Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 34

Inefficiency in Legislative Policymaking: A Dynamic Analysis

By MARCO BATTAGLINI AND STEPHEN COATE*

This paper develops an infinite horizon model of public spending and taxation in
which policy decisions are determined by legislative bargaining. The policy space
incorporates both productive and distributive public spending and distortionary
taxation. The productive spending is investing in a public good that benefits all
citizens (e.g., national defense) and the distributive spending is district-specific
transfers (e.g., pork-barrel spending). Investment in the public good creates a
dynamic linkage across policymaking periods. The analysis explores the dynamics
of legislative policy choices, focusing on the efficiency of the steady-state level of
taxation and allocation of spending. (JEL D72, E62, H20, H50)

It has long been argued that legislatures in zon model of legislative policymaking. The
which representatives are elected by geograph- model is of an economy in which policy
ically defined districts will make inefficient de- choices are made by a legislature comprised
cisions. According to conventional wisdom, of representatives elected by single-member,
legislators will try to benefit their constituents at geographically defined districts. In each pe-
the expense of the general community through riod, the legislature chooses the level of a
pork-barrel spending and other distributive pol- distortionary income tax and decides how to
icies (e.g., cotton or tobacco subsidies). This allocate tax revenues between investment in a
leads to both excessive spending and a misallo- public good that benefits all citizens (national
cation of government revenues between distribu- defense or air quality) and district-specific
tive policies and important national public goods. unproductive transfers (pork-barrel spend-
Despite this widely held view, formal po- ing). Thus the model incorporates both pro-
litical theory tells us little about the dynamics ductive and distributive public spending and
of legislative policy choices. Will legislative distortionary taxation. The dynamic linkage
policymaking result in a long-run size of gov- across periods is created by the public good
ernment that is too large? What will be the which is the state variable. Legislative policy-
time path of investment in national public making in each period is modelled using the
goods and the long-run levels of these goods? legislative bargaining approach of David
What features of the environment determine Baron and John Ferejohn (1989).
the magnitude of the distortions arising from The results of the model provide a rigorous
legislative policymaking? This paper ana- formal underpinning for the conventional wis-
lyzes these questions in a novel infinite hori- dom described above by showing conditions
under which the steady-state size of government
(as measured by the tax rate) is too large and the
* Battaglini: Department of Economics, Princeton Univer- level of public goods is too low. We also show,
sity, Princeton, NJ 08544 (e-mail: mbattagl@princeton.edu); however, that this conventional view needs
Coate: Department of Economics, Cornell University, qualification. When the economy’s taxable ca-
Ithaca, NY 14853 (e-mail: sc163@cornell.edu). For helpful pacity is small relative to its public good needs,
comments, the authors thank three anonymous referees,
Marina Azzimonti, Tim Besley, Tim Feddersen, Gene
legislative decisions will actually be efficient in
Grossman, Tasos Kalandrakis, Per Krusell, Antonio Merlo, the long run, despite the fact that legislators can
Massimo Morelli, Nicola Persico, Tom Romer, and seminar benefit their districts via distributive policies.
participants at the University of Pennsylvania, Washington Moreover, the nature of the inefficiency emerg-
University in St. Louis, and the 2005 Meeting of the Society ing from legislative choice could be quite dif-
for Economic Dynamics. Battaglini gratefully acknowl-
edges support from the Alfred P. Sloan Foundation and ferent from that which the conventional wisdom
from National Science Foundation grants SES-0418150 and assumes. In particular, legislators could hold
SES-0547748. back on public good spending, recognizing that
118
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 119

creating too large a stock of these goods could ified majority, Baron (1991) shows that legisla-
lead future legislators to start engaging in pork- tors may propose projects whose aggregate
barrel spending. This means that the overall size benefits are less than their costs, when these
of government could be below optimal and rev- benefits can be targeted to particular districts.
enues could be allocated to their most produc- An interesting dynamic analysis of the effi-
tive uses—namely, maintaining public good ciency of legislative policymaking is provided
levels. by William LeBlanc, James Snyder, and Mickey
The model also generates a number of novel Tripathi (2000).4 They argue that majority-rule leg-
positive implications. First, it suggests that the size islatures will misallocate government revenues
of the legislative coalitions passing budgets may between distributive policies and public invest-
decline over time as a country builds up its stock ment. They make their argument in the context of
of public goods. Second, the model suggests that a finite horizon model in which, in each period, a
societies in which citizens have a more elastic legislature allocates a pool of exogenously given
labor supply will enjoy better quality government. revenue between targeted transfers and a public
A higher elasticity of labor supply reduces pork- investment that serves to increase the amount of
barrel spending but not the long-run levels of revenue available in the next period. Like us, they
public goods. Finally, the model suggests that the employ the bargaining approach to model legisla-
quality of government as measured by the propor- tive policymaking. Our model differs from theirs
tion of revenues devoted to distributive policies is in three key ways: (a) it is an infinite-horizon,
inversely correlated with the productivity of the general-equilibrium model; (b) government reve-
private sector. The model yields these clean com- nue in each period is endogenous because it de-
parative statics results because we fully character- pends upon the legislature’s choice of a tax rate;
ize the set of equilibria and, in particular, the and (c) investment in the public good has payoffs
conditions for a unique equilibrium. that last beyond the next period. These differences
In studying the efficiency of politically deter- allow us to study the long-run size of government
mined policy choices, our paper contributes to and also yield a richer set of conclusions concern-
the literature on the theory of political failure.1 ing the efficiency of legislative policymaking. In
A number of works have explored the efficiency particular, we obtain conditions under which leg-
of legislative decision making from a static per- islative policy choices are efficient and, in addi-
spective.2 In a well-known paper, Barry Wein- tion, conditions under which the legislature may
gast, Kenneth Shepsle, and Christopher Johnsen underinvest in public goods despite not spending
(1981) argue that distributive policymaking will on distributive policies.
lead to excessive government spending. They In solving a dynamic political bargaining
do not, however, model the process of passing model, our paper also contributes to the litera-
legislation, assuming instead that legislative ture on the legislative bargaining approach.5
policymaking is governed by a “norm of uni-
versalism.”3 In a legislative bargaining model in
which proposals need to be approved by a qual- need to balance the budget. Distributive policymaking then
becomes a pure common pool problem.
4
Andrés Velasco (2000) develops an analysis of the
1
This literature seeks to develop an understanding of the accumulation of public debt that models public decision
performance of political institutions in allocating public making as a dynamic common pool problem. The key
resources that matches our understanding of the perfor- assumption of this approach is that (as in the static model of
mance of markets in the allocation of private resources. It Weingast, Shepsle, and Johnsen 1981) legislators can all
includes the papers by Daron Acemoglu (2003), Acemoglu choose the amount of spending they want for their constit-
and James A. Robinson (2001), Timothy Besley and Coate uents. Thus, there is no voting on spending bills and hence
(1998), Coate and Stephen Morris (1995, 1999), Alessandro no need for legislators to build coalitions to pass them.
5
Lizzeri and Nicola Persico (2001), Torsten Persson and Lars This literature seeks to understand how legislatures
Svensson (1989), Guido Tabellini and Alberto Alesina choose policies in multidimensional policymaking environ-
(1990), and Donald Wittman (1989). ments where the median voter theorem cannot be applied
2
See Persson and Tabellini (2000) and David Austen- and party attachments are weak. The approach stems from
Smith and Jeffrey Banks (2005) for general discussions of the seminal work of Baron and Ferejohn (1989) and in-
this issue. cludes the papers by Banks and John Duggan (2000), Hulya
3
Under this norm, each legislator unilaterally decides on Eraslan (2002), and Eraslan and Antonio Merlo (2002). An
the level of spending he would like on projects in his own alternative “demand bargaining” approach to the problem is
district; the aggregate level of taxation is determined by the developed by Massimo Morelli (1999).
120 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

While most papers in this literature focus on the age of policies across periods. Such linkages
choices made for a single policy period, a few arise either directly as with public investment or
have explored dynamic decision making. Baron debt, or indirectly because today’s policy
(1996), Baron and Michael Herron (2003), and choices have an impact on citizens’ private in-
Anastassios Kalandrakis (2004) all study dy- vestment decisions. Extending standard static
namic models in which a legislature makes pol- models to understand fully dynamic policymak-
icy choices in each period.6 In contrast to this ing has proved difficult, however, even in the
paper, in these models the policy choices are not case of one-dimensional policy environments.
durable in the sense that the benefits from to- Accordingly, most dynamic analyses employ
day’s choices accrue in future periods. Rather, two-period models. While these have yielded
the dynamic linkage across periods is created by many useful insights, they do not permit the
the assumption that today’s policy choice deter- development of predictions about the dynamics
mines tomorrow’s default outcome should the of policy choices or steady-state policy levels,
legislature not come to agreement. This creates and this has spawned the recent research effort
complex interactions as today’s policymakers on infinite horizon models. Per Krusell and
choose policy, taking into account the implica- José-Vı́ctor Rı́os-Rull (1999) embed a negative
tions of shifting next period’s status quo.7 How- income tax system into the neoclassical growth
ever, the nature of the policy choices assumed model and assume that the rate of taxation is
in these models means that they yield no impli- determined by the median voter in each period.
cations for efficiency except in so far as citizens They are able to solve their model numerically
are risk averse.8 and use it to make predictions concerning the
Finally, our paper contributes to a small lit- long-run size of government. Using a simpler
erature trying to develop infinite-horizon polit- underlying economic model, John Hassler et al.
ical economy models of policymaking that (2003) develop an overlapping-generations
incorporate rational, forward-looking decision model of the welfare state where, in each pe-
makers. It has been well recognized in the po- riod, the level of welfare benefits is determined
litical economy literature that many interesting by majority voting. They are able to provide
issues arise from recognizing the dynamic link- analytical solutions of their model. Hassler et al.
(2005) extend this approach to a richer eco-
nomic environment in which the welfare state
6
See also Richard McKelvey and Raymond Riezman provides an insurance role.9 These models dif-
(1992) who study a dynamic legislative bargaining model fer from ours in that the policy space is one-
with elections where the dynamic linkage across periods is
created by the tenure of each district’s legislator. Also dimensional and the dynamic linkage occurs by
related to this literature is the recent paper of Armando having an impact on private investment deci-
Gomes and Philippe Jehiel (2005). They present a general sions. Closer to our paper is Marina Azzimonti
model of infinitely repeated coalitional bargaining that can (2005), who studies policymaking in an infinite
be interpreted as legislative bargaining. Their environment,
however, differs from the rest of the literature because they
horizon model in which in each period the
assume that there are no restrictions in monetary transfers winning political party allocates revenue be-
among players, so the proposer can extract all the expected tween targeted group-specific public goods and
continuation values from the other players with no limit. a public infrastructure good that serves to make
This assumption does not seem to fit with the realities of the economy more productive in the future. The
legislative bargaining where pork transfers are restricted to
be positive. major difference is that the winning political party
7
Dennis Epple and Michael Riordan (1987) present a is a policy dictator, and therefore there is no
related analysis in which legislators take turns in being the need to build legislative coalitions as in our
proposer as opposed to the proposer being randomly drawn model.10
each period. They also consider nonstationary equilibria.
8
In Baron (1996), legislators bargain over a single dimen-
sional policy such as the level of spending on a particular
9
program. Baron and Herron (2003) study a finite horizon Hassler, Kjetil Storesletten, and Fabrizio Zilibotti
version of Baron’s model but with a two-dimensional policy (2003) develop a related model where tax revenues are used
space. In Kalandrakis (2004), legislators bargain over the al- to finance public goods.
10
location of a fixed amount of revenue in each period. In all In addition, Azzimonti is primarily interested in un-
these models, equilibrium policy choices are uncertain, at least derstanding the implications of asymmetries in the popular-
in the short run. Thus, if citizens are risk averse, equilibrium ity of political parties for the time path of government
policy sequences can be Pareto dominated. spending and investment.
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 121

The organization of the remainder of the pa- specification implies that the interest rate is ␳ ⫽
per is as follows. Section I describes the model. 1/␦ ⫺ 1. At this interest rate, citizens have no
Section II creates a benchmark for comparison incentive to save or borrow. At wage rate w,
by solving for the efficient solution. The heart each citizen will work an amount l*(w) ⫽
of the paper is Section III, which solves for (␧w)␧, so that ␧ is the elasticity of labor supply.
equilibrium policy choices. Section IV develops Absent government transfers and taxes, a citi-
the model’s implications for the efficiency of zen’s associated per-period indirect utility func-
legislative decision making and points out some tion is given by
of its more interesting positive implications. A
brief conclusion is offered in Section V. An ␧ ␧w ␧ ⫹ 1
(3) u共w, g兲 ⫽ ⫹ Ag ␣ .
Appendix contains proofs of some of the more ␧⫹1
technical results.
Public decisions are made by a legislature
I. The Model consisting of representatives from each of the n
districts. One citizen from each district is se-
A continuum of infinitely lived citizens live lected to be that district’s representative. Since
in n identical districts indexed by i ⫽ 1, ... , n. all citizens are the same, the identity of the
The size of the population in each district is representative is immaterial and hence the se-
normalized to be one. There are three goods: a lection process can be ignored.12 The legislature
public good g; consumption z; and labor l. The meets at the beginning of each period. These
consumption good is produced from labor ac- meetings take only an insignificant amount of
cording to the technology z ⫽ wl. The public time, and representatives undertake private sec-
good can be produced from the consumption tor work in the rest of the period just like
good according to the technology g ⫽ z/p. The everybody else. The affirmative votes of q ⬍ n
public good is an investment good in the sense representatives are required to enact any legisla-
that units produced in the current period yield tion. The only way the legislature can raise funds
benefits in future periods.11 Specifically, if the is via a proportional tax on labor income.13 Tax
level of the public good at time t is gt, and It new revenues can be used to finance investment in the
units are produced in period t, then the level in public good, but can also be diverted to finance
period t ⫹ 1 is targeted district-specific transfers of the consump-
tion good, which are interpreted as (nondistortion-
(1) g t ⫹ 1 ⫽ 共1 ⫺ d兲g t ⫹ I t . ary) pork-barrel spending.14
To describe how legislative decision making
The parameter d is the depreciation rate of the works, suppose the legislature is meeting at the
public good. beginning of a period in which the current level
Each citizen’s per-period utility function is of the public good is g. One of the legislators is
randomly selected to make the first policy pro-
l 关1 ⫹ 共1/␧兲兴 posal, with each representative having an equal
(2) z ⫹ Ag ␣ ⫺ ,
␧⫹1
12
If citizens within districts are heterogeneous (say with
where ␣ 僆 (0, 1). The parameter A measures the respect to their public good preferences), then interesting
relative importance of the public good to the issues arise as to the selection of legislators. Austen-Smith
citizens. Citizens discount future per-period and Banks (1988), Besley and Coate (2003), and V. V.
utilities at rate ␦. Chari, Larry Jones, and Ramon Marimon (1997) explore
these issues in static models.
The assumptions on technology imply that 13
For simplicity, and to focus on the legislative invest-
the price of the public good is p and the wage ment decision, we abstract from the possibility of financing
rate is w. Moreover, the quasi-linear utility expenditures with public debt. In the conclusion, we discuss
a way in which the model may be adapted to explore the
implications of government borrowing.
14
The district-specific transfers could be either direct
11
Many public goods have this feature. Important ex- grants to particular localities or earmarks for specific public
amples are national defense activities, such as building projects that the districts would undertake anyway. In the
tanks and training troops; scientific knowledge, such as latter case, the earmarks would be nondistortionary and
cancer research; and environmental cleanups. equivalent to a direct transfer of consumption.
122 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

chance of being recognized. A proposal is de- by describing the policies that would be chosen
scribed by an n ⫹ 2-tuple {r, s1, ... , sn , x}, by a social planner whose objective is to max-
where r is the income tax rate; si is the proposed imize aggregate utility. In a period in which the
transfer to district i’s residents; and x is the current level of the public good is g, the plan-
proposed new level of the public good. The tax ner’s problem is to choose a new level of the
revenues raised under the proposal are given by public good x, a vector of transfers (s1, ... , sn),
R(r) ⫽ nrwl*(w(1 ⫺ r)) and the proposal must and a tax rate r to solve the problem
satisfy the budget constraint that ¥i si ⱕ B(r, x; g)
where B(r, x; g) denotes the difference between
tax revenues and investment spending, i.e.,
(5) max nu共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ 冘 s ⫹ ␦V共x兲
i
i

(4) B共r, x; g兲 ⫽ R共r兲 ⫺ p关x ⫺ 共1 ⫺ d兲g兴. s.t. si ⱖ 0 for all i

The set of constraints is completed by the


nonnegativity constraints that s i ⱖ 0 for each
and 冘 s ⱕ B共r, x; g兲,
i
i

district i (which rules out financing public


investment via district specific lump sum where V(x) denotes the planner’s value function.
taxes).15 This problem can be simplified by observing
If the proposal is accepted by q legislators, that if B(r, x; g) were positive, the planner would
then the plan is implemented and the legislature want to use all the available surplus revenues to
adjourns until the beginning of the next period. finance transfers, and hence ¥i si ⫽ B(r, x; g).
At that time, the legislature meets again with the Moreover, aggregate utility is independent of how
only difference being that the initial level of the planner allocates this surplus across the dis-
public capital is x. If, on the other hand, the first tricts because citizens’ utilities are linear in con-
proposal is not accepted, another legislator is sumption. Thus, we can eliminate the choice
chosen to make a proposal. There are T ⱖ 2 variables (s1, ... , sn) and reformulate the problem
such proposal rounds, each of which takes a as that of choosing a new level of the public good
negligible amount of time. If the process con- x and a tax rate r to solve
tinues until proposal round T, and the proposal
made at that stage is rejected, then a legislator is (6) max nu共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ B共r, x; g兲 ⫹ ␦V共x兲
appointed to choose a default policy. The leg-
islator is required to choose a policy that treats s.t. B共r, x; g兲 ⱖ 0.
districts uniformly, meaning that if he chooses
transfers, he must choose a uniform transfer that The problem in this form is fairly standard. The
goes to all districts.16 social planner’s value function must satisfy the
functional equation
II. The Social Planner’s Solution
(7) V共g兲 ⫽ max兵nu共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ B共r, x; g兲
To create a normative benchmark with which 兵r,x其

to compare the political equilibrium, we begin


⫹ ␦V共x兲 : B共r, x; g兲 ⱖ 0其,

15
For analytical convenience, we do not impose the and familiar arguments can be applied to show
constraint that investment is nonnegative, i.e., x ⱖ (1 ⫺ d)g. that it exists and is differentiable, increasing and
Thus, we are assuming, effectively, that investment is re- strictly concave. From this, the properties of the
versible. optimal policy may readily be deduced.
16
This assumption guarantees that if the legislature is
unable to agree on a policy proposal, the default outcome To understand the optimal policy, note first
will be efficient in the sense of maximizing the legislators’ that the revenue maximizing tax rate is given by
average utility, and so independent from the identity of the r ⫽ 1/(1 ⫹ ␧) and hence the maximum level of
last proposer. The assumption helps keep the model tracta- revenue that can be raised during the period is
ble. Nonetheless, it is important to note that when the
number of proposal rounds T is large, the particular default
R(1/(1 ⫹ ␧)). The levels of the public good x
policy that is chosen has only a small effect on equilibrium that the planner can implement with an initial
payoffs, which vanishes as T 3 ⬁. level g are therefore given by the interval [0,
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 123

(1 ⫺ d)g ⫹ R(1/(1 ⫹ ␧))/p]. If the planner marginal cost of public funds. The latter al-
would like to invest in the public good (i.e., x ⱖ ways exceeds one and is higher the more
(1 ⫺ d)g), he will choose an income tax rate elastic is the supply of labor and the greater is
just sufficient to finance this investment. Rais- the tax rate.17
ing surplus revenues to finance pork barrel The planner’s solution converges to a unique
spending will never be optimal because taxation steady state (ro, xo). To compute this, we first
is distortionary. Thus, the tax rate is r ⫽ r(x, g), need to find an expression for the social mar-
where the function r(x, g) is implicitly defined ginal benefit of the public good. We know that
by the equality B(r, x; g) ⫽ 0. On the other if x ⱕ ĝ then
hand, if the planner would like to disinvest in
the public good (i.e., x ⬍ (1 ⫺ d) g), he will (12) V共x兲
redistribute the proceeds through pork rather
than through an earnings subsidy. This means ⫽ max兵nu共w共1 ⫺ r共z, x兲兲, x兲 ⫹ ␦V共z兲其,
that the tax rate will equal 0 (as opposed to z

being negative) and B(r, x; g) ⬎ 0.


Given the properties of the value function, while if x ⬎ ĝ
there will exist some critical level of the public
good ĝ such that for all g ⱕ ĝ the planner will (13) V共x兲 ⫽ nu共w, x兲
want to invest, and for all g ⬎ ĝ he will want to
disinvest. Accordingly, if g ⱕ ĝ the optimal ⫹ p共1 ⫺ d兲共x ⫺ ĝ兲 ⫹ ␦ V共共1 ⫺ d兲ĝ兲.
policy functions must be such that
Using the Envelope Theorem and computing the
(8) x o 共g兲 derivative ⭸r/⭸x, we obtain that if x ⱕ ĝ then

⫽ arg max兵nu共w共1 ⫺ r共x, g兲兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦V共x兲其 (14) V⬘共x兲 ⫽ nA ␣ x ␣ ⫺ 1

and 1 ⫺ r共x o 共x兲, x兲


⫹ p共1 ⫺ d兲,
1 ⫺ r共x o 共x兲, x兲共1 ⫹ ␧兲
(9) r o 共g兲 ⫽ r共x o 共g兲, g兲,
and if x ⬎ ĝ
while if g ⬎ ĝ then xo( g) ⫽ (1 ⫺ d)ĝ and
ro( g) ⫽ 0. Moreover, on the interval [0, ĝ], the (15) V⬘共x兲 ⫽ nA ␣ x ␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹ p共1 ⫺ d兲.
optimal public good level xo( g) must satisfy the
first-order condition: To understand this, note that there are two fu-
ture benefits of investing more in the public
(10) ␦ V⬘共x兲 good. First, public good consumption is higher
in the next period. Second, less investment will
⭸u共w共1 ⫺ r共x, g兲兲, g兲 ⭸r共x, g兲 be necessary next period or, if x ⬎ ĝ, more
⫽ nw .
⭸w ⭸x disinvestment will be possible. The first term in
these expressions measures the former effect,
After computing the derivatives on the right- and the second term the latter. The size of the
hand side, this can be rewritten as latter effect depends on whether x is larger or
smaller than ĝ. If less investment is necessary

(11) ␦ V⬘共x兲 ⫽ 冋 1 ⫺ r共x, g兲


1 ⫺ r共x, g兲共1 ⫹ ␧兲册䡠 p.
next period, this will mean a lower tax rate. If
more disinvestment is possible, this will mean a
larger transfer. The value of a tax rate reduction
is greater than an equally costly transfer in-
This is the Euler equation for the planner’s
problem. The term on the left-hand side is the
social marginal benefit of the public good and 17
The “marginal cost of public funds” represents the
the term on the right is the social marginal social cost of raising an additional $1 of tax revenue. The
cost. The social marginal cost is the product difference between the marginal cost of public funds and $1
of the price of the public good p and the is a measure of the distortions taxation is creating.
124 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

crease because taxation is distortionary. While pends only on the current level of the public
the expressions differ, however, it is important good. We focus on symmetric equilibria in
to note that the social marginal benefit of the which each representative uses the same pro-
public good is continuous at x ⫽ ĝ because posal strategy and treats the other representa-
r(xo( ĝ), ĝ) ⫽ 0. tives anonymously.18 Such equilibria are
At a steady state, we have that xo ⫽ xo(xo), characterized by a collection of functions:
which must mean that xo ⬍ ĝ. Substituting in {r␶( g), s␶( g), x␶( g)}␶T ⫽ 1. Here, r␶( g) is the in-
the expression for the social marginal benefit of come tax rate that is proposed at round ␶ when
the public good into the Euler equation, it fol- the initial level of the public good is g, and x␶( g)
lows that, at a steady state, is the new level of public good. The proposer
also offers a transfer of s␶( g) to the districts of


(16) ␦ nA ␣ 共x o 兲 ␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹
1 ⫺ r共x o , x o 兲
1 ⫺ r共x o , x o 兲共1 ⫹ ␧兲
,
q ⫺ 1 randomly selected representatives, where
q is the size of a minimum winning coalition.19
Any remaining tax revenues are used to provide


pork for his own district. As is standard in the
1 ⫺ r共x o , x o 兲
p共1 ⫺ d兲 ⫽ 䡠 p. literature on legislative bargaining, we assume
1 ⫺ r共x o , x o 兲共1 ⫹ ␧兲 that legislators do not use weakly dominated
strategies when voting for a policy proposal: so
It is easy to verify that this equation has a they vote in favor if and only if their utility
unique solution and this is the planner’s steady- under the proposal is at least as large as their
state level of the public good. The steady-state continuation value in the event it is rejected. We
tax rate is given by ro ⫽ r(xo, xo). focus, without loss of generality, on equilibria
Although the analysis of the planner’s prob- in which, at each round ␶, proposals are imme-
lem is relatively standard, it is useful to have a diately accepted by at least q legislators, so that
graphical representation of the solution. This on the equilibrium path, no meeting lasts more
will set the stage for the more complicated than one proposal round.20 Accordingly, the
political equilibrium. Figure 1A shows the Eu- policies that are actually implemented in equi-
ler equation. The decreasing function is the so- librium are described by {r1( g), s1( g), x1( g)}.
cial marginal benefit of the public good ␦V⬘(x). To be more precise, {r␶( g), s␶( g), x␶( g)}␶T ⫽1 is
The increasing functions are the social marginal an equilibrium if, at each proposal round ␶ and all
costs evaluated at different initial public capital public good levels g ⱖ 0, the equilibrium proposal
levels. Note that these curves are always above maximizes the proposer’s payoff subject to the
p, since r(x, g) ⱖ 0. The intersection of these incentive constraint of getting the required
two loci gives us the planner’s investment
choice xo( g), which is represented in Figure
18
1B. This curve is increasing on [0, ĝ] and con- See Peter Norman (2002) for a discussion of the
significance of the anonymous treatment assumption in leg-
stant thereafter. It can be shown to have a slope islative bargaining games.
less than one and hence intersects the 45° line 19
In our model, while the proposer is free to offer transfers
once. This intersection identifies the steady- to more than q ⫺ 1 representatives, there is no loss in gener-
state level xo. It is apparent from the figure that, ality in considering only minimal winning coalitions, since in
from any initial level, the equilibrium level of no stationary equilibrium would the proposer find it optimal to
offer transfers to more than q ⫺ 1 representatives.
the public good converges monotonically to the 20
Since there is no discounting within bargaining stages,
steady state xo. The tax rate can be shown to be there are equilibria in which, in correspondence to some state,
monotonically decreasing if, as seems natural, a proposal may be rejected at some round ␶ and accepted at a
the economy starts out with a public good level later round ␶⬘. Without loss of generality, however, we can
lower than the steady-state level. ignore these equilibria, since they would be payoff equivalent
to equilibria with immediate agreement. Although the proposer
at period ␶ may be indifferent between making a proposal that
III. Political Equilibrium is accepted and one that is rejected, it is easy to see that he
cannot possibly prefer the latter. If this were the case, there
We look for stationary equilibria in which would be a feasible policy choice that in equilibrium wins a
majority in some later round ␶⬘ ⬎ ␶ and that it is preferred by
any representative selected to propose at pro- the proposer to any other proposal that would pass at ␶. But this
posal round ␶ 僆 {1, ... , T} of the meeting at is impossible, since the proposer is free to propose at ␶ any
some time t uses a proposal strategy that de- policy that would pass at ␶⬘.
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 125

FIGURE 1. THE PLANNER’S PROBLEM

number of affirmative votes and the feasibility where v 1 ( x) is the legislators’ round-one
constraint that transfers be nonnegative. For- value function (which describes the expected
mally, (r␶( g), s␶( g), x␶( g)) must solve the problem future payoff of a legislator at the beginning
of a period in which the current level of
(17) max u共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ B共r, x; g兲 public good is x) and v ␶ ⫹ 1 ( g) is the expected
共r,s,x兲 future payoff of a legislator in the out-of-
equilibrium event that the proposal at round ␶
⫺ 共q ⫺ 1兲s ⫹ ␦v1 共x兲 is rejected. The first constraint is the incentive
constraint and the latter two are the feasibility
s.t. u共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ s ⫹ ␦v1 共x兲 ⱖ v␶ ⫹ 1 共g兲, constraints.
The legislators’ round-one value function is
B共r, x; g兲 ⱖ 共q ⫺ 1兲s, and s ⱖ 0, defined recursively by
126 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

(18) v 1 共g兲 ⫽ u共w共1 ⫺ r 1 共g兲兲, g兲 legislators’ value function v1( g) is strictly con-
cave. We will restrict attention to concave equi-
B共r 1 共g兲, x 1 共g兲; g兲 libria in what follows, and henceforth when we
⫹ ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x 1 共g兲兲. refer to an equilibrium it should be understood
n
to be concave.21 Note also that economy-wide
aggregate utility in an equilibrium is given by
To understand this, recall that a legislator is nv1( g). This follows from the fact that each
chosen to propose in round one with probability district has a population of size 1 and citizens
1/n. If chosen to propose, he obtains a payoff in obtain the same payoffs as their representatives.
that period of Our analysis of political equilibrium is di-
vided into three parts. We begin by assuming
(19) u共w共1 ⫺ r 1 共g兲兲, g兲 that an equilibrium exists and characterize what
the equilibrium policy proposals must look like.
⫹ B共r 1 共g兲, x 1 共g兲; g兲 ⫺ 共q ⫺ 1兲s 1 共g兲. We then show that there are three possible types
of equilibrium, each of which has distinct dy-
If he is not chosen to propose, but is included in namics and a different steady state. Finally, we
the minimum winning coalition, he obtains a will establish the conditions under which each
payoff of u(w(1 ⫺ r1( g)), g) ⫹ s1( g), and if he of these three types of equilibrium exists.
is not included he obtains a payoff of just Throughout the analysis, we will maintain the
u(w(1 ⫺ r1( g)), g). The probability that he will following assumption:
be included in the minimum winning coalition,
conditional on not being chosen to propose, is ASSUMPTION 1:
(q ⫺ 1)/(n ⫺ 1). Taking expectations, the pork-
barrel transfers s1( g) cancel and the period pay-
off is as described in (18). R 冉 1 ⫺ q/n

冢冉 冊冣
1/1 ⫺ ␣
1 ⫹ ␧ ⫺ q/n ␦qA␣
For all proposal rounds ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T ⫺ 1, the ⬍ .
expected future payoff of a legislator if the p q
p 1 ⫺ ␦共1 ⫺ d兲
round ␶ proposal is rejected is n

(20) v ␶ ⫹ 1 共g兲 ⫽ u共w共1 ⫺ r ␶ ⫹ 1 共g兲兲, g兲 Basically, this requires that the tax base of the
economy not be so large that a minimum win-
B共r ␶ ⫹ 1 共g兲, x ␶ ⫹ 1 共g兲; g兲 ning coalition of legislators could accumulate
⫹ ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x ␶ ⫹ 1 共g兲兲. their desired level of the public good in a single
n
period. The role this assumption plays will be-
This reflects the assumption that the round ␶ ⫹ come apparent shortly.
1 proposal will be accepted. Recall that if the
round T proposal is rejected, the assumption is A. The Equilibrium Policy Proposals
that a legislator is appointed to choose policy
and that he must choose a uniform policy The basic structure of the equilibrium policy
which, if it involves transfers, must make the proposals is easily understood. To get support
same transfer to all districts. Thus, for his proposal, the proposer must obtain the
votes of q ⫺ 1 other representatives. Accord-
(21) v T ⫹ 1 共g兲 ingly, given that utility is transferable, he is
effectively making decisions to maximize the

共r,x兲

⫽ max u(w(1 ⫺ r), g) ⫹
B(r, x; g)
n
utility of q legislators. The optimal policy will
depend on the state variable g. If the stock of the
public good is sufficiently low, then even


though the proposer is only taking into account
⫹ ␦v1(x) : B(r, x; g) ⱖ 0 .
21
As we will prove, a concave equilibrium always exists
in our model. Although we could not find an example of a
An equilibrium {r␶( g), s␶( g), x␶( g)}␶T ⫽ 1
is nonconcave equilibrium, we have not formally proven that
said to be concave if the associated round-one such an equilibrium cannot exist.
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 127

the well-being of q legislators, he will still not x*共g兲 ⫽ arg max兵u共w共1 ⫺ r共x, g兲兲, g兲
want to divert resources to transfers. Transfers x

require either reduced public investment or in-


creased taxation, and when the stock of the ⫹ ␦v1 共x兲其; and
public good is low, the marginal benefit of
public investment and the marginal cost of (ii) if g 僆 ( g*, ⬁) then for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T,
taxation are both too high to make transfers
attractive. The proposer will therefore choose 共r ␶ 共g兲, x ␶ 共g兲兲 ⫽ 共r*, x*兲,
the tax rate–public investment pair that max-
imizes collective utility and the outcome will for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T ⫺ 1,
be as if he is maximizing the utility of the
legislature as a whole. Once the stock of the
B共r*, x*; g兲
public good becomes sufficiently large, the s ␶ 共g兲 ⫽ ,
opportunity cost of transfers is lessened and n
the collective utility of the q legislators will
be maximized by diverting some resources to and
pork. Accordingly, the proposer will propose
pork for the districts associated with his min- sT 共g兲 ⫽ vT ⫹ 1 共g兲 ⫺ u共w共1 ⫺ r*兲, g兲 ⫺ ␦v1 共x*兲,
imum winning coalition.
In any equilibrium, therefore, there will where
exist a threshold level of the public good that
divides the state space into two ranges. In the 共r*, x*兲 ⫽ arg max q关u共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦v1 共x兲兴
lower range, in every proposal round, the 共r,x兲
proposer will propose a unanimous coalition
solution in which the policy proposal maxi- ⫹ B共r, x; g兲.
mizes aggregate legislator utility, implying
that no revenues are devoted to pork. These The threshold level of the public good is g*
proposals will be supported by the entire leg- and the proposition tells us that the tax rate–
islature. In the upper range, in every proposal public investment pair proposed in each pro-
round, the proposer chooses a minimum win- posal round will maximize aggregate legislator
ning coalition solution in which the proposer utility when g ⱕ g* and the utility of q legisla-
provides pork for his own district and those of tors when g ⬎ g*. It is straightforward to verify
a minimum winning coalition of representa- that
tives. The tax rate-investment pair maximizes
the aggregate utility of q legislators, given 1 ⫺ q/n
that they appropriate all the surplus revenues. (22) r* ⫽
The transfer paid out to coalition members is 1 ⫹ ␧ ⫺ q/n
just sufficient to make them in favor of accept-
ing the proposal. Thus, only those legislators and that
whose districts receive pork vote for these pro-
posals. (23) x* ⫽ arg max兵␦qv1 共x兲 ⫺ px其.
This discussion motivates: x

PROPOSITION 1: Let {r␶( g), s␶( g), x␶( g)}␶T ⫽ 1 Thus, both the tax rate and level of the public
be an equilibrium with associated value func- good proposed in the minimum winning coali-
tion v1( g). Then there exists g* ⬎ 0 such that: tion range are independent of the existing level
of the public good and, furthermore, the tax rate
(i) if g 僆 [0, g*] then for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T, is independent of the value function. Another
useful fact is that at g ⫽ g*, the unanimous and
共r␶ 共g兲, s␶ 共g兲, x␶ 共g兲兲 ⫽ 共r共x*共g兲, g兲, 0, x*共g兲兲, minimum winning coalition solutions coincide
so that
where r(x, g) is the tax rate function from the
analysis of the planner’s problem and (24) 共r共x*共g*兲, g*兲, 0, x*共g*兲兲 ⫽ 共r*, 0, x*兲.
128 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

This implies that B(x*, r*; g*) ⫽ 0, an obser- in the next period. Second, less investment will
vation that permits the computation of the be necessary next period. The benefits from the
threshold value g* once x* is known. first effect are the same whether or not the
Proposition 1 provides us with the basic pic- legislature is choosing to make transfers in the
ture of what the equilibrium proposals look like. next period, but the benefits of the second effect
The next step is to obtain more information do depend on this choice. In the unanimous
about the function x*( g) and the public good coalition case, the lower investment translates
level x*. Since these obviously depend upon the into a lower tax rate. With minimum winning
nature of the equilibrium value function, we coalitions, it means higher transfers. But the
must investigate this first. From Proposition 1 value of a tax rate reduction is greater than the
we have that if x ⱕ g* then value of an equally expensive transfer increase
because taxes are distortionary and hence the
(25) v 1 共x兲 kink.
We can now use the expression for the
⫽ max兵u共w共1 ⫺ r共y, x兲兲, x兲 ⫹ ␦v1 共y兲其, slope of the value function to characterize the
y function x*( g). If v1(x) is differentiable at the
solution, then x*( g) satisfies the first-order
while if x ⬎ g* condition
(26) v 1 共x兲 ⫽ u共w共1 ⫺ r*兲, x兲

B共r*, x*; x兲
(29) ␦ v⬘1 共x兲 ⫽ 冉 1 ⫺ r共x, g兲
1 ⫺ r共x, g兲共1 ⫹ ␧兲 冊冉 冊 p
n
.

⫹ ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x*兲.
n This first-order condition reflects the fact that
any increase in public good investment must
As we will see, this value function is differen- be financed by an increase in taxes. Thus, the
tiable everywhere except at g ⫽ g*.22 Thus, by increase is worthwhile if and only if the per
the Envelope Theorem we have that if x ⬍ g* capita benefit of an additional unit of public
then good ␦ v⬘1 ( x) exceeds the per capita tax cost,
which is [(1 ⫺ r)/(1 ⫺ r(1 ⫹ ␧))]( p/n). The
(27) v⬘1 共x兲 ⫽ A ␣ x ␣ ⫺ 1 latter is the product of the per capita cost of
the public good and the marginal cost of
⫹ 冉 1 ⫺ r共x*共x兲, x兲
1 ⫺ r共x*共x兲, x兲共1 ⫹ ␧兲 冊冉 p共1 ⫺ d兲
n
, 冊 public funds.
There are three cases to be considered. The
first is that at g* the discounted right-hand de-
while if x ⬎ g* rivative of the value function exceeds the per
capita tax cost. In this case, ␦v⬘1(x) must equal
p共1 ⫺ d兲 the per capita tax cost in the minimum winning
(28) v⬘1 共x兲 ⫽ A ␣ x ␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹ . coalition range. Accordingly, x*( g) exceeds g*
n and satisfies the first-order condition
The equilibrium value function has a kink at g*
in the sense that the left-hand derivative limxmg*
v⬘1(x) exceeds the right-hand derivative limxng*

(30) ␦ A ␣ x ␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹
p(1 ⫺ d)
n 册
冉 冊冉 冊
v⬘1(x). This reflects the fact that the value of an
additional unit of public good is lower in the 1 ⫺ r(x, g) p
⫽ .
minimum winning coalition range. As in the 1 ⫺ r(x, g)(1 ⫹ ␧) n
planner’s problem, there are two sources of
future benefits from investing more in the public The second case is that at g* the left-hand
good. First, public good consumption is higher derivative of the value function is less than the
tax cost. In this case, ␦v⬘1(x) must equal the tax
22
As will be clear from the proof of Proposition 5, this
cost in the unanimous coalition range. Accord-
follows by standard arguments (see Nancy Stokey, Robert ingly, x*( g) is smaller than g* and satisfies the
Lucas, and Edward Prescott 1989). first-order condition
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 129


(31) ␦ A ␣ x ␣ ⫺ 1
The third possibility is that p/q lies between the
left- and right-hand derivatives of the value
function at g*, in which case we must have that

⫹ 冉 1 ⫺ r(x*(x), x)
1 ⫺ r(x*(x), x)(1 ⫹ ␧) 冊冉 冊册
p(1 ⫺ d)
n
x* ⫽ g*.

冉 冊冉 冊
B. The Three Types of Equilibrium
1 ⫺ r(x, g) p
⫽ .
1 ⫺ r(x, g)(1 ⫹ ␧) n We can now bring the information just ob-
tained about the function x*( g) and the public
The third case is that the tax cost lies between good level x* together with Proposition 1 to
the left- and right-hand derivatives of the value get a picture of how equilibrium plays out.
function at g*. In this case, we must have that There are three possibilities to be considered. In a
x*( g) ⫽ g*. Type I equilibrium, x* exceeds g*, so that if the
Turning to x*, if v 1 ( x) is differentiable at current level of the public good is in the minimum
the solution, then x* satisfies the first-order winning coalition range, the equilibrium invest-
condition ment decision will be such as to keep it there. In a
Type II equilibrium, x* is less than g*, so that in
p the minimum winning coalition range, the equi-
(32) ␦ v⬘1 共x兲 ⫽ . librium investment decision will be such as to put
q
the public good level back in the interior of the
This first-order condition reflects the fact that unanimity range. In a Type III equilibrium, x* is
any increase in public good investment simply equal to g* so that the equilibrium investment
reduces the amount of transfers received by the decision will be such as to put the public good
q representatives in the minimum winning coa- level back at the boundary of the two ranges. We
lition. Thus, the increase is worthwhile if and consider each in turn.
only if the per capita benefit of an additional
unit of public good ␦ v⬘1 ( x) exceeds the per Type I Equilibrium.—In this case, x* must
capita transfer cost to coalition members, which satisfy the first-order condition (33). Solving
is p/q. this implies that
There are again three cases. The first is that at

冢冉 冊冣
1/1 ⫺ ␣
g* the discounted right-hand derivative of the ␦ qA ␣
value function exceeds the transfer cost p/q. In (35) x* ⫽ .
q
this case, ␦v⬘1(x) must equal p/q in the minimum p 1 ⫺ ␦ (1 ⫺ d)
winning coalition range. Accordingly, x* ex- n
ceeds g* and satisfies the first-order condition
Furthermore, since B(x*, r*; g*) ⫽ 0, this im-

(33) 冋
␦ A␣x␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹
p(1 ⫺ d)
n
p
⫽ .
q 册 plies that

px* ⫺ R共r*兲
(36) g* ⫽ .
The second possibility is that the left-hand p共1 ⫺ d兲
derivative at g* is less than p/q. In this case,
␦ v⬘1 ( x) must equal the transfer cost in the This gives us closed-form solutions for x* and
unanimity range. Accordingly, x* must be g*. For this equilibrium to exist, the parameters
smaller than g* and must satisfy the first-order of the model must be such as to imply that x* is
condition indeed greater than g*, and we will give a
condition for this below.


(34) ␦ A ␣ x ␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹
It remains to describe the behavior of
x*( g). From (24) we know that at g ⫽ g* it
must be the case that x*( g) ⫽ x*. This im-

冉 冊冉 冊册
plies that the marginal cost curve for the
1 ⫺ r(x*(x), x) p(1 ⫺ d) p unanimity case [(1 ⫺ r( x, g*))/(1 ⫺ r( x,
⫽ .
1 ⫺ r(x*(x), x)(1 ⫹ ␧) n q g*)(1 ⫹ ␧))]( p/n) will equal p/q at x equal to
130 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

x*. Now define the public good levels ĝ and of the public good in the unanimity range.
g⬘ from the equations Lower initial levels of the public good shift
these lines to the left.


(37) ␦ A ␣ g* ␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹
p(1 ⫺ d)
n 册 The minimum winning coalition public good
level is determined by the intersection of the
marginal benefit curve and the curve p/q. Given

⫽ 冉 1 ⫺ r(g*, ĝ)
1 ⫺ r(g*, ĝ)(1 ⫹ ␧) 冊冉 冊
p
n
that x* exceeds g*, the intersection must occur
to the right of g* as illustrated. The function
x*( g) is determined by the intersection of the
marginal benefit and marginal tax cost curve
and [(1 ⫺ r(x, g)/(1 ⫺ r(x, g)(1 ⫹ ␧))](p/n). At g ⫽
g*, this intersection occurs at x*. As we

(38) ␦ A ␣ g* ␣ ⫺ 1
lower g, the marginal cost curve shifts left-
ward and we trace out successively lower
levels of x. In the interval [ g⬘, ĝ], lowering g

⫹ 冉 1 ⫺ r共x*, g*兲
1 ⫺ r(x*, g*)(1 ⫹ ␧) 冊冉 p(1 ⫺ d)
n 冊册 has no impact on the level of the public good
that is chosen. On the interval [0, g⬘], the
marginal cost curve intersects the upper

冉 冊冉 冊
1 ⫺ r(g*, g⬘) p branch of the marginal benefit curve, and
⫽ . x*( g) once again decreases as we lower the
1 ⫺ r(g*, g⬘)(1 ⫹ ␧) n initial level of the public good.
Panel B of Figure 2 uses this information
Observe that g⬘ ⬍ ĝ ⬍ g*. about x*( g) and x* to graph the equilibrium
On the interval [ ĝ, g*], x*( g) is implicitly level of x as a function of the state variable g.
defined by the first-order condition (30). It is This curve intersects the 45° line at x*. It is
increasing in g and exceeds g*. Effectively, in apparent from this figure that, from any initial
this part of the unanimity range, the public good condition, the equilibrium level of the public
is sufficiently valuable that the aggregate utility good converges monotonically to the steady
of the legislators is maximized by choosing a state x*. The steady-state tax rate is r*. In the
level of investment that will induce pork to be steady state, the proposer raises more revenue
distributed in the next period. On the interval than necessary to maintain the public good level
[ g⬘, ĝ], x*( g) is constant and equal to g*. Here at x*, and this revenue is used to finance pork.
the proposer is deterred from investing more Thus, we have:
than g* because it will result in a minimum
winning coalition solution in the next period. PROPOSITION 2: Let {r ␶ ( g), s ␶ ( g),
Finally, on the interval [0, g⬘], x*( g) is im- x ␶ ( g)} ␶T ⫽ 1 be a Type I equilibrium. Then, the
plicitly defined by the first-order condition (31) equilibrium level of the public good and tax rate
and is less than g*. In this range, the pro- converge monotonically to the steady state (r*,
poser chooses the level of investment that (␦qA␣/p(1 ⫺ (q/n)␦(1 ⫺ d)))1/1⫺ ␣). In this steady
maximizes aggregate legislator utility knowing state, in each period the districts of a mini-
that in the next period the proposer will do the mum winning coalition of representatives receive
same. pork.
The situation is illustrated in Figure 2. In
panel A the vertical axis measures units of con- Type II Equilibrium.—If x* is less than g*, it
sumption and the horizontal axis measures units must be the case that x* satisfies the first-order
of x. The downward-sloping line with the dis- condition (34). This is not a closed-form solu-
continuity at g* is ␦v⬘1(x) and hence represents tion for x*, since it depends upon x*( x*). Turn-
the per capita benefit of an additional unit of the ing to x*( g), we know from (24) that at g ⫽ g*
public good. The horizontal line p/q represents it must be the case that x*( g) ⫽ x*. On the
the per capita marginal cost in the minimum interval [0, g*], x*( g) is implicitly defined by
winning coalition range. The upward-sloping the first-order condition (31). It is increasing
convex lines [(1 ⫺ r(x, g))/(1 ⫺ r(x, g)(1 ⫹ over this range and thus less than g*. Accord-
␧))](p/n) represent the per capita marginal cost ingly, the proposer chooses the optimal level of
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 131

FIGURE 2. TYPE I EQUILIBRIUM: x* ⬎ g*

investment knowing that in the next period the g*, the intersection of the marginal benefit
proposer will also be maximizing aggregate leg- curve and the curve p/q must occur to the left of
islator utility. g* as illustrated. The function x*( g) is deter-
The situation is illustrated in Figure 3. The mined by the intersection of the marginal ben-
interpretation of the various curves in panel A efit curve and the marginal cost curve [(1 ⫺ r(x,
are as for Figure 2A. Given that x* is less than g))/(1 ⫺ r(x, g)(1 ⫹ ␧))](p/n). At g ⫽ g*, this
132 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

FIGURE 3. TYPE II EQUILIBRIUM: x* ⬍ g*

intersection occurs at x*. As we lower g, the level of x as a function of the initial public good
marginal cost curve shifts leftward and we trace level g. This curve intersects the 45° line at x̂. It
out successively lower levels of x. is apparent from this figure that, from any initial
Panel B of Figure 3 uses this information level of the public good, the equilibrium con-
about x*( g) and x* to graph the equilibrium verges monotonically to the steady state x̂. The
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 133

steady-state tax rate is r̂ ⫽ r(x̂, x̂). The steady imum winning coalition solution being se-
state (r̂, x̂) involves no pork and satisfies lected in the next period. On the interval [0,
g⬘], x*( g) is implicitly defined by the first-


(39) ␦ A ␣ x̂ ␣ ⫺ 1
order condition (31) and is less than g*. In
this range, the proposer chooses the optimal
level of investment, knowing that in the next

⫹ 冉 1 ⫺ r̂
1 ⫺ r̂(1 ⫹ ␧) 冊冉 p(1 ⫺ d)
n 冊册 period the proposer will also be maximizing
aggregate legislator utility.
The situation is illustrated in Figure 4. Given

冉 冊冉 冊
that x* equals g*, the curve p/q must intersect
1 ⫺ r̂ p the marginal benefit curve at the point of dis-
⫽ .
1 ⫺ r̂(1 ⫹ ␧) n continuity, as illustrated in panel A. The mar-
ginal cost curve for the unanimity case [(1 ⫺
It follows from (16) that (r̂, x̂) must equal the r(x, g*))/(1 ⫺ r(x, g*)(1 ⫹ ␧))](p/n) will equal
planner’s steady state. This yields: p/q at x equal to g*. As we lower g, the marginal
cost curve shifts leftward but on the interval [ g⬘,
PROPOSITION 3: Let {r␶( g), s␶( g), x␶( g)}␶T⫽1 g*] this has no impact on the level of the public
be a Type II equilibrium. Then, the equilibrium good that is chosen. On the interval [0, g⬘], the
level of the public good and tax rate converge marginal cost curve intersects the upper branch
monotonically to the planner’s steady state of the marginal benefit curve and x*( g) de-
(r o , x o ). creases as the initial level of the public good is
lowered.
Type III Equilibrium.—If x* is equal to g*, it Panel B of Figure 4 graphs the equilibrium
must be the case that level of x as a function of the initial public good
level g. This curve intersects the 45° line at g*.
p It is apparent from this figure that from any
(40) lim ␦v⬘1 共x兲 ⱖ ⱖ lim ␦v⬘1 共x兲.
xmg* q xng* initial condition the equilibrium converges
monotonically to the steady state g*. The
Moreover, since B(x*, r*; g*) ⫽ 0, we can steady-state tax rate is r*, which also equals
solve the budget equation to obtain r( g*, g*). This steady state involves no pork,
but is not the planner’s steady state. Thus we
R共r*兲 have:
(41) x* ⫽ g* ⫽ .
pd PROPOSITION 4: Let {r␶( g), s␶( g), x␶( g)}␶T ⫽ 1
be a Type III equilibrium. Then, the equilibrium
Turning to x*( g), we know that at g ⫽ g* it levels of the public good and tax rate converge
must be the case that x*( g) ⫽ g*. Now define monotonically to the steady state (r*, [R(r*)/
the public good level g⬘ from the equation pd]). In this steady state, no districts receive
pork.


(42) ␦ A ␣ g* ␣ ⫺ 1
C. Existence, Uniqueness, and Multiplicity

⫹ 冉 1 ⫺ r(g*, g*)
1 ⫺ r(g*, g*)(1 ⫹ ␧) 冊冉 p(1 ⫺ d)
n 冊册 of Equilibria

The foregoing analysis has provided a com-

冉 冊冉 冊
plete characterization of equilibrium. It has
1 ⫺ r(g*, g⬘) p shown that there are three possible types of
⫽ .
1 ⫺ r(g*, g⬘)(1 ⫹ ␧) n equilibrium and has described the dynamics
of the equilibrium policy proposals in each
It is the case that g⬘ ⬍ g*. On the interval case. Moreover, it solved for the steady-state
[ g⬘, g*], x*( g) is constant and equal to g*. levels of public goods and taxes in each case.
Here the proposer is deterred from investing It remains to establish the conditions under
more than g* because it will result in a min- which each type of equilibrium exists. There
134 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

FIGURE 4. TYPE III EQUILIBRIUM: x* ⫽ g*

are two main questions of interest. First, does public good in the minimum winning coalition
an equilibrium always exist and, second, is it range equal to p/q at R(r*)/pd, that is,

冋 冉 冊
possible that two or more types of equilibria

␣⫺1
can coexist? R共r*兲 p(1 ⫺ d) p
Recall that A parameterizes the value of the (43) ␦ A␣ ⫹ ⫽ .
pd n q
public good to the citizens. Define A to be the
value of A that makes the marginal benefit of the Similarly, let A be the value of A that makes
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 135

the marginal benefit of the public good in the parts. One part is deterministic and directly af-
unanimity range equal to p/q at R(r*)/pd, that fects the proposer’s future utility: investing in
is, an additional unit of public good generates a
benefit of A ␣ g ␣ ⫺ 1 in the following period,

冋 冉 冊 冉 冊
␣⫺1
R(r*) 1 ⫺ r* independently of the behavior of other repre-
(44) ␦ A␣ ⫹ sentatives. But the other part depends on the
pd 1 ⫺ r*(1 ⫹ ␧)
strategy used by representatives in the future.

冉 冊册
If the representatives in the future are “virtu-
p(1 ⫺ d) p
⫻ ⫽ . ous,” they respond to the reduced need to
n q invest in the public good by imposing a lower
tax rate. If they are not virtuous, they respond
Notice that A must be less than A since, holding by increasing pork-barrel spending. Virtuous
constant preferences, the marginal benefit of the behavior increases the incentives to invest in
public good is higher in the unanimity range. the public good and, in this way, is self-
Then we have the following result: reinforcing.

PROPOSITION 5: (i) If A 僆 (0, A ) there is a IV. Implications of the Model


unique equilibrium and this equilibrium is a
Type I equilibrium. The results of the previous section provide a
complete picture of what political equilibrium
(ii) If A ⬎ A there is a unique equilibrium and looks like. In this section, we draw out some of
this equilibrium is a Type II equilibrium. the implications of the model. We first discuss
what it tells us about the efficiency of legislative
(iii) If A 僆 (A, A ) there are three equilibria, policymaking and then turn to some of its pos-
one of each type. itive implications.

Thus, there always exists an equilibrium and, A. The Efficiency of Political Equilibrium
for a range of the parameter space, all three
types of equilibria discussed above coexist.23 To understand the model’s implications con-
Multiple equilibria arise because there are cerning efficiency, we will focus on a compar-
complementarities between the public good de- ison of the equilibrium and planner’s steady
cisions of different proposers in different peri- states. We will refer to the steady-state levels of
ods.24 Consider a proposer deciding whether to the public good and tax rate in the planner’s
use p units of tax revenue to purchase an addi- solution as “the efficient levels.” This is moti-
tional unit of the public good or to finance pork vated by the fact that the planner’s solution is
for the districts of a minimum winning coalition the unique Pareto-efficient policy sequence in
of representatives. The gain from the latter strat- the set of policy sequences that provide all
egy is p/q. As already noted, the gain from the citizens with the same expected payoff. Since
former strategy can be decomposed into two all citizens have the same expected payoff in
political equilibrium, divergencies between
equilibrium and planner’s steady states repre-
23
When A ⫽ A, there are two equilibria, one of Type I
and one of Type III. As A approaches A from above, the sent Pareto inefficiencies and thereby constitute
Type II equilibrium converges to the Type III equilibrium at “political failures” in the sense defined by Bes-
A. Similarly, when A ⫽ A there are two equilibria, one of ley and Coate (1998).
Type II and one of Type III and, as A approaches A from We begin by understanding how the equilib-
below, the Type I equilibrium converges to the Type III
equilibrium at A.
rium steady state differs from the planner’s in
24
Indeed, these complementarities make it somewhat the three types of equilibrium. For the Type I
surprising that the equilibrium is unique (at least in the class equilibrium we can show:
of symmetric Markov equilibria with concave value func-
tions) for a range of the parameter space (i.e., (0, A) 艛 (A, LEMMA 1: Let {r␶( g), s␶( g), x␶( g)}␶T ⫽ 1 be a
⬁)). This finding complements previous research in the
legislative bargaining literature that has provided unique-
Type I equilibrium. Then, the steady-state pub-
ness results for Baron and Ferejohn’s (1989) static model lic good level is below the efficient level. More-
(Eraslan 2002). over, the steady-state tax rate is above the
136 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

efficient level if A 僆 (0, A) and below it if A 僆 reducing taxes because of the deadweight cost
(A, A). of taxation.
Combining the results of Lemmas 1 and 2
Thus, public goods are always underprovided in and Propositions 2 to 5, the efficiency implica-
this type of equilibrium, but the overall size of tions of the model can be summarized as
government as measured by the tax rate may be follows:26
below or above the efficient level. When A 僆
(0, A) this type of equilibrium reflects well the PROPOSITION 6: If A ⬍ A, the steady-state
conventional wisdom concerning legislative de- equilibrium tax rate is too high and the steady-
cision making. Namely, it results in government state equilibrium level of public goods is too
being too large in the sense that taxes are higher low. If A ⬎ A, then the steady-state equilibrium
than the efficient level and, in addition, that is efficient. If A 僆 (A, A), the steady-state
these tax revenues are misallocated, with public equilibrium could be efficient or inefficient. If it
goods being underprovided and pork being is inefficient, there are two possibilities. In the
overprovided. When A 僆 ( A, A ) (and we are in first, the tax rate will be too low but revenues
a Type I equilibrium), the picture differs from will be allocated efficiently. In the second, the
the conventional one because government is tax rate will also be too low and some revenues
below its efficient scale, although revenues are will be used to finance pork.
still misallocated to pork.
We know from Proposition 2, that for the What are the basic reasons for the inefficien-
Type II equilibrium, the equilibrium and effi- cies in policymaking that can arise in the
cient steady states coincide. This just leaves the model? Four factors are crucial in the sense that,
Type III equilibrium, for which we can estab- without them, the equilibrium policy choices
lish: would be Pareto efficient. The first is majori-
tarian decision making. With unanimity (i.e.,
LEMMA 2: Let {r␶( g), s␶( g), x␶( g)}␶T ⫽ 1 be a q ⫽ n), it is the case that A ⫽ A ⫽ 0, which
Type III equilibrium. Then, the steady-state implies that the political equilibrium is always
public good level is below the efficient level if efficient.27 Majoritarian decision making allows
A 僆 (A, A]. legislative coalitions to benefit their districts at
the expense of noncoalition members. The sec-
Since there is no pork in the Type III equilib- ond is the availability of distributive policies,
rium, this result implies that the overall size of i.e., policies whose benefits can be targeted nar-
government is below optimal.25 The nature of rowly and whose costs are financed centrally. If
the inefficiency therefore differs completely there were no such policies, there would be no
from that suggested by the conventional wis- way for majoritarian coalitions to transfer
dom. Not only is government too small, but wealth to themselves. The third factor is polit-
available tax revenues are allocated efficiently. ical uncertainty arising from the random allo-
The legislature is not willing to choose a public cation of proposal power. If the proposer was
good level higher than g* because they know constant over time, the political equilibrium
that the public good level will go back down to would certainly differ from the planner’s solu-
g* the next period, so there will be only one tion, but it would be Pareto efficient. In particular,
period of additional public good consumption. it would not be possible to make the citizens in the
Moreover, the extra revenues that will be saved
by not having to purchase as much public good
in the next period will just be spent on transfers
rather than reducing taxes. Spending on trans- 26
When A ⫽ A, the steady-state equilibrium could be
fers is less efficient in an ex ante sense than efficient or inefficient. If it is inefficient, the tax rate equals
the efficient level, but some revenues are used to finance
pork. Similarly, when A ⫽ A, the steady-state equilibrium
could be efficient or inefficient. If it is inefficient, the tax
25
A Type III equilibrium exists for all A 僆 [ A, A ]. rate will be too low, but revenues will be allocated effi-
When A ⫽ A, the steady-state public good level is efficient. ciently.
Since there is no pork, the equilibrium and efficient steady 27
Indeed, generally there will exist some critical q̃ ⬍ n
states coincide in this case. such that if q ⱖ q̃, legislative policymaking is efficient.
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 137

proposer’s district better off. The final factor is cient equilibria not only when the depreciation
lack of commitment. The inefficiencies in both the of public goods is high, but also when there is
Type I and III equilibria could be resolved by sustained technological progress that favors
Coasian bargaining between present and future high long-run levels of public good invest-
legislators. Such Coasian bargains are not ments.
possible, however, because the identity of Under what circumstances is the political
future legislators is not clear, and even if it equilibrium more likely to be inefficient? Prop-
were, future promises would not be credible. osition 6 suggests that a feel for this can be
In interpreting Proposition 6, it is important obtained by studying how the critical public
not to oversimplify the conclusions concerning good preference thresholds A and A depend
the role of the public good taste parameter A. It upon the underlying parameters. Ceteris pari-
may seem unsurprising that when A is high bus, factors that serve to raise A and A make
enough, the political equilibrium is efficient. inefficiency more likely. The relevant parame-
After all, the higher the benefit of the public ters of interest are the discount rate ␦, the price
good, the higher is the incentive to invest in it, of the public good p, the rate of depreciation d,
independently of the decision-making process. and the size of the majority required to pass
In our model, however, the consequences of A legislation q. Also of interest is the elasticity of
for efficiency are indirect and more subtle than labor supply ␧. When analyzing this, however,
this. In a static model, the marginal benefit of one must recognize that the laissez-faire na-
the public good necessarily depends only on the tional income at wage w is nw(␧w)␧, and hence
exogenous parameters such as A: a high enough raising the elasticity of labor supply ␧ increases
level of A would imply that the marginal benefit the size of the tax base. To circumvent this, we
of g is higher than the marginal benefit of pork consider compensated changes in the elasticity,
transfers, and therefore that all tax revenues i.e., changes in ␧ compensated by changes in w
would be used for g. But in our dynamic model, that leave the size of the tax base constant. We
the marginal benefit of investing in the public now have:
good is endogenous because it depends on the
level accumulated in previous periods. As A PROPOSITION 7: An increase in the price of
becomes higher, the long-run level of the public the public good p or the economy’s wage rate w
good increases as more accumulation takes induces an increase in A and A, while an
place: this compensates for the higher level of A increase in either the discount rate ␦ or the
by reducing the marginal benefit of investment. required majority q induces a decrease in A and
For this reason, a high absolute value of A is not A. A compensated increase in the elasticity of
sufficient to guarantee that the equilibrium level labor supply ␧ also induces a decrease in A
of the public good is efficient. For example, as and A.
the depreciation rate d converges to 0, both A
and A converge to infinity (see the proof of Thus, political equilibrium is more likely to
Proposition 7). Thus, the equilibrium is ineffi- be inefficient when citizens are more impatient,
cient when d is very small, irrespective of the public goods are more expensive, and the pri-
level of A. This reflects the fact that when d is vate sector is more productive. On the other
very small, if the equilibrium were efficient, hand, equilibrium is more likely to be efficient
there would be almost no investment in g and when supermajorities are required to pass tax
therefore close to zero taxes in the steady state. and spending bills and when the elasticity of
But this cannot happen because when taxes are labor supply is high. The latter result is partic-
close to zero the marginal deadweight cost of ularly interesting and reflects the logic that
taxation is close to zero, so it would always be when tax revenues are more costly to raise, they
optimal to raise taxes to fund pork-barrel trans- will be less likely to be squandered on pork.
fers. In the steady state, therefore, we have an The proposition does not speak to the impact
efficient equilibrium only when the long-run of an increase in the depreciation rate because it
level of investment is high enough to imply that is ambiguous. While A and A are decreasing in
the (endogenous) deadweight cost of taxation is d for sufficiently small d, the derivatives may
higher than the marginal benefit of pork trans- switch sign at larger d. There are two interesting
fers. This suggests that we should expect effi- facts to note, however, about the depreciation
138 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

rate. First, as noted above, as d converges to 0, the legislature ramps up investment in the pub-
both A and A converge to infinity. Thus, the lic good.
equilibrium must be inefficient when d is very A second interesting implication concerns the
small and the inefficiency takes the conven- elasticity of labor supply. Consider two societ-
tional form in which the steady state tax rate is ies that differ only in the elasticity of their
too high and revenues are misallocated to pork. citizens’ labor supply (␧0 and ␧1) and their wage
Second, when d ⫽ 1, A ⫽ A and the third type levels (w0 and w1). Suppose the wage levels
of equilibrium cannot arise. This reflects the across the two communities are such as to make
fact that there is no difference between the the size of the laissez-faire national income the
marginal benefit of investment in the unanimity same (i.e., w0(␧0w0)␧0 equals w1(␧1w1)␧1). Fi-
and minimum winning coalition ranges when nally, suppose that in both societies, the steady
depreciation is 100 percent. In particular, in- state involves underprovision of the public good
vesting more in the public good leads to no tax and excessive taxation (i.e., A ⬍ min{A 0, A1}).
or transfer changes in the next period, because Then, the steady-state level of public goods will
none of the extra investment carries over to the be the same in both societies, but the tax rate
next period. Moreover, Assumption 1 implies will be lower in the society with a higher elas-
that when d ⫽ 1, A ⬎ A, meaning that the ticity of labor supply. Thus, the citizens in the
equilibrium must be efficient.28 society with the low elasticity would be better
off with the public good–tax rate pair that arises
B. Some Positive Implications in the society with the high elasticity.29 In this
sense, societies where citizens have a high elas-
The first interesting positive implication of ticity of labor supply will have better-quality
the model concerns the dynamics of legislative governments.
coalitions. Consider the case in which A ⬍ A so Finally, consider the implications of an in-
that the steady state involves underprovision of crease in the productivity of the private sector as
the public good and overtaxation. In the steady measured by the wage rate w. Assuming that the
state, budgets will be approved only by a min- steady state involves pork, an increase in w has
imum winning coalition of representatives. As- no impact on the size of government as mea-
suming, however, that the economy started out sured by the tax rate, nor on the steady-state
with a sufficiently low level of the public good, level of the public good. Because tax revenues
in the early phases of governance as the public are higher, however, the amount of pork is
good was accumulated, the legislature would increased and the quality of government is
not have engaged in distributive policymaking lower. Compare this with the implications of an
and budgets would have been approved unani- increase in the productivity of public spending
mously. Thus, the model suggests that we might as measured by A. Again, assuming that the
observe a decline over time in both the quality steady state involves pork, a small increase in A
of government and the degree of consensus in has no impact on the size of government, but
the legislature. Relatedly, starting from a steady does increase the quality of government by rais-
state in which budgets are passed by minimum ing the level of the public good. Thus, increases
winning coalitions, if the value of the public in private productivity worsen the quality of
good increases very dramatically (for example, government, while increases in public produc-
as result of a new military threat), we would tivity improve it.
expect to see a shift to unanimous coalitions as
V. Conclusion

This paper has presented an infinite-horizon


28
In assuming that public investment increases the rev- model of public spending and taxation in
enue available for redistribution in the next period, Leblanc, which policy decisions are made by a legislature
Snyder, and Tripathi (2000) effectively assume that d ⫽ 1.
Moreover, their assumption that the pool of available rev-
29
enue the legislature has available is always sufficient to The public good–tax rate pair in the high-elasticity
finance the surplus-maximizing level of investment (29) is society will necessarily be feasible for the low-elasticity
the exact opposite of Assumption 1. This explains why their society, because the tax rate will yield more tax revenues in
model has a unique inefficient equilibrium. the low elasticity society.
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 139

consisting of representatives from geographi- spending. This behavior yields an equilibrium


cally defined districts. In each period, policies with no distributive policymaking and an over-
are determined by legislative bargaining. The all size of government that is below optimal.
model incorporates both productive and distrib- The model also yields some interesting pos-
utive public spending and distortionary taxa- itive implications. First, it suggests that when
tion. The dynamic linkage across policymaking the need for public goods is acute, the legisla-
periods is created by the fact that the productive ture will approve its budgets by unanimity, but
spending has long-run benefits. Despite the fact as the need for public investment is saturated,
that the policy space is quite rich, the model is the political equilibrium will shift to a regime of
tractable. Key to this tractability is that, distrib- minimal winning coalitions. Thus, the size of
utive policies notwithstanding, all citizens are the legislative coalitions passing budgets may
ex ante identical at the beginning of each decline over time as a country builds up its
period so equilibrium can be summarized by a stock of public goods. Second, the model sug-
single value function. This permits a particu- gests that societies in which citizens have a
larly clean analysis of the welfare properties of more elastic labor supply will enjoy better qual-
equilibrium. ity governments. A higher elasticity of labor
The welfare analysis sheds new light on the supply reduces distributive policies but not the
efficiency of politically determined policy long-run levels of public goods. Finally, the
choices. First, it provides a rigorous formal un- model suggests that the quality of government
derpinning for the conventional wisdom that as measured by the proportion of revenues
legislatures, in which representatives are elected devoted to distributive policies is inversely
by geographically defined districts, will produce correlated with the productivity of the private
a long-run size of government that is too large sector.
and long-run levels of national public goods that There are many ways in which the model
are too low. Proposition 7 provides conditions might usefully be developed.30 Perhaps the
under which this is the unique outcome. most important task is to incorporate govern-
Roughly speaking, these conditions require that ment borrowing. To maintain tractability, one
the taxable capacity of the economy is large could simplify the model by assuming that the
enough to easily meet the needs of maintaining public good was not durable but allow the
an adequate level of public goods. legislature to finance spending by a combina-
The analysis also shows, however, that the tion of taxation and issuing public debt. Debt
conventional wisdom needs qualification. When would then form the dynamic linkage across
the economy’s taxable capacity is small relative periods. In this context, it would be natural to
to its public good needs, legislative decisions assume that the per-period value of public
will actually be efficient in the long run. Legis- goods was stochastic (reflecting, for example,
lators will not choose to redistribute to their wars or terrorist threats), and to study how
districts when maintaining public good levels debt, spending, and taxation responded to
requires a level of taxation that creates signifi- shocks. This would facilitate a political econ-
cant distortions in the economy. Moreover, the omy investigation of the normative theory of
direction of the distortions emerging from leg- debt and taxation suggested by Robert Barro
islative choice could be the opposite from that (1979).
suggested by the conventional wisdom. Specif-
ically, legislators can hold back on public good
spending in the belief that accumulating too 30
It might also be interesting to incorporate into the
large a stock of these goods will lead future framework the alternative “demand bargaining” approach to
legislators to start engaging in pork-barrel legislative policymaking suggested by Morelli (1999).
140 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

APPENDIX

PROOF OF PROPOSITION 1:
To prove the result, we will need some additional notation. For any strictly concave function v(x),
consider the problem for all ␮ 僆 [0, ⬁):

(A1) max ␮关u共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦v共x兲兴 ⫹ B共r, x; g兲


兵r,x其

s.t. B共r, x; g兲 ⱖ 0.

Interpreting v(x) as the expected payoff with x units of the public good, the problem is to maximize
the aggregate utility of ␮ legislators under the assumption that any revenue that is not used for
investment in the public good is used to finance pork in these legislators’ districts. Under the
assumption that v is strictly concave, there is a unique solution to this problem given by r( g; ␮, v)
and x( g; ␮, v).
Note the following facts about this problem. First, for ␮ sufficiently small, the solution will
involve a positive budget surplus (i.e., B(r, x; g) ⬎ 0). Second, for ␮ sufficiently large, the optimal
tax rate will be such that all tax revenues are used to finance investment in the public good and hence
B(r, x; g) ⫽ 0. Third, if it is the case that for some ␮˜ it is optimal to select a tax rate–public good
pair such that all revenues are used for investment (i.e., B(r, x; g) ⫽ 0), then this must also be optimal
for all ␮ ⬎ ␮˜ .
Now define ␮( g; v) to be the size of the smallest group of legislators who would choose to devote
all revenues to investment. Formally,

␮ 共g; v兲 ⫽ min兵␮ 僆 关0, ⬁兲 : B共r共g; ␮, v兲, x共g; ␮, v兲; g兲 ⫽ 0其.

Then, all groups of legislators of size less than ␮(g; v) would devote some revenues to pork and all
larger groups would devote all revenues to investment. It should be noted that ␮(g; v) exists and is
unique for all g. We now have:

LEMMA A.1: Let {r␶( g), s␶( g), x␶( g)}␶T⫽1 be an equilibrium with associated payoff function v1( g):
(i ) If ␮ ( g; v 1 ) ⱕ q, then (r ␶ ( g), s ␶ ( g), x ␶ ( g)) ⫽ (r( g; n, v1), 0, x( g; n, v1)) for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T.
(ii) If ␮( g; v1) ⬎ q, then (r␶( g), x␶( g)) ⫽ (r( g; q, v1), x( g; q, v1)) for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T, and

s ␶ 共g兲 ⫽ 再 B(r(g; q, v 1 ), x(g; q, v 1 ); g)


n
for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T ⫺ 1
v T ⫹ 1 (g) ⫺ u(w(1 ⫺ r(g; q, v 1 )), g) ⫺ ␦ v 1 (x(g; q, v 1 )) for ␶⫽T
.

PROOF OF LEMMA A.1:


We begin by considering the problem of the proposer in the final round T. From the discussion in
the text, we know that (rT( g), sT( g), xT( g)) must solve the round T proposer’s problem

max关u共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ B共r, x; g兲 ⫺ 共q ⫺ 1兲s ⫹ ␦v1 共x兲兴


共r,s,x兲

s.t. u共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ s ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x兲 ⱖ v T ⫹ 1 共g兲,

B共r, x; g兲 ⱖ 共q ⫺ 1兲s, and s ⱖ 0,

where vT ⫹ 1( g) ⫽ max(r, x){u(w(1 ⫺ r), g) ⫹ [B(r, x; g)/n] ⫹ ␦v1(x) : B(r, x; g) ⱖ 0}. In a Technical
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 141

Appendix available on this journal’s Web site (http//:www.e-aer.org/data/mar07/20050737_app.pdf),


we establish the following result:31

Claim A.1.—Let (rT, sT, xT) solve the round T proposer’s problem. Then (rT, xT) solves problem
(A1) with ␮ ⫽ q and v ⫽ v1. In addition, sT ⫽ vT ⫹ 1( g) ⫺ ␦v1(xT) ⫺ u(w(1 ⫺ rT), g).

It follows from this that if ␮( g; v1) ⱕ q, then (rT( g), sT( g), xT( g)) equals (r( g; n, v1), 0, x( g; n, v1)),
while if ␮( g; v1) ⬎ q, then (rT( g), sT( g), xT( g)) equals

共r共g; q, v 1 兲, v T ⫹ 1 共g兲 ⫺ u共w共1 ⫺ r共g; q, v 1 兲兲, g兲 ⫺ ␦ v 1 共x共g; q, v 1 兲兲, x共g; q, v 1 兲兲.

Now consider the round T ⫺ 1 proposer’s problem

max关u共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ B共r, x; g兲 ⫺ 共q ⫺ 1兲s ⫹ ␦v1 共x兲兴


共r,s,x兲

s.t. u共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ s ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x兲 ⱖ v T 共g兲,

B共r, x; g兲 ⱖ 共q ⫺ 1兲s, and s ⱖ 0.

If ␮( g; v1) ⱕ q, then we know that

v T 共g兲 ⫽ u共w共1 ⫺ r共g; n, v 1 兲兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x共g; n, v 1 兲兲 ⫽ v T ⫹ 1 共g兲,

so applying the exact same logic as above implies that the solution to the round T ⫺ 1 proposer’s
problem is (r( g; n, v1), 0, x( g; n, v1)). Repeated application of the same logic implies that the solution
to the proposer’s problem is (r( g; n, v1), 0, x( g; n, v1)) in all earlier proposal rounds.
On the other hand, if ␮( g; v1) ⬎ q then we know that

B共r共g; q, v 1 兲, x共g; q, v 1 兲; g兲
v T 共g兲 ⫽ u共w共1 ⫺ r共g; q, v 1 兲兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x共g; q, v 1 兲兲 ⫹ .
n

So we need to show that the solution to the round T ⫺ 1 proposer’s problem with this level of
reservation utility is

冉 r共g; q, v 1 兲,
B(r(g; q, v 1 ), x(g; q, v 1 ); g)
n 冊
, x(g; q, v 1 ) .

Let (rT ⫺ 1, sT ⫺ 1, xT ⫺ 1) denote the solution. It is straightforward to show the desired result if sT ⫺ 1 ⬎
0, so we need only rule out the possibility that sT ⫺ 1 ⫽ 0. If sT ⫺ 1 ⫽ 0, it must be the case that B(rT ⫺ 1,
xT ⫺ 1; g) ⬎ 0 and that (rT ⫺ 1, xT ⫺ 1) solves the problem

max u共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦v1 共x兲 ⫹ B共r, x; g兲

s.t. u共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x兲 ⱖ v T 共g兲.

31
A technical appendix with complete proofs is also available in Battaglini and Coate (2005).
142 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

Now consider the proposal


共r⬘, s⬘, x⬘兲 ⫽ r(g; q, v 1 ),
B(r(g; q, v 1 ), x(g; q, v 1 ); g)
n 冊
, x(g; q, v 1 ) .

The payoff to the proposer under the policy (r⬘, s⬘, x⬘) is

(A2) q关u共w共1 ⫺ r⬘兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x⬘兲兴 ⫹ B共r⬘, x⬘; g兲 ⫺ 共q ⫺ 1兲v T 共g兲.

But we know that u(w(1 ⫺ rT ⫺ 1), g) ⫹ ␦v1(xT ⫺ 1) ⱖ vT( g), and hence a lower bound of (A2) is

q关u共w共1 ⫺ r⬘兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x⬘兲兴 ⫹ B共r⬘, x⬘; g兲 ⫺ 共q ⫺ 1兲关u共w共1 ⫺ r T ⫺ 1 兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x T ⫺ 1 兲兴.

The payoff to the proposer under the optimal policy (rT ⫺ 1, 0, xT ⫺ 1) is given by

u共w共1 ⫺ r T ⫺ 1 兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x T ⫺ 1 兲 ⫹ B共r T ⫺ 1 , x T ⫺ 1 ; g兲.


It must be the case that

u共w共1 ⫺ r T ⫺ 1 兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x T ⫺ 1 兲 ⫹ B共r T ⫺ 1 , x T ⫺ 1 ; g兲 ⬎ q关u共w共1 ⫺ r⬘兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x⬘兲兴

⫹ B共r⬘, x⬘; g兲 ⫺ 共q ⫺ 1兲关u共w共1 ⫺ r T ⫺ 1 兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x T ⫺ 1 兲兴,


which implies that

q关u共w共1 ⫺ r T ⫺ 1 兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x T ⫺ 1 兲兴 ⫹ B共r T ⫺ 1 , x T ⫺ 1 ; g兲

⬎ q关u共w共1 ⫺ r⬘兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦ v 1 共x⬘兲兴 ⫹ B共r⬘, x⬘; g兲.

This contradicts the fact that (r⬘, x⬘) ⫽ (r( g; q, v1), x( g; q, v1)).
Repeated application of the same logic implies that the solution to the proposer’s problem is

冉 r(g; q, v 1 ),
B(r(g; q, v 1 ), x(g; q, v 1 ); g)
n
, x(g; q, v 1 ) 冊
in all earlier proposal rounds. This completes the proof of Lemma A.1.
Lemma A.1 tells us what equilibrium proposals must look like. The next step is to develop
expressions for (r( g; n, v1), x( g; n, v1)) and (r( g; q, v1), x( g; q, v1)). If ␮( g; v1) ⱕ q, then it must
be the case that B(r( g; n, v1), x( g; n, v1); g) ⫽ 0. It follows that we can write

共r共g; n, v 1 兲, x共g; n, v 1 兲兲 ⫽ 共r共x*共g兲, g兲, x*共g兲兲,

where r( x, g) is the tax rate function from the analysis of the planner’s problem, and

x*共g兲 ⫽ arg max兵u共w共1 ⫺ r共x, g兲兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦v1 共x兲其.


x

If ␮( g; v1) ⬎ q, then B(r( g; q, v1), x( g; q, v1); g) ⬎ 0 and hence (r( g; q, v1), x( g; q, v1)) must solve
the unconstrained problem

(A3) max q关u共w共1 ⫺ r兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦v1 共x兲兴 ⫹ B共r, x; g兲.


共r,x兲

Notice that the solutions to this problem are independent of g and thus we denote them by (r*, x*).
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 143

To complete the proof of the proposition, it remains only to show that there exists a unique g* ⬎
0 such that ␮( g; v1) ⱕ q for all g ⱕ g* and ␮( g; v1) ⬎ q for all g ⬎ g*. In the on-line Appendix
we prove that ␮( 䡠 ; v1) is an increasing and continuous function. We also show that ␮(0; v1) ⬍ q,
and for g large enough ␮( g; v1) ⬎ q. From these properties it follows that there exists a unique g*
⬎ 0 such that ␮( g*; v1) ⫽ q. Because ␮( 䡠 ; v1) is increasing, this g* will have the property that for
all g ⱕ g*, ␮( g; v1) ⱕ q and for all g ⬎ g*, ␮( g; v1) ⬎ q. Thus, the proof of Proposition 1 is
complete.

PROOF OF PROPOSITION 5:
The proof will proceed in two parts. First, we develop necessary and sufficient conditions for the
existence of an equilibrium of each of the three types. Then we analyze when these conditions will
be satisfied, relating them to A and A.

Existence of a Type I Equilibrium.—From the analysis preceding Proposition 2, in this case we


have that

冢冉 冊冣
1/1 ⫺ ␣
␦ qA ␣
x* ⫽
q
p 1 ⫺ ␦ (1 ⫺ d)
n

and that g* ⫽ [ px* ⫺ R(r*)/p(1 ⫺ d)]. It then follows that x* ⬎ g* if and only if

冢冉 冊冣
1/1 ⫺ ␣
R共r*兲 ␦ qA ␣
(A4) ⬎ .
pd q
p 1 ⫺ ␦ (1 ⫺ d)
n

This inequality is therefore a necessary condition for the existence of a Type I equilibrium.
In such an equilibrium, if g ⬎ g*, then the legislature will choose the public good level x* and
tax rate r* that period and every period thereafter. It must therefore be the case that the value function
v1( g) satisfies:

(A5)


max{u(w(1 ⫺ r(x, g)), g) ⫹ ␦v1(x)} g ⱕ g*
.
冉 冊
x
v1 共g兲 ⫽ B(r*, x*; g) ␦ B(r*, x*; x*)
u(w(1 ⫺ r*), g) ⫹ ⫹ u(w(1 ⫺ r*), x*) ⫹ g ⬎ g*
n 1⫺␦ n

The question is whether there exists a strictly concave value function v1 that satisfies this relationship
when inequality (A4) is satisfied. If so, there will exist an associated equilibrium {(r␶( g), s␶( g),
x␶( g))}␶T⫽1 in which if g 僆 [0, g*], then

共r ␶ 共g兲, s ␶ 共g兲, x ␶ 共g兲兲 ⫽ 共r共x*共g兲, g兲, 0, x*共g兲兲 for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T,

and if g 僆 ( g*, ⬁), then (r␶( g), x␶( g)) ⫽ (r*, x*) for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T, and

s ␶ 共g兲 ⫽ 再 B(r*, x*; g)


n
for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T ⫺ 1
vT ⫹ 1 共g兲 ⫺ u共w共1 ⫺ r*兲, g兲 ⫺ ␦v1 共x*兲 for ␶⫽T
.
144 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

The proof of the following lemma establishes not only that there does exist such a function but also
that it is unique.

LEMMA A.2: There exists a Type I equilibrium if and only if inequality (A4) is satisfied. Moreover,
there is a unique such equilibrium.

PROOF OF LEMMA A.2:


Let g៮ ⬎ x* be an arbitrarily large but bounded scalar. We will first restrict the domain of public good
levels to [0, g៮ ] and prove the existence of a unique v1( g) that satisfies (A5) when this assumption is
satisfied. Then we will extend the solution for g ⬎ g៮ . Define for g 僆 [ g*, g៮ ] the function

v៮ 共g兲 ⫽ u共w共1 ⫺ r*兲, g兲 ⫹


B共r*, x*; g兲
n


1⫺␦ 冉
u(w(1 ⫺ r*), x*) ⫹
B(r*, x*; x*)
n
. 冊
This function v៮ ( g) is continuous, bounded and strictly concave on [g*, g៮ ]. Then let F denote the set of
continuous, bounded, weakly concave functions v : ⺢⫹ 3 ⺢ such that v( g) ⫽ v៮ ( g) for all g 僆 [ g*, g៮ ].
This set is nonempty, closed, bounded, and convex. Finally, define the functional ⌿ on F as follows:


max兵u共w共1 ⫺ r共x, g兲兲, g兲 ⫹ ␦v共x兲其 g 僆 关0, g*兴
x .
(A6) ⌿共v兲共g兲 ⫽ B共r*, x*; g兲
u共w共1 ⫺ r*兲, g兲 ⫹ ⫹ ␦v៮ 共x*兲 g 僆 共g*, g៮ 兲
n

For a given expected continuation value function v at time t ⫹ 1, ⌿(v) provides the expected value
function of a legislator at time t in an equilibrium with x* ⬎ g*.
We will now prove that there exists a unique v1 僆 F such that v1 ⫽ ⌿(v1). The first step is to show
that ⌿ maps F into itself, i.e., that ⌿(v) 僆 F. It is immediate that ⌿(v)( g) ⫽ v៮ ( g) for all g 僆 [ g*, g៮ ],
and that ⌿(v) is bounded on [0, g៮ ]. A proof that ⌿(v) is continuous and (strictly) concave is available in
the on-line Appendix. Using Blackwell’s sufficient conditions (see Theorem 5 in David Blackwell 1965),
we also prove that ⌿⵺ is a contraction with modulus ␦. It then follows that there exists a unique
continuous, bounded, strictly concave value function v1 that satisfies (A5) on the domain [0, g៮ ].
To see that the equilibrium value function can be extended for g ⬎ g៮ , note that we can define
v( g) ⫽ v៮ ( g) for g ⬎ g៮ . The resulting value function is continuous, strictly concave, and continues
to be a fixpoint of (A6). This completes the proof of Lemma A.2.

Existence of a Type II Equilibrium.—In this case, Proposition 3 tells us that the equilibrium
converges monotonically to the planner’s steady state. Thus, it must be the case that for all g ⱕ g*,
v1( g) ⫽ V( g)/n where V( g) is the planner’s value function. This means that x* satisfies ␦[V⬘(x*)/n] ⫽
p/q. In addition, g* ⫽ ( px* ⫺ R(r*))/p(1 ⫺ d). It turns out that x* ⬍ g* if and only if the marginal
cost of public funds at the planner’s steady state exceeds the ratio n/q, that is,

(A7) 冉 1 ⫺ r(x o , x o )

1 ⫺ r(x o , x o )(1 ⫹ ␧)
n
⬎ .
q

To see this, note, from the Euler equation for the planner’s problem, that at the planner’s steady state
␦V⬘(xo) ⫽ p(1 ⫺ r(xo, xo))/(1 ⫺ r(xo, xo)(1 ⫹ ␧)). Thus, if the condition is satisfied, it must be the
case that V⬘(xo) ⬎ V⬘(x*), which by the concavity of the planner’s value function implies that x* ⬎
xo. But since the condition implies that ro ⫽ r(xo, xo) ⬎ r*, this means that

px o ⫺ R共r o 兲 px* ⫺ R共r*兲


xo ⫽ ⬍ ⫽ g*.
p共1 ⫺ d兲 p共1 ⫺ d兲
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 145

From Figure 3B, it is clear that this implies that xo( g*) ⫽ x* ⬍ g*.
For g ⬎ g*, we know that the legislature selects the public good level x*, which puts proposals
back into the no-pork region in one period. Accordingly, it must be the case that


V(g)
g ⱕ g*
n
v 1 共g兲 ⫽ B(r*, x*; g) V(x*) .
u(w(1 ⫺ r*), g) ⫹ ⫹␦ g ⬎ g*
n n

It is now straightforward to show that this is indeed an equilibrium value function and is strictly concave.
The associated equilibrium policy proposals {(r␶( g), s␶( g), x␶( g))}␶T⫽1 are such that if g 僆 [0, g*], then

共r ␶ 共g兲, s ␶ 共g兲, x ␶ 共g兲兲 ⫽ 共r共x*共g兲, g兲, 0, x*共g兲兲 for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T,

and if g 僆 ( g*, ⬁), then (r␶( g), x␶( g)) ⫽ (r*, x*) for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T, and

s ␶ 共g兲 ⫽ 再
B(r*, x*; g)
n
for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T ⫺ 1
vT ⫹ 1(g) ⫺ u(w(1 ⫺ r*), g) ⫺ ␦v1(x*) for ␶ ⫽ T
.

Thus we have:

LEMMA A.3: There exists a Type II equilibrium if and only if inequality (A7) is satisfied.
Moreover, there is a unique such equilibrium.

Existence of a Type III Equilibrium.—In this case, we know that x* ⫽ g* ⫽ [R(r*)/pd]. Further,
we know that it must be the case that

(A8) 冋
␦ A ␣ x* ␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹
p(1 ⫺ d)
n
p
册 冋
ⱕ ⱕ ␦ A ␣ x* ␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹
q 冉
1 ⫺ r*
1 ⫺ r*(1 ⫹ ␧) 冊冉 p(1 ⫺ d)
n 冊册 .

In such an equilibrium, if g ⬎ x* then the legislature will choose the public good level x* and tax
rate r* that period and every period thereafter. It must therefore be the case that the value function
v1( g) satisfies


max{u(w(1 ⫺ r(x, g)), g) ⫹ ␦v1(x)} g ⱕ x*
x
(A9) v 1 共g兲 ⫽ B(r*, x*; g) ␦ .
u(w(1 ⫺ r*), g) ⫹ ⫹ u(w(1 ⫺ r*), x*) g ⬎ x*
n 1⫺␦

The question is whether there exists a strictly concave value function that satisfies this relationship
when inequality (A8) is satisfied. If so, there will exist an associated equilibrium {(r␶( g), s␶( g),
x␶( g))}␶T⫽1 in which, if g 僆 [0, x*], then

共r ␶ 共g兲, s ␶ 共g兲, x ␶ 共g兲兲 ⫽ 共r共x*共g兲, g兲, 0, x*共g兲兲 for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T,

and if g 僆 (x*, ⬁), then (r␶( g), x␶( g)) ⫽ (r*, x*) for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T, and

s ␶ 共g兲 ⫽ 再
B(r*, x*; g)
n
vT ⫹ 1(g) ⫺ u(w(1 ⫺ r*), g) ⫺ ␦v1(x*)
for all ␶ ⫽ 1, ... , T ⫺ 1
for ␶⫽T
.
146 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

The following Lemma shows that the answer is yes.

LEMMA A.4: There exists a Type III equilibrium if and only if inequality (A8) is satisfied.
Moreover, there is a unique such equilibrium.

PROOF OF LEMMA A.4:


The proof is similar to the proof of Lemma A.2 and hence is relegated to the on-line Appendix.

When Are the Conditions Satisfied?—Defining A and A as in (39) and (40), we have the following
convenient result.

LEMMA A.5:

(i) Condition (A4) is satisfied if and only if A 僆 (0, A).


(ii) Condition (A7) is satisfied if and only if A ⬎ A.
(iii) Condition (A8) is satisfied if and only if A 僆 [A, A].

PROOF OF LEMMA A.5:

(i) Let x*(A) ⫽ (␦qA␣/p(1 ⫺ (q/n)␦(1 ⫺ d)))1/1 ⫺ ␣. Then, we know that condition (A4) is satisfied
if and only if x*(A) ⬍ [R(r*)/pd] or, equivalently, if and only if A 僆 (0, Â) where x*(Â) ⫽ [R(r*)/pd].
But note that

冢冉 冋 冉 冊 册
冊冣
1/1 ⫺ ␣ ␣⫺1
R共r*兲 ␦qÂ␣ R共r*兲 R(r*) p(1 ⫺ d) p
x*共Â兲 ⫽ N ⫽ N ␦ Â␣ ⫹ ⫽ ,
pd q pd pd n q
p 1 ⫺ ␦(1 ⫺ d)
n

which implies that  ⫽ A.


(ii) Condition (A7) is that (1 ⫺ r(xo, xo))/(1 ⫺ r(xo, xo)(1 ⫹ ␧)) ⬎ n/q. Let xo(A) denote the planner’s
steady-state public good level, with public good preference parameter A, and ro(A) ⫽ r(xo(A), xo(A)), the
associated tax rate. Clearly, xo(A) and ro(A) are increasing in A. Letting à be such that [(1 ⫺ ro(A))/(1 ⫺
ro(A)(1 ⫹ ␧))] ⫽ n/q, it is clear that condition (A7) is satisfied if and only if A ⬎ Ã. But note that ro(Ã) ⫽
r* and that ␦nÃ␣xo(Ã)␣ ⫺1 ⫽ p[1 ⫺ ␦(1 ⫺ d)][(1 ⫺ r*)/(1 ⫺ r*(1 ⫹ ␧))] or, equivalently,


␦ Aគ ␣xo(Ã)␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹ 冉 1 ⫺ r*
1 ⫺ r*(1 ⫹ ␧)
p(1 ⫺ d)
n 冊冉 冊册 p
⫽ .
q

Furthermore, B(x o (Ã), r*; x o (Ã)) ⫽ 0, which implies that xo(Ã) ⫽ [R(r*)/pd] and hence that à ⫽
A as required.

(iii) This is immediate.

This completes the proof of Lemma A.5.

Proposition 5 now follows by combining Lemmata A.2 to A.5.

PROOF OF LEMMA 1:
We know from Proposition 2 that the equilibrium steady state is

冢 冢冉 冊冣 冣
1/1 ⫺ ␣
␦qA␣
r*, .
q
p 1 ⫺ ␦(1 ⫺ d)
n
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 147

The planner’s steady state (r o , x o ) satisfies: ␦[nA␣(xo)␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹ (1 ⫺ ro/1 ⫺ ro(1 ⫹ ␧)) p(1 ⫺ d)] ⫽
[1 ⫺ ro/1 ⫺ ro(1 ⫹ ␧)] 䡠 p and R(ro) ⫽ pdxo, which means that

冋 冉 冊 冉 冊 册
␣⫺1
R(ro) 1 ⫺ ro p(1 ⫺ d) 1 ⫺ ro p
␦ A␣ ⫹ ⫽ 䡠 .
pd 1 ⫺ r (1 ⫹ ␧)
o
n 1 ⫺ r 共1 ⫹ ␧兲 n
o

The equilibrium steady state satisfies ␦[A␣x␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹ (p(1 ⫺ d)/n)] ⫽ p/q. By definition (see (44)), we
know that

冋 冉 冊 冉 冊冉 冊册
␣⫺1
R(r*) 1⫺r* p(1⫺d) p 1⫺r* p
␦ A␣ ⫹ ⫽ ⫽ 䡠 .
pd 1⫺r*(1⫹␧) n q 1⫺r*(1⫹␧) n

Thus, if A ⬍ A we have that

冋 冉 冊 冉 冊冉 冊册
␣⫺1
R(r*) 1 ⫺ r* p(1 ⫺ d) 1 ⫺ r* p
␦ A␣ ⫹ ⬍ 䡠 .
pd 1 ⫺ r*(1 ⫹ ␧) n 1 ⫺ r*共1 ⫹ ␧兲 n

This implies that r* ⬎ ro—the equilibrium tax rate is higher than the planner’s tax rate. On the other
hand, if A 僆 ( A, A] we have that

冋 冉 冊 冉 冊冉 冊册
␣⫺1
R(r*) 1 ⫺ r* p(1 ⫺ d) 1 ⫺ r* p
␦ A␣ ⫹ ⬎ 䡠 ,
pd 1 ⫺ r*(1 ⫹ ␧) n 1 ⫺ r*共1 ⫹ ␧兲 n

which implies that r* ⬍ ro.


What about the claim concerning the level of public goods? The result is obvious if r* ⬍ ro, so
suppose that r* ⬎ ro. The level of public goods at the equilibrium steady state satisfies


␦ A␣x␣ ⫺ 1 ⫹
p(1 ⫺ d)
n
⫽ 册 1 ⫺ r* p
䡠 ⬎
1 ⫺ ro
o
p
䡠 .
1 ⫺ r*共1 ⫹ ␧兲 n 1 ⫺ r 共1 ⫹ ␧兲 n

Thus, it is clear that the level of public goods is below that at the planner’s steady state, because the
marginal cost is higher and the marginal benefit is lower. This completes the proof of Lemma 1.

PROOF OF LEMMA 2:
It suffices to show that r* ⬍ ro. But we know from the proof of Lemma 1 that this follows if A 僆
(A, A].

PROOF OF PROPOSITION 7:
This is straightforward and thus relegated to the on-line Appendix.

REFERENCES comes.” American Political Science Review,


82(2): 405–22.
Acemoglu, Daron. 2003. “Why Not a Political Austen-Smith, David, and Jeffrey S. Banks. 2005.
Coase Theorem? Social Conflict, Commit- Positive Political Theory II: Strategy and Struc-
ment, and Politics.” Journal of Comparative ture. Michigan Studies in Political Analysis.
Economics, 31(4): 620 –52. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Acemoglu, Daron, and James A. Robinson. 2001. Azzimonti Renzo, Marina D. 2005. “On the Dy-
“Inefficient Redistribution.” American Polit- namic Inefficiency of Governments.” Unpub-
ical Science Review, 95(3): 649 – 61. lished.
Austen-Smith, David, and Jeffrey S. Banks. 1988. Banks, Jeffrey S., and John Duggan. 2000. “A
“Elections, Coalitions, and Legislative Out- Bargaining Model of Collective Choice.”
148 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2007

American Political Science Review, 94(1): Interactions: On the Persistence of Inefficien-


73– 88. cies.” Journal of Political Economy, 113(3):
Baron, David P. 1991. “Majoritarian Incentives, 626 – 67.
Pork Barrel Programs, and Procedural Con- Hassler, John, Per Krusell, Kjetil Storesletten,
trol.” American Journal of Political Science, and Fabrizio Zilibotti. 2005. “The Dynamics
35(1): 57–90. of Government.” Journal of Monetary Eco-
Baron, David P. 1996. “A Dynamic Theory of nomics, 52(7): 1331–58.
Collective Goods Programs.” American Po- Hassler, John, José V. Rodrı́guez Mora, Kjetil
litical Science Review, 90(2): 316 –30. Storesletten, and Fabrizio Zilibotti. 2003. “The
Baron, David P., and John A. Ferejohn. 1989. Survival of the Welfare State.” American
“Bargaining in Legislatures.” American Po- Economic Review, 93(1): 87–112.
litical Science Review, 83(4): 1181–1206. Hassler, John, Kjetil Storesletten, and Fabrizio
Barro, Robert J. 1979. “On the Determination of Zilibotti. Forthcoming. “Democratic Public
the Public Debt.” Journal of Political Econ- Good Provision.” Journal of Economic
omy, 87(5): 940 –71. Theory.
Battaglini, Marco, and Stephen Coate. 2005. Kalandrakis, Anastassios. 2004. “A Three-Player
“Inefficiency in Legislative Policy-Making: Dynamic Majoritarian Bargaining Game.”
A Dynamic Analysis.” National Bureau Journal of Economic Theory, 116(2): 294 –
of Economic Research Working Paper 322.
11495. Krusell, Per, and José-Vı́ctor Rı́os-Rull. 1999.
Besley, Timothy, and Stephen Coate. 2003. “Cen- “On the Size of U.S. Government: Political
tralized versus Decentralized Provision of Economy in the Neoclassical Growth
Local Public Goods: A Political Economy Model.” American Economic Review, 89(5):
Approach.” Journal of Public Economics, 1156 – 81.
87(12): 2611–37. Leblanc, William, James M. Snyder, Jr., and
Besley, Timothy, and Stephen Coate. 1988. Micky Tripathi. 2000. “Majority-Rule Bar-
“Sources of Inefficiency in a Representative gaining and the Under Provision of Public
Democracy: A Dynamic Analysis.” Ameri- Investment Goods.” Journal of Public Eco-
can Economic Review, 88(1): 139 –56. nomics, 75(1): 21– 47.
Blackwell, David. 1965. “Discounted Dynamic Lizzeri, Alessandro, and Nicola Persico. 2001.
Programming.” The Annals of Mathematical “The Provision of Public Goods under Alter-
Statistics, 36(1): 226 –35. native Electoral Incentives.” American Eco-
Chari, V. V., Larry E. Jones, and Ramon Mari- nomic Review, 91(1): 225–39.
mon. 1997. “The Economics of Split-Ticket McKelvey, Richard D., and Raymond Riezman.
Voting in Representative Democracies.” 1992. “Seniority in Legislatures.” American
American Economic Review, 87(5): 957–76. Political Science Review, 86(4): 951– 65.
Coate, Stephen, and Stephen Morris. 1995. “On Morelli, Massimo. 1999. “Demand Competition
the Form of Transfers in Special Interests.” and Policy Compromise in Legislative Bar-
Journal of Political Economy, 103(6): gaining.” American Political Science Review,
1210 –35. 93(4): 809 –20.
Coate, Stephen, and Stephen Morris. 1999. “Pol- Norman, Peter. 2002. “Legislative Bargaining
icy Persistence.” American Economic Re- and Coalition Formation.” Journal of Eco-
view, 89(5): 1327–36. nomic Theory, 102(2): 322–53.
Epple, Dennis, and Michael H. Riordan. 1987. Persson, Torsten, and Lars E. O. Svensson. 1989.
“Cooperation and Punishment under Re- “Why a Stubborn Conservative Would Run a
peated Majority Voting.” Public Choice, Deficit: Policy with Time-Inconsistent Pref-
55(1-2): 41–73. erences.” Quarterly Journal of Economics,
Eraslan, Hulya. 2002. “Uniqueness of Stationary 104(2): 325– 45.
Equilibrium Payoffs in the Baron-Ferejohn Persson, Torsten, and Guido Tabellini. 2000. Po-
Model.” Journal of Economic Theory, litical Economics: Explaining Economic Pol-
103(1): 11–30. icy. Zeuthen Lecture Book Series. Cambridge
Eraslan, Hulya, and Antonio Merlo. 2002. “Ma- and London: MIT Press.
jority Rule in a Stochastic Model of Bargain- Stokey, Nancy L., Robert E. Lucas Jr., and Ed-
ing.” Journal of Economic Theory, 103(1): ward C. Prescott. 1989. Recursive Methods in
31– 48. Economic Dynamics. Cambridge, MA: Har-
Gomes, Armando, and Philippe Jehiel. 2005. vard University Press.
“Dynamic Processes of Social and Economic Tabellini, Guido, and Alberto Alesina. 1990.
VOL. 97 NO. 1 BATTAGLINI AND COATE: INEFFICIENCY IN LEGISLATIVE POLICYMAKING 149

“Voting on the Budget Deficit.” American Economy of Benefits and Costs: A Neoclas-
Economic Review, 80(1): 37– 49. sical Approach to Distributive Politics.”
Velasco, Andrés. 2000. “Debts and Deficits with Journal of Political Economy, 89(4): 642–
Fragmented Fiscal Policymaking.” Journal of 64.
Public Economics, 76(1): 105–25. Wittman, Donald. 1989. “Why Democracies
Weingast, Barry R., Kenneth A. Shepsle, and Produce Efficient Results.” Journal of Polit-
Christopher Johnsen. 1981. “The Political ical Economy, 97(6): 1395–1424.
This article has been cited by:

1. David P. Baron, Daniel Diermeier, Pohan Fong. 2011. A dynamic theory of parliamentary democracy.
Economic Theory . [CrossRef]
2. Marco Battaglini, Thomas R. Palfrey. 2011. The dynamics of distributive politics. Economic Theory
. [CrossRef]
3. Daniel Diermeier, Pohan Fong. 2011. Bargaining over the budget. Social Choice and Welfare 36:3-4,
565-589. [CrossRef]
4. John Duggan, Tasos Kalandrakis. 2011. A Newton collocation method for solving dynamic bargaining
games. Social Choice and Welfare 36:3-4, 611-650. [CrossRef]
5. Johanna M. M. Goertz. 2011. Omnibus or not: package bills and single-issue bills in a legislative
bargaining game. Social Choice and Welfare 36:3-4, 547-563. [CrossRef]
6. Jørgen Juel Andersen. 2011. Costs of taxation and the size of government. Public Choice . [CrossRef]
7. Levon Barseghyan, Ani Guerdjikova. 2011. Institutions and growth in limited access societies. Journal
of Economic Theory 146:2, 528-568. [CrossRef]
8. Marcelin Joanis. 2011. The road to power: partisan loyalty and  the centralized provision of local
infrastructure. Public Choice 146:1-2, 117-143. [CrossRef]
9. J. H. Bai, R. Lagunoff. 2011. On the Faustian Dynamics of Policy and Political Power. The Review
of Economic Studies 78:1, 17-48. [CrossRef]
10. PATRICK O'BRIEN. 2010. The nature and historical evolution of an exceptional fiscal state and its
possible significance for the precocious commercialization and industrialization of the British economy
from Cromwell to Nelson. The Economic History Review no-no. [CrossRef]
11. Tasos Kalandrakis. 2010. Minimum winning coalitions and endogenous status quo. International
Journal of Game Theory 39:4, 617-643. [CrossRef]
12. Abhinay Muthoo, Kenneth A. Shepsle. 2010. Information, institutions and constitutional
arrangements. Public Choice 144:1-2, 1-36. [CrossRef]
13. KIMIKO TERAI. 2009. Interregional Disparities in Productivity and the Choice of Fiscal Regime.
Journal of Public Economic Theory 11:3, 383-409. [CrossRef]
14. Elizabeth Maggie Penn. 2009. A Model of Farsighted Voting. American Journal of Political Science
53:1, 36-54. [CrossRef]
15. RAPHAL SOUBEYRAN, PASCAL GAUTIER. 2008. Political Cycles: Issue Ownership and the
Opposition Advantage. Journal of Public Economic Theory 10:4, 685-716. [CrossRef]
16. Marco Battaglini, Stephen Coate. 2008. The Political Economy of Fiscal Policy. Journal of the
European Economic Association 6:2-3, 367-380. [CrossRef]
17. Marco Battaglini, Stephen Coate. 2008. A Dynamic Theory of Public Spending, Taxation, and DebtA
Dynamic Theory of Public Spending, Taxation, and Debt. American Economic Review 98:1, 201-236.
[Abstract] [View PDF article] [PDF with links]
Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.

You might also like