Lost Worlds: Environmental Disaster, "Culture Loss," and The Law by Stuart Kirsch

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 32

C u r r e n t A n t h r o p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

䉷 2001 by The Wenner-Gren Foundation for Anthropological Research. All rights reserved 0011-3204/2001/4202-0001$3.00

Before the river was not like this;


Lost Worlds it makes me feel like crying.
These days, this place is ruined,
so I feel like crying.

Environmental Disaster, Where I used to make gardens,


the mud banks have built up.
“Culture Loss,” and the Law1 Where I used to catch prawns and fish,
there is an empty pool. . .
So I feel like crying.
by Stuart Kirsch
Before it wasn’t like this.
We had no difficulty finding food in our garden or
wild game.
We had everything that we needed.
Indigenous claims about “culture loss” pose a problem for con- Now we are suffering and I wonder why.
temporary definitions of culture as a process that continually un-
dergoes change rather than something which can be damaged or
lost. This issue is examined in the context of hearings at the Nu- d u r i k e m y a t , 1996
clear Claims Tribunal in the Marshall Islands, which was estab-
lished to adjudicate claims regarding damage and loss to persons
and property resulting from United States nuclear weapons test- A significant counterpoint to the exuberant claims made
ing during the 1940s and ’50s. The concept of cultural property
rights is used to identify the referents of discourse about culture for the benefits of globalization are native people’s ex-
loss, including local knowledge, subsistence production, and con- pressions of loss associated with the transformation of
nections to place. The problems caused by the taking of inaliena- their societies, including relocation from traditional
ble possessions are also considered. At issue is whether indige- lands, threats to the continuity of their languages (Hill
nous relationships to land are of ownership, belonging, or both.
The definition and significance of culture and loss are increas-
and Hill 1986, Kulick 1992, Nettle and Romaine 2000,
ingly debated in legal contexts ranging from tribunals and truth although see Warren 1998) and the reduction of political
commissions to land rights hearings and heritage legislation autonomy (Cultural Survival 1993, Dean and Levi n.d.,
around the world. Gray 1997, Maybury-Lewis 1997, Ramos 1998). The
sense of loss is especially pronounced in the wake of
s t u a r t k i r s c h is Visiting Assistant Professor in the Depart- environmental disasters that damage local land and re-
ment of Anthropology of the University of Michigan (Ann Arbor,
Mich. 48109-1382, U.S.A. [skirsch@umich.edu]) and Visiting Sen- sources, including oil spills, exposure to nuclear radia-
ior Research Associate in the Department of Social Anthropology tion, deforestation, and the toxic impacts of mining.
at the University of Cambridge. Born in 1960, he was educated In ethnographic research with people living down-
at George Washington University (B.A., 1982) and the University stream from the Ok Tedi copper and gold mine in Papua
of Pennsylvania (Ph.D., 1991). He has consulted on a number of
environmental law cases in the Pacific, including the lawsuit
New Guinea, I have described how pollution has affected
against the Ok Tedi mine. His primary research is with the local relationships to the landscape (Kirsch 1997a, n.d.).
Yonggom of Papua New Guinea, who have been greatly affected Tailings and other mine wastes have poisoned local riv-
by that project. His publications include “Lost Tribes: Indigenous ers, destroyed several hundred kilometers of rain forest,
People and the Social Imaginary” (Anthropological Quarterly
ruined rich garden land, and precipitated the decline of
70[2]:58–67) and “Changing Views of Place and Time among the
Ok Tedi,” in Mining and Indigenous Life Worlds in Australia local fauna. These problems have forced many of the
and Papua New Guinea, edited by Alan Rumsey and James Wei- communities living downstream from the mine to de-
ner (Adelaide: Crawford House Press, in press). The present paper pend on compensation provided by the US$500 million
was submitted 27 iv 00 and accepted 26 ix 00. settlement of their lawsuit against the Australian cor-
poration BHP, the majority shareholder and operating
partner of the mine (Kirsch 1997a). Whereas local his-
1. This paper was written while I was in residence at the University tories were once intimately associated with the land-
of Cambridge, with funding provided by the United Kingdom Ec- scape, the destruction of the places where these events
onomic and Social Research Council in conjunction with the Prop-
erty, Transactions and Creativity project organized by Marilyn occurred has prompted these communities to reformu-
Strathern and Eric Hirsch. I thank the other members of that pro- late their narratives of the past in chronological terms.
ject, the four anonymous referees from current anthropology, Their magic, which addresses the animals and the other
and the participants in the seminars at the University of Cambridge, beings with whom they share the rain forest, is now
the University of Kent at Canterbury, and the University of Mich-
igan for their responses to this paper. Michael Brown, Gillian Fee- questioned given the disappearance of its audience. Local
ley-Harnik, James Leach, Andrea McDowell, and Michael Wood accounts of these changes convey a profound sense of
also provided particularly helpful comments. The Public Advocate’s loss, as is illustrated by Duri Kemyat’s lament above
office, Davor Pevec, and Laurence Carucci generously shared key (Kirsch n.d.).
research materials. I am especially grateful to Bill Graham and the
Public Advocate’s Office in Majuro, the advisory committee, and
The theme of loss has echoes throughout the indige-
the people from Rongelap who contributed to this research. Any nous world, often in association with damages to and/
errors of fact or interpretation are solely my responsibility. or displacement from their land. Deborah Rose (1996:
167
168 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

20–21), for example, describes the Aboriginal novation and creation. Balanced against Brown’s objec-
characterization of land that is no longer being managed tions to cultural property rights, however, are the polit-
by its caretakers as “a loss of life, a loss of life support ical resources that they might provide for indigenous
systems, and a loss of relationships among living things communities, including enhanced control over what cir-
and their country. For many Aboriginal people, this ‘wild’ culates, for property rights can restrict as well as facil-
[i.e., land that is no longer maintained through fire] has itate distribution.
a quality of deep loneliness.” Richard Baker (1999:179), The examples of indigenous discourse considered here
also writing about Aboriginal Australia, quotes an in- suggest that loss has recently become a critical site for
formant as saying, “We have lost all our everything.” the objectification of culture, raising questions that are
Looking out across a changing landscape, the Fuyuge of distinct from the dilemmas of cultural appropriation.
Papua New Guinea anticipate the growing impacts of While there is a long anthropological history of discus-
mining, including new social boundaries and the poten- sion about culture loss, including the allegory of Ishi,
tial “loss of [their] way of life or culture” (Hirsch 2000). the last of the Yahi Indians (Kroeber 1976), and Ruth
Verena Keck (1998) has considered the various threats Benedict’s (1960:34) metaphor of a broken cup signifying
posed to traditional knowledge in the Pacific, particu- “the loss of something that had value equal to that of
larly knowledge directly related to the material world. life itself, the whole fabric of . . . [a] people’s standards
A distinctive feature of indigenous responses to dis- and beliefs,” my argument is about the disappearance
possession and environmental degradation is the claim not of entire societies or ways of life but of particular
of “culture loss.” The concept of culture loss poses a things—knowledge, ideas, and practices of local value.
problem of analysis for anthropologists given contem- The concept of cultural property rights can provide the
porary definitions of culture as a process that continually means to identify these losses, which might otherwise
undergoes change rather than something which can be be obscured or ignored. While the problems raised by
damaged or lost. Marshall Sahlins (1993:4) points out questions about culture loss are particularly salient with
that defining culture in this way “has the effect of erasing respect to indigenous communities because of shared co-
the logical and ontological continuities involved in the lonial and postcolonial experiences, they are by no
different ways that societies interpret and respond to the means limited to them.
imperialist conjuncture. If culture must be conceived as I develop my argument through the examination of
always and only changing, lest one commit the mortal recent court proceedings held in response to nuclear
sin of essentialism, there can be no such thing as identity weapons testing by the U.S. government in the Marshall
. . . let alone continuity.” To completely naturalize Islands during the 1940s and ’50s.2 In particular, I focus
change also obscures what is lost or forgotten. on the testimony of anthropologists, lawyers, and judges
In this essay I argue that the notion of cultural property in the Nuclear Claims Tribunal in the Republic of the
rights can be used to address this critical blind spot of Marshall Islands, which was established to adjudicate
the culture concept, in which loss is unseen or under- claims regarding damage and loss to persons and property
valued. In particular, I will show how the concept of resulting from exposure to radiation and other destruc-
cultural property rights can help to identify the referents tive impacts of nuclear testing.3 I also make reference to
of indigenous discourse about culture loss. Cultural related courtroom debates about cultural property in
property rights, as Marilyn Strathern (1999b:177) ob- Australia and environmental disasters in Alaska and
serves, imply new forms of integration and new ways of Papua New Guinea. Central to all of these cases is the
organizing persons and collectivities. These rights are intersection of property, culture, and loss.4
intended to prevent loss of property, knowledge, bodily
integrity, or creation itself and of the value of the things
that they may beget. Cultural property rights offer po-
The Nature of Loss
tential resources as ideas and things move into new con-
texts, orders of signification, and economic regimes of
commodification. They can also make visible the losses If property is a manifestation of social relations (Hann
experienced by indigenous communities. 1998; C. Rose 1994:227), then so is loss. What are the
Simon Harrison (1999:11) has suggested that concerns kinds of things or relations that can be lost, and what
about cultural appropriation—the desire to protect “cul- are the contexts in which loss is implicated? The notion
tural practices and symbols against unauthorised use or of loss appears to have two primary registers. It may refer
reproduction by outsiders”—are a form of boundary
maintenance parallel to defensive efforts that seek to 2. The documentary film Half life, produced by Dennis O’Rourke
(1986), provides an excellent overview of the Bravo test and the role
minimize the intrusion of foreign ideas or practices. Mi-
of the U.S. government in nuclear testing in the Marshall Islands.
chael Brown (1998) has raised concerns about the use of 3. I do not claim ethnographic authority for the Marshall Islands;
legal regimes to limit acts of cultural appropriation, most this argument is analytic rather than descriptive or interpretive.
notably their implications for the unrestricted flow of My intention is to explain how claims about culture loss might be
information that is central to (certain domains of) liberal understood rather than to promote a particular compensatory
regime.
democratic society. Brown also wonders whether the ex- 4. See Kirsch (1997b) for a discussion of indigenous efforts to locate
tension of legal restrictions to cultural property might the problems of environmental degradation in social and moral
in fact facilitate its commodification and/or limit in- domains and Strathern’s (1999c:229–33) comments on this process.
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 169

to possession—to the objects or property for which one pensation. When an exact equivalent is unavailable, the
might claim rights or ownership. Loss in this guise im- substitute is always inferior to the original, perpetuating
plies value and property relations; it may therefore be the sense of loss (see Schieffelin 1976:109–12). The issue
possible to gain new understandings of property by ex- arises both in the payment of monetary compensation
amining responses to loss. In other contexts, however, and in attempts to imagine the possibilities of compen-
such as the intimate losses associated with grief, loss sation in kind.
may be improperly referenced to property relations, as Finally, it is necessary to consider the responses that
one does not necessarily hold comparable rights to per- narratives of loss can evoke in an audience given the
sons as to things. Here it is possible to speak of loss in proliferation of environmental and other disasters in the
relation to the notion of kinship and belonging rather past century and our increased exposure to these events
than possession. I suggest that the relationship implied through the media. Bikini, Bhopal, Chernobyl, the Exxon
by cultural property rights may be a form of belonging Valdez, and Ok Tedi are iconic of the destructive capac-
as well as a kind of possession. The case before us re- ity of 20th-century industry and military power, but sit-
quires that we take as an empirical question the kinds uating these events too abstractly in time and space
of relationships that the Marshallese have toward their makes them perhaps too easily interchangeable, too easy
land: are they modeled after relations of kin, of property, to let go (see Strathern 1999a:54–63). By focusing on the
or both? I will consider this issue with respect to local problem of loss, however, and reembedding these events
knowledge, subsistence production, and attachments to in social relations, it may be possible to slow the move-
place. These examples raise questions about the alien- ment of images long enough and to reduce their scale
ation of property that is ordinarily regarded as sufficiently to carry out the necessary work of analysis.
inalienable.
Any discussion of loss must also take its productive
possibilities into account. In order to form relationships, Nuclear Wasteland
people must separate themselves from one another (see
Strathern 1988), although differentiation in the social From 1946 until 1958, the United States tested 67 nu-
realm is not ordinarily conceived of in terms of loss. Yet clear weapons in the Marshall Islands. The most pow-
in marriage, for example, people move into other cate- erful of these tests was the Bravo shot, a 15-megaton
gories of kin, other lineages. This is simultaneously a device (1,000 times the power of the bomb exploded over
loss to their natal clan and the precondition for new Hiroshima) detonated on March 1, 1954, at Bikini Atoll
kinds of social relations, for productive as well as repro- (Barker 1997:291). Bravo was engineered to maximize ra-
ductive relations of exchange. Similarly, the dynamics dioactive fallout, which was carried by the wind to the
of memory and forgetting, the entropic tendencies of rit- east, reaching the inhabited atoll of Rongelap (Alcalay
ual knowledge, and the incompleteness of the intergen- 1992:48). A second sun rose in the western sky that
erational transmission of knowledge all pose questions morning, followed by the roar of thunder, winds at tor-
about the possibility of loss. Yet loss may be integral to nado strength, and earthquakes (Toyosaki 1986:49). Sev-
these systems in that it permits innovation and eral hours later, radioactive fallout rained down on the
improvisation. island. People brushed the powder from their food and
In the case before us, however, of nuclear testing in ate; they cleared it from their water cisterns and drank;
the Pacific and its consequences, it is difficult to con- children swimming in the lagoon put it in their hair and
ceptualize the losses experienced by the people affected pretended that it was soap. Shortly thereafter, the 64
by nuclear testing as productive. Their land was not people on Rongelap that day began to suffer the ill-effects
transformed into something of value; rather, it was de- of acute radiation exposure: their hair fell out, their skin
stroyed because it was only of value to the U.S. govern- was burned, they began to vomit, and they suffered from
ment in its potential loss.5 This is negative reciprocity a thirst that water could not quench (interview with Li-
writ large across the landscape: the wholesale destruc- jon Eknilang, 1999).6
tion of things (property, land, memory) and social rela- Two days later, the U.S. Navy evacuated the people of
tions organized through land, as well as the capacity for Rongelap; they were later resettled on Ejit Island in Ma-
reproducing these relationships in place. juro Atoll, at the center of the Marshall Islands (Weisgall
It might be argued that in compensation claims, people 1994:303). In 1957, three years after Bravo, the people of
seek to establish relationships with the parties respon- Rongelap returned home (Kiste 1974:194). They were as-
sible for the loss or damage and to acquire a replacement sured that the background levels of radiation were within
for what has been lost. Yet in the Marshall Islands there the limits of safety. A medical team from the Brookhaven
is a fundamental incommensurability between what was National Laboratory visited the island annually to mon-
taken and what might be given back in the form of com- itor the long-term consequences of their exposure to ra-

5. Commenting on the naming of women’s two-piece bathing suits 6. In addition to the 64 persons on Rongelap at the time of the
after Bikini Atoll, Teresia Teaiwa (1994:87) argues: “The sexist dy- Bravo test, another 18 were on the nearby atoll of Alinginae, in-
namic that the bikini performs—the objectification through exces- cluding 4 pregnant women who gave birth during the period of
sive visibility—inverts the colonial dynamics that have occurred relocation. Thus the total number of exposed persons, according to
during nuclear testing in the Pacific, objectification by rendering the U.S. government, including the 4 in utero, is 86 (Bill Graham,
invisible.” personal communication, 2000).
170 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

diation. Yet the people of Rongelap were never fully in- ing on behalf of the Defender of the Fund for the Nuclear
formed about their increased exposure to risk from the Claims Tribunal and the people of Enewetak respec-
contaminated food and water that they consumed (Bar- tively.9 I focus on courtroom debate about the definition
ker 1997:295). Today the Marshallese have the highest and significance of property, culture, and loss.
rates of certain types of cancer in the Pacific and unusual
numbers of miscarriages and birth defects.
The incidences of cancer and childhood deaths from The Context of Claims for Loss
leukemia, combined with the release of additional in-
formation about their exposure to radiation, prompted
the community to leave its atoll again in 1985, 31 years Indigenous claims about culture loss are increasingly as-
after its initial exposure. The Rongelap people currently sociated with political and legal contexts in which com-
reside in Ebeye, adjacent to the proving grounds for U.S. munities seek reparations for past injustices.10 The so-
“Star Wars” technology in Kwajalein Lagoon, in Mejatto, ciologist John Torpey (2001) has described the recent
and in the capital of Majuro. Funds have been set aside florescence of forums that address such claims, distin-
by the United States government to rehabilitate their guishing between acts of violence and injustice com-
home atoll, although there is dispute over the appropriate mitted during World War II, the transition to democracy
level of risk: the 100-millirem radiation standard used in countries that have suffered from state terrorism and
by the U.S. Department of Energy and the Nuclear Reg- other authoritarian practices, and claims made by indig-
ulatory Commission, which may be achievable, or the enous communities against states dominated by the de-
more cautious Environmental Protection Agency stan- scendants of European settlers.11 Restitution is sought in
dard of 15 millirems, which might delay resettlement for terms of monetary compensation and the return of prop-
many years. erty, policies of rehabilitation, and/or the negotiation of
A formal agreement between the Marshall Islands and novel accommodations between local autonomy and
the U.S. government was reached in 1983 in which the state sovereignty. The institutionalization of these fo-
United States formally accepted responsibility for loss rums and the legal statutes through which they are or-
and damage to property and persons resulting from its ganized—tribunals, truth commissions, land rights hear-
nuclear testing program.7 As part of the negotiated com- ings, and heritage legislation—influence the form and
pact between the United States and the Republic of the content of the claims that are advanced.
Marshall Islands, a claims tribunal with the jurisdication James Weiner (1999) addresses this issue in his analysis
to “render determination upon all claims, past and fu- of the Hindmarsh Island controversy in southern Aus-
ture,” was established in 1987. The tribunal has begun tralia. He describes the legislative processes governing
to pay compensation for the health effects of radiation Aboriginal heritage claims as a form of elicitation that
and is currently hearing class action claims for property shapes the practices they seek to protect. The dispute in
damage, loss, and suffering on Enewetak and Bikini, the question concerned a claim regarding Aboriginal
two sites for weapons testing. women’s rituals (or “business”) associated with a pro-
In 1999, I was briefly engaged as an adviser to the posed site for commercial development. The courts did
Public Advocate’s office in the Marshall Islands to assist not recognize culture as a contemporary process of val-
in the preparation of a report to the Nuclear Claims Tri- uation, relying on the more restricted criteria of histor-
bunal regarding land values for Rongelap.8 I draw on this
9. Pollock (1992:20) is the author of These Roots Remain, a com-
research and on the comparable but more advanced parative study of food habits in the central and eastern Pacific,
claims presented to the tribunal by the people of Ene- which draws on 15 months of fieldwork on Namu Atoll in the
wetak, who lived in exile for 33 years as a result of nu- Marshall Islands from 1967 to 1969. Laurence Carucci (1997:xi) is
clear testing. Central to the hearings on Enewetak were the author of Nuclear Nativity, an ethnography of ritual and
exchange on Enewetak, which draws on more than three years of
written reports and oral testimony provided by the an-
ethnographic research between 1976 and 1996.
thropologists Nancy Pollock and Laurence Carucci, act- 10. In her written submission to the Nuclear Claims Tribunal, Pol-
lock (1999:1) described the historical and institutional dimensions
7. The agreement came into effect in 1986 (Bill Graham, personal of claims about culture loss in the following terms: “The issue of
communication, 2000). ‘cultural loss’ is currently a subject of much debate in international
8. The motivation for the project was given as follows: “In this fields as indigenous people assert their claims against uninvited
unique and unusual quest for assessing the value of land in a non- disruptions to their lives. Reparations sought include claims for
market environment, for the purposes of awarding just compen- loss of land and all its cultural meanings, loss of a way of life that
sation, claimants are not suggesting that the Tribunal ignore the had been passed down from ancestors, loss of social interactions
transactional indicators that do exist. They are suggesting, however, leading to the ongoing viability of society, loss of the basis of in-
that other factors such as tradition and custom must also be given digenous belief systems and loss of the right to self-determination.
due consideration to ensure that justice is done. It is therefore the The assumption [of the anthropologist] is that these elements of
intent of the claimants to involve knowledgeable anthropologists, culture are not static but continually readjust to current and past
sociologists, and others with experience and understanding of the contexts. But the contexts being highlighted in this debate are all
importance of land in the Marshalls throughout the appraisal pro- ones where the loss was derived from impositions by major powers,
cess to ensure that the valuations ultimately reached are truly rel- colonial powers, that exerted their power over minority states to
evant” (Graham and Lowe 1998). The other anthropologists in- achieve . . . [their] goals, both economic and strategic.”
volved in this project were Holly Barker and Barbara Rose Johnston, 11. Torpey (2001) has also suggested that contemporary claims for
who have written separately on these issues (Barker and Johnston reparations made against states by historically victimized groups
2000). are an outgrowth of political responses to the Holocaust.
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 171

ical significance and continuity. When the Aboriginal Judge Holland refused to recognize cultural differences
women elected to protect their claims to secret ritual between native and nonnative fishermen with respect to
knowledge by refusing to testify in court, the developers the impact of the oil spill. His position was supported
were granted permission to construct a bridge on the by the testimony of the distinguished American cultural
disputed site.12 The participants in the debate failed to anthropologist Paul Bohannan, who had been engaged by
recognize how heritage legislation evoked a response Exxon. In his deposition to the courts, Bohannan defined
that was focused on political rights and interests. culture as a strategy for adaptation, “[a] basic device for
Whereas Australian heritage protection requires Ab- surviving and prospering—a set of ideas and artifacts by
original communities to demonstrate the continuity of means of which human beings adapt to the environment,
local traditions, the process is reversed in the Marshall including the social environment” (p. 9). He argued that
Islands: the Nuclear Claims Tribunal, which provides Alutiiq culture and its core meanings were not substan-
compensation for damage and loss, obligates commu- tially affected by the oil spill. Finally, he concluded that
nities to demonstrate a break with the past. Much as the impact of the natural disaster was equivalent for all
Aboriginal culture is elicited in part through political of those persons affected, regardless of ethnic or cultural
processes in Australia, Marshallese claims about culture identity, declaring, “I believe the Alaska natives are no
loss are influenced by the legal processes through which different from anybody else in the matter” (p. 11).13 The
they are adjudicated. judge agreed that there was no basis for distinguishing
While the protection of cultural heritage has assumed between the claims for loss of the two communities;
the guise of a universal imperative, culturally specific cultural difference was irrelevant to his findings. “All
claims of loss are not necessarily as well received. The Alaskans have the right to lead subsistence lifestyles,
issue of culture loss, for example, figured significantly not just Alaska natives,” Holland (1996:167) later
in courtroom debates about the impact of the 1989 Exxon explained.14
Valdez oil spill in Alaska, which released over 11 million
gallons of crude oil into Prince William Sound. Accord-
ing to the anthropologist Joseph Jorgensen’s (1995) anal- Legal Determination of Loss
ysis of that case, social scientists testifying on behalf of
the indigenous plaintiffs used a definition of culture that The analytic challenge in the Marshall Islands case is to
was later discredited by both the opposing anthropologist make visible the referents of claims about culture loss,
and the court. They argued (in Jorgensen 1995:2) that while the political challenge is to do this with reference
damage to any core element [of a society] (e.g., natu- to existing legal categories. The latter task is framed by
ral resource base or kinship system) damages the two opposing opinions. On one side is the view expressed
culture and the people. . . . Because subsistence is by Phillip Okney (1999:17), the Defender of the Fund,
the basis of modern Alutiiq culture, the oil spill . . . who argued against the Enewetak claim for consequen-
damaged that culture in a multitude of ways . . . tial damages, including hunger, deprivation, isolation,
and physical distress, resulting from their relocation. He
[and] to the extent that Alutiiq people’s subsistence,
was equally dismissive of claims for what he character-
the most fundamental basis of their culture and life,
remains disrupted, they and their culture have been
13. In contrast, Jorgensen (1995) argues that there are substantive
damaged. differences between the two communities, native and nonnative.
He makes the following observation about native choices
post–Exxon Valdez: “Packing up and leaving . . . is not the native
Judge Holland rejected the reification of culture implied solution to adversity. . . . Native cultural traditions, as instanced
by this argument, determining instead that “villagers by the nexus of kinship and friendship obligations, facilitate re-
cannot collect damages for harm that was alleged to have maining in place, while sentiments and ideas about place and space
influence a person’s resolve to stay” (p. 20). Jorgensen (p. 4) also
been suffered by native culture” (p. 2). While acknowl-
argues that natives are “very different from nonnatives” in terms
edging that “the Exxon Valdez was a disaster of major of the “ethics that they express and practice, . . . in the ways and
proportions,” he concluded that “it did not deprive extent to which they participate in their communities, in the net-
Alaska natives of their culture” (p. 5). He based his opin- works and activities in which they engage, . . . in their family-
ion on the view that culture is “deeply embedded in the household organizations, and, if class is an issue, in their education,
occupations, incomes, political knowledge and participation in po-
mind and the heart” and is therefore undiminished by litical affairs.” He also demonstrates that there are substantial dif-
external events such as environmental disaster (p. 5). ferences between the two communities in terms of “subsistence
The courts also ruled that the Alutiiq people had been activities, knowledge of the environment, ideas about the environ-
deprived of access to resources, prompting a negotiated ment, sentiment about the environment, and sharing activities,”
all of which are relevant with respect to the consequences of the
settlement with Exxon for US$20 million. However, oil spill (p. 56).
14. Berger (1985:64) argues that there is support for both positions
12. Consider Deborah Rose’s (1996:2) comments on this subject: on indigenous difference in Alaska: while the 1971 Alaska Native
“During the course of my work in New South Wales, Aboriginal Claims Settlement Act extinguished “aboriginal rights of hunting
people have told me time and again that because they have lost so and fishing,” the Alaska National Interest Lands Conservation Act
much, they are not prepared to speak publicly about their knowl- of 1980 “found it necessary to protect subsistence for Native people
edge in any detail. They fear that they will lose control of that on a different basis than for non-Native people,” citing a special
which remains.” relationship between subsistence and native “cultural existence.”
172 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

ized as the “rather attenuated and ethereal injuries of Bikini Atoll (KANSAS-Eisenring v. Kansas Turnpike Au-
‘mental suffering,’ ‘loss of cultural heritage and a cus- thority, 183 Kan 774, 332 P [2nd] 539 [1958], citing Trea-
tomary and traditional way of life’ and the ‘loss of home- tise; emphasis added):
land.’” Okney asserted that these claims are “uncertain,
speculative and disallowed” by the tribunal, given that The absence of market value, in the sense that there
they are not sufficiently associated with property. is a lack of evidence of comparable sales, does not
Rather, the claims “affix to the individual who makes prevent recovery by the owner in the event of con-
up part of the whole which is claimed to have suffered demnation. It occasionally happens that a parcel of
the injury.” He concluded that “the human being is not real estate or a leasehold interest taken by eminent
property such as one makes claim for in eminent domain domain is of such a nature, or is held or has been
or in the case of inverse condemnation.”15 improved in such a manner, that, while it serves a
Okney’s position on appropriate recompense for the useful purpose to its owner, he would be unable to
people of Enewetak was governed by the application of sell it at anything like its real value. Where the
the strictest possible test for determining the market usual means of ascertaining market value are lack-
value of property: “Only that which is capable of sale to ing, or other means must from necessity of the case
a willing buyer can be properly considered for an award be resorted to, it is proper to determine the market
of damage.” He presented the following fictional model value by considering the intrinsic value of the prop-
of the “willing seller” and the “willing buyer” (p. 21): erty, and its value to the owners for their special
The willing seller is found, as held in J. O. Powel et purposes. The owner of the property taken is not re-
al. v. Shelby County, 130 So 2d 170 (1961) to be a quired under such circumstances to make any pecu-
seller not forced to sell (to disallow reduced values) niary sacrifices. He is entitled to whatever the prop-
and the willing buyer is a buyer not required to buy erty is worth to him, or anyone else, for any purpose
(to disallow inflated values). Under the reasoning in to which it is adapted. These special uses, or pur-
Powel the willing seller is conceived to be a seller poses to which the property is adapted must be
who would not be influenced by sentimental attach- real—founded upon facts capable of proof—and not
ments to property and the willing buyer is also con- merely speculative or imaginary. If the owner has
sidered to be immune to the sentimental attributes adopted a peculiar mode of using the land by which
of property. It is the fiction of the prudent buyer and he derives profit, and he is to be deprived of that
the prudent seller that the courts employ and not use, justice requires that he be compensated for the
the sentimental seller and the sentimental buyer. loss to himself. It is the value which he has, and of
This rationale, as applied in Powel, dictate[s] that which he is deprived, which must be made good by
the sentimental value of the homestead [is] not al- compensation.
lowed as an element of damage.

The ruling creates an opening for determinations of value


Okney acknowledged “that ethics demand that within
that exist beyond the scope of the market, including cul-
the confines of negotiations for leaseholds that the gov-
tural property rights.
ernment recognize the unique place of land rights in the
life and law of the Marshall Islands. . . . The attendant In his testimony before the Nuclear Claims Tribunal,
changes in the lives of the lessors are obviously consid- the anthropologist and Enewetak ethnographer Carucci
ered and taken into consideration when fixing the contrasted the values that Americans and Europeans
amount of compensation to be received by the lessors” “hold for their land” with the values of the Marshallese
(p. 2). While willing to consider the positive cultural val- “about, with and for their land” (Nuclear Claims Tri-
ues of land associated with its use, Okney rejected the bunal 1999a).16 He noted that Americans move on av-
possible (negative) values associated with its loss. erage six times during their lifetimes and treat land as a
Okney’s position must be taken seriously, because as commodity, “something that is used, purchased and
Defender of the Fund he attempts to set limits on the sold.” Relationships to place are temporary, and land is
compensation paid by the Nuclear Claims Tribunal. Yet “something that one can buy, utilize for a short period
it is not clear that the market provides an adequate mea- of time, and pass on.” Our attachment to place, in Car-
sure of the value of land in the Marshall Islands. An ucci’s estimation, is “quite modest.” In contrast, the
alternative perspective on the potential scope of property Marshallese regard land as a “different kind of entity,”
claims was articulated in the case of Eisenring v. Kansas an element “of one’s very person” and an “integral part
Turnpike Authority, cited in a property assessment for of who people are and how they situate themselves in
the world.” Their “sense of self, both personal and cul-
15. Eminent domain refers to “the inherent power of a govern-
mental entity to take privately owned property, esp. land, and con-
vert it to public use, subject to reasonable compensation for the
taking,” whereas inverse condemnation refers to “an action brought
by a property owner for compensation from a governmental entity 16. Unless otherwise indicated, all quotations from Carucci are
that has taken the owner’s property without bringing formal con- taken from his oral testimony (Nuclear Claims Tribunal 1999a).
demnation proceedings” (Garner 1999:287, 541). See also Carucci and Maifeld (1999).
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 173

tural, is deeply embedded in a piece of land,” their weto learning about the natural world and applying the re-
or land parcel.17 sulting insights—practices which may themselves dif-
Carucci explained that land in the Marshall Islands is ferentiate indigenous from scientific knowledge (Ellen
highly valued both because it is so limited in quantity18 1998). Different ways of knowing may be not necessarily
and because it “represents the collective labor of gen- more or less accurate but more or less appropriate ac-
eration[s] . . . of human activity”: cording to the context and the audience (Forsyth 1998).
In other words, indigenous knowledge is very much
Living persons are but a minor piece of those genera-
local knowledge in the sense that it is closely linked to
tions of time that link people through their land and
specific environments. The people of Enewetak suffered
through that land to an extended history. . . . Living
greatly on Ujelang, a remote, uninhabited, and largely
in a place, working in a place, changing that land
desolate atoll. In his testimony before the tribunal, Car-
into a piece of one’s own being makes [a person] one
ucci referred to the absence of the species of pandanus
with that land. Equally, consuming the products of
used by women to weave mats and the lack of the mature
that land continues and completes the cycle through
breadfruit trees needed to build canoes: “Group organ-
which one comes to take on a total identity as per-
ized tasks like building canoes fell apart. . . . This was
son and place that will exist not only momentarily
an atoll that [lacked] the products that it was supposed
. . . but in perpetuity. . . .
to have.” Absence from their home atolls and the en-
vironments in which their knowledge was applicable
Carucci’s testimony suggests that the people of Ene- posed a challenge to its continuity. Judge James Plasman
wetak use the idiom of kinship and belonging to con- asked Carucci for clarification: “The question of sailing
ceptualize their relations to their land. canoes and the loss of the means to traditionally main-
In the following sections I consider several examples tain and operate and build these canoes . . . was [that] a
of loss experienced by the Marshallese as a result of dam- loss of culture that people have suffered?” Carucci re-
age to their land and prolonged exile from their home sponded: “[The] real loss was the whole generation of
atolls. In particular, I focus on land and its significance young men who have grown up without the ability to
for local knowledge, subsistence production, and rela- practice under the most skilled of these men who knew
tions to place. I will argue that these relationships reflect how to shape a canoe properly. . . . Enewetak canoes are
both ownership and belonging, raising questions about quite unique. I don’t [know] . . . if there is a possibility
the alienation of property regarded as inalienable. of re-developing those skills.”
The anthropologist Nancy Pollock, testifying for the
Defender of the Fund, challenged Carucci’s claims about
Property as a Way of Knowing the fragility of this knowledge during cross-examination
by Davor Pevec, attorney for the people of Enewetak:
David Anderson (1998) has suggested that for reindeer
herders in Siberia “property is a way of knowing,” that Pevec: [If these resources] are not in existence or
“knowing the land properly . . . is what legitimated their [can]not . . . be imported, people would not be able
right to take wood, water and animals from the land, to maintain the traditional knowledge which you
whilst at the same time explaining their capacity to do have described.
so” (p. 69). Paul Sillitoe (1998a) has argued that the tran-
sition from capital-intensive to information-intensive Pollock: It does not disappear.
technology and the emphasis on participation in devel-
opment have created new demands for local knowledge, Pevec: It does not disappear, but they are not able to
especially in relation to the environment, and recom- actually practice it.
mended that anthropologists position themselves as
knowledge brokers to facilitate this process. His respon- Pollock: What is happening with canoe culture at
dents suggest that it may prove more difficult than Sil- the moment is that there is a lot of old knowledge
litoe envisions to convert indigenous understandings which is being resurrected around the Pacific be-
into other forms of knowledge, in part because they tend cause of interest in canoes.
to be contingent and local rather than systematized and
universal, but agree that alternative forms of knowledge Pevec: Unless you have the resources on your atoll
have value even if not fully translatable. The most im- . . . [He is cut off by Pollock].
portant dimension of local knowledge may not even be
specific information per se but particular strategies for Pollock: No. People are very innovative. . . . Every-
where I go in the Pacific, I see small children, one of
17. Annette Weiner (1992:104) has argued that “taking a possession the things they love to do is . . . build little canoes,
that so completely represents a group’s social identity as well as out of paper or whatever they’ve got. . . . It doesn’t
an individual owner’s identity and giving it to someone outside the die, it remains. It is not easily replicated in the full
group is a powerful transfer of one’s own and one’s group’s very
substance.”
size, but in the children’s representations, the toy,
18. As Barker (1997:293) notes, “In a nation with just 70 square that knowledge can be seen.
miles of land, land is by no means expendable.”
174 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

Marshallese canoes include the long-distance sailing ves- In Australia, the courts have recognized the losses as-
sel known as walap, as much as 30 m in length, which sociated with damage to subsistence economies in hear-
can transport 40 passengers and is built for travel on the ings about the environmental impact of the Ok Tedi
open sea between atolls; the mid-sized tipnol, which car- mine (Kirsch 1997a). The case against the mine did not
ries 10 passengers and is used for rapid transport and address damage to property, because the courts were un-
fishing in the lagoons and the open sea; and the small able to hear claims about land held under customary land
rowing canoe known as the korkor, which may also have tenure in New Guinea (Gordon 1997:153). Alternatively,
sails and carries 1–2 persons for fishing and traveling lawyers for the plaintiffs made the novel argument that
within the lagoon. In the past, every family owned at people living downstream from the mine had suffered a
least one mid-sized canoe and a small rowing canoe. loss due to its impact on their subsistence economy.
Construction of these vessels required mature breadfruit Judge J. Byrne (1995:16) endorsed the underlying prin-
trees for the hull and outrigger and a variety of other ciple, determining that
woods. People planted and tended trees that years later
would be used to build canoes. The complex require- to restrict the duty of care to cases of pure economic
ments of canoe building, only hinted at here, raise ques- loss would be to deny a remedy to those whose life
tions about the effective intergenerational transmission is substantially, if not entirely, outside an economic
of knowledge. In the absence of a robust tradition of system which uses money as a medium of exchange.
literacy, such knowledge is reproduced through concrete It was put that, in the case of subsistence dwellers,
acts of teaching and use, and the loss of access to the loss of the things necessary for subsistence may be
resources necessary for canoe building is of consequence seen as akin to economic loss. If the plaintiffs are
for the communication of these practices across gener- unable or less able to have or enjoy those things
ational lines. Property can be a way of knowing, and local which are necessary for their subsistence as a result
knowledge may depend on continued access to land and of the defendants’ negligent conduct of the mine,
resources. Women on Enewetak no longer teach their they must look elsewhere for them, perhaps to ob-
daughters how to weave mats because the necessary va- tain them by purchase or barter or perhaps to obtain
rieties of pandanus are unavailable, and men no longer
some substitute.
teach their nephews and sons how to build sailing canoes
because they do not have the raw materials. Already the
knowledge of how to construct and maintain the long- The case against the Ok Tedi mine established a prec-
distance sailing canoes of Enewetak, unique in design, edent for the right to engage in subsistence production.
may have been forgotten (Nuclear Claims Tribunal In the negotiated settlement of the case, a commercial
1999a). Such knowledge is cultural property, and its vul- fisherman was awarded financial compensation for lost
nerability in the sense of being local should not diminish revenues. Yet, in contrast to the situation in the Exxon
its value in the courts. It is neither imaginary nor Valdez case, cultural differences were taken into con-
speculative. sideration with respect to the reliance on natural re-
sources of subsistence economies in the form of financial
support for the restoration of local sustainability. The
Australian courts recognized in subsistence production
The Value of Subsistence Production a set of economic rights, relations, and values compa-
rable to those which organize the ownership of property
in capitalist societies.
During interviews on Majuro, informants described how Anthropologists have observed that land and kinship
they had become dependent on the cash economy since are often “mutually implicated” in subsistence econo-
their relocation from Rongelap. Contemporary substi- mies (Hirsch 1995:9).20 Sahlins (1999:xvii) has recently
tutes for subsistence practices require capital invest- described the social and cultural continuities of indige-
ment; whereas fishing grounds were once accessible to
all without restriction, boats and fuel are now required
in order to fish (interview with Johnsay Riklon, 1999).
A man from Rongelap described the transformation in tourism destination for scuba-diving (see www.bikiniatoll.com).
The primary danger is from local foodstuffs consumed over an ex-
terms of the restrictions on personal autonomy: “If you tended period of time. Radiation thus inverts the notion of property:
live in town, you are like a guest in someone’s house, while in the past their relationship to land implied exclusive use
[whereas] on your own land, you feel freedom” (interview of its resources, today the risks of cumulative exposure to radiation
with Ken Kedi, 1999). The loss of their subsistence econ- prevent them from exploiting these resources, even though strang-
ers who lack historical connections to Rongelap, including fishing
omy has transformed local relations of production, gen-
boats from Southeast Asia, are not prevented from doing so (inter-
erating new forms of socioeconomic inequality.19 view with Ken Kedi, 1999).
20. For Aboriginal Australians, “the relationships between people
19. Health risks posed by radiation create an additional paradox of and their country are intense, intimate, full of responsibility, and,
place for the people from Rongelap. The risk in visiting the lagoons when all is well, friendly. It is a kinship relationship, and like
or islands affected by nuclear testing is minimal; Bikini Atoll, relations among kin, there are obligations of nurturance. People
ground zero for many of the tests, now markets itself as an eco- and country take care of each other” (D. Rose 1996:49).
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 175

nous populations, especially northern hunters, in spite nuclear weapons, they were stunned by its transforma-
of widespread economic and political change: tion: “all the markers of [their] sense of place and history,
and their sense of their own person [were] transformed.”
Their long, intensive and varied engagements with
Carucci also described the disjunction between the
the international market economy have not funda-
“new” and the “old” Enewetak, which now exists only
mentally altered their customary organizations of
in their memories: the “sacred landscapes ha[ve] been
production, modes of ownership and resource con-
destroyed . . . all of the embedded stories . . . [of] their
trol, division of labor, or patterns of distribution and
own past [and] the activities of their ancestors going back
consumption; nor have their extended kinship and
to the first moment in time [are] no longer attached . . .
community bonds been dissolved or the economic
to the physical locations with which they are associated
and social obligations thereof fallen off; neither have
in people’s minds.” The resulting “dissonance between
social (cum “spiritual”) relations to nature disap-
what once existed and what [now] exists . . . presents
peared; and they have not lost their cultural identi-
people with a problem in terms of establishing a mean-
ties, not even when they live in white folks’ towns.
ingful Enewetak identity.”
While Pollock acknowledged Carucci’s claim that
Hunters and gatherers still actively engage in these pur- “land anchors people in place . . . and gives them iden-
suits, he points out, and these practices have become tity,” she disagreed with him on the nature of this re-
central to their identities much as they have remained lationship, arguing that “identity and . . . land exist be-
essential for their social relations. In what he describes yond the economic, beyond the surface layer, beyond the
as the “indigenization of modernity,” these communi- map that we see here [in the courtroom]. It is a spiritual
ties have put capitalism in service of their subsistence tie to land and it is a tie to land that can never be broken.
practices. Yet these activities are contingent upon their . . .” Relations to land are a “very important continuing
continued access to land and resources, which elsewhere factor that was not severed as Dr. Carucci argued . . .
has been jeopardized or impaired by the destructive con- because the spiritual tie persists over time and over
sequences of modern technologies of warfare and devel- space, no matter where you are.”
opment (see Brody 1988). The division of people into Pollock supported her claim to the spiritual primacy
social categories through their relationships to land and of ties to land in two ways. She referred to her conver-
resources is the basis of relations of production in many sations with people in Majuro: “[When I] asked ‘Where
indigenous societies and an important means through are you from?’ . . . they would [name their home atoll].
which these relationships are reproduced; a community’s They . . . may not have ever been there, but they still
capacity to support itself through subsistence production have very strong ties to land.” Pollock also argued that
is simultaneously a matter of belonging and a matter of the “Marshallese people are very proud of their history
possession. of movement. . . . They move constantly and the res-
urrection of the canoe and current interest in canoe
building is all part of that. They’ve always moved freely
Place and Community using sailing canoes and linking up with the lands where
they have kin relations.”21 The debate between the two
anthropologists hinges on competing views of culture,
The anthropologist Roger Keesing (1989:19) once argued
although they do not make their positions on the subject
that Pacific interest in land rights was a postcolonial
explicit.
invention, part of a broader creation of “myths of an-
To clarify these issues, I suggest a lateral shift to an
cestral ways of life that serve as powerful political sym-
bols.” “Land, and spiritual connection to it, could not alternative set of definitions. Arjun Appadurai (1995:209)
have, other than in a context of invasion and displace- posits a distinction between neighborhood, which he de-
ment and alienation, the ideological significance that it fines as a “context, or set of contexts within which
acquires in such a context” (p. 33). While land has ac- meaningful social action can be both generated and in-
quired new significance throughout the Pacific, com- terpreted,” and “ethnoscape,” his neologism for collec-
parable to the changes in Aboriginal valuation of their tive identities that transcend place, as in the case of dias-
own traditions described by Weiner (1999), Keesing has poric cultures. While an ethnoscape is independent of
been criticized for ignoring the value that land had for place, a neighborhood is a thing which can, of course, be
people in the past (Trask 1991), particularly for island destroyed. The dissolution of a neighborhood—a histor-
communities where land is limited and population den-
21. Pollock also suggests that relocation has a cultural precedent
sities approach local carrying capacity.
in the Marshall Islands: “[The] Iroij or chief of the Marshalls . . .
In their testimony to the Nuclear Claims Tribunal, had the power to [order people] to relocate. Relocation, as I under-
Carucci and Pollock offered contrasting interpretations stand it, is a part of Marshallese culture” (Nuclear Claims Tribunal
of the relationships between people and land in Ene- 1999b). Here she conflates two very different processes—the au-
wetak. Like Keesing’s critics, Carucci argued that the thority to ostracize members of the community by forcing them
to relocate, which is effective as a form of punishment precisely
relationship between past and present was the most sa- because these persons are separated from their social group, and
lient for the people of Enewetak. When they returned to the power to remove the entire community from its home atoll,
their home atoll 30 years after it had been used to test which has no local precedent.
176 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

ical accumulation of experience and identity—not only the one hand, “property is necessary to give people
represents a concrete loss but also affects the production ‘roots,’ stable surroundings, a context of control over the
of local subjects. A spiritual attachment to place is not environment, [and] a context of stable expectations that
the same as living on one’s home atoll, nor are travelers fosters autonomy and personality” (p. 197). On the other
the same as migrants; prior to the bomb, Marshallese hand, economic considerations require that property be
sailors had homes to which they could return at will. subject to market forces. To resolve the contradiction,
The distinction between ethnoscape and neighborhood Radin proposes the disaggregation of the concept of prop-
must be qualified, however. Research on diaspora com- erty, arguing that “some categories of property rights do
munities emphasizes the costs of disrupting local rela- justifiably become bound up with persons and then
tions to place (e.g., Lovell 1998, Olwig and Hastrup 1997). ought not to be prima facie subject to rearrangement by
Diasporic experience is always suffused with nostalgia, market forces” (p. 197). Like the legal precedent in Ei-
itself an awareness of loss, and accompanied by new senring v. Kansas Turnpike Authority discussed above,
strategies to preserve memory and identity. The severing Radin’s view provides an opening for the consideration
of connections between people and place always entails of cultural property rights, for the designation of what
loss. is and what is not properly alienable is a cultural rather
than an analytical matter.
This observation is significant with respect to the Mar-
Property and Alienability shall Islands case. In her testimony before the Nuclear
Claims Tribunal, Pollock asserted that material condi-
tions (including market forces) do not affect the rela-
In the debates before the Nuclear Claims Tribunal, the
tionship between persons and land in the Marshall Is-
issue of cultural difference emerged most significantly
lands. Her position is comparable to the view expressed
in relation to property.22 The legal scholar Carol Rose
by Judge Holland in the Exxon Valdez case that culture
(1994:296) has argued that “seeing property is an act of
is located in our “minds and hearts” and therefore un-
imagination—and seeing property also reflects some of
affected by external events. Furthermore, she ignored the
the cultural limitations on imagination.”23 She describes
problem of alienability in the Marshalls; whereas indi-
how the concept of property is constrained by assump-
vidual blocks of land may, subject to local restrictions,
tions about economic value and governed by commodity
be leased to others, there is no historical precedent for
logic that assumes the detachability of persons and
the alienation of an entire atoll (Zorn 1993:126–29).
things. This limitation of Anglo-American property re-
When inalienable possessions are treated as alienable
gimes is particularly telling in the Marshall Islands case.
property, as occurred during nuclear testing in the Mar-
Largely concealed from view at the Nuclear Claims
shall Islands, the resulting loss is social as well as ma-
Tribunal, albeit implicit in Carucci’s arguments about
terial and thus inadequately represented by its market
Enewetak relationships to land and place, is the as-
value alone.
sumption of alienability—the view that all forms of prop-
The alienation of land is of general concern for indig-
erty are inherently convertible into other forms of prop-
enous peoples; as I suggested earlier, the loss of otherwise
erty. Annette Weiner (1992:4) has emphasized the
inalienable homelands can jeopardize not only the ma-
significance of inalienable possessions in Pacific socie-
terial conditions of survival, including subsistence prac-
ties, arguing that certain forms of property provide con-
tices, but also the requirements of social reproduction
tinuity to social relations by presenting an alternative
as embedded in kinship relations. Local knowledge and
to the ephemeral nature of human existence. The im-
relations to place may be affected as well. The concept
portance of these objects transcends their exchange
of loss, with its dual registers of belonging and posses-
value, and their loss poses a threat not only to their
sion, provides an alternative understanding of property,
owners but also to the group of which they are members
helping to bridge what Rose (1994:5) has described as
because their historicity preserves memories of the past
“the peculiar gap between property-as-thing and prop-
(p. 6).
erty-as-relationship.”
Margaret Radin (1993:197) identifies alienability as the
It is worth asking why the discussion of loss in the
central paradox of Anglo-American property theory. On
Marshall Islands should be framed in terms of property
22. Carol Rose (1994:50) asks provocatively: “What are we trying models at all.24 One might propose alternative strategies
to accomplish with a property regime? If we know the answer to to analyze their losses. For example, Carucci describes
this most general question about property, we can begin to under- Enewetak experiences of anomie, as expressed by the
stand what we include in property and why, and what we leave out Marshallese idiom of jebw we, a term that means to drift
and why, and thus what kinds of governmental actions we deem
at sea and is used to describe the “conceptually and emo-
to take property and why we so deem them. Though these questions
clearly involve issues of theory, they are also intensely practical; tionally disconcerting state of ‘having no direction’”
and practice itself should yield some information about which the-
ory or theories best inform our general vision of property.” 24. Consider what Deborah Rose (1999:16) writes about the Mabo
23. Carol Rose notes (1994:295; see also D. Rose 1999) that in Aus- court decision in Australia as an inadequate remedy for colonial
tralia, “many European settlers simply did not see anything at all injustice: “The peculiarity of the case was to establish the existence
that signified indigenous entitlement, . . . [and] many justified their of a form of property; while any number of terrible things happen
moves [onto Aboriginal lands] . . . by what they said was the emp- in colonisation . . . people cannot be deprived of their property
tiness of the land.” without certain legalities being in order.”
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 177

(Carucci and Maifeld 1999:3–4).25 This idiom clearly ex- and American conceptions of property. There is no an-
presses some of the pain, loss, and suffering experienced thropological consensus on how to describe the complex
as a result of nuclear testing and relocation. Yet the Nu- histories of indigenous communities and the problem of
clear Claims Tribunal requires an interpretation that cor- culture loss. In one of the most widely read accounts of
responds to Western models of property and loss. Even how the concept of culture is deployed in the courtroom,
judges sympathetic to the claims of people from Ron- James Clifford’s (1988:277-346) analysis of the unsuc-
gelap and Enewetak will find their options limited—and cessful application for federal recognition by the Mash-
their analogies wanting—unless anthropologists provide pee Indians of Cape Cod, metaphors of holism and con-
them with the tools of analysis necessary to rule on these tinuity prevented the courts from appreciating their
issues. history of accommodation, political negotiation, and cul-
tural innovation. Anthropological arguments about cul-
ture must be able to account for the contradictory de-
Conclusions mands that the courts placed on the Mashpee and the
people of Rongelap: to recognize change while simulta-
I want to present a final image, of a tribunal hearing held neously acknowledging loss.
in the High Court of the Republic of the Marshall Islands, The proliferation of legal proceedings about culture
the back benches crowded with interested plaintiffs from raises other important issues for anthropologists to con-
Enewetak, the front of the room occupied by three jus- sider. Legal forums that adjudicate claims of loss might
tices (one Marshallese and two American) and the op- be seen to further commodification by establishing mon-
posing lawyers seated beside the anthropologists whom etary values for cultural property which previously ex-
they have engaged as expert witnesses. I quote Judge isted outside of economic domains. Money is hardly an
Plasman, who addresses the implications of Carucci’s ideal substitute, although it can be the means to other
testimony (Nuclear Claims Tribunal 1999a): ends—to decontaminate Rongelap Atoll, for exam-
ple—which cannot be achieved in any other way. Legal
When we talk about culture loss . . . are we to some activism can provide important political and economic
extent faced with a Humpty Dumpty situation resources for indigenous peoples, as the Ok Tedi case
where the pieces are broken and in some respects [it illustrates, particularly when the terms of the debate are
will not] be possible to put Humpty Dumpty back set and the mechanisms of justice controlled by non-
together again? . . . The tribunal obviously has to indigenous bodies. Nonetheless, not all losses are com-
struggle with this question. To the extent that the pensable or even judicable. The acknowledgment of loss,
claim is that there has been a loss of culture, to however, along with appropriate acts of commemora-
what extent is the cure going to be worse than the tion, historical documentation, and, where relevant, ac-
sickness? People don’t want to go back to the prime- ceptance of responsibility, and the implementation of
val garden of Eden. . . . Culture changes and accom- reforms designed to prevent past wrongs from recurring
modation has to be made between the old and the are partial but legitimate responses to claims of culture
new. Where do you see that balance? Perhaps [Car- loss.
ucci’s] comment that [this] needs to be done by the The problem of culture loss raises questions about
people of Enewetak themselves . . . [is the right agency and responsibility. What distinguishes between
answer]. man-made disasters and their natural counterparts, such
as the seasonal typhoons that can inflict heavy damage
Culture has a new set of interlocutors and new contexts on fragile Marshallese atolls and force temporary relo-
for its deliberation as judges, juries, and expert witnesses cation? Carucci’s answer to this question during the tri-
deploy alternative definitions: something which can be bunal was that the Marshallese are well adapted to the
lost or damaged, something embedded in our minds and risks and challenges of atoll life. Of course, the scale and
hearts, a mode of adaptation, a process of change. In the scope of the transformations wrought by the weather and
Exxon Valdez case, Bohannan’s emphasis on the human by nuclear weapons differ tremendously. Yet it may well
capacity for adaptation prevented him from recognizing be that claims about culture loss will arise more fre-
important cultural differences. By arguing that culture quently in the context of assigning social responsibility
is largely independent of the material world, Pollock pre- for negative events.
sented an essentialized view of Marshallese culture. Car- Why privilege the Rongelap claim or indigenous
ucci persuasively argued the case for cultural relativism, claims more generally if the experiences are not unique?
identifying fundamental differences between Enewetak In a general sense, claims of culture loss may be a di-
agnostic feature of our time, given the unprecedented
25. Pollock disputes Carucci’s reference to anomie, which she de- pace of technological change and its social consequences.
scribes as being “very much taken from Western ideas and trying The shift to a postindustrial economy in Europe and
to account for [the] response to the cash economy.” She argues that America, for example, has greatly reduced or even elim-
the concept is inapplicable in the Enewetak case: “People felt that inated entire economic sectors, including small-scale
[their relocation] was beyond their control, but they tried their best
to adjust. That does not mean that they suffered any anomie” as a farming and coal mining, often at considerable cost to
result. She implies that because people are able to adapt to chal- the associated communities, including impoverishment,
lenging circumstances, they do not incur any loss. displacement, and a profound sense of loss (Read 1996,
178 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

Charlesworth 2000). Yet claims of loss are particularly 1993, 1994). Caboclos—Amazonian riverside peasants of
salient for indigenous communities, which frequently mixed European, Amerindian, and African descent
have special ties to land and place that, while they have —employ indigenous strategies for subsistence and col-
analogues elsewhere, differ in relation to the way that lect forest resources for the market (see Parker 1985).
these societies organize and reproduce themselves Although they are not considered indigenous people, it
(Kirsch n.d.). The analysis of the contemporary predic- has been argued that they should be given special ac-
aments of indigeneity may provide the impetus for a commodations, such as recognition of common land ten-
general rethinking of the theoretical challenges associ- ure, because their economic activities are relatively more
ated with culture change, cultural property rights, and sustainable than those of other social groups given their
loss. special knowledge and methods of resource use (cf. An-
Anthropological debates on cultural property rights derson 1990). In fact, Nugent (1993) argues that they
(e.g., Dove 1996, Brush 1996, Brown 1998) have focused should be regarded as a distinct group. If we accept Nu-
primarily on the issues of cultural appropriation, com- gent’s argument, then they are like the groups Kirsch
modification, and potential restrictions on the circula- discusses with regard to cultural property rights.
tion of knowledge and creative processes. I have chosen For at least 100 years caboclos in the region had gath-
an alternative starting point, suggesting that ethno- ered rubber and Brazil nuts, mined for diamonds in the
graphic studies of loss may enrich our understandings of Tocantins River for the market, and gardened, hunted,
property and, conversely, that the concept of cultural and gathered other forest products for their subsistence.
property rights may inform ongoing debates—legal, in- The diamond mining and most of the Brazil nut gath-
digenous, and anthropological—about the problem of ering were market-oriented via patron-client relations
culture loss. whereby caboclos received access to resources in
Finally, I hope that this paper has been able to still for exchange for the product. However, in at least one place
a moment the circulation of images of environmental the people themselves controlled access to a large area
disasters like Bikini, Bhopal, the Exxon Valdez, and Ok of Brazil nuts that they held in common and controlled
Tedi. Only by reembedding these events and their con- by community sanctions that ensured a level playing
sequences in a network of social relations and thereby field (Biery-Hamilton 1994). The extractive industry was
reducing their scale is it possible to address them both almost entirely destroyed during the 1980s by the de-
analytically and politically. velopment projects initiated by the Brazilian govern-
ment, which made no provisions for the caboclos’ econ-
omy because they were not indigenous. Some people
received indemnification from the power company for
Comments the land they had in production at the time, their houses
and other buildings, and their orchards, but the money
they received was a small amount and was eaten up by
g a y m . b i e ry - h a m i l t o n inflation in the 1980s. However, no lump sum of money
Latin American and Caribbean Affairs, Rollins could sustain them in the long run in the same way as
College, 1000 Holt Ave., 2761, Winter Park, Fla. their former subsistence strategies. They lost their tra-
32789, U.S.A. (gbieryh@rollins.edu). 12 xi 00 ditional means of making a living, experienced economic
specialization and stratification, and were no longer in
Kirsch shows that different definitions of culture used control of their economic options or political process
by anthropologists in court have real-world repercus- (Biery-Hamilton 1994, 1996). Moreover, since locals were
sions on indigenous peoples who have been impacted by no longer making their living using these traditional
human-made disasters. Wisely, he doesn’t call for a uni- strategies, the younger generation was not learning about
fied definition of culture but instead proposes a consid- them experientially, and specialized knowledge about
eration of cultural property rights, which includes loss. horticulture, hunting, wild plants, and water currents
However, as anthropologists we recognize that culture was being lost.
is integrated in that how people make a living and use As in other places where people lose access to land
their environment has direct ties to their ideas, artifacts, and resources from development and relocation projects,
core values, and meanings. When people lose their ability these caboclos lost former strategies of subsistence pro-
to make a living, they experience major changes in their duction, connections to place, and local knowledge.
ideational realm. All aspects of their culture will change, Their previous economic strategies were associated with
and in my fieldwork people who had experienced such their common access to resources and land, and the loss
change certainly expressed feelings of loss (Biery-Ham- they experienced meant their cultural impoverishment
ilton 1993). In fact, in the Tucuruı́-Marabá region of Pará, economically, politically, socially, spiritually, and ex-
Brazil, in the Amazon, many caboclos were relocated in perientially. Caboclos’ ideas of common access to re-
the 1980s (Mougeot 1986) because of the Tucuruı́ Hy- sources and social sanctions were necessary aspects of
droelectric Dam and a transition to private property. In their subsistence strategies. Kirsch points to the fallacy
the process both relocatees and people who did not move of separating ideas from economy. If anthropologists can-
lost access to critical river and forest resources necessary not agree on a definition of culture, perhaps we can agree
to sustain their former lifeways (Biery-Hamilton on the usefulness of his notion of cultural property rights
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 179

in integrating the ideational and material realms of be easy to identify, intermarriage and cultural blending
culture. make it increasingly difficult to define the boundaries of
Anthropologists who assist in court cases like the ones the indigenous (Gonzales 1998). What are we to make,
Kirsch describes are forced to make culture something for instance, of the emergence in the Mexico-U.S. bor-
that is legible (Scott 1998) to a judge who will decide. derlands of the Mexica movement, whose members have
The basis of the decision is going to be a simplification jettisoned an identity as Hispanics or Latinos in favor of
of what is a very complex understanding of culture, for reconnection with their Indian roots? “We are not Span-
example, whether culture is in the head and heart or iards. We are the Mexica of Anahuac!” declares one of
grounded in the physical world and the way people make the movement’s websites. “Artificial European bound-
a living. Judges, influenced by anthropologists, have the aries on our land can never sever our ties to our common
power to decide what culture is and what it is not, and Olmeca mother civilization and our shared Maya, Teo-
thereafter people can claim a loss and be indemnified for tihuacan and Nahuatl-Mexica culture, or our shared op-
it only if it fits that definition. Kirsch’s definition rec- pression and exploitation” (Chicano Mexicano Mexica
ognizes the complexity of local history and culture but Empowerment Committee n.d.). Even if we accept that
provides a way of articulating particularistic aspects into people are free to reinvent their identities as they like,
a broader framework that might be intelligible to non- it is hard to justify giving this group the same special
anthropologist decision makers. Further, his concept of standing that existing law grants to the Hopi or the
cultural property rights has the potential to give anthro- Pitjantjantjara.
pologists and indigenous groups a way of influencing lit- More vexing still is the question of when claims of
igation and policy in their behalf. The concept is prom- culture loss would expire, if ever. We live in an era when
ising, too, for groups like caboclos, so that they can demands for slavery-related reparations are taken seri-
protect their livelihoods and contribute their expertise ously by some in the United States (see, for instance,
to the critical effort of developing a more sustainable Barkan 2000) and when a judicial struggle over owner-
resource management program in the Amazon. ship of gold salvaged from an 18th-century shipwreck
can give rise to the suggestion that the booty be returned
to South American Indians rather than repatriated to
m i c h a e l f . b ro w n Spain (Broad 2000). Kirsch proposes no statute of limi-
Department of Anthropology and Sociology, Williams tations for culture-loss claims, leaving the door open to
College, Williamstown, Mass. 01267, U.S.A. a panorama of litigation mining the darkest chapters of
(mbrown@williams.edu). 22 xi 00 human history. Although the turn toward revisiting an-
cient wrongs opens new career opportunities for lawyers,
Kirsch’s essay is an important contribution to the wid- it is hard to see how it will help us confront the political,
ening circle of work that registers the reification of cul- economic, and ecological challenges of the future.
ture, its transformation from an abstraction largely de- The search for a workable framework for culture-loss
rived from belief and behavior into something that a claims is further hampered by the overblown rhetoric to
given population “possesses” and can therefore “lose.” which published work on the subject of cultural rights
This turn of events has led some anthropologists to re- seems fatally inclined. An example, by no means excep-
nounce the culture concept altogether. But culture has tional, is Tove Skutnabb-Kangas’s (1999:8) insistence
become a social fact, one that is readily reconceived as that discriminatory language policies qualify as geno-
a form of property. It is too late to disown this child of cide. The logic of Skutnabb-Kangas’s claim runs some-
our discipline, however discomfiting its current thing like this: (1) the United Nations Convention on
behavior. Genocide recognizes the forcible relocation of children
The cases that Kirsch uses to support his argument from their families to another group as a form of geno-
are convincing. I suspect that few readers will challenge cide; (2) coercive language policies alienate children from
his assertion that egregious wrongs were done, serious their own group and orient them to another; (3) ergo,
losses suffered. Still unspecified by his analysis, however, state practices that favor one language over another con-
are the limits of culture-loss claims—the outer bound- stitute genocide. Such twisted casuistry does little to
aries beyond which the culture-loss concept loses its advance the legitimacy of cultural damage claims in the
force. minds of legislators, jurists, and the general public.
Kirsch presents a plausible case for seeing indigenous Kirsch’s admirably measured approach to these com-
peoples as uniquely vulnerable to cultural disruption plex issues doubtless reflects his experience in the ap-
when environmental disasters affect their communities. plied world. Although I am generally convinced by his
From this he concludes they they merit special consid- argument, I hope that he will develop it further by tack-
eration in processes of remediation. But exactly who is ling knottier questions about the social and temporal
indigenous? As John R. Bowen (2000) has shown, defi- boundaries beyond which claims of cultural damage or
nitions of indigenousness that have emerged from global loss may be discounted. A clear definition of the limits
human-rights forums are often misleading when applied of his approach will immensely strengthen the position
to populations outside of regions reshaped by European of groups with legitimate grievances. Without it, I fear,
settler colonialism (e.g., North America, Australia, and the culture-loss concept can be too easily dismissed as
New Zealand). Even in places where First Peoples should another example of the politics of victimization.
180 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

s t e p h e n b . b ru s h david a. cleveland
Department of Human and Community Development, Department of Anthropology and the Environmental
University of California, Davis, Calif. 95616, U.S.A. Studies Program, University of California, Santa
15 xi 00 Barbara, CA 93106-3210, U.S.A. (clevelan@
lifesci.ucsb.edu). 27 xi 00
Kirsch invokes the concept of property but fails to ground
his discussion of culture loss in a theoretical or histor- Kirsch does an excellent job of identifying a critical the-
ically informed vision of property as a social institution. oretical and practical problem for anthropology—that
He neglects the important dichotomy of property as a contemporary definitions of culture as fluid and dynamic
utilitarian construct versus property as a natural right. make it extremely difficult to assess and redress cultural
This dichotomy underlies much of the current conflict loss by indigenous communities as a result of biophys-
over extending property rights to areas such as indige- ical, economic, and social globalization. His method for
nous knowledge and cultural expression. The view of “the work of analysis” required to address this problem
property as a social contract underlies much 20th-cen- is twofold: (1) reembedding indigenous loss in social re-
tury social analysis and is derived from Hohfeld’s (1913) lations in order to “slow the movement of images” and
seminal article. In this formulation, property is under- “reduce their scale” and (2) using a concept of “cultural
stood as a set of social relations that are explicitly ac- property rights,” which includes knowledge of things as
knowledged and sanctioned. Recognition has different property and of people as relationships. He is successful
sources, but the social utility of privileging a particular in demonstrating that indigenous loss of physical place
group is nearly always present. Implicit costs to other is often also loss of cultural property in the sense of
parties are likewise acknowledged. It is precisely this subjective or mental loss.
construction that has driven the legal decisions that I have two suggestions to complement his proposal.
Kirsch laments. An individual, group, or anthropologist First, I think that we need to take more seriously possible
may embrace the concept of cultural property, but this problems with attempts to grant rights to indigenous
notion has little value unless it is also embraced by other cultural property in terms of Western property rights.
social groups and institutions. The tragedy of colonized For example, on the basis of research in Indonesia, Dove
people such as the Marshallese and Native Americans (1993) has suggested that the introduction of Western
obscures the fundamental theoretical issues of assigning
intellectual property rights regimes will likely only
or withholding property rights from novel domains. A
worsen the situation because of the destruction of local
property contract in these situations involves both the
resources not only by outsiders but by local people them-
dominant and dominated parties that confront each
selves. The long struggle for recognition of Native Amer-
other in the cases reviewed by Kirsch. Under Hohfeld’s
icans’ water rights and for compensation for their loss
(1913) reasoning, recognition of cultural property must
of these rights has resulted in legal remedies based on
be beneficial both to those who “own” culture and to
the dominant society’s standards, which equate rights
those who recognize that ownership. Unilateral decla-
with the level of resource “use.” In many cases this has
rations do not suffice because they do not generate the
obligation to respect another’s rights. There are other strengthened large-scale commercial irrigation develop-
formulations of property that might be entertained to ment on Indian land, with subsequent loss of indigenous
allow something like cultural property, but these need knowledge and landscapes connected with traditional
to be laid out and weighed against the prevailing theory small-scale, family-based irrigation (Cleveland 1998).
of property involved in the cases reviewed by Kirsch. If instead we are to attempt to construct alternative
The negotiation over what is and is not property in- “rights” that interface between indigenous and Western
evitably must confront the issue of the public domain rights, we return to the original problem as stated by
(Brush 1999), a concept that is absent in Kirsch’s paper. Kirsch, because rights are also fluid in cultural time and
A large, theoretically rich, and relevant literature exists space—they are culturally constructed. In a world of 6
on social impact analysis and the internalization of billion humans that may well be environmentally un-
“costs” that have hitherto gone unrecognized (e.g., Coase sustainable, there are multiple claims of rights to in-
1960). Anthropologists who wish to propose new forms creasingly limited resources, and any attempt to con-
of property would be well served by addressing that lit- struct new rights regimes must consider these absolute
erature. Again, the extremity of double victimization un- limits. Therefore, the social construction of rights will
der colonization and nuclear testing may obscure the also be to some extent contingent on the empirical re-
issue of the wider social benefits and costs that are at lationships between culture and the conservation of
play in recognizing culture as property and culture loss place. We must not assume that indigenous peoples nec-
as deserving compensation. essarily either destroy or conserve their own local
“places” and cultural properties, because there are no
valid theories from which to deduce either position and
there are examples of both. Rather, we need to document
what conditions are correlated with conservation of
place by both indigenous and outside actors and inves-
tigate potential causal relationships. While the results of
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 181

this research cannot determine rights, they can help to tialism or hybridity but rather to investigate the political
inform their social construction. implications of disciplinary disagreements. Kirsch is
Second, it is unnecessary to conclude that if indige- conscientious in his search for a concept that can be
nous knowledge is dependent on local, physical place it helpful to those in search of justice, and he offers “cul-
is therefore completely defined by it and thus essentially tural property rights” as one such concept. But I think
different from Western knowledge (Agrawal 1995). There that his respect for disciplinary protocols prevents him
is a need to develop a coherent intellectual framework from going a bit farther to raise questions about the po-
in which indigenous knowledge can interface effectively litical meaning of the case under discussion, its impli-
with Western science (Sillitoe 1998b). Just as we have cations for problems of domination in the contemporary
moved beyond definitions of indigenous knowledge as world, and the part anthropologists (and others) play in
static and bounded, so we need to move beyond defining it.
it as essentially different from Western knowledge. An- There are two aspects to the question. The first is the
thropologists have documented the ability of indigenous assumption that claims to culture (or cultural authen-
cultures to float free of their physical places to form ticity) may be adjudicated in courts in order to be com-
virtual communities (Appadurai 1990), using the tools pensated for “culture loss.” This may seem a strange
of modern Western technology to perpetuate themselves question, since courts may be the only venue in which
on a global scale. In the same way, indigenous peoples those who have suffered at the hands of colonialism,
may benefit not only from modern technology but from capital, and the military can seek compensation. The
the data and theories of modern science (just as scientists Marshall Islanders who suffered radioactive colonization
can benefit from indigenous knowledge). For example, at the hands of the United States military can hardly be
understanding the conceptual similarities and differ- blamed for seeking compensation through the courts. It
ences of the plant-breeding knowledge of farmers and is confusing the issues, however, to state as Kirsch does
scientists may facilitate collaboration between them that “indigenous claims about culture loss are increas-
that results in improvements in farmers’ own terms ingly associated with political and legal contexts in
(Cleveland, Soleri, and Smith 2000, Soleri et al. 2000). which communities seek reparations for past injustices.”
This is important, because if local peoples are to main- We ought to know better than to refer to the “political
tain their cultural properties and physical places collab- and legal” in the same breath, especially in a context in
oration with outsiders based on the similarities and dif- which both politics and legality need to be questioned
ferences between indigenous and Western knowledges in light of claims to cultural difference. In a case such
may be critical. If we find similarities, this does not mean as that of the Marshall Islanders, the “legal context”
that the power of the scientific over the indigenous will serves to cover up the political, resignation to which may
necessarily increase. The results will depend on how this well be an expression of their ultimate helplessness, es-
information is used and within what power structure, pecially where issues of cultural autonomy are in ques-
and therefore we need to understand this power structure tion. They can make their claims for justice only in the
to facilitate an equitable status for indigenous knowledge language of the jurisprudence and property-rights regime
in discussions about future development and in the so- of those responsible for their plight in the first place. It
cial construction of rights. may seem a benign act on the part of the United States
We can make important contributions that comple- to allow them into the courtroom, but the price of ad-
ment Kirsch’s suggestions by encouraging the discussion mission is to abide by the very culturally determined
and social construction of rights in which indigenous assumptions, rules, procedures of that courtroom, which
peoples participate as equals and by documenting the already indicates a further erosion of any claims to cul-
similarities and differences between indigenous and sci- tural autonomy. From this perspective, the legalization
entific knowledges and the power structures in which of political issues signals a consolidation of hegemony
they operate to contribute to the social construction of that remained an incomplete project under formal co-
rights and to provide the empirical basis for imple- lonialism or even neocolonialism. It may be argued that
menting those rights in the context of locally controlled the restriction to litigation of opposition to the legacy
change. of colonialism testifies to the ultimate victory of colo-
nialism. A concept such as “cultural property rights”
may sharpen disciplinary distinctions over issues of cul-
arif dirlik ture and may provide the plaintiffs with a weapon in the
Department of History, Duke University, Durham. courtroom, but it also further deepens the hegemony.
N.C. 27708, U.S.A. (adirlik@duke.edu). 20 xi 00 A Japan-specialist colleague of mine is fond of observ-
ing that the Japanese could never have a revolution be-
Kirsch’s discussion is important for pointing to a ques- cause it was against the law. The remark is important
tion that goes beyond anthropology in its implications: for considering issues of politics in the contemporary
the importance of politics even as the political is inter- world, where it has become nearly impossible to con-
pellated into the juridical. If this question is to receive ceive of radical options because such options are indeed
the attention that it deserves, it is important not to dis- against “the law”—which, although it is a systematic
solve it into abstract disciplinary problems of culture product of modern capitalism and nationalism and there-
such as cultural universalism or relativism and essen- fore founded upon Euro-American cultural norms, is
182 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

transnationalized with universal claims as the regime of the same.” The interesting thing about the notion of the
modernity is globalized. It would obviously be counter- “expert” is that what distinguishes one expert from an-
productive for Marshall Islanders to walk into a court- other is technical problems of sources and interpretation
room to declare their opposition to such laws and pro- rather than politics—which involves ideologies of cul-
cedures on the grounds that they were culture- or ture and property as well. If I may take issue with Kirsch,
system-bound or that they represented a more refined “the debate between the two anthropologists (Carucci
form of colonialism. They would simply be abandoning and Pollock, who were involved in this court case)” that
their hopes for compensation—or even recognition. The he describes “hinges” not just on “competing views of
legally unthinkable also sets limits on what is politically culture” but also on two different political sympathies
thinkable. That is what hegemony is about. This total- and appreciations of culture. This may well be the reason
ization of hegemony may also provide a clue to why that they never made “their positions on the subject ex-
opposition to Euro-American hegemony is so often ex- plicit,” politics obviously being inadmissible as a sup-
pressed in the language of fundamentalist essentialism. porting argument in a court of law. Pollock in this de-
This is not just a problem for the Marshall Islanders scription appears as an academic who makes oppor-
or the formerly or currently colonized. Ours seems to be tunistic use of facile analogies to justify old-fashioned
an age of reparations. What is important is that whereas colonialist arguments. However, the more liberal argu-
in the past the legacies of slavery, colonialism, Nazi ments of Carucci and Kirsch, unable to deviate from the
atrocities, the internment of (Japanese) American citi- restrictions of the law and making a political case of the
zens, genocide of indigenous peoples (including through whole issue, are possibly more revealing of the workings
nuclear radiation), etc., produced political oppositions of power in our times, since they are no more willing to
calling for systemic changes to prevent their recurrence, challenge the value of “expert” testimony.
they now appear as court cases demanding recompense Kirsch’s account is reminiscent of the story that when
for past wrongs—on the assumption that these are indeed Columbus landed in Hispaniola he read to the natives a
past wrongs that an improved present can provide com- proclamation in Spanish of his takeover of the lands in-
pensation for. It is not very clear what we are to do with dicated in the name of the majesties who had sponsored
the memories and legacies of these past wrongs once they his conquest, to which the natives are supposed to have
have been settled in court. Of more immediate concern nodded in happy assent. The Marshall Islanders are not
is their relegation to the past when, in some cases, as in the inhabitants of 15th-century Hispaniola, which
the case of the Marshall Islanders, they may represent makes their case more disturbing; in their case, the sub-
not the end but the final victory of colonialism. jection to a legal procedure that is the product of a Euro-
This is what I mean by the interpellation of political American capitalist definition of rights and property is
into legal questions. Common to all such litigation is an an assent not to an incomprehensible language but to a
assumption that any deviation from liberal norms of pol- painfully familiar one that, however it may undermine
itics is punishable by law, which means, in effect, no native practices, must now be accepted as the only lan-
politics outside that which is specified in the legal pro- guage in which dissent can be expressed. It is the con-
cedures of the neoliberal state. The Marshall Islanders quest of culture and politics by a juridical language
deserve all the help they can get, but the particular route which no longer recognizes an outside to its domain.
they follow through the courts itself indicates helpless- What we need to keep reminding ourselves is that jurid-
ness before a world of domination that cannot be chal- ical language itself is founded upon political and cultural
lenged for what it is, if not dissolution into its hegemony. assumptions—which may at least caution against the
The second aspect of the question is the assumption reduction of political questions to technical or discipli-
that claims to cultural authenticity in a case such as this nary ones. Kirsch’s essay does not raise this question,
one may be authenticated by expert testimony, which is but it provokes the thought.
further evidence of the extent to which colonial practices
persist, armed by postcolonial arguments against cul-
tural authenticity. Depoliticization of the issues at hand virginia dominguez
is at work in the very notion of “expert” testimony. But Department of Anthropology, University of Iowa,
knowing what we do about past collusion between co- Iowa City, Iowa 52242-1322 (virginia-dominguez@
lonialism and anthropology, we need to inquire whether uiowa.edu). 24 xi 00
such depoliticization serves to disguise a continuing re-
lationship between them, especially where the anthro- Kirsch grounds his argument for the usefulness of the
pologist’s testimony is given priority over the self-images concept of “cultural property rights” in its ability “to
of the natives—as if only the natives’ memories were identify the referents of indigenous discourse about cul-
subject to constructedness and not the anthropologists’ ture loss.” Using the records of a legal tribunal that has
scholarship. The issue here is not the privileging of na- struggled to make sense of particular indigenous claims
tive self-images or some multiculturalist relativism but to “culture loss,” he explores “several examples of loss
rather a need to question the priority given to so-called experienced by the Marshallese as a result of damage to
scientific expert testimony. their land and prolonged exile from their home atolls”
The account that Kirsch offers is testimony to the old against the challenge of working within a legal frame-
adage that “the more things change, the more they stay work. While I can imagine responses to this essay that
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 183

focus understandably on the pros and cons of translating and strategic.” Something very specific is being said even
the broader issue into a language of legal rights, I think when the reference to culture makes it seem diffuse.
it is the concept of “culture loss” itself that Kirsch wants I am, however, interested in extensions that Kirsch
us, the anthropological community, to discuss—at least implies but does not elaborate on. I am thinking of “cul-
in part because so many of us shape our professional ture loss” as an object of public discourse and even of
work in terms of a concept of culture and are called upon legal discourse in settings not involving indigenous
to serve as expert witnesses for competing sides. groups or other underempowered communities experi-
My own response focuses on a question I find myself encing serious population decline. What is its sociolog-
asking: When is a loss “cultural”? Or to reframe it, what ical topography? Has it indeed spread beyond indigenous
is it that leads particular people to call some losses “cul- communities, or has it now become so closely associated
ture losses”? Clearly, this happens in a minority of cases with indigenous movements that we fail to see its “cous-
and, I suspect, in a minority of places or communities. ins” elsewhere? When French cultural and political
People experience loss all too often, but they rarely call elites, for example, take actions to protect “French cul-
it “culture loss” or label what they have lost their “cul- ture” from linguistic and other “intrusions,” many an-
tural property.” Much of the time we lose something thropologists roll their eyes in mild amusement, but
that matters little or matters a lot for a short period of aren’t these actions, in fact, paralleling indigenous
time—a bet or a set of keys or even a credit card. It may claims in more ways than all may want to recognize?
be inconvenient, even worrisome, but rarely is it life- We do tend to react differently on the basis of our
changing. People also lose loved ones to disease or tendency to champion the causes of underempowered
through accidents, forced displacement, and family groups and to critique structural, symbolic, and physical
breakups. Rarely do I hear these called “culture losses,” forms of violence. The point is evident here as well.
though the loss is often intense and long-lasting. It is When “culture loss” (or fear of it) is invoked by people
true that an anthropologist might be moved to label a with the social, political, and economic power to affect
particular response to loss cultural, but the point is that millions of lives, I doubt that many of us would struggle
people experiencing loss rarely see it as “culture loss.” to choose a side in a legal dispute the way we do now
It is personal. It may be a serious blow to a family or when we confront the dilemma of how to respond when
even a self-identified community, but it isn’t “culture it is invoked as a strategy for recognition (or even com-
loss.” pensation) by others. Kirsch’s notion of cultural property
Calling a loss cultural clearly signals something rights can, indeed, sharpen our eye here. A powerful so-
else—something of different dimensions, more akin to cial group proclaiming the need to prevent “culture loss”
devastation or group extinction. The phrase names a feel- may claim exclusive rights to many things as its “cul-
ing, a fear, a sadness—even though it is easy to hear it tural property”—and the impact is not on hundreds or
as a legal neologism introduced in court battles today to thousands but on millions or billions.
gain both additional compensation and the high moral
ground. I think its paradox is that in court battles it can
easily be undermined because both inside and outside a r t u ro e s c o b a r
anthropology people use the term “culture” to mean sig- Department of Anthropology, University of North
nificantly different things, thereby leaving judges and Carolina, Chapel Hill, N.C. 27514, U.S.A.
jurors with no clear referent, whereas outside the court- (aescobar@imap.unc.edu). 6 xii 00
room it may evoke much more sympathy and enlist
many more supporters precisely because so many people Kirsch’s “Lost Worlds” is an intelligent, constructive,
around the world today use some concept of “culture” and courageous intervention in the anthropological de-
and consider it a good thing. Hence, calling a loss “cul- bates on globalization and culture. Behind it there is no
ture loss,” I would think, heightens the possibility of trace of the long-discarded paradigm of salvage anthro-
empathy and through empathy at least some form of pology, nor does this piece reinsert anthropology into the
satisfaction, if not social justice itself. “savage slot” by discussing issues of indigenous cultural
Kirsch is right in suggesting that monetary compen- loss (as, unfortunately, the American Anthropological
sation, though useful, is often not the main goal. Charles Association’s handling of the Neel/Chagnon affair
Taylor would say that the real issue is recognition, and tended to do). On the contrary, Kirsch seeks to return
I would add that it is recognition in two senses: (1) rec- the avant-garde of the discipline to the long-standing is-
ognition of a presence that has often been made invisible sue of culture change that anthropology has skirted for
and (2) recognition of wrongs that need to be acknowl- the past two decades while devoting its best efforts to
edged. Rhetoric matters, but, as Nancy Pollock writes in developing a powerful approach for the study of the pro-
her 1999 report to the Office of the Defender of the Fund, duction of culture under globalization. I think that this
Nuclear Claims Tribunal, quoted by Kirsch, we are not is a theoretical and political project of great importance
talking about a random collection of local groups invok- to the discipline. Anthropologists have seldom shied
ing a notion of “culture loss” but, rather, about contexts away from discussing the political context and impli-
“where the loss was derived from impositions by major cations of their work. In recent years, however, we seem
powers, colonial powers, that exerted their power over to have become enthralled with the very sophistication
minority states to achieve [their] goals, both economic of our analyses—intent on showing in detail the contes-
184 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

tations, impurities, hybridities, and fluidities of culture mentioned. Carucci’s, in contrast, is a more phenome-
and the traveling, border crossings, and diasporas of cul- nological and practice-based conception of culture as em-
tural production—to the extent that our sense of politics bedded in bodies and places and, thus, eminently sus-
has become diluted. That our analyses show that power ceptible of being lost.) What are the political tasks we
is negotiated at every level makes us unsure where we are called upon to assume as experts in these situations,
stand vis-à-vis our subjects. This has been particularly and how do these political tasks relate to subaltern strat-
true in North American anthropology, which has mo- egies for the defense of place and culture or, conversely,
tivated reactions in other parts of the world. Far from to dominant attempts at cultural reconversion?
suggesting that Kirsch’s argument is less complex, what As Kirsch says, loss has become a critical site for the
I mean is that this piece, along with others that want to objectification of culture (one might think in similar
return the discipline to a more engaged approach to is- terms about the loss of biodiversity in relation to nature
sues of cultural politics, proposes an alternative model and culture). The language of loss displays incommen-
and set of concerns for anthropological work. Models of surability of cultural backgrounds and practices (as in
“good work” in anthropology come and go, as in any the example of property developed in the paper); publicly
good normal science. At some level, Kirsch’s paper calls debated contrasting cultural conceptions in turn suggest
on us to pluralize those models once again. the possibility for a pedagogy of alterity in international
We may, for instance, take on again an unfashionable and intercultural negotiations that could be further de-
issue such as “culture loss” and ask what new and per- veloped out of studies such as this one. There is an entire
haps original problems it poses for anthropology, our un- cultural politics at stake in globalization that we need
derstanding of culture, and the world at large. We may to highlight and document ethnographically. I would go
also be less reluctant to investigate who is making claims farther than Kirsch in saying that at issue in the cases
today about “culture” and how. In other words, we may he discusses is not just alternative conceptions of prop-
want to investigate how claims to truth are made in the erty and place but different conceptions and practices of
name of culture outside anthropology in ways that le- nature and the economy. These conceptions may be im-
gitimize particular agendas with which we may or may portant as we think about the defense of place-based
not be in agreement. And we may also take a seat by the worlds and, beyond this, contribute to their re/
side of peoples whose claims to “culture loss” we can construction.
help to conceptualize and defend, perhaps against the
claims of more powerful actors such as judges or even
colleagues on the other side of the fence. Some of these b e n fi n n e y
issues may seem perilously “applied” to some of our Department of Anthropology, University of Hawaii,
more academic-minded colleagues, but this is precisely Honolulu, Hawaii, 96815, U.S.A. (bfinney@hawaii
the point: that in another model the boundaries between .edu). 30 xi 00
“academic” and “applied” and between “knowledge pro-
ducers” (experts/anthropologists) and “users” (local peo- How could anything so seemingly “academic” as culture
ple, social movements) are no longer neatly construed. theory tie anthropologists up in such tangled knots?
What we learn, for instance, is that if we take some Musings about how people invent their cultures may
people’s claims about culture, place, and nature seriously make good sense to theorists but appear insulting, ac-
we need to rethink our by now strongly naturalized con- cusatory, and misinformed to those whose cultures are
ception of change (Kirsch’s main claim); that in this age so labeled. Now anthropologists with opposing cultural
of seemingly inescapable mobility and deterritorializa- readings are clashing in court over whether the Marshall
tion people’s sense of belonging and attachment to place Islanders suffered grievous cultural loss over and above
continue to be important sources of cultural production the fictional market value of their atolls when the U.S.
and mobilized politically to various ends (and there are government blew up their islands and/or saturated them
more and more anthropologists, archaeologists, and ge- with radioactivity.
ographers interested in place); and, finally, that there are Upon returning from the Marshalls to Hawai’i in Oc-
discussions about alternative conceptions of property tober 2000 I discovered Kirsch’s cogent paper in my mail-
and personhood in circles outside of anthropology. In box. Since I had gone to the Marshalls to discuss with
other words, there is a complex cultural politics around the Bikini Council a project to revive ancient ways of
contested notions of person, nature, property, subsis- navigating, I was jolted to discover from the paper that
tence, and place that we would do well to incorporate the significance of the decline of canoe voyaging had
into our own studies and take a position on. And as the been contested in expert testimony given by a pair of
example of anthropologists Pollock and Carucci dem- anthropologists before the Nuclear Claims Tribunal. In
onstrate, these positions can be quite different, which my discussions with Bikini Council members they had
goes to show that our conceptions of culture count. (I do bitterly charged that their forced exile from Bikini Atoll
not think, however, that Pollock’s conception of culture to Kili, a lone coral rock without a central lagoon or
is necessarily essentialist. Rather, it is a narrower un- sheltered beaches for launching and landing canoes, had
derstanding of culture as things people hold in their condemned their children and their children’s children
minds, which lends itself to being thought about as end- to a life without canoes and skills in ocean sailing and
lessly transformed in the manner of the works I have navigation, seafarers no more. In testifying before the
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 185

Nuclear Claims Tribunal, the anthropologist Laurence Marshallese to revive it in all its former glory. However,
Carucci had made virtually the same point concerning such a program should not be developed as a sop to divert
the exile of the Enewetak people from their atoll to an- attention from all that needs to be done to make these
other, less well endowed one and their consequent loss islands livable again and their people whole. If the Ha-
of seafaring skills. Yet Kirsch tells us that Carucci’s fel- waiian experience is any guide, a voyaging revival could
low anthropologist Nancy Pollock denied this loss under contribute to the realization of these larger goals. Though
cross-examination by the Enewetak attorney. Instead, not overtly political, the Hawaiian revival of voyaging
she stressed that such cultural knowledge never totally has played a key role in the current sovereignty move-
disappears and cited the recent revival of canoes and voy- ment and the uneven progress the Hawaiians have been
aging elsewhere in the Pacific as a supporting example. making. The pride gained by re-creating their canoes and
As someone who has been working in East Polynesia methods of wayfinding has encouraged young Hawaiians
over the past four decades to revive ancient voyaging to challenge their de facto status as a subjected minority
canoes and skills and test these over long sea routes and in their own islands and to work together for common
has witnessed the tremendous cultural impact of this goals.
effort, it seems apparent to me that the Marshallese have
suffered a grievous cultural loss of seafaring skills
(among others) and along with that a vital part of their tamara giles-vernick
former identity as seafaring farmers and fishers. But it Department of History, University of Virginia,
also seems possible that they may be able to recover Charlottesville, Va. 22903, U.S.A. (tg2y@virginia.edu).
some of that loss with positive cultural and social effect. 21 xi 00
That the revival of voyaging could be cited to deny cul-
tural loss has never occurred to me and my colleagues Kirsch has made an important, compelling, and impas-
in Hawai’i, Tahiti, the Cook Islands, and Aotearoa. Voy- sioned argument about culture, property rights, loss, and
aging canoes and their navigators had disappeared from compensation in the context of environmental disasters.
East Polynesian seas long before we started. Using eth- He seeks to elaborate a concept of culture that allows
nohistorical and ethnographic sources, and with the help us to “recognize change while simultaneously acknowl-
of the master navigator Mau Piailug (from Satawal Atoll, edging loss” by accounting for notions of property as
Federated States of Micronesia), we set out to re-create rights in things, people, knowledge, and places. I admire
the old sailing canoes and ways of navigating as well as Kirsch’s quest for a legally defensible definition that will
we could, recognizing that because of the discontinuity compel courts to compensate people in the Marshall Is-
with the old Polynesian masters some skills and tech- lands, who have suffered horrendous, incalculable losses
niques might well be lost forever. In this respect the from nuclear testing in the 1940s and ’50s. I also believe
Marshallese are in a somewhat better position than the that his reconceptualization of culture can be useful in
Hawaiians and other East Polynesians. As recently as the some contexts, but because he shelters particular con-
1960s some of them were still sailing their large deep- cepts and relations from historical change his argument
sea outrigger canoes (walap), and although these fell out may not have the wide applicability that he seeks. In
of use soon thereafter this loss has been recent enough order to strengthen his formulation, he needs to account
that there are still some aged masters alive today who for the historical processes by which people produce, de-
once built, sailed, and navigated them. Over the past bate, and give meaning to categories of “indigeneity,”
dozen years Dennis Alessio, Alson Kelen, and others of “local knowledge,” and “loss.”
the organization Waan Aelan in Majel (Canoes of the Kirsch takes the meaning of “indigeneity” to be self-
Marshall Islands) have been taking advantage of this sit- evident. “Indigenous” people may be easy to identify in
uation by having these living treasures work with Mar- the Marshall Islands, but elsewhere this category has
shallese youths, teaching them as together they build been profoundly shaped by historical (and political) pro-
and sail these magnificent canoes. cesses. In Africa, for instance, the meaning of “indige-
Lack of regular funding, spells of official indifference, nousness” has varied substantially over time and space
and a loss of confidence on the part of some Marshallese and has most often been constructed against other cat-
in their ability to build, sail, and navigate their tradi- egories of people—not simply Western scientists but also
tional canoes has made progress slow. However, a num- geographically mobile agricultural, urban, or “modern”
ber of canoes have been built, and the vanguard of a new people. The historical creation of “indigenous peoples”
generation is now beginning to sail again. The next in some parts of West, Central, and Southern Africa has
step—before the last of the old navigators pass away—is relied on arbitrarily delineated spatial and temporal
to revive the unique Marshallese system of navigating boundaries that fail to account for the long-term, wide-
from island to island by reading the way the deep ocean spread geographical mobility of all populations (Richards
swells are deformed as they pass around and between the 1996, Giles-Vernick 1999, Crapanzano 1985). And the
atolls. purposes of imposing or claiming indigenousness have
Rather than argue over the extent and meaning of the varied, from building state power to claiming or allo-
Marshallese loss of voyaging, let us admit that this key cating rights to particular resources (Giles-Vernick 1999).
technology has been endangered to the point of extinc- In various African countries, some groups of Africans
tion and consider that just compensation would help the have self-consciously adopted the label “indigenous” as
186 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

part of a political effort to gain special rights and pro- measure mutation rates and other responses to radiation
tections from African states (Peters 1996, Hitchcock (pp. 297–300). Kirsch similarly draws attention to the
1994). Historical change, then, can render the exercise way in which the Marshall Islanders have been used as
of identifying “indigenous people” a treacherous one. guinea pigs in radiation research.
As a way of rethinking cultural loss, Kirsch employs There are many issues at stake here, but let us con-
the concept of cultural property, arguing that ways of centrate on the questions Kirsch raises for discussion.
knowing, subsistence production, and a sense of place How can peoples like those of Rongelap Atoll be com-
are about both belonging and possession. Here he makes pensated for the sufferings and loss caused by nuclear
some especially convincing contributions, but I do won- tests or other “environmental disasters”? (I put “envi-
der about his insistence on sheltering certain features of ronmental disasters” in quotation marks to indicate that
“local” or “indigenous” knowledge from historical the term is somewhat problematic and could perhaps
change (see also Sahlins 1999). Such knowledge can gain from a bit of unpacking.) How should their suffering
change not only in its content but in its epistemologies. be measured or valued? Does displacement or loss of land
There is ample evidence that people can appropriate both also imply loss of culture? And, finally, what have an-
practices and ways of perceiving and thinking about thropology and anthropologists to offer in cases like this?
themselves, their cosmologies, and their environmental Kirsch addresses these questions in relation to court
relations. Michelle Kisliuk’s (1998) study of BaAka (so- cases in which compensation claims have been raised by
called pygmy) performance in the Central African Re- indigenous peoples and anthropologists are engaged as
public shows that these forest dwellers have appropriated expert witnesses both for and against the recognition of
from outsiders not only knowledge but also ways of see- such claims. He suggests that by focusing on “cultural
ing the world. Ajay Skaria’s (1999) environmental history property rights” one can identify losses which otherwise
of the Dangs in western India reveals that forest-dwelling might be “obscured or ignored” and that by examining
communities’ engagement with British colonial agents indigenous discourses on cultural loss we (anthropolo-
produced profoundly altered ways of understanding gists) can “gain new understandings of property.”
themselves, their political power, and their Cultural and intellectual property rights have become
environments. important sites for indigenous struggles, and Kirsch’s ar-
Finally, it would be useful for Kirsch to interrogate ticle does help us think about these complex issues. Even
further the concept of loss in a broader range of social so, I am not fully convinced by his argument. First,
and historical contexts. “Loss” can have a multitude of whereas he presents his article as an engagement with
meanings, can pervade a wide range of historical narra- cultural loss as an indigenous discourse, in fact he
tives, and can be associated with highly conservative mainly discusses anthropologists debating cultural loss.
nostalgia for mythical origins and unity (Chakrabarty Anthropologists may have theoretical difficulties in an-
1992, Skaria 1999, Giles-Vernick 2000). A more fully alyzing cultural loss “given contemporary definitions of
elaborated and historicized concept of loss might permit culture as a process,” but this is a completely different
us to distinguish the destruction of cultural property matter from whether indigenous communities objectify
about which Kirsch writes from a nostalgia that per- culture and describe their predicament as that of culture
meates wide-ranging narratives about the past. loss. It seems to be the institutional setup of the Nuclear
Kirsch’s essay takes important steps toward develop- Claims Tribunal itself that makes cultural loss an issue
ing a more legally useful definition of culture, but em- of central importance. That “Marshallese claims about
bracing rather than selectively shying away from his- cultural loss are influenced (my emphasis) by the legal
torical change would make his contributions even more and political processes” certainly seems an understate-
compelling in parts of the world where we cannot accept ment. But, again, as we lack indigenous voices, it is hard
so much at face value. to tell how the Marshallese see things. In the quotation
from an interview with a man relocated from the Ron-
gelap Atoll, it is the loss of freedom and economic self-
b. g. karlsson reliance that concerns him, and the poem from New
South Asia Language and Area Center, University of Guinea with which the article opens speaks of loss of
Chicago, Chicago, Ill. 60637, U.S.A. (beppe.karlson@ land and all that they could grow on it or extract from
uland.uu.se). 25 xi 00 it (fish and prawns from the river, wild game, etc.).
Secondly, is the idea of “cultural property rights” really
Kirsch’s interrogation of the legal aftermath of the U.S. the best that anthropology can come up with for assign-
nuclear tests in the Marshall Islands and related cases of ing value to that which cannot (easily) be translated into
displacement of indigenous peoples is most welcome and a market value/price? Here I would insist on the question
opens up a series of questions of the greatest importance. that Kirsch raises towards the end of the article—why
The tests are part of a chilling story of U.S nuclear im- the Marshallese losses “should be framed in terms of
perialism. One of the charges in Tierney’s (2000) Dark- property models at all.” Expanding the notion of property
ness in El Dorado is that the U.S. Atomic Energy Com- might indeed be a way of working the “system” in favor
mission, which funded Chagnon’s research, used the of marginalized groups, and, to be sure, compensation
Yanomami Indians as a control group in research in claims by indigenous peoples are always articulated in
which people were injected with radioactive iodine to situations of domination. But in the Marshallese case I
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 187

think that more is lost than gained by such a move. structions” as a way of trying to gain recognition for
Kirsch was appointed as adviser to the Public Advocate’s forms of relations which exist or once existed outside of
office, which was required to determine appropriate com- them.
pensation levels, to examine how land was valued by the Kirsch argues that we must re-embed the events of
people of Rongelap. I suppose that he wanted to find a loss and damage in the context of social relations in order
way to help them strike as fair a deal as possible at the to reduce their scale and slow them sufficiently to carry
tribunal. But rather than translating their profound sense out analyses which will allow relativization. To that end
of loss into the language of property, an alternative po- he examines subsistence production, place, and local
litical strategy of the concerned anthropologist might be knowledge. But when we seek to argue the judiciability
to keep insisting on the inalienability of land and to and compensability of impacts, questions arise with re-
provide a thick ethnography of how this loss is experi- gard to their immediacy and longer-term temporality, as
enced and expressed. This together with further inves- well as their greater and lesser scale and specificity of
tigations into the gross human rights violations caused effect, that begin to suggest considerations of degree and
by the nuclear test program and advocacy for a new type call into question notions of cultural formations as “in-
of tribunal focusing on Marshallese grievances rather tegral” in the conjuncture. There can seemingly be few
than nonexistent market values would probably have impacts as immediate and radical as the bomb blasts
been a more effective use of anthropological authority. visited upon the unknowing Marshallese. One wonders
In the end, it is the people of Rongelap themselves who at the kind of argument made by Pollock for the “con-
ought to be listened to. tinuity of culture” in view of the scale and immediacy
of impacts for those directly affected, in circumstances
in which any capacity they may have had to act was
francesca merlan rendered irrelevant by being radically disabled. The for-
School of Archaeology and Anthropology, Australian mulation of “culture” here as “embedded in the mind
National University, Canberra 0200, Australia. and heart” and thus beyond the reach of immediate cir-
(francesca.merlan@anu.edu.au). 16 xi 00 cumstantial change appears to have been appropriated to
an interested language and logic of the struggle in which
Kirsch’s thematically rich paper is explicit about the so- the assessment of impact was being worked through. Yet
cial-justice impulse underlying the project of relativi-
we find that in relation to much longer-term processes
zation he advocates. Definitions of culture in terms of
of articulation, for example, of Fourth World peoples
capacity for continuous change obscure the visibility of
within dominant societies, Sahlins also argues for an es-
loss and damage, he argues. Contemporary arbiters need
sential continuity of a cultural formation in the notion
to be provided the tools for analysis of loss and the de-
of the “indigenization of modernity.” Similar kinds of
livery of social justice; ways need to be found to put the
arguments have been made, for example, in some Aus-
interests of disparate societies into relation. Understand-
tralian land claims cases, where successful outcomes
ings in terms of “cultural property” make relativization
have depended upon demonstration of some kind or de-
possible. In Kirsch’s account, the designation “cultural”
seems to mark difference, that which remains incom- gree of continuity in the case of apparent change. But all
mensurable, and “property” the basis for commensura- those participating in such processes are aware of aspects
bility. “Loss” in this context refers to those aspects of of social life that such formulations keep beyond the
relations, concepts, and operations that drop out of the immediate field of vision, however these are to be ana-
cultural system to which they have belonged. lysed. In contrast, the Marshall Islands Nuclear Claims
Placing evidence of damage and loss from other cul- Tribunal has required people to demonstrate loss and
tures in relation to Western models of property brings to rupture, and culture here appears as the object of assault.
light paradoxical connections between the authorita- Although these arguments differ in some ways and are
tiveness and the historical constructedness of the latter. deployed in different circumstances, what they share is
Western property notions are a part of the broader system some kind of integral notion of “culture” as more than
of uneven development and unequal distributions of re- the sum of concepts, relations, and practices—as an en-
sources and power to which the disadvantaged (both tity that these together constitute. What is needed is
within the West and between it and other recognizable concepts that do not obscure what changes, what is lost
sections of the world) now appeal for the resolution of or damaged, but also enable us to theorize more ade-
issues of loss and damage. At the same time, the con- quately than this cultural holism does the role of con-
frontation helps to make visible the extent to which ster- tinuity and change in the ongoing social and imaginative
eotypical Western economistic understandings of prop- life of the people involved.
erty arise from centuries-long processes of subordination In other words, the realization of Kirsch’s project will
of human lifeways to various forms of objectification and have more than one kind of practical implication and
regulation (e.g., to the market [Polanyi 1944] and the outcome. It will show ways in which people’s lives have
historical constitution of law [Baker 1971]) and thus the been more and less drastically affected, but it will also
extent to which such understandings are susceptible to contribute to the deconstruction of cultures as holistic
deconstruction. There is nevertheless some irony in the entities in terms of which such assessments can be
appeal to institutions built upon such “cultural con- made.
188 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

alcida rita ramos Anthropological Association signed an agreement with


Departamento de Antropologia, Universidade de the Attorney General’s Office in the 1980s for the official
Brasilia, Campus Universitario Darcy Ribeiro, Asa appointment of experienced professionals to specific
Norte, ICC Centro, Sobreloja, B1-347, 70.910-900 cases. Even so, ignoring this agreement, now and again
Brasilia, D.F., Brazil. (arramos@unb.br). 17 xi 00 unqualified people are hired as experts to testify on be-
half of local political or economic interests to the det-
Ironic as it may seem, it is comforting to see the thorny riment of indigenous rights. When such actions are not
issue of anthropologists as expert witnesses come to the denounced in time, irreparable damage can be done to
fore, and I congratulate the author for this rare occasion native peoples.
and for his treatment at once unbiased and committed. Central to Kirsch’s concerns seem to be the conse-
His careful analytical response to the events he describes quences of anthropology in its applied and implicated
matches the severity of the suffering imposed upon na- undertakings (Albert 1995). While the former points to
tive peoples by fits of absentmindedness on the part of the unequal power between providers and receivers of
world powers. The careful unfolding of cases and con- aid, the latter points to the inevitable ethical obligation
cepts is far more effective for our ethical sensibility than inherent in anthropological work. While in some na-
the familiar denuciatory style. Particularly felicitous is tional contexts commitment to indigenous causes is a
his focus on loss to highlight cultural property rights. matter of individual choice, often sneered at by one’s
Equally fecund is his association of possession with be- peers, in other settings the professional community ex-
longing and property with knowledge as analytical tools horts anthropologists to assume their role as political
to counteract the Western ethnocentrism that is still actors (Ramos 2000). But the disposition to act as expert
firmly moored despite the century-old doctrine of cul- witness is one thing and being sufficiently fluent in legal
tural relativism. discourse to be effective is another (Dallari 1994, Oliveira
But although analytical density and ethnographic 1994). An emotion-laden report often jeopardizes the de-
depth are necessary they are not always sufficient con- fense of indigenous rights because it diverges from the
ditions for furthering the cause of interethnic justice. forensic principle of impartiality (Gonçalves 1994). Emo-
Ethnographic knowledge is often reduced to impenetra- tional detachment, ethical commitment, and analytical
ble jargon, incomprehensible renditions of strange cus- depth are not easy to combine. If one of these ingredients
toms, or cursory generalities. The capacity to turn de- is missing, the outcomes may be similar for different
tailed ethnographic knowledge into legal evidence is reasons: a judge may reject overtly pro-indigenous bias,
seriously undermined when generic notions about the may interpret ethical indifference to mean desirable im-
locus of culture win the battle as in the Exxon Valdez partiality, or may be unimpressed with a shallow report.
and, especially, the Marshallese case. In both situations, In any case, the burden of the anthropologist’s inade-
the imbalance of power is so great that it allows the quacy falls on the native people who are the object of
accused’s defense to question the legitimacy of the plain- legal argumentation. Kirsch’s article clearly confirms
tiffs’ grievances in the face of manifest crimes. The right this predicament.
to cultural difference is called into question under the
guise of universalist justice. Such cases drive home the
disquieting realization of how often native peoples are l a w r e n c e ro s e n
at the mercy of the rhetorical virtuosity of anthropolo- Department of Anthropology, Princeton University,
gists and how often their own voices are covered over Princeton, N.J. 08544, U.S.A. 10 xi 00
by those of their surrogate experts.
Concepts such as culture are potential weapons in po- When one sets out to construct a legal remedy, several
litical and legal disputes, confirming once again the often very careful distinctions need to be drawn. One must,
obscured fact that anthropology is not a neutral enter- for example, specify the harm that is to be avoided or
prise. To reinforce this sober lesson one might invoke compensated, the theoretical grounds on which the rem-
the delayed effect of Radcliffe-Brown’s seemingly inno- edy is to be constructed or analogized, and the rationale
cent concept of the local descent group as it was applied upon which compensation is to be regarded as making
to Australian Aborigines. Decades after Radcliffe-Brown up, in whatever material or inchoate way, for the loss
coined the term, Australian courts were using it as a incurred.
criterion for granting land to Aborigines. Claims that In the case of an indigenous group’s loss of habitat or
could not be proved authentic by displaying local descent way of life, several theories for compensation suggest
groups would not be contemplated (Meyers 1986a:147). themselves. The loss may be analogized to a property
Although the participation of anthropologists in legal interest, the idea of what constitutes “property” being
cases is not new (Rosen 1977, Meyers 1986b), serious extended well beyond its prior range of examples. Before
discussion of the professional, ethical, and political im- the invention of the water mill Europeans did not con-
plications of being an expert witness is surprisingly ceive of water as capable of being owned, and hence it
scarce. In some American countries with permanent are- lacked compensable property interest. Nowadays, such
nas of interethnic conflict the requirement of anthro- unusual items as frozen sperm, the air around oneself,
pological witnesses in legal cases has been insti- or one’s “zone of personal privacy” may be regarded as
tutionalized. In Brazil, for instance, the Brazilian forms of property. Kirsch rightly regards the loss of a
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 189

group’s territory and even its way of life as a kind of by force, just as one may then be able to include in the
property and even suggests that the knowledge they have compensable the knowledge that made that life mean-
relating to their specific adaptation is a kind of property ingful (see Coombe 1998). In no case will financial com-
interest. But while this analogy, like others in Western pensation replace the loss, but the logic of the theory
legal history, is logically supportable, it may not consti- may permit the extension of remedies beyond the mon-
tute the best ground for righting the asserted wrong. etary that a simple reliance on property concepts alone
First, it is unclear whether all aspects of a people’s may fail to address. The result could be, at both the
culture are equally valuable or by what criteria—to say theoretical and practical levels, a more realistic and cre-
nothing of by what agency—that shall be determined. ative appreciation of the needs and entitlements of those
One does not want to have to argue that, having lost the deprived of that which made their world make sense.
opportunity to take the heads of their enemies, a group
should receive compensation for loss of knowledge and
culture. Similarly, situations of clear destruction, inten- madhavi sunder
tional or not, by outsiders must be distinguished from University of California Davis School of Law, Davis,
loss that arises from competitive pressures. Kirsch’s ex- Calif. 95616, U.S.A. (msunder@ucdavis.edu). 22 xi 00
amples from the Marshall Islands or the loss of a limb
that could not otherwise be sold may lead to logical dif- New arguments for property rights in culture face an
ficulties for the very situation one hopes to assuage; there uphill battle in today’s academy and in courts, both of
are cases of overt destruction or losses that could never which are more receptive to postmodern theories of prop-
be converted to a sale, and therefore both their nature erty and culture. In the law schools, property professors
and their valuation become extremely problematic. have deconstructed traditional property theories to re-
Moreover, one cannot both assert that the loss is capable veal a fundamental paradox: while an important justi-
of valuation and deny the applicability of market mech- fication for property rights is that land and personal ob-
anisms without undercutting one’s ultimate goal of com- jects can be integral to our personalities, the paramount
pensating indigenous peoples for their losses. In short, right to transfer our property in market exchanges en-
for all its intellectual and moral appeal, the idea of courages us to alienate that property which is most es-
knowledge as property is supportable only if the mech- sential to us and harm our personhood in the process
anisms for its assessment are addressed with adequate (Radin 1982). This insight suggests that property rights
conceptual rigor. And if one is to make a claim to com- in culture may be counterproductive because they would
pensation for loss of knowledge, a far more rigorous ar- encourage the alienation, not the preservation, of
gument will have to be made than the assertion, so res- culture.
onant among many anthropologists but so lacking in real Intellectual property professors, too, would be wary of
content, that the situation of indigenous communities proposals for creating new property rights in culture (e.g.,
is distinctive because of “the way these societies organ- intellectual property rights in local knowledge held by
ize and reproduce themselves.” indigenous peoples), bemoaning such proposals as yet
A more useful argument might be constructed not in another step toward the enclosure of our public com-
terms of property law but in terms of the law of torts. mons and the propertization of knowledge and ideas his-
Tort law is about injury—harm—rather than loss of the torically held in the public domain (Benkler 1999, Lem-
corporeal alone, and it has the advantage of long expe- ley 1999, Lessig 1999). Postmodern intellectual property
rience in acknowledging that the immaterial has genuine scholars might further argue that justifying intellectual
value for both its uniqueness and its meaningfulness. property rights on theories of authorship—here, the
Thus, in both the common and the civil law concepts claim would be that cultural groups create their own
have been developed for compensating emotional harm stories, knowledge, symbols, and songs and thus should
or various forms of pain and suffering that are beyond have exclusive rights to these cultural arti-
medical calculation. In each instance one must begin facts—romanticizes creativity as spawned by isolated
with a theory of what is compensable and why, just as genius and fails to recognize that cultural creation is in
one must build analogies for new kinds of property in- fact a dialectical process that involves interaction be-
terests. Here it may be well to think carefully about the tween cultures (Boyle 1996; cf. Coombe 1993).
idea of cultural integrity as an interest which, if inten- Outside of law, as Kirsch points out, postmodern an-
tionally harmed, may be compensable (see Rosen 1991). thropologists and cultural studies theorists have unwit-
Difficulties may still arise. Will the simple loss of a way tingly erected their own barriers to cultural property
of life to a superior technology be regarded as harm? claims by complicating traditional definitions of culture
Probably not, since the loss of a horseman’s way of life itself. Postmodern definitions of culture as something
to the culture of the automobile, for example, may be that travels and transforms without necessarily being
no different from that which affects native groups in the lost or destroyed (Clifford 1997, 1988) pose serious prob-
face of competition. And the fact that competition is lems for cultural property rights claims in court, which
seldom worked out on a “level playing field” demon- rely heavily on the expert testimony of anthropologists.
strates how hard it would be to apply such a concept. Ironically, the problem is not that courts are unable to
But one may well be able to sustain a logical argument understand postmodern theories of culture but rather
in tort for loss of a way of life when it has been taken that in accepting anthropologists’ antiessentialist anal-
190 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

yses of culture courts conclude that cultural change is Exxon Valdez disaster illustrates. In the end, if we as-
natural and inevitable and, therefore, not appropriately sume that a subjective evaluation of the harm of culture
redressed through property rights or damages for cultural loss is higher than an objective, free-market evaluation
loss. Claims that particular cultures are connected to of that harm, then a property rule would seem to create
particular places are similarly challenged by postmodern stronger incentives to avoid such harms. That said, any
theories, such as diaspora theory, which view culture and remedy based on property approaches would have to ad-
place as distinct. dress its potential negative consequences, including
In describing courts’ reluctance to recognize “culture problems of commodification (Radin 1982) and conflict
loss” because it is “attenuated and ethereal,” Kirsch’s within cultural groups over who owns the culture (Sun-
analysis is not unlike traditional critiques of the law’s der 2000).
inadequacies in addressing intangible harms, such as the Revealing the relationship between property and post-
harms of sexual harassment. But Kirsch goes farther, modernism helps us understand how, despite the best of
highlighting how theories from the left, which I classify intentions, the postmodern lawyer, collaborating with
here as “postmodern,” are also to blame for the failure the postmodern anthropologist, might leave minority
of courts to recognize the problem of culture loss. cultures at the mercy of the forces of commerce and
Though unstated, embedded in Kirsch’s argument is a colonialism.
critique of postmodernism itself: that postmodernism’s
deconstructing theories fail to recognize real harm and
real loss. In response to this problem, he proposes that edith turner
cultural property rights “can be used to address this crit- Department of Anthropology, University of Virginia,
ical blind spot of the culture concept” by making “visible Charlottesville, Va. 22903, U.S.A. (elt9w@virginia
the losses experienced by indigenous communities,” spe- .edu). 14 xi 00
cifically, the loss of “knowledge, ideas, and practices of
local value.” His thesis is compelling: that the property The key to Kirsch’s essay is that the claim of the Mar-
concept can help us to understand culture in a more shall Islanders in the matter of culture loss has been
complex way—namely, as both ethereal and real. overridden in the courts. This is the pivot on which turns
I am not so sure that the property concept alone will an immense philosophical issue. What are things, prop-
do all the work of helping us to recognize the complex erty? Is the positivist assessment of what a thing is to
nature of culture, but I do think that Kirsch’s critique of be considered absolute? Is tribal history or culture not a
postmodernists’ easy acceptance of cultural change, thing? What does the world actually think about Amer-
without concern for the causes of change, is important. ican property law? Has the U.S. legal system painted
Admittedly, in today’s world it is increasingly difficult itself into a corner, and has its service to the big cor-
to distinguish what cultural changes are part and parcel porations separated it from credibility in the eyes of hu-
of modernity and what changes are spurred by a culture man beings as human beings? Kirsch pointed out that
falling prey to cultural imperialism (Sunder 2000). That the way to convince the public and the judges in such
said, I think that Kirsch is right that we need not throw cases is with particulars—the particulars of the natural-
out the baby with the bathwater. If what concerns cul- cum-cultural need of the unfortunate exiled islanders
tural property rights critics most is that property rights and their loss of opportunity to fulfil that need. The nat-
would restrict the free flow of information, ideas, and ural and cultural needs can in no wise be separated.
culture within and between cultures, this concern does Here I want to insert some personal history that con-
not rule out the possibility of designing law that would firms what Kirsch describes more generally. In 1958 in
narrowly address the problem of unnatural cultural Manchester, England, where I was living with my family,
changes coerced by external forces (e.g., oil spills, nuclear there occurred what is now termed the Sellafield disas-
weapons tests, or language restrictions). ter, in which an experimental atomic pile about 11 miles
On the important issue of “why property?”—rather from the city leaked radioactivity. At the time, the Brit-
than, say, a tort claim—to protect culture, a quick review ish government announced with great assurance that the
of the differences in legal remedies may be useful. A tort danger was very slight. In 1959 I gave birth to a Down’s-
claim for culture loss would require the person who syndrome baby, Lucy, who died after five months. This
causes that loss to pay damages equal to the fair market event, of course, affected my husband, Victor Turner, and
value of the loss (with the possibility of punitive dam- me deeply. I had no idea that the baby’s death was caused
ages). In contrast to a tort claim, a property right would by radioactivity and felt that there was something wrong
present the option of allocating damages based on the with me, and for years I undervalued myself.
subjective value of the property, which, as Kirsch points In 1987 I spend a year in Point Hope, Alaska, studying
out, could take into consideration an individual’s feel- healing among the Iñupiat. Puzzled by the prevalence of
ings of belonging and possession. Yet a third option cancer there, I and others began to inquire into the cause,
would be to declare cultural property inalienable (Cal- both during that year and during subsequent short visits
abresi and Melamed 1972), which has some initial appeal that I made to the village. In June 1992, Dan O’Neill of
because inalienability would prevent both the commo- the University of Alaska at Fairbanks, conducting ar-
dification and the exploitation of a culture. However, an chival research on the Project Chariot activities of
inalienability rule would likely prove unworkable, as the 1958–63, discovered documents about the illegal dump-
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 191

ing at the Chariot site, under the cover of the withdrawal them. This may eventually be seen as the only healthy
from the site, of 15,000 tons of radioactive soil deliber- relationship in economics, politics, industry, science,
ately transported for the purpose of experimentation family, and all human interactions.
from the Nevada test sites and secretly positioned near
Point Hope without the necessary legal containers. In
the middle of August the nine villages of the North Slope toon van meijl
learned what O’Neill had revealed. Rex Tuzroyluk told Center for Pacific and Asian Studies, University of
me that when the news came out he went around to his Nijmegen, P.O. Box 9104, 6500 HE Nijmegen, The
mother’s, and she just sat and wouldn’t talk to him. Her Netherlands. 24 xi 00
daughter Tuzzy, a brilliant university student, had re-
cently died of cancer. Rex’s wife, Pikuq, who had not Since culture is no longer conceived of as a fixed entity
been well, sounded in shock too. This was the general that can only be lost and not retained in a changed form,
mood. Jack Schaefer reported that on October 9, 100 an- it has been conceptualized as a dynamic practice em-
gry and fearful residents of Point Hope met at their com- bracing constant change. The naturalization of change
munity center and George Kingik made a speech in in contemporary conceptions of culture, however, raises
which he compared their situation to the Holocaust. the question how claims based on “culture loss” may be
When I visited Point Hope again the mood was black. acknowledged. Kirsch is to be commended for addressing
All the white authorities were denying that the dump this increasingly important issue.
had anything to do with the people’s ill health. The peo- To resolve and redress the loss of culture, Kirsch ad-
ple had begun to doubt that the government would ac- vances the concept of cultural property rights, which has
tually move the material. Jacob Lane, who had been an been developed particularly in Fourth World societies.
important man, could no longer run a whaleboat and had He argues that the concept of loss refers not only to
had to give up the captaincy. He was now unshaven; material possessions but also to immaterial matters such
many of the men had let their beards grow. There was as culture and everything for which it stands. Salient in
more trash lying about in the village. None of the vil- indigenous discourses is, of course, the loss of land, but
lagers seemed able to lift up their heads. There had been apart from being a material object land is also considered
insult—the government had been found to have played a spiritual asset and as such symbolizes a sense of be-
them false. These people embodied the oldest village in longing. For that reason, too, the concept of cultural
America—did no one honor that? No one from outside property should be defined not only with reference to
cared about it, and nuclear waste had been dumped on things but also with reference to relationships. The in-
them that would kill them. trinsic link between things and relationships, between
During the investigations I discovered more about the possession and belonging, has been incorporated skill-
Sellafield disaster. It seemed that news had been released fully into Kirsch’s definition of cultural property, but to
in 1974 that there had been many thousands of Down’s- my knowledge it is by no means recognized in the legal
syndrome and other abnormal births in Manchester dur- regimes that are to provide for claims on culture loss.
ing the 1958–59 period. It dawned on me that the loss This is clearly the weakness of Kirsch’s argument. He
of my baby had not been my fault but the result of the cogently contends that our understanding of loss should
atomic pile disaster. Since then I have discovered that be broadened and, accordingly, that the concept of cul-
contaminated material is still flooding into the Irish Sea tural property rights should be extended, but he does not
and causing radioactive conditions in Drogheda, with the seem to be taking into account that generally the law
result that the calcium in schoolchildren’s teeth shows does not change as fast as anthropology’s paradigms.
abnormal radioactive contamination. The British gov- Kirsch substantiates the legal aspects of his argument
ernment has not moved to correct the problem at Sel- with reference to two interesting innovations in law.
lafield and argues that it is impossible to do so. Little is First, he refers to a court ruling that might have opened
heard about any compensation for these various forms up the avenue for determining value beyond the scope
of loss. of the market, including cultural property rights. Sec-
Clearly, losses due to radioactivity are not truly to be ondly, he endorses the view developed by Radin, who
satisfied with money. I know this is so with regard to has disaggregated property by arguing that some cate-
the loss of my own child. What all such crimes against gories of property are inextricably bound up with people
humanity require is simply complete truth and recon- and therefore not convertible into other forms of prop-
ciliation—forgiveness on the part of the injured in return erty that may be alienable by market forces. This astute
for true caring for the powerless on the part of the au- academic view, however, is diametrically opposed to the
thorities and of all those who are powerful. This is the restricted definition of property used by the courts ad-
principle of subsidiarity—in a way, the principle of dressing indigenous claims of “culture loss.” And when
dharma, of the Japanese amae, also seen in the Native a judge appears sympathetic to indigenous grievances, as
American principle of generosity, in the idea of human in the case mentioned by Kirsch, this does not imply
rights, and in the notion of the necessary moral unity of that he has resolved the ambiguities arising out of at-
humankind. The term may be defined as the law (beyond tempts to define culture in legal terms.
and including the law of mystical participation) that the In this context, I think it is telling that all the examples
life’s work of those in authority is to serve those under elaborated by Kirsch are based on the loss of land,
192 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

whereas the concept of cultural property has been de- cause it presupposes cultural essentialism or primordi-
veloped primarily in relation to claims on knowledge. alism. As Hobsbawm and Ranger (1983) have shown,
Knowledge claims have frequently been formulated in “tradition,” as we know it, is mostly recent invention.
cases in which specific forms of knowledge have alleg- Culture is always something constructed in history; it
edly been misappropriated and applied to pecuniary ad- should be seen not as a static thing but as a dynamic,
vantage, for example, by pharmaceutical industries. Few evolving process.
of these claims, however, have been successful for the Kirsch’s account revolves around the narrative of loss.
simple reason that cultural property rights or, in this The “entropic” images of the loss may be all the stronger
case, intellectual property rights are generally claimed because it was the result of the environmental disaster
to be the collective property of communities, clans, or caused by the U.S. nuclear weapons tested at Bikini
tribes, whereas Western property regimes recognize only Atoll. The author’s approach to the theme is, however,
property rights that are held by individuals. quite fruitful for the study of culture. He notes that his
It is equally significant that as part of the reformed intention is “to explain how claims about culture loss
General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade most Western might be understood.” I agree, then, with his view that
governments have eagerly signed the Agreement on “studies of loss may enrich our understanding of property
Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights, and, conversely, that the concept of cultural property
which facilitates the transfer of knowledge to global rights may inform ongoing debates—legal, indigenous,
companies, which, in turn, counteracts indigenous as- and anthropological—about the problem of culture loss.”
pirations to protect their cultural knowledge. Of course, Kirsch focuses upon the courtroom debate over com-
the United Nations is working hard to seek protection pensation claims. Analyzing the debate, he argues that
of indigenous knowledge systems in a Declaration on the loss of property and, in particular, land should be
the Rights of Indigenous Peoples, but it is unlikely that understood not only in the material sense but also in the
this declaration will ever be ratified, at least in its current context of social relations. Therefore, the loss of land
form. One of the main reasons for this is that there is means the loss of subsistence and of indigenous knowl-
no consensus on the concepts of cultural and intellectual edge and the technology related to it, such as pandanus
property. A colourful spectrum of local traditions and mat making or canoe building—in a word, the loss of a
legal procedures forms a decisive obstacle to negotiations culture rooted in the specific environment of a specific
on the issue of cultural property rights. In fact, Kirsch territory. The narrative of loss, thus analyzed, paradox-
also shows the complexity of cultural property rights at ically reveals the nature of the loss and the concept of
the level of international politics by comparing, for ex- culture involved in the narrative.
ample, countries in which people are asked to demon- The concept of culture at stake is what Jan Nederveen
strate continuity when lodging a claim on “culture loss” Pieterse (1995) has called “territorial culture.” It con-
with countries in which they are invited to prove dis- trasts with that of “translocal culture,” in which culture
continuity. Unfortunately, however, this insight has not is understood as a kind of “software” that transcends
prevented him from advancing the concept of cultural territory. The two concepts have long existed side by
property rights as a panacea for claims about “culture side: there are no “territorial” cultures that function only
loss.” Cultural property rights are indeed on the agenda with a single closed system or “translocal” cultures
of indigenous politics, but the next step should be to without a place. In this age of global cultural flows (Ap-
work out precisely what is understood by cultural and padurai 1998), everybody on earth is experiencing the
intellectual property rights in different legal contexts and problems of being unable to compete with local/indig-
traditions. enous knowledge alone. Returning to the culture rooted
solely in a particular territory may be impossible. The
problem ultimately is how people handle the process of
shinji yamashita accommodation to a system wider than their own ter-
Department of Cultural Anthropology, University of ritory. In this respect, the Marshall Islands do not seem
Tokyo, 3-8-1 Komaba, Meguro-ku, Tokyo 153-8902, to be exceptional, even though the original loss was
Japan (cshinji@mail.ecc.u-tokyo.ac.jp). 30 xi 00 caused by nuclear tests. Kirsch’s analysis of Marshallese
culture loss, then, may be valid only when he can specify
In The Predicament of Culture James Clifford pointed the loss of particular elements of territorial culture such
to two kinds of narratives of culture: narratives of ho- as the indigenous knowledge of pandanus mat making
mogenization and loss and narratives of emergence and or the technology of canoe building.
invention (1988:17). A narrative of homogenization be- Kirsch writes wisely that his argument is analytic and
comes one of loss when homogenization means the loss that his intention is to understand claims about culture
of indigenous tradition. There are frequent references in loss rather than to promote a particular compensatory
the literature to the disappearance of “authentic” cul- regime. His intention may be all right for the study of
tural traditions because of the impact of modern Western culture, but if legal intervention in culture is inevitable
civilization, colonialism, or Coca-colanization. I have be- in the contemporary predicament of indigenousness it
come skeptical of this kind of narrative through my may be necessary to feed the results of his analysis back
study of the relationship between culture and tourism into the courtroom. It may be in the courtroom that the
in Bali (Yamashita 1999). In fact it is often incorrect be- real value of anthropological understanding will be
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 193

tested and assessed, and this exposure may enrich and their responsibility to “serve those under them.” Di-
enlarge our discipline. rectly challenging Pollock’s claim about the conserva-
tion of seafaring knowledge in the Marshall Islands, Fin-
ney provides compelling examples of both loss and
Reply potential revitalization.
The clear limits and statutes of limitation on the rec-
ognition of culture loss requested by Brown and the op-
stuart kirsch erationalization of concepts that Yamashita recommends
Ann Arbor, Mich., U.S.A. 12 xii 00 are secondary, in my view, to the identification of the
general principles involved. Practical solutions to these
I thank the respondents for producing a rich and stim- problems will have to be negotiated on a case-by-case
ulating set of commentaries that underscore the need for basis. Dominguez asks how anthropologists would re-
more discussion of the challenges posed to indigenous spond to majority groups’ claiming the same cultural
peoples by globalization and the problem of culture loss. property rights as those proposed here on behalf of mi-
Nearly all of the comments and questions raised in these nority groups, but assumptions of universality and same-
responses address one or more of the following themes: ness are not the only basis for equality (see Kymlicka
culture, loss, indigeneity, cultural property rights, and 1995, Anaya 1996).
politics. Several respondents (Brown, Giles-Vernick, Biery-
Brown begins by astutely observing that culture has Hamilton) question the generalizability of the concept
been transformed into a social fact which can no longer of indigeneity, which has a particularly thorny history
be withdrawn from the public domain. Escobar points in Africa (Giles-Vernick). Biery-Hamilton draws on her
out that we need to investigate how culture is used to research in the Amazon, where peasants have been de-
fashion truth claims, especially outside of the discipline, nied access to land because the Brazilian government
and make explicit the consequences of conceptualizing refuses to recognize common-property regimes except for
culture in particular ways. Merlan points to the differ- indigenous peoples and therefore have suffered losses
ence in the way culture is used in Australian land claims, comparable to those which I have described. I agree with
to emphasize continuity while obscuring losses, and in Giles-Vernick that it is important to historicize the pro-
Marshallese claims for compensation, where it appears cess through which people “produce, debate, and give
as the object of loss, and suggests the need for alternative meaning to” the concept of indigeneity. Rather than a
conceptions that can transcend this figure-ground natural social category, indigeneity should be seen as a
reversal. political discourse about rights—not unlike, for example,
Dominguez suggests that the notion of culture loss the concept of the nation—which connects people to a
signals a particular kind of sadness. These are losses global politics beyond the state (see Li 2000). It is, as
which can never be made whole, losses of relations be- Escobar notes, one of the ways in which “people’s sense
tween generations and connections to place that were of belonging and attachment to place continue to be im-
conceived of as fundamental and enduring, and they portant sources of cultural production and mobilized to
could not have been imagined prior to colonialism. Local various ends.” Along with culture and the nation, how-
vocabularies are ultimately inadequate to account for ever, indigeneity has become a social and political fact
these experiences, and therefore they have found ex- and in many cases a legal status as well. What is im-
pression in terms of culture. Giles-Vernick points to the portant is to indicate the limits of its applicability, as
importance of distinguishing between the sense of loss these commentators have usefully done.
and other forms of nostalgia, which can be profoundly Rosen and Sunder, the two legal readers of the argu-
conservative. Yamashita suggests that some losses (and ment presented here, take opposite positions on whether
some aspects of culture) may be associated with terri- claims about culture loss are best argued in terms of
toriality and others with translocality, a relationship that property claims or in terms of tort law. Sunder agrees
I tried to invoke. However, he also historicizes these that property claims may provide significant opportu-
concepts, suggesting that globalization requires people nities for addressing the subjective evaluation of loss,
to address both a local and a translocal notion of culture including culture. Rosen argues that tort law is the more
(or understanding of themselves), although the latter no- promising avenue for redress, suggesting that harm to
tion may well have been present, albeit less self-con- “cultural integrity” may be compensable. His invocation
sciously, in the past. of the holistic notion of integrity, however, seems likely
Dominguez observes that whether a particular loss is to cause more problems than it resolves (see Merlan
judicable or compensable may be subsidiary to the act above). Given broad differences in forum and historical
of recognition—calling attention to something which circumstances, however, and in whether statutory au-
had been invisible and identifying the wrongs that have thorities are primarily concerned with the valuation of
been committed. Drawing on personal experiences as loss or the demonstration of continuity, having recourse
well as those of the Iñupiat, Turner emphasizes the im- to more than one legal remedy seems desirable rather
portance of truth and reconciliation in response to losses than problematic.
which cannot be remedied with money. In her view, what Brush, van Meijl, and Rosen express skepticism re-
is critical is that persons with power and authority accept garding the willingness of the courts to recognize cul-
194 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

tural property rights. Brush argues that “unilateral dec- commitment, and analytical depth” as the three require-
larations of novel property rights” are insufficient. Van ments of successful testimony, and she is rightly con-
Meijl notes that most debates about cultural property cerned about the indigenous people who bear the burden
refer to the appropriation of cultural knowledge, whereas when anthropologists fail to meet these requirements.
the claims addressed in my essay all refer to land. Brush Furthermore, she questions the legitimacy of legal pro-
also argues that the “extremity of double victimization ceedings in which the imbalance of power “allows the
under colonization and nuclear testing may obscure the accused’s defense to question the legitimacy of the plain-
issue of wider social benefits and costs that are at play tiff’s grievances in the face of manifest crimes.” Com-
in recognizing culture as property and culture loss as parable reasoning prompts Karlsson to recommend the
deserving of compensation.” In a related context, how- familiar and reasonable strategies of documentation and
ever, William Pietz (1997:108) has described how new protest, including continued insistence on the inalien-
monetary values may be established in response to trau- ability of land and ethnographic description of loss.
matic losses, a process which is suggestive for the do- Similarly, Dirlik argues that judicial systems like the
main of cultural property rights: tribunal impose structures of meaning on the partici-
pants, with the result that by following its rules and
It may be that the historical limits of capitalist rela- procedures they necessarily submit to its power. Fur-
tions appear in those traumatic events that fall out- thermore, he maintains that any attempt to posit alter-
side the economic realm of commercial exchange natives within this hegemonic framework can only re-
and contractual agreement, but whose material im- produce the existing relations of domination. That the
pact on individual human lives, in the cases of acci- courts operate “as if only the natives’ memories were
dental injury, and on whole peoples, in the form of subject to constructedness and not the anthropologists’
war, nevertheless valorizes new debt relations that scholarship” was precisely my point. As Merlan points
modern social orders must somehow realize in the out, it is ironic that claims about loss should be made
form of monetary value. with reference to Euro-American concepts of property
implicated in those losses, but that is still where the
In cases of culture loss like those described here, it may power lies. Carucci’s aim was to instruct the courts not
be possible to see more clearly the need for a remedy to assume that their views, particularly the assumption
of the inherent alienability of all things, are universal.
that involves the concept of cultural property rights.
Furthermore, the concept of cultural property rights was
Also at issue is whether legal precedents of the variety
proposed to make the referents of local discourse about
discussed here are necessarily established from the top
culture loss visible to the courts. Straightening out the
down through agreements negotiated by multilateral or-
intercultural debates on these issues, as Escobar sug-
ganizations, as Brush and van Meijl suggest. Legal prec-
gests, is not only a worthy academic project but also a
edents might also be created through small-scale inno-
politically compelling one.
vations at the level of case law, as plaintiffs’ lawyers and
Escobar observes that the “boundaries between ‘aca-
judges respond to novel problems associated with cul-
demic’ and ‘applied’ and between ‘knowledge producers’
tural difference and claims regarding the grievous harm (experts/anthropologists) and ‘users’ (local people, social
suffered by indigenous peoples. Sunder apparently en- movements) are no longer neatly construed.” I would
dorses this view, suggesting that even though the notion like to conclude by illustrating this claim with a final
of cultural property rights may be rejected for some do- image drawn from my experiences working with the peo-
mains, it might still be used to fashion a constructive ple living downstream from the Ok Tedi mine. It is a
remedy to the problems of culture loss. substantially different picture from that of the court-
I support van Meijl’s call for comparative research on room, although it is part of the same sphere of indigenous
cultural and intellectual property rights, although it political action. When Rex Dagi, a leader in the political
seems necessary to address the general while working and legal struggle against the mine, attended the 1992
out the local. Cleveland observes that all declarations of Earth Summit in Rio de Janeiro, he was invited to speak
rights are culturally (and historically) constructed. He to a group of journalists assembled aboard the Green-
argues that we must also consider absolute limits on peace Rainbow Warrior II in the Rio harbor. When I later
rights, referring in particular to unsustainable demands asked him about the press conference, he said that he
on the environment, but this insight is equally valid with had read from a paper that I had written on the basis of
respect to contexts in which there are competing or over- interviews with him and other people affected by the
lapping property claims. He also suggests that solutions mine. Dirlik might say that once again anthropology has
to these problems are likely to be hybrid in nature, com- been used to silence the voice of the “natives,” but such
bining, for example, indigenous and scientific knowledge a claim would radically underestimate Dagi, a charis-
in the practice of conservation or environmental matic and articulate orator, and his strategic decision to
reclamation. (re)appropriate my text. The challenges of intercultural
Dirlik, Finney, and Ramos raise questions about the communication are significant, and anthropologists oc-
role of anthropologists as expert witnesses and the trans- casionally have resources to offer. This example also runs
formation of ethnographic knowledge into legal evi- counter to Dirlik’s claim that plus ça change, plus c’est
dence. Ramos identifies “emotional detachment, ethical la même chose: 500 years after Columbus read a proc-
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 195

lamation in Spanish to the “natives” declaring sover-


eignty over the New World, Dagi arrived in Rio from References Cited
Papua New Guinea to protest corporate-sponsored en-
vironmental degradation. While power and hegemony a g r a w a l , a r u n . 1995. Dismantling the divide between in-
have by no means disappeared from the world in the digenous and scientific knowledge. Development and Change
intervening five centuries, the varieties of resistance and 26:413–39. [dac]
the possibilities for political engagement have certainly a l b e r t , b r u c e . 1995. “Anthropologie appliquée ou anthropol-
ogie ‘impliquée’? Ethnographie, minorités et développement,”
multiplied.
in Les applications de l’anthropologie: Un essai de réflexion
Escobar argues that our sense of politics may have be- collective depuis la France. Edited by Jean-François Baré, pp.
come diluted by the very sophistication of our analyses. 87–118. Paris: Karthala. [arr]
Anthropologists seem most comfortable searching for a l c a l a y, g l e n . 1992. Pax Americana in the Pacific. Covert
political solutions in notional spaces that are free of the Action 40:47–51.
a n a y a , s . j a m e s . 1996. Indigenous peoples in international
domination of capital, binary dualisms, neocolonialism, law. New York: Oxford University Press.
and other forms of hegemony rather than through en- a n d e r s o n , a n t h o n y b . Editor. 1990. Alternatives to defor-
gagement. What is at stake in the cases considered estation: Steps toward sustained use of the Amazon rain for-
here—in addition to the interests of the people them- est. New York: Columbia University Press. [gmb]
a n d e r s o n , d a v i d g . 1998. “Property as a way of knowing
selves—is not only getting it right anthropologically or
on Evenki lands in Arctic Siberia,” in Property relations: Re-
even fashioning an academy that is continually chal- newing the anthropological tradition. Edited by C. M. Hann,
lenged by rather than isolated from the world but ulti- pp. 64–84. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
mately a politics that acknowledges a wider range of a p p a d u r a i , a r j u n . 1990. Disjuncture and difference in the
analytic possibilities.1 global economy. Public Culture 2(1):1–24. [dac]
———. 1995. “The production of locality,” in Counterworks:
Managing the diversity of knowledge. Edited by Richard Far-
don, pp. 204–25. London: Routledge.
———. 1998. Modernity at large: Cultural dimensions of globali-
zation. Minneapolis and London: University of Minneapolis
Press. [sy]
b a k e r , j . h . 1971. An introduction to English legal history.
London: Butterworth. [fm]
b a k e r , r i c h a r d . 1999. Land is life: From bush to town—the
story of the Yanyuwa people. St. Leonards: Allen and Unwin.
b a r k a n , e l a z a r . 2000. The guilt of nations: Restitution and
1. In a memorandum of decision and order on April 13, 2000, the negotiating historical injustices. New York: W. W. Norton.
Nuclear Claims Tribunal determined that claimants from Ene- [mfb]
wetak Atoll are entitled to US$ 324,949,311 in compensation as a b a r k e r , h o l l y m . 1997. “Fighting back: Justice, the Marshall
result of the impact of U.S. nuclear weapons testing and their re- Islands, and neglected radiation communities,” in Life and
location. This figure includes $199,154,811 for past and future loss death matters: Human rights and the environment at the end
of use, $91,710,000 to restore Enewetak to a safe and productive of the millennium. Edited by Barbara Rose Johnston, pp.
state, and $34,084,500 for hardships suffered as a result of relocation 290–306. London: Alta Mira.
and loss of access to their land. In explaining its decision, the tri- b a r k e r , h o l l y m . , a n d b a r b a r a ro s e j o h n s t o n .
bunal noted that the Marshallese Constitution stipulates that just 2000. Seeking compensation for radiation survivors in the Mar-
compensation must be based in part on the “unique place of land shall Islands: The contribution of anthropology. Cultural Sur-
rights in the life and law of the Republic.” It chose restoration rather vival Quarterly 24(1):48–50.
than compensation for the difference in the value of their land b e n e d i c t , r u t h . 1960. Patterns of culture. New York: Men-
before and after it was damaged, justifying this decision by making tor Books.
reference to claims made by Carucci that land in the Marshalls is b e n k l e r , y o c h a i . 1999. Free as the air to common use: First
viewed as “a part of one’s person and one’s entire identity.” The Amendment constraints on enclosure of the public domain.
tribunal also acknowledged that land in the Marshall Islands is New York University Law Review 74:354–446. [ms]
inalienable and therefore no market value for the sale of land can b e r g e r , t h o m a s r . 1985. Village journey: The report of the
properly exist, arguing that “a market approach would not provide Alaska Native Review Commission. New York: Hill and
a true measure of loss because it would not account for the deeply Wang.
personal reasons of the Enewetak people for restoring their land.” b i e r y - h a m i l t o n , g a y m . 1993. “The displacement of a
It admitted the category of hardship damages despite the objections population that did not relocate: The impact of the Tucuruı́
of the Defender of the Fund because they were “so closely related Dam on a riverside community in the Brazilian Amazon,” in
to the underlying subject matter of land damages.” In conclusion, Selected papers on refugee issues. Washington, D.C.: American
the tribunal noted that “the claimants have suffered damage beyond Anthropological Association. [gmb]
that which money can compensate. The destruction and disruption ———. 1994. Economic strategies and changing environmental
of their community and the attendant life style and values cannot systems in a Brazilian Amazon community. Ph.D. diss., Uni-
be compensated with an award of dollars. The passage of time and versity of Florida, Gainesville, Fla. [gmb]
changes in culture preclude a return to the way things were half a ———. 1996. “The differential impacts of development upon an
century ago. While that which was lost may be priceless, it does urban population on the Tucuruı́ Reservoir, Pará, Brazil,” in
not mean that it was without value; nor does it justify an award Energia na Amazônia, vol. 1. Edited by Sônia Barbosa Magal-
which is not firmly based in fairness and reasonableness” (Nuclear hães, Rosyan de Caldas Britto, and Edna Ramos de Castro. Be-
Claims Tribunal 2000). The Republic of the Marshall Islands has lem: Museu Paraense Emı́lio Goeldi, Universidade Federal do
petitioned the U.S. Congress to provide additional funding for the Pará and Associação de Universidades Amazônicas. [gmb]
Nuclear Claims Tribunal so that it can make this award. Among b o w e n , j o h n r . 2000. Should we have a universal concept of
the many factors that will influence Congress’s response is its de- “indigenous peoples’ rights”? Ethnicity and essentialism in the
sire to maintain the base on Kwajalein Atoll, where the U.S. mil- twenty-first century. Anthropology Today 16(4):12–16. [mfb]
itary tests the accuracy of its antiballistic-missile system. b o y l e , j a m e s . 1996. Shamans, software, and spleens: Law
196 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

and the construction of the information society. Cambridge: estation and development. Environmental Conservation 20:
Harvard University Press. [ms] 17–56.
b r o a d , w i l l i a m j . 2000. Court ruling on Spanish frigates ———. 1996. “Center, periphery, and biodiversity: A paradox of
foils modern-day treasure hunters. New York Times, July 31. governance and a developmental challenge,” in Valuing local
[mfb] knowledge: Indigenous people and intellectual property rights.
b r o d y, h u g h . 1988. Maps and dreams: Indians and the Brit- Edited by Stephen B. Brush and Doreen Stabinsky, pp. 41–67.
ish Columbia frontier. Toronto: Douglas and McIntyre. Washington, D.C.: Island Press.
b r o w n , m i c h a e l . 1998. Can culture be copyrighted? cur- e l l e n , r o y. 1998. Comment on: The development of indige-
rent anthropology 39:193–222. nous knowledge, by Paul Sillitoe. current anthropology 39:
b r u s h , s t e p h e n b . 1996. “Whose knowledge, whose genes, 238–39.
whose rights?” in Valuing local knowledge: Indigenous people f o r s y t h , t i m o t h y. 1998. Comment on: The development of
and intellectual property rights. Edited by Stephen B. Brush indigenous knowledge, by Paul Sillitoe. current anthropol-
and Doreen Stabinsky, pp. 1–21. Washington, D.C.: Island ogy 39:240–41.
Press. g a r n e r , b r y a n a . Editor in chief. 1999. 7th edition. Black’s
———. 1999. Bioprospecting the public domain. Cultural Anthro- law dictionary. St. Paul: West.
pology 14:535–55. [sbb] g i l e s - v e r n i c k , t a m a r a . 1999. We wander like birds: Mi-
b y r n e , j . 1995. Rex Dagi et al. v. The Broken Hill Proprietary gration, indigeneity, and the fabrication of frontiers in the San-
Company Limited. No. 5782 of 1994 and others, Victorian Su- gha River Basin of Equatorial Africa. Environmental History 4:
preme Court of Melbourne, 10 November. 168–97. [tg]
c a l a b r e s i , g u i d o , a n d d o u g l a s m e l a m e d . 1972. ———. 2000. Translating Doli: An environmental history of loss
Property rules, liability rules, and inalienability: One view of in the Sangha Basin of the Central African Republic. Journal of
the cathedral. Harvard Law Review 85:1089–1128. [ms] African History 41:373–94. [tg]
c a r u c c i , l a u r e n c e m a r s h a l l . 1997. Nuclear nativity: g o n ç a l v e s , w a g n e r . 1994. “Terras de ocupação tradicional:
Rituals of renewal and empowerment in the Marshall Islands. Aspects práticos da perı́cia antropológica,” in A perı́cia antro-
DeKalb: Northern Illinois University Press. pológica em processos judiciais. Edited by O. S. Silva, L. Luz,
c a ru c c i , l a u r e n c e m a r s h a l l , a n d m a ry h . m a i - and C. Helm, pp. 79–87. Florianópolis: Editora Universidade de
f e l d . 1999. Ien e_taan im jerata, times of suffering and ill Santa Catarina. [arr]
fortune: An overview of daily life on Ujelang and Enewetak g o n z a l e s , a n g e l a . 1998. The (re)articulation of American
since 1946. Report submitted to the Public Advocate’s Office, Indian identity: Maintaining boundaries and regulating access
Nuclear Claims Tribunal, Majuro, The Republic of the Mar- to ethnically tied resources. American Indian Culture and Re-
shall Islands. search Journal 44:199–225. [mfb]
c h a k r a b a r t y, d i p e s h . 1992. Postcoloniality and the arti- g o r d o n , j o h n . 1997. “The Ok Tedi lawsuit in retrospect,” in
fice of history: Who speaks for “Indian” pasts? Representations The Ok Tedi settlement: Issues, outcomes, and implications.
37:1–26 [tg] Edited by Glenn Banks and Chris Ballard, pp. 141–66. National
c h a r l e s w o r t h , s i m o n . 2000. A phenomenology of work- Centre for Development Studies and Resource Management in
ing-class experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. the Asia-Pacific, Pacific Policy Paper 27.
chicano mexicano mexica empowerment commit- g r a h a m , b i l l , a n d d a v i d l o w e . 1998. Statement of peri-
t e e . n.d. Mexica movement. www.mexica-movement.org. ods of denied use and comments on valuation process. Before
c l e v e l a n d , d a v i d a . 1998. Indian agriculture, conventional the Nuclear Claims Tribunal, Republic of the Marshall Islands.
United States agriculture, and sustainable agriculture. Ameri- In the matter of the Alabs of Rongelap et al., claimants for
can Indian Culture and Research Journal 22. In press. [dac] compensation (NCT No. 23-02440), in the matter of Jabon on
cleveland, david a., daniela soleri, and steven Rongelap Atoll (NCT No. 23-05443-B), in the matter of Ron-
e . s m i t h . 2000. A biological framework for understanding gerik Atoll by Iroij Anjua Loeak et al., claimants for compensa-
farmers’ plant breeding. Economic Botany 54:377–94. [dac] tion (NCT No. 23-05445-B) and in the matter of Iroij Imata Ja-
c l i f f o r d , j a m e s . 1988. The predicament of culture: Twenti- bro Kabua, Rongelap Atoll, claimant for compensation (NCT
eth-century ethnography, literature, and art. Cambridge: Har- No. 23-00501).
vard University Press. g r a y, a n d r e w. 1997. Indigenous rights and development:
———. 1997. “Traveling cultures,” in Routes: Travel and transla- Self-determination in an Amazonian community. Providence:
tion in the late twentieth century. Cambridge: Harvard Uni- Berghahn Books.
versity Press. [ms] h a n n , c . m . 1998. “Introduction: The embeddedness of prop-
c o a s e , r o n a l d h . 1960. The problem of social cost. Journal erty,” in Property relations: Renewing the anthropological tra-
of Law and Economics 3:1–44. [sbb] dition. Edited by C. M. Hann, pp. 1–47. Cambridge: Cambridge
c o o m b e , r o s e m a r y j . 1993. The properties of culture and University Press.
the politics of possessing identity: Native claims in the cul- h a r r i s o n , s i m o n . 1999. Cultural boundaries. Anthropology
tural appropriation controversy. Canadian Journal of Law and Today 15(5):10–13.
Jurisprudence 6:249–85. [ms] h i l l , j a n e h . , a n d k e n n e t h c . h i l l . 1986. Speaking
———. 1998. The cultural life of intellectual properties: Author- Mexicano: Dynamics of syncretic language in central Mexico.
ship, appropriation, and the law. Durham: Duke University Tucson: University of Arizona.
Press. [lr] h i r s c h , e r i c . 1995. “Introduction,” in The anthropology of
c r a p a n z a n o , v i n c e n t . 1985. Waiting: The whites of South the landscape: Perspectives on space and place. Edited by Eric
Africa. New York: Random House. [tg] Hirsch and Michael O’Hanlon, pp. 1–30. Oxford: Clarendon.
c u l t u r a l s u r v i v a l . 1993. State of the peoples: A global hu- ———. 2000. Culture and the new boundaries of influence: The
man rights report on societies in danger. Boston: Beacon Press. coming of mines to Fuyuge, Central Province. Paper presented
d a l l a r i , d a l m o . 1994. “Argumento antropológico e lingu- at the colloquium “Intellectual and Cultural Resources,” Gir-
agem juridical,” in A perı́cia antropológica em processos judi- ton College, University of Cambridge, March.
ciais. Edited by O. S. Silva, L. Luz, and C. Helm, pp. 107–14. h i t c h c o c k , r . k . 1994. International rights, the environ-
Florianópolis: Editora Universidade de Santa Catarina. [arr] ment, and indigenous people. Colorado Journal of Environmen-
d e a n , b a r t h o l o m e w, a n d j e r o m e m . l e v i . Editors. tal Law and Policy 5:1–22. [tg]
n.d. At the risk of being heard: Indigenous rights, identity, and h o b s b a w m , e r i c , a n d t e r e n c e r a n g e r . Editors. 1983.
postcolonial states. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. The invention of tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University
In press. Press. [sy]
d o v e , m i c h a e l r . 1993. A revisionist view of tropical defor- h o h f e l d , w e s l e y n . 1913. Some fundamental legal concepts
k i r s c h Lost Worlds F 197

as applied to judicial reasoning. Yale Law Journal 23:16–59. Enewetak, Philip Okney, Defender of the Fund, and the Tribu-
[sbb] nal Judges), 20 April 1999 in Majuro, Republic of the Marshall
h o l l a n d , h . r u s s e l . 1996. Letter. American Indian Culture Islands. Videotape.
and Research Journal 20(3):167–70. ———. 1999b. Testimony of Dr. Nancy J. Pollock before the Nu-
j o r g e n s e n , j o s e p h g . 1995. Ethnicity, not culture? Obfus- clear Claims Tribunal in re: the people of Enewetak’s claim for
cating social science in the Exxon Valdez oil spill case. Ameri- consequential damages (including questions from Davor Pevec,
can Indian Culture and Research Journal 19(4):1–124. attorney for the people of Enewetak, Philip Okney, Defender of
k e c k , v e r e n a . 1998. “Introduction,” in Common worlds and the Fund, and the Tribunal Judges), 21 April 1999 in Majuro,
single lives: Constituting knowledge in Pacific societies. Ed- Republic of the Marshall Islands. Videotape.
ited by Verena Keck, pp. 1–29. Oxford: Berg. ———. 2000. Memorandum of decision and order. NCT No. 23-
k e e s i n g , r o g e r . 1989. Creating the past: Custom and iden- 0902 in the matter of the people of Enewetak, et al., claimants
tity in the contemporary Pacific. The Contemporary Pacific for compensation, 13 April, Majuro.
1(1–2):19–42. n u g e n t , s t e p h e n . 1993. Amazon caboclo society: An essay
k i r s c h , s t u a r t 1997a. “Is Ok Tedi a precedent? Implications on invisibility and peasant economy. Providence and Oxford:
of the settlement,” in The Ok Tedi settlement: Issues, out- Berg. [gmb]
comes, and implications. Edited by Glenn Banks and Chris o k n e y, p h i l i p a . 1999. Memorandum of points and authori-
Ballard, pp. 118–40. Resource Management in the Asia-Pacific ties in opposition to an award of damages for relocation as a
and National Centre for Development Studies, Pacific Policy separate category of damages. Nuclear Claims Tribunal No. 23-
Paper 27. 0902 in the matter of the people of Enewetak, et al., claimants
———. 1997b. “Indigenous response to environmental impact for compensation.
along the Ok Tedi,” in Compensation for resource develop- o l i v e i r a , j o ã o p a c h e c o . 1994. “Os instrumentos de
ment in Papua New Guinea. Edited by Susan Toft, pp. 143–55. bordo: Expectativas e possibilidades do trabalho do antropólogo
Law Reform Commission Monograph 6/Resource Management em laudos periciais,” in A perı́cias antropológica em processos
in the Asia-Pacific and National Centre for Development Stud- judiciais. Edited by O. S. Silva, L. Luz, and C. Helm, pp.
ies, Pacific Policy Paper 24. 115–39. Florianópolis: Editora Universidade de Santa Catarina.
———. n.d. “Changing views of place and time along the Ok [arr]
Tedi,” in Mining and indigenous life worlds in Australia and o l w i g , k a r e n f o g , a n d k i r s t e n h a s t r u p . Editors.
Papua New Guinea. Edited by Alan Rumsey and James Wie- 1997. Siting culture: The shifting anthropological object. New
ner. Adelaide: Crawford House Press. In press. York: Routledge.
k i s l i u k , m i c h e l l e . 1998. Seize the dance! BaAka musical o ’ r o u r k e , d e n n i s . 1986. Half life: A parable for the nuclear
life and the ethnography of performance. New York and Ox- age. Los Angeles: Direct Cinema, Ltd.
ford: Oxford University Press. [tg]
p a r k e r , e u g e n e . Editor. 1985. The Amazon caboclo:
k i s t e , r o b e r t c . 1974. The Bikinians: A study in forced mi-
Historical and contemporary perspectives. Studies in Third
gration. Menlo Park, Calif.: Cummings.
World Societies 32. [gmb]
k r o e b e r , t h e o d o r a . 1976. Ishi in two worlds: A biography
p e t e r s , p a u l i n e . 1996. “Who’s local here?” The politics of
of the last wild Indian in North America. Berkeley: University
participation in development. Cultural Survival 20(3). [tg]
of California Press.
k u l i c k , d o n . 1992. Language shift and cultural reproduction: p i e t e r s e , j a n n e d e r v e e n . 1995. “Globalization as hybridi-
Socialization, self, and syncretism in a Papua New Guinean zation,” in Global modernities. Edited by Mike Featherston,
village. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Scott Lash, and Roland Robertson, pp. 45–68. London: Sage. [sy]
k y m l i c k a , w i l l . 1998. Multicultural citizenship: A liberal p i e t z , w i l l i a m . 1997. Death of the deodand: Accursed ob-
theory of minority rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press. jects and the money value of human life. Res 31:97–108.
l e m l e y, m a r k a . 1999. The modern Lanham Act and the p o l a n y i , k . 1944. The great transformation. New York and
death of common sense. Yale Law Journal 108: 1687–1714. [ms] Toronto: Rinehart. [fm]
l e s s i g , l a w r e n c e . 1999. Reclaiming a commons. Keynote p o l l o c k , n a n c y j . 1992. These roots remain: Food habits in
address, Berkman Center’s “Building a Digital Commons,” islands of the central and eastern Pacific since Western con-
Cambridge, Mass., May 20. http://cyber.law.harvard.edu/cc. tact. Laie, Hawai’i: Institute for Polynesian Studies.
l i , t a n i a m u r r a y. 2000. Articulating indigenous identity in ———. 1999. A perspective on cultural loss by the Enewetak
Indonesia: Resource politics and the “tribal slot.” Comparative people. Report submitted to the Office of the Defender of the
Studies in Science and History 42:149–79. Fund, Nuclear Claims Tribunal, 9 March.
l o v e l l , n a d i a . 1998. “Introduction,” in Locality and belong- r a d i n , m a r g a r e t j a n e . 1982. Property and personhood.
ing. Edited by Nadia Lovell, pp. 1–24. London: Routledge. Stanford Law Review 34:957–1015. [ms]
m a y b u r y - l e w i s , d a v i d . 1997. Indigenous peoples, ethnic ———. 1993. Reinterpreting property. Chicago: University of
groups, and the state. Boston: Allyn and Bacon. Chicago Press.
m e y e r s , f r e d . 1986a. The politics of representation: Anthro- r a m o s , a l c i d a r i t a . 1998. Indigenism: Ethnic politics in
pological discourse and Australian Aborigines. American Eth- Brazil. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
nologist 13:138–53. [arr] r a m o s , a l c i d a r i t a . Editor. 2000. The anthropologist as
———. 1986b. Locating ethnographic practice: Romance, reality, political actor. Journal of Latin American Anthropology. In
and politics in the outback. American Ethnologist 15:609–24. press. [arr]
[arr] r e a d , p e t e r . 1996. Returning to nothing: The meaning of lost
m o u g e o t , l u c j . a . 1986. “River impoundment related pop- places. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
ulation displacement in Brazilian Amazonia: The Tucuruı́ Re- r i c h a r d s , p a u l . 1996. Indigenous peoples: Concept, critique,
settlement Program (TRP, 1976–84),” in Competition for rural cases. Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh 104B:
and urban space in Latin America: Its consequences for low- 349–65. [tg]
income groups. Edited by J. M. G. Kleinpenning. Amsterdam. r o s e , c a r o l . 1994. Property and persuasion: Essays on the
[gmb] history, theory, and rhetoric of ownership. Boulder: Westview
n e t t l e , d a n i e l , a n d s u z a n n e r o m a i n e . 2000. The ex- Press.
tinction of the world’s languages. Oxford: Oxford University r o s e , d e b o r a h b i r d . 1996. Nourishing terrains: Australian
Press. Aboriginal views of landscape and wilderness. Canberra: Aus-
n u c l e a r c l a i m s t r i b u n a l . 1999a. Testimony of Dr. Laur- tralian Heritage Commission.
ence M. Carucci before the Nuclear Claims Tribunal in re: the ———. 1999. “Hard times: An Australian study,” in Quicksands:
people of Enewetak’s claim for consequential damages (includ- Foundational histories in Australia and Aotearoa New Zea-
ing questions from Davor Pevec, attorney for the people of land. Edited by Klaus Neumann, Nicholas Thomas, and Hilary
198 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

Ericsen, pp. 2–19. Sydney: University of New South Wales erty in persons,” in Property, substance, and effect: Anthropo-
Press. logical essays on persons and things, pp. 161–78. London: Ath-
r o s e n , l a w r e n c e . 1977. The anthropologist as expert wit- lone Press.
ness. American Anthropologist 79:556–78. [arr] ———. 1999c. “The ethnographic effect II,” in Property, sub-
———. 1991. The integrity of cultures. American Behavioral Sci- stance and effect: Anthropological essays on persons and
entist 34:594–617. [lr] things, pp. 229–61. London: Athlone Press.
s a h l i n s , m a r s h a l l . 1993. Goodbye to tristes tropes: Eth- s u n d e r , m a d h a v i . 2000. Intellectual property and identity
nography in the context of modern world history. Journal of politics: Playing with fire. Journal of Gender, Race, and Justice
Modern History 65(1):1-25. 69. In press. [ms]
———. 1999. What is anthropological enlightenment? Some les- t e a i w a , t e r e s i a k . 1994. Bikinis and other s/pacific n/
sons of the twentieth century. Annual Review of Anthropology oceans. The Contemporary Pacific 6(1):87–109.
28:i–xxiii. t i e r n e y, p a t r i c k . 2000. Darkness in El Dorado. New York:
s c h i e f f e l i n , e d w a r d l . 1976. The sorrow of the lonely W. W. Norton. [bgk]
and the burning of the dancers. New York: St. Martin’s Press. t o r p e y, j o h n . 2001. “Making whole what has been
s c o t t , j a m e s c . 1998. Seeing like a state: How certain smashed”: Reflections on reparations. Journal of Modern His-
schemes to improve the human condition have failed. New tory 73(2). In press.
Haven and London: Yale University Press. [gmb] t o y o s a k i , h i r o m i t s u . 1986. Good-bye Rongelap! Trans-
s i l l i t o e , p a u l . 1998a. The development of indigenous lated by Masayuki Ikeda and Heather Ikeda. Tokyo: Tsukiji
knowledge: A new applied anthropology. current anthropol- Shokan.
ogy 39:223–52. t r a s k , h a u n a n i - k a y. 1991. Natives and anthropologists:
———. 1998b. What know natives? Local knowledge in develop- The colonial struggle. The Contemporary Pacific 3(1):111–17.
ment. Social Anthropology 6:203–20. [dac] w a r r e n , k a y b . 1998. Indigenous movements and their crit-
s k a r i a , a j a y. 1999. Hybrid histories: Forests, frontiers, and ics: Pan-Maya activism in Guatemala. Princeton: University of
wildness in western India. Delhi: Oxford University Press. [tg] Princeton Press.
s k u t n a b b - k a n g a s , t o v e . 1999. Linguistic human w e i n e r , a n n e t t e b . 1992. Inalienable possessions: The par-
rights—Are you naı̈ve, or what? TESOL Journal 8(3):6–12. [mfb] adox of keeping while giving. Berkeley: University of Califor-
soleri, daniela, david a. cleveland, salvatore nia Press.
c e c c a r e l l i , a n d s t e f a n i a g r a n d o . 2000. Farmers’ w e i n e r , j a m e s . 1999. Culture in a sealed envelope: The con-
knowledge as a conceptual component of collaborative plant cealment of Australian Aboriginal heritage and tradition in the
breeding: Barley farmers of northern Syria. Paper presented at Hindmarsh Island bridge affair. Journal of the Royal Anthropo-
the international symposium “The Scientific Basis for Partici- logical Institute 5:193–210.
patory Involvement and Conservation of Crop Genetic Re- w e i s g a l l , j o n a t h a n m . 1994. Operation crossroads: The
sources,” Oaxtepec, Morelos, Mexico. [dac] atomic tests at Bikini Atoll. Annapolis: Naval Institute Press.
s t r a t h e r n , m a r i l y n . 1988. The gender of the gift: Prob- y a m a s h i t a , s h i n j i . 1999. Bali: Kanko jinruigaku no ressun.
lems with women and problems with society in Melanesia. Tokyo: University of Tokyo Press. (English translation by J. Ea-
Berkeley: University of California Press. des, Bali and beyond: Explorations in the anthropology of
———. 1999a. “The aesthetics of substance,” in Property, sub- tourism [Oxford and New York: Berghahn], forthcoming.) [sy]
stance, and effect: Anthropological essays on persons and z o r n , j e a n g . 1993. “The Republic of the Marshall Islands,”
things, pp. 45–63. London: Athlone Press. in South Pacific islands legal systems. Edited by Michael A.
———. 1999b. “Potential property: Intellectual rights and prop- Ntumy, pp. 100–141. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.

You might also like