Belnap - On Rigorous Definitions

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 33

On Rigorous Definitions

Author(s): Nuel Belnap


Source: Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic
Tradition, Vol. 72, No. 2/3, Definitions (Dec., 1993), pp. 115-146
Published by: Springer
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4320448
Accessed: 28/05/2009 14:36

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springer.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the
scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that
promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophical Studies: An
International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition.

http://www.jstor.org
NUEL BELNAP

ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS

(Received27 February1993)

Definitions are crucial for every serious discipline.' Here I consider


them only in the sense of explanationsof the meaningsof words or
other bits of language.(I use "explanation"as a word from common
speech, with no philosophicalencumbrances.)As a furtherlimitationI
consider definitions only in terms of well-understoodforms of rigor.
Prominenton the agendawill be the two standard"criteria"- elimina-
bility and conservativeness- and the standard"rules".There is, alas,
hardly any literatureon this topic. The discussion will therefore be
preliminary,all too elementary,andimperfectlyplain.

1. SOME PURPOSES OF DEFINITIONS

There are two especially clear social circumstancesthat call for a


meaning-explaining definition,and then manythat are not so clear.The
clear ones call either for (1) "dictionary"
definitionsor for (2) "stipula-
tive" definitions;one of the less clear circumstancescalls for an (3)
"analysis."

1.1. "Dictionary"or "Lexical"Definitions

One mightneed to explainthe existingmeaningof an old word;that is,


a word alreadyin use in the community,but unfamiliarto the person
wantingthe explanation.
1. EXAMPLE.(Lexical definitions) (1) What is a sibling? A
sibling is a brother or a sister. (2) What does it mean to
square a number?One obtains the square of a numberof
multiplyingit by itself. (3) Whatdo you mean by zero? Zero
is the least integer. (4) What is a brother?A brother is a
male sibling.

PhilosophicalStudies72:115-146, 1993.
C 1993 KluwerAcademicPublishers.Printedin theNetherlands.
116 NUEL BELNAP

I postpone discussion of (a) the question whether these interchanges


should be sprinkled with quotation marks and (b) the circularity
threatenedby combiningthe sibling/brotherexamples.

1.2. "Stipulative"
Definitions
One might wish to explain a proposed meaningfor a new word. The
purpose might be to enrich the languageby makingclear to the com-
munityof users that one intends that the new word be used in accord
with the proposed meaning.This case squarelyincludes the puttingto
workof an "old"wordwitha new technicalmeaning.
2. EXAMPLE.(Stipulativedefinitions) (1) Let omega be the
first ordinalafter all the finite ordinals.(2) Let a group be a
set closed under a binaryoperationsatisfyingthe following
principles ... . (3) By a terminological realist I mean a
philosopherwho subscribesto the followingdoctrines...
The person who introducesa new word mighthave any one of various
purposes.Here is a pair:the person mightwant a mere abbreviation,to
avoid lengthyrepetition("ByE2 I referto volume 2 of Entailment:The
Logic of Relevance and Necessity"); or the person might take it that he
or she is cuttingat a conceptualjoint (a complete lattice is a partially
orderedset in which every subsethas a least upper and a greatestlower
bound).

1.3. "Analyses"
or "Explications"
There are many cases not exhibitingeither of these clear purposes,
includingperhapsmost distinctivelyphilosophicalacts of definition;in
these cases (Carnapcalls some of them "explications")
one wants both
to rely on an old, existing meaning and to attach a new, proposed
meaning; it seems that one's philosophical purposes would not be
servedif one let go of eitherpole.
3. EXAMPLE. (Explicativedefinitions) (1) Let knowledge (in
the present technical sense) be justified true belief. (2) We
say that A impliesB if B is true on every interpretationon
whichA is true.
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 117

Observethat in these cases the philosopherneitherintendssimplyto be


reportingthe existing usage of the community,nor would his or her
purposesbe satisfiedby substitutingsome brandnew word. In some of
these cases it would seem that the philosopher'seffort to explain the
meaningof a word amountsto a proposal for "a good thing to mean
by" the word. I learnedthis phrasefrom Alan Ross Anderson.Part of
the implication is that judging philosophical analyses is like judging
eggs:Thereareno shortcuts;each has to be held to the candle.

1.4. Invarianceof StandardTheoryAcrossPurposes:Criteriaand Rules


The extraordinarythingis this:The applicabilityof the standardtheory
of definitionremainsinvariantacross these purposes - just so long as
the purpose is to "explainthe meaning of a word." (The phrase "a
word"suggeststhat it is a single word that is being defined,whereasthe
standard theory can certainly do better than that. For simplicity,
however, I omit discussion of the simultaneousexplanationof several
termsby meansof a singleact of definition.)
This standardtheory has two parts. In the first place, it offers two
criteria for good definitions: the criterion of eliminability (which
requires that the defined term be eliminable in favor of previously
understoodterms)and the criterionof conservativeness(whichrequires
that the definition not only not lead to inconsistency,but not lead to
anything - not involving the defined term - that was not obtainable
before). In the second place, it offers some rules for good definitions,
ruleswhichif followedwillguaranteethatthe criteriaare satisfied.

History. The standard theory of definitions seems to be due to


Lesniewski,who modeled his "directives"on the work of Frege, but I
cannottell you whereto find a historyof its development.The standard
citation seems to be Lesniewski 1931; see also Lesniewski 1981
(Collectedworks).I learnedmost of the theoryfirst from Suppes 1957,
who credits Lesniewski (p. 153, note). There should have been mini-
historiesin either Church1956 or Curry1963, but I couldn'tfind what
I was looking for. The matter was well understoodby Frege (e.g. in
Frege 1964), Couturat (see Couturat 1905), Carnap (e.g. in Carnap
1937) and Tarski (see e.g. Tarski 1941 for some well-chosenelemen-
118 NUEL BELNAP

tary words). Tarski himself contributed heavily to the theory, as


evidenced in the material translated and reprinted in Tarski 1956.
There Tarski gives the dates and circumstancesof his own early
contributionsin the 20s and 30s. But no one of these lays out an
account of the history of the matter in its beginnings.The standard
histories of logic (Bochenski 1956, Kneale and Kneale 1962) do not
discuss modem theories of definition.Neither does Kneebone 1963.
Neither does Church'sarticleon "definition"in Runes 1962. The 207-
page book Robinson 1950 neither discusses the technical theory nor
refers to its history (though there is some referenceto the history of
nontechnicaldiscussions).The definitionarticlein TheEncyclopediaof
Philosophy(1967) does not even mention Lesniewski.The only useful
general references I happen to know are the definition article in the
Dictionaryof Logic, Marciszewski1981, and some penetratingpara-
graphs and authoritativecitations in Luschei 1962 (see especially pp.
36-37 andnn. 34 and 78).
The criteriaare like the logician'saccount of semanticconsequence:
The latteris proposed as an accountof "goodinference,"the formeras
an account of "good definition."And the standardrules are like the
logician'srules definingderivabilityin a particularsystem:If you follow
the logician'srules for constructingderivationsin his system, you will
derive all and only correct semanticconsequences,i.e., you will make
all and only "good inferences."In the same way, if you follow the
logician'srules for constructingdefinitions,you will offer all and only
definitionsthat satisfythe criteriaof eliminabilityand conservativeness.
You will, that is, offer all and only "gooddefinitions."The analogyruns
deep: Just as it is a hard theorem that in first order logic semantic
consequences and derivability(in some one formal system) are in
agreement,so it is a hardtheoremthat the two criteriaand the standard
rules are in agreement.The hard part is Beth's DefinabilityTheorem.
There is an additional parallel. We know that agreement between
semantic consequence and derivability(in some one formal system)
gives out when first order logic is enriched in any one of several
respects. So does the agreementbetween the criteriaand the rules of
definition.
I discuss the two criteriain some length, and then say just a little
aboutthe rules.
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 119

2. ELIMINABILITY AND CONSERVATIVENESS I

The standardcriteriafor good definitionsare those of "eliminability"


and "conservativeness."Where do these criteria come from? Why
should we pay attentionto them? Indeed, we may and shall raise the
presupposedquestion of whether we should pay them attention.It is
surelyremarkablethat philosophical-logicalliteratureis nearlysilent on
these questions.
I have only the most elementaryof answersto propose. It seems to
me that we can derive a motivationfor these criteriafrom the concept
of definitionsas explanationsof the meaningsof words (or other bits of
language). Under the concept of a definition as explanatory,(1) a
definition of a word should explain all the meaningthat a word has,
and (2) it should do only this and nothing more. That a definition
should (1) explain all the meaningof a word leads to the criterionof
eliminability.That a definitionshould (2) only explain the meaningof
the word leads to the criterion of conservativeness.Observe that (1)
and (2) are not quite analogousin their respectiveplacementsof "all"
and "only."This warnsus that, as we shall see, the two criteriaare also
not exactlyanalogous.

2.1. Criterionof Eliminability(RoughAccount)


One may approachthe criterionof eliminabilityfrom the directionof
the "use"picture of meaning, with picture-slogan,"meaningis use."
Then to explain all its uses, that is, its use in every context. (I intend
that this recipe neglect ambiguity).The advance is this: The meta-
phorical quantifierin "all the meaning"is cashed out in terms of a
nonmetaphorical(if stillimprecise)quantifierover contexts.
And what is it to explainthe meaningof a word in a single context?
That depends on what counts as a context. The traditionhas found it
useful to concentrateon (declarative)sententialcontexts.I shalldo so as
well, even though these contexts are not enough for an adequatestory
about language.So what is it to explain the meaning of a word in a
single sententialcontext,say B? The standardmove, and a good one, is
to say that it is to explain the meaning of the containingsentence B.
The next standardidea is this:To explainthe meaningof a sentence is
120 NUEL BELNAP

to explainits role in inference.Combiningideas yields the doctrinethat


to explainall the meaningof a word is to explainthe inferentialconnec-
tions of each containingsentenceB.
At this stage there enter two new elements.First, explanationsquite
generallyare more prized if they are given in terms that are previously
understood. This we may call noncircularity.Second, in favorable
situationswe can hope to explainthe inferentialrole of a new sentence
by identifyingits role with that of an old sentence.This we may call no
inferentialenrichment.(I apologize for the jargon.)The combinationof
these two elements comes to this: There is in the language another
sentence that (a) does not contain the defined term and (b) occupies
exactly the same inferential role as that wanted for the containing
sentence B. The standard account presupposes that the situation is
favorable.Accordingly,the criterion of eliminabilityrequiresthat for
each sententialcontext B containingthe defined word, the definition
give enough informationto allow formationof an inferentiallyequiva-
lent piece of language B' that contains only previously understood
words. Then, and only then, will we be sure that we have explainedall
the meaning of the word to be defined - whether our purpose is to
explainan existingmeaningof an old word or to give a new meaningto
a new word. In either case, for each context in which the defined word
can grammaticallyoccur, we must provideenoughinformationto allow
constructionof an equivalentstatementthat contains only previously
understoodwords. Under the assumptionthat the defined word is not
"previouslyunderstood,"whatis then requiredis enoughinformationto
permit "elimination"of the defined word in favor of other words that
arepreviouslyunderstood.
The above account needs considerablerefinement;containingas it
does several obscure phrases, it cannot itself count as a definitionof
"satisfiesthe criterion of eliminability"that satisfies the criterion of
eliminability.I postpone this necessaryrefinementuntil after a prelimi-
nary accountof the criterionof conservativeness,but pause to illustrate
some of the obscuritywithan example.
4. EXAMPLE. (Holiness) Holiness is what the gods all love
(Euthyphro).
Taken as a definition, and read in a standardtwo-valued way, this
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 121

permits eliminationof "holy"in "extensional"contexts, which is good.


As Socrates pointed out, however, it does not permit eliminationof
"holy"in "becausal"contexts.Socratesasked Euthyphroto considerthe
followingplausiblepremiss.
Holy acts areloved by the gods becausethey areholy.
If we tried to use Euthyphro'sExample 4 to eliminate the second
occurrence of "holy" - the one in the scope of "because" - we should
findthatwe wereled to the followingimplausibleconclusion.
Holy acts are loved by the gods because they are loved by
the gods

This leadsus to see that"context"needs specification.


We should keep in mind quotationcontexts, and also psychological
contexts involving rapt attention such as "he was turningover in his
mind the questionof whetherprosecutionof his fatherwas holy."If we
do then we will be more likely to keep rememberingthat no definition
will permit eliminationin absolutely every context. Such remembering
will perhaps disinclineus to ask more of a definitionthan it can very
well deliver. But perhapsnot. Some people respond by cooking up an
account of quotes (for example)on which they do not count as "con-
texts." This seems to me an unhelpful obfuscation of the general
principle.
The matterof contexts is easily overlookedand criticallyimportant.
Since no definition can sensibly license universal elimination, any
sensible act of definition must include a reference to the family of
intended contexts. The point is easily overlooked because those who
care about the proper use of definitionsfrequentlythink of themselves
as alreadyhavingspecifiedsome backgroundfamilyof contexts,e.g. the
firstorderfunctionalcalculus.
The matterof no inferentialenrichmentis also easily forgettable,but
should not be forgotten.It is easy to describelanguagesin which there
are definiteinferentialroles whose statusis changedfrom "unoccupied"
to "occupied"by stipulativedefinitionsexploitingpreciselythose roles.
Here is an uncomplicatedexample.
5. EXAMPLE. (The Absurd) Let the language be entirely
122 NUEL BELNAP

positive, lacking any trace of negation, but be otherwise


standard.Stipulatethat to say of anythingthat it is F is to
say somethingthat implies everything.Thus each sentence
Fa paysthe role of The Absurd.
This evidently defines an inferentialrole for each sentence of which
each Fa is a part, and thus explainsall the meaningof F. But since no
sentence alreadyin the languageimplies every sentence, the definition
is inferentiallyenriching and does not satisfy eliminability.(Observe
that the failure of eliminabilityis not due to a violation of noncircu-
larity.)

2.2. Criterionof Conservativeness


(RoughAccount)
On the standardview a good definition(in the sense of an explanation
of meaning)should not only explain all the meaningof the word, as
required by the criterion of eliminability.It should only do this. It
should be empty of assertionalcontent beyond its ability to explain
meaning.If it were to go beyond the job assigned,say by claimingthat
Euthyphro is pious, it might indeed be doing something useful. It
would,however,no longer be entirelysatisfactoryas a definition.In this
perfectly good sense, a definition should be neither true nor false
(whetherexplainingan old word or introducinga new one): Whether
or not it has a truthvalue qua definition(we mightargueabout that),it
shouldmakeno claimsbeyondits explanationof meaning.
There is a special case to which I shall not return.Clearlya defini-
tion should not take you from consistencyto inconsistency;that would
be a dreadfulviolation of conservativeness.The older theoreticiansof
definitions in mathematicswere, however, insufficientlysevere when
they suggested that consistency is the only requirementon a mathe-
maticaldefinition.
Terminologyfor this criterionis a little confusing.Some folks use
"conservative"to mean somethinglike "does not permit the proof of
anything we couldn't prove before." This accounts for calling the
second criterion that of conservativeness:A definition satisfyingthe
second criterion is conservativein that very sense. Other folks use
"creative"to mean something like "permitsproof of something we
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 123

couldn't prove before."It is with this sense in mind that the second
criterionis sometimes called "the criterionof noncreativity."I opt for
the former name merely to avoid the negative particle.Under either
name, the criterion demands that the definition not have any con-
sequences (other than those consequencesinvolvingthe defined word
itself) that were not obtainablealreadywithoutthe definition.If before
the definitionwe could not establishthat Euthyphrois pious, and if the
definitionis of neither"Euthyphro"nor "pious"(but perhapsof "zero"
or "sibling"),then it shouldnot be possible to use the definitionto show
that Euthyphrois pious. Were we able to do so, the definitionwould
manifestlycontain more informationthan a mere explanationof mean-
ing:It would not be conservative.Neitherin explainingthe meaningsof
old words nor in introducingnew words should one use the cover of
definitionsto smugglein freshassertions.It'sbad manners.
6. EXAMPLE.(Noid) Suppose that Wordsmith introduced
"noid"by announcingthat all the guys on the other side of
Divider Street are noids (a sufficientcondition)and that all
noids arebornlosers(a necessarycondition).
Wordsmith'splan appearsinnocent:He wishes to help his gang under-
stand "noid"by squeezing it between two understood ideas. Word-
smith'sintroductionof "noid,"however,may or may not be innocent.If
the gang and Wordsmithhave already committed themselves to the
propositionthat all guys on the other side of Divider Street are born
losers, then Wordsmithhas not by this "definition"violated conserva-
tiveness.But if Wordsmithhas not done this, if he has not committed
himself and the gang to the born-losernessof all guys across Divider,
thenhe has violatedconservativeness.
This consideration is easily mixed with two others. There is in
Example6 an obvious differencein the emotionaland practicalfreight-
ing of the two bits connected via "noid."The one starts out in the
unloaded "space language,"as Carnap might say, while the other
suggests contempt and a practice of intimidation.What should not be
mixedis the divisionbetweensufficientand necessaryconditionson the
one hand, and the divisionbetween unfreightedand freightedlanguage
on the other. Furthermore,neither should be mixed up with what is
relatedto the possibilityof justificatorywarrant.
124 NUEL BELNAP

There is a middle case. Suppose Wordsmithis participatingin a


practiceaccordingto which his announcementcombines (1) the asser-
tion that all guys across Divider Street are born losers with (2) the
conservativeintroductionof "noid."There are two cruciallydifferent
subcases. Revealed assertion:The practice is such that Wordsmith's
form of words bears on its surface the division into assertion and
introduction.Concealedassertion:The practiceis such that the form of
words conceals the assertionalcontent or even misleads into the false
suppositionthat there isn't any. I shall pursue the differencebetween
revealedandconcealedassertionbelow.
7. EXAMPLE. (Emptyset) SupposeJanetsays "Definition:0 is
thatset thathas no members."
If Janet's communityhas already fixed on a theory that implies that
there is a unique set with no members,she is all right.But since this
"definition"permits her to prove that there is a set with no members
(by existential generalization),she violates conservativenessif she
couldn't prove it before. She would then be using the "definition"to
smugglein an existenceclaimto whichshe is not entitled.
Supposethe worst,however,thatJanet'scommunityhas a Lesniewski-
like theory accordingto which no set has no members.Suppose she
goes ahead and introduced 0 in accord with Example 7. What should
we say about her? What did she denote by 0? Probablyno one cares,
but there are cases like Janet'sabout which philosophersdo seem to
care. For exampleLeverrierintroduced"Vulcan"as the planet respon-
sible for certain astronomical anomalies. Later it was learned that
relativisticconsiderationssufficedfor the anomalies;there was no such
planet.Whatshallwe then say about the meaningof "Vulcan"and of all
the discourseusing this term?My own view is this. You should say that
the answerto "Isthere a uniqueplanetresponsiblefor the astronomical
anomaliesat issue?"is "No."You should say that the answerto "Isthe
definitiondefective?"is "Yes."You should say that some of what we
prize in science and other activitiesdoes not rest on answersto these
eminentlyclear questions,since we often manageto get along very well
when presuppositionsfail. You should add that neverthelessthere are
no general policies for what to do or what to say in the presence of
defectivedefinitions.Just about anythingyou remarkbeyond this will be
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 125

either artificial or unclear, and is likely only to add to the general


babbleof the universe.
It is easy to imaginelanguagesthat allow nonconservativeor creative
definitions in the following sense: In them a single speech act both
introduces the new terminologyand makes the assertion needed to
justify that introduction.In fact English, even scientificEnglish,is like
that. Our practices are lax. I suppose that is one thing people mean
whentheyadviseus to abandonthe analytic-synthetic distinction.
We should not, however,follow this advice.Those philosopherswho
wish to be clear should follow Carnap in maintainingthe analytic-
synthetic distinction to the maximumextent possible. That is, when
confrontedwith a complex speech act such as that of Leverrier,it is
good to idealize it as consisting of two distinct components: the
assertionof the existenceand uniquenessof an anomaly-causingplanet,
and the definitionof Vulcan as this very planet. There is, I think, no
other way to continue with a clear conversationabout the matter.For
example, I do not think we can otherwise make a clear distinction
between revealed and concealed assertions. And we should do so.
Speech acts that conceal assertions are (whatever their intentions)
misleading.We should try to avoid them wheneverwe are clear enough
to be able to do so. This, as we may infer from the historyof even the
best science, may not be often. Even when we are muddled,however,
we should at least try not to pretendto more claritythan the sad facts
warrant.

2.3. JointSufficiency
In conclusion of this preliminaryaccount, I add the following. The
proposal is that each of the criteriaof eliminabilityand conservative-
ness are necessaryfor a good definitionin the sense of an explanation
of meaning;and that togetherthey are sufficient(so that their conjunc-
tion providesa good definitionof "gooddefinition").The pros and cons
of necessityare easily discussedthroughexamples.In contrast,I do not
much know how to defend the claim to sufficiencyother than by a
rhetoricalquestion:You've asked for a good definition of this word,
and now I've given you a procedure for eliminatingit from every
intended context in favor of somethingyou yourself grant is entirely
126 NUEL BELNAP

equivalent;and I've done nothingelse (i.e., I haven'tslipped any further


statementspast you); so what more do you want? Until this rhetorical
device can be replacedby somethingbetter, there is conspicuouswork
to be done.

3. ELIMINABILITY AND CONSERVATIVENESS II

Such a rough account of the criteriaof eliminabilityand conservative-


ness calls for an increase in precision.The standardaccount provides
exactlythis.

3.1. Limitsof Applicability


You cannot buy an increase in precision without paying in the good
coin of limitation.Here the costs are of threekinds.
First, the discussion applies only to a communityof languageusers
whose languagecan profitablybe describedby labelingit an "applied
first order language."You should imagine that this language is a
fragmentof English,a fragmentthat the users think of as structuredin
terms of predicate, function, individual, and perhaps sentence con-
stants; truth-functionalconnectives; individual variables; quantifiers;
and identity.But you should also imagine that this languageis really
used and thereforehas lots of English in it. Think of the languagethat
some mathematicianssometimes employ: a mixture of English and
notation, but with the "logic"of the matter decided by the first order
calculus. For example, the languagewill use English common nouns
such as "set";but only in locutions such as "Somesets are finite"that
the usersthinkof as translatablein the usualfirstorderway.
I need to say more about what this first limitationmeans. So far I
have said that the users take the grammar of their language in the
standard first order way. They also think of their proof theoretical
notions as given in the standardway:I am thinkingof "axioms,""rules,"
"theoremhood,""derivabilityfrom premisses," "theory,""equivalent
relative to a theory," and so forth. And lastly, they think of their
semantic concepts in the standard way: "logical truth," "(semantic)
consequence of some premisses,""(semantic)equivalencerelativeto a
theory,"and so forth. They know, throughGodel, that there is agree-
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 127

ment between the appropriateproof-theoreticaland semanticideas. I


shall refer to these mattersby saying that the first order languagehas
an inferential use, or by saying that its sentences occur in inferential
contexts.
In the second place, I consider only definitions (explanationsof
meaning)of predicateconstantsand function constantsand individual
constants. This limitation is made reasonable (but is certainly not
forced) by the previousdecision to consideronly a first order language.
There is no consideration, for example, of Russell's treatment of
definite descriptions,or of the meaningof a conventioninvolvingthe
droppingof outermostparentheses,or of quantifiersof a certainstyle
havingsome limitedrange.
In the third place, I am going to follow the standard account in
consideringonly definitionsthat are themselvessentential,and that are
in the very same languagecontainingthe defined and definingterms.In
imposingthis limitationI do not intend to be decidingwhetherthe act
of defining is "really"imperativalinstead of assertional,or "really"
metalinguisticratherthan not. I do intend to assert, however, that the
technicaltheory of definitiongoes very much more easily if in givingit
one has to talk about only one language:the languageincludingthe
defined term, the definingterms,and the definitionitself. In fact we do
need to considertwo languageswith respectto vocabulary:the language
with, and the languagewithoutthe newly definedterm;and that is quite
enough in the directionof complicationfor such an elementarydiscus-
sion as this.
We can therefore see that the policy, exhibited in Example 1, of
giving example definitions above in the "materialmode" (as Carnap
puts it) correctly forecasts this decision. By taking the definition of
"sibling"to be "Anythingis a siblingif and only if it is a brotheror a
sister" instead of "Replace 'sibling' by 'brother or sister' wherever
found!",the technical work is greatly simplified,as you will see for
yourselfif you try to spell out a technicallyadequatetheory of defini-
tions of (say)the metalinguisticimperativekind.
But, you may say, isn't a definition a speech act? How can you
pretend adequacy for a theory of definitionsthat does not contain a
theory of such acts? Answer: There is no pretense. The standard
account is not adequate to the aim you have envisaged. There is,
128 NUEL BELNAP

however, no existingrigorousand helpful explicit theory of definitions


in the guise of speech acts carriedout by agents.Such a theory would
need to be founded on a general theory of speech acts carriedout by
agents.And this in turn would need to be founded on a generaltheory
of agency.Perhapsthe Belnap/Perloff"seeingto it that"approximation
to agency ("stittheory")is sufficientfor the purpose;it seems plausible
thatthis shouldbe so. But the workremainsto be done.

3.2. The Termsof the StandardAccount


Recall that the focus is on definitions (1) that are of individual
constants, predicate constants, and function constants;(2) that are in
the "materialmode";and (3) that are in (not an arbitrarylanguagebut)
an applied first order language with an inferential use. This focus
permitsus to give the criteriaof eliminabilityand of conservativeness
themselvesin the form of definitions,namely,definitionsof "satisfying
the criterion of eliminability"and of "satisfyingthe criterion of con-
servativeness."
It turnsout that there are four key entitiesinvolvedin explainingthe
standardideas of eliminabilityand conservativeness;or, as one might
well say, each of these ideas is explained as a four-placepredicate.I
shall attachto each of these key entitiesa variable,but for intelligibility
I shall use for each a spelled-out variablehaving a certain mnemonic
force.
* Theoryis the backgroundtheory (before the definition)in
the context of which the definitionis being entered. Theory
is a set of sentences of the usual kind; sometimesit is best
to think of it as closed under semantic or proof-theoretic
consequence,but my use of the variableis such that often
Theorycan be coded as a set of axioms.If the background
theory is thoroughlyinterpreted,Theorycan even be the set
of truths.
* Previous-definitionsis the set of previousdefinitions- a set
of sentences. This element is requiredto permit discussion
of circularity(a brother is a male sibling; a sibling is a
brotheror sister).
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 129

* Definition will be the definition itself. I remind you that


Definition is a sentence on a par with the rest of the
sentences in the context of which the act of definition is
taking place. One can therefore meaningfullyand without
quibblespeak of its grammaticaland deductiveand semantic
properties and relationships.It is just another first order
sentence.
* Symbolis the new symbolbeing defined.Recallthat Symbol
is to be a (new) predicate,operator,individualconstant,or
perhaps a sentence constant.The deepest theory would not
requireor even permit Symbol to be a symbol,permittingit
or even requiringit instead to be a grammaticalfunctionof
an appropriatetype;but I shall not in this discussionplumb
thatparticularabyss.
The above discussionhas mixed intuitiveand rigorousconsiderations.
Here I specify the latter,in particularsuppressingall verbs of psycho-
logicalattitude.
* Theoryis a set of sentences.
* Previous-definitions is a set of sentences.
* Definitionis a sentence.
* Symbol is a symbol (a predicate,operator,individualcon-
stant,or perhapssentenceconstant).

3.3. Criterionof Eliminability(RigorousAccount)


It is important to have the standard account of eliminabilitymade
rigorousso that one can more plainlysee whatis at stake.As promised,
the accountis presentedas a definitionof a four-placepredicate.Recall
that it is a presuppositionof the discussion that sentences are made
exclusivelyby way of truthfunctionsandquantifiers.

8. (Eliminability)Let Theory,Previous-definitions,
DEFINITION.
Definition, and Symbol be just as above. Then Definition,
qua definition of Symbol, satisfies the criterionof elimina-
bility relativeto Theoryand Previous-definitions if and only
if: For all (possibly open) sentences B in the languageof
130 NUEL BELNAP

Theory,Previous-definitions, and (especially) Symbol,there


is a (possiblyopen) sentenceB' suchthat
1. B' is in the languageof Theoryand Previous-definitions,
2. Symboldoes not occurin B', and
3. B and B' are EQUIVALENT relativeto Theory,Previ-
ous-definitions,and Definition.

Informally:For every sentence with the symbol there is an equivalent


sentencewithoutthe symbol- so all its meaningis given.
The standard account unpacks the critical notion of EQUIVA-
LENCE in either of two interchangeableways: proof-theoreticallyor
semantically.

* Proof-theoretically: One must be able to prove the "material


equivalence"of B and B' from the theorems, previous
definitions,and the definition(or their "formalequivalence"
if either is open). That is, B B' (or its universalclosure)
must be derivable (in a standard calculus) from Theory,
Previous-definitions, and Definition.
* Semantically:B and B' must be semanticallyequivalentin
the context of the theorems, previous definitions,and the
definition;that is, B and B' must have the same truthvalue
in every interpretationof the nonlogicalconstants(and free
variables if present) that renders all of Theory,Previous-
definitions,and Definitiontrue.

Equivalenceis at the heart of the eliminability.Because equivalenceis


well understoodfor truth-functions-cum-quantifiers languages,we can
be sure that for these languagesthe standardaccount makes sense. If,
however, a language does not have a well-understood concept of
equivalence,thenwe cannotbe surewhatto makeof eliminability.
It is plain that the concept of equivalence used in the standard
accountis an idealizationof "inferentialequivalence."Whatis confusing
is that this strong notion of equivalenceis required even though the
sentencesthat form the premissesand conclusionsof the inferencesare
all assumed to be made from truth functions and quantifiers.In
particular,the accountwould go to pieces with respectto the inferential
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 131

use of sentences if one were to substitute "materialequivalence"in


clause 3 above. This is not surprisingsince the gap between material
equivalenceand inferentialequivalenceis a pretty severe chasm.Here
are two witnesses to the cleft. (1) Clause 3 relativizesequivalenceto
Theory,Previous-definitions, and Definition;but it makes no sense to
relativize material equivalence. (2) Suppose, contrary to sense, that
clause 3 were stated with material equivalence. To make true the
resultant "for every B ... there is a B' such that ... B is materially
equivalentto B"', we would need only two valuesof B': a true one and
a false one. Thatwouldbe too easy.

3.4. Contextsand Meaning


The discussion of definitionsprobablygoes better if we elaboratethe
confusingmatterof "contexts."
In the first place, there are explicitcontextsand implicitcontexts.In
the exampleat hand, all the explicitcontexts are providedby the usual
array of extensional predicates, extensional operators, extensional
connectives(truthfunctions),and extensionalquantifiersleadingup to
a declarativecontext.The implicitcontext is that of inference(or some
close cousin). There is in the standardlanguageno "explicitation," in
Brandom'sphrase,of the inferentialcontext.We have to pay attention
to it, and so do the languageusers, but they have no device by which
explicitlyto speakof inference.Theyjustdo it (so to speak).
In the second place, we can therebysee that there are two contrasts,
two differentdimensionsalongwhich'context'couldbe enriched.
With regardto explicit contexts, one might have added their modal
featuresor "metalinguistic" featuresso as to give the users new explicit
contexts useful in speaking of inferentialconnections. This addition
might be preciselyto explicitatesome contexts so far left implicit.The
standardaccount does not deal with these. When such materialsare
added, we expect an account of meaningthat is no longer extensional.
We expect new predicates,operators,connectives,and quantifiersthat
are intensionalinstead of extensional.The general outlines of elimina-
bility and conservativenessremain, but the rigorous details must be
elaborated.
With regardto implicit contexts, the inferentialcontext imaginedin
132 NUEL BELNAP

the standardaccountis thin stuff.For example,it containsonly distant


approximationsto any of evidence, interest,relevance,explanation,or
practical decision. These are cognitive and practical concepts, essen-
tially relativizedto specific persons with specific mental equipmenton
specific occasions. The standardaccount does not provide a notion of
equivalence that can sustain replacementin such contexts. Such an
equivalencewould have to work for intentionalas well as intensional
contexts.It wouldneed to provideus withsense equivalence.
Becauseboth the inferentialor intensionalcontextsand the cognitive
or intentionalcontexts are often implicitratherthan explicit,it is easy
to forget this. Even Tarski, the most methodologicallysophisticated
definer of all time, once made a mistakeabout context.The mistakeis
easy to verifybecause Tarski 1935 stated his methodologyso carefully:
For a proposed definitionof "truth"to be adequate,it is both sufficient
and necessarythat it be "formallycorrect"and "materiallyadequate"in
the well knownsenses that Tarskigave to these phrases(p. 188, includ-
ing note 1). EvidentlyTarski'sidea of formalcorrectnessis just what I
am calling the standard account. It is equally evident that Tarski's
condition of material adequacy suffices to fix the inferentialrole of
"truth,"and not just its actual extension,as some folks sometimessay.
This is made explicitby his statementin Tarski 1944 that all adequate
definitions would have to be "necessarilyequivalent"(p. 354). It is
anyhow made implicitly clear by his use of the concept of "conse-
quence"in his statementof materialadequacy.
The mistake occurs when Tarski suggests an application for his
definition. Under the heading of "applicabilityof semantics to the
methodology of the empirical sciences," Tarski first considers the
reasonablenessof the following.
An acceptable theory cannot contain (or imply) any false
sentences.
His verdict is negative,partlybecause "we do not know, and are very
unlikelyto find, any criteriaof truth which enable us to show that no
sentenceof an empiricaltheoryis false"(p. 367).
This applicationby Tarskiis admissible.Whatmakesit so is that the
truth-ascriptionoccurs in the above sentencein an extensionalcontext.
This is the very sort of context for which the techniques on which
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 133

Tarski relies are apt. "Acceptability"is of course a cognitiveidea, but


the truth-ascriptionis not withinthe scope.
Tarski goes on, however, to propose that the following is "an
importantpostulate which can be reasonablyimposed on acceptable
empiricaltheoryandwhichinvolvesthe notionof truth":
As soon as we succeed in showingthat an empiricaltheory
contains(or implies)false sentences,it cannot be any longer
consideredacceptable(ibid.).
Here Tarskihas made a mistake.The difficultyis that in this postulate
the truth-ascriptiondoes occur withinthe scope of a (not just nonexten-
sional but) intentionalconnective.To show this, let me do as best as I
can to put the Tarskipostulateinto middleEnglish.
For each time t, for each empiricaltheory T, if (there is a
sentence x such that at t we succeed in showingthat ((x E
1) & - (x is true)))then T is not acceptableby us at t.
The mistakeis not that the postulateis false;it seems like quite a good
thing to say. Nor is it that Tarski'ssemanticdefinitionof truthcannot
help elucidate the postulate,though I certainlythink the prosentential
theory of truth does a better job of that. The mistakeis about defini-
tions. Tarski's mistake is that his definitional methodology fails to
license an eliminationof "x is true"within the scope of an "at t we
succeed in showingthat ." A moment'sthoughtsuffices to conclude
that inferentialequivalencebetween B and B', which is what Tarski's
methods guarantee,could not possibly suffice for replacingB with B'
within the scope of this nonextensionaland nonintensionalcognitive
connective.The rangeof applicationsfor his definitionthat are secured
by his methods,thoughgreat,are less thanhe envisaged.
So the standardtheory does not provide for eliminationin inten-
tional (as opposed to intensional)contexts.It cannot since its concept
of equivalenceis itself intensional equivalence(or inferentialequiva-
lence) ratherthan intentionalequivalence(or cognitiveequivalence,or
sense equivalence).The road forks. (1) Some may argue that we want
an enrichmentof the standardaccount of definitionthat would permit
eliminationin cognitive contexts. (2) Some may argue that we keep to
the intensionality-without-intentionality
of the standardtheory,thereby
134 NUEL BELNAP

giving up a call for eliminationin intentionalcontexts.For a powerful


discussion of the issues with particularreference to Frege, see Horty
1993. Horty gives a compelling argumentfor (2), which is now my
view.
These remarks are relevant to the aim of "extensionaladequacy"
sometimes proposed for a definition (but not by Tarski). Having
attained such an aim, one has no measure of the inferentialuse of
sentences containingthe newly defined Symbol.Extension alone does
not suffice to specify a role in inference. Given only extensional
adequacy,it thereforemakes doubtfulsense to infer either from or to
any sentence with the newly defined Symbol. Furthermore,since the
practiceof assertionis unsnippablytied to inference,we should worry
equallyaboutassertionon the basisof mereextensionaladequacy.
One mighttry to base a counterto this line on an idea publishedin
the same year by Bressan 1972 and Kripke1972, and muchearlierin a
somewhat different form by Marcus 1961. One may take the newly
defined symbol to be "rigid,"to adapt Kripke'sphrase,or to fall under
an "absoluteconcept,"to adaptBressan's,or to be a "tag,"followingthe
idea of Marcus.(These ideas are not the same;absolutenessis deepest
of these, and the closely relatednotion of "substanceconcept"in Gupta
1980 is equally deep and more manageable.But any will do for the
immediate purpose.) Taking this line makes an indexical out of the
newly introducedsymbol,somethinglike "theextensionof the definiens
as things actually stand here and now."There is nothing even mildly
wrong with such a definition;but it cannot be treated as a continuous
part of a language,such as thatwe were envisaging,that is "standard" in
being free of indexicals.The only mistakewould be to pretend other-
wise. In the standardlanguage,there is no room for such a counter.
Even in the richer language one would find the counter to fail, for
carefulanalysisrevealsthat you cannotavoid the need for an inferential
role, and therefore you cannot avoid awardingan intension.All that
happens when a "rigid"term is introduced is that its intension is
definitionallydeterminedby its indexicallydeterminedextension. My
point, however,is not to make theory.It is only this:If we are to think
seriouslyabout such definitions,it should be againstthe backgroundof
a carefulandrigorousaccountof them.
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 135

3.5. Criterionof Conservativeness


(RigorousAccount)
9. DEFINITION.(Conservativeness) Let Definition, Symbol,
Theory,and Previous-definitionsbe as above. Then Defini-
tion, qua definition of Symbol, satisfies the criterion of
conservativenessrelativeto Theoryand Previous-definitions
if and only if: For all sentences B in the languageof Theory
and Previous-definitions(but not containing Symbol), if
Definition,Theory,and Previous-definitions togetherIMPLY
B, then Theory and Previous-definitions(already, without
the necessityof Definition)togetherIMPLYB.
Using the languageof consequenceas a substitutefor that of
implication,as I usually do below, conservativenesscomes
to this:If a Symbol-freeB is a CONSEQUENCEof Theory
and Previous-definitionswith the help of Definition,then it
is so withoutits help.
Informally:Every sentence without the symbol is a consequence
withoutthe definitionif it is a consequence at all - so the definition
does nothingbut give the meaning.
The notion of CONSEQUENCE used above can be unpacked in
eitherof two (interchangeable) ways:proof-theoreticallyor semantically.
* Proof-theoretically,consequence means derivability (in a
standardcalculus).
* Semantically,for B to be a consequenceof some sentences
is for B to be true in every interpretationmaking those
sentencestrue.
Just as you cannotsubstitutematerialequivalencefor equivalencein the
preceding discussion of eliminability,so here you cannot substitute
materialimplicationfor implicationor consequence.These ideas make
no sense without an inferentialcontext. For example,suppose Theory
and Previous-definitions
are empty.Then if we were contrasensicallyto
read "IMPLY"materially,conservativenesswould say, I suppose, that
for each Symbol-freeB, (DefinitionD B) D B, i.e. (Definition V B).
And since some Symbol-freeB's will surelybe false, this comes to just:
Definition.Saythatagain?
136 NUEL BELNAP

3.6. Examples

10. EXAMPLE. Take Definition = "forall x, if x # 0, then for


all y, Inverse(x) = y iff x X y = 1."

Thus Definitiontakes Inverse(x) as the standardmultiplicativeinverse


of x, usuallywritten"1/x". And Inverse(x)"is defined"only when x is
not zero so that the problem of division by zero is avoided. Such a
definitionis often called a "conditionaldefinition,"the conditionbeing
thatx # 0.
Evidently Definitiondoes not satisfyeliminability,since you cannot
use it to eliminate all uses of Inverse(0). It does, however, satisfy a
"partial eliminability,"since Definition does permit elimination of
Inverse(t) for any term t such that Theory and Previous-definitions
imply that (t $ 0). More generally,Definitionpermits eliminationof
Inverse(x) in any sentence VxB(x) {or 3xB(x)} in which Theoryand
Previous-definitions imply that VxB(x) is equivalentto Vx((x $ 0) D
B(x)) {or that 3xB(x) is equivalentto 3x((x $ 0) & B(x))}. Since
these are known in advance as the only contexts of Inverse(t) or
Inverse(x)that we care about, such partialeliminabilityis conceptually
satisfying.
We know that Frege thoughtotherwise;he believed in total elimina-
bility. My own view is that Frege's belief (or practice) arose from a
certainslightlymisdirectedcompulsiveness- the same compulsiveness,
however, that gave the world its most glorious standardof uncom-
promisingrigor.Many of us, perhapsalmost equallycompulsive,avoid
conditional definitionsfor what we announce as mere technical con-
venience. Our alternate device is to use "don't-careclauses," e.g.
definingInverse(0)as equal to 0 (or perhapsas equal to 14), and then
remarkingthat this bit of the definitionis a don't-care.If one studies
our inferentialpractices,however,one sees thatwe never use the don't-
care clauses, and that we counsel others to avoid relying on them for
conceptualinterest.So practicallyspeaking,conditionaldefinitionsand
don't-careclausescome to the samething.
11. EXAMPLE.(Solubility) Take Definition = "for all x, if x is
put in water,then x is soluble if and only if x dissolves"as a
definitionof "soluble."
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 137

This is what Carnap called a "reductionsentence."He was surely


thinking that Definition gave us a "partial"definition of "soluble."
Supposethe theory Theorycontains"Samis put in water."Then clearly
Definitionpermitseliminationof "soluble"in the context B = "Samis
soluble,"for relative to the theory Theory,B' = "Sam dissolves"is
equivalentto B. But we couldn't eliminate the defined symbol from
"Maryis soluble"unless her presence in water was a consequenceof
our theory.
The superficialform of a reductionsentenceis the same as that of a
conditionaldefinition.I thinkthis resemblancemisleadsmanywho rely
on reductionsentences.But reductionsentencesand conditionaldefini-
tions are very different.In the case of conditionaldefinitions,we do not
want an account of the newly introducedsymbol as applied to argu-
ments not satisfyingthe condition.In the case of the reductionsentence
for solubility,however,the sampleswhose presencein waterwe cannot
deduce from the theory are preciselythose sampleswhose solubilitywe
care about.For example,it would be ridiculousto provide a don't-care
clause for the condition,addingthe followingto Example 11: "andif x
is not put in waterthan x is a rotten apple."That this would be foolish
is obvious from examinationof the inferentialcontexts in which one
findsthe conceptof solubility.
I infer that Carnap's terminology represents a serious blunder.
Reduction sentences do not give partial "reductions";unless, on
analogy,one wishes to take "countingto three"as "partiallycountingto
infinity."
Still considering Definition as in Example 11 above, suppose the
following oddity: "t is put in water"is a consequence of Theory,for
absolutely every closed term t. This would still not ensure that
Definitionabove satisfieseliminability;for consider some context B =
"for every x, x is soluble if and only if x . . . ," where the defined term is
used witha variableinsteadof a constant.
Turningnow to the other criterion,the reductionsentenceDefinition
of Example 11 is doubtless conservative.Suppose, however, that we
enrichDefinitionby addinga conjunct.

12. EXAMPLE.Let Definition' be taken as a definition of


solubility,where Definition' = (Definition& VxVy(ifx and
138 NUEL BELNAP

y are of the same naturalkind, then x is soluble if and only


if y is soluble)).
Adopting Definition' would doubtless enlarge the cases in which we
could eliminate "soluble."But notice that we can now conclude that
each thing of the same naturalkind as Sam, if put in water,dissolves if
and only if Sam does. Unless our Theoryalreadycommittedus to this
view, our definition would have smuggledin new assertionalcontent
and would not be conservative.A healthy respect for conservation
regardssuch sneakingas reprehensible.Thus again,reductionsentences
are not much like definitions after all. They do not reduce, or not
enoughto count.
What, then, do reduction sentences do? It is perfectly all right to
suggestthat they describe or establish"meaningrelations"between the
mysteryvocabularyto which "soluble"belongs and the less mysterious
languageof water and the like. The only thing that is wrong is to think
of them as "reducing"the mysterious to the less mysterious, even
partially.Onlythe terminologyis wrong.
Here is an example that early Carnap considered on his way to
reduction sentences, though I add a moral of which only the later
Carnapwouldhaveapproved.
13. EXAMPLE. (More solubility) Suppose we let Definition =
"forall x, x is soluble if and only if, if x is put in water,then
x dissolves."
This definitionof solubilityis bound to satisfyboth criteria,regardless
of theorems of previous definitions.Given our understandingthat we
are readingEnglishas if it were a standardfirst order language,it does,
however, have the strange (but still conservative)consequence that
whateveris not put in water is soluble, so that as stipulativeit is not a
happy choice and as lexical it is doubtlessfalse to our usage. One can
see here a motivefor an alternativetheoryof "if".The first and best job
of following out this insight is to be found in Bressan 1972. In rigor-
ously defining concepts of serious physics, such as the concept of
"mass"accordingto the intuitiveideas of Mach and Painlevee,Bressan
uses modal concepts precisely because of the failure of extensional
concepts to be apt. Carnap,in correspondencewith Bressan, strongly
encouragedthiswork.
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 139

4. RULES OF DEFINITION

Here, briefly, are the standardrules for producingdefinitionsguaran-


teed to satisfy the criteriaof eliminabilityand conservativeness.They
are easy. And by Beth's DefinabilityTheorem, they are complete for
the first order languagetruthfunctionswith quantifiers.Why is it, then,
that so much philosophyotherwisefaithfulto first-orderismis carried
out contraryto the policies they enjoin?Answer:Logic books, except-
ing Suppes 1957, do not give these matters proper discussion. The
consequence is that students of philosophy,even those who are thor-
oughly taught to manipulatequantifiers,are not taught the difference
between acceptable and unacceptabledefinitions. Since philosophers
spend vastly more time proposing and using definitionsthan they do
manipulatingquantifiers,thisis sad.
As promised,the rules are presentedas definitions.(Surelyit won't
occurto anyoneto thinkin this regardof circularity.)

14. DEFINITION.(Standardrule for definingby an equivalence)


Definition is a standarddefinitionof a predicatesymbol R
relativeto Theoryand Previous-definitionsiff for some n
(the n-arity of R), and some variables vl, . .. , vw, and some
sentenceA (the "definiens"),
1. Theory and Previous-definitionsare sets of sentences
(theoryand previousdefinitions,respectively),R is an n-
ary relation symbol (to be defined), and Definition is a
sentence(the candidatedefinition).
2. Definition is an n-times universallyquantifiedbicondi-
tionalV vl V vn(Rv, **vn A).
3. The variablesv1,. . ., vnare distinct.
4. The definiensA has no "dangling" or "floating"variables,
thatis, no free variablesotherthanv1,. . ., Vn.
5. Each nonlogicalsymbolin A is drawnfrom amongthose
of Theoryand Previous-definitions.
6. R is foreignto Theoryandto Previous-definitions.

It followsthatin particular,R does not occurin A.

15. DEFINITION.(Standardrule for defining an operatorby an


140 NUEL BELNAP

equivalence)Definitionis a standarddefinitionof an operator


symbol 0 relativeto Theoryand Previous-definitionsiff for
some n (the n-arityof 0), and some variablesv, . . . V, w,
and some sentenceA (the "definiens"),
1. Theory and Previous-definitionsare sets of sentences
(theoryand previousdefinitions,respectively),0 is an n-
ary operator symbol (to be defined), and Definitionis a
sentence(the candidatedefinition).
2. Definition is an (n + 1)-times universally quantified
biconditionalVv1... VvnVw((Ov1. . . vn= w) A).
3. The variablesv1,... ., vnand w are distinct.
4. The definiensA has no free variableother than vI,...,
v, and w.
5. Each nonlogicalsymbolin A is drawnfrom amongthose
of Theoryand Previous-definitions.
6. 0 is foreignto Theoryandto Previous-definitions
7. The sentence v1 ... vn3yVw[( y = w) A]is a con-
sequence of Theory together with Previous-definitions.
That is, it is a consequence of the theory together with
previous definitionsthat, for each n-tuple of arguments
V ... ., v, there is in fact exactly one value w such that
A; so A is "functional."
So 0 does not occurin A.

5. ADJUSTING THE RULES

Even withinthe purviewof the standardaccount,there are other forms


of definition with an equal claim to propriety.In the context of the
axiom of extensionalityin set theory, for instance, one may properly
define set-to-set operators by way of membershipconditions. In the
context of higher order axioms establishingan inductivelygenerated
structure(such as Peano's axioms),one may properlydefine operators
by rehearsingthe mode of inductive generation.Sometimes,in some
contexts, some of these are called "implicitdefinitions."In these cases,
"properly"means "insuch a way as to satisfythe criteriaof eliminability
and conservativeness."So much is a built-ingeneralityof the standard
account.
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 141

Suppose, however, the inductivematerialis added instead in a first


order way, includinga license for new inductivedefinitions.People who
wish to avoid relianceon higherorder logic sometimesproceed in this
fashion. Expressionsso defined are likely to be inferentiallyenriching
and therebyviolate the criterionof eliminability.This inductivepractice
is so well understood,however, that it appearsunreasonableto call it
into question- unless perhapsthe questionis foundational.Otherwise
it maybe betterto weakenthe criteriaandbendthe rules.
If the languageat issue is changedor extended,with the implication
that eliminabilityis now requiredfor additionalcontexts,then the rules
need adjustingin another sense; that is, following the rules may not
suffice for satisfyingthe criteria.For instance,a universallyquantified
biconditionalas in Definition 14 will evidentlynot permit elimination
of a defined predicatefrom a modal context. Should, then, Definition
have the form 0 Vx(Rx A), or should it instead have the form
Vxfl (Rx A)? Or will both or neitherof these do? The fundamental
point is this:We do not have to resort(much)to intuition.It is a matter
of whatis requiredto satisfythe criteria;that'sall.
Relevance logic offers an excellent example of the same phenome-
non. It is an interestingexercise to work out how to adjustthe rules for
defining new operators in Meyer's relevantarithmetic(see Anderson,
Belnap and Dunn 1992). With one eye on the two criteria,you can see
with the other preciselywhy and in what sense relevantarithmeticdoes
and shouldprohibitthata divisionoperatorbe defined.
A language with explicit tolerance for vagueness unquestionably
needs its own matchingstory about definitions.Some of Tappenden's
forthcomingwork on "pre-analytic" statementsseems to me to count as
in the requireddirection.

6. RELAXING THE CRITERIA (OR CHANGING THE RULES)

The standardcriteriaand rules must be counted as logic of the greatest


interest. They are, I should say, always to be respected as devices to
keep us from addle. On the other hand, one can easily find cases in
which good thinkingbids us moderatetheir force. Here is an illustra-
tion concerningnoncircularity.
Gupta(1988/1989) establishedthe following.
142 NUEL BELNAP

1. Some concepts are essentially circular.(Normal results of


inductivedefinitions,e.g. multiplication,are not examplesof
circularconcepts.)
2. The standard account of definitions says nothing useful
aboutcircularconcepts(I supposeit deniestheirexistence).
3. One obtains a powerful theory of circular concepts by
reworkingthe theory of definitionsto admit circulardefini-
tions.
4. Truth(in e.g.English)is a circularconcept.
5. The ideas of the reworkeddefinitionaltheory,when applied
to truth, make fall into place both the ordinary and the
extraordinary (pathological, paradoxical) phenomena to
whichphilosophershavecalledattention.

These notions are extended and defended in The Revision Theoryof


Truth,Guptaand Belnap 1992, which I will referenceas RTT. It is not
possible to summarizeeven the main ideas here; I only make a few
remarksrelatingthe RTTworkto the standardaccountof definitions.
RTT fully accepts conservativeness.The norm remains: If it's a
definition, then it should not provide camouflage for a substantive
assertion.I shan'tsay anythingmoreon thistopic.
RTT abandons eliminability,and in particularnoncircularity.The
indispensableidea is that a definitionalscheme cannot illuminatea
circularconcept except with the help of a circulardefinition,and that
circularityintrinsicallyprevents eliminability.As the standardaccount
is satisfiedwith only partialeliminabilityfor conditionaldefinitions,so
the RTT account is satisfiedwith only partialeliminabilityfor circular
definitions. For example, the RTT definition of truth permits its
eliminationfrom "'Euthyphrois pious'is true,"but not from "Thisvery
sentence is true."There is, however, a deep differencebetween how
noncircularityis relaxedin the presence of standardconditionaldefini-
tions and in the presence of RTT circulardefinitions.In the case of the
former, there is an inferentialaccount of when eliminabilityis to be
expected, and when not; the very form of a standard conditional
definitionsuppliesmaterialfor such an account,as explainedabove. In
contrast,on the RTT theory of circulardefinitions,eliminabilitymay
depend on contingentfacts. There is no grammaticalor even inferential
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 143

test to distinguisheliminable,innocuous circularityfrom ineliminable,


vicious circularity.Furthermore,RTT also abandonsthe other support
of eliminability,namely,no inferentialenrichment.In the case of truth,
RTT only requiresthat a definitionfix for it an appropriateintensionor
inferentialrole. It does not requirethat there alreadybe presentin the
languagesomethingelse that occupies that role. RTT thinksof truthas
an enrichmentof the languagein that sense, but as "definable"in the
sense that its intension is fixed. Adding truth is therefore just like
addingThe Absurd, as in Example 5, to a purelypositive language.In
both cases the inferentialrole is uniquelydetermined,but unoccupied
priorto the definition.
RTT changes the grammarof definitions.Definitionsare not given
explicitly as sentences, or even as theories, of the language.Instead,
"implicit"definitionalideas are introduced.In one scheme, ratherthan
requiringDefinition to be a sentence, as in Definition 14, a definition
straightwayrelates a definiendumto a definiens.The system of defini-
tions is thought of as an implicit part of the languagein just the way
that inferential connections are implicit. We, standing outside the
language,may clearly describe a part of such a system by writinge.g.
"Rx =Df A", just as we may write "A is a consequence of B." Other
rulesremainin force,except,crucially,(6) of Definition14.

16. EXAMPLE.RTT ignores an explicit Tarski biconditional


such as "'Euthyphrois pious'is true Euthyphrois pious,"
but it takes very seriously that there be a nonsymmetric
definition relation between "'Euthyphrois pious' is true"
and"Euthyphrois pious."
In an exactlyparallelfashion,where it is assumedthat Liar
- "Liar is not true", RTT ignores the self-contradictory
sentence "Liaris true Liar is not true",but it takes with
great seriousness the nonsymmetric definitional relation
between"Liaris true"and"Liaris not true".

RTT provides a semantic account of circulardefinitions.The Kernel


idea is given by the word "revision."You startwith an extensionfor all
but the various definienda,and you choose a hypothesis as to what
their extensions might be. You now have a hypotheticalextension for
144 NUEL BELNAP

everythingin the language,and thereforefor every definiens.You use


the definitionsto reviseyour hypothesis,arrivingat a new hypothetical
extension for each definiendum.And so forth - a phrase here indi-
catingprogressinto the transfinite.The hope is that you can eventually
arriveat categoricalresultsindependentof your startinghypothesis.
An especially fascinatingpart of this story is that RTT furnishes
somethingworthwhileto say about circularconcepts such as trutheven
in those cases in which eliminabilityfails. It does so by attendingto
their patterns of revision under different hypotheses. In this way forms
of pathologicalitycan be distinguishedone from the other in a concep-
tually satisfyingway. You can see the difference between "This very
sentence is true" and "This very sentence is false" by watching the
unfoldingof theiraltogetherdifferentpatternsof revision.
RTT describesproof-theoreticaltechniquescorrespondingas closely
as mightbe hoped to the semanticsof revision,thus completingthe trio
grammar/semantics/prooftheory. Of particular interest is that the
proof theoryreflectsa fundamentaldistinctionbetweenintroducingand
eliminatinga termby meansof a definition.

7. CODA

Two items remain.The first is to expressregretthat these remarkshave


been too coarse to capture the fine structureof even the standard
account of definitions.The second is to make explicit that the general
lesson has the usual banalform. On the one hand, the standardcriteria
and rules are marvelousguides. They have point. They are not to be
taken lightly. Every philosopher and indeed I should say everyone
engagedin conceptualwork oughtto know and understandthem.He or
she who unknowinglybreaks with the standardcriteria or the rules
risks of folly. On the other hand, there is no single aspect of these
criteriaor rulesthatwe shouldconsiderunalterable.

NOTE
1
Thankto A. GuptaandJ. Tappendenfor many-sidedhelp.
ON RIGOROUS DEFINITIONS 145

REFERENCES

Anderson, A. R., Belnap, N. D. and Dunn, J. M. (1992) Entailment:The Logic of


Relevanceand Necessity,Vol. 2, Princeton,PrincetonUniversityPress.
Bochenski, J. (1956) Formale Logik, Freiburg,K. Alber. Translatedand edited by I.
Thomas,A Historyof FormalLogic, second edition, New York, ChelseaPublishing
Company,1970.
Bressan, A. (1972) A GeneralInterpretedModal Calculus,New Haven and London,
Yale UniversityPress.
Carnap,P. (1937) The Logical Syntaxof Language,Internationallibraryof psychology,
philosophy and scientific method, New York, Harcourt, Brace. Translation of
LogischeSyntaxderSpracheby A. S. Smeaton(Countessvon Zeppelin).
Church, A. (1956) Introduction to MathematicalLogic, Princeton, NJ, Princeton
UniversityPress.
Couturat,L. (1905) "Lesdefinitionsmathematiques," L'Enseignementmathematique7,
27-40.
Curry,H. (1963) Foundationof MathematicalLogic,New York,McGraw-Hill,Inc.
Frege, G. (1964) The Basic Laws of Arithmetic;Exposition of the System,Berkeley,
Universityof CaliforniaPress. Translatedand edited, with an introduction,by M.
Furth.The translationis of "the introductoryportions of the first volume and an
epilogueappendedto the second."
Gupta,A. (1980) The Logic of CommonNouns:An Investigationin QuantifiedModal
Logic,New Haven,Yale UniversityPress.
Gupta,A. (1988/1989) "Remarkson Definitionsand the Concept of Truth,"Proceed-
ingsof theAristotelianSociety89, 227-246.
Gupta,A. and Belnap,N. (1992) The Revision Theoryof Truth,Cambridge,MA, The
MITPress.In press.
Horty,J. (1993) "Fregeon the PsychologicalSignificanceof Definitions,"Philosophical
Studies72. 223-263 (this issue).
Kneale, W. and Kneale, M (1962) The Developmentof Logic, Oxford,The Clarendon
Press.Reprintedfromcorrectedsheetsof the firstedition, 1966.
Kneebone, G. T. (1963) MathematicalLogic and the Foundationsof Mathematics,
Princeton,NJ,New York,Toronto,London,D. van NostrandPublishingCompany.
Kripke, S. (1972) "Namingand Necessity."In: D. Davidson and G. Harman (eds.),
Semantics of Natural Language,pp. 253-355. Dordrecht, D. Reidel Publishing
Company.
Legniewski,S. (1931), "Jber Definitionenin der sogenanntenTheorie der Deduktion,"
Comptesrendus des seances de la Societe des Science et des Lettresde Varsovie,
ClasseeIII,24, 289-309.
Lesniewski,S. (1981) CollectedWorks.S. J. Surma,J. T. J. Srzednicki,and D. I. Barnett
(eds.),Syntheselibrary,vol. 118, Boston,D. ReidelPublishingCompany.
Luschei, E. C. (1962) The Logical Systemsof Lesniewski,Amsterdam,North-Holland
PublishingCompany.
Marciszewski,W. (1981) "Definition."In: Marciszewski,W. (ed.), Dictionaryof Logic,
pp. 89-96. The Hague,MartinusNijhoff.
Marcus,R. B. (1961) "ModalitiesandIntensionalLanguages,"Synthese13, 303-322.
Robinson,R. (1950) Definition,Oxford,The ClarendonPress.
Runes,D. D. (1962) Dictionaryof Philosophy,Totowa,NJ, Littlefield,Adams.
Suppes, P. (1957) Introductionto Logic, PrincetonNJ, New York, Toronto, London,
D. vanNostrandPublishingCompany.
Tarski, A. (1935) "Der Wahrheitsbegriffin den formalisiertenSprachen,"Studia
Philosophica 1, 261-405. Germantranslationof a book in Polish, 1933. English
146 NUEL BELNAP

translationby J. H. Woodger,"TheConcept of Truthin FormalizedLanguage,"in


Logic, Semantics,Metamathetics,papers from 1923 to 1938 by A. Tarski,Oxford,
OxfordUniversityPress, 1956, pp. 152-278.
Tarski,A. (1941) Introductionto Logic and to the Methodologyof DeductiveSciences.
Enlargedand revised edition, New York, Oxford UniversityPress. Translatedby
Olaf Helmer from a work that appeared in Polish in 1936 and the in German
translationin 1937.
Tarski,A. (1944) "The SemanticConception of Truth,"Philosophyand Phenomeno-
logicalResearch4, 341-375.
Tarski, A. (1956) Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics,London and Oxford, The
ClarendonPress.

Departmentof Philosophy
Universityof Pittsburgh
Pittsburgh,PA 15260
USA

You might also like