Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 16

Althusser's Marxism without a Knowing Subject

Author(s): Steven B. Smith


Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 79, No. 3 (Sep., 1985), pp. 641-655
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1956835
Accessed: 26/01/2010 07:08

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=apsa.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The American Political Science Review.

http://www.jstor.org
Althusser's Marxism without a Knowing Subject
STEVEN B. SMITH
Yale University

The quest for unassailable "foundations"for knowledge has preoccupied Western thinkers at least
since Descartes. Without some such foundation or Archimedian standpoint, it was argued, our
knowledge of the external world as well as our basis for moral andpoliticaljudgment wouldfallprey
to relativism, historicism, and ultimately nihilism. Recently, though, this Cartesian questforfounda-
tions has come under attack from some of the most powerful minds of our age.
In this article I examine the contribution of Louis Althusser to this current of thought and assess
whether his critique of foundationalist epistemologies and ethics can avoid the pitfalls of relativism.
Althusser is compared to other thinkers who share his anti-Cartesian persuasion (Wittgenstein,
Heidegger, and Foucault) and is criticizedfor his use of a kind of structuralism to abolish the "know-
ing subject" as the locus of thought and action. I conclude thatAlthusser's "antihumanism" has pro-
duced a convenient ideology for a new class of Marxist intellectuals to exert their claims to power over
ordinary human agents who have been reduced to "bearers" or "supports" of certain systemic, struc-
tural relations.

The title of this article is drawn from Karl Pop- The attempt to eliminate the subject from the
per's 1967 lecture "Epistemology Without a product of knowledge may well strike the reader
Knowing Subject." Here we read: as perverse. Ever since Descartes it has been the
aim of modern philosophy to discover some
We maydistinguishthe followingthreeworldsor "foundation" or Archimedian standpoint on
universes:first the world of physicalobjects or which we can ground knowledge (Bernstein, 1983;
physicalstates; secondly, the world of states of Rorty, 1979). Virtually the textbook case of this
consciousness,or of mentalstates,or perhapsof
behavioraldispositionsto act; and thirdly, the approach is to be found in the opening pages of
world of objective contents of thought, espe- Descartes's Meditations, in which he tells of his
ciallyof scientificand poeticthoughtsand works efforts to find a secure foundation for knowledge
of art. (Popper, 1972, p. 106) in the "thinking subject" (ego cogitans) reflecting
upon itself. Indeed, the radical challenge of
It is not my purpose here to examine Popper's Descartes was his claim that not tradition, not
theory of the "three worlds" of knowledge or prejudice, not received opinion, but only the ego's
even to compare Popper's theory of scientific own critical rationality can provide a touchstone
method to that of Althusser, although such a for what is to count as knowledge. Although few
comparison might not be unfruitful. I want in- philosophers today accept the substance of
stead to examine Althusser's own attempt to pro- Descartes's argument, his search for some ab-
duce a theory of the products of the human mind, solute, self-evident, and unimpeachable starting
what Popper calls those "unembodied world- point for knowledge has captured the imagina-
three objects" apart from and independent of the tions of both empiricists and rationalists alike.
"knowing subject."' Without such a foundation, it is argued, our
knowledge of the external world, as well as our
basis for moral judgment and action, would fall
prey to some form of relativism, historicism, or
Received:May 4, 1984 even worse.
Revisionreceived:August21, 1984 And yet, Descartes's emphasis on the primacy
Acceptedfor publication:November1, 1984 of the knowing subject has not gone unchal-
I would like to thank Robert Dahl, Joseph Ham- lenged. In opposition to the Cartesian paradigm
burger, David Johnston, Ian Shapiro, and Rogers with its image of the solitary thinker reflecting
Smith, as well as three anonymous readers for the upon the possibility of knowledge, there has
APSR, for making helpful comments on an earlier ver- grown a powerful anti-Cartesian counter move-
sion of this article.
'The main texts consulted are Althusser For Marx
(1969), Reading Capital (1970), Lenin and Philosophy
and Other Essays (1971), Politics and History: Montes- Self-Criticism (1976). To conserve space, I refer to these
quieu, Rousseau, Hegel, and Marx (1972), and Essays in works by initials; for example, For Marx is cited as FM.

641
642 The American Political Science Review Vol. 79
ment which has sought to "decenter" the privi- and categories of the western liberal tradition,
leged position of the subject. Hegel was perhaps such as freedom, autonomy, dignity, and rights.
the first to challenge this conception of the It may be that what is at stake in this seemingly
autonomous thinker by showing that reason itself abstruse epistemological debate is the very sur-
has an intrinsically social and historical character. vival of the humanistic tradition of political
The knower is not apart from, but embedded in, thought in general and liberal values in particular.
the stream of history that he seeks to com-
prehend. The search for an Archimedian point for The Banishment of the Author
knowledge was pushed even further back owing to
the progressive onslaughts of Marx, Nietzsche, Althusser's first assault on the subject occurs in'
and Freud, all of whom, in very different ways, his theory of reading and interpretation. No
sought to dethrone the autonomy of reason, reading, he has maintained, is "innocent," by
showing it to be determined by certain subrational which he means that no reading can avoid making
or extrarational forces that it failed to com- certain assumptions and presuppositions that pre-
prehend and control. In our own day the works of judice the reader in a certain way (RC, pp. 14-15;
Levi-Strauss, Foucault, and Althusser have fur- cf. pp. 74-78). No interpretation, then, can be en-
ther contributed to the "end" or "death" of man tirely neutral or value-free. Althusser's own
by showing that the subject cannot be analyzed reading is premised on the assumption that behind
apart from the overarching structures or systemic the "explicit discourse" of a text, there is a sec-
relationships in which it finds itself. The Cartesian ond "silent discourse," the meaning of which is
image of the autonomous self reflecting in splen- ''unconscious" to its author and must therefore
did isolation has been declared nothing more than be "dragged up from the depths." It becomes
a myth in which Western thought has been im- necessary then to abandon anything like the
prisoned for over three centuries. author's intention as providing a touchstone for
This leads us back, then, to a consideration of interpretive validity and to focus on that esoteric
the possibility of an epistemology without a or "symptomatic" discourse which must be ex-
knowing subject. For whatever we have heard amined for the "absences," "lacunae," and
lately about the advent of a "post-structuralist," "silences" that the first conceals.2
a "post-Wittgensteinian," or a "post- Althusser launches a powerful attack on the
Heideggerian" age, it is by no means clear that the thesis that the interpretation of a text must at-
Cartesian approach to knowledge is simply dead. tempt to recapture an author's meaning in the
In our century it has reappeared under the guise manner he intended it to be taken. The main
of Husserl's "transcendental phenomenology," presuppositions of this kind of hermeneutic
Sartre's "existential ontology," and more re- recovery are first, that the author is the sole deter-
cently in the various "possessive neo- miner of the text's meaning; second, that this
individualist" theories of politics and society meaning is in principle objective, reproducible,
(Dallmayr, 1981, pp. 12-16). The works of Rawls, and accessible to the interpreter who may be
Nozick, and Dworkin all presuppose some Carte- reading it from a different tradition or point in
sian understanding of the self as unencumbered time; and third, that the meaning of the text is
by any natural or empirically acquired ends or worth recovering. Such an understanding of the
purposes as the only intelligible locus for their interpreter's art has a long history of its own, go-
theories of rights and justice. ing as far back as Spinoza's attempt to recapture
The question, then, is: To what extent can the the literal meaning of Scriptures, but which more
search for an Archimedian standpoint for knowl- recently has been identified with writers as dif-
edge be abandoned and at the same time the pit- ferent as Leo Strauss, Eric Hirsch, and Quentin
falls of relativism, historicism, and ultimately Skinner.3 Whatever the differences between them,
nihilism be avoided? If the Cartesian search for a they all maintain that the primary goal of inter-
certain and reliable foundation for knowledge and pretation is to understand the meaning of a text
morality is indeed a myth, it does not follow that through the recovery of the author's intention and
the rejection of foundationalism tout court will his understanding of his own situation which re-
provide us with anything better. In this article I quires, so far as possible, the elimination of preju-
hope to show that a middle position between dices and assumptions arising from the inter-
foundationalism and Althusser's anti-
Cartesianism may therefore be defensible. Such a
position may help to avoid the difficulties that 2This is not to be confused with the distinction be-
Althusser's radical antifoundationalism raises for tween esoteric and exoteric writing made famous by
political thought and practice. As I shall argue, Strauss (1952, pp. 22-37); see also Strauss (1959, pp.
the attack upon foundations has simultaneously 221-232).
been an attack upon some of the major concepts 3A useful summary is provided by Gunnell (1979).
1985 Althusser's Marxism Without a Knowing Subject 643
preter's own historical horizon. Indeed, in one govern the thinking of a scientific community.7
currently important version of this approach, the The theory of paradigms has been adapted to the
interpretation of a text in the past is likened to the study of -the history of political thought by
understanding of "speech acts" in the present.4 Pocock, who has argued that the "linguistic
The task of the interpreter is to determine "what paradigm" of a writer ought to take precedence
[the] author, in writing at the time he did write for over the author's professed intention, which can
the audience he intended to address, could in almost be, as it were, deduced from this
practice have been intending to communicate" paradigm. Taking exception to Skinner's ap-
(Skinner, 1969, p. 49). It is clear from this remark propriation of Austin's speech act theory, Pocock
that temporal distance or alien modes of thought (1971) writes:
should present no special difficulty to the inter-
preter trying to capture "what the author... Once history is seen in linguistic depth, the
could have been intending to communicate." All paradigmwith which the author operatestakes
that is necessary is a knowledge of the prevailing precedenceover questionsof his "intentions"or
the "illocutionaryforce" of his utterance,for
"linguistic context" which determines the "range only after we have understoodwhat means he
of possibilities" with which an utterance could had of sayinganythingcan we understandwhat
have been conventionally uttered.5 he meant to say, what he succeededin saying,
In contrast to the hermeneutic recovery of what he was taken to have said, or what effects
meaning, however, Althusser proposes a second, his utterancehad in modifyingor transforming
quite different style of reading "with nothing in the existingparadigmstructures.(p. 25)
common with the first" (RC, p. 24). This style of
reading has nothing to do with understanding a Like Pocock, Althusser accords interpretive
writer in the way that he understood himself, but priority to the study of language "structures"
attempts to go beyond the author's own self- over individual utterances or even entire texts.
understanding to the "unconscious" presupposi- The problematic is, according to him, "the par-
tions by which his thought was determined. These ticular unity of a theoretical formation" (FM, p.
unconscious presuppositions Althusser calls the 32). It is the overall framework of a theory which
"problematic" of a work or text. This term is puts the basic concepts into relation with one
taken by him to signify a hierarchical structure of another, determines the nature of each concept by
problems which sets internal limitations on what its place and function within the whole, and con-
an author can and cannot say. Put in this way, the fers on each concept its pecular significance. It
problematic serves as a kind of ideational infra- determines the form or "horizon" within which
structure to the history of ideas in the sense that it problems can be posed as well as solutions enter-
determines what kind of problems may be posed tained.
as well as what kind of solutions to these problems
may be found acceptable. The problematic may This introducesus to a fact peculiarto the very
serve, then, to mark off the conceptual bound- existenceof science:it can only pose problemson
aries that identify the thinking of a writer, a the terrain within the horizon of a definite
theoreticalstructure,its problematic,whichcon-
school, or an entire tradition of thought. In this stitutes its absolute and definite conditions of
respect the problematic resembles, as Jameson has possibility,and hencethe absolutedetermination
noted, nothing so much as Collingwood's theory of the forms in which all problems must be
of "absolute presuppositions" particularly in its posed, at any given momentin the science.(RC,
idealistic character (Jameson, 1972, p. 137).6 p. 25)
The importance of the problematic as an inter-
pretive device has, of course, been widely dis- The problematic, then, delimits the theoretical
cussed in a variety of disciplines ranging from field governing what is and is not to be included
literary criticism to the history and philosophy of within it. It is, as he puts it, a "determinate
science. Readers familiar with this literature will unitary structure" unifying all the elements con-
recognize a family resemblance to Thomas Kuhn's tained therein (FM, p. 67).
theory of paradigms or conceptual models that Althusser develops this concept of the prob-
lematic in the context of his controversy over the
status of the works of the "young Marx" (FM,
4The origins of this theory can be found in Austin
(1962) and Serle (1969); for a recent effort to develop
this theory see Habermas (1979, pp. 1-68; 1984, pp. 7The critical literature on this subject is too
288-295, 305-307, 319-328). voluminous to recount here; for a sample see Lakatos
5For some critical commentaries see Tarcov (1982) and Musgrave (1970); MacIntyre (1977); Bernstein
and Shapiro (1982). (1978, pp. 84-93; 1983, pp. 51-93); see also Miller (1972,
6See also Collingwood (1972, chap. 5). pp. 804-806).
644 The American Political Science Review Vol. 79
pp. 51-86). For some there is a direct continuity author has some privilegedaccess to his text's
between Marx's early "ethical" writings es- meaning, what is being suggested is that the
pecially, the 1844 Manuscripts with their talk of writer'savowalof his own purposeis to some ex-
"alienation" and the reappropriation of the tent unnecessaryonce we havethe text. What, for
"human essence" and the later or mature analysis instance, Kant may have intended to prove by
of the production process in Capital. This con- argumentin the Critiqueof Pure Reason is one
tinuity is said to be guaranteed by the reappear- thing. What he succeededin saying is another,
ance in the later works of Marx of certain key con- which can be distinguishedfrom his purpose in
cepts, notably "alienation," under the guise of writingit. The upshot is that the finishedtext ac-
the "fetishism of commodities." This is taken to quiresan "autonomy"of its own apartfrom the
prove that there is no break or caesura between author's privatethoughtsor mental states. As a
the young and the old Marx as the guarantee of critique of the unduly mentalisticconcepts like
continuity is provided by Marx himself (Avineri, will and intentionality,this is probablycorrect.
1968, p. 40). Yet Althusser claims that this pur- What is more difficult to discern is how this
ported continuity between the young and old banishmentof authorialor communicativeintent
Marx is the result of a "naive" or "eclectic" affectsthe criteriafor determininginterpretiveac-
reading which takes the literal presence of certain curacy.
terms at their face value without pausing to con- In the first place, the suggestionthat a prob-
sider whether or not the problematic that gives lematic or paradigmgoverns the thinking of a
them their meaning had changed. The problem writeror speakerimpliesa sort of linguisticdeter-
with this approach is that it introduces a sort of minism which cannot account for varieties of
cryptoteleology into the study of ideas in its linguisticusages. Although ordinaryor conven-
search for continuities and resemblances, germs tional speech may well be determinedby such
and anticipations, of a later doctrine within an closed and self-contained frames of reference,
earlier one (FM, pp. 56-57). By doing this, a kind these cannot explainhow a writercan and indeed
of false coherence or system is placed upon works often does challenge and go beyond existing
that may in fact be radically different. linguisticboundariesand in the processsay some-
One seemingly peculiar feature of the prob- thing new. This was certainly the case with
lematic upon which Althusser insists is that it Machiavelli,who endowedtraditionalmoralcon-
plays the active role in the determination of a cepts such as liberality,piety, and goodnesswith
theory. Indeed, he attributes functions to the new meaningand implications.To attemptto ex-
problematic that other epistemologies had done to plain Machiavelli'susagessolely withinthe domi-
the human subject. In words that we are enjoined nant problematicof his day would scarcely do
to take "literally," Althusser claims that it is no justice to the novelty and originality of his
longer the individual subject who thinks and con- thought. The same would also be true for the
structs theories, but the problematic that thinks in other great innovatorsin the history of political
and through the subject. thought. Thus Althusser'slinguisticdeterminism
is at fault for viewinglanguagesolely in termsof
The sightingis thus no longer the act of an in- the restraints and limitations that it imposes
dividual subject, endowed with the faculty of ratherthan the creativeand dynamicpropensities
"vision" whichhe exerciseseitherattentivelyor that it affords. Accordingly, when conceptual
distractedly;the sightingis the act of its struc- change is acknowledged,it can only appearas a
tural conditions,it is the relationof immanent
reflectionbetweenthe field of the problematic radicalbreakor rupture(coupure)withthe past in
and its objects and its problems.... It is liter- which one self-enclosed problematicor frame-
ally no longerthe eye (the mind'seye) of a sub- workof meaningtakesthe placeof another.Such
ject whichsees whatexistsin the field definedby change is only possible because it breaksall the
a theoreticalproblematic:it is this field which rulesall at once, whichis preciselywhat I wantto
sees itself in the objectsor problemsit defines arguecannothappen(FM, pp. 32-34;RC, pp. 27,
sightingbeing merelythe necessaryreflexionof 44-45).9
the field on its objects. (RC, p. 25) Second,Althusseris vagueabouthow the prob-
This attempt to dissolve the knower into the
products of his knowledge is not altogether ab-
8An early attempt to exorcise the Cartesian "ghost in
surd. By drawing attention to the problematic as
the machine" can be found in Ryle (1949, pp. 15-24).
the unconscious infrastructure governing the 9Aithusser is indebted for his epistemological theories
"production" of particular utterances, Althusser to Bachelard; for a sample of his writings see Bachelard
wants to show that it is impossible for even the (1934, 1938, 1968); an account of his epistemological
most careful writer to be the sole determiner of history can be found in Lecourt (1969, 1975); see also
the text's meaning. Against the view that an Schmidt (1981, pp. 86-93).
1985 Althusser's Marxism Without a Knowing Subject 645
lematic of a text can be identified and described. engage. Whenever we translate from one language
Rejecting the view that we can have access to a to another, analyze critically the values and beliefs
text through the communicative intent of the of societies different from our own, or even when
author, he seems to regard access not as some- Althusser criticizes other readings of Marx, we are
thing discovered by but as created or produced by implicitly assuming the existence of certain com-
the reader, the result of an ongoing dialectic be- mon criteria of evaluation that transcend any one
tween reader and text. But if the problematic is problematic or form of life. Of course, that we
not something already there in the text, how do characteristically do engage in these activities does
we know if we have in fact found it? Strictly not render them immune from criticism, but
speaking, we could not speak of finding it at all. because we are able to rise above any one frame-
The implication is that there can be no single cor- work or form of life, we are able to depict either
rect reading of Marx or any author. There are or both in terms of a more synoptic or com-
only readings produced by the act of interpreta- prehensive perspective. What I have in mind here
tion. But by denying that the recovery of an is something like Gadamer's conception of a "fu-
author's intention may serve as the foundation for sion of horizons," where we are able to depict
interpretive accuracy, Althusser leaves himself both our own and an alien way of life as alter-
open to the charge of rejecting any claims for native possibilities to certain human constants at
scholarly objectivity or even serious debate among work (Gadamer, 1975, pp. 269-274). One advan-
rival interpretations. Thus, to the question of why tage of this approach is that it protects us against
one should recommend or adopt Althusser's the claims of a presumptuous Cartesianism to
reading of Marx rather than the many others that transcend all problematics and forms of life
have presented themselves over the last century, without collapsing into ethnocentric prejudice or
we could do nothing more than express a sort of mere relativism. Thus, if Althusser is to salvage
resigned methodological agnosticism (Giddens, his own reading of Marx from epistemological
1976, p. 63; Smith, 1984a, pp. 80-81). relativism, it can only be by admitting to a great
To be sure, Althusser would not be happy with deal more overlap among different epistemic stan-
the relativistic implications of his views. After all, dards than his theory of problematics would be
he has read and criticized the works of other inter- willing to concede.
preters-Engels, Plekhanov, Kautsky, Lukacs,
Gramsci, and Sartre, to name just a few. Matters The Problem of Knowledge
of interpretive accuracy cannot, therefore, merely
be a matter of indifference to him. His manner of "To conceive Marx's philosophy in its speci-
reading Marx assumes a position of superiority to ficity ... is to conceive knowledge as produc-
those who have read him before. But in just what tion" (RC, p. 58). In describing knowledge itself
respect his reading is superior he is loath to say. as a kind of production or practice, namely,
Presumably to attempt to identify fixed criteria "theoretical practice," Althusser has two aims in
would be to fall back on the kind of"foundation- mind: one positive, the other critical. The positive
alism" he has everywhere sought to reject. The goal is to highlight the "autonomous" character
most he is willing to concede is that our criteria of of theory. As opposed to other Marxist theoreti-
interpretive accuracy are internally bound up with cians who would explain all the basic forms of life
the problematics that we are called upon to com- activity as derivative from the economic sphere,
pare and evaluate. But far from answering this Althusser proposes to consider the independence
difficulty, this solution evades it. For if our of theory (Deprun, 1970, pp. 67-82). "We must
criteria of validation already presuppose what it is recognize," he says, "that there is no practice in
that is to be evaluated, there is no way of deter- general, but only distinctive practices" for "there
mining whether one problematic, paradigm, or can be no scientific conception of practice without
language game is to be adjudged in any way a precise distinction between the distinct prac-
superior to or more adequate than any other. The tices" (RC, p. 58). The autonomy of theory apart
result would be a circularity in which the prob- from the other practices that compose the "social
lematics in question would be called upon to formation" is guaranteed by its own "internalist"
validate themselves. or "immanent" form of justification. For
In fact, as I shall show in the next section, this is Althusser, knowledge is not verified either em-
precisely what Althusser intends in his rejection of pirically by reference to "facts" or "brute data"
the classical "problem of knowledge," the search or pragmatically as an expression of social needs
for permanent foundations or guarantees for or "interests" (as many Marxists might argue).
knowledge or truth. First, however, I must point Rather it is said to contain its own canons and
out that the model of interpretation just enu- protocols of validation that are internal to knowl-
merated prohibits us from engaging in a number edge alone (RC, p. 141).
of activities in which we characteristically do The claim that knowledge is "production" is
646 The American Political Science Review Vol. 79
also used as a polemicalweaponagainstany form material nor the product, but the practice in the
of epistemological"foundationalism."By foun- narrow sense; the moment of the labour of trans-
dationalismI mean here the search for transhis- formation itself, which sets to work, in a specific
structure, men, means, and a technical method
toricalor transtheoreticalmeasures,standards,or of utilizing the means. (FM, pp. 166-67)
guarantees against which knowledge may be
verified.For Althusser,the searchfor guarantees There are four distinct kinds of practice:
is a part of the traditional"problem of knowl-
economic, political, ideological, and theoretical
edge" whichhe rejects(RC, pp. 52-54).The prob- (FM, pp. 167, 229). It is the "combination" or
lem with these previous epistemologies is the
"articulation" of these practices that constitutes
belief that absoluteor a priorifoundationscould the overall "social formation" or "mode of pro-
be discoveredupon which knowledgeor science
duction." Yet while each of these practices is
could be grounded.An exampleof this founda- distinct, they still share a common or
tionalism would be the claims embodied in "homologous" form: a raw material, "the labour
classical empiricism.For the empiricist, every- of transformation itself," and a finished product.
thing that is to count as knowledge must be In the case of theoretical practice, the raw mate-
capableof verificationthroughperceptualexperi- rials present themselves as a series of discrete men-
ence. This requirementis concretized in the tal events or ordinary, commonplace concepts.
famous "verification principle," according to The point to be noted here is that evidence never
which if our statementsabout the externalworld presents itself as a world of "fact" or "brute
are to be meaningful, they must be testable data" open to direct inspection, but rather as an
againstrealityor some portionof it. Only knowl- already existing universe of concepts or linguistic
edge based on experiencecan lay claim to objec- entities. It is not something immediately "given,"
tivity. The problemhere is simplythat the princi- but is a world already mediated by interpretation
ple of verifiabilitycannot itself be verified on and judgment of an "ideological" sort. The raw
perceptualor testablegrounds. It thereforecon- materials of theoretical practice are, then, a type
tradicts its own premises for determiningwhat of thinking, but thinking at a very low level of in-
knowledge is, and this contradiction,Althusser tellection, what another tradition would call
holds, underlies all such attempts to ground "prethetic" reflection or the standpointof the
knowledge.The same difficulty underliesthe ra- "natural"attitude.
tionalist's search for such principles as self- Characteristically, Althusserdisplayslittle con-
evidenceand logical inviolabilityas the basis for cern with the diverseoriginsand naturesof these
certainty.Becausethese principlesmust claim to
precede the knowledgethey are called upon to commonplaceconcepts that form the basis for
validate,they must eitherseek otherjustificatory knowledge.Althoughthey may precedethe com-
ing into being of science,they are an inert, pliant
principles by which to validate themselves or kind of stuff fashioned out of the exigenciesof
stand condemnedof self-contradiction.'0 "lived experience."They are, for this reason, all
Instead of attempting to determine a priori
rules of evidencefor what is to count as knowl- but useless for scientificpurposes,since science,
as we have seen, comes into being only througha
edge or how knowledgeis to be verified,Althusser "rupture"with this experience.Accordingly,the
proposes a quite different procedure,where the
decisive "moment" of any science consists in
knowledgeor sciencein questionis calledupon to
validateitself. The first step in this procedureis "elaboratingits own scientific facts through a
the argument that knowledge is not so much critiqueof the ideological'facts' elaboratedby an
earlierideological practice." To elaboratethese
discovered as created. It is a form of
"facts" is, moreover, "to elaborate its own
"production" or "practice." He proposes a
'theory' since a scientificfact-and not the self-
tolerablyspecific definitionof what is meant by styled pure phenomenon-can only be identified
practice. in the field of theoreticalpractice"(FM, p. 184).
BypracticeingeneralI shallmeananyprocessof Whereasa theoreticalpracticemay begin with an
transformation of a determinategiven raw existing system of representations,its aim is to
materialinto a determinate product,a trans- produce a "corpus of concepts" that both "re-
formationeffectedby a determinatehuman jects the old one even as it englobes it, that is,
labour,usingdeterminate means(of "produc- defines its 'relativity'and the (subordinate)limits
tion").Inanypracticethusconceived,
thedeter- of its validity" (FM, p. 185). The point is that
minantmoment(or element)is neitherthe raw -theoryrecognizesno "facts" that do not already
presupposea prior theory. Even in science we
10Thiscritique is brilliantly developed by Hegel (1971, move within a circle of interpretationthat can
pp. 131-145); for an excellent commentary see Norman never be broughtto an end because it is always
(1976, pp. 9-28). subjectto furtherinterpretation.
1985 Althusser's Marxism Without a Knowing Subject 647
The direction, then, of Althusser's "knowledge serious difficulties of its own, namely, an un-
= production" thesis is away from any search for critical relativism concerning the content of
epistemological foundations or transcendental knowledge.Since Althusser'sinternalcriteriaare
guarantees for knowledge and toward some form strictly relative to existing ideological or
of internal or immanent criteria of validation. By theoretical practices, they can tell us nothing
an internal or immanent (as opposed to a founda- about the truth of these practices.
tionalist) theory of knowledge I mean one that In the first place, it could be argued that
seeks validity claims within the knowledge to be although the logicomathematicalproceduresof
verified. In contrast to the claims of a Kantian proof referredto in the above passage may be
"first philosophy," which seeks to establish once valid for certain restrictedareas of scientificin-
and for all the conditions of possible knowledge, quiry, they cannot hold true for the social
Althusser maintains that standards of cognitive sciences,whichare bound by the demandsof fact
acceptability are already at hand within existing or evidence. If there is no body of hard factual
sciences or "theoretical practices." There is no evidencethat is takento be objectiveand indepen-
point, he believes, in trying to establish ideal rules dent of the inquirerinto it, then we have no com-
to see whether our knowledge measures up or pelling basis on which to distinguishtruth from
"corresponds" to an independently existing exter- falsity. The result of Althusser'srejectionof the
nal world, but rather to see whether the knowl- "problemof knowledge"is to rendertheoryim-
edge in question lives up to its own self-imposed mune to empiricalfalsification(Callinicos,1976,
standards of adequacy. This, he hopes, will put to pp. 59-60; Thompson, 1978, pp. 10-13, 16-25,
rest once and for all the traditional problem of 33-35, 3940). Althusseradmitsas much when he
knowledge. says that it is necessaryto "purifyour conceptof
the theory of history. . . of any contamination
Theoreticalpractice is indeed its own criterion by the obviousnessof empiricalhistory"(RC, p.
and contains in itself definite protocols with 105).But the questionremains,if everytheoryhas
which to validatethe qualityof its product... its own immanentcriteriaof validity, how is it
No mathematicianin the world waits until possible to compare and evaluate different
physics has verified a theorem to declare it
proved,althoughwholeareasof mathematicsare theories?On this accountit would seem to be im-
appliedin physics:the truth of his theoremis a possible to choose rationally between, say, a
hundredper cent providedby criteriapurelyin- scientificand a theologicalaccount of the origin
ternal to the practice of mathematicalproof, and development of the species or between a
hence by the criterionof mathematicalpractice, Marxistand a liberalconceptionof the state, since
i.e., by the forms requiredby existing mathe- both could be heldto containtheirown immanent
maticalscientificity.(RC, p. 59) logic and standardsof intelligibility.The point is
that unless our conceptions are at some level
By insisting that theory supplies its own internal based on fact, our whole constructioncould be
criteria of acceptability, Althusser is enabled to rigorouslycoherentand still be a delusion.
avoid the pitfalls of the traditional theory of To some extent Althusser's relativismstems
knowledge. More positively, by adopting the from the philosophical source from which his
standpoint of an internalist theory, he not only epistemologyis culled.The doctrinethat "truthis
provides an alternative to foundationalist epis- its own criterion"is taken directlyfrom Spinoza,
temologies with their search for transcendental whom Althusser regards as "the only direct
truths or guarantees but is in accord with much of ancestor of Marx" (RC, p. 102; cf. ESC, pp.
the recent work done in this area. In the later 13241).12 In theEthicsSpinozahad usedthis doc-
works of Wittgenstein, for instance, it is argued trineto indicatethe systematiccharacterof truth,
that epistemic standards must be sought not in that truth lies in the whole (Spinoza, 1952, p.
some sort of "metalanguage" or "first philos- 115).'3 To describea statementor propositionas
ophy" but within established ways of true for Spinoza is not to say that it adequately
proceeding.' The use of language itself provides picturesor representsthe world. Rathertruthlies
us with criteria of reflective acceptability, so that in the relationbetween one statementand some
it is only necessary to check our judgments against logically"concatenated"set of statementsthat it
existing linguistic standards to discover whether presupposes.Spinozacould, however,adopt this
or not we are justified in making them. Neverthe-
less, the procedure of immanent validation raises
'2For the relation between Althusser and Spinoza see
Eco (1968, p. 360); Deprun (1970, pp. 77-79); Anderson
"Wittgenstein's turn from ontological realism toward (1976, pp. 64-66).
conventionalism has been noted by Rosen (1969, pp. '3Spinoza's theory of truth is treated in Hampshire
1-27). (1962, pp. 86-90, 97-107),
648 The American Political Science Review Vol. 79
rigorously coherentist theory of truth and still to count as true or false, "logical or illogical"
avoid epistemic relativism because he also enlisted withinthe discipliesor modes of life in question.
the support of a monistic metaphysics to But they cannot tell us how these disciplinesor
guarantee that the order and connection of things modes of life can be comparedor evaluated,or
always remains parallel with the order and con- whetheror not theymakesense.Thereis a kindof
nection of ideas. "Ordo et connexio idearum latent positivismwithin this approachaccording
rerum idem est, ac ordo connexio rerum" to which various theories and language games
(Spinoza, 1951, p. 86). Lacking any such merelyare and, as such, must be accepted.There
"psycho-physical parallelism,"'4 Althusser can is a paradoxicalagreementbetweenAlthusserand
offer no such promise that the real object (objet Wittgenstein'sdictum that "What has to be ac-
rMel)will in any way coincide with its conceptual cepted, the given, is-so one could say-forms of
representation (objet de pensde) (RC, pp. 35-42, life" (Wittgenstein,1968, p. 226). The result of
62-63, 66-67). what Gellner(1974, p. 20) has called this "skep-
Althusser's response here is to dismiss the tical abstinencefrom transcendentclaims" is to
whole problem of knowledge, that is, the verifica- re-endorseuncriticallythose patternsof life and
tion and empirical validation of truth claims as interactionthat merelyhappento exist. And this
"ideological." In his own words: "We can say, is preciselywhat we need not, and ought not, to
then, that the mechanism of production of the accept.
knowledge effect lies in the mechanism which But this seemingacceptanceof the inviolability
underlies the action of the forms of order in the of our theoretical practices glosses over the
scientific discourse of the proof" (RC, p. 67). But discrepanciesthat can arisenot only betweenbut
this offhand dismissal of the problem of founda- within forms of life, languagegames, and prob-
tions by no means succeeds in resolving our dif- lematics. The criteriaof reflective acceptability
ficulties. Without some rules of procedure in- operativeat any one timearenot monolithic;they
dependent of the practice in question, not only may not only contain internalincoherencesand
will we be unable to decide between competing ac- contradictionsbut may be challengedby rival
counts but we will be thrown back into the morass practitionersof the same field. Thus Alasdair
of epistemic relativism discussed in the last sec- MacIntyrehas said in responseto Winchthat "at
tion. any given date in any given societythe criteriain
This raises a further problem. Not only does current use by religious believersand scientists
Althusser's rejection of foundationalism will differ from what they are at other times and
eliminate the constraints of evidence, it tells us places. Criteriahavea history"(Maclntyre,1979,
nothing of how criteria themselves change over pp. 66-67; emphasis added). But if the criteria
time. Curiously, Althusser's argument that every change, they may not be consideredall of one
problematic contains its own internal norms of in- piece, and to refer to them as though they were
telligibility is not unlike the position argued by misses a crucial dimension of epistemological
Winch (1958). In discussing the differences be- change.The moreimportantpoint is why at some
tween the claims of theology and those of science, points in the history of thought existingcriteria
Winch suggests that "intelligibility takes many for validatingknowledgeclaims are regardedas
and varied forms" and that there is no "norm for satisfactory, whereas at other times anomalies
intelligibility as such." "For instance," he writes, and incoherencesbecome so great as to sanction
''science is one such mode and religion is another; as "epistemologicalbreak."
and each has criteria of intelligibility peculiar to Finally, Althusser'sinsistenceon the "radical
itself. So within science or religion actions can be inwardness"of our criterialeadsto a severanceof
logical or illogical.... But we cannot sensibly theory from practice. He begs the question by
say that either the practice of science itself or that referringto theoryitself as a kind of practice,but
of religion is either illogical or logical; both are such a conceptionis totally at odds with Marx's
non-logical" (Winch, 1958, pp. 100-101). more pragmatic theory of truth (Kolakowski,
In other words, just as Althusser maintains that 1968,pp. 38-66).The basicpoint of departurefor
no mathematician requires the aid of physics to all of Marx's epistemologicalreflections is the
verify mathematical theorems, so Winch is sug- conviction that the relation between the species
gestings that both science and theology have their and its environmentis fundamentallyone of need.
own internal criteria of intelligibility peculiar to As Marxindicatesin a numberof places, reality
themselves and as such must be judged simply on itself is a human creation, and theory, man's
their own terms. These criteria can tell us what is "practicalconsciousness,"our awarenessof the
worldof things,is definedby its abilityto assistus
in appropriatingthe worldas the sum total of the
'4The emphasized term comes from Collingwood possible objects of need. Thus, in the German
(1942, p. 8). Ideology we find statementslike "consciousness
1985 Althusser's Marxism Without a Knowing Subject 649

is. . . from the very beginning a social product knowledge which is peculiar to theoretical practice
and remains so as long as men exist at all," and constitutes a process that takes place entirely in
more specifically that "language is as old as con- thought" (RC, p. 42). The idea that there are
sciousness, language is practical consciousness neither transcendent standards, as the Platonist
that . . . only arises from the need, the necessity, believes, nor "brute data," as the positivist
of intercourse with other men" (Marx, 1970a, pp. argues, against which our knowledge can be
49-50). judged adequate testifies to a condition that Rorty
The implication here is that all thinking is in- (1982, p. xxxix) has described as "decadence" or
herently practical or problemsolving in nature. what I prefer to call left-wing Kantianism.
Not truth but success in practice, success in enabl- Althusser's position is "Kantian" because it
ing us to acquire the objects of need, is the claims that the mind has no direct access to reality
primary category of evaluation. As Marx in- independent of or apart from the linguistic prac-
dicates in his second Thesis on Feuerbach: "The tices that we use to describe, explain, and evaluate
question whether objective truth can be attributed it. It is "left" because it maintains that even our
to human thinking is not a question of theory but most deeply held convictions and beliefs have no
is a practical question.... The dispute over the permanent fixity or foundation but are the pro-
reality or non-reality of thinking which is isolated ducts of a critique of earlier theoretical and
from practice is a purely scholastic question" ideological practices which are themselves liable
(Marx, 1970a, p. 615). The conception, then, of a to epistemological upheaval in the future. As we
"theoretical practice" unconnected to the shall now see, Althusser's own theoretical practice
satisfaction of practical needs would have struck is premised on a critique of the humanistic con-
Marx as a typically idealist fantasy." ception of the self as a knowing and acting sub-
There may be good intellectual reasons for re- ject. This essentially Cartesian understanding of
jecting Marx's pragmatist or instrumentalist con- the subject as possessed of such attributes of
ception of knowledge. After all, not all thinking freedom, dignity, and rights is not only said to be
(e.g., the playful examination of ideas in a based on a philosophically false anthropology but
Platonic dialogue) is ruled directly by practical one that may now be nearing its end.
necessity. Yet by cutting theory off from any
foundation in either nature or social practice, The Death of the Subject
Althusser's solution to the "problem of knowl-
edge" remains subject to the same strictures Marx Althusser's attack upon the Cartesian search
levelled against Hegel and the German idealists of for foundations of knowledge and action in the
the 1840s. The idealism of Althusser consists not thinking ego has its final end or purpose in the re-
in the denial of an independently existing external jection of any philosophical anthropology based
world, but in the positing of a self-generating con- upon the conception of "man." In his own
ceptual universe with no ties to social practice and words, Marxism must become a "theoretical anti-
claiming its own immanent criteria of validity. humanism" (FM, pp. 229-231, 241). By anti-
There is, in the final instance, no interplay or humanism Althusser means that the self, the
dialectic between "social being" and "social con- human subject, does not so much constitute but is
sciousness," but, as with all systems of idealism, constituted by the structural, systemic relations in
the latter is given an "autonomy" of its own apart which it finds itself. It is the belief not that men
from the sordid world of politics and history. make history but that history makes men or that
Althusser's answer, then, to the traditional history makes itself that defines this movement
"problem of knowledge" is the idea of an imma- (ESC, pp. 35-57). As I shall show later, this anti-
nent critique. An immanent critique is one that re- humanism forms the Althusserian pendant to the
jects the search for natural or apodictic starting structuralist dictum that "man is dead"
points for knowledge and the picture or corres- (Dallmayr, 1981, pp. 21-29; Smith, 1984a, pp.
pondence theory of truth that accompanies it. 192-200).
Knowledge, one could say, both begins and ends This theoretical antihumanism has as its pur-
within the sealed chamber of "theoretical prac- pose the decentering of the subject. Indeed, this
tice." "It is perfectly legitimate to say," act of decentering has been crucial to every
Althusser remarks, "that the production of modern discipline claiming scientific status. As
Freud has indicated, the "naive self-love" of man
has become progressively decentered by the ad-
vances of modern science (Freud, 1969, pp.
"5Althusser has made some efforts to correct this
284-285). The first blow fell when Copernicus
"theoreticism" (i.e., idealism); see FM, p. 15; ESC, pp.
119-125; for evaluations of these "self-criticisms" see discovered that the earth was not the center of the
Callinicos (1976, pp. 107-114) and McCarney (1980, pp. universe but a tiny speck within a cosmic space of
70-79). infinite vastness. The second blow came when
650 The American Political Science Review Vol. 79

Darwin dislodged the species from its supposedly any such metaphysics of the subject, it is
privileged position within creation, showing it to necessary to decenter or dissolve man by returning
be just one in a long line of evolutionary forms. to a more primordial sense of Being. Only when
The third blow fell when Freud himself showed the human is understood as rooted in rather than
that the ego, once regarded as the sovereign sub- standing over Being can the arrogance of
ject, is not even "master in its own house" but is humanism be held in check.
directed by deeper unconscious drives and pur- Following Heidegger, Althusser has repudiated
poses. And finally, this process of decentering has humanism not as a "metaphysics" but as an
culminated in our own day when Althusser, "ideology." Ideology is to be understood here in
Foucault, and Levi-Strauss have tried to eliminate contrast to science. Ideology, Althusser writes, is
the influence of man altogether as a subject of distinguished from science in that in ideology,
historical and ethnographic research.'6 "the practico-social function" dominates the
Althusser's own attempt to decenter the subject theoretical function (FM, p. 231). Elsewhere he
has taken the form of an attack on humanism and comments that ideology is governed by certain
Enlightenment philosophies of "man." The "interests" beyond the requirements of knowl-
distinctive feature of traditional humanism, that edge alone (RC, p. 141). Ideologies perform the
of Feuerbach for instance, has been the desire to further task of "interpellating" individuals as
recover or reappropriate for man those attributes "subjects." The category of the subject, like that
that traditional philosophies had ascribed to God of ego or consciousness, is said to be "constitutive
or some metaphysical Absolute (ESC, pp. of all ideology" or "all ideology has the function
195-207). The most important of these attributes (which defines it) of 'constituting' concrete in-
is the capacity for free choice or creative causality. dividuals as subjects" (LP, p. 160). It follows,
Indeed the belief that we are free agents capable therefore, that ideologies are ensembles of false
of initiating and therefore responsible for our own beliefs not, as Marx believed, because they inter-
actions stems originally from Christianity and the pret the world from the standpoint of any one
"myth" that God addresses man "by name" (LP, particular class within society, but because they
p. 166). Humanism is, then, merely an inverted are tied to the claims of a "constitutive subject"
theology. It merely substitutes a generic mankind or of individuals as self-directing agents. The con-
or human subject as the omnipotent knower and ception, then, of "a subject endowed with a con-
maker of the world. To be sure, this dependence sciousness" must be rejected as an "absolutely
of humanism on theology may be a negative one, ideological 'conceptual' device" (LP, p. 157). It
but it is a dependence all the same. follows further that Marxism qua science must be
The Althusserian critique of humanism itself subjectless, that is, a "process without a subject,"
follows a line of thought first developed by a process without end or purpose, unilluminated
Heidegger in the Letter on Humanism (1977, pp. by any rational necessity or transcendent Absolute
193-242). There he argued that the "atheist" exis- (PH, pp. 181-183; ESC, pp. 94-99). Once history,
tentialism of Sartre was nothing more than an conceived as a rational or meaningful whole, can
outgrowth of the Western "metaphysical" tradi- be shown to be unintelligible or opaque in its
tion. This metaphysical tradition, stretching from essence, it becomes possible to reduce "the philo-
Plato to Marx, has consisted of a series of increas- sophical (theoretical) myth of man . to ashes"
ingly disastrous attempts to impose our own con- (FM, p. 229).
scious designs and efforts on nature. Metaphysics Althusser's own form of antihumanism begins
conceals a fundamentally technical interest in with the denial that man or even groups of men
gaining mastery and control over both the natural form the primary unit of Marx's analysis. Marx,
and the social worlds. Such anthropocentric Althusser tells us, was not interested in man as
humanism has led to the subjugation and ex- such but in certain "ever-pregiven" relations of
ploitation of all beings, including man, by an ag- production which distribute the roles and func-
gressively self-centered humanity. Humanism is tions that agents play out in their daily lives. Re-
thus a form of anthropocentric hubris: the jecting Marx's early philosophical anthropology
deification of man instead of God. To eliminate as tainted with the "ideology" of man and its
belief in a substantive human nature ("species be-
ing"), Althusser cites approvingly from Marx's
last work, his Marginal Notes on Adolph
'6See Nair (1974, p. 169): "With Sartre there is too Wagner's "Handbook of Political Economy" to
much history, with Levi-Strauss, Foucault, Althusser, show that by the end of his life Marx had left the
and Lacan there is no longer any history; yesterday ob- last vestiges of his earlier humanism far behind.'7
ject and structure were dissolved into the subject; today
subject and consciousness are buried in the object. The
soul of the world was free and conscious choice, now '7Poster (1975, pp. 67-71); Schaff (1978, pp.
the unconscious is king and the world has lost its soul." 128-139); Kolakowski (1978, p. 486).
1985 Althusser's Marxism Without a Knowing Subject 651

"My analytical method," Marx says there, "does the "mode of production" within which they find
not start from man but from the economically themselves. There is no action in the Althusserian
given social period'" (Cited in FM, p. 219). Not universe where this is understood as purposive
our lived experience but the various structures of behavior directed toward the pursuit of some
social life-economic political, ideological-con- freely chosen end or purpose. There is only a set
stitute the real "subjects" of history. of reactive responses determined "in the last in-
WIthin Marx's own writings, Althusser finds stance" by the needs of the production process.
warrant for this antihumanism in Marx's use of The stage, Althusser says, is set and the players
the term Trager, which is a fairly commonplace merely perform according to scripts already writ-
German word that means literally "bearer" or ten out for them in advance.
"support." Althusser does not, therefore, merely
import this term from the outside to give his Now we can recallthat highlysymptomaticterm
"Darstellung, " compare it with this
Marxism a structuralist turn. Rather it is a con-
"machinery"and take it literally,as the veryex-
cept that Marx uses regularly throughout Capital istenceof this machineryin its effects: the mode
to show the way in which economic agents are of the stage direction misee en scene) of the
turned by capitalism into "personifications" of theatrewhichis simultaneouslyits own stage, its
the social relations of production. Thus at one own script, its own actors, the theatre whose
point we read that, "In the course of our in- spectatorscan on occasion, be spectatorsonly
vestigations we shall find, in general, that the becausethey are first of all forced to be its ac-
characters who appear on the economic stage are tors, caught by the constraintsof a script and
but the personifications [Trager] of the economic partswhoseauthorsthey cannotbe, since it is in
relations that exist between them" (Marx, 1970b, essencean authorlesstheatre.(RC, p. 193)
p. 85). The difference is that whereas Marx uses
this concept as a means to indict capitalist society These passages provide literally textbook ex-
for treating men as things, Althusser uses it to amples of what Dennis Wrong (in another con-
show that the very idea of man is a chimera that text) has called the "oversocialized conception of
we would be better to drop altogether. man" (Wrong, 1961, pp. 183-193; cf. Zetter-
Althusser uses Marx's Trager concept to show baum, 1971, pp. 240-246). On this account what
that economic agents are never anything more we are is so completely determined by the "places
than "bearers" or "functionaries" within a given and functions" that we occupy that there is
mode of production. There are only a limited nothing else left over. There is no Archimedian
number of places and functions that these agents point of exemption of the kind searched for by
can occupy which are continually reproduced and Descartes, no transcendental subject of the Kan-
continually develop what they demand of their oc- tian or Husserlian variety capable of standing out-
cupants. Men cannot, therefore, be regarded as side experience, for the fact is that we are condi-
active creators or makers of this process. They are tioned beings all the way down. By rejecting the
never anything more than its "supports." idea that there is a permanent nature or essence of
man which is, to be sure, shaped and molded by
The structure of the relations of production
determinesthe places and functions occupied culture but which may also stand in a position of
and adopted by the agents of production,who conflict or tension with that culture, Althusser has
are never anythingmore than the occupantsof provided a structuralist conception of the self as a
these places, insofar as they are the "supports" personification or passive functionary of the em-
[Trager]of these functions.The true "subjects" pirically determined circumstances in which it
(in the sense of constitutivesubjectsof the pro- finds itself. The oversocialized conception of the
cess) are thereforenot these occupantsor func- self aims to provide an answer to the age-old ques-
tionaries, are not, despite all appearance,the tion, "How is society possible?" or "What are
"obviousness"of the "given" of naive anthro- the sources of social order?" by claiming to
pology, "concrete individuals," "real men"-
but thedefinitionand distributionof theseplaces demonstrate that we are exclusively the products
and functions. The true "subjects" are these of the social roles we inhabit.
definersand distributors:the relations of pro- The idea, of course, that human beings are
duction(andpoliticaland ideologicalsocial rela- molded by circumstance or that we become what
tions). (RC, p. 180) we are in and through interaction with others has
long ceased to be controversial. One may be a
Elsewhere Althusser goes so far as to suggest feudal lord, a serf, a property-owning bourgeois,
that the production and reproduction of social life or a university professor, and to an extent one's
is not something carried out by intelligent agents behavior is determined by the norms and expecta-
with awareness of what it is they are doing, but tions governing those roles. But to say that
takes place, so to speak, behind the backs of men everything we do (or refrain from doing) can be
who are never anything more than the supports of explained by the "places and functions" we oc-
652 The American Political Science Review Vol. 79

cupy is by no means obvious. Althusser is so con- porary social and political theory whose outcome
cerned to deny the humanist thesis that men make has been declared under the slogan "the death of
their own history and in doing so make themselves man." Along with Althusser, the most prominent
that he overlooks the fact that the production and member of this school has been Michel Foucault,
reproduction of social life are above all skilled who has written that Nietzsche's declaration of
performances sustained and made to happen by the death of God has been followed one hundred
intelligent social agents who act in the light of years later by the end of his murderer. In fact the
their understood situations. Seen in this way, in- conception of man as an agent or center of in-
dividuals are never merely representatives of a set itiative endowed with the capacity for free, pur-
of prescribed social roles, nor can human actions posive, and responsible action is only as old as
be explained solely in causal or functional terms, Rousseau and Kant. "Before the end of the eigh-
that is, in terms of how they keep the system go- teenth century," Foucault writes, "man did not
ing. Social actors must be understood at least in exist . . . he is a recent creature which the
part as intentional subjects acting in response to demiurge of knowledge fabricated with its own
an understood situation and whose actions must hands less than two hundred years ago"
also be seen in terms of their symbolic or mean- (Foucault, 1970, p. 308). But just as this
ingful character for the agents themselves. It is the "creature" has come into being, so too in our
meaningful side of human action that Althus- own day do we see it beginning to pass away. "As
serian structuralism fails to grasp (Giddens, 1976, the archaeology of our thought easily shows, man
pp. 44-48, 74-77; Winch, 1958, pp. 43-53, is an invention of recent date. And one perhaps
116-120). nearing its end" (Foucault, 1970, p. 387).
It should now be clear that the aim of this This proclamation of the end or death of man
"oversocialized" conception of the self is to jet- should not be taken simply as a prophecy of
tison whatever permanent core or substance was doom. The dissolution of the subject does not
once thought to belong to a human being and to mean that human beings as a species are bound to
substitute in its place the conception of the self as disappear. What will disappear is not man as such
a bearer or functionary, a "role player" as we but one historically specific conception of man as
might say.'8 When, for instance, premodern a thinking and active subject who is simultane-
thinkers regarded the self, they thought largely in ously both knower and maker of the world. What
terms of character or even soul. The soul in turn will also disappear is the attempt to ground the
was thought to have a distinct nature defined by a human in terms of purportedly permanent at-
hierarchy of needs dictated by the concerns for tributes like freedom, autonomy, dignity, or
human excellence and nobility. When even rights. These categories and concepts belong to
modern thinkers like Kant spoke of the essential only one epoch in the "archaeology of
freedom or "dignity" of man, he meant not each knowledge," which is now nearing its end. Thus it
individual but the totality of the species as is the search for some more basic and permanent
"represented" by or embodied in the individual foundation to the self that is destined to disap-
subject. In contrast, then, to this search for any pear, "like a face drawn in the sand at the edge of
defining center or core to which the universal con- the sea" (Foucault, 1970, p. 385).'9
cept of man might refer, Althusser prefers to This dissolution of the self with which I have
dissolve the self into the social relationships which been concerned here results from a critique of En-
uniquely determine it. Indeed, he is fond of lightenment humanism that Althusser shares with
quoting from Marx's sixth Thesis on Feuerbach as some of the most powerful thinkers of our age. By
an anticipation of this decentered self. "The contrast to the conception, extending as far back
human essence," Marx says there, "is not an as Protagoras, that "man is the measure of all
abstraction inherent in each individual . . . it is things," the Althusserian critique of humanism
the ensemble of social relations" (Cited in FM, stresses the insurmountable limitations imposed
pp. 227-228, 242-243). upon man by those non-human or extrahuman re-
This dissolution of the self into its nexus of lations of production, the "places and functions"
social relations is no mere eccentricity on the part that we occupy. Man is no longer conceived as the
of Althusser. His denial of any finality or fixity is, active creator of the world, but as a supporting
as I have already indicated, part of a broader agent in a complex web of relationships whose
counter movement now underway in contem- axis revolves around the relations of production.

'8This is developed by Goffman (1959); for an ex- '9A more developed account than I am able to give
cellent critique of this kind of sociologism see Wrong here can be found in Garaudy (1969, pp. 229, 238,
(1961, pp. 183-193); see also Smith, (1984bi.especially 241-250); Poster (1975, pp. 334-339); Dreyfus and
pp. 528-535). Rabinow (1982, pp. 28-43).
1985 Althusser's Marxism Without a Knowing Subject 653

Like Spinoza's Substance or Heidegger's Dasein, Indeed, Althusser's seemingly benign insistence
these "structures" denote the preexisting world on the "autonomy" of theory is but one more
that is the product of neither individual or collec- sophisticated way of justifying the dominance of
tive design and of which human agents are ulti- the Marxist intelligentsia claiming to speak for or
mately attributes. The result of this critique has in the true interests of the proletariat. The result
been an astonishing reversal of the teaching of has been the creation of an inward-looking, self-
Descartes. Rather than "the masters and posses- sufficient theoretical culture with no generic ties
sors of nature," we have become its servants. to the working classes, a development, needless to
say, that Marx scarcely intended or expected to
happen (Berki, 1975, p. 72). This goes some way
Conclusion toward explaining, I think, why this kind of
Marxism has met with widespread acceptance in
The Althusserian critique of humanism and its the universities and among the intellectuals while
search for substantive foundations for both being ignored by ordinary people.
knowledge and action is directed against some of There is, of course, a final irony in this situa-
the most deeply held convictions of the western tion. If Marx was correct when he argued that the
liberal tradition. The most cherished of these con- ideas of thinker must in some sense express the
victions is man, the human subject, whose moral values or interests of his class or social position,
worth resides in a capacity for reasoned judgment then this must be ipso facto true for Althusser and
and the ability to conform conduct to the dictates his contemporaries. Althusser, I would suggest, is
of this judgment. The capacity for judgment, and part of a new technocratic intelligentsia which is
of free agency that this implies, is the distinctive now in the process of formation. That such a
mark of the human. What distinguishes liberalism "new class" of Marxist intellectuals is now seek-
not only from classical political philosophy but ing to provide itself with some legitimacy is a
from the variety of modern antiliberalisms is its phenomenon attested to by writers on both sides
uncompromising insistence on the power of of what it is no longer fashionable to call the Iron
autonomous human reason as the basis of our Curtain (Djilas, 1957; Kristol, 1976; Parkin,
claim to be treated with equal "concern and 1979). It is a distinct possibility that a theory that
respect." regards men as attributes of agentless structures
The attempt to displace this predominantly may well express a reality dominated by imper-
liberal conception of man as an active and'know- sonal bureaucratic, if not to say technocratic,
ing subject, the bearer of rights and obligations, is methods of control. Such methods may well
at bottom what Althusser understands by "Lenin- reduce human agents to Trdger, mere func-
ism" (RC, p. 141). Leninism, the justification of tionaries rewarded by their ability to adapt or re-
rule by an elite or a central committee, is only spond to the exigencies of the system of produc-
possible when human beings are denied the tion. It is an arresting thought that Althusser's
capacity to act, the ability to make or create their Marxism without a knowing subject is the best ex-
history, and are instead regarded as an inert or pression to date of the soul of modern bureau-
recalcitrant mass, there to be molded and manipu- cratic rule, what one critic has called "the rule of
lated by a class of master technicians or engineers. nobody" (Arendt, 1969, p. 81).

References

Althusser, L. Essays in self-criticism (ESC) (G. Lock, World, 1969.


Trans.). London: New Left Books, 1976. Austin, J. L. How to do things with words. Cambridge,
Althusser, L. For Marx (FM) (B. Brewster, Trans.). Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1962.
London: Penguin Books, 1969. Avineri, S. The social and political thought of Karl
Althusser, L. Reading capital (RC) (B. Brewster, Marx. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
Trans.). London: New Left Books, 1970. 1969.
Althusser, L. Lenin and philosophy and other essays Bachelard, G. La formation de l'esprit scientifique.
(LP) (B. Brewster, Trans.). London: New Left Paris: J. Vrin, 1938.
Books, 1971. Bachelard, G. Le nouvel esprit scientifique. Paris:
Althusser, L. Politics and history: Montesquieu, Presses Universitaires de France, 1934.
Rousseau, Hegel, and Marx (PH) (B. Brewster, Bachelard, G. The philosophy of no: The philosophy
Trans.). London: New Left Books, 1972. of the new scientific mind (G. C. Waterson, Trans.).
Anderson, P. Considerations on western Marxism. New York: Orion Press, 1968.
London: New Left Books, 1976. Berki, R. N. Socialism. New York: Saint Martin's,
Arendt, H. On violence. New York: Harcourt, Brace & 1975.
654 The AmericanPoliticalScienceReview Vol. 79

Bernstein, R. Beyond relativism and objectivism. wealth 1976. New York: Basic Books, 1976.
Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, Lakatos, I., & Musgrave, A. (Eds.). Criticism and the
1983. growth of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge
Bernstein, R. The restructuring of social and political University Press, 1970.
theory. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Lecourt, D. L'epistemologie historique de Gaston
Press, 1978. Bachelard. Paris: Vrin, 1969.
Callinicos, A. Althusser's Marxism. London: Pluto Lecourt, D. Marxism and epistemology: Bachelard,
Press, 1976. Canguilhem, and Foucault (B. Brewster, Trans.).
Collingwood, R. G. The new leviathan. Oxford: London: New Left Books, 1975.
Clarendon Press, 1942. MacIntyre, A. Epistemological crises, dramatic narra-
Collingwood, R. G. An essay on metaphysics. Chicago: tive and the philosophy of science. Monist, 1977, 60,
Henry Regnery, 1972. 453-472.
Dallmayr, F. J. The twilight of subjectivity: Contribu- MacIntyre, A. Is understanding a religion compatible
tions to a post-individualist theory of politics. with believing? In B. Wilson (Ed.). Rationality. Ox-
Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1981. ford: Basil Blackwell, 1979.
Deprun, J. Y-a-t-il une "pratique theorique?" Struc- Marx, K. Capital. London: Lawrence and Wishart,
turalisme et marxisme. Paris: Union generate d'Edi- 1970. (b)
tion, 1970. Marx, K. The German ideology. London: Lawrence
Djilas, M. The new class. New York: Praeger, 1957. and Wishart, 1970. (a)
Dreyfus, H. & Rabinow, P. Michel Foucault: Beyond McCarney, J. The real world of ideology. New York:
structuralism and hermeneutics. Chicago: University Humanities Press, 1980.
of Chicago Press, 1982. Miller, E. Positivism, historicism, and political inquiry.
Eco, U. La Struttura assente. Milan: Bompiani, 1968. American Political Science Review, 1972, 66,
Foucault, M. The order of things (A. M. Sheridan- 798-817.
Smith, Trans.). London: Tavistock, 1970. Nair, K. Marxisme ou structuralisme? In J. M. Vincent
Freud, S. Introductory lectures on psychoanalysis (Ed.). Contre Althusser. Paris: Union Generale
(J. Strachey, Trans.). New York: Norton, 1969. d'Edition, 1974.
Gadamer, H.-G. Truth and method. New York: Seas Norman, R. Hegel's phenomenology: A philosophical
bury Press, 1975. introduction. Sussex: Harvester Press, 1976.
Garaudy, R. Perspectives de l'homme: existentialisme, Parkin, F. Marxism and class theory: A bourgeois
pensde catholique, structuralisme, marxisme. Paris: critique. New York: Columbia University Press,
Presses Universitaires de France, 1969. 1979.
Gellner, E. The legitimation of belief. Cambridge: Pocock, J. G. A. Languages and their implications: The
Cambridge University Press, 1974. transformation of the study of political thought. In
Giddens, A. New rules of sociological method: A posi- Politics, Language, and Time. London: Methuen,
tive critique of interpretive sociologies. New York: 1971.
Basic Books, 1976. Popper, K. Objective knowledge: An evolutionary apt
Goffman, I. The presentation of self in everyday life. roach. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972.
New York: Doubleday, 1959. Poster, M. Existential Marxism in postwar France:
Gunnell, J. Political theory: Tradition and interpreta- From Sartre to Althusser. Princeton, N.J.:
tion. Cambridge, Mass.: Winthrop, 1979. Princeton University Press, 1975.
Habermas, J. The theory of communicative action: Rorty, R. Consequences of pragmatism. Minneapolis:
Reason and the rationalization of society (Vol. 1) (T. University of Minnesota Press, 1982.
McCarthy, Trans.). Boston: Beacon Press, 1984. Rorty, R. Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Prince-
Habermas, J. What is universal pragmatics? Communi- ton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979.
cation and the evolution of society. (T. McCarthy, Rosen, S. Nihilism: A philosophical essay. New Haven,
Trans.). Boston: Beacon Press, 1979. Conn.: Yale University Press, 1969.
Hampshire, S. Spinoza. London: Penguin Books, 1962. Ryle, G. The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson,
Hegel, G. W. F. The phenomenology of mind (J. B. 1949.
Baille, Trans.). London: George Allen & Unwin, Schaff, A. Structuralism and Marxism. New York:
1971. Pergamon Press, 1978.
Heidegger, M. Basic writings (D. F. Krell, Trans.). Schmidt, A. Structure and history (J. Herf, Trans.).
New York: Harper & Row, 1977. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1981.
Jameson, F. The prison-house of language: A critical Serle, J. Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of
account of structuralism and Russian formalism. language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1972. 1969.
Kolakowski, L. Karl Marx and the classical definition Shapiro, I. Realism in the study of the history of ideas,
of truth. Marxism and humanism: Essays on the left History of Political Thought, 1982, 3, 535-578.
today (J. Z. Peel, Trans.). New York: Grove Press, Skinner, Q. Meaning and understanding in the history
1968. of ideas. History and Theory, 1969, 8, 1-53.
Kolakowski, L. Main currents of Marxism: Its rise, Smith, S. B. Althusser and the overdetermined self.
growth, and dissolution (P. S. Falla, Trans.). Ox- Review of Politics, 1984, 46, 516-538. (b)
ford: Clarendon Press, 1978. Smith, S. B. Reading Althusser: An essay on structural
Kristol, I. On corporate capitalism in America. In N. Marxism. Ithaca, N.Y,: Cornell University Press,
Glazer & I. Kristol (Eds.). The American common- 1984. (a)
1985 Althusser's Marxism Without a Knowing Subject 655
Spinoza, B. de. The ethics (R. H. M. Elwes, Trans.). Winch, P. The idea of a social science and its relation
New York: Dover, 1951. to philosophy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,
Strauss, L. Persecution and the art of writing. Glencoe, 1958.-
Ill.: The Free Press, 1952. Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical investigations (G. E. M.
Strauss, L. What is political philosophy and other Anscombe, Trans.). New York: Macmillan, 1968.
studies. Glencoe, Ill.: The Free Press, 1959. Wrong, D. The oversocialized conception of man in
Tarcov, N. Quentin Skinner's method and Machiavelli's modern sociology. American Sociological Review,
"Prince." Ethics, 1982, 92, 692-709. 1961, 26, 183-193.
Thompson, E. P. The poverty of theory and other Zetterbaum, M. Self and political order. Interpretation,
essays. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1978. 1971, 1, 233-246.

You might also like