•r
theory has recently been taken up by several modem writers on political ilium . .. ergo habent jus e t dominium !lup•·r om'"'" illas. N

.15. lhid ., 7J, " ll<'m, d<' juw naturnli 1-sl 'I""'' homo n >n:<t'rvC't se in es.., <'. S<-tl hot· nn11
29. Charles J. Reid, Jr. HThe Canonistic Contribution to th<- W<•stem Rights Tradition,~ poh•st !<inP aliis cn•aturi!' ... Er1tn hnht•I 111• 11!1•11.tl 111111111>11~ illi!\."
Boston College I.Aw Rroiew 33 ( 1991 ): 37- 92 at 64. JI.. lt>id .• 74, " Non !M•lum 11nlvrnlt4• rt 11111111111111111" .. ..... t •111iliht•t homo i n 11IAt11 1Ml11

...
30. G. Otte, Das Privatrecht hl!i franri.<eo Jr V1torut (<. ·ol<>Klll'. 1%4), '.17. Tlw c.moni~tic hack· r.11• intl'~r.w. id 1•s1. ~t .1mfn In 11olo j111r n""""''· ••1111 .t11111h111• omnium n•rum 1·n•111,,n1m rl
ground to Vitoria'!' work wa:o al!M• <'mph11.• l7<'•1 hy I Mui.loon. /'•'/""'· /11fid't~. a111l l.11111.vtr~ potc•r,1t u l i I'! .1h11ti on111lh11• 1111 •111111111111111 """ '"" l'l"rl AHl11 hmnlnll•u" Y<'I 111\11.'• 'llw
(Philad<'lphi11. 19711). 144 amt hv 1; M<tllh111lv. ~,.,,,,,,,,,,,,., 1111•lu111111·v (I "hk"M''· 1w;r;), '211!,. w11r.I ~ . ._,1'1•···lwr<' ""' llw •1•11.,. 111 .. ,.. 11•1• 111• '"1111•1 1h1111 "'h• "''""'"' ••
264 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ARISTOTLE ANO THE AMERICAN INDIA NS 265

natural law or natural right (ius naturale) proceeds from God, then it would transfer their property away from them, and their own rulers, were un-
seem that no one can deprive a person of this right to everything. Scotus willing to yield up their lands. "Certainly," Vitoria wrote, "as regards the
had argued that God repealed the natural law prescribing community Indians, no one can take their lands from them."42
of property after Adam's sin; but Vitoria rejected this view because it Vitoria took much of his discussion on property directly from Sum-
conflicted with Gratian's assertion in the Decretum that natural law was menhart, but anyone familiar with the earlier material will recognize in
immutable. Vitoria preferred an argument presented by Summenhart his argument layers of thought that go back to Ockham and John XXIJ,
which explained that the natural law ordaining community of property Aquinas and Scotus, Rufinus and Hugucio. It would be possible, though
was not a precept binding for all time but only a kind of permissive law; 37 tedious for the reader, to construct chains of texts leading from the early
it left men free to make alternative arrangements. In this situation, just Decretists to Vitoria's mature formulations.43 It is also significant that Vi-
because all things were common, men could come together and say "You toria relied on Aristotle and natural reason as well as on scripture in con-
take this, and you this, and I will have this." 38 ! structing a doctrine of natural right, an original " right and dominion" of
Still following Sununenhart, Vitoria argued that the original division
could have been made in three ways. Adam could have divided things
I" each individual over all the things of the world.

himself (either by his paternal power alone or with the consent of his
VITORIA. RIG HTS AND INDIANS
sons); or the people could have elected a ruler to make the division; or the
people could have met together and agreed among themselves about the When Vitoria turned specifically to the rights of American Indians
apportionment.39 Vitoria showed more awaren~ than his predecessors of in his Relectio de lndis, he continued to deploy Thornist and Aristotelian ar-
the difficulties inherent in this last solution. What if a minority dissented guments in defense of a doctrine of natural rights. The Spanish master's
from the proposed division? It was a principle of natural law that the ma- work has often been discussed as a contribution to the early development
jority should prevail, Vitoria maintained.40 The community or a majority of ."
: I
; of international law; from that point of view his arguments about just and
them could make an actual apportionment of lands, or could decide that unjust wars, about the valid or invalid claims of the Spanish in America,
ownership would go to the first occupant. Moreover the decision did not and about the pretensions of popes and emperors to a universal temporal
have to be explicit and formal; virtual consent or mere acquiescence would authority are of central importance. But, if we are interested primarily in
suffice, so that when one person began to cultivate a piece of land others Vitoria' s thought about natural rights, the key passage is the first part of
would tacitly recognize his claim to it.0 This was a consent expressed ''by his Releclio de Jndis,44 where he asked whether the Indians had any true do-
deeds rather than by words," Vitoria wrote. minion, public and private, before the arrival of the Spaniards. That is to
Once division has been made by human law natural law came into say: did they have legitimate rulers and rightful ownership of property?
play again to protect private property. According to natural law, owner- The issue concerned theologians, Vitoria explained, because the Indians
ship could be transferred from one person to another in only two ways, were not subject to the Spanish by human law; hence, their status had to b<>
either by the will of the owner or by the authority of the ruler. This phase considered in relation to divine law, presumably the divine natural law
of the discussion concluded with an argument that Christians could not that initially conferred dominion on humankind.45 The subsequent discus-
occupy the lands of infidels; once a division has been made their lands sion centered on the term dominium but since, as Vitoria wrote, domi11i11m
belonged to them alone. There was no Christian ruler set over them to was nothing else but a right, his argument was essentially about rights
and, insofar as he was considering natural dominion, about natural rights.
'
I
37. Ibid., 76, "Sed arguit Conradus . . . lex potest esse praeceptiva, et alia potest esse con·
Vitoria began with an argument concerning natural slavery. Accord in~
sultiva, et alia permissiva." . .
38. (bid., 77, "Concedo; immo quia omnia erant communia, ideo de 1ure naturaJ1 . .. to civil law, a slave could not own a nything and, according to Aristotll•,
potuenmt inter se ronvenire homines taJiter quod dicerent: tu cape hoc, et tu hoc. et ego l
habebohoc." 42. !hid ., R2, "Sicut Jt• isl is irnli.~ n•rll• 11111111~ pos.°'('I capt>rt> terras ab eis.
N

39. Ibid., 78, "Primus est quod Adam fecit ilJam . . . Secundo modo . . . homines ex con· 4:l. E.g. Vitoria look h iii .to<lrhw 11l 1wn11IJ<•dvr 11.1t11ral law from Summ('nh.irt; S11111mrn
sensu omnium potuerunt eligere prindpem .. . qui Jividen- et appn>priar" poh1it illi.~ r('~ h.trt <itc.J Alc·undc·r of Jf,,1,.•. /\lr,11111lr1 u·ll••d ''" th•· Tlc..·n•li~l11' dilltincliot1 ht'lw1••'f1 llw
omnes . . . Tertio modo potult fierl per communt'm nmM'mmm." pn•n•pls and 1f,·m11nslmli<1111'.• 1•l nr1h1111l l"w. fl1•l (•"'1'"'""''°'' hy Rufim L~. r.1. 11111)
40. Ibid., 79, uEt patl't, quill f'itl ,f,. Jul"C' nnl11r<1ll 1111n1I n u1lor p11nt l'l'lllpt'r vh..-al in <'Oil· 44 A rt'lrrlit1 ( lllrrnllv rttru1ll1111l w~• " 1111111<11 p11"1h l1.. ·t11n• ··~plnrl111t 111 1l•·lr1il "'""''
~mo." lupil' 1h.1t IMd n inw up h1 111•1,.vl1111• 11111101•
41 . Ibid., " El hoc ntHl 11lt•11111 11>1111C"11"11 1111111<111. ""'' vh 1111•11 ·• 41\ l'•·r•·l\'1 1'•' 11·1 1'11'1111"'· tfrln 111• 1/r 111111• 1~1.,,,.,. 11 .'). l '111r/111/111111. H
266 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ARISTO TLE AN D THE AMERICAN INDIANS 267

barbarians were all slaves by nature. It followed that they could not be following a conventional line of argument when he held that the Indians
owners could not hold dominion.~ But against this it could be argued that could not be held to lack dominion because they were sinners. Natural do-
the Indians were in a state of peaceful poc;~ession, as regards both public minion belonged to man as a creature made in the image of God, Vitoria
authority and private property, and so ought not to be dispossessed. Vi- ~inted out, but this likeness to God inhered in man's power of reason and
toria noted here that he would pass over all the intricate definitions and this was not lost by sin. A sinner did not lose his natural dominion over his
distinctions about daminium which he and other theologians had pre- o~n acti~ns or over h~s own body, and he retained a right of defending
sented elsewhere, "lest more necessary things be omitted." And, indeed, his own hfe_. 49 Also, scnp~ had recognized the lordship of various kings
the earlier refined scholastic analyses which in an author like Sum.menhart who were smners. Followmg Innocent rv, Vitoria quoted here the words of
had led to a complex maze of distinctions and subdistinctions played no Matthew 5.45, "God makes his sun to rise on the good and the evil. .. ." so
part in the discussion that followed. When Vitoria was faced by ~ great As regards infidels, scripture again recognized the authority of kings
if
practical issue, the claims of the Spaniards in the New Wor~d~ it was who ~er: ~believers; and Aquinas had proved the same point by reason.
enough for him to remember the basic juristic doctrine that dommium was ) The distinction between belief and unbelief was based on divine law;
a right, a right to own or a right to rule. There were only four reasons, !I but divine law did not cancel the human laws based on natural reason
he argued, that might render the Indians incapable of holding such do- that established government and property. Even heretics did not lose do-
47
minium-that they were sinners, or infidels, or irrational, or insane. ~e minion of their property until they had been formally condemned and
presumption was that all peoples had rights to own property and to in- legally dispossessed. And so Vitoria reached his conclusion. " Barbarians
stitute their own rulers unless some specific defect in them prevented are not impeded from being true lords (domini), publicly and privately,
this. The discussion that followed presented an extended argument on the on account of the sin of infidelity or any other mortal sin."51
qualities that rendered a creature capable or incap~ble. of being a ~earer Infidels and sinners, then, could be bearers of rights. But what if the
of rights. The outcome of it was that the defects Vitona had menhoned Indians were mentally impaired, witless or irrational creatures? The con-
did not render people in general, or the Indians in particular, incapable of ~ide:ation of this qu~tion led Vitoria into a d igression about the rights of
being right-holders. . . . irrational creatures m general that forms an importa.n t part of his argu-
The idea that sinners and infidels could have no rightful domm1on ment. Here he turned to Aristotle and Aquinas to refute a characteristic
had a respectable ancestry in the works of theologians like Giles of Rome teac~ing ?f Gerson and Summenhart, both of whom taught that animals
and Richard FitzRalph. Among the canonists, Innocent IV had defended and mammate creatures possessed a kind of dominion with associated
the rights of infidels in mid-thirteenth century, but the gre~test cano~ist rights. According to Summenhart the stars had a right to shine and sub-
of the next generation, Hostiensis, held that, after the commg ~f Chnst, celestial bodies also had many forms of dominion and rights. Each element
there could be no rightful dominion outside the church. The issue re- had a right to its own place in the universe. Animals had a right to the
mained a matter of dispute until the Council of Constance in 1415 con- herbs ~nd grass that were assigned to them by God as food. And, among
demned Wyclif's radical version of the doctrine of dominion founded on the animals, some held dominion over others; the lion was king of the
grace.48 Wyclif, it will be recalled, argued that since all power came from beasts and the eagle lord of the birds.52
God, anyone who was in a state of mortal s~ and ~ho there~ore di~ not Vitor~a would have none of this; for him only human beings could
enjoy God's grace could not rightfully exemse ruhng authonty or nght- possess nghtful dominion. He first proved this by calling on the juridical
fully own property. Since, here on earth, men could not know whether principle that irrational creatures could not suffer or inflict injury. From
a ruler or property-owner actually was in a state of grace, the argument
could have led on to sheer anarchy, and it was generally rejected by ortho- 49. CH .lndis, 1.3, 18. " Ergo. si propter off('nsam Dei homo penleret dominium d vilt•,
dox theologians in the time of Vitoria. The Spanish thinker was therefore ,.,,~em ration~ perd~r~t etiam dominium natumlP. Falsitas autem consequt>nlis pru batur,
•1t11;t non perd1t dom1mum supt•r rr<•prlo:o ndu!t t•I !lup«>r propria rtlt'mbra; ergo h11ht•t pPt"<'ll
46. Dt tndis, t.1, 14, " Et Aristoteles dicit i uslum et n aturale ~s.e ut tales S<"rviant. Ergo tor ius dt•fl'fldrndi pmpria m vit1u11 •·
tales non possunt esse domini." . !°>(). Ibid., 1..3, 19.
47. Ibid.,"... si barbari non hatwrent dominium, non vid<•lur <1111>d po:i.~I pnwt<•ml1 al111 . 5 1. lhi~ ., 1.10, 25. " foe on1nlh11• hi• -111t111r •·n11t 111..hr •1110J houbarl 1l('<' pmptrr J"C'<"<"llln
causa, nisi vel quia ~uni pccc<1ltm'1' vrl <1111., infi.t,•lt-:t vrl quia nmt-nlN< Vt'I i11M·n~1t i."' "h,1mn rlflh,111<'<" pmptrr 1..,_·n1l11111 lnlhl,.lll•ll•. "'"' hn1>c.,ll11nt 11r 1111ln 11lnt v••rl 1tomlnl, t 11 m
48. On th~ 1•11rli<•r d l~ruh•N In ,-..l11t111t1 t11 thr p111l•l•·m~ 1•1 ti..- h1<H•·" ,...,. M11hl11011. /'"/.,.~. puhlin• •111.nn prlvolllm
/11fidrJ.., and /.nuryr,.,, .'i 211 r;2. lhhl . I II. 2't 7t•. n •l,.111111& 111 ti111111111•11h•lf. I Ir 1111111111 lll•u-. 111 ~ nhovt•. 7"H
268 THE IDEA Of NATURAL RIGHTS ARISTOTLE AND THE AMERIC.AN INDIANS 269

this Vitoria concluded, with a play on the words ius and iniuria, that they In the De lndis Vitoria applied the Thomist argument to his discussion
could not have any right. They could not have a ius because they could not about the kinds of creatures that could be holders of dominion. Owner-
experience injustice; or, one might say, they could not have a right (ius) be- ship implied control, and since brute animals could not control their own
cause they could not suffer a wrong (iniuria). To deprive a wolf or lion actions they could not control external things.57 They could therefore have
of its prey was not to do the beast an injury; to close a shutter against the no right of ownership. Vitoria's conclusion followed quite logically from
sunlight was not to injure the sun. And since irrational creatures could Aquinas's earlier arguments; but Vitoria had transposed them into a dif-
have no rights they also could have no dominion for, as Summenhart had ferent framework of discourse. Aquinas wrote that humans could use
acknowledged, dominion itself was a right.53 To argue othen:ise led _t~ ab- animals for their own purposes, but it did not occur to him to ask specifi-
surdities. For instance, if animals did have a right of ownership (domm1um) cally whether animals had rights.
then anyone who excluded deer from a pasture would be guilty of theft Vitoria next asked whether children before the age of reason could be
because he would take something away against the will of the owner. In owners (domim). The preceding discussion emphasizing reason and self-
fact animals had no dominion even over their own bodies; and, as Aris- mastery might seem to exclude them; but now the argument about ius and
54
totle showed in the Politics, it was natural and just for men to hunt them. iniuria was turned around and used in their favor. Children could suffer
Vitoria was affirming here a central principle common to many later injury (iniuria), Vitoria wrote; but this implied that they could have a right
human rights theories, the unique value and status of the human pe~on. (ius); and therefore they could have dominion of things, since domin-
He developed the point further by returning to an argument of Aquinas ion was nothing other than a right. 511 Moreover, children were formed in
that he had mentioned earlier. Aquinas maintained that every person was the image of God, and this was the foundation of all dominion. Unlike an
master (dominus) of his own acts. Moreover it was by virtue of this self- irrational animal, a child existed for its own sake, not for the sake of an-
mastery that humans possessed a natural domini~n over other creat~res. other. Vitoria added that, not only children whose rational faculties were
Through the exercise of his gifts of reason and will man could dominate undeveloped, but even the incurably insane, could also be holders of do-
the rest of created nature; and this was fitting since, by virtue of these minion, at least according to natural law. The same argument applied; they
gifts, man was made in the image of God and so ~ndowed wit~ a _PO':er could suffer injury, therefore they could have a right.59
analogous to God's absolute dominion.55 For Aquinas the key distinction When at last Vitoria returned to the American Indians, he acknowl-.
between humans and other creatures was that humans, by virtue of their edged that all this discourse about irrational creatures was not strictly
self-mastery could act freely; other animate and inanimate creatures ~c~ed relevant to his argument. He had explored the issue at such length ap-
by necessity. Commenting on Aquinas, Vitoria added that ~lf-d~m1mon parently because he considered it necessary for any detailed understand-
was a right inhering only in humans: "Brutes do not have a nght m them- ing of the nature of rights and dominion. But, he acknowledged, the
selves but man has a right (habet ius)." 56 So, for Vitoria, freedom and self- Indians were not in fact witless creatures, devoid of reason. To make this
mastery and inherent human right were all interconnected. point, Vitoria invoked another Aristotelian principle. "Nature does noth-
ing in vain."
53. Ibid., 1.12, 26-1:7, "Patel, quia dominium est ius, ut fatetur etiam Conrad us. Sed crea·
turae irrationales non possunt habere ius. Ergo nee dominium. Probatur minor, quia non According to the truth of the matter they are not irrational, but they have
possunt pati iniuriam; ergo non habent ius. Probatur assumptum, quia qui p~hiberet lupum the use of reason in their own way. This is dear because they have a cer-
aut leonem a praeda vel bovem a pastu, non fareret ei iniuriam, nee qui claud1t fenestram ne tain order in their affairs, ordered cities, separate marriages, magistrates,
sol illuminet, facit iniuriam soli." 1be Latin word iniuria did not mean simply harm but rulers, laws.... Also they do not err in things that are evident to others,
~~ha~ . . which is evidence of the use of reason. Again, God and nature do not fail
54. .Ibid., 1.12, 1:7, "Et confirmatur, quia si bruta haberent domimum, ergo qui tolleret
herbam cervo, faceret furtum, quia capit alienum, invito d omino. Item, ferae non habent do-
minium sui. Ergo multo minus aliarum rerum. Assumptum probatur, quia licet eas impune 57. /)~ /rrdis, 1.12, 227- 28. " Et mnfirmatur luK· i\UC"lnritate S. Thomae.. . . Sola c-n.•atur,1
interficere et etiam animi gratia. Unde etiam Philosophus (primo Politicorum) ait quod Vf!- r.11ionabilis habet dominium sui llC"ht!l. . . Si •·'K" bruta non habcnt dominium !luo rum
natio ferarum est iusta et naturalis." ,,.·tuum, l'rgo> nee aliarum n>n.tm. . Non •·ntm 11ldm11N ali<JU<.>m t'SSE' dominum, nl.~i t'iw1
55. Summa tktologiat, 2.2ae. 66.l. The idt>a o f '"wll·d11minion" wall of rour!it' not p«uliar •tmKI sit um ••st in sua facullatl'. ·• Vi111rl11 N'l<'llrtl lwrl' lo A<tuin,,!l'll Srmrnra ll11•11/1'l(inr, I .K2. I,
to Aquinas. Earlier we considered a llimllnr n•rKt•pl In I h•nry of ( ;tw~t. F'.1r d<1~1ini11111 s11i in I 2.w.1.1- 2. 1.2,u>.6.2 amt -""'""'" 1wtltll .1lr1tll/,• . I 1111
Franciscan sources !let' r. GroMl, lbu~ fadi '.\IJQ :ll., (11ht1w :1711. Kol) (,nl!llll, I th111k. l"<ngi1;«.>r· I'"'"'·'I"'"
5R. lhitl .. I IJ, 211, ~ I In•" pu•-11111 p11ll l11h11l~m . r~o l111ht-nl ht~ n•rum; 1'rKt1 •·~1
atl'5 the diffl'nonCt> lit-lwffn Thuml-1 "111l 1'1n111 l•1 rm thou1thl In thl• ,iri.,, illi" .t11111hti11m. 'I"'"' nlhll 111t111t .,_, 'l""m 111- '
~ (), j11~lili11, 2 2M· ,,.. I. ']117 r.•.1 ll•11l , I I\. }'I
270 THE IDEA OF NATURAL R IGHTS ARISTOTLE AND THE AMERJCAN INDIANS 271

for a great part of a species in what is necessary. But the special quality much as the body differs from the soul, or an animal from a man."64 Vitoria
in man is reason, and potency which is not actualized is in vain.60 seems to have just ignored or failed to assimilate these aspects of Aris-
totle's thought. In referring to the Indians' "dominjon over themselves
Anthony Pagden oddly misunderstood this passa~e as meaning_tha~ the
and over other things" (dominium sui) he was instead deploying once more
Indians' rationality was still in potentia, not actualized, and their mmds
Aquinas's language of natural dominion, a dominion that Vitoria persis-
"frozen in a state of becoming." 61 But of course Vitoria meant exactly the
tently treated as a right. The Spanish master had achieved the consider-
opposite. The Indians could not be a people whose intellect was merely
able feat of associating a defense of natural rights with Aristotle's theory
potential rather than actual because the existence of such a people would
of natural slavery. He concluded that, even if the Indians were as foolish
imply a failure of God and nature.
and slow-witted as people said, this did not prevent them from holding
Vitoria returned, finally, to the objection he had presented at the be-
true dominion or justify their being treated as civil slaves.
ginning of his argument; according to Roman law a slave could ow~
At other points in his argument Vitoria showed how a doctrine of
nothing and, according to Aristotle, barbarians ~~re slaves by nature. Vi-
natural rights might be used in a different way to defend the Spanish role
toria responded by distinguishing between the av1l and legal enslavement
in America. He asserted, for instance, that the law of nations, "which either
of Roman law and Aristotle's natural slavery. Those who were legally en-
is natural law or derives from it," conceded certain rights to all persons.
slaved could indeed own nothing, but no one was a slave of this kind by
nature. As for natural slavery, Vitoria at first seemed to accept Aristotle's They included a right to travel freely, a right to trade, a right to equal treat-
teaching without demur. ment with other strangers, a right to acquire citizenship. If the Indians
denied to the Spaniards any of these rights the Spaniards in tum might
As Aristotle elegantly and accurately observed, some are slaves by have a right to wage a just war against them.65 Vitoria also maintained that
nature, namely those who are better fitted to serve than to rule.62 there was a general right to intervene on behalf of others who were to
This was indeed Aristotle's doctrine. But the Greek philosopher would suffer unjustly. Applying this principle to the human sacrifices and alleged
probably have been surprised at Vitoria's interpretation of it. cannibalism of the American Indians, he argued that the victims had an in-
herent right of self-defense that they could not renounce. "No one can give
To this I answer that Aristotle certainly did not understand that such to another the right to kill him," Vitoria wrote. The Spanish king could
people belong by nature to others and have no dominion over them- therefore have a corresponding right to protect the innocent victims even if
selves and over other things.63 they did not request help or want it.66
Vitoria was envisaging a status for those who were servants by nature The outcome of Vitoria's argument was that all human beings-
radically different from the chattel slavery of ancient Greece and Rome. sinners, infidels, children, even natural slaves as Vitoria understood the
Aristotle described his natural slave as an "animate instrument," "by na- term-<ould be bearers of rights and did possess certain natural rights.67
ture not his own man but another's," one who differed from others "as Conversely, Vitoria maintained, no non-human creature, animate or inani-
mate, could be a right-holder. For Vitoria, natural rights were rooted in
60. lbid ., 1.15, 29-30, nrrobatur, quia secundum rei veritatem non s unt amentes, sed
human nature, not in the nature of the external world. It was a significant
habent pro suo modo usum rationis. Patet, quia habent ord i~m a!iqu~~ in s uis r~us, conclusion. If the doctrine of Gerson and Summenhart had prevailed, and
postquam habent civitates quae ordine constant, et habent matrimonia dastincta'. m~g~tra­ natural rights had been conceived of as vaguely diffused in all creaturt•s
tus, dominos, Jeges, opifida, commutationes, quae omnia requirunt usum rati°'.11s;_ i_tem lhroughout the cosmos, the concept of a right might have lost its force as a
religionis speciem. Item n on errant in rebus, q~ae aliis su.~t evidentes, quod est ~~ 1au m
usus rationis. Item Deus et natura non deficiunt in necessarus pro magna parte speoe1. Prae-
cipuum autem in homine est ratio, et frustra est potentia, quae non ~ucitur ad actu~ . n 64. Politics, 1.4.2, 1.4.5.
61. A . Pagden, The Fall of N11t11r11l Man (Cambridge, 1982), 94. This, and other m1s~ad­ (>~ . De lndis, 3.1-5, 77-84.
ings of Vitoria in Pagden's work are criticized in m~ paper, "A~istotle and the American ff,_ De lf'nlpt!Tantia in T. Urdano7., <'ti., ( >l•m.• dr Francisco de Vitoria (Madrid, 1%0). JO~L
Indians-Again. Two Critical Discussions,n Cristi11nl'S1mo n_ella stor1~ 12 (1991): 295-322. 67. VPn.,ncio Carm Pnth1111iMtk11lly 1111111n1t'll up this ll•aching by writinit th.11, iu-curdlng
62. De lndis, 1.1, 13, " Probatur, nam, ut Arl11totel<>S (pnmo Eth1corum 5) eleganter et ac- lo Vitoria, '"'That which iJll n11l11r11I, hr II ullrcl l11w ur right. faculty or powrr, 111 !ft• n•n11111>-
curate tradit, aliqui sunt natura servi, quibu~ ll<"llin.'t mt>llu.~ est 9ervlre quam lmperan.'." sl.111tial with lhe hl•ing of mnn lh•I II "'11111111• l11111111t11hlr in f'Ve•ry cla11J11 o f mt-n 11ml ho• <"~1111111
63. Ibid., 1.16, 30-31, " Ad hoc n.,.pnnJro •111utl c'4•rlt> Arl,.lot<'lt'K non lnh•llt>xlt q110..t '"''"!i, 1,,,.., or .w.111irr it through"'"· wh..tlw1 "" '"' ( l11l•ll1rn nr l'"l'.llfl, t>lnck or whih'." S.'t' V1°n'111
qui parum valent ingc•nin, J1inl n11tur11 nllr 11l lurl11 "' """ h11t...1111I domlnl11m ••I ".'.'' 1•1 .11i,1rum e·iu I l ( ·.un•. "'"Jlu· SpM1f~h "f11.,.1l11Kh"11! J111 hll1 "' llrn,.l•-•"111 r ,"' In J l'rl1•1l1• 11111111 l(,..·n. "'I" .
wrum; hiu.'<· rnim t'11t 114•rvlt11J1 dvlllio rl lrKllhn11. 'I'"' 11ul111" ,.,.t ,..., vu.. " n1tt11rn llr11 ''''""'~ ,f~ 1,,, ( ·11...1• 111 1/1.-111111 (I i..._11lh. Ill I'll 11 J rt Ji/ 111 ?'11
THE ID EA OF NA11.lRAL RIGHTS ARISTOT\.E /\ND ntE AMERICAN INDIANS 273
272

key element in the construction of political th~~es. ~itoria substitute~ a children to adults, women to men, the savage and cruel to the mild and
vision that was, in its way, profoundly humamshc. Hts work was not in- gentle, the grossly intemperate to the continent, I might almost say as
fluenced so much by the literary humanism of his age as by an older monkeys to men.11
theological and philosophical humanism that saw h~man~ind as t~e end On this view the Indians had to be subdued by force before any work of
of all creation. Vitoria was convinced that all the things m the uruverse conversion could effectively be undertaken.
God had created, even the last star, were meant to serve humanity. Other- In response to such arguments Las Casas often presented the Indians
wise, he asked, a little naively perhaps, why should they have been made as a morally and intellectually superior people. In the Apologetica historia
at all? 611 he described them as "gentle, patient, and humble," endowed with "ex-
cellent, subtle, and very capable minds," characterized by "temperance in
eating and drinking, moderation in sensual desires, and a lack of care and
LAS CASAS, INDIANS AND RIGHTS anxiety about worldly things." According to Las Casas the Indians sur-
Vitoria passed his life in libraries and lecture-halls; he encountered passed even the ancient Greeks and Romans in the use of natural reason.n
the problem of the Indies as a disputed issue of moral theology. Las Casas There is perhaps a little pardonable exaggeration in all this; but the core of
lived and worked among the Indians for twenty years before he entered Las Casas' case for the Indians can be found in two eloquent lines at the
th<> Oominican Order and turned to a systematic study of theology and end of his rebuttal of Sepulveda. "They are our brothers, and Christ gave
law. He saw first hand some of the atrocities that he inveighed against _in a his life for them.''73
flood of later writings. His works ate filled with a passion and immed1~cy Las Casas was so much concerned with the particular grievances of
that set them apart from the typical writings of the Spanish scholas~cs. the Indians that it has sometimes been doubted whether he ever formed a
These qualities also eamed Las Casas a conflicted posthum~us reputah?n. doctrine of universal natural rights at all. Michel Villey observed that Las
Some nationalist historians, incensed by Las Casas' role m the creation Casas wrote only to defend the liberties of the Indians, not those of other
of the Black Legend of Spanish cruelty, have dismissed the Dominican as peoples-Negroes or Chinese for instance-and so had hardly any con-
arrogant, unbalanced and even "para~oiac"; more c~mmonl~ now~~ays cern for the rights of mankind in general.74 But this seems inconsistent
he is seen as an "authentic representation of the Sparush conscience. with some lines of Las Casas that have become famous.
The whole of Las Casas' life's work was inspired by a conviction that
All the peoples of the world are humans and there is only one definition
the Indians could be converted to Christianity only by peacefu' persuasion of all humans and of each one, that is that they are rational. . .. Thus all
without any violence or coercion.10 In ~efendi~g the In~ians, the~fore, the races of humankind are one.75
he especially emphasized the natural nght to liberty. Hts adve.rsanes-
notably Juan de Sepulveda, against whom Las Casas contended m a great The idea of a universal brotherhood of man is an ancient Stoic concep-
confrontation at Valladolid in 1550-maintained on the contrary that the tion, and, indeed, Las Casas quoted Cicero here. But, like Vitoria, he went
Indians were a degraded people, just barely human, naturally made for beyond the ancient sources by supplementing them with a medieval doc-
slavery. SepUlveda wrote, for instance: trine of natural rights.
Lewis Hanke once wrote of the early writers on America that "they
The Spaniards rule with perfect right over the barbarians who,. in pru- tended to look at the New World through medieval spectacles.'' Evidently
dence, talent, virtue and humanity are as inferior to the Spamards as
we cannot understand the thought of Las Casas without some knowledge
of the tumultuous events of his life and some awareness of the savage
68. IX juslitill, 2.lae.62.1, n-73.
69. On Las Casas as paranoiac see R. Menendez Pidal. El padrr Uis Casas. Su dob!t ~n­
alidad (Madrid 1963). llle second quotation is from a resoluti#on.ad°!'ted at t~e 1lurty-s1xlh 71. Angel Losada, rd., /"1n Gi11rs dt' Srpuliontn. I kmocrales ~gundo o ~las jusla~ c·ausn!f tlr
Annual Conference of Americanists, quoted by Juan Comas, Htstoncal Reahty and the De- lr1 gurrra contra l<ls Indios (M11drid, 11151 ), :n . I\~ thf' Nlilor noted {3..l n. 28). the phraM.· ahem!
tractors of Las Casas," in Friede and Keen, Bartolom~ dt Uis Casas, 487- 537 at 531. See aL'iO m nnkl'ys was dropped in Sc.>p1ilvc'tlA' " flnAI vrn<ion ur th1• trxt.
B. Keen, "Introduction: Approaches to Las Cna!I, 1535- 1970,H in ibid., 3- 63. . 72. Apol~rlrca lrisrorin !<Untn111rf11 I. r.I V l\hrtl <'11•h•llr'1 rt al., O bra.•, 6:285-1'16.
70. Las Casas expounded this vww in tii11 e11rly work, On lht Only Way of ~llraclrn~ All 7.1. l\polaxin, rd. l\ngrl I A.,.a1l11, c l/•1111, •1 hf>(
Pttiple to tht Trut Faith, and repeatro It In m11ny 1.. 1,.r w rll~nK~· St•t• hiii l>r "":"'.' Vt~·11tum1~ 74. M. Villt•y, " l'n>l>lrnu1llct1"' ,,.,. choll• ct.. t'hummr," In'"'' ( ·"""' t'I la 1~1/ill11'rr cfl'!f 1frol1..
modo, ed. P. Castal\rda ~lgado aml A. I ;411rd• Llt'I Mnrfll In I ""' fllirloluml rlr I'" < ''"'''· Clhra!I .It' /'11r1nrn11• (All!·<'n ·l'rovr11r'W', IV?n), \flll 01 111 ltlV
Complttas, 14 voUI- {Motdrld, II.IHI\ QCI). 7 7r, /\l'o/cisrlirn l1l•hrrf1111111t1t110111 II. I lfc1111. 'f 'I WI If
274 TliE IDEA OF NAruRAL RIGHTS

struggle for wealth and power that lay behind all the theoretical writings
on the New World; but also we cannot explain Las Casas's specific role in
l
••
ARlsrcrrt..E AND TiiE AMERICAN INDIANS

as a devoted Thomist, could not have taught the latter doctrine.11 He


wanted to liberate the Indian peoples, but he did not assert that individual
275

the development of a theory of natural rights without considering his in- persons had a right to liberty.82 According to Andre-Vincent, even when
tellectual formation and the preconceptions he brought to his work. As Las Casas used the word iura in the plural he was referring to the laws and
with Vitoria, this is still a matter of controversy among modem Thomists customs of the Indians not to their rights.83 And when he referred to the
and other critics. Probably the most commonly held view is that the friar subjective attributes of persons he used words like "faculty" or "power"
derived a doctrine of natural rights from Aquinas. Venancio Carro, for ..i but not "right.''34 Andre-Vincent especially praised the realism of Las
instance, in discussing Las Casas, wrote of "the Thomist principle that i' Casas in addressing the concrete grievances of the Indians and contrasted
natural rights come before all other rights."76 Abril Castello saw the Span- :.'" ! this approach with the abstract "rights of man" claimed by Enlighten-
ish Dominican's thought as "traditional Thomist ideology" supplement~ ment theorists.15
with elements of Augustinian political theology.77 Luf\o Pena t°<:> main- Before going any further we need to note that this point of view
tained that Las Casas relied on Aquinas's rational natural law (wsnatu- really cannot be sustained. And, indeed, Andrt?-Vincent never made any
ralismo rationalista) in formulating his characteristic doctrine of a natural attempt to sustain it by a systematic examination of Las Casas' actual use
f
right to liberty inhering in every human person.78 Edmundo O'Gorman, -~ I of the terms ius and iura. The modem scholar's medieval spectacles were
on the other hand, argued that Las Casas spoke with " the voice of Vol- ~i strongly tinted with Thomism; he could not see anything in Las Casas
taire, Hume, and Rousseau," but only because he abandoned his earlier that was out of harmony with his understanding of Aquinas. But in fact
Christian-Aristotelian view of human nature and turned to a kind of pre-
Cartesian rationalism.79 Other writers have discerned an essential moder-
f one can open a work of Las Casas like the De thesauris almost anywhere at
random and, reading on for a few pages, come upon specific references to
, II
nity in Las Casas without accepting this particular argument of O'Gorman. the rights of the Indians. Las Casas wrote, for instance, of the "dignities,
I goods and other rights (j11ribus)" that even infidels held by natural law;
Pena, for instance, while emphasizing the Thomist source of Las Casas' !
thought, also saw the Dominican as "a precursor of the modem teaching I of "regalian rights" (iura) belonging to the Indian princes; of their "juris-
on the rights of man."80 In this way of thinking the writings of Las Cas~s dictions, dignities, rights (iura} and dues."86 Las Casas also referred in this
formed a link between a doctrine of natural rights already present m work specifically to the rights of single individuals and defined a right
Aquinas and modem pronouncements on human rights. as meaning a kind of power.87 Again, Andrt?-Vincent wrote that Las Casas
A view different from all these has been presented in the many publi- 81 . P. Andrl?-Vincent, "La con cretisation de la notion classique de droit nature! a travers
cations of a modem Dominican, Philippe Andre-Vincent, on Las Casas.
Andre-Vincent asserts that the whole concept of subjective natural rights
was alien to Las Casas' thought. Arguing from the same neo-Thomist
standpoint that we discussed in considering the work of Villey, ~e ma~­
t.
.i
l°OC'uvre de Las Casas," in Las Casas tt la politiq11t, 203-213. " L'oeuvre de Las Casas se rat-
tache a saint Thomas d 'Aquin par de no mbreuses referen~ et surtout un sens concret et
oojectif du droit" (203). This paper presents a clear outline of the views that Andre-Vmcent
developed in his various other writings on Las Casas.
82. "Concretisation," 205. "Cette liberte . .. n 'est jamais revendiquee comme un droit in·
tains that the "classic natural right" we find in Aquinas is radically in- j
I dividuel."
compatible with the idea of subjective natural rights. Las Casas, therefore, l S3. "Concretisation," 204, "Par contre on ne rencontre jamais dans les ecrits la.scasiens le
mot droit employe dans le sens de rive subjectif. . . . Ainsi quand on lit chez Las Casas "Les
droits des lndiens" ... ii s'agit des lois des Jndiens...."
76. Carro, "The Spanish Theological-Juridical Renaissance, ft 253. 84. "Concritisnlion," 204, "Las Casas .. . parlera de capacites, de pouvoirs, non de droits.."
77. v. Abril Castello, "Bartolome de las Casas, el ultimo communero," in Las Casas ti In 85. Writers on Las Casas often seem ambivalent on this point. On Las Casas' " moder·
politiqut, 92-123 at 110. . . .. nity" see above, n. 80. On the other hand, J. Hoffner wrote that of course Las Casas did not
78. Lui\o Pena, "Presupuestos historico-doclTinales de la teona Las Casas d e la hbertad, a'iSert the secularized human rights of a later age. (See Pena, " Presupuestos," 165, n. 64.) M .
in ibid., 153-65 at 156. Mahn· Lo t, Bartolome de Ins Cnsa~ t'I le droil dN> lndim.~ (Paris, 1982), 258, succeeded in hilvinR
79. E. Q'Gorman, "Lewis Hanke on the Spanish Struggle for Justice in the Conqut>St of it both ways . She wrote, " II faut ~<· gu•lt·r .. . tie confondre le droit nature! de Ia tht'ologil"
America,ft Hispanic Amnicon Historical Rroitw 29 (1949): 56:l-71. . . sn1I.1stiquC' el le droit nillun•l 111o•l1•m. •••lui di• <:n 1ti11s 1•t <IC'S F.ncydop&tislC'S," but 11l!Co, "'ii
80. "Presupuestos," 162. For a discus.~ion of viC'W!'i on l.a:r; Casas' mnd..-rnity sre /\. h. y ;i unC' filiati<>n indeni.1'11<' •l•'ll h1>1111111.,. ,,,.,. I .11111u' n"' ,, l\'colc• de Salamanqur... ."
Perez Luno and J. Gonulez R(>dr!gu<•:r.. t>r rr'1ilf f"•IN>lalr, <>!mis, 12:1-XXXIX al XIV. lih. lk ll11•'4J11ris, 4'd /\nKrl I•"'"''"· I''''''" 11 I, 71•. Hll
XXXlll-XXXIX. See also L. Han kt', " I .11 f"n"' tl1• l'rAy 11.lrh•lnm•~ Jt• l.u1 ( ·,,,..,~:· in f:~111di1is I J I!<· K7. On riKhl!! u f sinl(lt' ln1livhl1111l• ...,., , ,,. ,,,~..11111o. 11 J, 1111, •• . • nun 1•r11t lntrntlun!JO 111u•
casianos (Seville, 1966), 1 - 1~ 11t II•, """1''"'"11 1... ~ (""'"" tr.whh111 111 th•• ll11ih•1I N.1tin11~ 11111b11H "1t""' n <1l11rnll11m ••I •11111111111111111'"'""""10011 ''""'K"'r •• At 222, I.A• <'A!lll• rr
Drdaration on ll11m11n Kil(hho"1ul t11lhr1•r1111111u,. rmr11t• 111V.11111111< ·uu n•1111 h•1n~I tu llw liKhl 111i\1.1111( 11• ··111• '""'"P 1•11t..•l11tl• •· •;111111111 " ""Krll oc't'llr 11t :llti. .177
276 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ARISTOTLE ANO THE AMERICAN INDIANS 277

never claimed for the Indians a "droit de," a right of doing something; but wanted to prove that, even after they became Christians, the Indians
Las Casas did use such language in phrases like ius movendi bellum (the would not be obliged to accept the universal temporal authority of the
right of making war) or potestas et auctoritas vel ius eligendi (the power and po~e as a matter of fait~, and so acknowledge a papal right to hand over
authority or right of electing).88 . . their. lands to. the Spaniards. The proof was in the form of a syllogism.
Although Andre-Vincent's argument is unacceptable it leaves us with Aquinas provided the major premise. "No one acts against the faith if he
a problem. 1be modem Dominican ~ at .least right ~ asse~ng that Las d~ubts on a_matter where Catholic doctors hold contrary opinions." The
Casas did not take a doctrine of subjective natural nghts directly from minor premise came from the great canonists, Innocent IV and Hostiensis.
Aquinas; for, as we noted in discussing Vit~ria, ~quinas did not present These two eminent Catholic authorities did indeed hold contrary opinions
such a doctrine. We still need, therefore, to mvestigate the actual sources about the temporal power of the pope and the rights of infidels. So the con-
of Las Casas' thought. Fortunately Las Casas himself has left us a clue. In a clusion followed that Las Casas had set out to prove.'1
Jetter written to the friars of his Mexican diocese of Chiappa, he wrote that, The best example of a purely Aristotelian-Thomist argument for
however hard and rigorous his propositions might seem, they could all natural liberty in the writings of Las Casas occurs in his defense of the
be defended from the teachings of St. Thomas, even though they were 1 Indians agai:"st the at~ack o~Sepulveda. One of Sepulveda's principal ar-
not expressly stated there. But he also wrote here that he had labored for gum~nts rehed on Ar~stotle s teaching about natural slavery. According
forty-eight years to study the law and to reach a clear understanding of t to Aristotle, all barbanans were natural slaves, Sepulveda noted, and the
its principles.119 In similar vein Las Casas wrote, when he contem~tuously Indians were evidently barbarians; they ought therefore, as slaves, to
/ dismissed the view of John Mair on the Indians, "Away then w1th John submit meekly to their Spanish masters; and if they refused to do so they
V Mair and his dreams; he knows neither the law nor the facts."90 Las Casas could be warred against just as one might hunt down wild beasts.9 2 Las
prided himself on knowing both the facts and t~e law. J:iis essen_tia~ a_ch- Casas, however, recalled that Aquinas, in commenting on the relevant
ievement on a theoretical level, was to graft, qwte consciously, a 1undical text of Aristotle's Politics, had observed that the word "barbarian" could
doctrine ~f natural rights onto Aquinas's teaching on natural law. In this refer to several d ifferent classes of people. Then he proceeded to adapt
he was like Vitoria and other Spanish theologian-jurists of the sixteenth Aquinas's distinctions to suit his own argument.
century; but the appeal to legal sources was m~re over_t and persistent in In the first place, Las Casas wrote, any cruel and merciless person
Las Casas than in Vitoria or most of the other wnters. HIS pages are strewn c')uld be called a barbarian; but, in this sense, the Spaniards themselves
with hundreds of references to Roman and canon law and to medieval were "barbarians and worse than barbarians" on account of their cruelties
commentators on the two laws. to the lndians.93 Again, peoples who could not understand each other's
Las Casas resembled Ockham in frequently appealing to canonistk speec~ regarded one another as barbarians; but in this sense the Spanish
texts in order to defend a doctrine of rights, and he was also like the Fran- were 1ust as much barbarians to the Indians as the Indians were to the
ciscan in another way. He kept on repeating the same argum~nts over and Spanish.94 In yet another meaning of the word, all non-Christians could be
over again in treatise after treatise. The reaso~_was the sa~e m both cases. ~lied barbarians; but this definition included civilized peoples like the an-
Las Casas was not articulating a coherent political theory m the ca~m of ~e cient Greeks and Romans.95 The only barbarians " in the absolute and strict
study; he was engaged in constant battle; his adversanes kept reaterat~ng sense of the word," Las Casas held, were scattered savage individuals,
the same arguments against his position, and Las Casas kept responding strangers to reason, who dwelt alone in forests and mountains without any
from his prepared stock of counter arguments. Often he chose to fight on ordered society, leading a life like that of brute animals. These were the
the ground his adversary had chosen. When faced with an Aristotel~an "wild men" of medieval legend. Las Casas conceded that this class of
argument he would argue back from Aristotle or Aquinas. When dealing humans might correspond to Aristotle's natural slaves;96 but he had two
with a juridical objection he would deploy an array of le~a~ texts..So~~
times, most interestingly, he would weave together Thorrusti~ and 1unshc 91. [)I' thesnuris, 294.
doctrines to reach a new conclusion. Thus, in the De thesaurrs, Las Casas 92. Drmocmlt's Y R11t1<fo, 22.
93. Al'oieJKia, 80, 122, MHi'r""' . i..,rt..iri s u n t c·t b.1 rbaris peio res."
94. Ibid ., 116.
88. Dt tht sauris, 380, 236.
89. J. P~rez de Tudela BuellO. OhrCIS ~JSlidas tf,. fr11.11 Rartoloml dr Uis Ctr~~. 5 vols '15. Ibid ., 1111.
-~I
(Madrid, 1957-58). 5:470, 471. % . Ibid ., I lff, " l>r h lo ltw111lh11 l'hll11•" 1'h11• r t " " " p rommlinl """" n.,lru n 11e•rvo11
90. Apol~ill. 6114. Sc-.· R. lt.•mh1•lnw r. w,1,1 Mt11 l11 ll1t Ml1l1ll• "~'·(I '"""'"'K"· MAM., 1111\1)
278 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ARISTOTLE AND THE AMERICAN INDIANS 279

important further points to make. Even men like thc:se were not alto~e~er Lufto Pena cited this text to show how Las Casas derived his doctrine of
devoid of rights. They had a right to "brotherly kindness and Christian a natural right to liberty from Aquinas.103 But that is less than half the
Jove.'"" They were not to be hunted down like wild animals and subjected story. The reference to Aquinas was inserted between two texts taken from
to harsh and cruel labor but rather gently persuaded to adopt a better way Roman and canon law. The cited passage of Aquinas did declare that "na-
of life.98 Las Casas' other point was that barbarians of this kind were nec- ture made all men equal in liberty"; but, when Las Casas wanted to prove
essarily very rare; they were freaks of nature like a man born with some that liberty was specifically a right, he turned to a text of the Decretum
physical abnormality- lame, crippled, blind or one-eyed.99 Las Casas went (Dist. 1.c.7} that had been a locus of discussion about natural rights ever
on to present at some length an argument that Vitoria had only suggested since the twelfth century.104
in a couple of elliptical lines. Aristotle had written, "Nature always does For Las Casas, liberty was " more precious and priceless" than any
what is best of things possible." The existence of many abnormal, defec- riches a people might possess.105 In the De regia potestate the Dominican
tive humans would, therefore, imply a frustration of nature and a failure also defended a right to property and a right to institute rulers by consent
of God's plan for humankind. There could not be a whole race of such as ancillary to the fundamental right of liberty. As regards property, in
people.100 Here again, as with Vitoria, Aristotle's own teachings were used the beginning all things were "free" in the sense that they did not belong
101
to subvert the assertion that all barbarian peoples were slaves by nature. to anyone; therefore each person had the power to take anything for his
When, later in his Apologia for the Indians, Las Casas turned to other own.106 (Las Casas did not present any complex theory of property; he
problems about the waging of a just war that were raised.by Sepulveda, he simply accepted the Roman law doctrine of first occupancy without fur-
relied more on juridical sources. In a later work, De regra potestate, where ther discussion.) When a ruler was instituted he acquired jurisdiction over
Las Casas was more concerned to assert positively a natural right to liberty his subjects but not ownership of their property. 107 And since, in the be-
than to refute the theory of natural slavery, he based his argument almost ginning, all people were free, the authority of a ruler could be derived only
entirely on legal authorities. But in the crucial definition of liberty there from their voluntary consent-otherwise they would be deprived of the
was again an interweaving of Thomist and juristic texts. liberty that belonged to them by natural right. 108 It followed too that a ruler
could not impose taxes or other burdens unless the people voluntarily con-
As regards humans, it is shown that from the begi~i~g of their rati~nal
nature, they were bom free, as in the law Manum1ss1ones of the Digest, sented; they did not lose their liberty when they elected a ruler.109 All this
Title De iustitia et iure (Dig. 1.1.4).... The reason for this according to led to a conclusion about the alienation of crown lands and crown rights.
Thomas (on the Sentences, 2.44.1.3) is that a rational nature in itself is not
ordered to some other as its end .... For liberty is a right (ius) necessarily
instilled in man from the beginning of rational nature and so from natural .-essistate et per se ab exordio rationalis naturae, et sic je iure naturali (ul J. dist. c. ius 1111turalt.
law (iure) as in Distindio 1 (of the Decretum) in the chapter Ius naturale at ihi: Omnium 11na l1bertas).''
the words, Omnium una libertas (Dist. 1.c.7).102 103. " Presupuestos," 156.
104. For the comments of Huguccio and Ockham on this text see above, 65, 178-80.
97. Ibid., 98. 105. De regia poltslate, 2.8.5, 82.
98. Ibid., 98-100. 106. Ibid., 1.2.1-3, 40- 44, "Quantum autem ad res inanimatas ut sunt terra, praedia,
99. Ibid., 90. "Raro enim naturales causae cessant produrere effectus naturae suae con- •·t qu<1elibet res aliae, similiter est dicendum quod fuerunt originaliter de iure naturali
gruentes. Raro enim homo nascitur daudus vel mancus vel c~ecus vel u~~lus.. . . " primaevo liberae . . . Apparel etiam hac ratione: omnis terra et omnis res, antequam occu-
100. Ibid., 94, " Rursus si credamus tam immensam hommum multitud1nem barbaram l'•uetur, in nullius bonis erat ... Unde homo quilibet concessione d.ivina potestatem habuit
esse, sequeretur intentionem Dei maxima ex parte effectu caruisse .. . et sic perfectioni totius praroccupandi possessionem cuiuscumque rei.... "
universi multum detraheretur...." 107. Ibid., I 3, 1-3, 48, " . .. aliud rei proprietas, aliud autem iurisdictio.. . . Nl'C obstnl
101. In an earlier encounter at the court of Charles V Las Casas had declared robustly •1111>d dicant reg~ regnum ~se s uum, quia intelligitur suum esse quoad iurisdictiontm "'
that Aristotle was just " a pagan burning in Hell." See Historia dt Ins l11dias Ill, ed. M . Ang~I protcctionem.n Las Casas was agi'lin following Roman law here. See the Ordinary C.ln!<.• lo
Medina et al., Obras 5:2413. But Las Casas was no t averse to citing the Philosopher when •l l ·, ~/. 7 _17.3 s.v. onmin pmrciJ'iS, "••I hk t"•P"'"' ntl pmtcxt iontm uel iurisdictionem."
suited his own argument. • . HIS. Ibid., l.4. 1- 3 , 60- 62, " l'mh111trr Ah lnllln omni~ rt!ft, omnis populus fuit lil>t'r; 1<1
102. Dt regia potestalt, ed. A. Larios Ramos and A . Garcia del Moral y Gamdo, O/Jr~.~ . ..onlra pupuli vt'I p rival i domlnil 1111• 11h111 R'I vuh111l11lrm imponnentur, fol't'flt ab!lqut' d ut>lo
12:1.1.l, 34. " Et quidem, quantum ad homiONO, probatur quoniam ab u rigine naturile raho- viult•nla, el sic' pmhillt•wl11r pnp11l11M 1111 •ttll lll,..1l11lr. •pint• cir iurt> naturali compt"IC't>al. . .
r>alis 1;;,.....n nascebantur, ul I. manumil'..•innt'I'. Dt• iulil, t•I iur. Qula in n.1t11r,1 pari l>t•us non limit' impt'rlu m lmm1•tll.,tr 1•N M'f'Hll 11 l'"I'"'"· "'("'I'""'" 111!1 C'AllM 1•ffrr tlv11 n'KUnt ......
fadl unum alterius M-rvum, St-rl par c•mnlhu~ ,.......~.,.,.11 nrhllrlum l ·uhL• r.11lu ,.,., "'"·11ml11111 prindrum. ·•
Thom am (2 St'nl. di.• t. 44, q. I. art . '.l), •111111 n11111111 "r11tlun11U~. •1111m111111 ....1 •I<' '"'· 11011 nnli1rnl11r 111'1 lhi.t . I 4 4, It/, '' l'111111h1•"''•••1t1l111•1h11 l1•,.111 .,... " 'K" m. llhrrt11lrm "'"""non 1111111.11,
ul ntt fi11t'm '"' 111111111. 111 homo '"I hu1nl11r111 ·• Nini\ hhr tlll• ,.,., tu• 111•1111111 h1>ml11lht11< •"' n•• ""' pole••lt1h•111 • •ttllllll•ll 1111l t 11111.,.. 1t 111 •~1111111 ·
280 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGllTS ARISTUTl.E AND THE AMERICAN INDIANS 281

"No prince or king, however supreme . . . may alienate any city, land, or protectorate, "a universal imperial jurisdiction" over the Indian.s. 115 But
fortified place however small ... unless the citizens or inhabitants ... Las Casas also insisted that this jurisdiction must respect the rights of the
freely consent to such alienation." 110 Unlike most of Las Casas' works, the Indian peoples and their rulers, and that it could be exercised justly only if
De regia potestale was written in rather dry and abstract terms but, as the Indians consented to it.
always, Las Casas had in mind a specific problem concerning the Indies. In his early writings Las Casas had taken a decidedly royalist stance;
His immediate purpose here was to dissuade the king of Spain from grant- he hoped that the crown would intervene to protect the Indians against
ing to the Spanish colonists permanent encomiendas-semi-feudal grants of the abuses of the encomaderos. When these hopes were frustrated after
land worked by native labor that included jurisdiction over the Indian in- the failure of the New Laws of 1542 (laws that favored the Indians but that
habitants. were never put into effect) his attitude became more radical. At the end
Luciano Perena, an editor of the De regia potestale, complained a little of his life, in the De thesa11ris, Las Casas argued that the existing Spanish
about the careless handling of legal sources in this work. Las Casas, he rule in the Indies, as it had actually come to exist-a conquest by violence
noted, often quoted his authorities at second-hand, not from the original followed by a plundering of the land and its inhabitants-was utterly ille-
source; at times he cited sources imprecisely; and sometimes he used texts gitimate. The situation could be remedied only by a full restitution to the
in a way contrary to their original meaning. 111 I would agree that Las Casas Indians of all the rights and lands and treasures that had been snatched
was opportunistic in his use of juridical authorities, but his knowledge of away from them. It was not a very realistic program on the level of prac-
the literature was really very extensive. One would not expect anything tical politics. Perhaps by this time, as Juan Friede suggested, Las Casas
else from forty-eight years of study! The impression that texts are being was more anxious to make his peace with God than hopeful of changing
wrenched from their original meaning typically arises, not because Las the politics of Philip II. But, although the work could have no immediate
Casas misunderstood his sources, but because he was deploying them in a practical effect, it has a considerable theoretical significance as a systematic
new context that their original authors could not have foreseen. application of the scholastic doctrine of natural rights to a concrete histori-
This is especially true of Las Casas' last major treatise De thesauris in cal situation. It is in this regard that Las Casas' use of juridical sources is
Peru, sometimes called his Testament. The work contains strains of Thom- especially interesting. By appealing to specific well-established principles
ist thought as I noted earlier. Las Casas, for instance, took his definition of of the law he was able to add flesh and bone and muscle to the theoretical
natural Jaw from the Summa theologiae of Aquinas, 112 and when he made concept of natural rights that had been developed in the schools. I would
the standard point that human law should be in accord with natural law like to conclude by giving a few examples of this kind of reasoning.
he cited both theologians (Aquinas and Augustine) and canonists (Gratian A principal theme of the De lhesauris maintained that the papal dona-
and Baldus). 113 But the whole fabric of the argument in this work-an ar- tion to the Spanish crown did not and could not deprive the Indians of
gument about the natural rights of the Indians, especially their right to their pre-existing rights and liberties even though it granted " lordships
liberty-was sustained by juridical reasoning.114 .md jurisdictions" in the Indies to Spain. As one proof of this, Las Casas as-
Las Casas never argued against a Spanish presence in the New World; serted that a papal rescript favoring one individual should not prejudice
his whole life's purpose was to bring the Indians to Christianity through the rights of a third party. Now this was indeed a familiar doctrine of tht•
the work of Spanish missionaries. He also acknowledged that Pope Alex- canonists, asserted in various scattered texts of the Gregorian Decrelals. l...is
ander Vi's Jetter assigning the Americas to the Spanish crown as a mission l ·asas quoted several of these texts and added, with only a little exaggl·rn-
territory did give the Spanish kings a claim to a kind of overlordship or tion, that innumerable Jaws could be adduced to prove the same point.'"
But the texts of the Decretals referred only to technicalities of canon law.
110. Jbid., 1.12.1, 98. for instance, when the pope granted some privilege to a papal lcgat<•, ht•
111. "Estudio preliminar,# in ~ rrgia polt'Slatt, ed. L. Perena et a l. (Madrid. 1969),
CXLVIll. 115. /)1"1/11"51!/lrIS 112.
112. ~ thtSauris, 90, HDe quo S. Thomas 1.2 .q .96 a .4 ... ' F.-;t aul<'m lt>11 Oillurali" in nohi~ 116. bid., 96, n Prolt>lllatur inftuprr Summuft l'ontifl'11 111tl' inl<'nlionb nun'lw1m ,.,._.,.
quedam partidpatio legis eteme .. .'." ·•lic1uid rruuidt•n• ;mt m .. nd1111', ,.,.., 111111• 1111.-rcu, , ...r ., ....,, '11irui prf'iudldum lrrc'j\C'tllr.. . .
113. Ibid., 90- 92. " uni .1 li,. innuml'r,. iur• qur ••I prcil••lh"1r111 h11h10111< .. ll pu11~unt 11.tdud.H l.a11 Cuu dh·•I
114. This was e mpha."i1.t>d hy K. l'<'nllington. " 11.,rtnlumi' ,1,. '""' l ·.,,..,io anti th<' Tr.ltlilion IU'rt' 111•v1•n lt••lii Imm llw I >r1rr/11/, I" I it 17. 11 I 7'1 I'I. X '.t:lll.:l, X. l.J.1', X.2.12 I. X .~ I 24,
of Mt>dieval I.aw," Churi·h lli:tl1•rv :WI 1'170) 14•1 ltl ·n1h• 1Htld1• tll1! not n ..·r lv1· dll th1• ..111•11· 'I( I .1 711). two trum th.- I "'"'"hm1 ll · l'I 'I /, " · I JI 'I 1, I) 1111.t 1>111' fmm lhr (",_,,. (1'1-/ "4 II)
lion it tft'!W'rvrtl in tile' latrr •pAI• ol I •• C •••• •l111llr" •;,•mt• of th<' • cmo nl•tl• 11'-I• 111111111 ''""' tly ltll'l1llfl"cl 1t1 lh<' l"•lltlcm • llr'tl
282 TuE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS
ARISTOTLE AND THE A M ERICAN INOIANS 283
did not intend to prejudice the rights of the local diocesan bishop. When
the pope granted a benefice to some petitioner he did not intend to injure i~ accordance with the commonly accepted rules governing the interpreta-
the rights of some other person who might have a prior claim. And so on. tion of such documents.123 And so Las Casas reached his conclusion:
Las Casas had already stated that the Indian princes held their rights and Therefore the said (papal) institutio n, concession o r donation . . . must
dignities by natural law and the law of nations.117 His next move was to n~essarily ~ understood, interpreted, and declared as meaning that the
transpose the whole body of canonistic argumentation that he had pre- kings and pnnces of all that region may use and hold free ly their digni-
sented to the plane of natural law and natural rights. ties, properties, jurisdictions, regal states and pristine honors after the
said institution . . . as before even though the pope did not mention this
Indeed he (the pope) knows well that . . . the natural rights of others in his letterY~
which pertain to anyone by natural and divine law ought to remain fixed
and immutable.1111 fn this argument Las Casas characteristically deployed a considerable
bod_y of o[d legal technicalities to elucidate a new situation-the rights of
Las Casas then added that the purpose of the papal grant was not to Indians under a Spanish occupation.
enrich the Spanish kings but to evangelize the Indians.119 Throughout the De thesauris, Las Casas seems to have been uneasy
A little further on, Las Casas cited two passages from the Decretals and about the role that he should attribute to the Spanish kings. He did not
the commentary of Innocent IV, asserting that the pope could not deprive want to deny completely that the papal grant had given them some kind of
infidels of their properties and jurisdictions. This view was held by all the right a~ ~gards !he Indies, but he was quite unwilling to acknowledge that
canonists, he wrote, and by the more zealous theologians.120 Then, return- the ex1stmg regime there was legitimate. To complicate matters further
ing to his original theme, he unleashed another blitz of legal texts. First he he persistently applied to the Indians and their native rulers the doctrine
quoted the fifteenth-century canonist Dominicus de Sancto Gemignano he had stated in more abstract terms in the De regia potestate-that all le~
as saying that, "when the pope concedes some new right he is not under- gitimate government must be based on the consent of the governed. At
stood to intend to take away a right that some third party held before." one f><?i~t in the De thesauris he resolved the issue by another appeal to
The jurists Baldus and Bartolus supplied further texts from Roman law to canomsttc language, this time distinguishing between a ius ad rem ("right
illustrate the same point.m From all this it followed that the pope's grant to to a thing" ) and ius in re ("right in a thing"). The distinction had originally
the Spanish crown was not to be understood as violating the rights of the applied to elective offices. As Las Casas noted, when a prelate had been
Indians that belonged to them by natural law and the law of nations.122 elected to an office he acquired a "right to" it, a sort of preferential claim
It was true that Alexander had granted the Indies to Spain " with all their to the_ office; but he did not acquire a " right in" it, that is a right actually to
lordships and jurisdictions," and it was true that the pope did not ex- exercise the powers of the office, until his election had been confirmed.
pressly state that he intended to respect the rights of the existing Indian Then, turning from canon law to the current situation in the Indies, Las
rulers, Las Casas acknowledged, but the papal letter had to be understood Casas suggested that the Spanish kings were in just the same position as
a prelate-elect. They had indeed received election and institution from
117. Dt thtSOuris, 76. Las Casas referred here to the Niuribus aliis et dominio quod, super the pope, and this gave them a " title and right" to the Indian realms that
sibi subiectos habent, iure naturali et gentium." no other Christian king possessed. But this right was only a ius ad rem ; it
118. Ibid., 98, "Seit nempe melius ipse quod . .. aliena iura et que unicuique de iure natu· could become a ius in re only after it had been confirmed; and in this cast•
rali et diuino competunt, fixa et immutabilia esse oportet.n
confir~ation could come only from the free consent of the Indian peoplt•
119. Ibid.
120. Ibid., 106, referring to X.1.27 and X.3.34.8. For Innocent !V's commentary on these ;md their rulers. Consent was the "natural foundation and efficient cause"
texts see above, 143-44, 172 n. 3. Innocent IV held that, although the pope did not normally of the power to exercise jurisdiction, Las Casas wrote. So long as it was
have jurisdiction over infidels, he could punish them for offenses against natural law. Las
Casas disagreed with the pope about this.
121. Ibid. Many more Roman law texts from Baldus and other juristii were presented in 12J. lliid., 116. NE I id1•0 Ul'rh.1 n~ rlpli n•dpi unl limilationcm a iurt' communi, c•l tllllllt'!I
c lausulC' opposite in ~ripto rt',.hh1K1111hir prnt•h'n•n possunt :o;<> opponf'n• 1unnt'!I , 11111,.
the following pages. . . . . .
122. Ibid., 112- 114, Nlntelligend11, inquam, Pl dl'CIM11ml111td hnt'm 1•! hm1tes rahonis nalu· "''Knlium tangil, lic1•t non 11111 llli'nlhc ,f,. llll• ....._ 11ncl11m IS.•rnilruum." ( )n bu1 Ci\~1 ,.· furlhi•r
ralis et ne fiant iniurie, uel lurium lll11r11m K"ntlum vlnl11tl11, 1·um ;ut illn11 p<>r1ine;int it1rt> ""''of lht• q111-t 1111111rs 11111.1111 I'' h1df'h• .,.,.. 1..-luw 11..- llc•111.1n(11,. mrnlinm'<i hC'rr (i11n1rrN"'l ly
gentium et natural!, ul lk'J"' dktum ""' N
lc h•ntifii>tt hy tlw •'< litnr") I• flt•111111<l11• 1'1111111•11•1• Ii.,. 1r h.,••11t•1• I~ 111 ht, gli11t.• 1111 X 1.2•1 l'I
17-t lhicl . llH
284 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS ARISTOTLE AND THE AMERICAN INDIANS 285

withheld the king's right was, so to speak, in a state of suspension; without to consent-with good reasons and sweet inducements, Las Casas sug-
consent he lacked the ius in re which would give him "the power of ex- gested.
ercising supreme jurisdiction." 125 Here again Las Casas had made a leap The argument then took a more radical tum. Las Casas recalled a text
from the technicalities of the medieval canonists to the real-life problems of the Decretals (Cum omnes), where Innocent III had noted that a group
of his own day. of persons could possess a right either as a corporate whole or as single
Let us consider one more example of this kind of reasoning. In a individuals. In the first case a majority sufficed in some matter affecting the
particularly interesting passage, Las Casas defended the Indians' right to right; in the second case the consent of each individual was required. 118
liberty and their correlative right to consent to Spanish rule by invoking This was another technicality of medieval canon law; Innocent's decretal
the legal doctrine of quod omnes tangit-"What touches all is to be ap- referred to the canons of a collegiate church who might hold property cor-
proved by all." A considerable modem literature has grown up around porately or as individual benefices. But, as usual, Las Casas saw in the text
this little phrase. 126 It first occurred in Roman private law where it signi- an immediate relevance to the plight of the American Indians. Submission
fied that, when a group of co-tutors or co-owners possessed some right in to Spanish rule would not affect only the kings, lords, and leaders of
common, they all had to be consulted in any matter that affected the right. the people, he wrote, but also lesser persons and every single individual.
The maxim was first transformed into a principle of constitutional law by Therefore they all had to be summoned and to consent; the right of all
the canonists; around 1200 they began to argue that, when a general coun- would be diminished if a free people lost its "sweet liberty." 129 Moreover,
cil was summoned to discuss matters of faith, even the laity ought to where liberty was concerned, the case was "common to all and many and
be represented since the faith was a matter that "touched" them all. Sub- to single individuals." In these circumstances the consent of a whole
sequently the phrase was very commonly cited, both in discussions of rep- people or city could not prejudice the right of a single person withholding
resentative government and in actual summonses to church councils and consent.130 Even if a majority freely consented to accept an alien king's rule,
secular assemblies. Now Las Casas found a new use for it. He had been since they acted against liberty their action could not prejudice a dissenting
arguing that, if the Spanish subdued the Indians by force without their minority; in such a case the opinion of a minority refusing consent should
consent, they would be imposing "a servitude contrary to natural law and prevail. 131 All this amounted to a very extreme defense of the individual
reason." Then he continued; right to liberty. Las Casas concluded that, since the Indians were free, they
were granted a power and faculty of consenting by natural law.132
Whenever a free person and, still more, a free people or community is to
be obliged to accept some burden or pay some due and generally when it Therefore all, both great and small, the whole people and individual per-
is a question of something prejudicial, especially to many, it is fitting that sons, are to be summoned and their consent sought and obtained. 133
all whom the matter touches be called and their free consent obtained;
otherwise what is done has no validity.121 128. Ibid., 198. "Quod inlelligitur secundum lnnocentium et omnes, in cap. cum omnrs,
De conslitutionibus, quando aliquid est commune pluribus ... sed ut singulis uel super iure
But the acceptance by the Indians of Spanish rule would indeed imply singulari. Tune nempe, oportet scire et consentire singulos.# "The reference was to X.1.2.6.
the assumption of new burdens; and the Indians never had given their This was the same canon.istic text that Ockham used in a different way to buttress his theory
consent to this rule. To legitimate it, therefore, they had to be persuaded of limited government. See above, 184.
129. Ibid., 202, u • •• reges. principes, et subditi, magni et parui, perdant suam amabilem
libertatem ... . H

125. Ibid., 316-318, usic est de regibus nostris: habent nempe electionem siue institu- 130. Ibid., 200, HManifestum, nempe, est quod hac causa, omnes, tam magnos, id at,
tionern papalem et sic titulum et ius ad regna illa, quod regum nemo christianorum de reges et dominos . .. quam paruos et singulos oportet uocari. Et omnes et singuli habent con·
mundo habet. Sed adhuc restat iUis aliud potentius et principalius ius obtinendum, scilicet, '4'nlire; alias nihil ualebat quidquid factum fuerit in contrarium. Nee si etiam omnes, dum
consensus populorum et regum suorum . .. quatenus ius acquinmt in re reges nostri, id liht>t populo uel ciuitate consentiant, non periudicabunt uni soli non uocato aut non con·
est plenam consequantur potestatem exercendi iurisdictionem supremam .. .. Ergo quan- ...•ntienti, quod hec cau.Y t~I c-omm11n<' omnibus et pluribus et singulis maxime fouon•
diu populi et habitatores prefati, cum regibus suis, libere non consenserint ... tantum lill<'rtatis."
habebunt reges nostri titulum et ius ad ttgna illa, non autem in regnis . . . quia . .. deest regi- 131. Ibid., 20fl, "lmmo. l't~I mAlnr P""' n>llM'Tlti01t ~ponte sine aliquo !Tl('lu, qula fadunt
bus nostris naturale fundamentum t't t'fficims catL"1, scilket. .-on!lt'nStlS populorum et regum n1ntra libertatem, 1wn pr11rlmllnu...1 11011 t u1U•r11tlrntll•11!1, l'I t"Met 11tandum minor! pnrtl nun
suorum.n t.·c1nst•ntil'Tlt~."
126. The ~t di..cu...•hH1 IN hy Yvc•,. ( ·"''K"'· "()lu><I 0111111.,. t1111Kll, ''" 1>nmihu!I ln,ctari 1•t t:\2. lhi<I .• 210, "Ht 1·11111111"'"' ••l•IAlll, " '"A 111at1111\ll l11n- p<>lt'lll111' '"' fnc11ltft1' nin11C"11\11•1wll
nppnib11ri .trtwt," Rr1•11r /1/,.r.1rl'fllr<lr 1lt111l f 11mv11• r l 1111111.~-. . 41• ,.,., 'lt• ( 1'1'>11)" '/Ill 2r,~ 1lnt11r rt l'lllllnt1lkrrull ••
127. f'lrlhr.<i<J11tn. l!Jtl 1\1 lhl1t
286 THE IDEA OF NATU RAL RIGHTS ARISTOTI.E AND THE AMERICAN INDIANS 287
Again, it was not a very practicable political program. What the De the- widely diffused and was readily available for use by future generations of
sauris achieved was something different. It provided an elaborate juridical jurists and philosophers.
defense of the principle asserted with crisp simplicity in the De regia potes- There is one further point. The Spanish Dominicans were inevitably
tate, "Liberty is a right instilled in men ...." influenced by an underlying Christian attitude that animated all the
Las Casas is often considered an eccentric even by his admirers, and scholastic disciplines, an attitude that attributed a unique value to individ-
the argument we have just considered shows how intransigent he could ual persons as children of God, made "in his image." In this connection
grow in his old age; but the structure of his thought was not eccentric. they often quoted scripture, especially the first chapter of Genesis; but, by
In interweaving juridical and Thomistic arguments Las Casas was typical drawing on a juridical tradition that derived natural rights and natural law
of the whole school of Spanish scholastics, though the appeal to juristic from human rationality and free will, and by appealing to Aristotelian phi-
sources was indeed unusuaUy prominent in his work. losophy (when it suited their purpose), they also showed how a doctrine
This way of thinking, continued later by Jesuit writers like Suarez, de- of natural rights might be constructed without any overt dependence on
ci~ivdy influenced the growth of later natural rights theories. As we saw in Christian revelation.134
an earlier discussion, Michel Villey held that the teaching of the jurists was
always dependent on the work of some preceding philosopher. Specifi-
cally, there could be no jurisprudence of natural rights before Ockham had
invented a philosophy that would justify such a doctrine. But the truth is
more complicated. Gratian incorporated elements of Stoic thought about
natural Jaw into his great canonistic text, the Decretum; then Aquinas made
quite extensive use of the Decretum in his Summa theologiae; then, begin-
ning with Guido de Baisio, the canonists began to cite Aquinas in their
legal commentaries; then Ockham in tum drew on the canonists. What we
encounter in the sources is not a simple dependence of jurisprudence on
philosophy but a persistent interplay between the two disciplines from the
twelfth century onward. The work of the Spanish scholastics exemplifies a
further stage in this process of assimilation.
Current writings on the rights theories of the sixteenth-century Span-
ish authors often assume, either that they found a doctrine of natu-
ral rights in Aquinas and simply appropriated it, or that they "betrayed"
Aquinas by adopting a doctrine that was opposed to his teachings and that
was derived ultimately from Ockham's nominalism and voluntarism.
Both views seem simplistic. Ockham did not invent the concept of natural
rights; it had deeper roots in medieval jurisprudence. And the doctrine of
subjective rights did not formally contradict anything that Aquinas wrote.
It remains true, though, that the earlier Dominican master had chosen to
exclude this meaning from the several definitions of the word ius that he
presented in the Summa theologiae. The Spanish Dominicans were intent on
reviving and propagating the teachings of the greatest master of their
Order. They might have decided to follow his example in this matter also.
But, in the context of their times, they needed a doctrine of natural rights,
above all to cope with the moral probl(•ms raised by the Spanish conquests
in America. Accordingly, they chost• to assc.x:iatt• a doctrine of rights with 1.\4. I •'Ill p.•~~inK ov<'r h1....- lh,. 11 1111plt'• l••lll'" 11hn11I th1• !lt'<'t1l.ui7.-,ti11n uf wliglo1111 ltt1•11•
the Thomist prinl"iplt•s thnt tlwy proft'Slit'ti. ·nwn•sult w.1s that, wlwn nl'W ' "''"'' I hy 11. lll11rnl'nhNK. I llf I '.~111111/lfll 1frt Nfu,,11 ( 1 1111 11 ~ lurt, I 'It.ti). Hwno I• 11t11111• tti11<·u11

prublt•ms ams.• in tlw 1•nrly 11111\lnn 1•r.1, .1tlll'ory11( nalurnl ri~hls was very
•11111 of 11,...,.. I••
1,.,,.,,..• In rt'l11!11111 II• ""'t
1 ·,.,.,.,.In 111 v '" r\tl•t11tl 1• lhf' r\mrrlnm 111111"""
A11111n "
RIGHTS, COMMUNITY, ANO SoVEREICNTY 289

temal disorders and foreign enemies. National kings were coming to com-
mand greater financial resources, larger military establishments, and more
complex bureaucracies than their predecessors. Their status, moreover,
w~s commonly buttressed by revived notions of royal theocracy-some-
thing the church had frowned on since the papal reform movement of the
eleventh century-now expressed in the doctrine of a divine right of kings.
At. the same time, however, other circumstances of the age, above all the
existence of religious dissensions in various countries of Europe, stimu-
late~ a demand for some limitation of royal power-perhaps by inferior
TWELVE mag1st.rates, per_ha~s by a representative assembly of estates, perhaps by
an ancient conshtuhon.
·- .,
•' . . .... .
. . .... _,_ ..,. .The discussion o~ sovereignty was further complicated-perhaps
~nnc~e~-b~ the persistence of the medieval language of natural rights
RIGHTS, COMMUNITY, AND SOVEREIGNTY m pohtical discourse. It survived especially in the Spanish writers of the
"second scholasticism,"2 and then in Grotius, who eventually handed on
!o the modem world many of the earlier ideas that we have been explor-
ing. In the work of Vitoria and Suarez and Grotius we can trace a devel-
oping tradition of thought that sought to combine a strong theory of state

D uring the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries Europe became


divided, irremediably it seemed, into a collection of independent
sovereign states, differing in religion, often at war with one another. The
sovereign_ty ~ith a continued assertion of individual natural rights. Jn this
way of thmkmg, the natural sociability of humans led to the formation of
political societies with sovereign governments; but the sociability itself
medieval ideal of a united Christendom had indeed never found adequate was related to the needs of individual persons-especially the need of in-
institutionaJ expression. The concept of a universal empire was never more dividuals to associate with one another for self-preservation and for the
than a dream; the papal claim to universal temporal authority had always sake of a morally fulfilled life. Some authors insisted further that politi-
been contested. But there was at least a common religion that continued to c~l ~iety was created in the first place by the voluntary acts of free in-
nurture in its adherents a sense of belonging to a single Christian com- d1v1duals and that some of the rights that existed in pre-political society
monwealth. The religious cleavages of the sixteenth century created a new ~ere not and could not be yielded to a sovereign community or a sover-
situation. Christians became alienated from one another and, in Protestant eign ruler. This is the familiar style of argumentation that we find in the
countries, from their own recent past. Religious conflicts stimulated wars classic rights theories of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. It could
between the emerging national states and civil dissensions within them. be used to support a variety of political regimes. Some authors, most fa-
Given the circumstances of the age, it is understandable that much mously Hobbes, tried to use a theory of absolute natural rights to sustain a
political writing of this period dealt with international relations and with doctrine of absolute sovereign power; but the argument seemed unper-
the just conduct of wars. 1 This is certainly true of the three authors I want suasive to most of Hobbes's contemporaries and it was, I think, ultimately
finally to consider, Vitoria again, and Suarez, and Grotius; but the themes incoherent.3 ln the final outcome, modem constitutional thought evolved
in their work that will especially interest us are different ones, concerned in the way it did partly because the practice of monarchical absolutism
with internal sovereignty and individual rights in an era of expanding rnu ld not easily be reconciled with a theory of the state expressed in th<'
state power. l;inguage of natural rights. And the most influential thinkers of the ag<' did
A widespread understanding grew up in the sixteenth century that a not choose to abandon that lilngua~c·.
nation needed strong central government to protect its people against in-
l. Thi5 was especially emphal'lizl'd by J. A. r.-m111lllt•z-Santam11rla, The> Slnlc>. Wnr and 2. Early Calvinisl n..,.l~lnm·r thM•I Ii•• 0•11111h,.-11.-.l 11111n• lhr pow••r of inf~rior maKl~IMh'"
lh.m th•• natur,11 riKhl" nf l11<1ivklu.tl•
Puce. SponiJlr Polllictil ThollJtlrl in llrt Rmai1111am·r (('nmhrlill(c', 11171) nrnl 11 .( ;. f11Hh'flhown,
1 l>odrim•" of lh•-.,.·1·.c1h 11l11ul11ll•111 • 1111111 l1t• • ulu•11•11I l•ul tlll'y 11"'1 fon·•· wilh thr
Fr«nci11ro dt Vitoria zu KrWK ""' l"rlnlm (( "oluM""· 1'~11)
11mw1h ol E11lt11hh•nmrnl 11lllhul"•
- 2KK
290 TuE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS RIGHTS, COMMUNITY, AND SOVEREJGNTY 291

In this chapter I want to consider Vitoria's teaching on the individual, archical source of danger to established monarchies led him to insist on an
sovereignty, and the state, then to summarize the views of Suarez on this immediate divine origin of royal power. At the same time, he was unwill-
theme and also on some other major topics that we have pursued in the ing to abandon the Aristotelian-Thomist doctrine that the state was natural
works of Vitoria and his predecessors-the understanding of ius as sub- to man, or the widely accepted juridical thesis that a ruler's power was de-
jective right, the origin of a right to property, and the right of resistance to rived from a grant made by the people. 6 All this made for tensions and
tyranny. anomalies in his thought.
Vitoria began his On Civil Power by attacking the views of the ancient
skeptics, Epicurus and Lucretius, who had held that everything in the uni-
VITORIA. SOVEREIGNTY AND DIVINE RIGHT
verse came about by chance. Against this Vitoria presented a picture of
We have already seen how Vitoria derived a doctrine of subjective an ordered cosmos in which "every single atom exists for some use and
rights from Aquinas, Gerson, and an underlying stratum of juridical purpose."7 Then, turning at once to the situation of humans in this well-
thought. We have also seen how the Spanish master deployed his con- ordered world, he explored the origin of the state in terms of Aristotle's
cept of rights in discussing the origin of property and the status of the four causes. The final cause--the end or purpose of civil power-was to
American Indians. So far his thought seems coherent and relevant to some satisfy basic human needs. Nature had equipped all other animals with
outstanding problems of the age. But, when we tum to the issue of state some means of preserving life by flight or combat-with wings or fangs or
sovereignty and individual rights, Vitoria' s writings seem rather to illus- claws. But humans were not endowed in t.h is way; they could preserve
trate the difficulties that could arise in weaving together various disparate themselves only by forming societies for mutual support.8 The gift of lan-
strands of sixteenth-century thought. Vitoria composed his one systematic guage too, and the capacity for friendship and intellectual development all
treatise or relectio on the nature of the state near the beginning of his career marked out humans for social life. Quoting Aristotle, Vitoria accordingly
at Salamanca, before he had developed his mature theory of rights.4 Un- observed that "man is a social animal." The kind of society that most ade-
derstandably, therefore, there are tensions between the earlier and later quately responded to all human needs was a political association; hence
writings; but there are also tensions within the original work itself. the state (civitas) was the most natural community. It did not come into ex-
When Vitoria wrote On Civil Pcrwer in 1528 he was working in the istence by human invention or contrivance as something artificial, but was
aftermath of the communero revolt of 1520-21 and the German Peasants' suggested to man by nature for his safety and survival.9 Finally, a political
War of 1524. He was also writing in the early years of the Protestant refor- society could cohere only if it were ordered by some ruling power; so the
mation, which Vitoria evidently saw as an antinomian movement threat- end of civil power was the same as that of the commonwealth itself, to pro-
ening all existing political order. "There have been some writers even vide for the urgent needs of human life.
among those who call themselves Christians," he wrote, "who have d enied Vitoria next wrote that the efficient cause of civil power was God, for if
that kingly power or any kind of rule by a single person comes from God, Cod created men with a need and inclination to live in political society
affirming that all sovereigns, generals and princes are tyrants and robbers under a ruling power, then God must be seen as the efficient cause of both
of human Iiberty."5 Of course this was far removed from anything that the society and the power. 10 The material cause of civil power was the com-
Luther actually taught; but Vitoria's perception of a new heretical and an- monwealth itself, the political community. Civil power must originally
have inhered in the whole community because, when men first came to-
4. "On Civil Power," in A. Pagden and J. Lawrance, eds ., Francisco dt Vitoria. PoliIlea/ Writ·
ings (Cambridge, 1991), 1-44; "De potestatecivile," in T. Urdanoz, Obras dt Fmncisco dt Vitoria 6. The key text of Roman law is Dig. 1.4.1 " What has pleased the prince has the force o f
{Madrid, 1960). 149-95. Urdanoz gives a Latin text with Spanish translation. In the following l.1w because ... the people conferred on him all its authority and power.h There are ~imllar
notes on this work I have given references to Lawrance 's excellent translation since it is based tt-xts al Cod. 1.17.1.7 and Inst . 1.2. 6.
on the best and most complete early manuscript (MS Palencia 13). The printed editio ns have 7. 0 11 Ci vil Pouw. 2, Poliliral Wrllit1J{~. 6; 0 1'ra1', IS4.
many readings different from the Palencia MS a nd omit some key phra~. The changes we re II. Ibid., 3, Polilical Wrilit11C'· 7; <>lira, . I 'i4 Vllo rl11 was quoting here directly from I .ad11n·
probably made for the most part by Vitoria's posthumous edito rs . Somt' pl"l'Sumably rt'flcct Ii""· l~ opificio dei, 2.2- 4 aml :l 1 7
Vitoria's own second thoughts. Rcfl'rt'JIC'f'S all' givf'n first l o thf' numht'rt'd parag rap hs tha t <I. Ibid .• 5, I'oli timl Wrr/1111(11, II; f l/1ta•. I '"7
are the same in the LawrancP and Urd11n111: 1>dition~. tht·n lo pag~ in <'i1d1 vt•rsino . I havc> aliw IC!. lhid ., 6, l'nlilwul Wr/111111•. Ill. I l/1111•. I~ '1•1 ··~·I •' IR" I >t•ul' llt"-"<'!lllit11h•m t~t11111 nh111r
u!lt'd Lawranet>'s trnnRlntinn of Vlln rl""s C>11 111~ /',111•·111f //1,. C/111rd1. ln.-lln.1ll11m•m h11minlh1111 1IC'1llt. 111 111111 In ••" ll'l•t.. "' """ """ puh•11l11IC' "'K''nh• drK••n• non
5. 011 Ci11i/ 1'11wt"r. ?, 1'11/ilin1IW11lm.11~. 11. 11/11 11•. ll~ I ('"'""'"'· hn1· l1,.,11m I,..,, 1111.-11111111•11111111111,.f.,1 u• '"" ....., ..., •·
292 THE I DEA OF NATURAL RIG HTS RIGHTS, COMMUNITY, AND SoVEREIGNTY 293

gether in a civic assembly, there was no reason why one individual rather magistrates, to whom the community delegated its powers, had the
than another should rule over all, especially since each one had a natural same authority as the community itself. 1s At this point Vitoria launched
right of self-defense.11 Most of the difficulties in Vitoria's argument arose in his attack on the contemporary apostates from the church who called
this part of his text, and I will return to a more detailed consideration of themselves Christians but who, "corrupted by their vicious ambitions
it. But we may first note that, to complete the Aristotelian framework of and pride," maintained that all kingly power was a form of tyranny. Vi-
his argument, Vitoria wrote that the formal cause of civil power was toria replied by introducing his own version of a divine right theory.
the form of government adopted by a community. Vitoria mentioned here In opposition to the Protestant error (as he perceived it), he declared
Aristotle's three basic types of government-monarchy, aristocracy, and that "sovereigns have their power by natural and divine law, not from
democracy-and expressed a clear preference for monarchy.12 the commonwealth or from men."16 To support this view he quoted first
Let us return to the commonwealth as "material cause" of civil power. the Old Testament. "In the Books of Kings, some kings are created by God
Vitoria discussed here both the inherence of ruling power in the commu- himself and others are elected at his command." Then he added sev-
nity and its exercise by a ruler; and he insisted that both the community's eral texts of St. Paul that suggested a divine origin for a ruler's power:
power and the ruler's were of divine origin. He first proved thi~ by pr~­ "(T)here is no power but of God" (Rom. 13.1); "Whosoever resisteth the
senting, with a new emphasis, an argument that had been mentioned m power resisteth the ordinance of God" (Rom. 13.2); "For he is a minister
passing by Almain. It was forbidden by divine law, in one of the Ten Com- of God ... ." (Rom. 13.4).'7 Vitoria then summed up his preceding argu-
mandments, for an individual to kill a fellow man; but the commonwealth, ment in this way.
unlike its individual members, did have the authority to inflict capital pun-
Let us conclude by leaving these matters and go back to clarify a point
ishment. No human law could override a divine command; therefore this I mentioned before, namely that royal power is not from the commonwealth,
authority must have been granted by divine law. 13 Vitoria also repeated but from God himself, as Catholic theologians believe. It is apparent that
here another argument of Almain. Every man had a " power and right" of even though sovereigns are set up by the commonwealth, royal power
self-defense by natural law; therefore the commonwealth, which was also derives immediately from God. For example, the pope is elected and
one body, should have the same right. (Vitoria here applied to the political crowned by the Church, but nevertheless papal power does not come
commonwealth the words of Paul about the early church, "We being many from the Church, but from God himself. In the same way, the power
are one body, and every one member one of another." ) Just as an individual of the sovereign clearly comes immediately from God himself, even
could sacrifice a limb for the sake of the whole body, so too the com- though kings are created by the commonwealth. That is to say, the
monwealth could "compel and coerce" its individual members, and just as commonwealth does not transfer to the sovereign its power (potestas),
individuals could not give up their right of self-defense, so too the com- but simply its own authority (auctoritas); there is no question of two
separate powers, one belonging to the sovereign and the other to the
monwealth could not deprive itself of its own inherent power.••
community.•a
When Vitoria turned to the power of rulers, he noted that the multi-
tude who formed a commonwealth could not conveniently exercise its This is a dense and difficult passage. It is not only hard to understand
own power and had to entrust it to one man or several. These rulers and in itself; also the propositions set out here in such an unqualified and confi-
dent fashion seem contradicted by Vitoria himself at other points in his
11. Ibid,. 7, Politico/ Writings, 11; 01'ras, 159. HSi enim priusquam in civitatem homines con· writings, both within the text of On Civil Power and elsewhere. An initiill
venirent, nemo erat aliis superior, non est a liqua ratio cur in ipso coetu, seu conventu civili,
quisque sibi super alios potestatem vendicaret; maxime cum quilibet ho m o iure naturali
difficulty arises out of the suggestion that a king's power came directly
habeat potestatem et ius defendendi se. H

12. Ibid., J0-11, Political Writings. 18-21; Obras, 165-67. Occasionally Vitoria wrote favor· 15. Ibid., 7, Political Wrilinxs. 12, "Now although this power and authority Wt' ~pt·.1k 11f
ably of mixed government in which monarchy was romb_ined with oth~r e~ements. Here he h.-long.~ fir.;t of all and ptr se lo the .-ommonw('alth i~lf. the same authority Ix-long." lo nil...,.
wrote (P:;litical Writings, 21) that the Spanish government itself was or this kmd. .111.t m<1gistrates lo whom the commnnwt•.i llh ha" tl<'lrgatC'd its powers." Urdancl7. (Obr11~. 1"4'1)
IJ. Ibid., 7, Political Writings, 11; Obr11s, 160. #Ite m ho minem occidere t'SI iure divino pm· t:ivt•s a different n•ading. Rut l>c•th v..r"i1111• rrfl'r to rult•r.i " to whom lht' rommt1nw C'11lth ""'"
hibitum, ut patet in praeceptis Dt-calogi. f.rgo auctorila:l occidt'ndi uportet quod ~it_a iu": ,f,•l1•gatt•d its powrr!<."
divino. Sed respub\ica, ut ex usu el C'On~ut>lmlin(' cum1tl'll, hahl't au<"torll'111•m ocridNuh In. !hid., II, l'ttlitiml W111i11g•• ... 14. I II•'''"· I r1I· "7. •. 1lln• wg1~ l'liam ,1 lurt' cllvlnu t'111111
hominem. Ergo habet a iure divino: · 111.>li h.•ltt•n• P'' " '"t.,h•m , rl non •I• IJ'.,. 1r1'11hlh • . •nt 1•1111•11• 11h h11mlnlh11• "
14. Ibid.• 7 . w.1•11t1ti<'11I Writi".'I"· II. 1•1; Clt1111". '""· ''"' ("llw .... , Al I''''"'· l!i'I KiYc'!l '1 17 lhi<I , H. f'Hlillu1/ W'lllllJI•. t'I Ito. I 111111• lro) ''I
~hortl'r re01.tin~ omilllnK lhr n·lrrru.-•• 111 I '11111 ) IH lhiol . II. l'Hlll/1 11/ W'lllllit•. ltl, 1111111• 1114
294 THE IDEA OF NATURAL R IGHTS R IGHTS, COMM UNITY, ANO SoVEltElCNTY 295

from God in the same way that a pope's did. 19 ln spite of Vitoria's phrase, The texts of Vitoria's On Civil Power are ambivalent then. His later
"as Catholic theologians believe," this view went against the prevailing writings seem more dear and consistent, but only because he tacitly
current of Catholic thought. Defenders of the papacy more commonly dis- abandoned the idea of a direct divine origjn of a ruler's power, without.
tinguished between ecclesiastical and secular government in order to em- however, ever recanting his earlier view. In Vitoria's first relectio on ec-
phasize the unique status of the pope as wielder of a divinely ordained au- clesiastical power (De potestate ecclesiastica), he wrote, "[A)ll the power
thority. of secu]ar princes comes from the community," and "lT)he power of
Moreover, it is hard to sustain Vitoria's position within the context of princes comes wholly from the commonwealth."2S Vitoria seems to have
his own argument. The view that a community merely authorized an indi- forgotten his earlier distinction between a transfer of power and a grant
vidual to occupy an office whose power came "immediately" from God of authority. The focus of his interest had shifted. In writing about the
implied that this power did not inhere in the community itself. But there church he was concerned to contrast the power of secular princes with that
was no consistency in Vitoria's use of the words potestas and auctoritas.20 of ecclesiastical prelates, whose offices really were directly instituted by
A little earlier Vitoria had written that "the commonwealth has power by Christ in a way different from those of temporal rulers, as Vitoria now
divine law" and that the power of a ruler was "none other than the com- acknowledged.
monwealth's power administered through the sovereign."21 This raises There was also another change of doctrine in Vitoria's later teaching
another problem. If power did originally inhere in the whole common- about the origin of the state. In On Civil Power, political society was "not a
wealth, and if the commonwealth did not transfer its power to the ruler, human invention or contrivance"; it was rather "implanted by nature
as Vitoria stated in the passage quoted above, than it would seem that in man" and endowed with a power conferred by God. But, in his com-
sovereignty remained fundamentally with the political community. This mentary on Aquinas, Vitoria envisaged separate individuals in a state of
view was quite commonly held in Vitoria's day, especially in the schools nature, each already endowed with a right of dominion, coming together
of Paris at the time when he studied there. It carried the implication that voluntarily to make a division of property. They could do this either by en-
the whole community was always greater than the ruler it established. tering into mutual agreements or by electing a ruler to make the division.21>
But Vitoria rejected this view. Instead, he wrote that a king was above There was no suggestion here of any divine right implanted in the com-
the commonwealth, "not only above any individual but above all the munity or in the ruler; the original right inhered in the individuals who
citizens together," and that there could be no appeal against the king to came together. Again, in the earlier work Vitoria argued that the power of
the commonwealth.22 In the same vein Vitoria wrote, citing scripture, that a commonwealth could not be derived from positive law because the com·
kings were not "ministers of the commonwealth" but "ministers of God.''D monwealth had to exist before any such law could be enacted.27 But in the
And yet, at still another point in On Civil Power he compared a monarch to De lndis he wrote that, although man was a civil animal, nevertheless civil
the commonwealth's "appointed agent."2 4 power "was not instituted by nature but by law."21
In his commentary on Aquinas, instead of basing a theory of sov-
t.•reignty on divine right, Vitoria opted for one of the standard secular
19. In the text given by Urdanoz the parallel between the origin of royal and papal powec
was omitted. 11\e later comments of Vitoria in his Rtltctio dt potrstatt ecclrsiastica given below arguments in support of strong monarchy, the d octrine that a people alien-1
suggest that he changed his mind on this point. .1ted its own ruling power in the act of constituting a ruler. Vitoria argued
20. In the passage quoted in the text above he asserted that the community did_~ot here that once a commonwealth had given its power to a king it could not
transfer power to the ruler but only authority. But a little earlier in the same work (Polrticol
Writings, 12) Vitoria wrote that Hauthoritybelongs to rulers and magistrates to whom the com-
monwealth has delegated its powers. ..." (emphasis added). For various other usages of • u!<sed this same point he held the people responsible prt'Cisdy because the comm1111i1y ,..
auctoritas and potrst/IS see Political Writings, 18, 50, 53. t.1inl'd its o wn jurisdiction and so could correct an erring ruler. Vitoria mel't'ly wmll' th11t tlw
21. On Civil Por«r, 8, Political Writings, 14; Obras, 162. Again the wording in the Obras text t""'lflle ought to have elected a ju11t rul<'r in thl' first placl'.
is different, but to the same effect. " Ergo potuit commendari potestas quae eadem est quae 2"i. O n tl1r Pori!t'r of lhr C1111rd1. 2 ..1, 2.7. f'1•lil in1f Wrilinxs. 103, 107; Obrns, :l20, :l2"i. 111 lhr
reipublicae." The anomalies in Vitoria's thought were noted by Oecke~; he found Vitoria's ·u-.·rn1d l<'xl Vitoria argued th.it 114•n1IM prlnc-.•11 n111ltl not t.ikl' away the lilX'rtiPll nf th1• dmrd1
various assertions to be baskally incompatible with one another (Ctm:h11xkt1I, 285). l•1-.·.uoil4.' tht>y wt•re ~ranlt·d hy 1111' wholt• ( luholt•lll 1·u1111111111wt•alth. I It> 11t't'nl8tu1u.•um1•. h11
22. On Civil Por«r, 14, Political WritinX'· 30-31; Olm1s, 179-80. 1111• p urpost• of thi~ ;u-gurnrnt, th111" rulro I• hu1111tl hy tlw l11w of !ht• t'o mm11nlty.
23. Ibid., 8, Political WritinXf. 17; Obros. IM."... prindp<"' IJci mm w ipuhlira<' ministro:o 2<•. f)r j11~tilr11. 2.2'1r t•) I. r•I 11.,,,,,11 ... 1 11111111ml11t11" :17K (""' 11hovr, 2.'iK, n 1f>1m1I 1h4)
appellat (scriptura)." . }'! I llr I ·;111//'t111~·r. 7, f't1/lll1~( W11t11111•. I I fl l1111ttr1l l11 I Jt•m•)
24. Ibid., 12. Polilin1/ Wrili11.~~. 21. ' Jl14• rhr111M• h• 11111l1h..l l11<1/rriu. Vllorl" wu MKUlllK lwn• 7K I Ir lmf,.. ' "' l'nl'l\111111111'1111.,, l'1•11ttt111. J J. \"/ . •· 111111 lt11111•111111hlr11 l'<'ll l1•1tr, """II
that a ~·pl1• niulil l11wf11lly ht• punl•h<'•I Im 1111 uffrnM• 111 ti" l.hlK Whr11 i\lm11in ""' ' tli" '"'"...,..
296 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIG HTS RIGHTS, COMMUNITY, AND SOVEREIG NTY 297

retain that power for itself, "otherwise it has not given it."29 He still, how- context that was mainly concerned with the individual's duty of self-
ever, maintained that the community could depose a tyrannical king by preservation. He also presented here a detailed account of the right of
exercising its inherent right of self-defense: "{E]ven if the commonwealth self-defense and of the manner in which it couJd properly be exercised.
has given away its authority it keeps its natural right to defend itself." 30 In the De homicidio, Vitoria offered an extended defense of Aquinas's
I can see no way of explaining the inconsistencies in Vitoria's writ- doctrine that a natural inclination was indicative of a preceptive natural
ings except to assume that the author changed his mjnd about the origin law where rational creatures were concemed.32 The inclination of all crea-
and nature of the state during the 1530s. Perhaps he came to see that the tures to preserve their own being indicated that, for humans, there existed
Lutheran and Anglican doctrines of the monarch as a kind of prince- a natural law prorubiting suicide.33 Also, suicide was contrary to the scrip-
prelate, head of the church as well as of the secular commonwealth, was a tural command, 'Thou shalt not kill," and to the scriptural injunction that
greater source of danger to traditional Catholic order than the threat of an- a man should love himself as well as his neighbor.34 Finally a man was not
archy that he had at first perceived. This was strikingly illustrated in 1534 the master of his own life in the same way that he was an owner of external
when, in order to validate the divorce of King Henry VIII from the Spanish goods. If he killed his own horse or burned down his own house he did no
princess Catherine of Aragon, the English parliament declared that the one a n injury. But, as regards human life, "Only God is lord of life and
king was "the only Supreme Head in earth of the Church of England." death." 35 So a person who killed himself did an injury to God.
Another set of problems, especially relevant for understanding Vi- On the way to this conclusion Vitoria raised various objections. One
toria's thought on natural rights, concerns the relationship between in- of them suggested that a man's inclination to preserve his life would con·
dividual, community, and government once a political society had been flict with his duty to prefer the common good to his own private good.
established. The descriptions of the state that we have mentioned so far But Vitoria denied here that man was by nature inclined to love his own
seem essentially holistic, without any concern for individual rights. The good more than the good of the community. On the contrary, he wrot<'
right of self-defense was mentioned only as a metaphor to emphasize that, "man, whom God has made part of the commonwealth, is inclined by
the organic unity of the state. Individual members of the commonwealth nature more to the common good than the private."36 He then presented
were compared to limbs of a human body that could be sacrificed to pre- again his organic image of the state in which individuals were compared
serve the well-being of the whole. The implications of the argument seem to members of a human body, existing not for themselves alone but for th<'
starkly absolutist. Yet in other contexts, as in the De Indis, Vitoria devel- sake of the whole. According to divine and natural law, Vitoria wrote,
oped an overt doctrine of natural rights inhering in individuals, especially it was licit to kill a man harmful to the state since a single member could
the right of self-defense.31 Like Gerson he apparently wanted to uphold be cut off for the good of the whole body.37 Returning to his argument on
both individual rights and community values; but in the Spanish thinker suicide, Vitoria concluded that a person who killed himself injured thl·
the two sides of the argument were developed separately and not formally commonwealth as well as God. "One who kills himself takes away from
related to one another. the commonwealth what is its own." 38
For a good illustration of the coexistence of the two lines of thought, Vitoria's argument in the De homicidio points to another unresolved
corporatist and individualist, in Vitoria's work we can tum to his Relectio tension in his thought, for in the commentary on Aquinas, written a littll•
de homicidio (On Homicide), which in fact was mainly about suicide. In this later, he observed that sinful man was more inclined to pursue his own
work Vitoria again discussed the organic structure of the state, but in a
32. Vitoria was arguing against the Lutherans who s harply separated nature i\ncl grim·
.incl denied to unaided human nature any capacity for rig hteous behavior. See Dt' homic·illic•, 2,
29. V. Beltran de Heredia, ed., Comment1ma al Tratado dt la ley: (In 1-11, QQ.9a-108J; frag· 0/lrns, 1090.
mmtos th meccion~ (Madrid, 1952). On 1.2ae.105. l , 81, "Ad argumentum , respublica facit 33. Dt homicidio, 10, Obras, 1106..
regem: Ergo est supra regem, nego consequentiam; quia s i dedit suam potestatem regi, non 34. Ibid ., 1106, 1112. ln Dt ltllll't'rantia, 1, Obras, 1007, Vitoria cited Ma tthe w 22.:\Q, "Thou
retinuit illam sibi, alias non dedit" Vitoria repeated here his argument that the king should be .~h.1 ltlove thy neighbor as thyllelL"
greater than an the citizens together. not just great~ than each individual. .1 5. CH ho111iddio, 23, Ohrtt<, 11 IA .. Nnn ,.,.1 nut.-m ita d ominus aut corpuriii a ut vilnc• pru
30. Ibid., l .2ae.105.2, 82. pri.w. Est Pnim ~olull I >ru,; 1lomlnuo• vlt11r c•t mnrll,;."
31. Vitoria maintained that there was a natural right of !l('H-deft>nSf" t'Vt'n again~t an evil .16. lhid ., 10, ( l/lra.•, 11 Cl.1
pope. Dt poleslalt papat rt roncilii, 2.'l, <lhra~. 487, " (.)uia vim v i W!"'llc•n• llo•t iun• naturali . . . .'7. Ibid ., IR; t>l•r1u, 11111; VII nth• l11•l•lr.I. howrvn, lhnl lhl" pc•w1•r brlnn~rtl only tu
no n q•Jod aliquid pcis.wt ..,.,... lu.11·- P"I'""· "''•I pc•r moclum olrlf'm•lcml.'t l ·ullihc•I ••nlm c'l'I in~ puhlk mnKl!'lmt..,.. nnl '"I" l1111lt1 l111llvhlmll11
ad n'\'li.~tt>ndum inluriftf' rt lmprcli••ncl11111 clrlr111lr11.t111111111r " U1 ihl<I . 77, I l/11110, 111 J, .. 1'1"11•tttl•111' hlll 1111lr11 "rrp11h1l,·11 c1111Ml N1111111 l'!ll ..
298 THE I DEA OF NATURAi. RIGHTS RIGHTS, COMMUNrTY, AND S0VER£1GNTY 299

good than the common good. Commenting on this anomaly, Deckers sug- self-defense always existed and could not be alienated a man might choose
gested that, arguing as a theologian in the De homicidio rather than as a not to exercise the right he possessed in his own life. He could not deliber-
moral philosopher, Vitoria rejected the idea of an inclination to one's own ately kill himself, for that would be an injustice to God, "the supreme lord
good.JIJ But this is not really true. For Vitoria, suicide was not only harmful of life"; but it was sometimes permissible and even laudable for him to set
to the commonwealth but also a sin against charity, the love that a man aside his own right in his life and to accept death for the sake of another.43
owed to himself. This could imply a corresponding right to defend one's Vitoria presented this as a controversial doctrine. Many, he wrote, held that
own life. And in fact, in the De homicidio, the argument for a community's a private individual could not relinquish the duty to preserve his own
power over its members was accompanied by a particularly careful and life.« But Vitoria thought the opposite view more probable. Jesus did not
nuanced treatment of the individual right of self-defense. defend himself against the Jews and gentiles who condemned him un-
Vitoria was quite clear about the existence of this right. A man justly. Christian martyrs had accepted death voluntarily even when they
could even kill in self-defense and, if he did so, he was exercising an au- could have resisted.6 Vitoria argued further that, if two men were in a stale
thority derived from God through natural law.40 But Vitoria also had to of extreme need, one could give up his bread to save the life of the other. A
deal with a related set of problems common to the casuists of his age. Self- shipwrecked sailor could abandon the plank he clung to so that his king's
preservation was commonly seen as a precept of natural law and so as a life could be saved or, indeed, to save any friend or companion.% A man
duty owed to God; but Christian scripture extolled the act of sacrificing could even sacrifice h is life to save an enemy. A person attacked by a robber
one's life for another as supremely virtuous.•1 Moreover, self-preservation could certainly kill his assailant in self-defense; but he would act more
as an obligation, a duty owed to God, would seem to exclude rather than perfectly if he yielded his own life rather than send the thief to eternal
imply a right of self-defense if a right were seen as defining an area of per- damnation. In many cases, Vitoria wrote, a man could licitly preserve his
mitted conduct where an individual was free to act or not act. Some au- life and yet was not bound to do so.47 Here again a right, including the right
thors, like Henry of Ghent whose work we considered earlier, simply of self-defense, conferred a certain freedom of choice on the right-holder.
assumed that there was a class of rights that were also duties, rights that In Vitoria's De homicidio we encounter both a strongly organic theory
had to be exercised in case of necessity. Vitoria offered a more subtle solu- of the state (as in the De potestate civili) and a strong theory of individual
tion. He addressed these problems by distinguishing between God's right rights (as in the De Jndis); but the two themes were not related to one an-
and a person's own right in his life, and between the possession of a right other as aspects o f a coherent theory of the state. (To present a theory of the
and the manner of its exercise. state was of course not the purpose of the De homicidio). To understand
Although, as was said, man is not the master of his body or his life as he
how the two themes could coexist in Vitoria's work without his show in~
is of other things, nevertheless he does have something of mastery and any awareness of a p otential conflict between them we need to remember
right in his own life, so that if anyone harms his body he not onJy does an that, although the metaphor of the community as an organic whole was
injury to God, who is the supreme lord of life, but also to the individual very common in medieval thought, it was only a metaphor and was com·
man himself.<Z monly understood to be so. Aquinas carefully explained this, as we nokd
in discussing Gerson, when he wrote that the image of the church a~ a
This right of a man in himself was a right understood as Vitoria under- mystical body referred to "a resemblance . . . not an exact corresponde nn·
stood the term elsewhere-it defined a zone of human autonomy, an area or identity."~ Following Aquinas, Vitoria emphasized the same point in
of licit behavior, where a man could act as he chose. Although a right of
his second relectio on ecclesiastical power.
39. Gertchtigkeit, 58-62. "Theologisch ist d ie Annahme eine m clinatio ad bonl4m proprium
absurd" (58). In the Dt homicidio Vitoria asserted o nly that the inclination to one's own good 43. Ibid.. 24; Obras, 1119-20, " Hoc ergo iu s quod homo habet in proprium rnrpu"· poh'!Ot
was less than the inclination lo the common good. homo laudab iliter dimitlen> rt pt'rclc•n•, qu;tmvi~ habeat iu s se de£t'ndendi, l'I ~ic p 11tirnlrr
40. Ibid., 11, Obra.s, 1108. fr•rrt• morlC'm.''
41. Ibid., 24, Obra.s, 1121. Vitoria cited here John 15. 13, "G reater lovt' than this hath no 44. Ibid., 2.'i, 0/1ra.• , I 121.
man, that he lay d own his life for his friMld.'' 4fi . lhid .. 24. ()/1rn.<. 11 l'l.
42. Ibid ., 24, O bras, 1119, "Pro quot'l'I cnnllideranJum '(UO.I lkt'I (ut tlidum t'SI) homo nc>n 4l>. Ibid .. 2.'i, Cll1tu:., 1122 1 I
s it dominus sui corporill, aul viliw .!" lilt' llin1t ali11rum n•rum. tanwn .1lit111i.t .tu minii l'I iuri" 47 lhirl .. 24. c >/rr11~. 11 IH l'I
habet in vii.a llllil.• rnti111w n1h'" 1111i .,,,..,., in 1·or1><m• 111111 ,..,111111 f.u·il I '),•11, 'I"' ··~I ~llflD.'.IU!lo'.i 4K /\hov1•, 21111 'JU 1'1>1 fl •111111"1 11111111111•111 In I>.• •,.,,., M·•· 11 I l.u11Ht1111, l 111lrli1111 l1111tt)lltl
dominu.~ vita<>, 11t'<i 1•tlam lp~I homlni prlv11to. Ina ml nm ·· 11tj:.,.1 rml/1 t ·,.,,,,,,., S/l<llll (t hh•11I l'lfl II. It
300 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS RIGHTS, COMMUNITY, AND SoVEREIGNTY 301

Furthermore, the parts of a natural body are disposed entirely for the St. Thomas .. . says that all things are common in extreme necessity. If,
good of the whole, whereas the individual members of the church are then, they are common I have a right to them.55
for God and for themselves alone; the good of a private man is not even
principally, let alone entirely, ordained for the good of the whole com- Vitoria even wrote that, in order to assert their right, persons in extreme
munity.49 need could kill the rich who withheld food from them.56
In his later writings Vitoria offered all these remarks about particular
Commenting directly on Aquinas, Vitoria wrote that a human legislator,
rights outside the framework of his original theory of the state. One could
whether civil or ecclesiastical, was not "master of the whole man as one is
master of a horse." The ruler could not take the life of an innocent person; i wish that he had presented his major discussion on political theory near
anJ, generally, a human law did not oblige if obedience to it entailed I the end of his career at Salamanca instead of in his first relectio. He might
then have provided all the clarifications and qualifications that could have
death for the individual.50
accommodated his later insights within a coherent doctrine of sovereignty,
In many scattered contexts Vitoria referred to rights that persisted
community, and natural rights. As it is, we have a kind of divine right
after the institution of the state. There were property rights for instance.
theory of government combined with an Aristotelian conception of the
"[I)t would be tyrannical to deprive men of what is theirs by natural
state, and an organic theory of the state accompanied by frequent refer-
right," Vitoria wrote.s1 And, again, "[T]he king of Spain cannot take goods
ences to individual rights. For a more systematic treatment of these themes
from his subjects and merchants."52 Vitoria also mentioned a right to marry
we may turn to one of Vitoria's great successors in the school of Sala-
freely. It might seem, he wrote, that any right derived from a contract
manca, Francisco Suarez (1548-1617).
would be subject to the authority of the state; but in fact neither the state
nor the church could compel an unwilling couple to marry.53 Sometimes
rights could be exercised against the positive law of the state. Like Henry S U AREZ, SOVEREIGNTY AND NATURAL RIGHTS
of Ghent centuries earlier, Vitoria argued that a criminal condemned to
ln the seventeenth century Suarez was probably the most widely read
death ought to escape if he could. And if he were condemned to death by
and influential of all the masters of the Spanish "second scholasticism." As
starvation he should nevertheless take any food that was offered to him.54
a youth he had a reputation as a slow learner (like Aquinas); but eventu-
In discussing theft, Vitoria reiterated the o!J canonistic argument that in
ally his patient and powerful mind produced an impressive array of works
extreme necessity all things were common. In rather typical fashion he
that provide, besides Suarez' own distinctive views, an encyclopedic over-
quoted Aquinas here but grafted on to Aquinas's text a language of rights
view of late medieval scholastic thought.57 By the time Suarez wrote, it
that Thomas himself had not employed.
was becoming evident that the revived theories of royal theocracy could
threaten the traditional autonomy of the Catholic church. Unlike Vitoria,
49. On the POUla' oftMChurch, 15, Polilict1l Writings, 119; Obras, 365. therefore, Suarez wanted to formulate a theory of sovereignty and the state
SO. De fortitudine, 2.2ae.125.4, in Beltran de Heredia, Commentarios 5:363-64 ''. .. non est that was based solely on human will and consent, without any direct
dominus totius hominis sicut est dominus equi, nam sine culpa non potest me interficere; et divine grant of power to the ruler. In the same year that he published his
ideo non potest talem Iegem condere quae sit obligatoria circumstantia mortis." But Vitoria
conceded here that a citizen could sometimes be required to defend the commonwealth at the 55. De j11slitin, 2.2ae.66.8, 341, " .. . et ita videtur dicere hie sanctus Thomas, qu ia didt
cost of his own life. HQuia miles tenetur ire ad bellum quando vocatur a rege, non obstante c1m>d omnia sunt communia in extrema necessitate. Si ergo sunt communia, habeo jus ad ilia. H

rerta morte" (368). 56. Ibid., 2.2ae.118.4, Commentarios 5:264-65, "Quia illi qui sunt in extrema ne«>ssit,.tt•
51. Dt justitia, 2.2a.e , 66.l, Commentarios 3: 323, " Hoc dico propter reges qui non possunt po.~sunt licite capere a divitibus et eos interficere si nollent dare, quia habe.nt jus ad ilia in tali
sine caus:a rationabili appropriare aliquod thesaurum . .. quia esset tyrannicum privare m-<essitate. Vitoria here was following a'! opinion of Cajetanus.
H

homines de illo quod est de jure naturali.n Vitoria here was referring to the right of the first oc· 57. Two important earlier works are H. Rommen, Dit Stnatslthrt drs Frn11z S1111rr.
cupant of a "5 nullius. Elsewhere he wrote that a ruler was granted gu~rnatio (government), ( M iin <·h en-Gladbach, 1926) and L. R<'C11!1<'n.• Sic-hes, La filosofia dtl dt'rtcho dt Fr11ncis.·" S11an'z
not dominium ruum (ownership). See Tratado dt Ia fry, 1.2ae.105.2, 83. f M<'ldm City, 1947). 11ll' be!ll tn•atm1•nls c>f Suan•7.' political theory arc G . Jar lot, " I A.,. ictcot\•
52. De justicia, 2.2ae.66.8, 344. politiqurs de Suan-7. rt Ir fl(l11Ve>ir """olu,'· Arclrir't'" tfr 11/rilosophir IR (194Q): 64- 107, J. r' Som
53. Dt matrimonio, 7, Obras, 893-94. Vitoria held that a forced marriage would frustrate nwTVilll'. " From Su.1re7. lo r:ilnll'r A l<r'*t'J'llll~111 :· I /i,.tc1rirnl foum11/ 25 (191l2)525-4tl, "ml I< .
the principal end of matrimony, the fl'aring of c·hildl"l'fl, which rt'<)uin•d a relationship of Wih•nius, Tiw ,c;,,.-;11( 11111/ /'11/ltini/ / /1,.,11V1•f I 111111h111 .'lwrr~.t (I ld.~inki, I %3). For t>io~raphy ,..._.
mutual love. I 11. l'khh•r, Mtm 11/ Sr"'"'· 1'11111.-1• .'111111r: (N"w Yt•t~ . 1'142) l\mplt• hlh! i0Kr.1phk 111 unit.,.""'
54. Dt homiridio, 28, Obrn~. 1121. p1e1vidc•cl in !IN' 1•11llh1n ol tlw I It /r.~fl1110 llelC11l h1•l"w (11 '\•I)
302 """fttE IDEA O F NATURAL RIGHTS
RIGHTS, COMMUNITY, AND SoVEREJCNTY 303

massive De lege ac deo legislatore (On I.Aw and God the Lawgiver), Suarez also passage of the Summa theologiae where Aquinas defined ius as "the object
wrote a Defensio fidei catholicae that was directed specifically against the of justice" and "the just thing itself."60
divine right theories of King James l of England. For us it is important that So far we seem to be moving entirely in a world of Thomist thought.
Suarez' theory of the state was set in a broad-ranging discourse on natural Jus is something objective, "the just and fair," or what is justly due to som~
rights, natural Jaw, liberty, the right to property, and the origin of political one. But then the argument took a different tum. Suarez next wrote:
societies.
As is usually the case with major political thinkers, modem scholars According to the latter and strict signification of ius, it is customary to
disagree about various aspects of Suarez' thought. Historians of philoso- call ius properly a certain moral faculty that anyone has either regarding
his own thing or something due to him; and so the owner of a thing is
phy argue about whether he created a distinctively Suarezian metaphysics
said lo have a right in the thing (ius in re) and a workman is said to have
or remained faithful to the broad principles of Aquinas' s philosophy. a right to his wage (ius ad rem). . . .61
(Villey, characteristically, held that Suarez' teaching was corrupted by "the
poison of Ockham.") Suarez has been called a voluntarist and a rationalist, By associating the juridical language of ius in re and ius ad rem with
an organicist and an individualist, an absolutist and a constitutionalist. 58 Aquinas's definitions, Suarez arrived at a subjective understanding of ius
The Spanish scholar himself did not think it necessary to choose between as a moral faculty inhering in a right-holder. Suarez did not present this as
these alternatives; rather he sought to balance them against one another an alternative definition, different from that of Aquinas. He seems to have
in an inclusive synthesis. In the sphere of thought that concerns us, the assumed that this is what Aquinas meant all along.
history of natural rights theories, Suarez can best be understood as a Suarez went on to give a similar reinterpretation of Ulpian's welJ-
continuator of the line of thought that we have traced from the twelfth- known definition of justice as a virtue that " renders to each his right."
century canonists onward. Like Vitoria and Las Casas, Suarez wanted to Here again Suarez took the word "right'' (ius) to refer to a legal claim right
show how an originally juridical tradition of rights thinking (a tradition (actio) understood as a moral faculty. The association of ius and actio is
Suarez knew well), that had been transmitted by theologians like Ockham found in classical law, but neither term was understood as a moral faculty,
and Gerson, could be harmonized with a Thomist doctrine of natural law. and this is certainly not what Ulpian had in mind in his famous text.62
The initial dependence of Suarez on Aquinas is evident in the Spanish Finally Suarez turned to the second etymology that derived ius from
scholar's fundamental discussion on the various meanings of the word ius. iubendo (commanding). In this sense, he wrote, ius meant the same as lex
Suarez began by proposing two etymologies. lus could be derived from (law) because law was a form of command. This meaning was often used
either iubendo (commanding) or iustitia (justice). (A third possible deriva- by the jurists, Suarez noted, as when they distinguished between igno-
tion from iuxta was brushed aside as unacceptable.59) Pursuing first the rance of fact and ignorance of law (ignorantia iuris).&3
derivation from iustitia Suarez wrote that, in this sense of the word, ius To a modem reader it will seem evident that Suarez gave three defini-
meant the same as "the just and fair, that is the object of justice." He added tions-the original Thomist meaning, "the just" or "the object of justice";
that the word "justice" itself could have two meanings. It could refer gen- his own understanding of ius as a moral faculty or subjective right; and fi-
erally to any virtue; but, taken more strictly, it indicated the particular nally ius as meaning law. But Suarez himself wrote that he would give only
virtue that rendered to each his own. Similarly, the word ius, taken in a
strict sense, signified what was justly due to anyone. Suarez cited here a 60. Ibid., 1 2.4, 24, citing Summa thtOlogiae 2.2ae.57. l.
61. Ibid., 1.2.5, 24, "Et iuxta posteriorem et strictam iuris sign.ificationem sole! proprie iu!!
vocari facultas quaedarn moralis, quam unusquisque habet vel circa rem suam vel ad ttm slbi
58. Wilenius, Political TheOr!J, 108, described Suarez as " intensely anti-individualistic."
Jeb ita m; sic enim dominus rei dicitur habere ius in re et operarius dicitur habere im1 Ml
Fichter, MllTI ofSpain, 243, called him "a champion of human liberty." The Cambridge History of
:<tipmdium. ...-
Politic.al Thought, 1450-1700, ed. J. H. Bums (Cambridge, 1991) contains two appraisals o ( 62. Ibid., 1.25 , 25, citing Di.~t$t I.1.10, "lustitia est constans et perpetua volunta_~ iu!I 11uum
Suarez written separately by H . A. Lloyd and J.H .M. Salmon. Lloyd wrote, " In sum the thrust
niique tribuendi." Suart'7. C"omm..ntrcl, " 111.-i t>rgo actio seu moralis faculta!I qu;im un
o( Suarez' arguments ... was ... towards absolutis m" (297). According to Salmon, " N11 o ne
usq11isque habt't ad ttm suam vrl .,,f n·m 1111 M' nliquo modo pertinentem didtur iu11." ( >n ""
who reads attentively his answer to James l's ApoloXir can maintain this (absolutist) interprc·
.md actio in sixleenth ..·rnlury law ...... 1• S h• l11, '" I i.u1t•l111~ 11nd the Origins of lht' Mudl'm ( 'lvtl
tation. ..." (239).
59. Tractatus dr lr!(ibus II<" l>ro lrxislnlrirt", t•d. I .. l'1•rl'i'1A, V. i\hril, .111d I'. Sunc•r, I\ vol!!.
I.1w,µ in M i'latr]ll'S l"rln WuMlf'.'°'' I fl. i\111<11111 rl itl (l'rihoul"K, 1993), 42<1· S2. l>onC'll1111 diN
linKuisht'(I hl'lwt't'll" prlllMty 1111h1 lo 11 th1t114 1m1I "011•1·11111fory r iKhl lhm1111h whkh "dnlm
(Madrid, 1971-81 ) I: 1.2. 1-:1, 211 2:\. f l11i" 1·1lillt•11 i11d111ll'11 o nly llw Hr"! Four ll.~1k1111f rlw Pr
, 1111111 hc· p11r.ot1t"<I In, 0111 I
lr.l{ibus.)
1•1 1'1111 • I 1 h, 7h
304 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS RIG HTS, COMMUNITY, AND SOVEREIG NTY 305

two definitions.64 He apparently regarded the first two meanings as merely raised a further problem that had arisen in medieval theology and that has
different ways of saying the same thing. As Finnis wrote, "If you like, it is attracted a good deal of attention among modem scholars, mainly because
Aquinas's primary definition of 'jus', but transformed by relating it exclu- it recurs at a key point in the work of Grotius. One school of thought-
sively to the beneficiary of the just relationship." In other contexts Suarez Suarez traced it back to Gregory of Rimini-held that one could sin simply
gave only a twofold definition but still associated the idea of ius as a moral by acting against the natural law known through right reason and that,
faculty with the teaching of Aquinas. accordingly, even if there were no God, to act against reason would still
be sinful. The other school of thought-founded by Ockham according to
lus sometimes signifies a moral faculty to a thing or in a thing . . . which
Suarez-held that natural law consisted solely of divine commands, so
is properly the object of justice as we know from St. Thomas.. .. Some-
times ius signifies law, a rule of righteous conduct. . . . 65
that no act was wicked unless forbidden by God.111 Suarez chose a middle
course. The natural law discerned by reason, he held, both indicated what
Some modem neo-Thomists have been especially unhappy with was intrinsically good or evil and also commanded the one and forbad<'
Suarez' definition of ius as a moral faculty. Louis Lachance wrote that St. the other. But, in discerning natural law, reason also discerned the will of
Thomas never dreamed of such a definition, and complained that Suarez God for humankind. Since God chose to create humans as creatures en-
was making human will the basis of morality.66 Of course Suarez had no dowed with reason, we can know that he intended them to act in accord
such intention. In the passage just quoted he went on to establish a cor- with the dictates of their rational nature.
relation between ius defined as a moral faculty and ius understood as law,
Whence it may be further stated that this very judgment of the right
"a rule of righteous conduct." Aquinas himself never defined "right" as a
reason that is instilled by nature in man is itself a sufficient sign of the
moral faculty or conceived of it in that way but, as we noted in discussing divine will . .. .71
Vitoria, the subjective definition can reasonably be seen as complementing
Thomistic teaching. And Suarez was not innovating here. After Vitoria had Since the precepts of natural law related to what was intrinsically
shown how a subjective understanding of ius could be derived from good and intrinsically evil, Suarez held that they could not be changed
Aquinas and Gerson, definitions of the word as a faculty or power became even by God himself. But still he found room in his system of thought for
quite common among sixteenth-century theologians.67 (Suarez mentioned what Ockham had called natural law by supposition. For Suarez, natural
Driedo as the immediate source of his own definition.) law existed necessarily supposing that God had chosen to create rational
When Suarez turned to natural law he wrote, again referring to creatures.n Also some natural laws came into play only as a consequence
Aquinas, that this law "dwells in the human mind to distinguish the righ- of certain human acts, and ceased to take effect when the relevant condi-
teous from the evil."68 Suarez accepted the usual view that natural law tions no longer existed. Thus natural law required that promises be kept
was known by a "dictate of reason" or "judgment of the mind."69 But he and debts repaid, but the promisee or creditor could release the other party
from hjs obligation; in doing so he was not acting against natural law but
64. Ibid., 1.2.4, 23. luxta has ergo duas vocis derivationes, nomen ius duas praecipuas creating a factual situation where the law no longer applied. Similarly the
habet significationes... ." precept of natural law that forbade theft came into play only on the suppo-
65. De ltgibus 3:2.17.2, 100. FOi' other examples of the same twofold definition see 2.14.16,
33 and 2.18.2, 115. Also Dt statu ptrfeclionis in Francisci Suartz . . . operll omnia 28 vols. (Paris,
sition that private property had been instituted by human initiative.73
1859) 15:8.5.12, 565 and Dtfmsiojidti clltholicat, Opera 24:4.9.11, 396. For the comment of Finn is So far we have considered only the precepts of natural law. They all
see J. F'innis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford, 1980), 2('JJ. tt•nded to the same end, Suarez wrote, and this was "the due preservation
66. L. Lachance, LL conctpt dt droit st/on Aristolt ti S. Thom11s, 2nd ed. (Ottawa, 1948), .md natural perfection or happiness of human nature."74 We now turn to
294-95. Composta also emphasized a shift from an objective sense of ius in Aquinas lo a sub-
the other, complementary, side of his doctrine, ius naturale understood in a
jective sense in Suarez. See D. Composta, " La 'moralis facultas' nella filosofia giuridica di
F. Suarez," Saltsianum 18 (1956):476-97 and " La persona umana e i diritti soggetivi in p ros- subjective sense as specifying the natural rights that were also necessary
petiva metafiska,N lustiti111:7 (1974):42-72. to pn:>scrve and perfect human lif<>.
67. Many texts are presented in A. Folgado, Evoluci6n hislom:11 dtl conct'plo drl drrtrho s1Jb--
;t1ivo (Madrid, 1960). See especially Molina' s definition of i11s as fnculla.< (200) and Folgado'!I 711. ll:>id., 2 .6 .) 4 , 7Q 114.
criticism of Lachance's under5tanding of Suan•7. (50). 71. lhid., 2 .6 .24, 1117
68. Dt lrRibus 1:1.J .9, 44. Su ..rl'7. 1!1'ni1-.t hc•n• !hilt n.1tur.1l lilw pt•rt11irw'"I l o irr,1tion11l n. Jhid .. 2.t. v. wt.
creatures. 7J lll'll','(il>11• ot ·1 14 II , 711,"/ l'I 11. 1111
f,Q Pr/1·~il•11,J:2 'l 17 . 7 1. 1'l14. :n '/ 4 lldl','(ih11• I '}'/'/ , JIM
306 TKE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS RtGlfTS, COMMUNITY, AND SOVEREIGNTY

Suarez approached this theme by considering an old problem of Although community of property pertained only to the negative (or per-
the canonists concerning the rights to liberty and property. According missive) Jaw of nature, a positive precept of natural law required that no
to natural law all men were free and all property was held in common; - I
one be excluded from the necessary use of the common possessions. And
but human law had introduced servitude and private ownership. It i' once private property was established it was protected by the natural law
seemed, then, that natural law was not immutable.75 Suarez cited here the forbidding theft.80 Suarez added here the usual proviso that a person who
key texts of the Decretum, Quo iure and Dilectissimis, around which eddies used the goods of another when in a state of extreme need was not a thief.
of controversy had swirled ever since the twelfth century; and his expla- Elsewhere he explained that the original division of things could not have
nation of them relied on an argument that had originally been presented been just and reasonable unless it was understood at the time that super-
by the early Decretists. Natural law could take the form of a command, fluities were common in case of necessity.8 1
and such law was indeed immutable, Suarez held, but natural law could Suarez' discussion of the relationship between permissive natural law
also be merely "permissive or negative or concessive. "76 Liberty and com- and natural rights is an important part of his rights theory. He returned to
mon property pertained to this permissive natural law; these things were the topic a little further on when he was considering some aspects of th('
not actually commanded and they could be changed by human action. ius gentium. Here he wrote that concessive law could not be separated en-
By nature man was born free, but no law of nature commanded that he tirely from preceptive law. For example, if a privilege were conceded to a
retain his freedom. Liberty was a right but ~ot an inalienable right. person, it followed that others were commanded not to impede him in its
\ Up to this point the argument was traditional. But Suarez then consid- use. The same argument applied to concessive natural law. Since natu-
ered an objection that led him to some further refinements of thought ral Jaw permitted anyone to occupy vacant land and build on it, no on('
about permissive natural law as a locus of natural rights. The objection ran could justly disturb the first occupant. It would be inconsistent to say that
like this. H, under the rule of natural law, liberty and property were merely a person had a free right (liber facultns) and at the same time that he could
permitted, not commanded, then it would seem that any person could be impeded in the use of the right. The obligation not to violate a natural
licitly enslave another or snatch away his property without injustice, for right was a requirement of natural law.82
the aggressor would not be violating any actual precept of natural law.77 In other contexts Suarez explored further the rights that existed in "tht•
In response to this, Suarez referred back to his earlier definitions of ius natural state of mankind" before private property was instituted,&'.! and
as meaning either Jaw or a right to own or claim something. He would that persisted even if the right to property were renounced. This latter
now apply the same distinction to the term ius naturale, he wrote. His point issue arose when Suarez discussed the thorny old problem of Franciscan
was that a natural right 'which he now referred to as a ius dominativum) poverty. The question involved was whether the friars could renounct•
could arise from the kind of natural law that he had earlier described as all rights in property and retain only a simple factual use of things as tht•
"permissive or negative or concessive." Earlier Suarez had noted that per- Franciscans claimed to do. Pope John XX.II insisted that any licit use must
mission understood as mere indifference did not pertain to law.78 Now he imply a right of using. Suarez cited the relevant papal decretals but dis-
argued that there could be a permissive law that was not merely neutral. A agreed with them. He held that, when a person used something solely by
negative or permissive natural law could imply the existence of a positive license of another he had no right regarding it. Properly speaking, Suan•z
natural right.
homines positive (ut sic dicam) liberos cum inlrinseco iure libertalis ... simililer conlulil <'<1111
If we speak of dominative natural right, then it is true that liberty per-
muniler dominium rerum omni um el consequenter uniruique dedit poteslatem ulrndi."
tains to natural right positively and not only negatively ... because
80. Ibid., 2.14.17, 35: " Unde quamvis natura non praeceperit ul res sempcr CS.<;(.'nt t•om
uature made man free positively (so to speak) with an intrinsic right of munes, quo sensu dicitur communitas rerum de iure naturae (~ative). lamen duranlr illu
liberty. Similarly nature conferred a common dominion of everything ''"'u posilivum praeceptum iuris naturae eral ul nemo prohiberelur nee impt'dirt•tur ah uMu
and so gave to each one a right of using.79 111-.·t"S...ario communium rerum .. . l""'"l"•1 m facta •'SI et applicala 5unl dominia. ius nalumr
pmhilwt furtum scu indl'hilam a1·n•plinnrm rc·i .11i1•na1•."
75. Dt kgibus 4:2.14.2, 17. Kl . lhid., 2.16. 11, ~l; ·rrndr1l11• ,i,. 1fo11rl1r/1•, ( '1•rnr 12: 7 ..1.4, " . .. jur<' anlc•m K1·nti11111 •Uni
76. Ibid., 2.14.6, 22. chvis.1, qua.• d ivis io non poh••I ""-"' ''"'"· c·I 1.1th111l .-011"'""'· ni~i hat' l<"gf' fac·ta in1t•lliKt1hir, ul
77. Ibid., 2.14.15, 32. 'I"•"' pmprii~ tl1>mini" fm•nml •11pr11111,., 11111• 1•llk1nnl11t nmmn1nc•."
78. !Hl~ibus3:2. 12 . 1 , 178. K2 Jhicl , 2 .1114, 117 Ill, J Ill ·1. Ill, ·· """' "11111111 hrlta snnl iun• n.11tmw. Et"'"'''"'
79. lH /,gibu~ 4:2.1.(. If>, .14,
~ Al vrro 1<l li"I"''""" •It• lurr 11nt11rnll tlu111lrtr1tl110, ,.j,- 11t•rum nu>cln uhli11,1ll111111h111 "'' 111111 vh1l•n•l1tm '""' "'" nlh•1h1•. t1Al11rnlb1 lrKI~ "'' ··
est lilwrtatt>m C'Nk' th• i11w llllhmlll 1"'"111111· ,., """ h11\llllll 1t••11nllvc· ''"'" llollur.1 r...·11 KI <;111m·i 11.,..,1thr11l11 t1.... •f,.lmn ""1t11111l1•111 l111111t1111n1" nl 'J IH I, I l'l
308 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS RIGHTS, COMMUNITY, AND SoVEREIGNTY 309

wrote, a right was something that a man had as his own, that he could ex- Suarez' argument began in a conventional Aristotelian fashion. Man
ercise in his own name, that could not be taken away from him without was by nature a social animal. His social instinct was partly satisfied
injustice.94 But this left Suarez with a problem similar to one we have just by life in a family. But a single family could not contain all the offices
discussed. U a friar had no right in the things he used it would seem that and skills or all the knowledge needed for a fully satisfying human life.
anyone could deprive him of them without injustice. Suarez replied that Moreover the separate families would often be at strife with another. The
the friar always had a natural right to defend himself and that this ex- remedy for this situation was the establishment of a political or "perfect"
tended to the things he held. The right involved was not a property right; society.90 The problem was to explain how political authority could come
it was rather the natural dominion that a person had over his own actions to be instituted among men who were by nature free and equal, with no
including the actual use of things. (Here again the Thomist argument jurisdiction over one another.
about self-mastery that Vitoria had used recurs in a later rights theory.) The subtext of much early modem writing on the origin of the state
Suarez added that the friar's right could also be derived from "the natural was the doctrine of medieval corporation law asserting that a group of
right that anyone has to nourish, protect, and preserve his own body." 85• scattered individuals had no inherent jurisdiction but that such a power
In considering the original condition of humankind, the state of in- did inhere in the same persons united into a corporate body. Jurisdiction
nocence, Suarez noted that certain rights were inherent in human na- could then be exercised by the corporation as a whole or by the officers it
ture from the beginning. Although God gave the world to mankind in appointed.91 At first the jurisdiction was supposed to be derived from a
common, individual rights necessarily arose in the actual use of things. grant by the sovereign, pope or emperor; but medieval law became more
Anyone who plucked a fruit from a tree in order to eat it would acquire and more permissive until, in mid-thirteenth century, Innocent rv wrott•
a particular right in the fruit that could not be taken away without in- that, when three or more individuals joined together, corporate status
justice.86 The situation was not so clear with regard to rights in land; but followed automatically provided that the aim was "to preserve for each
Suarez thought that a person who cultivated a particular patch of ground his justice." And, as Antony Black observed, "/ustitia in this context may
could not justly be deprived of the use of it. Natural reason demanded this. just as well be translated as 'rights'."92 In effect the pope was endorsing
So it could be introduced by usage that anyone who occupied a piece of what we should nowadays call a right of association. Later medieval
land should possess it as his own so long as he did not leave it.87 This was jurists sometimes wrote that the right to form corporations was derived
still something short of outright ownership. According to Suarez this was from "the law itself."93
finally introduced through human will and consent in the ius gentium; 88 Suarez argued in just the same way (with a reference to Roman and
but he seems to have envisaged the ius gentium as ratifying or legitimiz- canon corporation law) when he discussed the formation of political com-
ing a state of affairs that had gradually grown into existence from the munities'1>4; but, since at first no positive law existed, he based his argument
beginning of the human race. on natural law. A multitude of men could exist as a mere disordered aggre-
In discussing the origin of property, Suarez insisted that the domin- gate with no inherent jurisdiction; but the same persons might be gathered
ion of man over external nature was not a supernatural gift, especially together by a special act of will or common consent into a unified politi-
bestowed by God on Adam after his creation; rather it was something in- cal body pursuing a common end.95 It would be impossible to conceive
trinsic to human nature from the beginning.99 If now we tum to another of such a body existing without government; so political power inherftl
topic, the origin of the state, we find a similar principle asserted.
90. De fegi&us 5:3.1.3, 8 - 10.
84. ~ statu perfection is, Opoa 15:8.5.29, 571 . 91. The locus of jurisdiction in a corporate body was the subject of a dispute between thr
85. [bid., 8.5.38, 575, " ... unusquisque habet naturale jus ad defendendum et se, et hrl'at canonists Innocent IV and Hostiensis. lnnocent wrote, "Rectors appointed by rorpor41·
quidquid apud se possidet ... hoc autem jus non necessario est dominium acquisitum ... sed t inn.~ have jurisdiction, not the corporations themselves.ff Hostiensis replied, "Wh"t l11rt0<"f'nl
est naturale dominium in proprias actiones, ad quas pertinet et usus facti . . . Potest etiam hoc n'j<'Cts is more true, altho ugh more diffiCtJlt. # Set> B. Tierney, Foundations ofthf' Conri/Uir '111n•t l(
jus revocari ad illud jus naturale, quod homo habet ad nutriendum, protegendum, et conser- (( '.1mbridge, 1955), 107.
vandum proprium corpus." '12. A. Black, Guild.~ and <'i111/ .o;,1c·1f'ly (lth,1rn, NY, 19114), 17.
86. ~ upett ~x dierum, Opoa 3:5.7.13, 418. •D. Ibid., 2ll.
87. Ibid. 9-4 IH ll'1(i&11~ l: l.ti. l'l, 12 1, dllnit /Ill("'' 111 7'/ •Ul•I />n·rrtalts5~11.1 4.
88. Drlrgi&us 4:2.17.ll, Ulfl. •15. I >r lt'Jeil111~ !'i::l.2.4, 24 'J'I, " 1' 1111 '"1'" "'"''" l'nn11lclrr1mda ~!II homlnum mult!tuclu ,
89. De Opt'rt', Opt<ra :l::l. lt>.Q, 2HO, " I lo•· •'CK" ju .i h.1h11il t'llot111 ho11111 '"' vi su;i1• .-r••a · • 111111t•n11~ ~1"14'<·1.•ll voh111lc1h• ,,..,. 1111111110111 1 """"""" 111 111111m <'<•rpuM polltk um •·onKr"K'"'
ti1mi~... " I 11r
310 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS RIGHTS, COMMUNITY, AND SoVEREIGNTY 311

in the community necessarily, "by the very nature of the thing."96 But will; but once instituted it possessed jurisdiction over the members "by the
the jurisdiction of the community included powers-among them the force of natural reason" or "by the force of natural law alone." 101 This was
power of capital punishment-that did not belong to the individuals another kind of suppositional natural law, a law that came into play only
who composed it. So Suarez still had to explain how this jurisdiction as a result of some preceding human act. By arguing in this way Suarez
arose in the first place. He considered the theory of divine right-that God was able to construct a theory of the state based on the characteristics of
had bestowed ruling power directly on some supreme prince and his human nature without appealing to any divine act or intervention after
descendants-but Suarez dismissed this as lacking any basis in reason or the first creation of Adam. A central feature of Suarez' thought on rights
authority.97 Another possibility was that Adam had been endowed with and political theory was his insistence that ruling power was brought into
sovereign power at the beginning of the human race. But Suarez rejected being, not by patriarchy or divine right or the supposed superiority of
this view too. Adam's power was domestic not political, he wrote. As some person or class, but by the will and consent of free right-bearing in-
Adam's progeny multiplied, separate families arose, each with its own dividuals who entered into a compact with one another to form a political
head. Political power began to exist only when they joined together in society. 102
a community; and the community was formed not by the will of Adam So far Suarez had argued that ruling power resided naturally in the
alone but by the wills of all those who assembled together.98 whole political community; pure democracy was the natural form of gov-
The most common view, Suarez noted, with a reference to Vitoria ernment for humankind.103 But Suarez also thought that "infinite con-
among others, was that political power was given to the community im- fusion and trouble" could arise if power remained diffused in this way.u>t
mediately by God. In a sense this was true, he acknowledged; but the im- Normally it was necessary to confer ruling authority on some particular
portant question was how God conferred this power.99 This question takes ruler or rulers. But a difficulty arose at this point. If natural law conferred
us to the heart of Suarez' argument. He insisted that the ability to institute power on the community, how could the community relinquish it? The
communities endowed with political power was innate in humans from answer was the same as the one Suarez had given when he considered
their first creation. It was a characteristic resulting from (human) nature. community of property. The natural law involved was merely concessive
It was not conferred by any special act or grant of God subsequent to or permissive.1115 No precept of natural law prohibited the community from
the creation. If political power had been so conferred we could know of it yielding its power to a ruler, and natural reason suggested that such a
only through revelation, not through natural reason, but this was not the transfer was necessary and expedient. 106
case. A dictate of reason shows us that such power is necessary for human The "democratic" side of Suarez' thought persisted in his teaching that
welfare; reason also shows that, accordingly, God instilJed this power in legitimate political power was necessarily derived from the consent of the
human nature.100 community. 107 His doctrine of sovereignty was expressed in two proposi-
Political power did not manifest itself in humans when men lived tions, both of which had a long medieval ancestry, and both of which had
as scattered individuals, but only when they joined together in a perfect been accepted by Vitoria. First, a ruler once instituted held a power greater
community. Such a community could be established only through human than that of the whole community subject to him, not merely greater than
that of the separate individuals who composed it. And, second, the trans-
96. Ibid., ·rn tali ergo rommunitate, ut sic, est haec potestas ex natura rei ..." fer of power to a ruler was not a mere delegation to a representative but a
97. Ibid., 3.2..2, 21.
98. Ibid., 3.2.3, 23. "Verumtamen ex vi solius creationis et originis naturalis sol um colligi I OJ. Ibid., 3. l.11, 16, " ... naturale ius per se non effecerit subiectionem politicam sine in-
potest habuisse Adamum potest:\tem oeconomicam, non politkam .. .."For another reforence tt•rventu humanae voluntatis, ut videbimus"; 3.3 .6, 32, " . .. ex vi rationis naturalis ~tin t•o";
to Adam, denying his political authority, see Dt Opl'l't, ~ra 3:5.7.14, 416. 1.2.4, 24 " . .. potestatem hanc ex vi solius iuris naturae esse in hominum communitate."
99. ~ legibus 5:3.2..2, 29; 3.2.4, Jl. 102. Suarez emphasized this point by contrasting secular jurisdiction with thf' powrr of
JOO. Ibid ., 3 .2.5, 31, #Deus non dat hanc potestatem per specialem actionem vel conces- tlw pop<' that really was conff'rred by a d irt'Ct div int' grant. See~ legil1us, 3.3.11, 33.
sionem a creatione distinctam. Alias de tali concessione deberet per revelatiollCTO constare, l fl1. Defensio, Opm1 15:3.2.<J, 209.
quod falsum esse constat. . .. Ergo datur ut proprietas ronsequens naturam, nimirum medio 1114. De lex1bus, 3.4.1, :lll
dictamine rationis naturalis ostendentis Deum suHicientt'r providis..<;<' humano generi et ron- 105. Otfrnsio, :l.2.9, 211'1. '"Ot11><·lrn1 I'"',..'"" hA1'<· .. J ici poles! de jure natunlli nt~11tlv..,
sequenter illi dedisse potestatem ad suam con~rvationt'm f't C"OOVE'llienh.>m gub<-rnatiorwm non po~i tivc, v1•I potiu11clc•111"" n.iluro1h 1 u111"""""'· 1101111implic-itrr priu"Ciplt'lll«>."
necessariam." This may bf' compa~ w ith an argum('llt 11dvann'tl l>y <kkham (in um· of hi~ tot.. I H lry(il•u• <;;J .4. 1. 1H; 11 K, .\4
moods). Rf'a.~n. rdlN-linK nn h11m1m n11hm'. nu1hl .tlN<·"m ( ;,,.j',. lnh•ntlun lc•r hunMnklml . 107 lhld , :l 4 2, 40, '' rlf't ....... 11•1 ttl •• • ""...,""" 1 nm1111mlt11llP11111 trlh1111hir " llr/rn~i11,
Stt 11hov«>, 174 7~. I J 12. 1111," 111111 rrl(O h11m..,lh1l11 o1 I i..u ..,,, o1 l'"I'"'" '"K''" h"l1<•11t pul<'11I01trm H
312 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS RIGHTS, COMMUNITY, AND SOVEREIGNTY 313

kind of alienation or "perfect grant." Once the people had granted away part of the common good. In one way the common ~ood related to p~b.tic
their power they could not reclaim it at will. 108 It followed too that the ruler property like temples and common pastures; but, in another way, 1t in-
could legislate or tax for just cause without requiring the explicit consent cluded the good of private citizens. Precisely because each person was a
of his subjects. 109 part of the community the good of each one redounded to the advantage
Suarez was not arguing here for monarchical absolutism. He observed of the whole.117 When laws were enacted that served the advantage of in-
that, although monarchy was in principle the best form of rule, never- dividual persons in a community it was "so that the common good may
theless, given " the frailty, ignorance and wickedness of mankind," it was arise from the goods of individuals." 118 This seems to echo the medieval
usually advisable to add some "common" element to the government. 110 way of thinking that we encountered in Gerson, where the common good
The form of government depended on the choice of the community. and individual goods were seen as typically existing in harmony with one
Suarez' point was that, whatever the form adopted, once a government another rather than in a state of conflict.
was instituted it possessed a sovereign power (supremo potestas). This was Suarez' views on the rights of citizens within a political community
true whether the government was a monarchy or an aristocracy or a have to be gathered from various scattered contexts. He mentioned casu-
mixture of the two, like the doge of Venice with his senate or a king ally a natural right to preserve one's good name, a right to marry, and a
with the nobles of his nation.111 In the case of a king, the ruler acquired a natural right to liberty, including "a maiden's right to her own freedom"
kind of ownership of the power conferred on him and could not be de- before she was married.119 As regards the rights to liberty and property, the
prived of it unless he lapsed into tyranny.112 state acquired a "higher right" in that a person could be deprived of liberty
Before we tum to the extreme case of tyranny, we need to consider for crime and taxes could be imposed for the common good. 120 But these
the status and rights of individuals in a political community under more rights did not simply cease to exist in a civil community. Liberty was a
normal conditions. When discussing the origin of the state Suarez de- natural right, and a right to property was protected by natural law once
ployed some traditional organic imagery. it had been instituted. A person could not be deprived of such rights with-
out just cause. In considering liberty, "a great perfection" of man, Suarez
Just as man .. . has power over himself and over his faculties and mem-
bers for their use ... so too the political body of mankind . .. has power
distinguished carefully between citizenship and servitude. The power of
and rule over itself and consequently has power and a particular domin- a magistrate was not the dominion of a master over a slave but a juris-
ion over its own members.113 diction established for the good of all.121 As regards property, it would be
most absurd, Suarez wrote, to imagine that a king could arbitrarily take
In keeping with this holistic imagery, Suarez acknowledged the primacy of away his subjects' goods; to d o so would be to violate a right granted by
the common good. Laws should be made for the good of the whole body.114
nature.122
It was indeed human sociability, the need of humans to live in communi- It followed from such considerations that an individual citizen was
ties that made laws necessary in the first place.U5 Accordingly, the common not obliged to obey unjust laws or, perhaps, any laws that were unduly
good should prevail if it conflicted with the good of a particular individ- harsh and burdensome, or laws that de facto were rejected by a majority
ual.116 But Suarez also held that the good of private individuals was itself a

HIS. ~ Itgibus 5:3.4.6, 43; 3.4.11, 49. 11 7. Ibid., }.7.7, 136.


109. lbid., 6:3.19,4-9, 40-46; 5.17.3 in Optra 5:492. 118. Ibid., 1 .7.3, 131. Discussing divine law here Suarez wrote that eternal happint>ss wa.~
110. Ddtgibus 5:3.4.1, 38. ,, common goal. But he e xplained that it was common only in the sense that it was sought t>y
111. lbid., 3.19. 6-7, 42-44. It could be, Suarez noted, that leg.i slative power inhered in the o·vl'ry ind ividual " through h imself and for h imself."

l
Icing w ith an assembly of estates; but then they together possessed supreme power; consent of 119. De sraru perftclionis, Optra 15: l .l.13-14, 6; 8 .4.3, 557; Dt legibus 4: 2.18.2, 117.
the subjects was not needed for each act of legislation. On the various legitimate forms of gov- 120. On the state's " higher right" regarding p roperty and liberty see Dt ltJ(ibus 1:1.7.7, 11'>;
ernment including mixed forms, see Defmsio, 3.2.4, 2f!l; 3.27, 208; 3 .2 .18, 212. 1 2.14.18, 36.
112. Ddtgibus 5:3.4.6, 44. !21. Dr opere: Optra J :S.7.9 - IO, 4 IS l h. s.....,i_..,/>..tr,~ibus 5:3.1.7. 13- 14, " Non t~t At1h•111
113. Ibid., 3.3.6, 32. 1.1ll' Jominium hoc. ut t'i n'llfllln•h•nl pro11rin Mrvilw• •IC"<po tica, ~ s ub it'din civili,.. f.rK" r~I
114. Ibid ., 1:1.7.1, 128, " ... omnium commune a xioma est de ratione et !lub~tantia lf'gi!I .lomimum iurisdi<"tioni!I. .. ·· Soml'llllll'• S11.-w1 o·•unp.irt•d thl' citit.l'n~· sulimi,,~inn to tlw
esse ut pro communi bono feratur." ~I.th• with"" indivitlual'!l 1111hmi""lo11 In vnhmtou V .,.., vi1ml1•, l'·K·· i\t Ix lr,~ibu!O 5:1.45, 41. Out
115. Ibid .• 1.3.19, 57, *Nam in h oc fundatur quod hnmot'!'t anlm11l 110Ci<llc> nl\tura sua I""'· '"' ,.,,111,, im't.l lh,.t thi" WA• only'"' iml"'' '"' t """''•KV loy 11oloti11~ thr won I,., "114•rv.,1., p mpor
tulans vitam civilem . . . quod rx lf'Kll11111unlrn1<1ul1111111•1~11nm11nlt11th1 m11xlmr f'l'nil••t." tln 1,..," ··,ot.,..•rvin)t .lur prup111tlu11 ··
116. Ibid., 1.7.J 4, 142. 1n 1>drx1l•11• 4 7 14 l'I. 11
315
RIGHTS, COMMUNITY, AND SOVEREIGNTY
11 ·1 THE IDEA OF NATIJRAL RIGHTS

- condemned monarch.131 Suarez added


of the peopl1•.1 " Suarez did not refer here specifically to the rights of in- for any private personlto lk1!ct:Oderstatement, that the king of England
dividuals hut r.llher to the lack of a duty to obey. In the modem legal lan- here with a perhaps ca cu a
' hi ments il2
guage of I lohfeld he was discussing "immunities." Similar arguments would not ta~e kindly to s argu d red. or extensive list of natural or civil
applied lo unjust taxation. An individual was not obliged to pay an un- Suarez ~id not present any o~e lete modem theory of rights and the
just tax and, if there were a doubt about whether a ruler had the right to rights. He _d id n~t construct a c;;,u Ph his definition of a right as a moral
impose a tax, the subjects retained possession of "their goods and their state. But m vanous ~ays-th tsgth t litkal societies were formed by
liberty." 12• faculty, and throug~ hi~ ~rgumen aaia ri ht to liberty and an inalien-
In considering the relationship between rulers and subjects, the right the volition of free individuals, and th g · tituted-the
i . ted after a government was ms
that Suarez insisted on most explicitly and emphatically was the right able right of self-de ense perstsbl' h th substructure on which later theo-
of self-defense. For Suarez this was " the greatest of rights," a natural in- Spanish master helped to _esta IS e
alienable right that inhered in individuals and communities, a right that ries of rights would be built.
could be exercised by subjects against a tyrannical ruler. Suarez distin-
guished conventionally between two kinds of tyrants-a usurper who
seized power without any just title, and a legitimate ruler who abused his
power.125 In the first case, any private person could justly kill the tyrant
since he was an aggressor making war on the commonwealth and all its
members.126 Although a private individual could not licitly punish a male-
factor on his own authority, he could kill in self-defense or in defense of
the state. The individual acted then with the tacit authorization of the state
and of God, who gave to everyone the p ower to defend himself and any
innocent person.127 If a king with a legitimate title made actual war on his
subjects the same rule applied. However, when a legitimate king ruled un-
justly but without continued and actual violence against his people, no
private individual could attack him. An individual could licitly kill such a
king only in defense of his own life. 128 In this case the remedy lay with the
community as a whole; after public deliberation of the nobles and citizens
the people could licitly judge and depose a tyrannical ruler. The com-
munity had this power both from its inherent right of self-defense and
because the original compact that instituted a king always assumed that he
would rule "politically not tyrannically" and would otherwise be subject
to deposition.129 Suarez held that the pope too could depose an erring king.
He acknowledged that the pope should use his power only for spiritual
ends. But, according to Suarez, this meant that the pope could depose a
king "directly" for a spiritual crime like heresy, and "indirectly" by con-
demning other sins of the king and approving his subsequent deposition
by the community.130 The sentence of deposition co uld include a mandate

123. Ibid., 6:3.19.11- 13, 47- 49.


124. De ltgrous, 5.17.18, 12-14 in Optra 5:496- 97.
125. Defensio, 6.4.1, Opera 24:675; Dt cluirilalt , 13.8.2, Optra 12:759 .
126. Deft nsio, 6.4.7, 677.
127. Ibid., 6.4.13, 679. On sclf-defmiw ns "th<• ~n·alt-:it right" ,.,... 11.4.~. t.7h.
128. Ibid ., 6.45 , 676.
129. I,,,,.,,,
Ibid., 6.4.15, 611(); lJ<' d1arilalf, 12 LI II :•. 7r;" UI lhhl . h 14 Ill. ""'
IJO. lhid .• :n :l2, '.H !i; 11 4 It•, hllO \ \) lhhl · '' 14 14. ti'/'J
GROTIUS. FROM MEDIEVAL TO MODERN 317

a rather florid baroque version, overladen with classical allusions and quo-
tations, may seem tedious to a modem reader, but it commended his work
greatly to his contemporaries.
Grotius made his purpose dear in the Prolegomena to his masterwork,
De j11re belli et pacis (On tire lAw of War and Peace).
Throughout the Christian world I observed a lack of restraint in relation
lo war, such as even barbarous races should be ashamed of ... ii is as if,
in accordance with a general decree, frenzy had openly been let loose for
the committing of all crimes!
THIRTEEN In the face of this situation Grotius insisted that there could be "a common
law among nations," and this he proposed to expound. Modem inten>st
in Grotius has centered around two themes-his contribution to the for-
mation of international law and his supposed role as the founder of a new,
GROTIUS. FROM MEDIEVAL TO MODERN modem doctrine of natural law and natural rights. It is the latter aspect
of his work that will concern us. In particular I want to explore some out-
standing questions concerning the relationship between Grotius's teach-
ings on natural rights and those of his medieval predecessors.

T he idea of natural rights grew up among Catholic jurists and theo-


logians during the medieval era. The further development of the
doctrine in the early modem world was almost entirely the work of Protes-
THE QUESTION OF MODERNITY

In the opening pages of the De jure be/Ii Grotius introduced the view
tant political theorists. Between the two worlds, linking them together, .!
of the ancient skeptic Carneades who maintained that there could bt•
L
stood the figure of the great Dutch scholar, Hugo Grotius.' no universal standard of natural justice because, by nature, all creahm'fl,

I
The Mexican author, Edmundo O'Gorman, once wrote that "sixteenth including humans, simply sought their own advantage. Against th b1,
century Spain is the bridge over which European culture passed from Grotius argued that man was a higher kind of animal, marked by a .sod11I
the medieval to the modem phase."2 One is tempted to extend the meta- instinct that impelled humans to live with their own kind in a pe11cl'f11I,
phor and write that the work of Grotius formed a last, indispensable arch ordered society.5 For Grotius, as for Suarez, this human sociability w1u1
of the bridge. But this would not be quite the whole truth. Grotius did J.,._ · lhc original source of law.6 Grotius also noted that humans were cnpnhlc• of
often quote the Spanish scholastics, partly no doubt for tactical reasons.3 ::. judging what was beneficial for humankind in the long run and •UK11t'tl
Often indeed, in considering his work, one seems to be reading Suarez :~ that to go against such a judgment would be to violate the law or 1mt11n<,
transposed into a different idiom. But Grotius was a learned jurist and namely of human nature. (For Grotius human nature was " thl• m11lh1•1
theologian in his own right; he could reach back behind the Spanish writ- of natural Jaw.")7 This law of nature required us primarily to r<>Sfll'l'I tht'
ers to make use of the earlier medieval tradition on which his work, rights of others-to leave to others, or render to them, what was their own
and theirs, depended. Grotius was also a brilliant humanist, a youthful Such language has suggested to some readers that, for Grotius, tlw !'il11h'
prodigy as a boy, and later the author of poetry and histories, as well as
works on jurisprudence and theology. His own variety of humanist Latin, 4. J. 8 . Scott, ed., Hugonis Grotii, Dr jurt ~Iii ti pacrs Wm Ires (Oxford, 1913) (Repn><lm·lln11
111 tht• Ed ition of 1646}, Proltgomnia, 6 . (1 have added page references for the Prul'R''"'' ""
which is unpaginated in the original.}
J. There is an excellent bibliography in P. Haggenmacher, Gro1i11s ti lo doelrinl' di' la x111·rrl'
~- Ibid .. 2, " Inter haK autem quae homini s unt propria est appetitus societalis, id M<t com
ju.sit (Paris, 1983). For later wOf'ks Stt the listing.~ in th<' journal Groliana (New ScriE':<).
munit .. t i~. non qualiscunque, ~ tranc111ill;w «'I pro s u i intellectus modo ordin:ital'. .. . "
2. E. O'Corman, #1.ewiii Hankl' on thl' Sp"n!sh Stmule for Justin• in the Conqu1•st of
t. lhid., 2.• " Hat'(" vem ... 1111< l<'IAlh1 f UNh>tll", humano intellectu convcni<'m1, forn1 <'111 ••Im
0

America," Hi.~J"'lnic l\mtric1111 I li~htr.irul ffrl'/1'1112•1 ( 1'14'1)· «;61 i;71 111 SM..
1uri~ . ' I" " pt•rtint•I alit'fli •.t>11tlm•11tl". rt •I 1111l1l .,ll1•nl h.ll>t•amu~ .. . l"t'lltilutlo .
3. Ill' wanl«'d lo 11t•r1m1ul1• Sp"ln to 1111·1·<'pl llw I >1111 h .ui-:u1111•nt for frt'<'tlom of n•mmt•rt'r
7 lhi1I , :l, " .. t•I ljllt'IJ l"ll l111lh 1111·l~11r "'l"' ltll"t. rll.,_111 •·ontra ju~ natur11c-, h11m11n11I' 114·11
on thl' high ,...,,l<.
111•1. ''"M,o l11h•llito1il11r"; 4," "'"11 rn1h1111ll• l11t1• "'"'" ' rNI lpM hum""" 1Ml11r11 ..
I,,,
318 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS GROTIUS. FROM MEDIEVAL TO M ODERN
319
existed only to preserve individual natural rights. Grotius next.presented pute broke out, centering around the work of James Brown Scott, as
the most famous lines of his treatise: "What we have been saymg would ~o whe~er Grotius or Vitoria should properly be called the father of
have a degree of validity even if we should concede that which cannot be mtemattonal law.14 Writing in the 1970s Charles Edwards challenged
conceded without the utmost wickedness, that there is no God .. . ." (Eti- the "double paternity" of Grotius as the father of both international
amsi daremus, quod . . . non esse Deum).8 law and of ~odem natural law. One of his critics noted that, "here open
The place of such ideas in the development of later theories of natural doors are being stormed." But, also in the 1970s, M. B. Crowe described
law and natural rights has ~n debated ever since the seventeenth cen- ~roti~~~s De jure be/Ii.as "epoc~ making ... a watershed in the history of
tury. Some writers see Grotius as a kind of Grundungsheros, a "founding tdeas. The most weighty and important book since then on Grotius, that
hero" of modem rights theories;9 others treat him as merely a transmitter of Peter ':f~ggenm~cher, treats the Dutch author as primarily a continuator
of late scholastic thought. The attitude of Grotius himself to his medieval of a tradition of discourse about the just war that goes back to Gratian's
predecessors was a little condescending but not hostile. They lived in an ~ecretum a~~ its early commentators, the starting point of our own inquiry
unhappy age, ignorant of the liberal arts, he wrote, but when they agreed mto the ongms of .natural rights theories. But, still more recently, Rich-
on a point of morals they were seldom mistaken.10 The idea that Gro- ard Tuck has seen m the work of Grotius "a manifesto for a new scienn•
tius, uninfluenced by any vestiges of previous scholarship, made a com- of morality." 16
plete break with the past seems to have been invented by Pufendorf later Although it is still quite commonly argued that Grotius inaugurated a
in the seventeenth century.11 But at about the same time writers like Felden n~~ era. of "modern natural law," there is little agreement about what was
and Huber were calling attention to medieval elements in Grotius's work. d1sh~chvely modem in his work. Sometimes it is suggested that Grotius
In the early eighteenth century Jean Barbeyrac praised "the illusti:ious substituted a new theory of natural rights for the old idea of natural law, or
Grotius" as the one who first "broke the ice" after the long dark medieval made natural law merely derivative from natural rights.17 But this is not
winter and dissipated "those thick Clouds of Darkness in which the World reallr true. In the _work of Grotius, as in that of his scholastic predecessors,
had been so long envelop'd "; 12 but a little later on J. J. Schmaus insisted we fmd natural rights and natural law existing side by side both associ-
that the teaching of Grotius on natural law was nothing but a return to ated with traits of hum~n nature that were taken to be impla~ted by God.
the old doctrine of the scholastics. 13 During the 1930s a brisk little dis- The mos! common earlier argument for Grotius's modernity maintaim•d
8 . Ibid., 3, "Et haec quidem quae jam diximus, locum aliquem haberent etiamsi daremus,
that he pioneered a new kind of "secular" and "rationalJst" approach thnt
quod sine summo scelere dari nequit, non esse Deum, aut non curari ~b eo negotia ~umana. freed the concept of natural law from the religious context in which it had
been e?",?e~ded. ~ut we now understand that the famous "impious hy
#

9. The term Grundungsheros is from F. Wieacker, Privalrtehtsgtschrchtt dt r Ntuurl, 2nd ed.


(Gottingen. 1967), 299. Wieaclcer provided a carefully bala~ account.~f the old .and the new pothes1s { Ev~n 1~ there were no God....")was a rather common toprn1
in Grotius in his HContractus und Obligatio in Naturrec:ht zw1schen Spatscholast1k und Aufk- ~
i . of late scholastic discourse and that Grotius could have picked it up fnim
lirung." in P. Grossi, ed., I.A second11 scholllslic11 (Milan, 1973), 223-39.
10. Dt jurt btlli, Proltgomma, 11. - ---·------
tt. S. Pufendorf, Specimtn controvtrsiarum circa jus naluralt ipsi nupa notnrrim (Uppsala, R. Feenstra, "Quelques remarques," 65 n. I; R. Tuck, Natural Rights Theories (Canih ri•IK•',
1678), 10. For a vigorous criticism of Pufendorf, emphasizing Grotius's ~ependence_ on the 1979), 75.
earlier scholastic tradition, and especially o n Suarez, see A.-H . Chroust, H ugo Grotius and 14. This was discussed by J. Muldoon, " The Contribution of the Medieval Canon I .awyi·r"
the Scholastic Natura] Law Tradition," Tht New Scholaslidsm, 17(1943): 101-133. It is not clear to the Formation o r International Law,HTraditio, 28 (19n): 483-97.
why Grotius quoted Suarez so seldom in the De jurt btlli when he certainly knew and admired
~5. C. S. ~d~ards, Hugo Grotius. The Miracle of Holland fChicago, 1981), 9 - 25. 1311 -~•.
the work of the Spanish scho lar. J. B. Scott suggested that it was for politic reasons. Suarez' ag;.11i:' emphas1z mg the similarities between Grotius and Suarez; C. Gellinek, " Book Rcvi•·w...
Deftnsio catho/icat jidei was condemned by the French parltmtnt because of ii~ defense of~­ l.rotra11n, n.s. 3 (1982). 77; M. B. Crowe, The Chang ing Profilr of thr Natural Law (The f filgtw,
rannicide· Grotius was living as an exile in France and h is book was dedicated to Louis 1977), 223.
xm. For further discussion see R. Feenstra, HQuelques re marques, sur les sources utilisees . 16. ':faggenmacher. Gutrrr jusle (abov(' n. I); R. Tuck, "Grotius and Selden, Hin Thr <:am
par Grotius dans ses travau.x de droit naturel," in T11e World of Hugo Grotius (1583-1645), ed., /ortdl(t Hr.story of Pol1tical Thnu11h1. 14.<;(} 1 71~. <'d. J. 11. Bums (Camb ridge, 1991), 499- 5:N al .';20
17: K. Haakon.~sen, " From N<tlur.d I-1w In lht• RiKhl~ of Man: A European PcnJ><'c1ivr on
R. Feenstra et al., 65-81 at 78-80. Feenstra suggested that Grotius could o ften have come to
Am1'nc;m 1)\-b;ite'S:" .in 11. ( ·11//11rr •'/ H.1.~ht.. n l M I I A1·1•y .111.t I<. Haakon.'i.~n (Camhridl(c',
the same conclusions as Suarez without a din-ct 1fc•p1•ndc•nn.•.
12. J. Barbeo) ta.., "f.\ n ll:..h •t i t • .. I f ', i•t..1l 1\ 14 cu111I ul llu· -.;, i. ,, • •• Pf f\t.1r.1l1tv;· 1t1
l.'1<11 ). I~ ·5 1 ,11..25, l·m . ( .roth .. lhr • 11111·"1' ' ut 11111111,,11,,w I~ tint,• tfrrivativ<' fro m right~ . .. -
S. rufendorf, Of lltr /AW o1{Naturr 1111J M1//111n, 111111•1 II KrnrlC'tl ( l m 1don, 1729), :l!>, 7<1•.
13. On the• r11rly nllh.. ul l :111lht• ..... M Vllh•y, " I ,.,. urtKlnt'll ,,,. l.1 n utlun 1lr tlrrnl ~uh·
s..... al"<1 1<lt•m, I lul(n <•h•tl11• •ml llu• I l l• ln1y nf l'n llll• ,,, I h1111Khl," l'olilicnl Thr11ry IJ ( l'IH'\)·
'! l'I 1.r;. I f,1,1l<nn'l!'l'll h11• WI 111"" ""ll•ltlvc•lv 1111 t .1 ..11110 l•ul lw I• mun· lnt1•rt•'>ft•d in lll<' I lutd i
~'t"tif, " in hi""'· I ,f'\1111• 1l'l1/ot11/1' rl1 111 1•l1ll1ro1•1•l1I~ r/11 1/11111 ( l',,rl~. I•1'l7 ). 24'1 HI .11 24'1 '1f1;
.,. h11t.u ·.. 1111lw·n11• "" l11h11r w1lh•1 0 lh1t111111 llu• 011111> 1•01111t1~ lht1llKhl
320 THE [OF.A OF NATURAL RIGHTS GROTIUS. FROM MEDIEVAL TO MODERN 321

Suarez or from any one of half a dozen sixteenth-century authors.18 More- law, derived from empirical evidence and based on the principle of self-
over, Grotius qualified his hypothesis at once by adding that there was interest-a principle that the skeptics themselves accepted.20 I can perhaps
indeed a God and that God's free will was "another source of law besides best bring out some salient features of Grotius's teaching by first consider-
the source in nature." 19 In the subsequent pages of his work there were ing the various phases of this approach to his work.
more references to the Bible than to any other source. One can hardly Tuck's argument is important and sophisticated. It deserves seri-
call this a "secularist" approach. As for Grotius's "rationalism," he did ous consideration. But it also presents many difficulties. Above all, there is
indeed maintain that human reason, reflecting on human nature, could very little evidence of any considerable preoccupation with seventeenth-
educe valid rules of moral conduct including a duty to respect the rights of century skepticism running through Grotius's writings. The Dutch scholar
others; but this was in keeping with a longstanding tradition of scholastic did indeed cite Cameades at the beginning of the De jure bel/i, just as Vi-
thought. Later writers were able to use Grotius as a source for natural toria had cited the ancient skeptics Epicurus and Lucretius at the begin-
rights theories more secular in spirit than his own because the idea of ning of his De potestate civile. But, like Vitoria, Grotius brushed aside the
natural rights that he transmitted always had been rooted in human rea- skeptical objection in a few paragraphs; then he went on for hundreds of
son, with divine revelation employed as a complementary (and, as it later pages of refined argumentation without ever adverting to the topic again.
proved, detachable) source of argument. A little earlier, in 1622, he wrote a treatise, On True Religion, in which he
Another interpretation of Grotius's thought as distinctively modem undertook to refute the archenemies of the Christian faith. This would
emphasizes his reliance on the fashionable neo-Stoicism of such authors as seem an obvious place for Grotius to have launched an attack on skep-
Justus Lipsius. But Stoicism always had been present in medieval thought, ticism if that had been one of his principal concerns. But the enemies he
not least in juristic thought. If we can ascribe any particular philosophy to thought worth refuting were the pagan, Jewish, and Muslim religions; he
the medieval jurists it was a sort of second-hand Stoicism derived for the did not mention ancient or modem skeptics.21 His other theological writ-
most part from the texts of Roman law and, among the canonists, from ings are likewise devoid of any serious engagement with seventeenth-
some passages of the Church Fathers transmitted by Gratian. Grotius was century skepticism.
erudite enough to quote the classical sources at first-hand; but the Stoicism Grotius never addressed the epistemological skepticism that so con-
he deployed had received a medieval impress from the jurists who had cerned his contemporary, Descartes. And he did not really respond to
grafted on to Stoic thought their own doctrine of subjective rights. the anthropological relativism of Charron and Montaigne by deploying il
The most interesting argument for Grotius's essential modernity has new body of "empirical evidence about social practices." 22 By the 1620s a
been presented by Richard Tuck. In a series of studies he has argued that significant amount of information was available concerning societies from
Grotius developed the concepts of natural law and natural rights in a new China to Peru. Writers like Acosta had begun to weave together this mate-
way in order to combat the moral relativism and skepticism of contempo- rial in works on comparative ethnography. But Grotius made no attempt
raries like Charron and Montaigne. Tuck sees this attack on skepticism as to collect such anthropological evidence in support of his view that certain
the central animating principle of Grotius's work and one of major signifi- values were common to all societies. He relied only on sources drawn from
cance for the future evolution of rights theories. From this perspective, the the tradition of his own culture, Christian and classical, and he assumed
m~~emity of Grotius consisted precisely in his "transcendence of skepti- that what he found there had a universal validity. It never occurred to the
cism." According to Tuck's argument, Grotius used his "enormous knowl- Dutch author that his whole conceptual apparatus of natural law and
edge of world history" to create a new theory of "minimalist" natural natu ral rights would have been unintelligible to a learned Chinese scholar;
a harsh critic might say that he challenged cultural relativism only by as·
18. The m ost detajJed account of earlier formulations of the impious h ypothesis is J. St.
Leger, Tht • Etiamsi damn us· of Hugo Grotius. A St11dy in th~ Origins oflnterniitional I.Aw (Rome, 20. R. Tuck, "C.mt ius, CarrwndC'S and I loh..-..," Grolian11, n .s . 4 (1983): 43-62. For q11nt11
1962). For an overall view of the various opinions regarding Grotius' s proximate source see lions in tilt' text 5('t' .'>4. T11<'k 1lf'vf'lt>l""I hi-" 11rg11nwnt furl~r in "Th~ 'Mod~rn· Tlwory 1•1
L Besselink. "The Impious Hypothesis Revisitt>d,- Groliana, n.s . q ( 1988): 3- 6.1. Natural Law," in A l'.11(11•·11. •••I . 1111' I lfll,1(1111,~t"I 1•{ l'olitirol Tllfory in [arly·M odtrn Eu"'1"' (Cnm-
19. De jurt btlli, Proltgomena. J, • Et ha<'<' jam .ilia juriH ori~O l'HI rr•wh•r illam naturalem, hridg<'. J<1'R7), <l'I 11'1; //ooll/,,.. (l h.lnnl. 1'111'11. 70 :i!.1, '\I 'i2; "( ;mtiu-" and St>l1k>n" (.1l>t>w n . lh);
veniens scilicet ex lib<-ra Dt'i volunl.l llt' ... ~ Gmtl1111 ndtl•'tl t h11t tht• n,i lural law d('ri vf'd fmm 1'/1111>!'-0/>h.lf lln<I C~''"""'"'"'' · /!'1 I llo!ol (l 11111lu hlK•'. 1'1111), >.Iv xvi, 1~201 .
the trails of human nalul't' ,.1,... .-nm1• fmm I :011 Minn• <;.,,\ wlll1.'tl In implnnl lho:-1• trail,. 21. Tht• work W4• 1•11l•ll•l1P1l l11 I hill h In lr•JI. 1111'11 l11 l..lll11 In 1fo2S.
in man. 27 "Thi• 'M111l1•m· 1111" 11 y .. 11 /
322 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGtn'S GROTIUS. FROM MFI>IEVAL TO M ODERN 323

serting a kind of cultural imperialism.23 Whether the hard-won insights or self than others." Similarly, in Gratian's Decretum we are told that "one
Western culture may eventuaJJy prove to have a relevance for all peoples who would give alms in good order must first give to himself." 27 Vitoria
remains an open question; but Grotius was not aware that any such ques- and Suarez and Grotius in tum all pointed out that the command to love
tion existed. our neighbor as ourselves implied that we should first love ourselves.211
Tuck's central argument suggested that Grotius reinterpreted the uni- The underlying point of the theologians was that every person was
versal impulse to self-preservation-which even the skeptics recognized- primarily responsible for his own moral welfare. They then went on to dis-
as a moral principle that could serve as the basis for a new doctrine of cuss the duty also to love one's neighbor and the situations that could arise
natural rights and natural law.24 Grotius did argue in this way; but there when the duties to self and to another conflicted. (We saw Vitoria explor-
was nothing novel in his approach. In medieval thought self-preservation ing such questions in the De homicidio.29 ) Grotius presented the same kind
always had been seen in moral terms as a duty enjoined by divine law that of argument. After discussing the "true and divinely-inspired self-love,"
implied a corresponding right of self-defense and a right to acquire the ne- he added that God also intended each individual to have regard for his
cessities of life. Grotius argued in just the same way. In his precocious early fellow-beings so that all could live in mutual harmony. And so, Grotius
work, De jure praedae, written in 1605, Grotius first asserted that what God concluded, "Love is twofold, love of self and love of others." 30 His doctrine
willed was law. Then he wrote that God willed the existence of his creation of natural law and natural rights was built around these two principles-
and so gave to each individual the natural properties necessary for self- self-love and sociability-not only or primarily on the first one. When Gro-
preservation. From these principles he deduced two laws: " It is licit to tius wanted specifically to refute the skeptic Cameades in the De jure belli,
defend one's own life.. . ."and "It is licit to acquire and retain the things it was the principle of sociability, that he appealed to.
useful for life."25 It would be hard to find any medieval jurist or philoso- I will tum to a more detailed consideration of Grotius's teaching on
pher who disagreed with such assertions. natural law below, but regarding the argument that he framed a "mini-
In arguing for self-interest as the basis of natural law in Grotius, mal" doctrine in order to refute contemporary skeptics there are two
Tuck quoted a striking phrase from the De jure praedae: "(T)he first prin- preliminary points to be made. In the first place Grotius's understanding
ciple of the natural order . . . is the love whose primary force and action are of natural law was not necessarily minimalist. He defined the term, like his
toward oneself.'126 This does seem like an assertion of unqualified egocen- scholastic predecessors, as "a dictate of right reason"; but this is an open-
trism, an anticipation of the extreme individualism that was to character- ended definition; it could lead on to the enumeration of many particular
ize some later natural rights theories; but the text needs to be considered in rules of right behavior. 31 And, secondly, medieval teaching always had
its historical context and in the context of Grotius's own writing. Grotius been minimalist as regards the primary principles of natural law. Gratian
attributed his doctrine to "the old poets and philosophers"; but it was also thought it necessary to mention only two such principles at the beginning
a characteristic teaching of medieval theology and canon Jaw. Peter Lom- of the Decretum. Aquinas discussed four " inclinations" that gave rise to the
bard's Sentences, the standard textbook of medieval theology, presented an basic precepts of natural law; 32 he then argued that from these few funda-
"order of charity" derived from St. Augustine, which required us to love
27. Peter Lombard, Stntenline. 3.28.1; Aquinas, Summa t~logiae. 2.2ae16.4; Suarez; ~
first God, then ourselves, then our neighbors. Accordingly Aquinas wrote, charitate. 3 .7; Dtcrttum, Dt pen. Dist. 3 c.19.
"Out of charity a man ought to love himself more than his neighbor," and 28. De jure btlli. 1.3.3. 47.
Suarez held that "according to the order of charity it is better to succor one- 29. Above, 299. Grotius also held that it was somt>times laudable to waive the right of self·
defense. But he did not agree with Vitoria that the v ictim of an attack should accept death
rather than send his assailant to eternal damnation by killing him. The victim also might nt'<'d
23. See W. Fikentscher, ModtS of Thought in Law and Politics (Berkeley. 1988), 27-31; A 8 . timt' to repent of his sins. Grotius observed (1.3.3 ., 47).
Bozeman, NOn the Relevance of Hugo Grotius and De Jure Belli el Pacis for Our Times,· Gm- 30. De jurepratdnt, 11.
1i1ma, n.s. 1 (1980), 53- 64. 31. For an oldt>r vi<•w. diwctly contrary tn Tuck' s. St't' H. A. Rommen, The Nat urn/ IJtrr• A
24. E.g., Hobbes. 21 . " ... Grotiu s had in a sense converted the skeptical humanists' Ian· Study m f.toKal nnd Sl1<i11/ / fi~tor.v n111l l'hi/o~'l'l111 (St I .oui". 11147). 73. Rom men saw (;mtin~ ,,~"
guage of self-preservation into a languagt' of natural riJehts-that i~ into a gt'nuint>ly moral l~al rationalii>I who ~I'"" uul h111111111•111hlr ''"''"''"' "'' '"'"' lilw fmm a few l>ai>ic' prindplt"IO.
language . . . Tile same themt" nm.1 lhrough <1ll 11f Tuck' :- writingR on Grotiu~.
H
tie contrastt'd thi~ with 111<1w 11tc,.l1•1tl • lnlm" 111 llu-1111.. Hrv11l '4<·hnla.~tic-s tTganlinK thr conlt'nt
25. H . G. Hamakl'r. Ni .• ll11Koni.< C: rotii dt' j 11rr l'rnl'dllt' r m11mmlar i11s (lllf- tlagut>. IAAR). of natural l;iw
7, 10. J2. Tlwy W•'f•• tu I 'll'Of't v• '"" '""" '" llv1• In ""' h-tv. '" 1r•t o f111prlng, nml In know< ;11<1
26. 1>r 111u /'rtrf'1faf . <J, d lr1l l11 ..( Mn'"'" h·,.:· •,;•. ·· 111.. ' Mm h ·r11' ·n.,.. •ry." 111 ; "( ;rollu' .11111 (S un111111 llm•lo)(ltlr. I /"' ' 114}) I ,1111111• ltth111l1111111 llu• lh•I lw11 In llw T'r..tr.~m11r1111 top,. Jurr
Sl'ld1•n," ';IJt>; l'/111•"'"'''"' ""'' c;,.,.,.,,,,,,,.,,,. rn l•f/11 ~111! llM• olh1•1 lw11 ~I I I It 'I
324 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS GROTIUS. FROM MEDIEVAL TO MODERN 325

mental principles one could deduce other more detailed rules.33 Grotius formally between the two meanings. Jn the lnleidinge, a major work on
again argued in the same way. In the course of the De jure belli he repeat- Roman-Dutch jurisprudence, Grotius defined recht in a broad sense as
edly appealed to natural law in order to justify detailed rules of conduct what was consonant with reason and, in a strict sense, as a relationship~­
that he wanted to establish. He even argued that natural law related not tween a person and what belonged to him.35 But his mature treatment of
only to strict justice, but also to the practice of the traditional moral this theme came only in the De jure belli.
virtues.34 It would be wrong to suggest that Grotius deliberately concealed the
So far I have been arguing that Grotius was not stimulated by the medieval origins of his central teachings. There are many medieval refer-
moral relativism of contemporary skeptics to create some new theory of ences strewn among the more common classical ones in his works. {In the
natural law and natural rights. Insofar as he took note of the skeptics at De jure be/Ii for instance there were thirty-one references to Bartolus, thirty
all, he simply maintained that the old theory could be successfully re- to Baldus, and forty to Aquinas.) But occasionally, perhaps just because of
asserted in the face of their criticisms. And yet it remains true that Grotius a fondness for displaying his classical erudition, Grotius did write in a way
did display a vigorous creative imagination in his handling of the tradition that could mislead a reader about the real sources of his thought. And this
he inherited, and he did indeed play a major role in the transition from is especially true of his discussion on the meaning of ius in the De jure be/Ii.
medieval to modem thinking about natural rights. In spite of all my criti- Grotius began with the standard Aristotelian-Thomist definition. Re-
'i
cisms, I think that Tuck's argument points to an underlying truth about .l ferring to the title of his own work he wrote, "lus here signifies nothing
Grotius. The Dutch scholar was addressing the problems of a new century,
in a new style, speaking to a new audience made up mainly of Protes-
1,• other than what is just."36 Then he quickly moved on to a second meaning,
which, he wrote, was different from the first one but derived from it. This
tants and humanists. For a proper evaluation of his work we need to is Grotius's formal definition of ius as a subjective right:
understand not only how he reappropriated particular elements of the In this sense ius is a moral quality of a person, enabling him to have or do
medieval tradition but also how he adapted them to the needs of his something justly.37
own age. Let us therefore turn from modem disputes about Grotius to
an analysis of some of his own texts about rights and consider in tum This definition was of central importance for Grotius's future argument
his arguments concerning the meaning of ius naturale, the origin of a right since a major theme of the De jure be/Ii was the assertion that just wars
to property, and the relationship between individual and community in a were fought to defend or assert rights or to punish violations of them. (A
political society. long list of the things that belong to us by a " right common to mankind"
was presented in a later chapter.38) Developing further his definition
Grotius wrote that the "moral quality" could designate a "faculty" or an
NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS "aptitude." A faculty, what the jurists called the suum (one's own), meant a
An obvious place to begin is provided by Grotius's own starting right strictly so-called; an aptitude designated a claim by reason of merit
points in the De jure praedae and the De jure belli-an exploration of the that could not be legally enforced.19 Grotius was mainly interested in ius
different meanings of the key term ius, "right." As Haggenmacher noted, as facultas. This " right in a strict sense" included power (potestas), either
in the earlier work Grotius used the word ius in both its subjective and power over oneself, meaning liberty, or over others. It could also includt'
objective senses, as meaning a right or a law, but without distinguishing ownership (dominium), either absolute or less absolute as in the case of
35. lnleidi11ge lot de Hollandsche Rechls·Gtftt,.dheid, ed. F. Dovring et al. (Leiden, 19S2),
33. Summa lheologille, 1.2ae.961. Aquinas observed here that the common principles of l. l.6- 7, I.
natural law would be applied differently among different peoples "on account o f the great 36. De jrm bdl1, 1.1.3, 2.
variety of human affairs. N 37. Ibid., I. I .4, 2, " Ab hac juri" significatiunt> di versa ~t altcra, sed ab hac ipsa veni<"ns . .
34. De jure ~Iii. 2.1.9, 104. As part of h is argument about minimalism Tuck pointed out Qualitas morali." pcr<;on;w, c·omp•·h.,,,. .111 .1llc111i<I jusl<> hahendum vel agt>ndum."
that Grotius did not regard even all of the Ten Commandments AS precepts of natural law. 38. lbid., 2.2.1-24. 112 171
("Cameades,N 56-57, #Grotius and Selden," 513.) Tuck sees this as radically mnovatory. :W. Only lh<' h•r111hu1luKY wo nrw '"""' I li..-1• rrrnimlc'tl uf I luguccio's wmark c<>nturh"'
But again there are medieval precedent11. Oum• S.·ulm• tn•al.-d tlw whole · S('Cond table" o f C'arlier, " Mi\ny lhh1K• 111<• 11w"' I lh11I c lllllH•I '"' .. ,u~ht hy lmlklotl pmcC'\Juw... ." (St't' .1hovt•,
the Decalogue as posilivP dlvlnl' lnw. l'ur .-rllkl"m of hi~ ,1rx11m<"nl !!<'<' Suan•7., l>r l~ilms, 74). C.rnliuM wrn t ••ff"'' 11111111(""' """' 111 1111111 ~ 1\1 l•lnllr'~ .1..tt11Ul11n of ntlrihullvr ju~lkt• ""
4: 2 .15.9, 5.1. h.1!1<•111111.,_,.,,1tll'lrlr<1l1ath"1 th1111111 llh•m•lh "' l' '"I'"' """
326 THE I DEA Of NATURAL RIG HTS GROTIUS. FROM M EDIEVAL TO MODERN 327

usufruct; and this right could also refer to the claim of a creditor, to which .I When Grotius turned to a consideration of natural law he observed
the obligation of another corresponded.40
Finally Grotius gave a third definition of ius. Jn this sense the word -~ I that this law could be known either a priori, from a consideration of man's
rational and social nature, or a posteriori from the principles common to all
meant the same as law (lex), understood as "a rule of moral action obliging nations or at least the more advanced ones.43 He denied here that brute
us to what is right." 41 He added that a permission had the quality of law animals could be subjects of natural law-for him, as for Vitoria and
only insofar as it obliged others not to hinder the one to whom permission Suarez, natural law was a law of reason that pertained only to rational
was granted. creatures.4' Grotius's argument also involved another problem that had
The tripartite understanding of ius as "What is just," as a subjective arisen in late medieval scholasticism and that we discussed in the work of
right, and as law is precisely what we find in Suarez. So is the use of the Suarez-whether the law of nature derived its binding force simply from
words moralis and facultas to designate a right. So too is the inclusion in its conformity with right reason or rather from the will of God. It has
this faculty of both ownership and a claim to things owed (Suarez' ius in re ·1 sometimes been argued that Grotius shifted from a voluntarist position
and ius ad rem). The reference to permissive law also echoes an observation ; I in the De jure praedae to a rationalist one in the De jure belli; but really the
of Suarez. Other sixteenth-century Spanish authors and various medieval difference seems to have been only one of emphasis. In the early work, as
jurists before them had likewise given &ists of the meanings of ius that we saw, he wrote, "What God has shown to be his will is law." This seems
included the subjective sense, that is, ius as meaning a right inhering in starkly voluntaristic; but Grotius buttressed his assertion by citing a text of
persons. There is no such list of meanings in any classical source. Yet, Aquinas that referred to God's supreme reason and wisdom.45 And a little
in presenting his argument here, Grotius succeeded in quoting Aristotle, further on he referred to the "sovereign reason" granted to man by God,
Philo, Cicero, Seneca, Florentinus, Augustine, and a scholiast on Horace. "who imprinted on man the image of his own mind." 46 In the De jure belli
He did not mention any of the medieval or sixteenth-century sources Grotius made his famous comment that reason would be able to discern
in which similar accounts of the meanings of ius had been given; but in natural law "even if we were to grant that there is no God. . . ."; but he also
fact his conceptual apparatus of law and rights, the ideas that would un- acknowledged that God's will was truly a source of law. When he came to
dergird the whole subsequent work, was of medieval origin. One must give a formal definition of ius naturale Grotius, like Suarez, combined both
11
suppose that Grotius was a good enough humanist to have been aware of
. elements of thought, rationalist and voluntarist.
I
•.
this. Certainly some of his early critics saw the point dearly. The Dutch

I
Natural law is a dictate of right reason indicating that an act, on account
jurist Huber complained that Grotius's use of ills to mean a right of owner- of its conformity or lack of conformity with rational nature, has in it a
ship was not properly classical but a ''barbarism" introduced by the me- quality of moral turpitude or moral necessity, and that consequently such
d ieval canon and civil lawyers (canonistae et accursianae).41 This is indeed an act is either commanded or prohibited by God, the author of nature.47
?
true (if we forg.i ve the word "barbarism"), but it would be impossible to f The definition could have been inspired directly by Suarez; but it is also in
d iscern the fact from Grotius's text and notes. Grotius was presenting a
harmony with much earlier medieval tradition going back to Gratian's De-
medieval and late scholastic structure of argument here; his originality lay
in using the scholastic language to introduce a systematic treatise on inter-
national jurisprudence.
.I cretum and its early commentators, a tradition that saw natural law both as
a dictate of reason and as expressive of the divine will for humankind.
: Alfred Dufour has rightly observed that Grotius presented a very re-
t fined doctrine of natural law; 48 but the refinements are of a kind that will
40. Ibid., l.15, 2, " Facuhatem lurisconsulti nomine Sui appellant: nos post hac jus proprie I I
aut stricte d ictum appellabimus: sub quo continentur Potestas, tum in se, quae lil>ertas dici~ur .!
tum in alios, ut patria, do m in ica: Dominium, plenum sive minus pleno, ut ususfructus, JUS 43. De 111rr be/ti, 1.1.12, 5.
pigno ris: et creditum, cui ex adverso respondet debitum." . 44. Ibid., 1.1.11, 5.
41 . Ibid., 1.1.9, 3, uEstet tertia ju.rissignifkatioquae idem valetquod Lex . .. ut sK Regula r' 45. ~ 1ure prlk'tfne, 8. citing S11m111n //tmloxinr l .2ftt'.Q.1 . l .
..:: , ;
actuum moralium obligans ad id quod rectum est." 46. Ibid., 12.
42. Huber's comment was q uoted by Villey, "Origines," 253. Villey saw in Grotius's defi- 47. Dt ;11re lvtti. I I Ill. 1, ··111. 11i1111ml1• •••I clkt,1111111 R'<'ll'll' rntionis indicam1, aclui alk ui, t' ~
nition " the birth of an individualistic type of juridical thought." 1 cannot u nde r:\tand why 1•jus convmit-nlin ""I 111•• unvr11l••11l h1 111111 Ip•• n11t11r" rftllonall, inf'!l..w mt>rnll'm turpl·
Tully saw the definitio n as " f'lid ing tlw con<"t"J>t o f a rixht to <•m"s Jut•." C:mtius was much tudinem i'IUI IW<"<'lll•ll"h'lll 111111 •lr111. "' 01111••1111•111..1 •I• " " ' ·Ion• nnlurAt' l>t'l• lalt•m adum 11111
concerned with right!! arislnK Imm n>11lrndunl 1>11liK11linn". St't' I Tully, I\ l>i.. .·ours.-of f'n'Jlf'rl_I( v 1•l,\n i'llll rr.11'dpl ..
(Camt>ridKt', IQllO). 711. 4H A. I l11fu11r. f l11•ll• 1f~ /"111111111., 1/11•11JhllUl~/11 t.1ol1 11r~ ( l'1u I~. 11111 f ). h:l.
328 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIG HTS GROTIUS. FROM M EDIEVAL TO M ODERN 329

easily be recognized by anyone familiar with earlier traditions of writ- So far the argument was entirely traditional. We have traced the con-
ing on this theme. Grotius held, for instance, that the precepts of the Jaw cept of a permissive natural law relating to property and liberty from the
of nature were unchangeable, even by God, but he also held that some twelfth-century Decretists to Vitoria and Suarez. But Grotius now applied
natural laws came into play only as a result of human acts. This is the the old doctrine in a new way. He went on to assert that the convoking
"relative" or "suppositious" natural law that we first encountered in the of church councils pertained to natural law (since man was by nature a
canonist Alanus and then in Ockham and Suarez. The examples Grotius sociable creature); but, Grotius argued, only permissive natural law was
gave were similar to those of his predecessors. Private property was first involved here. To understand his purpose we need to recall that, when
established by human volition, but, once instituted, it was protected by Grotius wrote the De imperio, the Dutch church was divided by a doctrinal
the natural law forbidding theft. A debtor was obliged by natural law to quarrel. One group wanted to summon a national church synod to impose
pay what he owed to his creditor, but if the creditor voluntarily remitted a rigorously defined doctrine of predestination on all the Dutch congrega-
the debt, the obligation no longer existed. As Ockham had explained, in tions. The other group, which Grotius supported, favored a less rigorous,
such cases natural law applied "unless the contrary is enacted with the more tolerant approach. Grotius wanted, therefore, to prevent the sum-
consent of those concerned." 49 moning of the proposed synod and to have the civil authority intervene in
Grotius also made extensive use of the medieval concept of permis- order to uphold a degree of toleration in church affairs. Hence his argu-
sive natural law as a locus of rights. The first two basic laws that we en- ment that the convocation of synods was not a precept of natural law but
countered in the De jure praedae were permissive ones-they declared that pertained only to the permissive law that was subject to the authority of
it was licit, or permitted, to defend one·s own life and to acquire the ne- the human legislator." It is a striking example of how Grotius could use a
cessities of life. ln the De jure be/Ii Grotius wrote that, even before the in- traditional medieval argument for a quite new purpose. It is also charac-
troduction of private property, each person's life, limbs and liberty were teristic of Grotius that he wanted the civil authority to intervene in church
his own, and each one had a right to use and consume whatever nature affairs, not in order to suppress dissent, but rather to restrain religious
required; and, he added, if a person's rights were attacked natural law fanaticism.
permitted him to resist force with force. 50 Grotius's most interesting dis-
cussion of permissive natural law came in the De imperio, written in 1616.
THE RIGHT TO PROPERTY
Here Grotius wrote, " By nature it is our right to do all things that are
not evil in themselves."51 But Grotius was not primarily concerned in this If we tum now to Grotius's theory of property we again find a pattern
context with the natural rights of individuals; he wanted particularly to of medieval argumentation adapted to serve a new purpose. At the time
make the point that permissive natural law could be changed by human the Dutch scholar wrote there already existed a rich tradition of thought
legislation and to apply the argument in a new way to a contemporary dis- about the origin of individual possessions, and Grotius seems to have
pute in the Dutch church. experimented with various elements of this tradition in several of his
There were two kinds of natural law, Grotius explained. The first de- works. ln the course of them he moved from a theory of property as exist-
fined immutable rules of conduct; for instance, to honor God, to love our ing naturally from the beginning of humankind to the more common
parents, not to harm the innocent. These laws could not be changed by any medieval position which held that the institution of private property was
human act. But there was a second kind of natural law that was merely permitted by natural law and suggested by natural reason, but that the
permissive; it concerned such things as community of property and per- first actual division required human agreement and consent.
sonal liberty. This kind of natural Jaw could be changed and had been Grotius first addressed this issue in the De jure praedae where his prin-
changed by the human laws introducing private property and servitude.52 cipal purpose was to argue that no nation could claim for itself ownership
of the open sea. (The Portugue>e were trying to exclude the Dutch from
49. o~ ju re ~Iii, l.1.10, 4-5. the East Indies lradt•.) I h• first diS<·usst•d the a rgument that the pope was,
SO. lbid., 1.2.1, 16-17. Grotius referred to permissive ni\tural law at 2.3.5, 127, and to act~
permitted Nby the force of narural liberty" at 2.2.21, 121. ~al~ 1.1.17, 'I, 2.25. 115 and lnlri-
by divine right, 1<•111por.1l l11ril ur th1• wholl· world and so entitled to bestow
dingt, 1.2.6, 4. In the background of tilt~ ar11Ktmwnt11 was thl' olcl l<'lll o f r>i,~NI q.2.45. " Vim
enim vi defenden- om~ k-x•"' nnt11l1u11u• lurA 1wrmlttunt " 5J. 1'1i<I , 7 J . 11:0 11,••,., I• " • "' '"'" ' ' """ 111 1hr "''" 11111<· of the• arfAlr. Mnmln•, thr
51. IJr inr/lf"ri11 '"'""'""""'1~•lr~t11/11111.1,..,, ""' "' (l'r"nl.lurt. lhllO). 7 7.. IQ S l,1<llh11lclc-r, dtllM' In •111'1"''' lllt' I l.1111•1 I'"' 11' 1lw <'11•1111111 oll•p11h•N 11'< 1In ll1r lmprll'<•lllll<'lll
52. 11>1.1 nl ( :mllu• ""''hi• •111-11111•111 ••Ill'
330 TuE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS GROTIUS. FROM MEDIEVAL TO MODERN 331

portions of the globe on whomever he pleased. Here Grotius could quote use there could be no separation between use and ownership.58 Food and
Spanish authors like Vitoria and Vazquez in support of his argument, but drink, for instance, became part of the very substance of the user and so
he also remembered to mention the commentary of Innocent IV on the necessarily belonged to him to the exclusion of anyone else.
Decretals and the canonist Huguccio, who had defended a dualist theory of
papacy and empire at the end of the twelfth century.~ Grotius's own first . This was the basis of Grotius's first theory of property. He next wrote
that, by a logical process, ownership was extended to things that were par-

I
theory of property was based, rather oddly it might seem, on another tially consumed. in use like clothing. Then, with a considerable leap of the
group of canonistic texts, those relating to the Franciscan poverty dispute imagination, Grotius explained. that the same principle was seen to extend
of the fourteenth century.55 Grotius began with some definitions. In his necessarily to arable land and pastures since, although they were not actu-
own day, he explained, the word domfr1ium referred to the exclusive own- ally consumed in use, their use was related to consumption, that is to the
ership of something, and the word "common" to ownership by a defined .Yi_ production of consumable goods.S9 After property had come to exist in this
group. But, for lack of a more adequate vocabulary, the same terms were
applied analogically to a primordial condition of humankind when no pri-
vate property existed. In references to that era the word dominium meant
ii.
~
fashion a law was established., imitating nature, and decreeing that owner-
ship should be acquired by occupation. In the final stage of his argument
Grotius maintained that the open sea could not be occupied (and so could
simply a faculty of using things common to all; and, according to the scho- not become anyone's property) both because of its vastness and because
lastics, Grotius noted, this use was a "use of fact," not of law.56 it was intrinsically suited to the common use of all mankind.60 And so Gro-
To explain "use of fact" Grotius cited the decree Exiit of Nicholas tius reached his desired conclusion about the freedom of the seas. Here
III, the starting point of the dispute about Franciscan poverty. In his usual again, he had taken a medieval structure of argument out of its original
fashion Grotius decorated his text with allusions to classical mythology context and applied it to a problem of his own age.
and with quotations from Cicero and Seneca and Horace; but the key The argument of Grotius may remind us of a similar, well-known one
terms of his argument were really drawn from the old quarrel between .•
of John Locke. "He that is nourished by the acorns he picked up ... has
John XXII and the Franciscans. In the first age of humanity, Grotius ex- certainly appropriated them to himself." The underlying assumption was
plained, there was no dominion of property in the modem sense. God again that or john XXII; the actual consumption of something certainly
gave all things to the whole human race, not to this or that individual. made one the owner of it. But Locke perceived that, in order to consume
Whatever dominion did exist was vague and indefinite, and it referred to licitly the acorns that had originally belonged to the common stock of
use rather than ownership.57 So far Grotius seems to have presented the mankind, a person must first have had a right to them. Grotius simply as-
primordial state of humanity just as the dissident Franciscans saw it. There sumed that the initial act of consumption itself established an individual
was use of fact but no private property. But for the next step in his ar- right, upon which all subsequent rights of property were modeled. It was
gument he borrowed a central thesis of John XXII, citing the pope's decre- not an altogether satisfactory argument, especially when applied to non-
tals Ad conditorem and Quia quorundam. As regards things consumed in consumables. Grotius failed to explain why others should respect the right
of one who carved out lands for himself from the common stock.
54. De ju" pratdae, 210. l doubt whether Grotius had actually read Huguccio. He probably Grotius amplified. his argument in the Jnleidinge. He repeated here that
took the reference at second-hand from Vitoria who, like Grotius referred to Huguccio as some things were consumed in use and called this a kind of ownership
#Hugo.~ Vitoria gave the reference to Huguccio's text incorrectly as Dist. 69 of the Dtc"tum
"not contrary to natural law." Moreover, reason dictated that things be-
(instead of Dist. 96), and the same mistake occurs in Grotius. In the Perei'ia-Peres Mendes edi-
tion of the De Indis Huguccio is incorrectly identified as Hugh of Sl Victor.
longing to no one (the res nullius of Roman law) should be owned by the
SS. It is not really surprising that Grotius was familiar with this material. The Franciscan first occupant. Grotius also argued here that each one was required to re-
d ispute was discussed by several of the Spanish authors whose work he knew, e .g., ~Soto, spect the property that others had acquired. by the natural law forbidding
Molina and Suarez. The relevant texts of Nicholas III and John XXll were available to him a person to do to others what he did not want done to himself. Finally, tw
in various printed editions of the Corpus iuris C11nonic1. On Grotius's other sources see R. Feen- l'Xplained th<tl, aftt•r political !mcit•lit•s wt.•rt• established, civil laws rcgu-
stra, "Der Eigentumsbegriff bei Hugo Grotius im Licht einiger mittclaltlicher und spat-
scholastiker QueUen," in FestschriftJilr Franz Wirackrr, ed. 0 . Behrends Mal. (Gottingen, 1978), SR. Ibid., 216, <·.,,,, 1•111111 '"" 11l11I ""'"'"""' "· 111111111111 11"11$ in ;il>u~u consislil . .. 111 dho c•t
209-34. pulu, proprirt11~ ~l"llm 1111111•il1'111Olh11•11111111 • r j11111 IA ••mi< 11il
56. Dt jurt proedae, 214.
~"- lhid
57. Ibid.• 21 s. Ml. lhid . 11 11
r
332 THE IDEA O F NATURAL. RIGHTS GROTIUS. FROM M EDIEVAL TO MODERN 333

lated the various ways of acquiring ownership.61 These were essentially with a doctrine that had a continuous history from the time of Huguccio
the same arguments that lnnoo:?nt TV had presented in mid-thirteenth onward.
century. In discussing the origin of property, Grotius combined a historical
In the De jure belfi, Grotius finally came to accept the more common narrative with a theory of rational natural law. To him, as to some of his
medieval doctrine that community consent was needed to establish in- medieval predecessors, the two approaches did not seem incompatible
dividual property rights in the first place. In this work he presented a with one another. Natural reason dictated different responses in different
historical account of the development of private property, beginning historical circumstances.63 Grotius's account of an original agreement by
with an age of innocence and common ownership that he illustrated from all of humankind evoked the ironical criticism of Filmer, and this in tum
both the Book of Genesis and the classical myth of a golden age. After the stimulated Locke to produce his labor theory of property. Others contin-
creation of the world, and then again after the Flood, God gave to the ued to defend some version of Grotius's argument. Here again Grotius
human race a general right over alt inferior things. At first humans lived in stood between the old and the new. His theory of property appealed to En-
a primitive simplicity marked by "ignorance of vices rather than knowl- lightenment writers like Burlamaqui and even Hume/'4 but it would also
edge of virtue." But this primitive harmony was disturbed by the acqui- have been intelligjble to Ockham or Innocent IV or Huguccio.
sition of knowledge (symbolized by the Tree of Knowledge) through
which man "degenerated into craftiness," and by rivalries and ambition.
Also people became dissatisfied with the spontaneous products of the ..•
~
INDIVIDUALS, SOctETY, AND SOVEREIGNTY
earth and chose a more refined way of life that necessitated the practice of I
In discussing the origin of the state Grotius again took up a late me-
various industries; and from this there arose a lack of fairness in sharing dieval tradition of thought and developed it in his own way. Vitoria had
out the fruits of labor. For all these reasons the old common way of life maintained that a commonwealth was formed by an association of indi-
became impracticable and private property was instituted. viduals; but (at least in his early work) he held that civil power was
This came about not by an act of will alone . . . but rather by a kind of infused into the community by a direct grant of God. Suarez dispensed
agreement, either expressed, as by a division, or tacit as by occupation.61 with the need for any direct divine intervention, arguing that the power
to form political societies was inherent in human nature from the begin-
The right of the first occupant was now based on the consent of the ning; but he still acknowledged that the political community possessed

I
community. We must suppose, Grotius wrote, that, once common property powers-especially the power to punish-that had not belonged to the in-
had been abandoned and a division not yet made, all agreed that what dividuals who formed the association. Grotius took the argument a step
each one occupied should be his own. Grotius added a reservation, that further. He maintained that a right to punish already existed in individuals
was common to all the theories of property we have considered, about in the state of nature before any civil authority was instituted. Then
rights in a case of extreme necessity. Like Suarez he looked back to the he argued that, just as a magistrate's right came from the community, so
original agreement establishing private property. We are forced to believe, too the community's right came from the individuals who joined together
he wrote, that those who originally introduced individual ownership in- to form it. Grotius, in effect, turned Vitoria's argument upside down. The
tended to depart as little as possible from natural equity. So in case of Spanish scholar maintained that, since the state had a power to inflict
extreme need the original right of use would revive just as though prop- punishment that did not inhere in individuals, the power must have been
erty had remained common. A person who took the property of another to conferred by God. Grotius maintained that, since the power of the com-
preserve his own life was not guilty of theft. Here again, we are dealing monwealth came from its individual members, and since no one could
confer a right he did not possess, the individuals must have possessed the
61. lnltidingt, 2.3.2, SO. Grotius added here that each one could keep what he acquired by right to punish before the state was formed .
his own industry and labor.
62. Dt jure btlli, 2.2.2, 114, "Simul discimus quo modo res in proprietatem iv<'rint: n<>n
animi actu solo . . . sed pacto quodam aut exprt'!'llO ut per divi~ionem, aut ta<ito ut pt•r occu · t.1. Cummt•nl intt 1111 I .1nll11•. s 1,.l'hr11 ll11dd1• w m h · uf "The h isto ric11l l"sk hullt Into
pationem, simulatque enim cnmmunio d i11pliruil, Ill'<" in~tituta t'!lt ciiv iiiio, cl'f'l!l<'ri dC'b<'t inl<'r mod<'rn natur.,l l11w ., S.... S l111d.t... N11/111fll I' "'' c11ul llrr 111rory of Pm~rt.v. Grotius lo I lumr
omnes coo venis!'I<', ut •1ucid <t11i~1111• ,,....."l'"-·l iel prnpriu m h,1llt•n•t ·· Ttw rl'fe•r..nn• I<> t;,dt (< hfor<I. 11)<11), '.''i 11 11(1
con!lf'nt 11<-t•mii an ,,.·ho c1f Vll111 In M . 1) J'orlw~. I l11rrrr • l '/11/,,.,,,,,,,, r1/ /'1•/f111 •I• 11111h1i. t11•·. 111'/'I), 77
334 THE lr>EA OF NAl\JRAL RIGHTS GROTIUS. FROM MEDIEVAL TO M ODERN 335

Therefore, since no one can transfer something that he did not have, it in the social life of medieval guilds and communes,68 in medieval corpora-
seems necessary that the right was held by private individuals before it tion law, and in the sort of political theology that we considered earlier in
was held by the commonwealth .. . punishment has a natural origin, but the writing of Gerson, and then in Vitoria and Suarez. This way of thinking
the state is formed by agreement.... Human society is from nature but still characterized the work of Grotius.
civil society from deliberate institution.c.s In the l11/eidi11ge Grotius wrote that a political community possessed a
This was a strong statement of the social contract theory that would "higher right" than its individual members; but this was because the mem-
often recur in seventeenth-century doctrines of natural rights. It seems bers could not be safeguarded unless the community was preserved.69
highly individualistic. But Grotius's later comments on the formation of Similarly Grotius wrote in the De jure belli that a commonwealth enjoyed
political societies were more ambivalent. In the De jure belli he balanced the the greatest right over its members; but he also maintained that the pur-
individualism of his earlier doctrine by insisting also on the sociable nature pose of the state was to safeguard each individual in the possession of
of man. His argument about the origin of the state in this book was very what was his own. 70 He added that it was not contrary to the nature of
similar to that presented by Vitoria before the Spaniard introduced the society for individuals to look out for their own advantage provided that
theme of divine right into his work. Humans could not survive or live they did not violate the rights of others.71 Even in writing about the
a satisfying life as isolated individuals or scattered families; so the es- common good Grotius could stress the advantage of individuals. He wrote
tablishment of civil communities was, in a sense, motivated by "oblique that a person should prefer his own good to that of another but should
self-interest"; 66 but for Vitoria man was also, by nature, a social animal. prefer the good of the whole community still more; but this was because
And Grotius too explained that the very nature of man, "the mother of the the good of the community included the goods of the individual mem-
law of nature," would lead us to form civil societies even if we lacked for bers.n Evidently Grotius did not intend individuals to be merely sub-
nothing.67 ordinate parts of a holistic organic community; each had his own sphere of
Grotius's discussions on the relationship between individuals and interests where he could legitimately pursue his own advantage. Some-
community within a civil society were very nuanced. If we were to put all times, indeed, Grotius wrote as though individual advantage was the sole
his relevant comments together side by side they might seem often to con- basis of social order and altruism only a kind of enlightened self-interest.
tradict one another; but to see them in this way would be to ignore the But this was not his real intention; just as when he discussed the origi-
tradition of thought within which Grotius was working. Medieval intellec- nal formation of the state, the appeals to self-interest were balanced by
tuals had been able to hold together, in coherent structures of thought, references to human sociability. Disputing an argument of Vazquez that
ideas that later thinkers would sometimes treat as polar opposites. Thus a person should put his own interest before that of the state, Grotius
they found room in their works for rationalism and voluntarism, na.t ure wrote, "We do desire the safety of the state for our own sakes, but not
and history, love of self and love of neighbor. Above all they emphasized only for ourselves, rather for ourselves and others too." 73 And, again, "We
bo;l1 individual rights and the common good as complementary rather are drawn to friendship spontaneously and by our own nature ... charity
than conflicting aspects of the human condition. We can find this attitude often advises me, sometimes commands me to put the good of many

. I
65. Dt jure praedat, 91-92. See Haggerunacher, Guerre justt, 141- 48. Grotius answered the
argument of Vitoria and Suarez almost inadvertently. In the context of t~e passage quoted he 68. Antony Black gave an admirable delineation of medieval communal life that m11tnti.•
was not primarily concerned with the origin of the state. He was pursumg an argument that 11111/nndis might define the attitude of Grotius too. See his Guilds and Civil Socitly. 65, - nu•
private warfare might be licit in exceptional circumstances whe~ ~o jud~cial recou~ wa_s crucial point about guilds and communes was that here individ11ation and association Wt'nl li1111rl
available. Th.is led him to discuss the situation that existed before ovil magistrates were msll- i11 /in11d."
tuted. He mentioned the origin of civil power as something incidental to his main argument. 69. /nlridingr. 2..3.2, 52.
In his later work Grotius continued to assert that a right to punish existed in the state of 70. DI' jurr /xiii, 2 ..'i21. l'i7. "C"o nso.-i,1111• 'I'"' multi patrt>s familiarum in unum populmn
nature; but he did not apply the argument to the origin of civil pow<'r. It became of major po- .K (°ivitatC'm CC)('unl m... in111n1 cl.cl ju~ ·~•rpc •rl m pitrlc..,"'; I 2.1. 16. "Nam socirla:o1 '"' h•urlll 111
litical significance only when Locke prescnled a ~imilar doctrine as part o f hi.~ rcspon~ to SUU0 1 CUiquc• ~"l1Vl10l -.at' I llllUUlllf• orw IU • ll1t~pt r11ticUU' ••
Filmer's patriarchal theory. 71. It.id., 1.2 I, 17. "'Nun r•I r11t11 '''""" ••" lrlnll~ lhclur.m1 sihi prollpin •n'. 111<1111• n 111·
66. Q . Skinnt-r, 17tl' Fo11ndatio11~ 11{ Morfnn f'c•/ilirn/ T/1m11i:lrl. 2 vol~ . (C:amhridg1•, 197R), "ult-rt•. dum j1111.1llc-11um " "" tul\"h11 •·
2: 160. 72. /Jr ;11rq•tnr1/nr. JI
t.7. I Ir ;11,,. l.,./lr. l'mlr.~m11rw1 . 4 7 l /11" /111.-Jorlli. J I •J. UM
336 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHn GROTIUS. FROM MEDIEVAL TO MODERN 337

above my own good."74 In one of his most holistic statements Grotius Roman and Jewish law, a man could sell himself into slavery; in the same
declared, contrary to the view of most moral theologians, that an innocent way, he argued, a whole people could submit itself to an absolute ruler,
person could be handed over to be killed by an enemy army if this would retaining no vestige of power for itself. This could happen, for instance,
save the whole community.75 But he also wrote that it would be a violation if a people threatened by destruction or starvation turned to an absolute
of natural law for a ruler to deprive his subjects of their rights without just monarch for succor.8 1 In another discussion on slavery Grotius remarked
cause.76 that, "if the condition is accepted within natural limits it contains no ele-
In this way of thinking individual rights could flourish only in a well- ment of undue severity."82 (One is reminded of David Davis's comment
ordered society; but a society could flourish only if the individual mem- that early modem discussions of slavery seem always to come from a
bers cared, not only for their own well-being, but for that of their fellow world remote from the real one that contained "the disease and sicken-
members and of the whole community. Grotius does not confront us with ing stench of the slave ships."53) Grotius's argument has an ugly sound in
isolated individuals facing an omnipotent state but with human persons, mode m ears, but one can see why he needed to include it in his work. He
sociable by nature, bound by ties of friendship and mutual support, each was trying to set out the principles of a system of international law that
acknowledging a duty to respect the rights of others. could apply to all states. Some of them were indeed dominated by ab-
I want finally to consider the views of Grotius on sovereignty and the solute governments ruling over subject peoples; a universal system had to
right of resistance. He introduced these themes with a new definition of include such regimes.
the "subject" in whom sovereignty inhered: There is no reason to suppose that Grotius favored absolutism; he
was not here discussing the best form of government, he explained, but
Let us see, then, what subject holds the supreme power. The subject is
the possibly legitimate forms. His argument then continued with an ac-
either common or special. Just as the body is the common subject of the
power of sight, the eye a special subject, so too the commonwealth, which count of a variety of constitutional arrangements in which the exercise
we defined above as a perfect association, is the common subject of ..
~ I j
of sovereignty was restricted or diffused in various ways. Everything de-
pended on the kind of regime that a people chose to establish in the first
supreme power."
"l place. An assembly of estates might have the power to enact laws bind-
The comparison of the political community with a human body was a very I ing on the king; a king' s exercise of sovereignty could be restricted by his
old metaphor, but Grotius here used it in a new way; his definition empha-
sized the abstract nature of the state by distinguishing between the
I own promises; a sovereign ruler might hold power only for a limited time
like a Dictator in ancient Rome; a people might reserve certain powers
underlying sovereignty of the whole and the exercise of sovereignty by the to itself when instituting a king; and there could be various forms of mixed
government that a commonwealth instituted. The essential characteristic constitution.114
of sovereignty, according to Grotius, was that its holder was not legally When Grotius considered specifically the right of resistance to an es-
subject to any superior authority. Sovereignty did not consist in an unlim- tablished government he was continuing, in a rather moderate fashion, a
ited power of imposing obligations.78 Subjects were not required to obey tradition of writing against tyranny that we often encounter in medieval
a law that commanded something dearly wrong or even a manifestly fool- .ind early modern sources. Like Suarez, he treated resistance to tyranny
ish and ridiculous law.79 Rulers were bound by natural law, divine law and .is a form of just warfare based on the right of self-defense. " By naturt-,"
the law of nations.80 he wrote, "everyone is the defender of his own rights; that is why Wl'
In spite on such considerations, Grotius included in the De jure belli a .ire given hands.''85 But this natural right of resisting injury was restricted
notorious defense of absolutism. He pointed out that, according to both when a civil society was instituted. The state then acquired a "greatc>r
74. Ibid.
right" over individuals and their property in order to maintain public trnn-
75. Ibid., 2.25.3, 411 . quility. Hence there could h<' no Kt.' rwral right to resist the authority of tht>
76. Ibid., 214.8, 258.
77. !bid., l.3.7, 52. II I. lhid., L:ll!, 'iJ.
78. Ibid., "Summa autem illa dicitur, cujus actus elteriu~ juri non ioubsunt . . . ."; 112. lhid .• 25.27. l'ill C11•ll110 ... 1.t... 1 h 1•11• ''"'' "m.•~h·r tli.t nol h .wt• a riKhl of Ill•• Ml<I
2.14.12, 159, " . .. ncque mim obllgandi infinilil pote~la~ i'ld lmp<"r·ium reel.- t>xerct'fldum •••·.1th ov.-r a s lav•• .1ncl lh"'I "'ol"'v" 1 11111•1 lh Hlv '"'~'' lltMhl lo "'v11l,l 1•"•"•'!l•ivt• t'rtll"lly.
nca!SSaria ~t ." 11.1. D. fl I >.ivi~. Hi,. 1'111/r/t111 •t/ "''" '" ~ 111 Wr'•l1·111 t 11/1,,,, (11'1,,1·" · NY, IWlf>), lllH
79. Ibid., l.4. l , H0; 7.. 4. 12,:Z~I 114. I Ir 1urr· 1~·111. I I IO Jll, 'I'/ ,,.,
HO. Ibid .• U . 111, r.I. II'• lh1<I , I '• I. <IH
338 TuE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS GROTIUS. FROM M EDIEVAL TO MODERN 339

state; that would lead to anarchy.86 Grotius would not even countenance mode of reasoning could appeal to his a priori arguments. The medieval
the Calvinist doctrine that inferior magistrates had an inherent right to tradition was multifaceted and, in transmitting many elements of it,
resist on behalf of the whole people.87 But he did acknowledge that a right Grotius left various choices open to his successors who would understand
of resistance could revive in circumstances of extreme necessity. He wrote his writings in various ways. One might apply to his work too the quota-
that he would not condemn either individuals or a minority of the people tions that I used earlier in discussing the medieval canonists. "[A].ny text
who, in the last resort, defended themselves against atrocious cruelty, may be an actor in an indefinite series of linguistic processes'' and " [A]/l
provided they did not abandon consideration of the common good. But linguistic interpretation involves interpretation by an audience."'lZ
Grotius held that, even in such extreme circumstances, the person of the We are still left with a problem. In writing on all the aspects of natu-
king had to be spared.1111 It was different with a usurper who seized power ral rights theories that we have been considering-the meanings of ius,
by force; because he was making war on the whole people he could licitly the idea of a permissive natural law, the origin of property, the relation of
be killed by anyone, even a private individual.89 Other grounds of resis- individual to community, the right of resistance-Grotius seems to have
tance depended on the form of government that a people had established I, '
been continuing medieval lines of thought. But, if this was so, why did
for itself. It might be specified in the original compact that a ruler could be ?;·•
his contemporaries and his successors for more than a century so often
deposed if he violated some particular law; or the people might resist if see him as an innovator, the founder of a new theory of natural law and

I
a king grasped after some power that had not been granted to him or if natural rights? It was partly of course because, to many readers, his hu-
the people had reserved a right of resistance to itself when it instituted manist style of writing seemed to come from a world far removed from the
a ruler.90 dusty technicalities of late medieval scholasticism. Haggenmacher real-
Grotius summed up his teaching on the various forms of government ized this when he chose as an epigraph to introduce his study of Grotius
in a characteristic phrase: "Just as, in fact, there are many ways of living, .'{:
1 some words of C.N.S. Woolf: "What men say is not the only important
some being better than others, and out of so many ways each is free to "·
thing; often it is equally important to know how they said it." One is
choose the one he wants, so also a people can select the form of govern-
ment it wishes.'191 A part of Grotius's appeal to later political theorists lay
-~
,/.
1'
reminded of Gerson's statement: " I shall not say things d ifferent from
others, but perhaps differently." To say that Grotius merely restated old
in the fact that his arguments were often open ended in this way. Monar- l
I ideas in a new way might seem to trivialize his work; but that would miss
chists could point to Grotius's defense of absolutism as a legitimate form the point of his achievement. Gerson's different way of saying things was
of government; constitutionalists could explore further his account of the of great importance for the future, and so was that of Grotius. This was
various ways in which sovereignty could be limited. Rationalists could because, like Gerson, Grotius was deploying old arguments, not only in a
emphasize Grotius's Etiamsi daremus ("Even if we grant that there is new idiom, but also in a changed context where they took on new mean-
no God .. .."); Christian rights theorists could insist on his teaching that ings and found a new significance.
God's free will was a source of law. Empiricists could treasure Grotius's Grotius was in fact using the medieval tradition of thought about
vast array of historical examples; those who preferred a mathematical natural law and natural rights to sustain a new vision of the world and the
church. Many Catholic authors- though by no means all-had given up
86. Ibid ., 1.4.2, 80, ~Et naturaliter quidem omnes ad an:endum a se injuriam jus habent re- the view of the medieval hierocrats who held that the pope was a temporal
sistend i. . .. Sed civili societate ad tuendam tranquillitatem instituta, statim civitati jus lord of the whole world. But Catholic thinkers still commonly maintained
quoddam majus in nos et nostra nascitur.. .. Potes! igitur civitas jus illud resistendi promis-
that the pope possessed at least an "indirect" power by virtue of which
cuum publicae pads et o rdinis causa prohibere. .. . Nam si maneat promiscuum illud
resistendi jus, non jam civitas erit, sed d issociata multitudo. h
he could intervene in temporal affairs to attain spiritual ends. Through his
87. Ibid., J.4.6, 84. indirect power the pope could release subjects from oaths of allegiance,
88. Ibid.. 1.4.7, 87, attamen indiscriminatirn damnare aut singu las aut partem populi
N • •• depose a heretical monarch, launch wars to extend or defend the Chris-
minorem, quae ultimo necessitatis praesidio sic o lim usa s it, u t interim et communis boni l't'- tian faith. The Catholic id(•al was a world order in which the pope was
spectum no n deferat vix ausim .... Illa interim caulio lenenda <'~I. etiam in tali periculo
supreme in s piritu.11 .1fl.tir11 1111d h114' 11 rnn11idC'rahl<' authority to regulatt'
personae regis parcendum .... "
89. Ibid .. J.4.16, 91-92, "Al· primum, ~i ht•llo injtLqtn . . . imp<>rium .1rrip11erit . . . a quo lil>l-1 temporal mattc•r!'I .1bo. l111 ·011tt11Ht ht thl11, ( :rotiw1 <>nvisage d a world madt•
etiam privato jun' pof('j<t lnlt'rfkl " up of fn~ ~ovc•n·l~n Hll\h•11, ( ' h rh•tl111111ntl 111111( "hri11tia11, owing allt•giann•
Q(l. ll>ld., 1.4 12 -14, 'H
·~I . /hid., I :1 II. 'I.I •n l\huvr. 47
f l

340 THE IDEA OF NATURA\. RIGliTS GROTIUS. FROM MELJJEVAL TO MODERN 341

to no external superior.93 It was a world in which commercial rivalries as Wolff, in whom the traces of medieval thought are still very evident. I also
well as religious conflicts had become a major cause of wars. A degree of think that Hobbes's attempt to combine fragments of medieval natural law
order and harmony in such a world could be maintained, Grotius thought, doctrine with his own radically different world-view produced incoher-
not by an appeal to some overriding spiritual authority, but by the ences between the different branches of his thought and lacunae within the
common consent of all nations to the code of international conduct that he political writings themselves.'5 Hobbes's great gift was for rhetoric, not for
had diligently worked out for them. logic-that is why his Leviathan is such a masterpiece of English prose.
Grotius's vision of the church was different too, and unusual for his Everyone notes that Hobbes intended to argue like a mathematician, but it
age. Catholic thinkers generally agreed that forced conversion of infidels .;
is seldom observed that he was very bad at mathematics. In a mathemati-
was not permissible, but they all took for granted the persecution of dis- ' cal argument rigorous logic is essential and its absence readily apparent.
sident Christians. For them the Roman Catholic church proclaimed the Hobbes's ventures into mathematics are absurdities.
one true faith and those who apostatized from it could be punished as These are complex issues. It is at least clear that, in Hobbes's theory,
heretics-even by death in the last resort. Suarez expounded this doc- the natural state of humankind was one of "war of all against all," that
trine quite contentedly as any other Jesuit of his age would have d one. ~ everyone had a natural right to everything, "even to another's body," and
But Grotius rejected the use of physical coercion as a way of responding to that no one had a duty to respect the rights of others. But how can this

I
differences of opinion among the various groups of Christians.94 He cher- conceivably be regarded as the origin of modem rights theories? What
ished a dream of a reunited Christendom in which all the churches could modem defender of natural rights or human rights is asserting such a doc-
cohere around a common core of Christian faith, tolerating differences on trine? Even contemporary libertarians, who might seem dose to Hobbes in
peripheral matters and respecting each others various rites and practices. that they put individual rights at the center of their political theory, have
j
Grotius's account of independent sovereign states, owing no external generally rejected his teachings and adopted a more Aristotelian view of
allegiance to any spiritual or temporal power, reflected the emerging re- human nature.%
alities of the seventeenth century. His vision of a universally accepted in- Let us return for a few final words to Grotius. We all know intellectu-
ternational law and of a reunited church were only idealistic hopes for the ally, but it is sometimes hard to grasp imaginatively, the bitter hatred of
future. But, for one reason or the other-because of the realism or because early Protestants for every aspect of the medieval Catholic church and the
of the idealism- later generations of political thinkers often looked back deep disdain of humanists for the inelegant but workmanlike prose of
on the Dutch scholar as a founding father of their discipline. His work in- the medieval scholastics. Protestants and humanists wanted to tum their
fluenced all the major rights theorists of the next century, Selden and backs on a thousand years of European history and return to an idealized
Hobbes and Locke in England, Pufendorf and Leibniz and Thomasius in ancient world of classical culture and primitive Christianity. It was a hope-
Germany, Domat and Pothier in France. less enterprise. The whole structure of Western society as it existed in
Of all these later writers, Hobbes is the most difficult and controver- the early modern era had been shaped by centuries of medieval experi-
sial. This is no place for an extended discussion of his work, but it would ence. The nations of Europe were medieval in origin; so were their lan-
be wrong to pass it over entirely without comment since there still exists
a considerable school of thought maintaining that Hobbes-not Ockham, ~. II guages, their monarchies, their courts of judicature, their assemblies of
estates. And medieval thinkers had also developed the concept of natural
not Gerson, not Grotius-was the true originator of a modem theory of
natural rights and that he expounded this theory with rigorous logic in his
political writings. Here I can do little more than indicate my disagreement
f 1
rights that was becoming of central importance in early modem political

t
95. Michael Oakeshott admired Hobbes's intellect but still wrote of his work, ff r-.·w .....
with such views. To me it seems that Hobbes's work is best seen as an counts of it do not end with tilt> dC'!t'<lion of a smn' of simple errors.... Stt "Introduction" to
ff

aberration from the mainstream of natural rights thinking that flowed /.r111alknn (O xford, 1'14h), Ii ( l11k•·•holl !'lnw 1lnhho'!'I :is a continuator of chango'!'I " whi,·h h ... 1
from the medieval jurists through Ockham, Gerson, and Grotius to Pufen- '"' I hei•n pion(>(•n'<i d•i••Oy l>y tlu- 1h.-nl111ti·"'" nl 1111" fifr.-.·nlh .1n.t !liXtl'('nth renturi~" (lili). 'fo nw.
dorf and Locke and writers of the Enlightenment like Burlamaqui and .1s noted ahov•·. I le •hi>•·".,..,....,. m111<• olo•vl1111I l >11" 1•rr"41t1.,I rn•lt• I might add that I firllt hc1(nn
to study I lnhl'4•• ''" """ llfly V•'""' "K'' "" "" 11wh•11trn1h1,1t.- Ill ( ),1k1·~holl 'l' polilkal lhrory
cunrs«' .11 ( "11mhrnl1t••
9'.l. On th<' difff'n•nt worhl vir w" of l :rnliu~ ""ti tlw Sp1m i'4h .,·hol"•lic ·~ so·•• I M11!.11>on, '16. c>n thl~ ""' tllt' '""' '""'""tu Mrto """· """""""'"" · •111•1 I >.•11I lyl111 2f1:\ n :\I 11!1ov1• '"'''
'1"11r Amfrirns iu ,,,,. Worlrl < 1,.,,.,
(l'hll'11l1•l1'hl11. 1'1'14). l'/ 4 N !111rry, ""llu·1 ·urn111•l nl N•l1111• 11111111•1,.l l'ullllc 1ol llu1111thl."' lcorir11d/off.rllf't/111rn11 ~fucl1r•
~4. lhi1I., 2.211 .">CI. .14h H(1 '111"1. I 17
- - - - --- - ·- - -- - - - - .

~4?. THE (DEA OF NATURAL RIG HTS

discourse to supplement the more ancient doctrine of natural law. Me-


dieval experience formed an indispensable part of the "usable past" of
seventeenth-century society. It was not possible to build a theory of the
state suited to such a world solely out of fragments of ancient Greek,
Roman, and Judeo-Christian lore. In spite of his own fondness for classical
allusions, Grotius chose a different path when he assimilated so much of
the medieval heritage into his new "modem" synthesis. For a Protestant
humanist of his time to enter with sympathy and insight into the world of
scholastic thought, to reappropriate essential elements of it, to "repristi-
nate" them so to speak by applying them to the new circumstances of the
age, and to reformulate medieval teachings in an idiom that made them
accessible and acceptable to future generations of scholars-all this was a
very great achievement. It required a far-ranging mind and a generous
heart. Grotius did not create a new theory of natural rights and natural
law; but what he did achieve was equally important. He made it possible CONCLUSION
for the old theory to live on into the modem world.

§ ome words of a modem pope, John XXIII, might be taken as sum-


ming up a principal theme of this book. According to the teaching of
Pacem in terris, natural rights and natural law are both derived, not from
some vision of cosmic nature ("the laws . . . which regulate the blind elt•-
mental forces of the universe"), but from our perception of human natun•
as "endowed with intelligence and free will." 1 Rights and duties, the popt•
wrote, flow as a direct consequence from human nature so understood.
Such ideas are not new. The popes of our age, who have embraced so
enthusiastically the idea of natural rights, after their predecessors con-
demned it for many years as an irreligious, Enlightenment aberration,
have been returning, unwittingly perhaps, to a tradition rooted in the
Christian jurisprudence and philosophy of the Middle Ages.
The idea of natural rights grew up-perhaps could only have grown
up in the first place-in a religious culture that supplemented rational
argumentation about human nature with a faith in which humans wert>
seen as children of a caring God. But the idea was not necessarily deprn-
d ent on divine revelation, and later it proved capable of surviving into
a more secular epoch. The disinclination of some Enlightenment skeptk~
to regard God's law as a sufficir nt ground for moral behavior, and thl·
widespread h•nd••ncy, .1f1l'T I lunw, lo doubt whether reflecting on human

I. " 1',u·.-111 In lc•11I",". 111 4 I "'"' ' " '"' llor l'"J'rll ,.,,, y./1111/s, '> vol". ( /\1111 l\rl>or, 1'1'111)
~· 11 111

'"'
344 THE [OEA Of NATURAL RIGHTS

inclinations could yield moral insights,2 raised new problems about the
r l •i CONCl.USION

new in each succeeding context. That is why a historical tradition can be


345

justification of rights that are still matters of dispute. But the appeal to intelligible, something other than a mere sequence of unconnected Fou-
natural rights became more prominent than ever in the political discourse caultian archaeological layers. Language inherited from the past, shaped
of the eighteenth century. The doctrine of rights shaped by the experience by old, perhaps forgotten contingencies, formed a part of the context
of previous centuries turned out to be still of value in addressing the prob- within whkh each succeeding rights theorist lived and thought and wrote.
lems of a new era. The proponents of the secularized rights theories of the Characteristics of language that were first acquired in the twelfth-century
Enlightenment had often forgotten the remoter origins of the doctrines persisted. The language of the Decretists was a part of the context for Oc.k-
they embraced; but their rhetoric about the rights of man becomes fully in- ham, Ockham's language for Gerson, Gerson's for Suarez, the language of
telligible only when it is seen as the end product of a long process o f Suarez for Grotius.
historical evolution. The history of natural rights theories can best be seen as a series of
Perhaps it would be more satisfying if the idea of natural rights had creative responses to a variety of past experiences. I have been empha-
entered Western political thought with a clatter of drums and trumpets in sizing that, in discussing this history, we need to consider a sequence of
some resounding pronouncement like the American Declaration of Inde- ; changing contexts, sets of contingent circumstances that no one planned
pendence or the French Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen. or foresaw. But I do not want to argue that the whole story of natural
In fact, though, this central concept of Western political theory first grew rights is just a chapter of historical accidents. The point is rather that, once
into existence almost imperceptibly in the obscure glosses of the medieval the idea that all persons possess rights had grown into existence, it dis-
jurists. One might say that, in the works of the early Decretists, a dis- played a remarkable vitality and adaptability and proved relevant to a
tinctive mutation of thought and language occurred which gave rise to a variety of emerging problems. At the end of the period we have con-
whole new species of ideas, the species of natural rights theories. Individ- sidered the process of development was by no means completed. The
ual examples of the species came to vary widely after a few generations, modern doctrine that freedom of religion is a natural right emerged only
shaped by the experience of changing environments. In some later histori- after the hard and bitter experiences of the seventeenth-century Wars of
j
cal environments natural rights theories could not survive at all. Some- Religion and then, at first, only in the writings of a few dissidents. The
times the seed fell on stony ground. Sometimes the theories that grew up
were stunted and deformed.
Biological metaphor can carry us only so far. Historians do not have
f medieval idea that liberty is a natural right led on to effective movements
for the abolition of slavery only when it was reinforced by the humanitar-
ian impulses of the late Enlightenment.
such elegant models to explain the development of ideas as scientists Not all later developments of thought were favorable to the persis-
use in describing organic evolution. It is partly of course because cul- tence of a political culture of rights. During the post-Enlightenment era
tural evolution is Lamarkian, not Darwinian. Acquired characteristics are natural rights fell into disfavor; by the end of the nineteenth century belief
passed on to succeeding generations. To put it differently, each particular in such rights had almost faded away before the onslaught of historicism,
rights theory was shaped partly as a response to a specific set of contingent cultural relativism, and legal positivism. To all this, Karl Marx added his
circumstances. So a history of natural rights theories has to be concerned own withering criticism. In a famous phrase, he wrote that the rights of
as much with contexts as with texts. In the Middle Ages we considered the liberal capitalism were merely egotistical, "the rights of the restricted indi-
contexts of twelfth-century juridical humanism, of fourteenth-century

.• .
I

vidual withdrawn into himself." But this was still not the end of the story.
~ r
Franciscan poverty disputes, and of fifteenth-century Conciliarism; then
the discovery of the New World, the turmoil of the Reformation, the na- '
i" :~
In the aftermath of World War II, there came a great revival of rights rhe-
toric, exemplified above all in the United Nations Universal Declaration of
tional and civil wars of the seventeenth century provided fresh contexts in
which rights theories could find new applications. But not everything was fl : Human Rights. Simple-minded moral relativism seemed inadequate in
face of the unthought of evils of the Nazi regime.
A survey of tlw early history of natural rights theories can fittingly t•nd
2. But the position of Hume himsdf on this mallt>r is far from clPar. Alasdair Macintyre
with a glanCT.' at tht• n1rn•nt situntion, tlw phase of the tradition that we an•
has observed, w ith reason, I thinlc, that " I lumt' rPas!l<·rt~'<i thl• founding of morality nn human
nature" against a Protestant virw th111 ."'1w hum;in~ "" radically nururt Wh;it ••Is•" n m a now living throuKh . 11"11 "n·11h1ry nfh•r the.• UN Declaration tht• status of
human morality ix- gruundt'd 1111, on,. might"""· t•xn ·pt on 11 n>nsicl..r.1tion of humnn chara«- human rights iH ll)(1'i11 1•1rn u i1111" TllC'n• .trc• two major probl<'m!'I. Jn tlw
ll'ri~li~ wht'llwr or 11111 w1• n•gnnl lhoiw d1itrnd1•1 j"ll"" "" lmpl11n1t.. t hy .1 ··11ring t ;net ? l'or West Wl' hnvt• 111•c•n cm .. 11111••1"''•lluf11111"111111 of rightR lnnguaKt'. 111111 IH
M;1d11lyn•1< vlf'w ,...,. W I> I huli•o n . ... 1. nrr 1~ c l11,11l1l ll11n l11•11 (l•>11<lun, l''"''l. ·l 'l nol simply <h1t• 111 th11 '1'1'111£111111111 111 wc•llM•' rlKhlic; thnl hn11 bt•c•n pnrt of
346 THE IDEA O F NATURAL RIGHTS CONCLUSION 347

the tradition from the beginning. The problem is rather that nowadays, be- has been eagerly accepted in all parts of the globe. Marxism is an ideology
sides a luxuriant array of rights inhering in various classes of humans- of distinctively West European origin; but, while it was fashionable, it
rights of ethnic minorities, rights of women, rights of children, rights of found its widest acceptance in other regions. So too the language of rights
gays, lesbians and bisexuals, rights of the handicapped, rights of consum- does not have to be uniquely Western. Rights language did not grow up
ers, rights of smokers and of nonsmokers, and so on almost endlessly- in the West because Western people are better or wiser than others; it is
besides all this we also encounter rights of animals, rights of trees, rights just that we have had a different history. There is at least a possibility that
of unborn generations. These various rights claims may all be ways of others may choose to profit from it.
advocating desirable social policies; but the multiplication of innumer- A glance back at the early history of rights theories may give us reason
able particular rights can erode any sense of community and the common to think that it could be so. We might learn from our history, for instance,
good, values that the earlier rights theorists never lost sight of. As Mary to appreciate the variety of cultural contexts within which an ideal of
Ann Glendon has recently complained, the modem inclination to force all human rights could flourish; medieval society was Christian and Western,
controversial issues into a straitjacket of rights talk tends to impoverish but in most ways it was more like the society of an underdeveloped coun-
our political and moral discourse. try nowadays than like that of a modem industrial state. We could learn
And yet, to abandon the language of rights altogether, and the belief too that the idea of natural rights in its earlier formulations was not one of
that some rights are human rights or natural rights, would be to cut the "atomic individualism"; it was not necessarily opposed to the communi-
heart out of our political tradition. To define such rights, perhaps the for- tarian values of traditional societies. Nor was the idea dependent on any
mula of Thomas Jefferson that we noticed at the outset-"Life, Libe rty, particular version of Western philosophy; rather it coexisted with a variety
and the Pursuit of Happiness"- is not such a bad one afte r all, especially if of philosophies, including the religiously oriented systems of the medieval
we extend the terms a little and take "Life" to include access to the necessi- era and the secularized doctrines of the Enlightenment. The one necessary
ties of life and "Liberty" to include freedom from arbitrary imprisonment basis for a theory of human rights is a belief in the value and d ignity of
and torture as well as from outright slavery. "Pursuit of Happiness" is a human life. The first rights theorists derived such a belief from their Chris-
notoriously vague phrase but we should not expect too much precision tian tradition, but all the great world religions have taught respect and
in this area. The concept of rights can be open-ended without becoming compassion for the human person. And the human needs to which human
all-embracing. Different people pursue happiness in different ways. As rights respond are not characteristic only of Western peoples. Surely in all
Grotius observed, "There are many ways of living, some being better than societies, humans have preferred life to death, freedom to servitude, suffi-
others." We should expect to find basic rights exemplified in varying ways ciency of food to starvation, dignity to humiliation. The rights language.•
in different societies. that grew up in Western culture was one way of addressing such universal
I said that there are two major problems concerning the current status concerns.
of human rights. The second, more grievous one, is that in many parts Rights talk cannot solve all moral dilemmas; it has a limited range of
of the world the most elementary rights are denied altogether to subject applicability; but it can be of very great value in the particular contexts
peoples. The leaders of repressive regimes sometimes pay lipservice to the where it is truly relevant. Rights claims are most effective when they are
ideal of human rights but ignore it in practice; sometimes they condemn used to combat gross political oppression or the harshest forms of eco-
the ideal itself as a Western aberration and resist the extension of basic nomic deprivation. In an age Hke ours, so fertile in the invent.ion of new
rights to other regions as just another form of Western chauvinism. forms of tyranny and characterized by such extreme degrees of poverty
It is true that an ideology of rights first grew up in the Western world. and wealth, these claims have a special urgency. The language of rights is
That has been the theme of this whole book. And it is most certainly true often abused nowadays but, when faced by such intractable probll'ms, Wt'
that we cannot elevate every Western predilection into an imaginary would be unwise to diminish its lf'gi timate role in our political discourst•.
human right and then expect other peoples, regardless of their histo ries If, instead, we nintim11• lo insist on a ft•w true human rights as a llfliv1.•rsal
and cultures, to embrace all such rights. But the Western origin of rights lwritagc, w1.• s hall pn•snvt• wh11I is ll(•s l in our tradition, and Wl' mi~ht
language does not in itself preclude the possibility that the underlying t•ven hopt• to .mll'liornlt•, lo No1111• 1•'Clt·nt, tlw nmdition of humankind in
ideals and aspirations inht•rt•nt in that languagt• ma y provt• to havl' a uni- tht• cumin~ millt•nlum
versal significancl'. Motkm ttochnoloxy i!oi . 1 product of tht• Wt•sh•rn world, Wt•stNn ri~r,ht11 llll'11t h•11w1•1s<11111, 111llwir11ri.~in, simply ,m t'llprt•ssion
rooted in ct>11h1ri1 ·~ of Wt•Nh'rn n1ll11rnl hi~lnry, hut, fur lll'llt'r or worst•, ii o ( 1111• more• •'>-totl11tl111l 1t111•11l1111•1t 1111•.ulv 111111!1·r11 c.1pit.1li~m1. Tlwv IMvt• ,,
348 THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS

respectable ancestry in medieval law and religion. They grew from good
seed; perhaps they will continue to bring forth fruit. That will depend on
the kind of environment we create for them in the years ahead. The texts
of the twenty-first century on human rights will also be shaped by their
contexts.

BIBLIOGRAPHY OF WORKS CITED

PRIMARY SouRCES

Alexander of Hales, Alexnndri de Hales ... Summa theologica, 4 vols. (Quaracchi,


1930-48)
Alma in, Jacques, Expositio circn decisiones Magistri G11illelmi Occam, in Johannes Ger-
so11ii opera omnin, L. Ellies du Pin, ed., 2 (Antwerp, 1706): cols. 1013-1120
- - -, Quaeslio res11mptiva . .. de dominio nnturali, civili et ecclesiastico, in Johannes
Gersonii opera omnin, L. Ellies du Pin, ed., 2 (Antwerp, 1706) cols. 962-76
- - - , Trndatus de nrictoritnte ecc/esiae et conciliorum generalium, in Johannes Gersonii
opern omnia, L. Ellies du Pin., ed., 2 (Antwerp, 1706): cols. 976-1012
Andreae, Johannes, In titulrtm De regulis iuris novella rommentaria (Venice, 1581)
- - -, /11 q11intum Decretalium librum novella commenlaria (Venice, 1581)
Aquinas, Thomas, De perfectione spiritualis vitae, in Sancti Thomne de Aquino 011ern
omnin i11ssu Leonis XIII PM. edita, 41 (Rome 1970): Part 8 , 67-122
- -, Summa contra gentiles, P. Marc, ed., 3 vols. (Turin, 1961-67)
- -, Summa lheologiae, P. Caramell, ed., 3 vols. (Turin, 1952- 76)
Baisio, Guido de, Rosnri11m decrelomm (Strasbourg, 1473)
Bentham, J., "Anarchical FaJlacies," in The Works of Jeremy Bent/ram, J. Bowring, t><L.
}: : 2 (Edinburgh, 1843): 489-534
, I
Bonagratia of Bergamo, Trnctatus de Christi el apostolorum pauperlnle, L. Oligt'f, t>tl .•
l, !' in Archivum Frnnciscnm1m historicum 22 (1929): 292- 335, 487-511
• I
.. i Bonaventure, Apo/01~frr pnrlJ'rrrmr. in 01•rra onmia rdila cura rt studio l'I'· co/ti-xii "
- l S. Bonm.11·11/11m. 8 (U11.1r.u·1·h i. 1898)· 2.1.1 :no
l!urlilmaqui. J.J.• Tfrr' f'11r11·11•lr··. r•f Nrr/11111/ / ' "''· T. N11"t•nl, trans . (Camhrid,.;t•, M .1ss .
1807)
I >1·1·rr·ta/r:; I >. ( :r1·;.:m II I .'i '"'" ~,,...,. (I v1111~. I 11)'1)
/:rlmm,l(fllll1'• /11ltr1111r1• .\ ',"(/I. I 1111111111. 1•.t (V11lh 1111 C 1ty, l'IH"l)
350 BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY 351

Filmer, Robert, Patriarcha and Other Writings, J.P. Sommerville, ed. (Cambridge, Innocent IV, Commentaria lnnocentii . .. super libros quinque ckcrttalium (Frankfurt,
1991) 1570)
Friedberg, E., ed., Corpus i11ris cancmici, 2 vols. (Leipzig, 1879) John XXIJ, "Quia vir reprobus," in Bullarium Frandscanum, C. Eubel, ed., 5
- -, Quinque comp;Jationes antiquae (Leipzig, 1882) (Quaracchi, 1898) 408-49
Caius, The Institutes of Gaius, F. de Zulueta, ed. (Oxford, 1946) John of Naples, Quaestiones variae Parisiis disputatae (Naples 1618)
Gerson, jean, Contra bu/lam "Rrgnans in excelsis", in fean Gerson. Oeuvres completes, John of Paris, De potestate regia et papali, F. Bleienstein, ed., and trans., fohannes
P. Glorieux, ed., 10 (Paris, 1973): 32-34 Q11idort von Paris. Ober koniglic11e und piipstliche Gewalt, (Stuttgart, 1969)
- - , De potestate ecclesiastica, in Oeuvres completes, 6 (Paris, 1965): 210-50 Las Casas, Bartolome de, Apologeticn historia sumaria, Vidal Abril Castell6 et al.,
eds., in Fray Bartolome de las Casas. Obras comp/etas, P. Castaneda Delgado ed.
- - , De vita spirituali animae, in Oeuvres completes, 3 (Paris, 1965): 113-202
6-8 (Madrid, 1992)
- - , Erreurs de fean Gorrell, in Oeuvres completes, 10 {Paris, 1973): 34-39
- - , Apologia, Angel Losada, ed., in Obras completas, 9 (Madrid, 1988)
- - , Propositio facta coram Anglicis, in Oeuvres completes, 6 (Paris, 1965): 125-35
- -, De regia potestate, J. Gonzalez Rodriguez and A. E. Perez Luiio, eds., in
- -, Tractatus de unitate ecclesiae, in Oeuvres completes, 6 (Paris, 1965): 136- 45 Obras completas, 12 Madrid, 1990): 1-223
Giles of Rome, Aegidius Romanus. De ecclesiastica potestate, R. Scholz, ed. (Weimar, - -, De regia potestate, L. Pereiia et al., eds., (Madrid, 1969)
1929) - - , De thesauris, Angel Losada, ed., in Obras completas, 11 (Madrid, 1992)
Godfrey of Fontaines, Les Quodlibets onze-qUJJrtorze de Godefroid de Fontaines, J. Hoff-
- - , De 11nico oocationis modo, P. Castaneda Delgado and A. Garda del Moral,
mans, ed. (Louvain, 1932) eds., in Obras comp/etas, 2 (Madrid, 1990)
Gratian, Decretum Gratiani ... una cum glossis (Venice, 1600)
- - , Historin de las lndias, M. Angel Medina et al., eds., in Obras comp/etas, 3- 5
- - , The Treatise of Laws With The Ordinary Gloss, A. Thompson and j. Gordley, (Madrid, 1994)
trans. (Washington, 1993) - - , Carta a los Dominicos de Chiapa y Guatemala, J. Perez de Tudela Bueso, ed.,
Grotius, Hugo, De imperio summarum potestatum circa sacra (Frankfurt, 1690) in Obras escogidas de Fray Bartolome de Las Casas, 5 (Madrid, 1958), 469-77
- - , De jure belli et pacis,J.B. Scott, ed. 2 vols. 1. Reproduction of the Edition of 1646 Locke, John, Two Treatises of Government, P. Laslett, ed. (Cambridge, 1967)
(Washington 0 .C., 1913). 2. A Translation of the Text, by Francis W. Kelsey
Mair, John, In qunrlum Sententiarum quaestiones 11tilissimae (Paris, 1519)
(Oxford, 1925)
- -, foannes Maior in quarlum Sententiarum (Paris, 1509)
- - , Hugonis Grotii de jure praedae commentarius, H .G. Hamaker, ed. (The Hague,
1868) - -, In secu11dum Senlentiarum quaestiones (Paris, 1519)
- -, Inleidinge tot de Hollandsche Rechts-Geleerdheid, F. Oovring et al., eds. Marsilius of Padua, Marsilii de Padua Defensor Pacis, ed. R. Scholz (Hanover, 1933)
(Leiden, 1952) - - , Marsilius of Padua. The Defender of the Peace, 2 vols., A. Gewirth, ed. and
- -, The Freedom of the Seas, R.V.O. Magoffin, trans. (New York. 1916) trans. (New York, 1951-1956)
Henry o f Ghent, "Quodlibet 9," in Henrici de Gandavo opera omnia, R. Macken, ed., Marx, Karl, HZur Judenfrage," I. Taubert, ed., in Karl Marx Friedrich Engels Grsom·
13 (Leuven, 1983) tausgabe, 1 Abt., 2 (Berlin, 1982): 141-69
Hervaeus Natalis, De iurisdidione, L. Hool, ed. (Munich, 1959) Mazzolini da Priero, Sylvestro, see Sylvester Prieras
- - , De paupertate Christi et apostolorum, J. G. Sikes, ed., in Archives d'histoire doc- Molina, L , Ludovici Molinae De justitin et jure (Cologne, 1759)
trinale et litteraire du moyen age, 12-13 (1937-38): 209-97 Monachus, Johannes, Glossa aurea (Paris, 1535)
Hobbes, T., De Cive. The English Version, H. Warrender, ed. (Oxford, 1983) Nicholas of Cusa, De co11corda11tia ratlmlica in Nicolai de Cusa opera om11ia, c.;. Kall1•11,
- - , Leviathan, M . Oakeshott, ed. (Oxford, 1946) ed. 14 (Hamburg, 1963)
Holcot, Robert, In quatuor Tibros Sententiarum q11aestiones (Lyons, 1518) <)ckham, William 1 >I. 1\11 1•m11·1•1•''· in c :11ilMmi 1/1· ( >,.k/1am opera polilica, 11.S. ( lfO..r,
ed., 1 (Mandw!il•·r. 1117'1) no ·11>
Hostiensis, Lectura in V /ibros Decretali11m (Venice, 1581)
- - , llrl'l•ilriq11111111 ,,,. ,,, 111111~1111 ty1111111/11', 111 It Sd10l7., t•d., Wilhrlm '""' <kA/111111
- -, S11mma LJm11i11i llr11rinis Ca'4li1111li.~ ll1l~lil'llsis (Lyons, 15:17) "'~ /'<lfili~d11·r I >mAf'I ,,,,,, .,.,,, ,,,,.,.,,.,,,,,,,,,,, ,,,. r•ri111·i1111/11 t.11m1111irn, (I A•lp7.IR.
I l11K11crio. S11111111111lrart11rw11. A.tmonl. Stlftshihlluh•k, MS 7 11144 )
352 BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOG RAPHY 353

- - -, De imperatorum et pontificum potestate, in R. Scholz, ed., Unbekannte kirche11- - - - , Francisco de Vitoria, Commenlaria a la secunda secundae de Santo Tomas, 6 vols.
politische Streitschriften aus der Zeit Ludwigs des Bayern (1327-1354), 2 (Rome, V. Beltran de Heredia, ed. (Salamanca, 1932-34)
1914)
- -- , Obras de Francisco de Vitoria, T. Urdanoz, ed. (Madrid, 1960)
- - -, Dialogus, in Monarchia S. Romani imperii, ed., M. Goldast, 2 (Frankfurt, - - - , Political Writings, A. Pagden and J. Lawrence, eds. and trans. (Cambridge,
1614): 392-976
1991)
- - , Octo quaestiones de potestate papae, in Opera politica, H. S. OfAer, ed., 1 (Man- - -, Relectio de Indis, L. Perena and J.M. Perez Prendes eds. (Madrid, 1%7)
chester, 1974): 1-217
Wolff, Christian, lnstitutiones juris naturae et genti11m, M. Thomann, ed., in Christian
---,Opus nonaginta dierum, in Opera politica, H. S. Offler, ed., 1-2 (Manchester, Wolff Gesammelte Werke, Abt. 2, 26 (Hildesheim, 1%9) (reprint of the 1750
1963-74): 287-858 edition)
- - - , Opera theologica, in Guillelmi de Ockham opera philosophica et theologica, Zabarella, Franciscus, Super quinq11e libris decretalium commentaria (Venice, 1602)
G. Gal et al., eds. 3-9 (Bonaventure, NY, 1967-86)
Zenzellinus de Cassanis, Glossa ordinaria ad Extrauagantes loannis XXll in Extraw-
Odofredus, Praelectiones in Digest11m nouum (Lyons, 1552) ganles . .. D. loa11nis Papne XXI/ (Venice, 1583)
Parmensis, Bemardus, Glossa ordinaria ad Decretales in Deere/ales D. Gregorii IX cum
glossis, (Lyons, 1624)
SECONDARY SoURCES
Pufendorf, S., De jure naturae et gentium libri octo, J.B. Scott, ed., 2 vols. (Oxford,
1934). 1. A Photographic Reproductio11 of the Edition of 1688 2. A Tra11slation of tire Abril Castello, V., " Vitoria-Las Casas, confrontacion y proyeccion," in C. Soria, ed.,
Text, by C. H. and W. A. Oldfather I diritti dell' uomo e la pace nel pensiero di Francisco de Vitoria e Bartolome de las
Casas (Milan, 1988), 155-72
- -, Of the Law of Nature and Nations, B. Kennett, trans. (London, 1729)
---."Bartolome de las Casas, el ultimo communero," in Las Casas et la politiq11r
- --, Specimen controversiarum circa jus naturale ipsi n11per notarum (Uppsala,
des droils de l'homme (Aix-en-Provence, 1976), 92-123
1678)
Adams, M.M., "The Structure of Ockham's Moral Theory," Franciscan Studies 4n
Rufinus, Die Summa Decretorum des Magister Ruftnus, H . Singer, ed. (Paderborn,
(1986): 1-34
1902)
Alberigo, G ., Chiesa conciliare. ldentita e significalo def conciliarismo (Brescia, 1981)
Scotus, John Duns, Opus Oxoniense. Quaestiones in quartum /ibrum Sententiar111n, in
foannis Duns Scoti . .. opera omnia, L. Vives, ed., 18 (Paris, 1894) Andre-Vincent, P., Droit des lndiens et droeloppement en Amerique latine (Paris, lq'71)
Sepulveda, Jean Gines de, Democrates seg11ndo o De las ji1stas causas de la guerra - - -, " La concretisation de la notion classique de droit nature) a travers l'oeuvn•
contra los Indios, Losada A., ~ - (Madrid, 1951) de Las Casas," in Las Casas et In politique des droits de /'homme (Aix-en-
Provence, 1976), 203-13
Soto, Domingo de, De iustitia et iure (Salamanca, 1556)
Bandman, B., ed., Bioethics and Human Rights (Boston, 1979)
Suarez, Francisco, De charitate, in Francisci Suarez . .. opera omnia, L. Vives, ed., 12
(Paris, 1858): 635-763 Barbeyrac, J., "An Historical and Critical Account of the Science of Morality," in
Samuel von Pufendorf, Of Ille Law of Nature and Nations, B. Kennett, trans.
- -, De opere sex dierum, in Opera omnia, 3 (Paris, 1856): 1-447
(London, 1729)
- - - , De statu perfectionis. in Opera omnia 15 (Paris. 1859)
Barry, N ., "The Concept of ' Nature' in Liberal Political Thought," Journal of Liber·
- - -, Defensio ftdei catholicae, in Opera omnia, 24 (Paris, 1859) tarian Studies 8 (1986): 1-17
- - -, Tractatus de legibus ac Deo legislatore, in Opera omnia, 5 (Paris, 1856) Bastit, M., Naissance de la loi modeme (Paris, 1990)
- - - , Tractatus de Iegibus ac Deo legislatore, L. Perei'ia et al., eds., 8 vols. (Madrid, Benson, R.L., The Bishop-Elect: A Study in Mediroal E.cclesiastical Office (Princt•lon.
1971- ) 1%8)
Summenhart, C., De contractibus licit is et illicit is (Venice, 1580) - - and G. Constilhh•, 1'<1~., Rrrrni$."lmrr a11d Renewal in the Twelftlr Ce11t11ry (Cun·
Sylvester Prieras. Summne Sylr>rstrinne (Venice, 1584) bridgt'. M.1ss.. 1'1147)
Teutonicus, Johannes, Glo!'sa ordinarin ml l>t'Crt't11111 Gmti1mi in l">rcrrtum Gmti1111i . . . Bt'fRl'r, N., Ri,i.:111.~: A J /1111111~'1•1. /•'' /'1'1•1•11' 1/mf,., A,\'t' (1 larmon&nvorth, 1<174)
urra cum Klossi$ (V<'niet'. Ififlll) lk·rlin, I., /"nm f!<~1111.• 1111I1/,..1111 (I hl11hl. 11ir11I)
Vi tori,,, i:rnnd,.n1 dt•, c ·111111111·11111111111/ li11/111l1• 1I.- 111 ,,._.,. ( 111 f II. L't.>.'HJ llJH), frnx1111·11 lll·rn1.111. I I 1.. I 1111• 11111( Hr'1~•/11ll1•11 I /r,. / ,,, 111111/1111 1•/ llw Wl'.•lrru I ''.\'11/ l'111liti1111 (< ·,1111
t1•!oi dt n·l1·...-i1111,..• . V 1'4·11ti\11 .t1• ll1•11·1tl11. 1•d (M111lritl. l'l'i?)
h1hlK•'. M""" . l'IK I)
r
354 BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBl.IOC RAPH Y 355

Bemheimer, R., Wild Men in the Middle Ages (Cambridge, Mass., 1952) Carro, Venancio D., La teologia et los te0logos-juristas espaiioles ante la conquista de
Berns, Walter, "The Constitution as Bill of Rights," in R.A. Goldwin and W. A. America, 2 vols. (Madrid, 1944)
Schambra, eds., How Does the Constitution Secure Rights? (Washington, 1985), - -, "The Spanish Theological-Juridical Renaissance and the Ideology of Bar-
50-73 tolome de las Casas," in J. Friede and B. Keen, eds., Bartolomt de Uis Casas in
- -, In Defense of Liberal Democracy (Chicago, 1984) History (DeKalb, m., 1971), 237-77
Besselink, L., "The Impious Hypothesis Revisited," Grotiana ri.s. 9 (1988): 3-63 Castillo Lara, R., ed., Studia in honon'm eminentissimi Cardinalis Alphonsi M. Stickler
(Rome, 1992)
Black, A., Council and Commune. The Conciliar Movement and the Fifteenth-Century
Huitage (London, 1979) Chroust, A.H., "Hugo Grotius and the Scholastic Natural Law Tradition," The New
Scholasticism 17 (1943): 101-33
- -, Guilds and Civil Society in European Political Thought from the Twelfth Century
to the Present (Ithaca, NY, 1984) Clark, D.W., "Voluntarism and Rationalism in the Ethics of Ockham," Franciscan
Studies 31 (1971): 72-87
- -, "Society and the Individual from the Middle Ages to Rousseau: Philoso-
phy, Jurisprudence and Constitutional Theory," History of Political Thought 1 - - , "William ofOckham on Right Reason," Spew/um 48(1973): 13- 36
(1980): 146- 66 Coing, H., "Zur Eigentumslehre des Bartolus," Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung fiir
- -, "The Individual and Society," in J.H. Burns, ed., The Cambridge History of Rechtsgeschichte (Rom. Ab.) 70 (1953): 348- 71
Medieval Political Thought (Cambridge, 1988), 588-606 - -, et al., eds., Das subjecktive Redlt und der Rechtsschutz der Persiinlichkeit
Blumenberg, H., Die Legitimitiit der Neuuit (Frankfurt, 1966) (Frankfurt, 1959)
Bobbio, N., Thomas Hobbes and the Natural Law Tradition, D. Gobetti, trans. (Chi- Coleman, }., " Dominium in Thirteenth and Fourteenth-Century Political Thought
c.ago, 1993) and Its Seventeenth-Century Heirs: John of Paris and Locke," Political Stud-
its 33 (1985): 73-100
Boehner, P., "Ockham's Political Ideas," in E.M. Buytaert, ed., Collected Articles on
Ockham (St. Bonaventure, NY, 1958), 442-68 - , " Property and Poverty," in J.H . Bums, ed., Tire Cambridge History of Me-
-
dieVtll Political Thought (Cambridge, 1988), 607- 48
Bozeman, A.B., "On the Relevance of Hugo Grotius and De Jure Belli et Pacis for
Our Times," Gratiana, n.s. 1 (1980): 53-64 Comas, J., "Historical Reality and the Detractors of Las Casas," in Friede and
Keen, Bartolome de Las Casas, 487-537
Brett, A., Liberty, Right and Nature: The Language of lndiuidual Rights in Later Scholas-
tic Thought (Cambridge, 1997) Combes, A., jean Gerson, commentateur dionysien (Paris, 1940)
Broadie, A., The Circle of fohn Mair (Oxford, 1985) - -, La theologie mystique de Gerson, 2 vols. (Rome, l %3-64)
Brooke, C.N.L., et al., eds., Church and Government in the Middle Ages (Cambridge. Composta, D., " II concetto di diritto nell' umanesimo giuridico di Francesco de Vi-
1976) toria O .P.," in C. Soria, ed., J diritti dell' uomo t la pace net pensiero di Franctsco de
Vitoria e Bartolome de las Casas (Milan, 1988), 276-91
Brown, C.O., Pastar and Laity in the Theology of Jean Gerson (Cambridge, 1987)
- -, "La 'moralis facultas' nella filosofia giuridica di F. Suarez," Salesianum 18
Buckle, S., Natural Law and the Theory of Property. Grotius to Hume (Oxford, 1991)
(1956): 476-97
Bums, J.H., Lordship, Kingship and Empire. The Idea of Monarchy 1400-1525 (Oxford,
- - , " La persona umana e i diritti soggetivi in prospectiva metafisica," lustitia
1992)
27 (1974): 42- 72
- -, "Po/ilia regalis et optima: The Political Ideas of John Mair, " History of Po-
Condren, C., "Democracy and the Defensor Pads: On the English Language Tra-
litical Thought 2 (1981): 31-61
dition of Marsilian Interpretation," II pensiero politico 13 (1980): 301-16
- -, ed., The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought (Cambridge,
- - , "Rheto ric, Historiography and Political Theory: Some Aspects of the l'ov·
1988)
erty Conlmvt•rsy Rcconsidert'd," /011mal of Religious History 13 (1984): 15 :\4
Busa, R., ed., Index Thomisticus. Sectio II. Concordantia priora, 23 vols. (Stuttgart,
Congar, Y., "Aspt•cls .... ·d(·si11l11gi')1tl'S d1· la q m•relle entre mendiants cl s~n1lil'Ts
1974-75)
dans la ~·cnrul1 · nuuth\ du Xl111• !til'd1• t'I h• d~hu t du XIVc-," Ard1itlf'S d 'l11st11irr
Carlen, C., ed., The Papal Encyclicals, 5 vols. (Ann Arbor, Ml, 1990) dodri1111/r ,., 1111111111,,. r/11 "'''""" llsr \t, ( l'lf•I): .1.'i l.'il
Carlyle, R.W. and A.J. Ciulylc•, A 11i!'lt11rv 11{ Mrdirml 1'11litirnl Tl1r11r.v i11 tlll' Wt'SI, ·- ," Om>tf 11111111111'""Kii."" 1111111tl•rn• lrnd ;11i l'I .1ppmlmri 1ft•lwt," H1·1•111• hr~
6 vol!'. (EdinliurJ<h. l'JCl:l :lt1) l1•riq1w ,f,.
1lr1•rl /11111,111• ~I t''11IUJir"I , 41 1 .,,. , ' ' ' ( l'tr;li) 2111 ~·1
r
356 BIBLIOGRAPHY
BtRLIOGRAPHY 357
Cortese, E., La norma giuridic.a, 2 vols. (MjJan, 1962-64) - -, "Quelques remarques, sur les sources utilisees par Grotius dans ses
Courtenay, W.J., "Nominalism and Late Medieval Religion," in C. Trinkhaus and travaux de droit naturel,'' in R. Feenstra et al., eds., The World of Hugo Grotius
Heiko A. Oberman, eds., The Pursuit of Holiness (Leiden, 1974), 26-59 (1583- 1645) (Amsterdam, 1984), 65-81
- - -, uThe Dialectic of Divine Omnipotence" in id., Covenant and Causality in Feinberg, J., "Duties, Rights. and Oaims," American Philosophical Quarterly 3 (1966):
Medieval Thought (London, 1984), IV, 1-37 137-44
Couvreur, G., Les pauures. Ont-ils des droits? (Paris, 1961) - -, "The Nature and Value of Rights," Journal of Value Inquiry 4 (1970):
243-57
Cover, R., "Obligation: A Jewish Jurisprudence of Social Order," Journal of Law and
Religion 5 (1987): 65-74 Fernandez-Santamaria, J.A., The State, War and Peace. Spanish Political Thought in the
Cranston, M., Human Rights Today (London, 1962) Renaissance 1516-1559 (Cambridge, 1977)
Crowe, M.B., The Changing Profile of the Natural I.Aw (The Hague, 1977) Fichter, J.H., Man of Spain, Francis Suarez (New York, 1942)
Dabin, J., " Droit subjectif et subjectivisme juridique," Archives de philosophie du Fikentscher, W., Modes of Thought in l..aw and Politics (Berkeley, 1988)
droit 9 (1964): 17-35 Finnis, J.• Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford, 1980)
- - , Le droit sul1jectif (Paris, 1952)
Damiata, M ., "Funzione e concetto delta poverta evangelica in Marsilio da .
; Folgado, A., Evoluci6n hislorica del concepto del derecho subjectivo (Madrid, 1960)
Forbes, D., Hume's Philosophical Politics (Cambridge, 1975)
Padova," Medioevo 6 (1980): 411-30 r.
Franklin, J., /ohn Locke and the Theory of Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1978)
- - , Guglielmo d'Oclrham: Puvertil e potere, 2 vols. (Florence, 1978-79) Freppert, L., The Basis of Morality According to William of Ockham (Chicago, 1988)
Davis, 0.8., The Problem ofSlavery in Western Culture (Ithaca, NY, 1966) Fried, J. and B. Keen, eds., Bartolome de las Casas in History (DeKalb, Ill., 1971)
Dawson, J.D., "Richard FitzRalph and the Fourteenth-Century Poverty Controver- Gagner, S., "Vorbemerkungen zum Thema 'Dominium' bei Ockham," Miscellanea
sies," /ounuzl of Ecclesiastical History 34 (1983): 315-44 mediaf'Vfllia 9 (1974): 293-327
Deckers, D., Gerechtigkeit und Recht. Eine historisch-kritische Untersuchung der Ge- Garcia, A., Thomas Hobbes: Bibliographie Internationale de 1620 a 1986 (Caen, 1986)
rechtiskeitslehre des Francisco de Vitoria (1483-1546) (Freiburg, 1991)
Gan:ia Garcia, A., Iglesia, Sociedad y Derecho (Salamanca, 1985)
Delorme, F., "Question de P. J. Olivi 'Quid ponat ius vel dominium' ou encore ' De
signis voluntariis'," Antonianum 20 (1945): 309- 30 Garrett, W., "Religion, Law, and the Human Condition," Sociological Analysis 47
(1987): 1-34
Deuringer, I<., Probleme der CAritas in der Schule von Salamanca (Freiburg im Breis-
Gellinek, C., "Book Review," Grotiatta, n.s. 3 (1982): 77
gau, 1959)
Dolcini, C., Crisi di poteri e politologia in crisi (Bologna, 1988) Gewirth, A., "Is Cultural Pluralism Relevant to Moral Knowledge?" Social Phi-
losophy and Policy 11(1994): 22-43
Donnelly, J., Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice (Ithaca, NY, 1989)
- -, Marsilius of Padua. The Defender of the Pe.ace, 2 vols. (New York, 1951-56)
Dover, K.J., Greek Popular Morality in the Time of Plato and Aristotle (Berkeley and
- - , ReaS<Jn and Morality (Chicago, 1978)
Los Angeles, 1974)
Dufour, A., Droits de /'homme, droit naturtl et histoire (Paris, 1991) Gierke, Otto von, Das deutsche Genossenschaftsrecht, 4 vols. (Berlin, 1868-1914)
Dumont, L., Essays on Individualism. Modern Ideology in Anthropological Perspective - - , Political Theories of the Middle Age, F.W. Maitland, trans. (Cambridge, 1900)
(Chicago, 1986) Gillet, P., I.A personnalite juridique en droit ecclisiastique (Malines, 1927)
Dworkin, R., Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, Mass., 1977) Glenn, G.D., "Inalienable Rights and Locke's Argument for Limited Government:
Edwards, C.S., Hugo Grotius. The Miracle of Holland (Chicago, 1981) Political Implications of a Right to Suicide," Journal of Politics 46 (1984): 80- IO.')
Ellis, D., "Europeans and the Rise and Fall of African Slavery: An Interpretation," Golding, M.P., "The C'onn'pl of Righi!!: A Historical Sketch," in B. Bandm;in 1•d .•
American Historical Review 98 (1993): 1399-1423 Bioethics a11rl 11111111111 1<(-<hlN (Urn1ton. 1978), 44- 49
Eschmann, l.T., "A lbomistic Glossary on thl' Principle of the Preeminence of a Goldwin, R.A. .mcl WA Sd1a111hra. 1•el11 . 11111111 lclt'S the Constitution Srrnre Ri~/1tsl
Common Good," Mediaroal Studirs 5 (1943): 123- 65 (WashinKlnn. i'IH'i) '

Fet>n!'ltra, R., " l~·r Eig1•n1t1m11ht•1<rifl lwi I lugo ( ;ro1iw1 im 1.il'hl l'illiKt'r miltt•lalt- (:ray, ).• l.i/lt'r.1/i~m ( Ml1111""I '"""· I''"''l
lkht>r untl icpitl111-ht1l"11llk1•r l.)lwll1•11," 111 ( >. 1'4-lm•nclic c•I 111 . ••cl'< . 1'1·•tsdirifl filr <;n-c•n, T. I I.• I .rr l 11rr111111 llit I'1 1111 l/•lr• 11/ I 'e1/111, 11/ I >I•/ l_'\11111111 (I .ontlon, 1•141 )
l'rn11.'. Win1d1rr, (l :mt111g1·11. 11014). 11~1 14 C;m11.'I, <' I 1,,., H,n·/111111 ,/,., l'(tll111lr It,,.., '"""II
358 BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOCRAPHY 359

Grossi, P., "Usus facti. La nozione di proprieta nella inaugurazione dell' eta Jones, J.W., The Law and Legal Theory of the Greeks (Aalen, 1977)
nuova," Quaderni Fiorentini per la storw del pensiero giuridico modemo 1 (1972): Junghans, H ., Ockham im Lichte der ne11ren Forschung (Berlin, 1968)
287- 355 Justenhoven, H.-G., Fmncisco de Vitoria zu Krieg und Frieden (Cologne, 1991)
- -, ed., La seconda scolastica nella formazione de/ diritto privato moderno (Milan, Kamenka, E. and A.E. Tay, eds., Human Rights (New York, 1978)
1973)
Kantorowicz, E.. Tiie King's Two Bodies. A Study in Medieval Political Theology
Grunebaum, J.O., Private Ownership (New York, 1957) (Princeton, 1957)
Haakonssen, K., "From Natural Law to the Rights of Man: A European Perspec- Kelley, D.R. and B.G. Smith, eds., What ls Property? (Cambridge, 1994)
tive on American Debates," in M.J. Lacey and K. Haakonssen, eds., A Culture
Kilcullen, J., "Natural Law and Will in Ockham," History of Philosophy Yearbook 1
of Rights (Cambridge, 1991), 19-51 (1993): 1-25
- - , "Hugo Grotius and the History of Political Thought." Political Tl1eory 13
Kolmel, W., "Das Naturrecht bei Wilhelm Ockham," Franziskanische Studien 35
(1985): 239-65 (1953): 39- 85
Habermas, J., Theory and Practice, J. Viertel, trans. (Boston, 1974)
- - , Wilhelm Ockham und sein kirchenpolitischen Schriften (Essen, 1942)
Haggenmacher, P.• Grotius et la doctrine de la guerre juste (Paris, 1983) Kuttner, S., "Gratian and Plato," in C.N.L. Brooke et al., eds., Church and Govern-
Hamilton, B., Political Thought in Sixteenth-Century Spain (Oxford, 1963) ment i11 the Middle Ages (Cambridge, 1976), 93-118
Hanke, L., All Mankind is One (DeKalb, IL, 1974) - - , Repertorium der Kanonistik, 1140-1234 (Vatican City, 1937)
- -, Aristotle and the American Indians (Chicago, 1959) LaCapra, D., "Intellectual History and Defining the Present as ' Postmodern'," in
- - . "La fama de fray Bartolome de las Casas," in £studios Lascasianos (Seville, I. Hassan and S. Hassan, eds., lnnowtion/Renovation. New PerspectiVts on the
1966), l-19 Huma11ities (Madison, WI, 1983)
- - , The Spanish Struggle for Justice in the Conquest of America (Boston, 1%5) Lacey M.T. and K. Haakonssen, eds., A Culture of Rights (Cambridge, 1991)
Harding, A.L., HPolitical Liberty in the Middle Ages," Speculum 55 (1980): Lachance, L., Le concept de droit selon Aristote et S. Thomas, 2d ed. (Ottawa, 1948)
423-43 Lagarde, Georges de, " lndividualisme et corporatisme au moyen age," in L'or-
Hart, H.L.A., "Are There Any Natural Rights?" Philosophical Review 64 (1955): ganisation corporative du moyen aged la fin de l'Ancien Regime (Louvain, 1937),
175-91 3-59
- -, "Bentham on Legal Rights," in Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, Second Series, - -, La naissance de I' esprit /aique au dee/in du moyen dge, 6 vols. (Paris, 1934-46);
A.W.B. Simpson, ed., (Oxford, 1973) 171-91 (reprinted in David Lyons ed., 2nd ed., S vols. (Paris, 1956- 70)
Rights) Lambert, M.O., Franciscan Poverty. The Doctrine of the Absolute Poverty ofChrist and
Helm, P., "Introduction," in id., ed., Divine Commands and Morality (Oxford, 1951) the Apostles in the Franciscan Order, 1210-1323 (London, 1961)
Henley, J.A., "Theology and the Basis of Human Rights," Scottish Journal of The- Laqueur, W. and B. Rubin, eds., The H11man Rights Reader (New York, 1979)
ology 39 (1986): 361-78 LeGoff, J., La naissancedu Purgatoire (Paris, 1981)
Hering, H.M., "De iure subjectivo sumpto apud sanctum Thomam," Angelic11m 16 Lenherr, T., "Der Begriff 'executio' in der Summa Decretorum des Huguccio,"
(1939): 295-97 Archiv fur katholisches Kirchenrecht 150 (1981): 5-45, 361-420
Hohfeld, W.N., Fundamental Legal Conceptions (New Haven, 1919) Levy, E., West Roma11 Vulgar Law (Philadelphia, 1951)
Horowitz, M.C., "The Stoic Synthesis of the Idea of Natural Law in Man: Four Lewis, E., "Organic Tendencies in Medieval Political Thought," American Politital
Themes," Journal of the History of Ideas 35 (1974): 3-16 Science Review 32 (1938): 849-76
Hudson, W.D., ed., The ls-Ought Question (Londo n, 1%9) Lomasky, L.E., PerS<ms, Rixlit~. and the Moral Community (Oxford, 1987)
Iaruiarone, A., "Genesis del pensiamento colonial en Francisco de Vitoria," in Lottin, 0 ., l.e dmil 1111t11rrl .-Ito. ~11i11t Tlim1111s rt ses prldecesseurs, 2d ed. (Aru~t'!I,
L. Perei'la and J. M. Perez Prendes, eds., rranci~co de Viloria. Rrlectio de llldi~ 1931)
(Madrid, 1%7), XXXl- XLI Loudl'n, IU .. , " l<IHhl11 l11fnl11nll11n 1md tlw lmpovc•rishml'nt of Moral Thl'ory,••-
Jaffa, If. American Omsrrr,,1ti~m 11111111"· Amt'Til'aH 1"11111111i11,it (lh1rham, NC, 141-W) /011rnnl 11/ V11l111' f111111lt1J I'/ ( lllK I) K"/ lllJ
JMIOI, c;., " (A.'S iiki"H pollthtll''" .... S111m•1 .. , 11• pouvoir .1h:ml11," Ar· l1it•1'S 1fr ,,,,;. I .twl'j11y, /\ .CI 11111 I t ; llt11U, I\ / l11t ""'""''" v rlt'1111 y 11/ l'rtm1ti111~111 111111 Hrf11tf'tl ltlr11.•
/11s1111l1ir I H ( 111"11). h4 I 07 (llnlt\111111r, I''\'\)
360 BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY 361
Luhmann, N ., "Am Anfang war kein Unrecht," in id., Gesellschaftsstruktur und Se- Menendez Pidal. R., El padre Uls Casas. Su doble personalidad (Madrid, 1963)
mantik. Studien zur Wissenssoziologie der modernen Gesellschaft 3 (Frankfurt,
1989): 11-64
Meuthen, E., Das Basler K?n.zil als Forschungsproblem der europiiischtm Geschichte
(Opladen, 1985) (=Rhetmsch-Westfalische Akadamie der Wissenschaften Vor-
- -, "Subjective Rechte," in Gesellschaftsstruktur und Semantik. 2 (Frankfurt, trage G274)
1981): 45- 104
Michaud-Quantin, P., Universitas. Erpressions du mouwment communautaire dans le
Lyons, 0 ., "Th.e Correlativity of Rights and Duties," Nous 4 (1970): 45-55 moyen-1lge latin (Paris, 1970)
- - , ed., Rights (Belmont, 1978) Miethke, J., Ockhams Weg zur Sozialphilosophie (Berlin, 1969)
Macfarlane, A., The Origins of English Individualism (Cambridge, 1979) Miller, F., Nature, Justice, and Right in Aristotle's Politics (Oxford, 1995).
Machan, T.R., Human Rights and Human Liberties (Chicago, 1975), 248 Minogue, ~·· "The History of the Idea of Human Rights," in w. Laqueur and
- - , Individuals and Their Rights (LaSalle, 1989) B. Rubin, eds., The Human Rights Reader (New York, 1979), 3-17
Macintyre, A., After Virtue, 2d ed. (Notre Dame, 1984) Monahan, A.P., From Personal Dulies Towards Personal Rights (Montreal, 1994)
MacPherson, C.B., The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes and Locke Morrall, J.B., Gerson and the Great Schism (Manchester, 1960)
(Oxford, 1962) - -•. "Some ":otes o~ a Recent Interpretation of William of Ockham's Political
Mahn-Lot, M., Bartolome de las Casas et le droit des lndiens (Paris, 1982) Philosophy, FranaSCJJn Studies 9 (1949): 335-69
Maine, Sir Henry Sumner, Dissertation on Early Law and Custom (New York, 1883) Mo~s, C;; "Individualism in Twelfth-Century Religion. Some Further Reflec-
Malachowski, A.R., ed., Reading Rorty. Critical Responses to Philowphy nnd the Mirror tions, Journal of Ecclesiastical History 31 (1980): 1-17, 195-206
of Nature (and Beyond) (Oxford, 1990) - -. The Discovery of the Individual, 1050- 1200 (London, I 9n)
Maritain, J., Les droits de l'homme et la loi naturelle (Paris, 1945) Muldoon, J.. Popes, Lawyers, and Infidels: The Church and the Non-Christian World
(Philadelphia, 1979)
Marrone, J., 'The Absolute and Ordained Powers of the Pope: An Unedited Text of
Henry of Ghent," Mediaeval Studies 36 (1974): 7-22 - - , The Americas in the World Order (Philadelphia, 1994)
Martin, G., "1st Ockhams Relationstheorie Nominalismus?" Franziskanisclte Studien - , "Th~ Contribution of the Medieval Canon Lawyers to the Formation of
32 (1950): 31-49 International Law," Traditio 28 (19n): 483-97
Martin, R. and J.W. Nickel, "A Bibliography on the Nature and Foundations of Norr, K., "Zu~. Frag~ des subjektive Rechts in der mittelalterlichen Recht!;wis-
Rights 1947-1977," Political Theory 6 (1978): 395-413 senschaft, m Dieter Medicus et al .. eds., Ftstschrift for Hermann Lange (Stutt -
gart, 1992), 193- 204
- -, "Recent Work on the Concept of Rights," American Philosophical Quarterly
17 (1980): 165-80 Oakley, F., "Figgis, Constance, and th e o·ivmes
· o( p ans,
· " American Histt1rinrl
Review 75 (1969): 365- 86
Mattingly, G., Renaissance Diplomacy (Chicago, 1955)
McCloskey, H .J., "The Right to Life," Mind 84 (1975): 403-25 - , "Gerson and d 'Ailly: An Admonition," Speculum 40 (1965): 74-83
McDonnel, K., "Does William of Ockham Have a Theory of Natural Law?" Fran- ~· "J~cobean Political Theology: The Absolute and Ordinary Powers of tlw
ciscan Studies 34 (1974): 383-92 King, /oumal of the History of Ideas 29 (1968): 323- 46
McGrade, A.S., "Ockham and the Birth or Individual Rights," in B. Tierney and P. - - , Natural Uiw, Conciliarism and Consent in the Late Middle Ages (London, 1984)
Linehan, eds., Authority and Power. Studies on Medieval Law and Government - -, " Natural La".", the Corpus Mysticum, and Consent in Conciliar Thought
Presented to Walter Ullmann (Cambridge, 1980), 149-65 from John of Pans to Mathias Ugonius," Speculum 56 (1981): 786- 810
- -, The Political Thought of William of Ockham: Personal and Institutional Pri11- - - , Omnipotmce, Covenant, and Order (Ithaca, NY, 1984)
ciples (Cambridge, 1974)
- - •. "On the_ Road from Constance to 1688: The Political Thought of John
McKeon, R.,"The Development o( the Concept of Property in Political Philoso- Ma1or •md <••'<>r~c' f111r hanan," fournal of British Studies t (1962): J- 31
phy," Ethics 48 (1938): 297-366
Oakley, J.. " luhn :'0 (11 •'"" Fr.mcis,·.m lnnon•nn•," Franciscan StudiPS 46 (19M)'
Melden, A.I., Rights in Moral liws (Berkl'lt'y, I 9AA) 217- 26 . .
Melloni, A .. " Williftm of< kkh11111'H< 'ritli1111• ol lnnc1<-.·nt IV," fri111i-i.~n111 5/rufirs 46 OfX'rman: I tA • 11ir I''" r'f'•f 11/ I 11f,. M,.dlri~rf I f1,.11l11x11· <:Ol1rirl Ric•( a11d IJ1tr Mc•1lirml
(11186): I 61 - 21l:l Nt1111mal1!trt1 (t '11111li1 hlMtt. M""" . l'H1 I)
362 BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY 363

Offler, H.S., "1be 'Influence' of Ockham's Political Thinking: the First Cen~;: in Pollock, F. and F.W. Maitland, The History of English Law, 2 vols., 2d ed. (Cam-
w. Vossenkuhl and R. Schonberger, eds., Die Gegenwart Ockhams (Wemhe1m, bridge, 1898)
1990), 338-65 Post, G., Studies in Medieval Legal Thought (Princeton, 1%4)
- - "The Three Modes of Natural Law in Ockharn: A Revision of the Text," Poste, E., Elements of Roman Law by Caius (Oxford, 1890)
Fr~nciscan Studies 37 (1977): 207- 18 Posthumus Meyjes, G.H.M., Jean Gerson, zijn kerkpolitik en ecclesiologie ('s-Graven-
O'Gonnan, E., "Lewis Hanke on the Spanish Struggle for Justice in the Conquest hage, 1963)
of America," Hispanic American Historical Review 29 (1949): 563- 71 Previte-Orton, C. W., The DefenS<Jr Pacis of Marsilius of Padua (Cambridge, 1928)
Oliger, L ., "Fr. Bonagratia de. Bergamo ~t eius Tr~cta~s de Christi ~t aposto- Pugliese, G., '"Res corporales', 'res incorporales' e ii problema del diritto sogge-
lorum paupertate," Arch1vum Franc1scanum htStoncum 22 (1929). 292-335, tivo," Studi in onore di Vincenzo Arangio-Ruiz 3 (Naples, 1954): 223-60
487-511
Quillet, J., IA philosophie politique de Marsile de Padoue (Paris, 1970)
Ostwald, M., Nomos and the Beginnings of Athenian Democracy (Oxford, 1969)
Rapaczynski, A ., Nature and Politics (Ithaca, NY, 1987)
Ott, H., "Zur Wirtschaftsethik des Konrad Summenhart," Vierteljahrschrift fiir
Raphael, D.D., "Human Rights, Old and New," in id., ed., Political Theory and the
Sozial-und Wirtschaftsgeschichte 53 (1966): 1-26
Riglrts of Man (Bloomington, 1%7), 54-67
Otte, G., Das Privatrecht bei Francisco de Vitoria (Cologne, 1964)
Rasmussen, D.B. and D.J. den Uyl. Liberty and Nature. An Aristotelian Defense of
Ozment, S., Homo Spiritualis (Leiden, 1969) Uberal Order (LaSalle, 1991)
- -, "The University and the Church. Patterns of Reform in Jean Gerson," Me-· Recasens Siches, L., La filosofia de! derecho de Francisco Suarez (Mexico City, 1947)
dievalia et Humanistica, n.s.l (1970): 111-26 Regis, E., ed., Gewirth's Ethical Rationalism: Critical Essays With a Reply by Alan
Pagden, A., "Rethinking the Linguistic Tum: Current Anxieties in Intellectual His- Gewirlh (Chicago, 1984)
tory," Journal of the History of Ideas 49 (1988): 519-29
Reid, C.J. "The Canonistic Contribution to the Western Rights Tradition: An His-
- -, The Fall of Natural Man (Cambridge, 1982) torical Inquiry," Boston College Law Review 33 (1991 ): 37-92
_ _ , <!J., The Languages of Political Theory in Early-Modern Europe (Cambridge. Roensch, F.J., Early Tlromislic School (Dubuque, 1964)
1987) Rommen, H., Die Staatslehre des Franz Suarez (Munchen-Gladbach, 1926)
Pangle, T., The Spirit of Modern Republicanism (Chicago, 1988) - -, "The Geneology of Natural Rights," Thought 29 (1954): 403-25
Pascoe, L., Jean Gerson: Principles of Church Reform (Leiden, 1973) - -, The Natural Law. A Study in Legal and Social History and Philosophy (St.
- -, "Law and Evangelical Liberty in the Thought of Jean Gerson," in Proc_ee~­ Louis, 1947)
ings of the Sixth International Congress of Medieval Canon Law. Monumenta 1uns Rorty, R., ''The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy," in A.R. Malachowski, ed.,
canonici, Series C: Subsidia, 7 (Vatican City, 1985): 351-61 Reading Rorty. Critical Responses to Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (and
Pateman, C., The Sexual Contract (Stanford, 1988) Beyond) (Oxford, 1990), 279-302
Patterson, L., "On the Margin: Postmodemism, Ironic History, and Medieval Stud- Rosenbaum, A.S., ed., Philosophy of Human Rights (Westport, CT, 1980)
ies," Speculum 65 (1990): 87- 108 Roshwald, M., "The Concept of Human Rights," Philosophy and Phenomenological
Pennington, K., "Bartolome de Las Casas and the Tradition of Medieval Law," Research 19 (1958-59): 354-79
Church History 39 (1970): 149-61 Ryan, A., Property (Minneapolis, 1987)
- - , Pope and Bishops. The Papal Monarchy in the Twelfth and Thirteenth Centuries St. Leger, J., The "Etiamsi daremusn of Hugo Grotius. A Study in the Origins of lutrr-
(Philadelphia, 1984) national Law (Rome, 1962)
- - The Prince and the Law (Berkeley, 1993) Samuel, G., " Epi~temology, Propaganda and Roman Law: Some Reflection<1 on th1•
Penn~k. J.R and K. Baier, eds., Human Riglrls: Nomos XXll (New York, 1981) History of tht• Suhj('divc• Right," /mirnal a/ Legal History 10 (1989): 161- 79
Piaia, G., Marsilio de Padaua nelfa riforma e nelfa contrariforma (Padua, 1977) Savigny, F.C. vnn, SV11lr1111ft'~ lir11l1.~ru IWmisdrrn Rrc11ts (Berlin, 1840)
Plamenatz, J.P., Consent, Freedom and Political Ohli!{atiorr (Oxford, 19:18) Saxonhousc.•, A W , W11111ru 111 tlir lll11l1•rv 11/ l 1111iliml Thought. Anrirnt Grrrcr 111
Pocock, J.G.A., "The Concepl of lanKUl'l~l' and tlw mftil•r d'hi~toric_n_: So~l' Con· Mad1inrir/11 (Nrw Yorio, l'IH'\)
sidcrations on Prnl"lkt•," In A l'11Kdt•n, t'tl., Tlrr I 1111,1./1111,t.11'" of 1'11/tl1rnl 1 ltr11r_11111 S<·hol1, R., Wi/11rl111 '"'" I 1, Atr1tt" 1tl1 r~•/111•• t1rt I ,,.,,A,.r 1111.I .~ri11 llrr1iil111111ium 1lr l''lnn
t:nrl_v M1"Nlrn1 /:11m1ir (l ·.1111hrhlK•'. l'IH7), 1•1 :lH t"''" 1111111111/n• (~ll11llM-'t I, I UU)
364 BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY 365

Schwarz, R., "Circa naturam iuris subiectivi," Periodica de re morali canonica litur- - -, " Natural Rights in the Thirteenth Century. A Quaestio of Henry of Ghent,"
gica 69 (1980): 191-200 Speculum 67 (1992): 58-68
Shapiro, I., " Realism in the Study of the History of ldeas,H History of Political - -, "Ockham, the Conciliar Theory and the Canonists," Journal of the History of
Thought 3 (1982): 535-78 Ideas, 15 (1954): 40-70
- - , The Evolution of Rights in Liberal Theory (Cambridge, 1986) - -, Origins of Papal Infallibility, 1150-1350, 2d ed. (Leiden, 1989)
Sigmund, P., "The Influence of Marsilius on Fifteenth-Century ConciHarism," four"' -.. - -, Religion, Law, and the Growth of Constitutional Thought, 1150-1650 (Cam-
nal of the History of Ideas 23 (1962): 393-402 bridge, 1982)
Skinner, Q., The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, 2 vols. (Cambridge, ·' - - -, "Religious Rights: An Historical Perspective," in]. Witte, Jr. and J. van der
1978) Vyver, eds., Religious Human Rights in Global Perspective: Religious Perspectives
Sommerville, J.P., "From Suarez to Filmer: A Reappraisal," Historical Journal 25 (The Hague, 1996), 17-45
(1982): 525-40 - -, "Tuck on Rights: Some Medieval Problems," History of Political Thought 6
Spiecs, K.E., "The Ecclesiastical Poverty Theory of Marsilius of Padua. Sources (1983): 429- 41
and Significance," II pensiero politico 10 (1977): 5-21 - -, "Villey, Ockham, and the Origin of Natural Rights," inJ. Witte, Jr., and F.S.
Stein, P., " Donellus and the Origins of the Modern Civil Law," in J.A. Ankum Alexander, eds., The Weightier Matters of the Law: Essays on Law and Religion
et al., eds., Melanges Felix Wubbe (Fribourg, 1993), 429-52 (Atlanta, 1988), 1- 31
Stickler, A., "Imperator vicarius papae," Mitteilungen des lnstituts Jilr Oesterreichis- - - and P. Linehan, eds., Authority and Por~r. Studies on Medieval Law and Gov-
che Gesdrichtsforschung 62 (1954): 165-212 ernment Presented to Walter Ullmann (Cambridge, 1980)
Strauss, L., Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1953) Tocco, F., La quistione della poverta net secolo XIV (Naples, 1910)
Stiimer, W., Peccatum und Potestas (Sigmaringen, 1987) Tuck, R., "Grotius, Cameades and Hobbes," Gratiana, n.s. 4 (1983): 43-62
Sumner, L.W., The Moral Foundation of Rights (Oxford, 1987) - - , "Grotius and Selden," in J. H . Burns, ed., The Cllmbridge History of Political
Thought, 1450-1700 (Cambridge, 1991), 499-529
Tabarroni, A., Paupertas Christi et apostolorum. L'ideale francescano in discussione
(1322-1324) (Rome, 1990) - -, Natural Rights Theories. Their Origin and Development (Cambridge, 1979)
Tarello, G., "Profili giuridici della questione della poverta nel Francescanesimo - - , Philosopl1yand Gouernment 1572- 1651 (Cambridge,1993)
prima di Ockham," Universita degli studi di Genova. Annali della Jaco/ta di - - , 'The ' Modem' Theory of Natural Law," in A. Pagden, ed., The umguagei; of
giurisprudenza 3 (1964): 338-448 Political Tlreory in Early-Modern Europe (Cambridge, 1987), 99-119
Thomson, J.j., The Realm of Rights (Cambridge, Mass., 1990) Tully, J., A Discoime on Property. John Locke and His Adversaries (Cambridge, 1980)
Tierney, B., "Aristotle and the American Indians-Again. Two Critical Discus- Turley, T., "John XXIJ and the Franciscans: A Reappraisal," in J.R. Sweeney and
sions," Cristinnesimo nella storia 12 (1991): 295-322 S. Chodorow, eds., Popes, Teachers, and unon Law in the Middle Ages (Ithaca,
- -, "Conciliarism, Corporatism, and Individualism. The Doctrine of Sub- NY, 1989), 74-88
jective Rights in Gerson," Cristinnesimo nella storia 9 (1988): 81- 110 Ullman, S., Semantics (New York, 1%2)
- - , Foundations of the Conciliar Theory (Cambridge, 1955) Ullmann, W., A History of Political Thought. The Middle Ages (Harmondsworth,
- -, "Hierarchy, Consent, and the Western Tradition," Political Theory 15 (1987): 1970)
646-52 van der Vyver, J., "The Doctrine of Private-Law Rights," in S. A. Straus.-; f'tl.,
- --, "lus dictum est a iure possidendo: Law and Rights in Decretales 5.40.12," in H11ldigu11gsbundel vir W. A. foubert (Durban, 1988), 201-46
O. Wood, ed., Church and Sovereignty, c. 590-1915: Essays in Honour of Michael Veraja, F., Lt orixini delln contrm1rrsia teoloxica sul contralto di censo nrl X1ll $1•cfllo
Wilks (Oxford, 1991), 457-66 (Rome, 1%0)
- -, "Marsilius on Rights," Journal of the History of ldra~ 5..'l ( JqqJ): :l- 17 Verbekt>, G ., TJ,,. t'rr.~1·111 ·1· 11/ Sl1111·1!<m ;,, M1·1li,.,.,1/ Tl111111~hl (Washington, D .C , 1Wl1)
---,Medieval Poor Law (Berkeley and Los An~dt•s, 1959) Villey, M., " /\hn\x•\ du tlmll 1111t11rt'I d11ro!'li•111r ,"Arr11i1>rs dr plril11tte1plrir r/11 11mil t>
- - , "Natu ral I.aw nm.I Canon I A1W in< kkham'!I l>i11/o,'<11.~ ." in J.<;. Row<>, t•d ., (1%1): 27 71
As1H'cts of 111t1• Mrili1•1111/ C111•t'rm111'11f ""'' Sod.-11(. /:11.'ilr_y11 l'ri'.~l'llfl'1f l11 /. ~ f J1111lrr , " Hc.•111'111111 rl 1., 1l111ll 111th11cil 1 l.- 1u11t11u·:· /lrd1il't'.~ <Ir 11Jii11J.•1•1•l1il' 1/111lr1•il 17
(foronto, l'IHt1), :1 2-t (1472): 421 11
366 BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAP HY 367
- - , "Bible et philosophie grero-romaine de Saint Thomas au droit modeme," - -, Privatrechtsgeschichte der Neuzeit, 2d ed. (Gottingen, 1967)
Archives de philoscphie du droit 18 (1973): TJ-57 Wilenius, R., The Social and Political Theory of Francisco Suarez (Helsinki, 1963)
- - -, Critique fh la pensk juridique moderne (douu autres essais) (Paris, 1969) Wilks, M ., The Problem of Suvereignty in the I.Ater Middle Ages (Cambridge, 1963)
- - - , "Droit subjectif et subjectivisme juridique," Arc.hives de philoscphie du droit
Wohlmuth, J., "Konziliarismus und Verfassing der Kirche," Concilium 19 (1983):
9 (1964): 17-35 522-26
- - , "Du sens de I' expression jus in re en droit romain classique," in Melanges
Wolf, E., Das Problem der Natu"echtslehre, 3d ed. (Karlsruhe, 1964)
Fernand de Visscher, IJ. Revue internationale des droits de l'antiquite 2 (1949):
417-36 Wulf, M . de, "L' individu et le groupe dans la scolastique du Xllle siecle," Revue
neoscolastique de philosophie 22 (1920): 341-57
- -, Ui formation de lo pens« juridique moderne, 4th ed. (Paris, 1975)
Yolton, J.S. and J.W. Yolton, John Locke. A Reference Guide (Boston, 1985)
- - - , " La genese du droit subjectif chez Guillaume d'Occam," Archives de plti-
losophie du droit 9 (1964): 97-127 Zuckerman, C., "The Relationship of Theories of Universals to Theories of Church
Government in the Middle Ages: A Critique of Previous Views," fournal of
- - , Le~ d'histoire de la philosophie du droit (Paris, 1957)
the History of Ideas 35 (1973): 579- 90
- - , Les droits de l'homme et la Joi naturelle (Paris, 1945)
- -, Le droit et les droits de l'homme (Paris, 1983)
- -, "Le 'jus in re' du droit romain classique au droit modeme," in Conferences
Jaites a l'Jnstitut de Droit Romain en 1947 (Paris, 1950), 187-225
- - , Philosophie du Droit: 1. Dejinilions et fins du droit, 3d ed. (Paris, 1982)
- -, Philosophie du Droit: 2. Les moyens du droit, 2d ed. (Paris, 1984)
- - , "Problematique des droits de l'homme," in Uis Casas et la politique des droits
de l'homme (AU<-en-Provence, 1976), 369-73
---,Recherches sur la littirature didactique du droit romain (Paris, 1946)
- -, "Saint Thomas dans l'histoire des sources," in Etudes d'histoire du droit
canonique dediks a Gabriel le Bras, 2 vols. (Paris, 1965), 1:355-95
- -, Seize essais de philosophie du droit (Paris, 1969)
- - , "Suum jus cuique tribuens," in Studi in onore di Pietro de Francisci, 4 vols.
(Milan, 1956), 2:361-71
- - , "Travaux recents sur les droits de l'homme," Archives de philosophie du droit
26 (1981): 411- 18
- - and G. Kalinowski, " La mobilite du droit naturel chez Aristote et Thomas
d 'Aquin," Archives de philoscphie du droit 29 (1984): 187-99
VilJoslada, R., LA rmivusidad de Paris durante las estudios de Francisco de Vitoria, OP
(1507-1522)(Rome, 1938)
Vona, P. di, I principi del Defensor Pacis (Naples, 1974)
Vonlanthen, A., Zum m:htsphilosophisc.hen Streit iiber das Wesen der subjectiven Rechts
(Zurich, 1964)
Waldron, J.W., The Right to Property (Oxford, 1990)
Weigand, R., Die Natu"echtslehre der Le_gisten _und Dekr~tistm von lrnnius bis Ar-
cursius und von Gratian bis Johnnnes fe11tomcu!l (Munich, 1%7)
Weil, Simone, Simmrr Wril. A11 Antl111lo,'{_ll• S. Mllt'll, t'(t. (I .oncfon, I9Mj
.
,l'

Wlt•ackt-r, JI., "Contr11d1111 111111 ( lhllK11lln 111 Nnlurrt•d1t 1.wh1dwn Sl'lllm-hc1ln11tk


um.I A11tl.IMn1t11(," In I' <;ruul, ..i1 , I 11 • r1·11111l11 111·11l111•tf111 {Mllim, 1'17:1), 22:1 :N

L
.. ..
,• . .,. ...
.. .. .
• .-;

INDEX

Abel, 142, 155, 165 Andrf.-\Tmcent, Philippe, 257, 274-275,


Abril Castell6, V., 256, 274 276
Abraham, 144, 145, 155, 165 Angelo de Clavasio, 106, 243
Acosta, Jose de, 321 Anglo-imperial alliance of 1337, 196
Act of Supremacy, 296 Animals, rights of, 717, 248-249, 267- 268
actio, 19, 123, 219, 262, 303 Antigone, 45
-See also ius. Apparatus, Militant siquidem, 73
Accursius, 41 Apostolic poverty. See Franciscan
Ad conditorem, 95, 330 poverty dispute
Adam and Eve, 13, 62, 132, 139, 141, Aquinas, Thomas. See Thomas Aquinas
142, 145, 147, 151, 152, 153, Aristotle, 1, 21, 71, 23, 25, 28, 31, 38, 45,
155, 157, 158- 159, 160-161, 105, 146, 238,245,254, 260, 263,
162, 167, 169, 174, 200, 203, 226, 265, 267,270,271,276, 277,278,
231,238,264,308,310,311 291, 326
- See also Garden of Eden; State of -Aristotelianism and Aristotelian",
Nature, or Innocence 2, 14, 20, 30, 34, 45, 98, 110, 130,
Adams, Marilyn M., 99 173, 189, 216, 251, 261, 262, 269,
Adrian I, 175 271, 276, 277,287,291 , 292,309, J2~
Alanus Anglicus, 54, 58, 73, 102, 141, 179, - theory of natural slavery, 254,
180, 328 265- 266,270, 271,277
Alberigo, G., 208 auctoritas, 293, 294
Alexander V, 223 Augustine, St., 119, 126, 127, 128, 139,
Alexander Vl, 280, 282 143, 166, 171,371, 326
Alexander of HaJes, 146-147, 178, Azo, 29
265
Almain, Jacques, 87, 88, 233, 234, Baier, Kurt, 14
236, 237, 238,239,262, 264, 292, Baldus, 280, 282, 325
294-295 Balzac, Honore, 47
Ambrose, St., 72, 137 Barbeyrac, Jean, 318
American India ns, 144, 254, 255, 256, 257, Barry, N ., 341
265,261>, 26q,271,272- 2R7, 290 Bartolus, 106, 243,282, 325
- and tl1>1111111011, 1t1'i 172 Bastit, Michel, '17, 126, 192, 196, 197-198,
- right!' of l111ll'1111t1lrlrn1l<'<I, 271 2R6 202
- St'\• nl"41, l11lhlPI", 1.... t ••u. ll<•nton, J.F., ~
llnrtoMm.-11, V1tu11... 111..111 1.. " 1lr ti.•n!Mtn, Rckrt L.., ~

l
370 INDEX INDEX 371

Bentham, Jeremy, 117 C hristianity, 26, 27, 35, 45, 134, 140, 200, Cover, Robert, 214 135, 143, 159, 160, 167, 167, 171,
Berger, Nan, 21 201, 213, 265, 274, 287, 288, 343,347 Cranston, Maurice, 3, 4 218, 240, 242, 260, 262, 265, 268,
Berlin, Isaiah, 14 -and the origin of rights theories, Crockaert, Pierre, 256 295, 325, 330
Berman, Harold J., 35, 56 23, 27, 45, 46, 68, 211-212, 215 C rowe, M.B., 53, 319 -dominium suorum acluum, 86, 268
Bernard of Parma, 26, 283 -Church reform and rights, 225-228 Cum intl'T nonnullos, % , 102, 120, 125 -dominium sui, 268, 271
-See also Ordinary Gloss to -creatures in God's image and -dominium utile, 244
Decretals rights, 269, 287, 327, 343 d' Ailly, Pierre. 87, 224, 234 -See alsoJacultas; ius; potestas;
Berns, Walter, 33, 215 - Eastern Orthodoxy and rights, 215 Dabin, Jean, 34, 70, 117 Property, right of; Rights
Besselink, L., 320 - modem papacy and rights, 343 Oamiata, M., 111 dominus, 16, 17, 154, 243-244, 268, 269
Blumenberg. Hans, 287 -primitive Church, 134-135, 140, David, 219, 232 Donnelly, Jack, 2, 3
Bobbio,N.,3 156, 157, 291, 340 Davis, David Brion, 337 Dover, Kevin J., 45
Black, Antony, 209, 213, 214, 309, 335 Chroust, Anton-Hennann, 318 Dawson, J.O., 229 Driedo, Johannes, 109, 304
Boehner, Philotheus, 32 Cicero, 46,63, 65, 273, 326, 330 Decalogue. See Ten Commandments Dufour, Allred, 327
Bologna, University of, 201 Clark, D.W., 99, 100 Deckers, Daniel, 257, 258, 261, 294, 298 Dumont, Louis, 14, 118, 208, 212
Bonagratia of Bergamo, 35, 96, 103, Clement I, Pope, n , 139 Declaration of Independence, 1, 344 Duns Srotus, 35, 147, 148, 178, 256, 264,
116, 119, 148- 155, 157, 158, Clement VI, 229 Declaration of Rense, 196 265, 324
161, 162 Coing, Helmut, 19, 106 Declaration of Rights of Man and -Srotists, 5
Bonaventure, St., 36, 37, 94, 147, 150 Coleman, Janet, 63 Citizen, 344 Durandus of Saint Pour.;ain, 237, 238
Boniface VIII, 26 Columbus, Christopher, 236 Decretists, 43, 54, 64, 68, 71, 79, 102, 117, Dworkin, Ronald, 134, 193
Bozeman, A.B., 322 Comas, Juan, 272 140, 141, 151-152, 154, 167, 170,
Brett, Annabel, 9, 113, 245 Combes, Andre, W9, 210 178, 202, 265, 345 Edwards, Charles S., 319
Broadie, A ., 242 Communero revolt, 290 - Bolognese school, 67 Eltis, D., 254
Brown, C.D., 226 Composta, Dario, 118, 304 - English school, 67-68 rnromadaos, 281
Buckland, W.W., 17 Conciliar movement, 8, 87, 207, 208-209, D'Entre ves, A.P., 4 English Civil War, 253
Buckle, Stephen, 333 220, 232, 236, 253, 344 Denunciation, evangelical, 74 Enlightenment, 208, 289, 333, 343, 344,
Bulgarus, 183 -and rights. W9-210, 220- 225, 228, Den Uyl. D.J., 133, 263, 340 345,347
Burlamaqui, J.J., 180, 333, 340 233, 234 Descartes, Rene, 19, 321 Epicurus, 291, 321
Bums, J.H., 236 Condren, Conal, 110, 111 -Cartesian rationalism, 274 Erasmus, 242
Bynum, Caroline Walker, 56, 213 Congar, Yves, 37, 222, 284 Dietrich of Niem, 234 Eschmann, l.T., 213
Constable, Giles, 56 dikaion, 21 , 22, 25, 26, 28 Evangelical Liberty, 53, 186, 187, 18R, 1'14,
Cain, 142, 145, 165 Constance, Council of, 221, 223, 229, 233, Diogenes Laertius, 45, 46 214,226-227,228, 239
Cajetanus, 301 266 Distinctiont?S Bambergenses, 67 -and rights, 187-188, 228
Calvinist resistance theories, 289, 337 Copemicus, Nicolaus, 236 Divine law, 39, 112, 114, 151, 155, 162, Exiit, 94, 95, 96, 121. 126, 149, 150, :no
Canon Law, 8, 24-25, 26-Zl 43-77, 111, Corporatism, medieval, 55-56, 110, 207, 165, 172, 174- 175, 187, 219,226,
201, 211. 219, 258, 262, 276, 279, 209-210, 221, 234 292, 293, 297, 305, 324 Facu ftas, 50, 67, 69, 220, 246, 247, 261 , :12~.
281. 282, 285, 322 -corporation law, 110, 184- 186, 203, -absolute, 98, 197, 200. 326
Canonists, 32, 35, 36, 40, 43- 77, 101, 209, 212- 214, 234, 285 - See also Divine Power; ius divinum; -li~r facultas, 307
102, 120, 153, 167, 176-177, 185, - locus of jurisdiction in Ockham, William of; Ten -See also ius; potestas; Rights
200-203, W9, 223-224, 230, 234, corporations, 309 Commandments; Voluntarism Fall of Man. See Adam and Eve; Stall' of
240,245, 254,284, 286, 300, 320 - fictive theory of corporations, 213 Divine Po wer, 30, 98, 185, 190, 197, 200 Nature, or Innocence
-See also Decretists; Gratian - "right-subjectivity" in -See also Divine Law; ius divinum; Fas, 59, 61, 67, 84, 246
Carlyle, A.J. and R.W., 135 corporations, 212-213 Ockham, William of; Ten -See also ius; potestas; Rights
Carneades,317,321 , 323 -See also Corpus mysticum; Commandments; Voluntarism Feenstra, Robert, 318, 319, 330
Carro, Venancio D., 256, 271, 274 Individualist ethic, and relation to Di Vo na, P , 111 Feinberg, Joel, 49, 50, 74
Catherine of Aragon, 296 communal ethic; Mys tical Body Dolcini, Carlo, 110 Felden, Johann von, 318
Charlemagne, 175 Corplls mysticum, 209, 224 Domat, Jean, J40 Feltmann, Gerhard, 15
Charles V, 278 -SN- also Corporatism , medieval; Dominican Onln, R1. lll4, 2"i7, 2."11, in, Feminists, 133
Charron, Pierre, 320, 321 My!'itkal Body 2Rh, 2H7 Fernandez-Santamaria, J.A., 256, 21\H
Chesterton, G.K., J.'i ( "urtl~'. !~in, IW Oominku11 di• Si\111111 I ;..11111(11111111. 1H2 Ft>m<1ndez de Oviedo y Valdk, ( ;., 2~
Chiappa, T>ioCP!I(' of, 276 ( ·uurl<'ll"Y· Wllli1101 L 12. fl1 tfonrirrillm, It•. 17, I''· /IJ, 411. '17, "''· H'I, l'icht('r, J.ft., :101, :102
China, J21 <'u11vn•11r. ( :1111•... 70 74 1110 lllf. IU'\, llln. 111, 114 If'\ l'lk•·nt~lwr, W., J22

l
372 INDEX INDEX 373

Filmer, Robert, 132, 159, 162, 167, 333 Glenn, G .D., 81 Helm, P., 98, 99 Infidels, rights of, 144, 172, 231, 254,
Fmnis, John. 4, 22. 34, 45, 118, 304 Glossa ad compi/Jltionmr I, 73 Henley, John A., 46 264-265, 266-267, 271, 275,277,
FitzRalph, Richard, 229, 238, 266 Godfrey of Fontaines, 37, 38, 200 Hen.r y Vm, 296 282
Flew, Antony, 3 Goldast, Melchior, 198 Henry of Ghent, 8, 37, 78-89, 93, 117, 132. -See also American Indians
Florentinus, 326 Golden Rule, 23, 59, 61 200, 300 iniuria, 268, 269
Folgado, A., 109, 304 Golding, Martin P., 14 Hering. H.M., 23 Innocent lll 57, 184, 185, 187, 192, 213,
Forbes, 0 ., 333 Gordley, James R., 58 Hermogenianus, 136 285
Gorrell, Jean de, 223
Francis of .AMisi, St., 35, 94, 95, 150, 157, Hervaeu s Natalis, 103, 104-108, 113, 118, Innocent IV, 94, 143, 144. 156, 1n, 254.
214 Grabmann, Martin, 105 130, 182, 222,243 267, 277, 282,309,330, 333
-Rule of, 94, 95, 149, 214 Gratian, 23,24,25,26,40, 54, 56,56,58, Hobbes, Thomas, 1, 3, 6, 18, 42, 43, 51, 52, intatsSe, 262
Franciscan Order, 29, 33, 93, 94, 106, 108, 59,60, 61, 62,64,65. 66, 69,84, 101, 65,78,81, 82, 99, 133, 214, 263,289, Isaac, 155
121, 122; and rights, 17-28, 35, 79, 127, 137, 139, 141, 143, 144, 165, 340-341 Isidore of Seville, 24, 59, 67, 124, 142.• 146,
83, 131, 142,145, 164,223,268, 330 168, 176,201, 223, 263, 264,280, Hoffner, }., 275 178, 179, 234
-Poverty dispute, 7, 8, 30, 36-37, 38, 286, 319, 320, 323 Hohfeld, Wesley N ., 8, 48, 55, 314 ls-Ought Problem, 5-6, 344
93-97, 104, 10'1, 108, 110, 111, 115, Gray, J., 132 Hokot, Robert, 88 Israel. 1
118-130, 133, 135, 148-157, 158, Great Schism, W, 229 H onorius III, 26 ius, passim
164, 167, 169, 170, 171, 174, 195, Gregory IX, 27, 94, 150, 186 Horace, 326, 330 -as moral precept or divine
196,199, 207,216,219,229,236, Gregory of Rimini, 305 Horowitz, M.C., 46 command, 24, 25
243,262,307,330, 344 Gregory the Great, 38, 186 Hostiensis, 73, 83, 119-120, 144, 145, 182, -ius ad rem and in re, 19, 58, 220,
Fraticdli, 207 Gross, Carl, 106 266, 277, 309 28.3,303, 326
Frederick II, 172 Grossi, Paolo, 37, 147, 268 Huber, Ulricus, 318, 326 -iusagendi, 119
Frederick Barbarossa, 183 Grotius, Hugo, 3, 42, 50, 51, 73, 89, 100, Huguccio, 54, 57, 58, 60-61, 64, 65, 68, 71, -ius altius tollendi, 16
Freppert, L., 99 103, 109, 117, 132, 135, 167, 180, 72,73,74, 75, 102, 103, 137, 139, -ius charitatis or ius evangtlicum,
Friede, Juan, 281 215,288, 289,305,316-341, 140, 141, 142, 143, 145, 146, 159, 216
Fuentes, Carlos, 77 345, 346 167, 170, 176, 203, 265, 279, -ius dominii, 23, 157, 171
-defense of absolutism, 336-337 330, 333 - ius tpiscopale, 218
Gagner, Sten, 100-101 -definition of subjective right, Hugh of St. Victor, 330 -iu.s possidmdi, 23, 119
Caius, 15, 16, 23, 136, 137, 144 325-326 Human nature, 5, 6, 24, 26. -ius suum cuiqut tributrt, 16, 25, 30J
Gallicanism, 83 -foundations of natural-law - autonomy of, 46; -ius utendi, 16, 29, 37, 94, 120, 121
Garcia, A., 78 thought, 322-324 -capacity for moral discernment, 6, -ius and dominium compared, 16 17.
Garden of Eden, 134, 149 -individual rights and society, 77,99, 197,305,327 105, 106, 107, 113-114,242,243, 244,
-See also Adam and Eve; State or 333-336 -mutable character, 23-24 247, 248, 250, 260,267-268
Nature, or Innocence - right to property, 329-333 -premise for natural rights, 36, 193, - ius and fas compared, 59, 246
Garrett, w., 52 -right of resistance, 337-338 271- 272, 317, 343 -ius and libtrtas compared, 189
(;ellinek, Christian, 319 -scholarly assessments, 318-322 -See also Natural Law; Natural -ius and pottstas compared, 28,
(;erman Peasants War of 1524, 290 - slavery, 336-337 Right; Rights 29,39, 40- 41 , 85, 107, 104-108, 325
(;erson,Jean,3,8, 53, 54, 55,64,65,67,69, -use of the medieval tradition, Humanists, renaissance, 242, 252, 253, -ius as facultas, 64, 201, 210, 220, 22.1,
75, 76, 89, 109 20'1-235, 236, 239, 338- 339, 341-342 341 227, 229,243,261, 262,303, 304, 32~
242. 245, 246, 250, 253, 259, 261, Grunebaum, J.O ., 133 Hume, David, 5, 6, 22, 274, 333, 343, 344 -ius as "objective law" and
262, 267, 271, 290,296,299, 304, Guido de Baisio, 27, 54, 102, 177, 180, 202, -See also ls-Ought Problem "subjective right," 105, 109
313, 339, 340 286 Hus, Jan, 32, 214, 221 112-113, 116-117, 119-120,
-active and passive rights, 217-220 Guillaume de St. Amour, 222 -Hussites, 229 125-126, 127, 128, 129, 234,
-church reform and rights, 225-228 242-243, 264, 324
-forms of dominion. 230-233 Haakonssen, Knud, 3, 73, 319 lannarone, Agostino, 255 ius eivi/e, 25, 112, 119, 242
- "Gersonians," 219-220 Hate sane/a, 221 lhering, Rodolf von, 117 ius consuttudrnis, 127
-droit as right, 223 Habermas, JUrgen,44, 45,49, 52 Indians, American. See American ius divinum, 23, 61, 242
-ius as subjective power, 210 Haggenmacher, Peter, 3 16, 319, 324, 334, lndi;ms ius dominatiuum, 306
Gewirth, Alan, 2, 3, 17, 41, 48 JJ9 lndividuali!>I l'lhic, i11lll n ·l11tion to c-om- ius gmti11m, 25, 136, t:\7, 307, :\()ft
Gierke, Otto von, 184-1 85, 208, 213 1lnmilton, 8 ., 256, 299 m111111l 1•thk. 4, 'ii\ 1\6, 711, I JO. 1%. i11s /ibertatis, 57
Giles of Rome, 147, 14A, 172, 229, 26.'i I fnnk•·. l -4"wh1. 2.c;(), 27J. 274, Jin 20H 7 I"/. 1·14, J \'\, J'>ti 'JW. :1111. 111$ 11nt11rnlr. 20. 2.1, 24, 25, 27, :\.1, :N, 4h,

Gillet, P., :H 1 lnnllnK, A I.., ~~ ·111 II I. t.'4. 14fl 411. 54, .'>II, 61 , 1>2, M - hll. ""· 7 1. 7t1,
Glmclon. Mary Ann, :14t1 I ltn l. 111 . A . 4t•. 411, t>H, 7 1, 1•1 S.'i' 111•11 l "''"" 1111•111, """ '"' ,... , 'Ill, 112. 122, 117. l'N, 141, 14'\, l'il.
374 INDEX I N llEX ~75

ius naturalt (cont.) - See also Property, right of; Lipsius, Justus, 320 Mallingly, Garrett, 262
175,176, 179, 186,201,264, 305, Sovereignty Livy, 17 Marx, Karl, 208, 345
324,327 juslt partage, 22, 25 Lloyd, H.A, 302 Melden, A.I., 14
-as reason, 64, 141, 201 Justenhoven, H .-G., 288 Locke, John, I, 3, 6, 42, 43, 51, 75, 76, 77, Melloni, Alberto, 1 n
-decretist definitions, 58-64 Justinian, 137 78, 79, 80, 81, 132, 135, 159, 168, Menhldez Pidal, R., 2n
-ius poli, 94-95, 199, 210 183,203,215, 248, 330,333,340 Meuthen, Eric,208, 209
-compared with iusfori, 118-130 Kalinowski, G., 24 toxos. 22 Mexico, 256
- ius naturale and ius positivum Kant, Immanuel, 18, 20, 22, 118 Lopez, Robert, 131 Meyjes, G .H .M. Posthumus, 209
compared, 123 Kantorowicz, Ernst, 213 Lot, 144, 145 Michael ofCese.na, 95, 96, 125, 148, 153,
-See also Natural Law; Natural Keen, B., 272 Lottin, Odon, 60 155, 195
Right; Natural Rights Kelley, Donald R., 168 Louden, Robert L., 49 Michaud-Quantin, Pierre, 110, 209
iustiti.a, 221, 262, 302, 309 Kilcullen, John, 99, 172 Louis xm, 318 Michelangelo, 236
Kolmel, W., 31, 97, 178 Lovejoy, Arthur 0., 48 Miller, Fred D., 45, 26.3
Jacob, 165 Kuttner, Stephan, 60, 64, 67, 68, 126, 140 Lucretius, 291, 321 Minogue, Kenneth, 3
Jacobus de Albenga, 27 Luhmann, Niklas, 132, 261 Molina, Luis de, 220, 245, 304, 330
Jaffa, H ., 215 Lacey, M.T., 73 Luii.o Pena, A.E., 274, 275, 279 Monahan, Arthur P., 255
James I, 302 La Capra, Dominick, 47, 48 Luther, Martin, 227, 236, 290 Montaigne, Michel de, 320, 321
Jarlot, G., 301 Lachance, Louis, 304 -Lutheran doctrine of monarchy, More, Thomas, 253
Jefferson, Thornas, l , 346 Lagarde, Georges de, 14, 31, 44, 45, 52, 83, 296 Morrall, J.B., 31, 32, 97, 209, 210, 216
Jesus Christ, 29, 55, 95, 96, 111, 115, 120, 97, 101, 111, 116, 171, 175, 180, 181, Lyons, David, 46, 249 Morris, Colin. 56, 214
144, 149, 150, 153, 154, 156, 157, 196, 201, 234-235 Moses, 1, 145,155
18.5, 187, 190, 211, 215, 22, 223, Lambert, M.D., 36, 93 Macfarlane, A., 55 -Mosaic law, 239, 250
295, 299 Las Casas, Bartolomeo de, 255, 256, Macintyre, Alisdair, 2, 3, 43, 44, 344 Muldoon, James, 144, 262, 266, 319, 340
Jewish Law, 254, 337 272-287, 302 MacPherson, CB., 44, 52, 78, 79 Muslims, 254
Johannes Andreae, 41, 125-126, 129, 144 -legal arguments against Spanish McCloskey, H .J., 79 Mystical Body, 209-210, 211, 212, 215,
Johannes Monachus, 40-42, 48, 93, conquest, 280-286 McDonnel, K., 99 224, 299
115-116 -natural righl of Liberty, 278-280 McGrade, A.5., 98, 100, 170, 175 -See also Corporatism, medieval;
Johannes Teutonicus, 102, 133, 219 -polemical nature of works, 276-277 McKeon, Richard, 168 Corpus mysticum; Individualist
-See also Ordinary Gloss to Dtcrtlum -refutation of natural slavery, Magna Carla, 47, 95 ethk, and relation to commun<1I
John xxn, 29, JS, 93, 95, 97, 102, 103, 104, 272-273, 277- 278 Machan, Tibor R., 193, 263, 340 ethic
119, 120, 121, 122, 124, 125, 126, - Thomism and rights, 274-276, Machiavelli, Nicolo, 236, 253
129, 131, 142, 144, 148, 149, 153, 280 Mahn-Lot, M ., 275 Natural law, 4, 5, 8, 25, 34, 38, 39, 42,
154, 155, 156, 157, 158, 159, 160, -universal brotherhood, 273 Maine, Henry Sumner, 15, 46 44, 46, 59, 6.3, 119, 175-176,
161, 162, 163, 164, 165, 166, 167, Laurentius Hispanus, 73, 137 Mair, John, 236, 237, 239-242, 244, 245, 177- 187, 302, 304-305, 306, 31 I,
169, 195, 198,207,265, 307, 330, 331 Le Bras, Gabriel, 13 253, 254, 276 317, 323,329
John xxm, 343 Le Goff. Jacques, 212 -rights of the poor, 239- 240 -commands and demonstrations,
John of Naples, 106 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm von, 340 -theory of property, 240-241 62- 63, 138, 139
John of Paris, 147, 148, 170, 201, 222, 224 LeoVIH, 175 Maitland, Frederic W., 70, 203, 213 -correlative with natural rights,
Jolowicz, H .F., 17 Levellers, 52 Martinus, 183 33-34, 199
Jones, J.W., 45 Levi-Strauss, Claude, 18 Maritain, Jacques, 4,34,215 -disobedience to unjust laws,
Judeo-Christian thought, 46, 211, 214, 342 Levy, Ernst, 17 Marrone, J., 83 313-314
Julius Paulus, 46 Lewis, E., 213 Marshall, John, 110 -permissive, 8, 33, 44-45, 51, 66,
Junghans, ff., 32 Lewis of Bavaria, 96, 169 Marsilius of Padua, 103, 104, 108-118, 259,306-307, 311, 328-329
Jurisdiction,171-176,237,238 lex, 22, 25, 51, 53, 65, 68, 116, 211, 221, 228, 119, 120, 129, 130, 182, 243 -source of law of nations, 271, :lt7,
-based on election and consent, 242, 259, 303, 326 - domini11m and use, 114-115 326, 339-340
175- 176, 182,183, 237, 283-284, - lex naturalis, 24, 25, 27, 212 - on objective and subjective right, -suppositious, 179, 305, 327
301 - lex naturt, 67 109, 111 - 113, 115-117 - "what nature has taught all
-derived from God indirectly, l.iber Sextus, 41 - rwrmiss ive law as source of rights, animals," 258
171-172, 185, 237- 238,310 Liberty, evangelical. SN• F.vangelicill 112, 117 - and the majority prindplt>, 2.M
-from Cod directly, 29J-:iq5 liberty iot hol111ly .,~,.•·•~1111•11111 , I Ill 111 - Set- al'IO iu~ nalurall'; Natur11I RIRhl;
-jurisdiction in a corporntlon, '.lel'I l.i1'fl i11ri.Q, llH> M11rtln, l<r •, I I. U l'mpt•rty, rl~ht 11(; RIRhl11
376 INDEX INl>fK 377

Natural right, objective or cla.ssical, 4, 42, 44, 56, 57,68, 75,76, 79,80,87, Pennock, J.R., 14 -Canon law and the origin o f,
20-21,22,23,25, 26, 32-33, 34, 39, 88 94, 96, 104, 105, 107, 108, 109, Perefta, Luciano, 280 137- 145
42, 45, 105 110, 117, 118-130, 135, 144, 145, Perez, Fernando, 219 -Roman law a.nd the origin o f,
-contrasted with subjective natural 148, 154, 157, 170-194,195, Perez de Tudela Bueso, J., 276 135-137
rights, 44-45, 51-52; 54, 143, 175, 196-203, 207, 210, 216, 227, 234, Peru, 255, 256, 321 - theological accounts of origin,
201-202, 234,258-259,324-325 236,237, 239,251,253,256,265, Peter, St., 185, 187, 207, 222 145-148
Natural rights, subjective, passim 276, 279, 286,302,305,310, 328, Peter Abelard, 55 -See also, ius; Rights
- as force or power of the human 333,340,345 Peter Lombard, 257 proprittas, 85, 94, 105
personality, 36, 63-65, 210, 245 - and canonists, 36, 101-103, 164, Philip II, 281 Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph, 168
-derivation from natural law, 4, 38, 167189-194, 198, 200-203 Philo,326 Pufendorf, Samuel, 78, 81, 82, 83, 132,
44, 47, 119, 263, 306 -and development of Western Piaia, G., 118 133, 135, 167, 168, 180, 183, 203,
-derivation from right reason, 65, rights thought, 195-203 Pia menatz, J.P., 49 318,340
128, 164, 166, 193, 199, 200, 210, 227 -and nominalism, 35, 196- 199, 208, Plato, 1, 82, 140, 238 Pugliese, Giovanni, 17
-historiographic issues, 1-6, 43-44, 216 - neo-platonism, 216 Purgatory, 212
48-49, 50, 78-79, 88-89, 195-196, -and property, 157-168, 171-175 - Platonic ideal forms, 31
208,215-216, 236,286,344-345 -importance of right reason, 99-100, -See also Realism, philosophical; Q11ia vir reprob11s, 97, 120, 121, 123, 124,
- of liberty, 53, 187-188, 231 , 272, 173, 174, 175, 193, 198, 199-200 Universals 125. 148, 153. 155, 161
278-280, 306,313,314 -on relationship of natural Jaw and Pocock, J.G.A., 47 Quillet, Jeanine, 111
-of self-defense, 233, 271, 292, natural rights, 175-182 Pollock, Frederick, 213 q11od omnes tangit, 283, 284
296-297, 298, 299, 308, 314 -on rights and the common good, Poor, rights of, see Rights.
-of self-preservation, 79-89, 114, 189- 191, 196 potestas, 17, 28, 29, 39, 40, 41, 57, 85, 105, Rapaczynski, A., 135
117, 237, 239-240, 296-297, 298, -scholarly assessments, 27- 32, 219, 245,246, 247, 260,262,293. Rasmussen, D.B., 263, 340
'299, 308 97- 101 294,325 Realism, philosophical, 31, 32, 196, 216,
-persistence after institution of -types of natural law, 175-182, 202 - potestas co11dt11di leges, 30 241
government, 182, 183, 296, 313, -unity of legal and philosophical - poltslns ulendi, 107 Reformation.• Protestant, 253, 288, 289
315, 336 thought discussed, 31-32, 97-98, -and n11ctoritas, 293- 294 Reid, Charles J., 8, 57, 262
-positive rights and natural rights, 196-200 -and potenttn, 245, 249 Renaissance of the twelfth century, 34,
20, 121-123, 126, 127-128, 241 Odo of Dover, 63 -See also facultas; ius; Rights 55-56, 216
-suppositious natural rights, 179, Odofredus, 193 Poste, E., 15 Republicanism, classical, 88
305,327 Offler, H.S., 102, 176, 177, 179, 181 Pothier, Robert Joseph, 340 res incorporales, 15, 16
ntcessitas, 84, 85 O'Gorman, Edmundo, 2.7 4, 316 Prendes, Perefia Perez, 265, 330 res 11ulli11s, 135, 142, 145, 163, 167, 3JI
Nerva Filius, 135 Olivi, John Peter, 39, 42, 89, 93 Previte-Orton, C. W., 111 Rescasens Sidles, L , 301
Nicholas Ill, 40, 94, 95, 96, 121, 126, 167, Ordinary Gloss to Decrl!fum, 57, 61, 74, 84, Prieras, Sylvester, 41, 106, 219, 245 Ricardus Anglicus, 54, 60, 64, 73, 141
330 85, 102, 128, 133, 181. 193, 219 Property, right of, 131-169, 183, 199, 238, Richard of Conington, 147
Nicholas of Cues, 234-235 Ordinary Gloss to Dtcretals, 25, 27, 57, 125, 264-265,279,300,302, 306, 324 Rights, passim
Nickel, J.W., 13, 44 176, 184, 192, 198 -claims of poor to surplus, 73- 75, -active and passive rights, 3, 4, 7,
Nimrod, 140, 141 Ostwald, M., 45 218, 239- 240, 301, 307, 332 58, 113, 217-218, 219, 220, 249
Noah, 147, 155, 165 Ott, H., 237 - first acquisition, 131-135, 136- 137, -adventitious rights, 7, 180
Nominalism, 8, 20, 23, 28, 29-30, 35 36, Otto, Gerhard, 262 140-141, 142-143, 154-155, -alienable and inalienable rights, I,
41,43, 97, 110, 118, 180, 196- 199, O!!o :, 175 157-159, 160-161, 162-163, 79-80, 93, 181, 182- 183,231,235,
216, 220, 240, 241 , 286 Ozment, Steven, 225 171- 175, 307, 308 238. 295-296, 306
-See also Ockham, William of; - in Gratian and decretists, 59-60, -choice theory compared with
Voluntarism Pacem in ferris, 343 61- 62, 71-73, 137-145 interest theory, 118, 189
Norr, Knut, 119 Pagden, Anthony, 47, 270 -natural dominion, 146, 230- 231, -deprivation of rights for grave
Pangle, T., 133 233,263,308 cause,57-58, 187,202,244, 259
Oakeshott, Michael, 52, 117, 340 Panormitanus, 125, 126, 234 -not dependent on state of grace, - human rights, I, 2, 20- 21 , 4J. 254,
Oakley, Francis, 83, 87, 211, 213, 2.14, 239, Pateman, C., 133 230. 238, 266- 267 268,273, 345
253 r dS<."tlt', L.B., 211, 225, 227 - n ri1o:in in human agreement, 132, - no prejudiet' lo third partit'!I, 21U ,
Oakley, John, 150 r•.1111. St., 24. 46, 67. M , 211 . 21s. rn, 292, 1.1'1. 14'>. It1'i l<>h, 2.lH, 264, JOll. 2R2-211..1
Oberman, H.A ., 226 2'n ll7 - n:onundation of right?', I 7t., IHI , I K2
<kkham, William of, :l, 4, 14, ''· 14, l.'i, II( I '1•l"K' "" ht•rt•'ly, 27h l''"l "'' 'V t IKhl- t11 rn1r·,. !"''"""· - -amt 1hlrct-p<lrly lw1wfki11rl1·"·
20. 2.'l, 27. :n. :14. ·"'· 11. '"· 411. 41 . l'1•1111l11Klnn, l\1•111ll'lh, 144. llfl. 1'111, 2Hll HI "I. "'' H'f K'I. Jr.K 4'1 "ill. 71
378 INDEX INDEX 379

Rights, passim (cant.) Rufinus, 54, 61, 63, 66, 137, 138, 139, 145, Spanish neo-scholastics, 8, 32, 41, 53, 68, -See also Divine Law; Divine
-and atheism, 214-215 167, 178, 265 75, 76, 108, 168, 253, 255, 258,286, Power; Voluntarism
-and common good, 189-191, 312, Ryan, A., 133 289, 316 Thomas Aquinas, 4, 9, 18, 21, 22, 23, 24,
334 -See also Las Casas, Bartol6meo de; 25, 26, 27, 28, 29, 31, 32, 37, 39, 40,
-and duties, 78-89, 193-194, 242, St. Germain, Christopher, 53 Suarez, Francisco de; Vitoria, 45, 69, 74, 75, 86,87, 88, 105, 108,
298-299 St. Leger, J., 320 Francisco de 130, 145, 146, 147, 178, 210,
-and restitution, 259, 260, 261, 281 SaJaJJ\anca, Schoolo~256.257, 290,301 Spiecs, K.E., 111 213- 214, 256- 265, 267, 268,269,
-and social contract, 334 -Set! also Spanish neo-scholastics State of nature, or innocence, 133- 134, 274, 275, 276, 277, 279, 280,20, 295,
-as faculties, 51, 53, 'Sl, 65-66, 67, Salmon, J.H.M., 302 145, 148-149, 150-151, 152, 153, 297, 300,301, 302, 303, 304,322,
69,210, 223, 227,228, 258,260, Samuel, Geoffrey, 118 159- 160, 161, 163, 238, 295,330, 332 323, 324,325
303-304 Saussure, Ferdinand de, 18 -See a lc;o Adam and Eve; Garden - Thomists and Thomism, 4, 5, 8, 32,
-as free choice or zone of individual Saxonhouse, A.W., 78 of Eden 42, 34, 87, 105, 108, 130, 210, 213.
autonomy, 44, 49, 51-52, 66-68, 79, Savigny, F.C. von, 49, 117 Stein, Peter, 303 216, 257, 261 , 262, 262, 265, 268,
189, 193, 298 Schmaus, J.J., 318 Stephanus, 61 269, 271, 274, 275, 276, 277, 278,
-as individual power, 23, 28, 48-49, Schwarz, Reinhold, 210, 219 Stickler, Alfons, 224 286, 291,302,308,325
51, 53, 57, 82, 85-86, 107, 228 Scott, James Brown, 318, 319 Stoicism, 45, 46, 62, 65, 66, 202, 273, 286, Thomas of York, 222
-as liberties, 57, 189, Xl2, 279, 286 Secular-mendicant controversy, 83, 320 Thompson, Augustine, 58
-as limitations on ruler's authority, 222- 223 Strauss, Leo, 4, 14, 33, 44, 52, 78, 208, 215 Thomson, Judith Jarvis, 133
182-193, 236, 279-280 Selden, John, 162, 167, 340 -Straussians, 133 Tocco, F., 95
-of association, 309 Self-preservation, right of. See Natural Sturmer, W., 171 Torah, 22, 25
-of the poor, 70-76, 218, 231, 239, rights Suarez, Francisco, 45, 51, 45, 76, 89, 100, Torello. Giovanni, 152
240, 301, 307, 332 Seneca, 137 103, 109, ll7, 124, 168, 233, 286, Tiibingen, University of, 236
-of use and ownership, 36-37, 96, Sepulveda, Juan de, 255, 272, 273, 277, 288,289, 301- 315, 316, 317, 318, Tuck, Richard, 4, 7, 18, 53, 56- 57, 64, 106,
104-105, 106, 107, 108, 114, 115, 278 319, 320, 322, 324,326,327, 329, 210, 216, 217- 220, 244,249, 257,
121-122, 124-125, 129-130, 131, Shapiro, Ian, 44, 47, 196 330,332,334, 337, 345 319, 320,321,322,324
153, l'Sl, 158, 161, 167,307,330,331 Sicardus, 63, 145 - definitions of ius, 303-304 Tully, James, 4, 233, 326
-See also ius; Natural Law; Natural Sigmund, Paul, 118 -juridic and philosophical sources, Turley, T., 95
Rights; Property, right of Simon of Bisignano, 63 302-303 Tyrolese marriage dispute of 1342, 196
Roensch, F.J., 105 Skinner, Quentin, 78, 210, 219, 237, 334 -on forms of government, 311-312
Roman emperors, source of authority Slavery, theory of natural, 254, 255, -on natural law, 304-305 Ullmann, Walter, 222
-translation theory, 183 265-266,270-271,X72-273,277 -on natural rights, 306-309 Ulpian, 16, 23, 28, 136,258, 303
-concession theory, 183 -See also Aristotle; Las Casas, -on the o rigin of the state, 309-311 UN Universal Declaration of Human
Roman emperors, and dominium, 183 Bartol6meo de; Grotius, Hugo; - rights within political community, Rights, 233, 274, 345
Rotnanlaw, l , 13, 24, 25,26, 28, 29,37,40, Vitoria, Francisco de 313-315 UNESC0, 2
46, 56, 74, 111, 118, 125, 135-137, Smalley, Beryl, 88 S11mm11 Bambergensis, 71 universals, 31, 216
142, 254, 258,276, 279,284,291, Socrates, 80, 82 Summa, lnperntorie m11ieslnle, 66 - See also Plato; Realism,
309, 320, 330, 337 Sommerville, J.P., 301 S11mmn, In nomine, 67 philosophica I
-Code ol Justinian, 26 Sophocles, 45 Summenhart, Conrad, 69, 89, 109, 236, Universitas fidefium, 207.
-Digest of Justinian, 40, 41, 111, 328 Soto, Domingo de, 109, 233, 241, 245, 252, 238, 242-252, 253, 256, 259, 260, -See also, Corporatism, med if'val
-Institutes of Justinian, 152 299,330 261,262, 262, 263, 264,265, 266, 267 University of Paris, 83, 213, 223, 236, 2.1H,
-glossators, of, 19, 29 Sovereignty, 288, 289 -analysis of Gerson's definition of 256, 294
-Ordinary Gloss to the Code, 279 -based on human will and consent, ills, 245- 248, 250-251 Urdonoz, Teofilo, 257, 290, 29:\, 2114
-Ordinary Gloss to the Digest, 41 301, 309-312, 334 -on ius and domini11m, 243- 245 Usus, 94
- rights in classical, 15-20 -defense of absolutist rule, - on objective and subjective right, - usus simplex fadi, 94
-seventeenth-century organization, 336-337 242-243 - See also, Ockham, William of;
15 -divine right of kings, 289, 290- 291, Sumner, L.W., 193 Rights
Romantic movement, 208 293- 295, 301, 302, 311,329 synderrsis, 53, 63, 64, 76, 228 ususfructus, 29, 30,94, ~26
Rommen, Heinrich, 14, 301, 323 - relatioMhip with natural rights, Utilitaria nism, IJ8, 190
Rorty, Richard, 5 2R9, 290, 313- 3 15, 317- 3 1R Taba rroni, A., 93
Roshwald, Mordecai, 52 and ~K"lnl nmtrnc·t, .1.13 );\ii Ten Commandments, 1, 23, 50, 71, 174, Vallad olid. 272
Rousseau, J.J., 274 Sc:-c• nl'"1 Jur-li.cl ktlon 292, 324 Vanlanthrn, A., 4'>
380 INDEX

Vatican Council Il, 274 -and right reason, 174-175, 286, 327
Vb.quez de Menchaca, Fernando, 330, -See also Divine law; Divine Power;
335 Nominalism; Ockham, Witliam of;
Venice, City of, 312 Ten Commandments
ViHey, Michel, 3, 4, 6, 7, 8, 13-42, 52-53, Vyver, Johan van der, 249
68, 79, 80, 97, 105, 108, 196, 199,
202, 208, 210, 215,216,220, 257, Waldron, Jeremy, 133
260, 273, 286, 302,318, 326 Wars of Religion, 253
Villoslada, R , 256 Weigand, Rudolf, 33, 60, 63, 137, 144
V-mcentius Hispanus, 73 WeiJ, Simone, 157
virtus, 41 Wieacker, F., 318
vis, 41, 46, 62- 64 Wilenius, R, 301, 302
Vitoria, Francisco de, 41, 68-69, 89, 233, Wilks, Michael. 83
245, 249, 255, 256, 256-265, Wohlmuth, Joseph, 209, 233
266- 272, 278, 288, 289, 290-301, Wolf, Erik, 48
302, 308, 310,311,319, 321, 323, Wolff, Christian, 51, 68, 77, 117, 228,
327, 329, 333, 334 340
-definition of subjective rights, Woolf, C.N.S., 339
259- 262 World War II, 345
-development of thought on Wyclif, John, 32, 196, 221 , 229, 230, 232,
sovereignty, 295-296 238, 266
-dominion among the Indians, -on sinfulness and rights, 229-230,
263- 265, 266- 268, 269-272 238, 266
-origins of the commonwealth. -Wyclifites, 233
290- 295 \oVulf, l\1. de, 31,213
-refutation of natural slavery,
267- 268, 270-271 Yolton, J .S., 78
-rights in the commonwealth, Yolton, J.W., 78
296-301
- and his Thomistic sources, 256-259 ZabareUa, Franciscus, 125, 126, 209, 212,
Vives, Juan Luis, 239, 242 216, 234
Voltaire, 274 Zenzellinus de Cassanis, 102, 125
Voluntarism,8,35, 53,97, 98-99, 100, 117, Zuckerman, Charles, 31, 196
118, 196, 197, 198,327 Zulueta, F. de, 17
"Brian Tierney has pioneered the discovery of the origins of rights language. He
combines mastery of a wide ran~e of sources with novelty ~ interpl'f!tation."
Antony Black, University of Dwukt:

"This is a historical work of extraordinary depth and breadth, which will interest
- and surprise - not only historians but also political theorists, legal scholars,
and others who wish to understand the origin and early developme.n t of contem-
porary theories of rights. Tierney's book shows that Western Christi.an rights the-
ories wett first elaborated within the communiwian values of traditional socie-
ties and thus have a universal validity that tran5«nds Enlightenment postulates."
Harold]. Boman. Emory Univtrsity

"A superb scholarly synthesis of medieval into early modem legal, philosophical.
and theological sources for an idea widely and not always favorably regarded as a
product of the European EnlightenmenL Tierney's extra.o rdinary gift of lucid and
engaging presentation of past subtleties not only takes us into the medieval mind
in its subtlest (and liveliest) phase, but, more important, brings medieval
thought into the center of our own world, and much to our good. This is a schol-
arly gem with cutting-edge relevance to our present global condition."
A. S. McGrtlk, Univtrsity of Connteticut

"A masterpiece showing that the canonists formulated a new language of rights
which has been foundational to the development of Western thought in the fol-
lowing centuri.es."
Giwstppt Albaigo, Univusity of Bologna

"Brian Tierney, one of the worlds leading scholars in the field of medieval canon
law, has produced a volume that is absolutdy essential reading for anyone inter-
ested in human rights issues."
James Muldoon, Rutgers University

Brian Tierney is the Bowmar Professor in Humanistic Studies, Emeritus, at Cor-


nell University. A world authority on Western history and canon law, he has pub-
lished a dozen books, including Foundations of the Conciliar Thtory; Rdlgion,
~ and the Growtlt of CoflStitutional Thought; Origins of Papal Infallibility; and
Mtdinral Poor Law

ISBN 0-6026-4554-0

_111imu 1in11

You might also like