Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 6

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/283348334

Aesthetics, Aesthetic Theories

Chapter · November 2015

CITATION READS

1 6,230

1 author:

Abby Mellick Lopes


Western Sydney University
44 PUBLICATIONS   153 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Transitioning to sustainable sanitation futures: a transdisciplinary pilot project of urine diversion systems View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Abby Mellick Lopes on 01 November 2015.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


AESTHETICS, AESTHETIC THEORIES 17

References and further reading 1998), where manufactured objects are understood and
promoted as reproductions of the one Idea.
Burke, D., J. Freedman, A. Frelinghuysen, et al. (Eds.).
Modern, western understandings of the terms
In Pursuit of Beauty: Americans and the Aesthetic
aesthetic and aesthetics derive from Continental and
Movement. New York: Rizzoli in association with the
British philosophers in the seventeenth and especially
Metropolitan Museum of Art, 1986, pp. 1–488.
eighteenth centuries, when philosophical endeavor
Calloway, S. and L. Federle Orr (Eds.), assisted by E.
was reappraising the value of the senses in the acqui-
Whittaker. The Cult of Beauty: The Aesthetic Movement
1860-1900. London: V&A Publishing, 2011.
sition of knowledge. Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten
Gere, C. and L. Hoskins The House Beautiful: Oscar Wilde coined the term “aesthetics” in 1735 (in his Reflections
and the Aesthetic Interior. London: Lund Humphries and on Poetry) to distinguish philosophical ideas about
the Geffrye Museum, 2000. what is sensed and imagined from logic, as a legitimate
field of philosophical inquiry related to the judgment of
Erica Warren “taste” (Guyer, 2014). David Hume was concerned with
a particular standard or sensitivity in judgments of taste
See also Art Glass; Aubrey Beardsley; Collinson and Lock; and established a seamless connection between moral
Daniel Cottier; Walter Crane; Lewis F. Day; Christopher and aesthetic value (Guyer, 2014), which continues
Dresser; Charles Eastlake; Frank Furness; E. W. to inflect cultural production as the visible expression
Godwin; Herter Bros.; Hukin and Heath; Interior Design; of moral ideas (see also the Earl of Shaftesbury). The
Japonisme; Jeffrey and Co.; Owen Jones; Liberty and division in the study of knowledge between rationalism
Co.; Linthorpe Pottery; London 1862; Queen Anne and empiricism hinged to some extent on the eye as a
Revival; Reformed Gothic; John Ruskin; Arthur Silver; reference point for the sovereign insights of reason, free
Bruce Talbert; Louis Comfort Tiffany; Candace Wheeler. of sensory experience (Descartes; Kant), or the explicit
and “perspectival knowing” of a particular sentient
being in the world (Nietzsche; Gadamer; Merleau-
Ponty). The idea of an aesthetic sensibility or attitude
AESTHETICS, AESTHETIC THEORIES as its own kind of knowing traverses both rational and
empirical thought, with significant transformations in
History of the term
the importance attributed to the perceiving body.
The term Aesthetic, derived from the ancient Greek
aisthanesthai (to perceive), refers to a dynamic
and complex set of relationships in human sensory
Aesthetic sensibility
perception. These are the sensory perception of Aesthetic judgment is “a force for making our sensory
things like nature or art; the feelings aroused by these reactions more acute, more pointed” (Barilli, 1993,
perceptual experiences; the character (or design) of p. 3). For Emmanuel Kant writing in 1790, concepts
the experienced things themselves; and the acuity of were nothing without percepts. Aesthetic judgment
subjective judgment associated with perceiving these depends on the form or design of encountered (natural)
things. objects as they come together as concrete phenom-
The idea of beauty has been profoundly influential in enon. The determination of “beauty” is not a matter
determining aesthetic value in the West to the current time. of subjective preference, but a universal truth that
For Plato, “beauty,” like “the good,” is an eternal Idea char- reaches consensus in the object with a general power
acterized by mathematical qualities of proportion, harmony of affect—we say something is beautiful, and it appears
(or “fitness”), and unity, and untouched by the constant that beauty belongs to the object. Taste for Kant is “the
flux of the human world where the Ideas are reflected. In ability to judge the pleasure occasioned by a presenta-
Aristotelian metaphysics, beauty is experienced as order, tion in terms of its potential universalizability” (Tanke
symmetry, and determinateness. Perhaps the most criti- and McQuillan, 2012, p. 237). The aesthetic encounter
cally important aesthetic principle emerging from Hellenic elicits the free play of imagination and reflective contem-
antiquity is that beauty consists in the imaginative or plation. It is not dependent on the interest or desire of
sensuous expression of unity in variety; the one in the the observer and is therefore non-teleological. This
many (Bosanquet, 1892, p. 32). This idea survives in necessary disinterest is in contrast to the useful quality
the Platonism of design (Verbeek and Kockelkoren, of Beauty present in Greek thought. Eyes are the first

T H E B LO O M S B U R Y E N C Y C LO P E D I A O F D E S I G N

9781472521545_txt_prf_A.indd 17 21/09/15 3:02 PM


18 AESTHETICS, AESTHETIC THEORIES

example quoted to prove the usefulness of beauty in that the disinterested, volitional, non-teleological qual-
Plato. For Plato, beautiful eyes are those that see best ities of the aesthetic encounter prompt an ethics bound
(Grube, 1927). For Kant, beauty is “useless purposeful- to the contingent particulars of form in time and space.
ness” (see Tonkinwise, 2003); it is only for its own sake. The sensory particulars of experience situate us in a
The disinterested stance of aesthetic judgment world, in a place in time to make sense of. This argu-
took material form in the designation of the “fine arts” ment resonates with the unique quality of “aura” in
as a special category of objects that mediate aesthetic Benjamin’s thought and connects with other writers on
experience. The study of fine arts became synony- aesthetics, for example Elaine Scarry, who links beauty
mous with the study of aesthetics through a correlation to justice and an awareness of a reciprocal aliveness
between aesthetic perception and aesthetic creation. between the perceiver and the perceived. Beauty elic-
As explained by Bosanquet (1892) in A History of its a creative impulse to reproduce, but not, and here
Aesthetic (the first history of aesthetics in English), “the she is also allied with Kant, to capture the thing experi-
History of Fine Art is the history of the actual aesthetic enced: the thing is not beautiful by virtue of its ability to
consciousness, as a concrete phenomenon” (p. 2). serve self-interest, but because it is in the interests of
This correlation was further realized in the museum everyone. For Scarry, loveliness of aspect (eidos) elic-
or “white cube” of the art gallery as special housing its carefulness and a delicate awareness: a capacity to
wherein such objects could present themselves for notice the manner of things. This empathetic impulse in
contemplation with the appropriate “breathing space” the aesthetic disposition allows insight into more than
(Baudrillard, 1996). is said, into the unifying design of a work. An ability to
Aesthetic judgment also had ontological implica- grasp the thread of Scarry’s thought, for example, is
tions. The cultivation of an aesthetic sensibility as an enhanced by sensitivity toward her particular sentient
appropriate manner in which to approach and appre- humanism in its sociopolitical and historical context.
ciate the intrinsic perceptual qualities of worldly things, We can also think here of the essay (a form of writing
detached from how these things came into being or pioneered by Hume) as an aesthetic mediation by way
the techniques involved in making them, evolved as of which the reader gets close to both the ideas and the
a sign of cultural capital (Bourdieu) and a detachment habitus of the thinker. It is important to note however
from the social, political, and ecological implications of that this reading of disinterest in aesthetics does not
sensory objects. The figure of the aesthete as a privi- make a claim for a necessary link between aesthetics
leged, hedonistic lover of beauty, basking indulgently and an ethics of practice.
in the sensorium (Baudelaire’s “dandy”; the Bloomsbury
group), free from purpose or sociopolitical conse-
quences, can now be linked to that of the cultural
Reification
consumer in twenty-first-century capitalism, indulging It is a common theme running through the thought
in the free play of symbolic exchange (see Sign). This on aesthetics that the senses are malleable and
free play underscored novelty as an important charac- schooled by social and cultural conditions (e.g., Marx
teristic of aesthetic experience (Barilli, 1993, p. 18). The in Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844;
refusal to account for the sociopolitical and historical Berleant, 2000). Sense perception mediates experi-
dimensions of objects was intolerable for some twen- ence, prior to the rationalization of that experience.
tieth-century theorists who called for the elimination However, the designed materiality of culture that forms
of aesthetics as a separate field of study (Bourdieu for the background condition of everyday life is also an
example, and Gadamer who rejected Kantian aesthet- aesthetic production. In his cultural history of water,
ics as ahistorical). Ivan Illich (1985) tells us the time that it took for people
to learn to feel nausea and shame at the smell of their
own bodily waste, depended on their access to the
Aesthetics and ethics infrastructure, products, and social practices of modern
Other theorists however have sought to foreground sanitation. These seemingly involuntary biological and
the particular importance of aesthetic experience and sensori-emotional responses are a result of cultural
even to argue for a connection between aesthetics aesthetic conditioning.
and ethics. Bringing Kantian aesthetics into a relation These observations suggest that far from being
with Levinasian ethics, Susan Stewart (2005) argues universal, aesthetic judgment is a culturally specific

T H E B LO O M S B U RY E N CYC LO P E D I A O F D E S I G N

9781472521545_txt_prf_A.indd 18 21/09/15 3:02 PM


AESTHETICS, AESTHETIC THEORIES 19

attribution of value that brings things into being over Consumerism and aesthetics
against the environment. In the frame of the World
Heritage List, custodians of contested lands must vie to As a legacy of Hellenic thought, the mass-produced
merit the attention of the appreciative gaze so that their forms of consumer culture reproduce the one Idea.
lands and cultural practices may be deemed aesthet- Guy Debord (1994) remarks “Each individual commod-
ically important and/or authentic and therefore worthy ity fights for itself, cannot acknowledge the others and
of protection from activities such as development or aspires to impose its presence everywhere as though it
mining. This reifying characteristic is a central feature were alone” (p. 43). The commodity form also reproduces
of the ways in which modern aesthetics has evolved. preexisting meanings and sensations. Modernism, the
Aesthetics has been accused of doing violence where dominant aesthetic of consumer culture, has become a
appreciation of beauty becomes an objectifying gaze universal standard for design. Through design’s mate-
(Sartre) and where reification of the senses places rial reproductions, our modernist aesthetic sensibilities
ocular knowledge above all else. For Morton (2007) have been schooled. We have learnt to appreciate
“the history of the aesthetic has been the story of how the look, smell, and feel of “box-fresh newness” and
bodies, and especially non-visual sense organs, have through the presence of certain aesthetic features (that
been relegated and gradually forgotten, if not entirely promote for example conventions of comfort, cleanli-
erased” (p. 165). ness, and convenience [see Shove, 2003]; or “realism”
For Heidegger, the discourse of metaphysics is ulti- [Stewart, 2005]) trust is elicited. We know in advance
mately realized in the technological transformation of what to expect of the emerging “good” and know that
life in the modern age, which operates by way of a once its perfection is tainted by use, it will never again
structural reification of figure and ground (enframing). be the same, or as good.
The authority of representation is brought into being Augmented by the rhetoric of promotional images,
and continually asserted by technologies of vision that the designed commodity is the Platonic form made
write over being in the world, being in a particular place material. In it, functional and aesthetic perfection coin-
and time, and the value of knowledge that belongs to cide. For Michl (1991), functionalism propped up the
the sentient being so situated. In tandem, representa- Modernist vision that design was a fine rather than
tion has brought into being a frontal ontology by which applied art. This idea is borne out by the graphics
all that matters is rendered in an opposition between tools used to prefigure industrial commodities, which
subject and object. Aesthetic appreciation through emphasize spatial, formal objective qualities suspended
distancing—the attitude of sitting back and watching in white (“breathing”) space. The visual aesthetic of
something without getting involved—is enhanced by modernism is intolerant to any sign of contingent mate-
representation. Ingold (2004) furthers this argument riality, such as the passage of time, while also being
about the oculocentric progress of modernity by eminently susceptible to wear and tear (on this point
attending to the aesthetic experiences suppressed by see Mostafavi and Leatherbarrow’s 1993 environmental
the design of our built environments. He insists that analysis of Le Corbusier’s Villa Savoye), that is, unless
human knowledge is not static but perambulatory— the ruin of the object’s perfection can also be aesthet-
we are meant to be able to walk around things, and icized; appreciated as a sign of neoclassical beauty
see the shadows pass over things in order to know or as a counterpoint to modern technological society
them (relative to our own moving body). The screen- (Beck [1995] on nature as a cultural model). What is
based knowing of the “seated society” that elevates sustained in the aesthetics of consumerism is the
the plane of social life over and above the ground of detached, nonreciprocity of the sign form (see Sign).
nature takes us further away from forms of knowledge
that situate our being in the world. Screen objects
move on behalf of the body, including the eyes.
Spectacle
Aesthetics as the experience of things (aesthesis) is The spectacle (Debord) refers to the totalizing power
replaced by aesthetics as visual representation: “a of commodification under the rule of representation.
symbolic transcription and subtraction of sensory The spectacle is not merely an image on a screen, or
qualities” (Barilli, 1993, p. 115). In spite of the “full- a concatenation of imaged events (celebrities, wars,
ness” of aesthetic effects, this bodily stasis is a form public humiliations, sporting events, advertisements)
of anesthetic: sensory deprivation. that hold the spectator/consumer in a contemplative

T H E B LO O M S B U R Y E N C Y C LO P E D I A O F D E S I G N

9781472521545_txt_prf_A.indd 19 21/09/15 3:02 PM


20 AESTHETICS, AESTHETIC THEORIES

stance, but an economically motivated societal and important concept for understanding the dynamic
cultural conditioning the result of which is a histori- relationship between the production of symbolic value
cal and political stasis. The spectacle is not “false” or and material production, and the dialectic of crea-
“illusory” (Descartes) but the false and illusory made tion and destruction it entails (see Fry, 2009). This
real, material, plural, and social through the autono- condition can be understood as growing in signifi-
mous power of economic production and exchange cance with the rise of digital economies and, with
value. The spectacle takes the reifying oculocentric the saturation of information and communications
gaze to a societal level, as an expression of this total- technology devices, has literally reached into every
izing power. The spectacle destroys social time and pocket of experience. The effective, perceptual sepa-
social creativity by creating time for the “consumption” ration between the means and ends of production
of images and the exchange of commodities. This argu- (identified by Debord) is most pronounced in the case
ment was advanced in Guy Debord’s 1967 book The of digitization where exponential ecological impacts
Society of the Spectacle, which can now be understood (caused by the siting, construction, and maintenance
as an articulate expression of disgust at the dramatically of data centers, innovation-driven waste streams,
depoliticized mood of contemporary society in spite of spread of digital infrastructure, consumption of
its wide socioeconomic disparity. The book was impor- human and fossil fuel-derived energy, and so on)
tant in galvanizing the student and worker insurrections are concealed by the seemingly autonomous flow of
of May 1968, which mobilized the critical capacity of images.
avant-garde practice (such as that of the Situationist
International) to effect a genuine disruption (détourne-
ment—see Sign) of the spectacle’s smooth progress.
Sustainment and aesthetics
Debord’s text suggests that it is through such actions Consumerism has reduced aesthetics to “cosmetic
that an aesthetic revolution could redirect historical life. treatment” (Barilli, 1993). But this does not mean that
For Adorno, aesthetic thought could only advance aesthetics should be understood as so reduced. It
by confronting the commodification of experience deliv- would be in error to underplay the historical significance
ered through the spectacle of images and commodity of aesthetics and its critical role in understanding how
forms. But as Debord recognized, analyzing the specta- perceptual dispositions toward “what is” have been
cle means talking in its language and with its conceptual shaped. This significance is demonstrated for exam-
and material tools, to some degree. This explains why ple by Denis Cosgrove’s observation that horizontal
critique of the commodification of culture and experi- fixed-point perspective marked the emergence of capi-
ence emerges largely from the legitimized domains of talism, Morton’s insights about the relationship between
aesthetic appreciation (the arts and the humanities), romantic literature and the formation of an “ecological
which know its objects in intimate detail, rather than imaginary,” or David Brody’s reflection on the inner
from the discourse of for example business, econom- connection between Platonic and Haeckelian aesthet-
ics, law, or the sciences. After Debord, the aesthetic ics, which underpins the argument discernable in the
disciplines must find ways to avoid replicating depo- contemporary science of biomimicry, that “beauty is
liticized free play in the practice of critical thought (as the proof of natural intelligence” (Brody, 2002, np). The
apologia), and determine an appropriate teleology for balance theory of ecology has its roots, therefore, in an
aesthetic critique. aesthetic argument.
The aestheticization of everyday life (Baudrillard, A number of authors have made the point that
Jameson, Featherstone) is an idea that offers an aesthetic thought is crucially important if we are to
inverse perspective on Debord’s totalizing critique understand our complex and intensively designed
to consider the semiological mediation of everyday environments in ways that can help us to live well in
social experience. Commencing with Marx’s theory of them. Yet, as Beck suggests, we can no longer trust
the fetishism of commodities and developed in vari- our senses. Material and semiotic design has actively
ous ways by Lukács, the Frankfurt School, Benjamin suppressed the capacity for aesthetic knowing. And in
(particularly his analyses of the materialization of addition to this, many of the unintended products of
commodity fetishism in the arcades of mid-nine- human making subvert the contemplative stance of
teenth-century Paris), and Jameson (Featherstone, aesthetic regard. Due to the hegemonic status of visual
2007), the aestheticization of everyday life is an representation we have not developed multisensory

T H E B LO O M S B U RY E N CYC LO P E D I A O F D E S I G N

9781472521545_txt_prf_A.indd 20 21/09/15 3:02 PM


AFFORDANCE 21

perceptual faculties up to the task of noticing the Ingold, Tim. “Culture on the Ground: The World Perceived
manner and design of things such as the oil slick, the through the Feet,” Journal of Material Culture, 9.3
bush fire, radiation, persistent biotoxins, and innumera- (2004): 315–340.
ble other “objects” of human design that exceed human Michl, Jan. On the Rumor of Functional Perfection, Pro
perception and knowledge (see Morton, 2011). Such Forma 2, Oslo, Norway (1990–1991): 67–81. http://
objects resist frontal representation and must be felt janmichl.com/eng.rumor.html
and experienced in new ways, for example, in terms Morton, Timothy. Ecology without Nature. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2007.
of their dynamic vitality or contingent biophysical, soci-
Morton, Timothy. “The Mesh”. In LeMenager, Stephanie,
opolitical, cultural, and historical impacts. An ethical
Teresa Shewry, and Ken Hiltner (Eds.), Environmental
aesthetics of sustainment might involve the design of
Criticism for the Twenty-First Century. New York:
percepts (Deleuze and Guattari, 1994) that facilitate the
Routledge, 2011, pp. 19–30.
reschooling of sense perception and imagination along
Mostafavi, Mosen and David Leatherbarrow. On
these lines.
Weathering: The Life of Buildings in Time. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 1993.
Scarry, Elaine. On Beauty and Being Just. Princeton, NJ:
References and further reading Princeton University Press, 1999.
Shove, Elizabeth. Comfort, Cleanliness and Convenience:
Barilli, Renato. A Course on Aesthetics. Trans. Karen E.
The Social Organization of Normality. Oxford and New
Pinkus. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press,
York: Berg, 2003.
1993.
Stewart, Susan. The Open Studio: Essays on Art and
Baudrillard, Jean. The System of Objects. Trans. James
Aesthetics. London: University of Chicago Press, 2005.
Benedict. London/New York: Verso, 1996.
Tanke, Joseph and Colin McQuillan (Eds.). The Bloomsbury
Beck, Ulrich. Ecological Enlightenment: Essays on the
Anthology of Aesthetics. New York and London:
Politics of the Risk Society. Trans. Mark A. Ritter. New
Bloomsbury, 2012.
York: Humanity Books, 1995.
Tonkinwise, Cameron. “Beauty-in-Use.” Design Philosophy
Berleant, Arnold. The Aesthetic Field: A Phenomenology
Papers 2 (2003). http://www.desphilosophy.com
of Aesthetic Experience. Christchurch: Cybereditions
Verbeek, Peter-Paul and Petran Kockelkoren. “The Things
Corporation, 2000.
That Matter,” Design Issues, 14.3 (Autumn 1998): 28–42.
Bosanquet, Bernard. A History of Aesthetic. London:
George Allen & Unwin, 1892. Special thanks to Helen Armstrong for contributing
Brody, David. “Ernst Haeckel and the Microbial Baroque.” resources to this entry.
Cabinet Magazine 7 (Summer 2002). http://cabinetmag-
azine.org/issues/7/ernsthaeckel.php Abby Mellick Lopes
Debord, Guy. The Society of the Spectacle. Trans. Donald
Nicholson-Smith. New York: Zone Books, 1994. See also Beauty; Consumption; Empiricism; Form;
Deleuze, Gilles and Félix Guattari. “Percept, Affect and Functionalism; Heritage; Modernism; Style.
Concept”. In Tanke, Joseph and Colin McQuillan (Eds.),
The Bloomsbury Anthology of Aesthetics. New York and
London: Bloomsbury, 2012, pp. 591–601.
Featherstone, Mike. “The Aestheticization of Everyday Life.”
AFFORDANCE
In Consumer Culture and Postmodernism (2nd ed.).
Affordance is the experience of a product or an aspect
London: Sage, 2007, pp. 64–81.
of a product as enabling an action. Psychologist of
Fry, Tony. Design Futuring: Sustainability, Ethics and New
Practice. New York: Berg, 2009.
perception, James Gibson, coined the term affor-
Grube, George M. A. “Plato’s Theory of Beauty,” The dance, to refer to experiences that exemplified the way
Monist, 37.2 (1927): 269–288. perception is interactionist. Gibson was reacting to a
Guyer, Paul. 18th Century German Aesthetics. Stanford model of perception that insisted on strict divisions
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/ between the perceiving subject and the perceived
entries/aesthetics-18th-german/, 2014. object. In that model, perception is a cognitive activ-
Illich, Ivan. H2O and the Waters of Forgetfulness: Reflections ity in which representations of things in the world are
on the Historicity of Stuff. Dallas, TX: The Dallas Institute interpreted in the minds of subjects. Having interpreted
of Humanities and Culture, 1985. what they perceive to be around them, subjects then

T H E B LO O M S B U R Y E N C Y C LO P E D I A O F D E S I G N

9781472521545_txt_prf_A.indd
View publication stats 21 21/09/15 3:02 PM

You might also like