American Oriental Society

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 3

Proofs for Eternity, Creation and the Existence of God in Medieval Islamic and Jewish

Philosophy by Herbert A. Davidson


Review by: Daniel H. Frank
Journal of the American Oriental Society, Vol. 110, No. 2 (Apr. - Jun., 1990), pp. 366-367
Published by: American Oriental Society
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/604560 .
Accessed: 30/12/2014 09:46

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Oriental Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of
the American Oriental Society.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Tue, 30 Dec 2014 09:46:50 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
366 Journal of the American Oriental Society 110.2 (1990)

The tone of positive assertion in the text contains no Proofs for Eternity, Creation and the Existence of God in
acknowledgement of interpretive debates. Many of Lapidus' Medieval Islamic and Jewish Philosophy. By HERBERT A.
statements are more controversial than he makes them seem, DAVIDSON. New York and Oxford: OXFORD UNIVERSITY
although differences of opinion are noted in the bib- PRESS, 1987. Pp. xii + 428. $37.50.
liography. Different people make different choices of what to
include or omit. Here Zaydis are omitted from the discussion Let it be said at once that this volume is a towering
of Shi'i Islam on pages 115-19 as is Islam in modern achievement. At the height of his powers here, Davidson has
Afghanistan and Muslims in northern Europe and the west- gone back to the sources to assemble all the significant
ern hemisphere. Arabia is ignored after the Islamic conquests medieval Islamic and Jewish proofs for the eternity of the
because it was "outside the framework of general Middle world, for the creation of the world, and for the existence of
Eastern developments" (p. 344). Nevertheless Lapidus re- God. Nine proofs for the eternity of the world, eight proofs
peatedly alludes to the development of a reform tendency in for its creation, and, finally, eight proofs for God's existence
eighteenth-century Makka without explaining what it was. are adduced. In addition, the responses to these arguments
Anyone who intends to use this volume as a textbook for from their respective opponents are also presented. Thus, the
a survey course should be aware that its elimination of book is in effect an extended dialogue across cultures and
former misconceptions is accompanied by the introduction centuries over the issues at hand. The major players are all
of new mistakes for the uninitiated to repeat. Najda (p. 60) here, beginning with Aristotle, continuing through Proclus
should be Najdiyya; Mazdaite (p. 79) should be Mazdakite; and his creationist critic Philoponus, and into the medieval
Kritzech (p. 940) should be Kritzeck; Alaric (p. 379) should period with (most importantly, but not exclusively) Avicenna,
be Visigothic (Alaric never lived to see Spain); the battle of Ghazali, Averroes, Maimonides, Gersonides and Crescas. It
Poitiers was in 733 not 732; and North African Berbers is most welcome to see the medieval Islamic and Jewish
converted to Khariji Islam in the eighth century not the philosophers treated so rigorously in their own right, not
seventh (p. 491). It is misleading to date the change in merely as precursors to Aquinas, or, even worse, as puppets
language of the tax registers to Arabic in Khurasan in 742 to dangling in a history of medieval thought. This book pro-
"shortly after 700," to speak of "Sunni" Muslims before the vides as clear an indication as one could hope to have of the
third fitna, or to locate the names of Sufi brotherhoods on health and vitality of Greek wisdom before its (re)discovery
only one spot on map 8, "Muslim schools of law and Sufi in (Christian) Europe.
brotherhoods: c. 1500." It is equally misleading to claim that The book is not only "exhaustive" but also exhausting.
the earliest experience of non-Muslim rule by Muslims was The argumentation is relentless, even with summaries ap-
in the Crusader states and Spain in the thirteenth century pended to most chapters and resumes after crucial argu-
(pp. 387-88) rather than the twelfth. There were even earlier ments. The book is clearly written but, given the denseness
experiences by the Muslim merchant colony in China in the of the material, I fear that it may be one that individuals will
eighth and ninth centuries, in northern Syria under the own but will not read except as a source book for one
Greeks and in the Alps after the fall of Fraxinetum in the argument or another. Furthermore, the book's rather un-
late tenth century, and an important experience under the compromising tone, coupled with the author's reputation,
pagan Qarakhitai in central Asia in the twelfth century. may seduce readers into accepting without question David-
Instructors will need to define Phalange (p. 658) themselves. son's interpretations as final. From a reading of the text one
They may also want to explain to beginners that Lapidus would not realize that controversy has attended (and attends)
uses "segmented" to mean differentiated or pluralistic, and at least some of the issues which Davidson discusses. (I
"lineage communities" for tribal societies rather than "seg- discuss one such issue below).
mentary" as used by anthropologists, which can be confus- Although the book is a contribution to the history of
ing. The text will be most suitable for courses organized philosophical ideas and, as such, eschews for the most part
along regional lines and will need to be supplemented with evaluation of arguments, the philosophically minded reader
something that provides more political history, such as the may wish Davidson had proceeded in a more critical manner.
books in the Longman series. As it is, he is content to let the philosophers speak for
In many ways this is a transitional work that looks themselves (and against each other), and rarely engages them
backward and forward at the same time. As such its signifi- in debate. When he does so, as in the case of his dismissal of
cance consists in the way it shifts the discourse from what Averroes' critique of Avicenna's "metaphysical" proof for
Islam does to what Muslims do. God's existence (pp. 331-34), the conclusion is compelling.
The bibliography cites no secondary sources, and virtually
MICHAEL G. MORONY none are cited in the footnotes save for Wolfson. To be sure,
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, Los ANGELES basing a book on primary texts, unmediated by commentary,
can be intellectually liberating, forcing one to return to the

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Tue, 30 Dec 2014 09:46:50 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Reviews of Books 367

sources themselves to make up one's mind rather than not have been, and thus the distinction between necessity
(merely) taking sides in a "current" dispute. On the other and possibility cannot be mapped on to a distinction be-
hand, such an approach can be (or appear to be) self-serving, tween necessary and possible being.
suggesting that virtually nothing that modern scholarship Avicenna's proof comes into clearer focus upon realization
has to offer is of worth. Even if this latter claim is true, it of this last point. The proof is in fact explicable only when
requires argumentation to show it. Unfortunately, the book we accept the (apparent) paradox that some necessary ob-
does not provide such argumentation. And such argumenta- jects are possible. And when we realize this, we may under-
tion would, I think, have enlivened the text. It would stand that the "necessity" (i.e., the actual existence) of
encourage the reader to take part in an on-going debate, possible objects entails the existence of something whose
and, pricked by the conflict of views, to return to the sources being accounts for or renders possible the existence of the
themselves to make up his own mind. possibilia. And such an existent is God, a being that exists
For the remainder of this review I focus upon a single, per se, through itself. From the fact, then, that there exists
controversial claim of Davidson's, namely that nowhere in an object (any object) whose being is dependent, i.e., not
medieval Islamic and Jewish philosophical literature is there necessarily existent by virtue of itself, we may ultimately
to be found an ontological proof for the existence of God establish the existence of that being which exists per se. The
(pp. 214-16). For this view Davidson expands upon a proof is indeed a cosmological proof, depending not merely
previous article of his own ("Avicenna's Proof of the Exis- upon the analysis of concepts, but also upon the (actual and
tence of God as a Necessarily Existent Being," in Islamic necessary) existence of an object which "must depend on a
Philosophical Theology, ed. P. Morewedge [Albany, 1979]) factor distinct from it to maintain it in existence" (p. 309). I
and, in the main, follows Wolfson ("Notes on Proofs of the think that Davidson has successfully countered the arguments
Existence of God in Jewish Philosophy," in Studies in the of those who wish to read Avicenna's proof as an ontological
History of Philosophy and Religion, vol. 1 [Cambridge, proof for God's existence. Rather, Avicenna's proof is of a
Mass., 1973], 569-70). He counters, most recently, More- piece with other (cosmological) proofs in the Aristotelian
wedge ("Ibn Sina, Malcolm and the Ontological Argument," tradition of which it is a part.
The Monist 54 [1970]; "A Third Version of the Ontological In sum, while requiring maximum effort on the part of the
Argument in the Ibn Sinian Metaphysics," in Islamic Philo- reader and without the customary genuflection to current
sophical Theology). scholarship, I nominate this volume as the most substantial
The paradigm case in the medieval Islamic-Jewish tradi- contribution to medieval Islamic-Jewish philosophy since the
tion for what is assumed to be an ontological proof for seminal works of Wolfson.
God's existence is Avicenna's celebrated "metaphysical"proof
(found most prominently in the Najdt), a proof based on an DANIEL H. FRANK
analysis of the concepts "necessarily existent" and "possibly UNIVERSITY OF KENTUCKY
existent." Although this proof is clearly distinguished by
Avicenna from one which proceeds from God's "creation
and effect" (a patently a posteriori, empirical proof depend-
ing upon the nature of the physical universe), the "meta-
physical" proof is not, according to Davidson, thereby an a Averroes Epitome in Physicorum Libros. Edited by JOSEP
priori proof. The analysis of "necessarily existent" is not by PUIG. Corpus Commentariorum Averrois in Aristotelem:
itself sufficient to prove the existence of a being "necessarily Series Arabica, A XX. Madrid: INSTITUTOHISPANO-ARABE
DE CULTURA, CONSEJO SUPERIOR DE INVESTIGACIONES
existent by virtue of itself," i.e., God. As Davidson presents
the case, the "metaphysical" proof depends in addition upon CIENTiFICAS, 1983.Pp. 283.
the existence of something (in fact, anything), and thus what Averroes Epitome de Fisica (Filosofia de la Naturaleza).
might appear to be an a priori (ontological) proof is in fact a Translated with commentary by JOSEPPUIG. Corpus Com-
type of cosmological proof for God's existence. mentariorum Averrois in Aristotelem (Versio Hispanica),
In his discussion of Avicenna's proof Davidson focuses A XX. Madrid: INSTITUTO HISPANO-ARABE DE CULTURA,
upon the seemingly logical modalities, necessity and possi- CONSEJO SUPERIOR DE INVESTIGACIONES CIENTiFICAS, 1987.
bility. He denies that Avicenna employs a notion of logical Pp. 270.
analyticity in constructing his proof, and further points out,
correctly in my view, that necessity and possibility are not In 1983 Professor J. Puig published the Arabic text of
used by Avicenna to demarcate a distinction between what Averroes' Epitome of Aristotle's Physics. Though the edition
must (and cannot not) be and what might not (and therefore was impressive and included a clear apparatus criticus, a
at some time was not and will not) be. For Avicenna (as for detailed analytical index as well as a Greek-Arabic index, the
Leibniz), all that (actually) exists must be, even if it might extreme brevity of its introduction (one page) was very

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Tue, 30 Dec 2014 09:46:50 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like